Sei sulla pagina 1di 18

PREFACE

My professional career has ended and I am now happily retired. However, there are a few unpublished papers that I would like to make available. While research on the hedonic view of happiness and well-being has flourished very little has focused on Aristotles eudaimonic theory. These might add something to the existing literature. To see our other studies on eudaimonia and our scale of moral virtue please go to : csufresno.academia.edu/SamuelFranklin I believe that virtue is the most important, but greatly misunderstood, idea in Aristotles theory. I have included several chapters on the topic of virtue in a recent book entitled THE PSYCHOLOGY OF HAPPINESS: A GOOD HUMAN LIFE, published by Cambridge University Press. I have also included a study on crowding that may be of interest. It suggests that crowding and scarcity of resources may lead to both political and social upheaval. Although the study was conducted in the 1970s it may portend the future for some.

AN EMPIRICAL EXAMINATION OF ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF VIRTUE AND ITS RELATIONSHIP TO WELLBEING

Samuel S. Franklin California State University,

Fresno

PAPER PRESENTED AT THE MEETING OF THE WESTERN PSYCHOLOGICAL ASSOCIATION LOS ANGELES APRIL, 1994

AN EMPIRICAL EXAMINATION OF ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF VIRTUE AND ITS RELATIONSHIP TO WELL-BEING

SAMUEL S. FRANKLIN CALIFORNIA STATE UNIVERSITY, FRESNO

Aristotle's Nichomachean Ethics

(NE) contains a well developed and Although

elaborate theory of the good life which he called 'eudaimonia.' the eudaimonic theory has been largely overlooked by contemporary

researchers of well-being and happiness, we believe it has much to offer. The theory is based upon the assumption that a good life is achieved to the extent that one actualizes or fulfills potentials. Aristotle would

probably very much agree with Ryff's observation that "Central emphasis has been given to short-term affective well-being (i.e. happiness), at the expense of more enduring life challenges such as having a sense of purpose and direction, and achieving a sense of self-realization" (Ryff, 1989).

Actualization requires the satisfaction of certain needs. According to Aristotle we have both physical and psychological needs, or 'needs of the soul', as he called them, such as the need for friends, art, learning, etc. In eudaimonic theory, how we fulfill our needs is crucial.

Aristotle emphasizes the necessity of acquiring the things we need at the right time, in the right amount and in the way. Most of the things we

need, or 'real goods' as Aristotle called them, are 'limited'; we need them for actualization, but only in certain amounts and only at certain times, and they may be good only if obtained in certain ways. Food, for

example, is a real good but it is not beneficial in unlimited quantities, at any time and under all circumstances. too much food is equally harmful. things we need. mean'. To correctly obtain what we need, virtue is required. ...if virtue , like nature, requires more accuracy and is better than any art, then it will aim at the mean.... In feeling fear, confidence, desire, anger, pity, and in general pleasure and pain, one can feel too much or too little; and both extremes are wrong. The mean and the good is feeling at the right time, about the right things, in relation to the right people, and for the right reason; and the mean and the good are the task of virtue. Similarly, in regard to actions there are excess, deficiency, and the mean. (Nichomachean Ethics [NE] II, 5. Bambrough, 1963, p. 309) While Aristotle may appear to be uncompromising about what is 'right', he is not. Right is always defined relative to the person. Aristotle says "We may now define virtue as a disposition of the soul in which, when it has to choose among actions and feelings, it observes the mean relative to us..." (NE II, 5. Bambrough, 1963, p. 309) Too little food is damaging and

The same may be said for most all the

In most things we are well advised to seek the 'golden

Virtue is a complex idea that became terribly misunderstood when it fell into the company of words like sin and chastity during the middle ages (Maclntyre, 1981). As the ancient Greeks used the term, however, virtue

is an extremely meaningful concept and I think translatable into the language of contemporary psychology. It is the purpose of this paper to

attempt such a translation and to empirically examine the relationship between virtue and well-being. First, I will attempt to show that

Aristotle's concept of virtue is composed of several measurable psychological processes.

