Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

A Humane Economy: The Social Framework of the Free Market
A Humane Economy: The Social Framework of the Free Market
A Humane Economy: The Social Framework of the Free Market
Ebook425 pages6 hours

A Humane Economy: The Social Framework of the Free Market

Rating: 4 out of 5 stars

4/5

()

Read preview

About this ebook

A Humane Economy is like a seminar on integral freedom conducted by a professor of uncommon brilliance.” —Wall Street Journal

“If any person in our contemporary world is entitled to a hearing it is Wilhelm Röpke.” —New York Times



A Humane Economy offers one of the most accessible and compelling explanations of how economies operate ever written. The masterwork of the great twentieth-century economist Wilhelm Röpke, this book presents a sweeping, brilliant exposition of market mechanics and moral philosophy.

Röpke cuts through the jargon and statistics that make most economic writing so obscure and confusing. Over and over, the great Swiss economist stresses one simple point: you cannot separate economic principles from human behavior.

Röpke’s observations are as relevant today as when they were first set forth a half century ago. He clearly demonstrates how those societies that have embraced free-market principles have achieved phenomenal economic success—and how those that cling to theories of economic centralization endure stagnation and persistent poverty.

A Humane Economy shows how economic processes and government policies influence our behavior and choices—to the betterment or detriment of life in those vital and highly fragile human structures we call communities.


 “It is the precept of ethical and humane behavior, no less than of political wisdom,” Röpke reminds us, “to adapt economic policy to man, not man to economic policy.”
 


LanguageEnglish
Release dateApr 8, 2014
ISBN9781497636422
A Humane Economy: The Social Framework of the Free Market

Related to A Humane Economy

Related ebooks

Historical Biographies For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for A Humane Economy

Rating: 4.249999625 out of 5 stars
4/5

8 ratings1 review

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

  • Rating: 3 out of 5 stars
    3/5
    Much of this book is beautifully written --Ropke (even in translation) has a vivid and sympathetic style that reminds me of Chesterton. However, I bought the book because it was supposed to be a brilliant defense of the ethics of a free market economy -- that the free market not only works, but is ethically preferable to even fully democratic socialism. Frankly, I simply did not find that here. Ropke is credited with much of the West German economic recovery, but the first 150 pages (out of 261) are nostalgic praise of a pre-industrial economy. It reminds me more of Small Is Beautiful than, say, Milton Friedman. Ropke's ideal seems to be a simple agrarian society with a low technological level. He speaks of a painting of a farm with a horse and says it would not be so pretty with a tractor. No doubt that is true, but no-one is seriously suggesting that modern farms go back to horses. It may well be that much of German agriculture was still horse-powered up to World War II, and I suppose Ropke may have grown up with that life, but it does not fit the Germany of Volkswagens and BMWs when he was writing in the 1960s. He laments the "proletarianization" of the industrial workforce, but he has no serious suggestion for how to move industry back to small-scale independent factories. After page 150, he moves into a serious critique of the welfare state, arguing that it includes built-in inflation, which may well be true, though very few economists (even conservatives) are serious "hard money" theorists nowadays, and politically I suspect hard money is impossible even if it is desirable. He also criticizes the "monopoly" position of labor unions, but given the collapse of unions in the US and Britain since he wrote, that does not seem very relevant either He says he is writing to convince sincere Christian socialists that the free market is morally preferable to the welfare state, but he says almost nothing about the application of Christian ethics to business. Personally, I am not a socialist, but if I were, I do not think this book would convert me.

Book preview

A Humane Economy - Wilhelm Röpke

A Humane Economy

The Social Framework of the Free Market

By Wilhelm Röpke

With a new introduction by Samuel Gregg

WILMINGTON, DELAWARE

CONTENTS

FOREWORD—Wilhelm Röpke

PREFACE TO THE ENGLISH-LANGUAGE EDITION

INTRODUCTION TO THE PAPERBACK EDITION—Samuel Gregg

Chapter I—REAPPRAISAL AFTER FIFTEEN YEARS

Personal

Old and New Vistas

Market Economy and Collectivism

Chapter II—MODERN MASS SOCIETY

Mass and World Population

Mass—Acute and Chronic

Mass Culture

Mass and Society

Boredom and Mass Society

Chapter III—THE CONDITIONS AND LIMITS OF THE MARKET

Social Rationalism

The Spiritual and Moral Setting

Nobilitas naturalis

The Asymmetry of the Market Economy

The Political Framework of the Market Economy

Chapter IV—WELFARE STATE AND CHRONIC INFLATION

Limits and Dangers of the Welfare State

The Problem of Social Security in a Free Society

The Welfare State on the International Plane

The Theoretical Background of Chronic Inflation

The Nature of Chronic Inflation

Wage Inflation

Conclusions and Prospects

Chapter V—CENTRISM AND DECENTRISM

The Dividing Lines in Social Philosophy and Economic Policy

The Web of Human Relations

International Centrism

Reckoning Without Man

NOTES

FOREWORD

Around the turn of the last century, the finial of a church steeple at Gotha was opened. In it was found a document, deposited there in 1784, which read as follows: Our days are the happiest of the eighteenth century. Emperors, kings, princes descend benevolently from their awe-inspiring height, forsake splendor and pomp, and become their people’s father, friend, and confidant. Religion emerges in its divine glory from the tattered clerical gown. Enlightenment makes giant strides. Thousands of our brothers and sisters, who used to live in consecrated idleness, are given back to public life. Religious hatred and intolerance are disappearing, humanity and freedom of thought gain the upper hand. The arts and sciences prosper, and our eyes look deep into nature’s workshop. Artisans, like artists, approach perfection, useful knowledge germinates in all estates. This is a faithful picture of our times. Do not look down upon us haughtily if you have attained to greater heights and can see further than we do; mindful of our record, acknowledge how much our courage and strength have raised and supported your position. Do likewise for your successors and be happy. Five years later, the French Revolution broke out; its waves have still not subsided, still throw us hither and thither. Gotha itself, famed for its Almanach de Gotha and its sausages, has been engulfed by the most monstrous tyranny of all times.

There could be no greater distance between the honest happiness of the document quoted and the spirit of this book. We may hope, of course, that the German language as written in 1957 would still be intelligible to a burgher of Gotha in 1784. But what, except dumbfounded horror, would be his reaction if he were to become acquainted with our world of today—a world shaken by tremendous shocks and menaced by unimaginable disasters, the prey of anxiety, a world adrift and deeply unhappy?

The science of economics had no doubt come to the notice of the erudite in Gotha, thanks to Adam Smith’s work, published a few years earlier. But it would seem as incomprehensible as all the rest to our burgher that a representative of that science should be writing a book such as this. Our own contemporaries will comprehend it all the better, in so far as they understand their own situation and the problems of their epoch. To further such understanding is the purpose of this book, as it was the aim of its predecessors. This volume is, however, more than its predecessors were, a book full of apprehension, bitterness, anger, and even contempt for the worst features of our age. This is not a sign of the author’s growing gloom, but of the progressive deterioration of the crisis in which we live. It is also a book which takes the reader up and down many flights of stairs, through many stories, into many rooms, some light, some dark, into turrets and corners—but this is perhaps the least reproach to be leveled against the author.