VIRTUE AND REASON The first component of virtue is reason. have the capacity to think. unique function. with reason..." For the Greeks, only humans

Reason is our ergon, our highest and most

"The function of man is activity of soul in accordance (NE I. 7. Bambrough, p. 293). According to Aristotle Intellectual

there are two related but distinguishable types of reason.

virtue refers to something like our general intelligence, abstract reasoning, theory, and the understanding of general principle. It

appears to be somewhat similar to what we now call fluid intelligence. Moral virtue, on the other hand, refers to the ability to apply general principles to specific instances. intelligence. It is sometimes called practical

Moral virtue must be learned by doing, by practice.

"Moral virtue is a product of habit" (NE II, 1. Bambrough, p. 303). And, it is important to acquire moral virtue early in life: "It makes no

small difference, then, whether we form habits of one kind or another from our very youth; it makes a very great difference, or rather all the difference." (NE II, 1. Ross, p.29)

VIRTUE AND DESIRE A second component of virtue is desire. Today we might call desire motivation. Action alone cannot be virtuous; the

motivation which propels the behavior must also be considered. Wanting to do what is right and best (relative to your life) is as important as the act itself. Urmson notes that the virtuous

person wants to be virtuous and enjoys virtuous action. "..whether one has excellent character (virtue) ... depends not merely on what one does but also on what one likes doing." Virtue is a..."settled disposition to want to act and to act in a way appropriate to the situation." (Urmson, 1988. p.26 ff)

VIRTUE AND CHOICE Reason and desire combine to produce the third component of virtue: choice. "Choice, therefore, is thought along with desire, or desire p. 345.) Adler (1980) notes (p.94).

along with thought."

(NE VI. 2. Bambrough

"... moral virtues are habits of making the right choices..."

Once we know the appropriate action, and desire it, we must choose to behave appropriately. acting. Choice mediates between knowing - wanting and

VIRTUE AND SELF-CONTROL A fourth component of virtue is self-control or restraint. Aristotle acknowledges that desires may compete with each other and that restraint is often required. We may know the best thing to do, and desire it too, Self control

but we may also know and desire a contrary action.

influences our choice.

"Virtue is within our power, and so, too is vice.

The point is that where we can act, we can also refrain, and vice versa" (NE III. 5. Bambrough p. 323). To act one way frequently requires that

we inhibit an alternative response.

VIRTUE AND ACTION/FEELING Finally, there is the virtuous action itself. Virtuous action includes

behavior and emotion appropriately chosen; at the correct time, in the right amount, for the right reason. For Aristotle, action and feeling go That is why punishment can be

together, feeling 'supervenes upon acts'. effective; pain and act go together. or wrongly has no

"...to feel delight and pain rightly "...virtue then, is

small effect on our actions."

concerned with pleasures and pains, and ....the acts from which [they arise]" (NE II, 3. Ross, p. 33).

Virtue then, includes several psychological functions all of which serve to guide us toward the goods we need for actualization. Virtue "...is

concerned with passions and actions, in which excess is a form of failure, and so is defect, while the intermediate is praised and is a form of success..." (NE II, 6. Ross p. 38).

Summarizing what we have said above, the concept of virtue includes the following psychological functions: KNOWING the appropriate thing to do and feel, both theoretically and practically, by application of correct principle to the current circumstance.

DESIRING/WANTING to act and feel appropriately.

CHOOSING the appropriate action and feeling.

SELFCONTROL, or the inhibition of competing behaviors and emotions.

ACTING and FEELING appropriately.

The present investigation was an attempt to examine this theoretical structure of virtue and its relationship to well-being.

PROCEDURES Subjects were 68 advanced undergraduate psychology students, 16 males, females and 4 subjects who did not declare their gender. was 25.55 years. 48

Their mean age

The disproportionate number of females was the result

of our psychology department's student population in which females are strongly over represented. This is not particularly disconcerting to the

author since in this study, and in earlier investigations of the problem, age and sex have not been important to the study of well-being (Costa, et. al., 1987; Franklin, LaMarca, & Barton 1991;

and its causes.