What other thoughts I wish to place at the head of this book, I entrust to the French tongue, once more claiming its place as the lingua franca of Europe. I could not express these thoughts better than my friend René Gillouin has done in his book L’homme moderne, bourreau de lui-même (Paris, 1951): "Ainsi nous sommes tous entraînés dans un courant qui est devenu un torrent, dans un torrent qui est devnue une cataracte, et contre lequel, tant que durera la régne des masses falsifiées, vulgarisées, barbarisées, il serait aussi insensé de lutter que de prétendre remonter la Niagara à la nage. Mais il n’est pas toujours impossible de s’en garer ou de s’en dégager, et alors de se retirer dans ce ‘lieu écarté,’ dont parle le Misanthrope pour y cultiver, dans la solitude ou dans une intimité choisie, loin des propagandes grossières et de leurs mensonges infâmes, lavérité, la pureté, l’authenticité. Que des sécessions de ce genre se multiplient, qu’elles se groupent, qu’elles se fédèrent, elles ne taderont pas à polariser un nombre immense d’espirits droits et de bonnes volontés sincères, qui ont pris le siècle en horreur, mais qui ne savent ni à qui ni à quoi s vouer. Ainsi pourraient se constituer des centres de résistance inviolables, des équipes de fabricants d’arches en vue du prochain Déluge, des groupes de reconstructeurs pour le lendemain de la catastrophe inéluctable."

—Wilhelm Röpke

Geneva, August 1957

PREFACE TO THE ENGLISH-LANGUAGE EDITION

In Dante’s time, scholars were, at least in one respect, better off than they are today. They all wrote their books in the same language, namely Latin, and thus did not have to worry about translations. Otherwise, one might surmise that Dante would have reserved to scholars an especially gruesome spot in his Inferno: to punish them for their vanity—a failing reputedly not altogether alien to them—they would be made to read translations of their own works into languages with which they were familiar. That this is, as a rule, indeed torture is well known to anyone who has had the experience.

This is the image by which I seek to give adequate expression to the gratitude I owe Mrs. Elizabeth Henderson for the skill and devotion she has brought to the translation of this book, together with her fine feeling for the two languages here to be transposed. What usually is torture for me, she has made a pleasure, and she has lifted me from Inferno to Paradiso. To be quite honest, it was not an unmitigated pleasure, for she has humbled me by discovering an undue number of errors in the German original. The reader of the English version is the gainer. Indeed, its only essential difference from the German original is the absence of these errors.

I am afraid, however, that even the qualities of this English rendering, while perhaps disposing my critics in the Anglo-Saxon world towards a little more indulgence, will not disarm them. As in the German-speaking world, I expect that my book will meet with four major types of response.

One group of critics will reject the book en bloc because it is in flat contradiction with their more or less collectivist and centrist ideas. Another will tell me that in this book, called A Humane Economy: The Social Framework of the Free Market, they really appreciate only what is to be found in the world of supply and demand—the world of property—and not what lies beyond. These are the inveterate rationalists, the hard-boiled economists, the prosaic utilitarians, who may all feel that, given proper guidance, I might perhaps have attained to something better. Third, there will be those who, on the contrary, blame me for being a hard-boiled economist myself and who will find something worth praising only in that part of the book which deals with the things beyond supply and demand. These are the pure moralists and romantics, who may perhaps cite me as proof of how a pure soul can be corrupted by political economy. Finally, there may be a fourth group of readers who take a favorable view of the book as a whole and who regard it as one its virtues to have incurred the disapproval of the other three groups.

It would be sheer hypocrisy on my part not confess quite frankly that the last group is my favorite.

—Wilhelm Röpke

Geneva, January 1960

INTRODUCTION TO THE PAPERBACK EDITION

An Economist for Our Time

by Samuel Gregg

The current world crisis could never have grown to such proportions, nor proved as stubborn, if it had not been for the many forces at work to undermine the intellectual and moral foundations of our social system and thereby eventually to cause the collapse of the economic system indissolubly connected with the social system as a whole. Notwithstanding all the harshness and imperfections of our economic system, which cry out for reform, it is a miracle of technology and organization; but it is condemned to waste away if its three cardinal conditions—reason, peace, and freedom—are no longer thought desirable by the masses ruthlessly reaching for power.

Wilhelm Röpke, 1933

When the German free-market economist Wilhelm Röpke spoke these words in a public address at Frankfurt am Main on February 8, 1933, none of his listeners doubted who he had in mind by the masses ruthlessly reaching for power.¹ Only nine days earlier, Weimar Germany’s president, Field Marshal Paul von Hindenburg, had appointed the leader of the National Socialist German Workers’ Party, Adolf Hitler, as chancellor of Germany.

From Röpke’s perspective, the Nazis’ accession to government was a disaster. As a highly decorated World War 1 veteran, a young distinguished academic, and, importantly, not Jewish, Röpke could have conformed to the regime’s demands and perhaps risen to high office. But Röpke had no illusions about where he believed Hitler would lead Germany, and he spoke his mind. No one was surprised that Röpke was among the first German professors to lose his position when, on April 7, 1933, the National Socialists purged Germany’s universities of scholars who were outspoken anti-Nazis, Jewish, or both.

Röpke departed into exile in November 1933. He initially found refuge in Amsterdam. Then, at the invitation of Turkish president Kemal Atatürk, Röpke joined other German intellectual refugees from National Socialism in Turkey, where he was appointed to a teaching position at the University of Istanbul. In 1937 Röpke accepted a post at Geneva’s Graduate Institute of International Studies, where he taught until his death in 1966. One of his colleagues at Geneva in the late 1930s was the prominent free-market economist Ludwig von Mises, who had been a major influence on Röpke’s thought. Mises’s book Socialism (1922) had inspired Röpke to resist the temptation to embrace top-down planning as the way of the future.

Exile did not diminish Röpke’s engagement in the world of ideas. Unlike most of his fellow free-market German economists, Röpke enjoyed an intellectual reputation that extended beyond the frontiers of the German-speaking world. He wrote prolifically, including several books, dozens of academic papers, and hundreds of newspaper articles.

Coming from a family that had produced Protestant clergy, lawyers, doctors, and civil servants, Röpke had studied law and then economics at the universities of Tübingen and Göttingen. He earned his doctorate under the supervision of Walter Troeltsch, a specialist in the economics of unemployment, at the University of Marburg in 1921. Röpke’s doctoral thesis concerned the economics of the German potash mining industry, which happened to be one of Germany’s most heavily cartelized industries. This experience marked the beginning of Röpke’s lifelong interest in curbing monopolies. For a later dissertation (known as his habilitation—a dissertation required of anyone with a doctorate who wanted to teach in German universities), he studied the economics of business cycles, a topic to which he consistently returned.

In 1924 Röpke was appointed professor at the University of Jena at the age of twenty-four, thereby becoming Germany’s youngest professor. He spent part of his tenure at Jena in the United States, where he studied the economic problems of agriculture. After spending time at the University of Graz in 1928, Röpke returned to the University of Marburg the following year to assume a full professorship.

As his public remarks after Hitler’s rise to power suggest, Wilhelm Röpke did not confine himself to the ivory tower. He advised various German governments on economic policy. Before taking his position with the University of Jena, he spent a year in the German Foreign Office advising the Weimar government on how to pay Germany’s war reparations. In 1930–31 he served on a government commission studying unemployment. After the Second World War he played a key role on the currency-reform council assembled by the man the Allies had made responsible for overseeing the economy of the Western-occupied zones of Germany, Ludwig Erhard.

Between 1947 and 1948 that council forcefully advocated the German economy’s liberalization. Röpke was perhaps most responsible for developing both the intellectual and the public case for implementing measures that went squarely against the Keynesian and social democratic consensus of the time. Within ten years, these reforms—specifically currency reform and the abolition of price controls—had made West Germany the economic powerhouse of Western Europe. Such success, however, did not stop Röpke from critiquing policies undertaken by many of the politicians and public officials to whom he provided intellectual support. In 1950, for example, West German chancellor Konrad Adenauer commissioned Röpke to write a defense of his government’s economic policies. The resulting paper not only praised Erhard’s liberalizing measures but also criticized emerging trends of government intervention.