Franklin and Torzynski, 1993).

The subjects were given three different packets of psychological scales over the course of a semester. and out of class. The scales were completed both in class Not all subjects

The rate of return was 86%.

completed all scales or all items of each scale so the N's for different variables and analyses vary slightly.

SCALES

REASON/THINKING Three scales were used to measure virtuous thinking. Moral virtue or

practical thinking, was measured by the Decision Making Scale (DMS) consisting of 12 items. life; The items identified 12 different domains of

family, education, friends, work, etc., and Ss rated their

'decision making ability' and 'the quality of the solutions they usually find' for the day to day problems in each domain. A Likert type scale

was used where 1 was bad and 5 described excellent decision making. This was the first time the DMS has been used and the correlation alpha of .72 seems quite reasonable. Because the 12 items of the scale refer to different life domains we might expect a less than perfect inter-item correlation.

A second measure of moral virtue consisted of the four 'ways' items from the Will And Ways Scale ( ). A similar

Likert type scale was used here to rate statements like "I can think of many ways to get out of a jam" and "Even when others get discouraged, I know I can find a way to solve the problem." The alpha obtained in the

present study was .69, not especially impressive, but since the scale had only 4 items and since it correlated reasonably well (r = .55, p < .00)

with the DMS measure it was decided to combine the two to derive our measure of moral virtue.

The third measure of reason was an attempt to tap the more generalized, theoretical thinking that Aristotle called intellectual virtue. purpose four subscales from the Constructive Thinking Inventory & Meier, 1989) were used. For this (Epstein

The subscales are designed to measure

categorical thinking, superstitious thinking, esoteric thinking, and naive optimism. All these subscales are potential impediments and blocks to A person high in 'categorical thinking',

good generalized thinking.

('making... undifferentiated judgments'), for example, would be likely to exhibit poor intellectual virtue because of a prevailing tendency to overgeneralize. A person high in superstitious thinking, e.g.

one who agrees with the statement 'When something bad happens to me, I feel that more bad things are likely to follow' would also Of the four intellectual virtue measures, only

seem to reason poorly.

two; the Superstitious Thinking and the Categorical Thinking scales were shown to be statistically tied to the variables of the present study.

Therefore, early in the data analyses a new measure consisting of the 8 item Superstitious Thinking scale and the 12 item Categorical Thinking scale was created and used in all analyses involving intellectual virtue. In the present study, the inter-item alpha's of the two measures and .74 for the superstitious and categorical thinking scales, respectively. Since intellectual virtue was measured by scales designed were .80

to tap the opposite of good generalized thinking, the label 'ContraIntellectual Virtue' is used throughout the paper to refer to performance on this scale.

DESIRE AND CHOICE Aristotle claims that the truly virtuous persons wants to feel and act appropriately. Some like and enjoy doing the right thing while others do

not. The present study does not include the data on desire and choice but leaves them for examination in later papers.

SELF-CONTROL Several measures of self-control were employed. The Deferred Gratification Scale (Ray and Najman, 1986), the NEO Impulsiveness subscale (Costa and McRae, 1985), The Procrastination Scale (Tuckman, 1991), and two subscales from Epstein and Meier's (1989) Constructive Thinking Inventory: The Emotional Coping (CTIEC) and the Behavioral Coping (CTIBC) subscales.

These two subscales consisted in a combined total of 37 items all of which refer to the subjects capacity to moderate his or her feelings and actions. follows: Sample guestions from the emotional coping subscale read as "The slightest indication of disapproval gets me upset" and "I

don't worry about things I can do nothing about." Sample behavioral coping items are: "When I realize I have made a mistake, I usually take

immediate action to correct it" and " When I have a lot of work to do by a deadline, I waste a lot of time worrying about it instead of just doing it." All self-control measures correlated significantly with each other

but a hierarchical regression analysis to virtuous behavior (see below) led us to restrict our attention to only the two coping scales from the Constructive Thinking inventory. respectable levels; Their correlation alpha's reached

.89 and .85 for the Emotional Coping and Behavioral

Coping scales respectively.