Often unwilling to wait for policy makers to ask his opinion, Röpke entered the public square. The publication of his book The German Question (1946) had similar effects on postwar German public opinion as Friedrich von Hayek’s Road to Serfdom (1944) had on Anglo-American audiences. Likewise, many of Röpke’s newspaper articles had a profound impact on informed opinion. One of his more famous pieces was an article in the Catholic weekly Rheinische Merkur. It is widely regarded as one of the most important articles that helped prepare German public opinion for Erhard’s reestablishment of the market economy in West Germany in 1948.

Economic Humanism

Like many others of his generation, Röpke was shaped by his military service in World War 1. That experience had a profound influence on his thought. Initially, Röpke’s antinationalism and antiwar positions translated into support for socialism. To his surprise, however, his university studies (especially his study of Mises) led him to conclude that his protest against war and nationalism mandated a commitment to liberalism in the sphere of international economic relations; in other words, to free trade.² The same reaction also aroused in Röpke a great wariness about the powers of the modern state and, along with this, about the powers of the various pressure groups within the nation.³

Röpke was acutely conscious that intellectual trends were heading in a different direction. But having made his choice, he never recoiled from its consequences. His views on what sound political economy required, Röpke wrote, meant speaking against most of the groups and policies that prevailed in the field of economics between the wars.⁴ Taking such stands was, he believed, the intellectual’s nonnegotiable moral responsibility.

Scholars typically place Röpke in the neoliberal tradition associated with twentieth-century figures such as Franz Böhm, Walter Eucken, Alfred Müller-Armack, and Alexander Rüstow. Many economists also associate Röpke with the Austrian School, of which Mises and Hayek were perhaps the most prominent members. Both descriptions are fitting. With neoliberal economists, Röpke shared an interest in modifying capitalism in ways compatible with free competition. And like the Austrian School, Röpke made significant contributions to business cycle theory and emphasized the importance of sound money, being a strong advocate of the gold standard. It is also worth noting that Röpke was one of the earliest and fiercest critics of the moral and economic fallacies of the welfare state.

But ultimately, neither label is sufficient to capture Röpke’s thought or influence. One of Röpke’s most important realizations was that economics had to be attentive to the nature of man and the sort of existence that was fitting to that nature.⁵ He wrote that his economic thinking had come with good reason to be called ‘economic humanism.’

To understand the nature of man required the study of history. Like other economists of his generation, Röpke spent much of his career reflecting on events that directly affected the contemporary world, including the First World War, the Great Depression, the rise of Hitler, and the Second World War. But he is notable for the fact that he believed the events he was living through were not isolated phenomena. His work reflects his long-standing interest in Western intellectual history and his conviction that the seeds of current problems were buried deep in Europe’s past. He saw Hitler’s rise, for example, as part of a wider chain of events, including certain inadequacies in economic liberalism. Similarly, Röpke traced a straight line between France’s Jacobin revolutionaries of the 1790s and the expansive welfare states that began to characterize Western European democracies in the mid-twentieth century.

This attention to history contributed to Röpke’s impatience with those economists who, he held, sought to reduce economics to a mathematical science of aggregates. Although he believed there were economic laws that societies defied at their peril, Röpke also thought that careful reflection on the past provided guidance for the present and future, especially if an economist was committed to preserving and extending particular moral values. This conviction contributed to Röpke’s insistence on the limits of economics as a science.

A Humane Economy represents the fullest fruition of Röpke’s economic humanism and his critique of mainstream economic thought and practice. Economics, from Röpke’s standpoint, was not an ideology, philosophy, or religion. Instead it was a social science capable of providing society with powerful insights into reality but incapable of encapsulating reality in its entirety. Röpke opposed collectivist policies not simply because economic science told him they were bound to inflict misery on millions. He also regarded collectivism as incompatible with authentic human freedom. Summarizing his view on economics’ relationship to morality, Röpke wrote:

We need a combination of supreme moral sensitivity and economic knowledge. Economically ignorant moralism is as objectionable as morally callous economism. Ethics and economics are two equally difficult subjects, and while the former needs discerning and expert reason, the latter cannot do without humane values.

Nearly thirty years later, a theologian who later assumed the highest office in the Roman Catholic Church articulated almost identical thoughts on this subject:

A morality that believes itself able to dispense with the technical knowledge of economic laws is not morality but moralism. As such it is the antithesis of morality. A scientific approach that believes itself capable of managing without an ethos misunderstands the reality of man. Therefore it is not scientific. Today we need a maximum of specialized economic understanding, but also a maximum of ethos so that specialized economic understanding may enter the service of the right goals. Only in this way will its knowledge be both politically practicable and socially tolerable.

From the earliest stages of his intellectual career, Röpke was willing to pursue knowledge beyond the parameters of strict economic science. There was immense value, Röpke believed, in the study of marginal utility, prices, subjective economic value, the fact of scarcity, the relationship between supply and demand, and other foundational assumptions of economics as a social science. But his willingness to go beyond these boundaries was, some of his peers believed, one reason why broader audiences listened to him. Hayek claimed that Röpke had achieved an influence that reached beyond professional economists partly because an economist can be in closer touch with reality in the social sciences when one does not limit oneself to those facts that are measurable and quantifiable.⁹ This refusal to separate empirical analysis from normative judgment shines through A Humane Economy. Röpke was as much concerned with promoting freedom and human thriving as he was with utility maximizing.

Viewed from this standpoint, Röpke was an unapologetic économiste-philosophe. He and other prominent twentieth-century free-market thinkers such as Hayek and Jacques Rueff (who played a major role in reforming the French economy in 1958) benefited from the education received by members of continental Europe’s upper-middle class. In Röpke’s case, this manifested itself in the ease, confidence, and authority with which he ranged outside the boundaries of economics in his wartime trilogy: The Social Crisis of Our Time (1942), International Economic Disintegration (1942), and Civitas Humana (1944). His German Question barely considered strict economics; instead Röpke drew on history, literature, and philosophy to explain Germany’s mid-twentieth-century catastrophe to German and non-German audiences.

The Market Economy and Its Foundations

A Humane Economy, the first edition of which appeared in German in 1958, was partly an effort to explore economic development in positive-scientific terms and partly a response to the particular challenges of the age. But it also laid out certain normative propositions that, in Röpke’s view, preceded and outlasted contemporary circumstances. These principles, he believed, would enable capitalism to overcome some of the philosophical burdens under which it had labored since the eighteenth century, limit the state to a small number of clearly defined economic roles, and prevent interest groups from using state power to escape free competition.

A Humane Economy thus represents an effort to integrate economics with a broader enterprise of influencing economic and social policy toward particular moral, social, and political goals. For Röpke, economics was not simply about studying the growth of wealth; it also concerned how to create and use this wealth to facilitate the freedom and happiness of all. Hence, although Röpke regarded positive economic science as having its own worth, he recognized its limits for determining the appropriate course of action in given circumstances. Röpke believed not just that economics ultimately should serve certain values—most notably liberty and order—but also that the economy, like all facets of human existence, is not self-sufficient. In A Humane Economy he wrote:

The market economy, and with it social and political freedom, can thrive only as a part and under the protection of a bourgeois system. This implies the existence of a society in which certain fundamentals are respected and color the whole network of social relationships: individual effort and responsibility, absolute norms and values, independence based on ownership, prudence and daring, calculating and saving, responsibility for planning one’s own life, proper coherence with the community, family feeling, a sense of tradition and the succession of generations combined with an open-minded view of the present and the future, proper tension between individual and community, firm moral discipline, respect for the value of money, the courage to grapple on one’s own with life and its uncertainties, a sense of the natural order of things, and a firm scale of values.¹⁰