VIRTUOUS BEHAVIOR The present investigation did not measure virtuous behavior directly but did examine the disposition to respond appropriately. The Self Appraisal

Scale (SAS) was constructed to assess ones ability to attain the right amount, at the right time, and in the right way. From Urmson's list

(1988, p.34) of the ancient Greek virtues several of the most commonly recognized (including temperance, courage, liberality, justice, and

pride) were selected and used to construct 48 True / False items regarding the tendency to engage in virtuous behavior. For example, the first

item "I give too freely of myself" is intended to tap ones ability to give the right amount (liberality) of himself to others. Another item, "I

tend to seek the easy way out in most situations" concerns ones 'courage',

the ability to endure temporary discomfort for future gains.

"I always The

want to win" was used to measure the virtue Aristotle calls justice.

SAS, designed as a measure of the disposition for virtuous behavior, has been successfully used in previous investigations (Franklin, LaMarca & Barton, 1992, Franklin & Torzynski, 1993). It's alpha in the present investigation was .88.

NEED SATISFACTION The Satisfaction Index (SI) was developed to assess the acquisition of real goods. The scale consisted of the same 12 life domains appearing in love, etc.) and subjects "... It was

the Decision Making Scale (family, work, money,

rated each on a 1 (terrible) to 5 (Great) Likert scale regarding the quality of each area of your life over the last few years?"

assumed that a qualitative judgment regarding a particular domain would reflect the level of need satisfaction in that area. The domain items

were presented in a different order than they assumed on the DMS.

WELL-BEING The recent literature on happiness and well-being seems to be in general agreement regarding two fundamental components a good life: life

satisfaction and a favorable balance of positive and negative affect (Diener, 1984). This modern view seems quite consistent with Aristotle's Surely, he would agree that happy people, people

notion of eudaimonia.

who fulfill their potentials, would find their lives both satisfying and pleasurable. Thus, well-being, the major dependent variable in this Life satisfaction was measured

study, was operationalized in this way.

by the Satisfaction with Life Scale (Diener, Emmons, Larsen and Griffen 1983). Affect was assessed by the Affect Balance Scale (Bradburn, 1969).

Both measures are widely used by researchers in the area of happiness and well- being and both have much to recommend them. In the present study Separate

the alpha for the Satisfaction with Life Scale (SWLS) was .87.

correlation alpha's for the positive and negative affect sub-scales of the Affect Balance Scale (ABS) were .91 and .50, respectively.

RESULTS

The purpose of this investigation was to empirically examine the theoretical structure of Aristotle's concept of virtue and to further assess his claim that virtue is essential to well-being. The scales used are presented in Table 1, along with their means, standard deviations, and alpha's. Table 2 presents a correlation matrix of the variables. It

may be noted from Table 2 that most of the scales, although structured very differently and intended to measure very different psychological processes, are quite highly correlated. for these correlations may be possible, While alternative explanations (e.g. all measures may reflect

the same psychological construct), we believe the relationships shown in Table 2 lend strong support to the eudaimonic theory.

The model presented in Figure I will serve as a guide for our discussion of the results.

It

should

be

noted

at

the

outset

that

neither

age

nor

sex

was

significantly correlated with any of the measures used in the study.

VIRTUOUS THINKING AND MORAL ACTION In the eudaimonic model the most important determinant of virtuous behavior is good thinking. One can not do the appropriate thing unless he Such knowledge consists of two distinct

or she knows what is appropriate. but related forms of reason.

First, intellectual virtue requires that we

understand certain principles which can be used to guide our actions. For example, to be just, we must understand the idea of fairness. But an intellectual understanding is not enough. this knowledge. We must also know how to use

We must be able to select the right amount of fairness We need both intellectual virtue and moral

for the situation at hand. virtue.

From Table 2 it can be seen that while contra-intellectual and .03) the

moral virtue are significantly correlated (r = -.29, p = correlation is not especially high.

This finding is consistent with

Aristotle's dichotomous treatment of virtuous thinking.