Röpke supported free markets rather than socialism not merely because markets were more efficient from the standpoint of utility. Markets also allowed people to exercise their freedom in ways that brought a certain order to human affairs, while simultaneously solving the economic problem of scarcity. In part, Röpke’s conclusions were derived from empirical observation concerning the operations of markets and planned economies and their respective consequences for political order. Yet they also owed something to his long observation of human nature and certain conclusions that he reached about the character of human beings. Humans, he claimed, were driven to a large extent by the type of enlightened self-interest Alexis de Tocqueville portrayed in Democracy in America. But Röpke’s understanding of man—his philosophical anthropology—is also rooted in what might be called the tradition of Christian realism often associated with St. Augustine.

Terms like conservative and liberal are regularly used to label a range of not-always-compatible political, philosophical, economic, and religious positions. Arguably, such terms have proved insufficiently stable to convey particular meanings over long periods of time. Yet for all these problems, the normative vision underlying Röpke’s economics might be accurately called one of conservative liberalism, insofar as it combines the conservative value of order with the liberal underscoring of human liberty. A question for readers of A Humane Economy is whether there is a tension between Röpke’s liberal focus on freedom and his conservative interest in order. This may simply be an irresolvable tension in the grand Western tradition to which Röpke regarded himself as belonging.

What is not in doubt, however, is the manner in which A Humane Economy challenges not only the direction of much post-1945 economic science but also those who question the market economy’s moral and economic benefits. In the twenty-first century, responding to such challenges remains more urgent than ever.

SAMUEL GREGG is director of research at the Acton Institute. He has written extensively on questions of political economy, finance, economic history, and natural law theory. He is the author of several books, including The Commercial Society (2007), Wilhelm Röpke’s Political Economy (2010), and Becoming Europe (2013).

Notes

To make a government requires no great prudence. Settle the seat of power; teach obedience: and the work is done. To give freedom is still more easy. It is not necessary to guide; it only requires to let go the rein. But to form a free government; that is, to temper together these opposite elements of liberty and restraint in one consistent work, requires much thought, deep reflection, a sagacious, powerful, and combining mind.

—EDMUND BURKE, Reflections on the Revolution in France, 1790

Men are qualified for civil liberty in exact proportion to their disposition to put moral chains upon their own appetites; in proportion as their love of justice is above their rapacity; in proportion as their soundness and sobriety of understanding is above their vanity and presumption; in proportion as they are more disposed to listen to the counsels of the wise and good, in preference to the flattery of knaves. Society cannot exist unless a controlling power upon will and appetite be placed somewhere, and the less of it there is within, the more there must be without. It is ordained in the eternal constitution of things, that men of intemperate minds cannot be free. Their passions forge their fetters.

—EDMUND BURKE, A Letter from Mr. Burke to a Member of the National Assembly in Answer to Some Objections to His Book on French Affairs, 1791

CHAPTER I

Reappraisal After Fifteen Years

Personal

About fifteen years ago I undertook the task of organizing into something like a coherent whole my ideas and opinions on The Social Crisis of Our Time, as my book was called. That first outline was subsequently filled in by two more rather detailed works, Civitas Humana and Internationale Ordnung—heute, which also appeared nearly as long ago, while even the papers later brought together in Mass und Mitte are now some ten years old. Much has happened since then, much has been thought and written, and the political, economic, and spiritual development of society since the collapse of National Socialist totalitarianism has been somewhat stormy. I feel now that it is incumbent upon me to take up once more my original subject, and to do so in a manner which will bring out what is permanently valid in the various topical and fragmentary contributions which I have tried to make in the meantime to the discussion of the old questions as well as of some new ones.

What has happened in those fifteen years, and just where do we stand today? What is to be said now in the context of the problems discussed in The Social Crisis of Our Time? These are the questions which first come to mind. They are questions to which one individual seeks an answer—the author of those earlier works and of this one—and they are questions to which it is not possible to give any but a subjective reply, however much it may be based on arguments made as cogent as possible and on the widest possible experience. It is, therefore, both honest and expedient for the author to begin with himself and to try to define his own position in regard to social and economic affairs. If this achieves nothing else, it may at least set an example.