Table 2 also reveals that both contra-intellectual and moral virtue are significantly related to moral action. Poor general thinking, assessed

by the categorical and superstitious thinking subscales of the CTI, correlated -.53 (p <.000) with SAS scores. Moral virtue, (combined DEC Both forms of

and WAYS scales) correlated .52 (p < .000) with the SAS.

virtuous thinking are strongly associated with virtuous action.

SELF CONTROL AND MORAL ACTION While adequate knowledge is essential to moral action, it is not enough. We must also be able to restrain some actions in favor of others. Several measures of self-control were administered (CTIEC, CTIBC, Procrastination, Deferred Gratification) but when regression analyses revealed that the two scales from Epstein's CTI were actually inclusive of

the others, our operational definition collapsed to the combined CTIEC (emotional coping) and CTIBC (behavioral coping) scores which we labeled Self-Control. Table 2 shows that Self-Control is strongly related to all variables of the model but especially to SAS (virtuous action), r = .72 < .000). Once again, Aristotle's model appears to be supported. (p

Restraint as well as reason is integral to moral action.

It is also interesting to note in Table 2 that virtuous thinking and selfcontrol are far from independent. The strong relationships between these

measures are quite consistent with the confusion in Aristotle's writings over the importance of will (self-control) in eudaimonic theory, and whether will can be explained entirely in terms of reason and thinking (Dahl, 1984). present paper. This is not an issue, however that can be addressed in the

VIRTUE AS A MEANS Another confusion in Aristotle's writings concerns the issue of whether virtue, that is, the interaction of reason, restraint, choice, desire, and action, is a means to happiness, or is happiness itself. Aristotelian

scholars differ on the question but some suggest both views are correct. The position taken in this paper is that virtuous thinking and selfcontrol permit virtuous action, which in turn enables the acquisition of the goods we need for fulfillment. That is, virtue is a means. While not

explicitly proposed by Aristotle, we predicted that virtuous behavior would be highly correlated with need satisfaction. prediction. Table 2 supports this

The correlation between the SAS (virtuous behavior) and the Those who act appropriately

SI (Satisfaction Index) is .47 (p <.O00). appear to acquire the goods they need.

VIRTUE AND WELL-BEING According to the model presented in Figure 1 getting the external and psychological goods we need leads to happiness; to well-being. Although I

have some doubts whether Aristotle would limit his definition of happiness to life satisfaction and a positive affect balance, I think he would concur that they are important pieces of the good life. demonstrates support for the eudaiemonic theory. Table 2 again

Need satisfaction (SI)

is strongly correlated with both Life Satisfaction (r = .60, p < .000) and with Affect Balance (r = .40, p = .001). It can be noted here,

incidentally, that support for the intrinsic value of virtue might also be found in the substantial correlations between the two measures of wellbeing (SWLS and ABS) and virtue (reason, restraint and moral action), without regard to need satisfaction.

REGRESSION ANALYSES A series of hierarchical regression analyses was used to further examine the data. In the first analysis the SAS (virtuous action) scores served The intellectual and moral virtue measures and Moral virtue (as measured by

as the dependent variable.

the self-control scores were the predictors.

the combined DEC and WAYS) predictS 29% of the variance in the moral

action scores, contra-intellectual virtue (CTICT + CTIST) accounted for another 14%, and self-control (CTIEC & CTIBC subscales) explained an additional 12 %. Altogether then, the three independent variables

comprising virtuous thinking and self-control explain 56% of the variance in moral action. It appears from the Beta weights shown in Table 4 that

the three independent variables (contra-intellectual and moral virtue and self-control) are relatively independent at this level in the model.

In the second step of the hierarchical regression analysis need satisfaction (SI) served as the dependent variable while moral action (SAS) was added to the predictors used in step 1. By this procedure the

contribution of all four variables to need satisfaction can be assessed. The independence of the predictors is reflected in their Beta weights. Taking Figure 1 and Table 4 together then, reveals that the four variables above need satisfaction (SI) explain 59% of its variance. As might be

expected from the model, contra-intellectual and moral virtue still retain some of their individual contributions to SI but moral action (SAS), being strongly influenced by the predictors above it, looses its unique predictive power.