Those who, like myself, were born a few weeks before the close of the last century can regard themselves as coevals of the twentieth century, although they cannot hope to see its end. Anyone who has, as I have, the somewhat doubtful privilege of having been born a national of one of the great powers and, moreover, of one of the most turbulent powers of this great, tragic continent and who has shared its varied fate throughout the phases of his life may add, like millions of others, that his experience spans a wider range than is normally given to man. A village and small-town childhood which, with its confident ease, its plenty, and its now unimaginable freedom and almost cloudless optimism, was still set in the great century of liberalism that ended in 1914 was followed by a world war, a revolution, and crushing inflation; then came a period of deceptive calm, followed by the Great Depression, with its millions of unemployed; then a new upheaval and an eruption of evil when the very foundations of middle-class society seemed to give way and the pathetic stream of people driven from house and home ushered in the new age of the barbarians; and finally, as the inescapable end to this appalling horror, another and more terrible world war. Now, before we have even taken the full measure of the political, economic, social, and spiritual shocks which this war engendered, the world is menaced by the sole surviving, the Communist, variety of totalitarianism and by the apocalyptic prospects of unleashed atomic energy.

What has been the impact of this experience and of its interpretation on a man like myself? Perhaps the one thing I know most definitely is something negative: I can hardly describe myself as a socialist in any meaningful or commonly accepted sense. It took me a long time to become quite clear on this point, but today it seems to me that this statement, properly understood, is the most clear-cut, firm, and definite part of my beliefs. But this is where the problem begins. Where does a man of my kind take his stand if he is to attack socialism because he believes it to be wrong?

Is the standpoint of liberalism the right one to deliver his attack? In a certain sense, yes, if liberalism is understood as faith in a particular social technique, that is, in a particular economic order. If it is liberal to entrust economic order, not to planning, coercion, and penalties, but to the spontaneous and free co-operation of people through the market, price, and competition, and at the same time to regard property as the pillar of this free order, then I speak as a liberal when I reject socialism. The technique of socialism—that is, economic planning, nationalization, the erosion of property, and the cradle-to-the-grave welfare state—has done great harm in our times; on the other hand, we have the irrefutable testimony of the last fifteen years, particularly in Germany, that the opposite—the liberal—technique of the market economy opens the way to well-being, freedom, the rule of law, the distribution of power, and international co-operation. These are the facts, and they demand the adoption of a firm position against the socialist and for the liberal kind of economic order.

The history of the last fifteen years, which is that of the failure of the socialist technique all along the line and of the triumph of the market economy, is indeed such as to lend great force to this faith. But, if we think it through, it is much more than simple faith in a social technique inspired by the laws of economics. I have rallied to it not merely because, as an economist, I flatter myself that I have some grasp of the working of prices, interest, costs, and exchange rates. The true reason lies deeper, in those levels where each man's social philosophy is rooted. And here I am not at all sure that I do not belong to the conservative rather than the liberal camp, in so far as I dissociate myself from certain principles of social philosophy which, over long stretches of the history of thought, rested on common foundations with liberalism and socialism, or at least accompanied them. I have in mind such isms as utilitarianism, progressivism, secularism, rationalism, optimism, and what Eric Voegelin aptly calls immanentism or social gnosticism.¹

In the last resort, the distinction between socialists and non-socialists is one which divides men who hold basically different views of life and its true meaning and of the nature of man and society. Cardinal Manning's statement that all human differences are ultimately religious ones goes to the core of the matter. The view we take of man's nature and position in the universe ultimately determines whether we choose man himself or else society, the group, or the community as our standard of reference for social values. Our decision on this point becomes the watershed of our political thinking,

Enjoying the preview?
Page 1 of 1