The third and fourth steps of the hierarchical analysis regressed all predictor variables of the Model to the constructs that define well-being; Life Satisfaction and Affect Balance. From Table 4 we note that all

variables of the model explained 49% of life satisfaction, and 26% of the affective dimension of well-being.

Table 4 also reveals that none of the Beta weights remain significant in the final steps of the hierarchical analysis. This finding seems to make good sense in the context of the model. Reason and restraint are the

basis of moral action, moral action enables the acquisition of the goods we need, and the latter is the basis of well-being. the model are interrelated. All variables of

Thus, while it is clear that reason and

restraint are the basis for about half the variance in life satisfaction, their effects are disbursed over the mediating variables of moral action and need satisfaction, thus dissipating most of their individual contribution.

DISCUSSION

Virtue plays a cardinal role in Aristotle's theory of the good life. Actualization requires that needs be met correctly; in the right amount, at the right time, in the right way, and for the right reason. enables us to 'hit the target.' Virtue

One of the goals of this investigation To this end, we

was to examine the theoretical structure of virtue.

looked at the relationships between the two types of reason, self control, and moral action/feeling.

VIRTUE AND REASON Intellectual virtue may be characterized as "understanding" or "reasoning cogently and validly", or by the "grasp of what is most fundamental-first principles", or by "the powers of the mind." (Adler, 1990, p.175 ff). Moral virtue applies reasoning and understanding to the practical matters of living. Moral virtue depends, in part, on intellectual virtue but For a variety of reasons,

the two are by no means, uniformly aligned.

theoretical knowledge may not be used or may be applied incorrectly. The less than perfect union of the two kinds of reasoning seems to be supported by the data. The correlation between our contra-intellectual To do the right thing

and moral virtue measures was only -.29 (p = .03).

requires that we understand certain principles and apply them correctly; but variables, like desire, choice, self-control and the habits developed over a life time also play a role in the practical world. Theoretically then, the modest correlation between intellectual and moral virtue seems consistent with eudaimonic theory. The failure of previous

investigations to find a connection between general or fluid intelligence, (which cannot be too far removed from what Aristotle called intellectual virtue) and well-being (Diener, 1984; Epstein & Meier, 1989, Valiant, 1977) might be explained by the neglect of moral virtue and all the variables which affect it. In eudaimonic theory, both are required.

VIRTUE AND SELFCONTROL There is controversy in the philosophical literature regarding the role of will in Aristotle's ethics (Dahl, 1984). On the one hand he seems to

recognize the importance of restraint and self-control, and on the other he suggests that restraint is ultimately explained by reason, or its deficiencies. It can be argued that the person who fails to act rightly "No man chooses

does so because of ignorance not because of weakness.

evil because it is evil; he only mistakes it for happiness, the good he seeks." (Mary Wollstonecraft). Dahl (1984) believes Aristotle does

provide a place for will or self-control and emphasizes Aristotle's concept of Akrasia, or the 'weakness of will'.

The findings concerning the relationship between reason and self-control appear to mirror the confusion in the philosophical literature. A

hierarchical regression analysis showed that contra-intellectual virtue explained 31% of the variance in self-control and moral virtue accounted for another 16%. Poorly managed behavior may well be caused by poor It is also possible that

thinking, both theoretical and practical.

thinking and self-control are bi-directionally related. link between self-control and cognition is

In any case, the Lazarus

we11-documented.

(1991) suggests that emotional and behavioral reactions are regulated by our cognitive appraisal. There is still much to learn about the

relationship of self-control and virtuous thinking.

VIRTUE AND ACTION/FEEING The coupling of action and feeling has a long tradition in psychology (James, 1890; Klinger, 1977), but Aristotle antedates them all. includes both, in concert; two aspects of the same thing. this is the essence of the good life. Virtue

And, maybe

If we think, desire, control and And, maybe that's what

choose correctly we will act/feel correctly. happiness is. virtue" -

"..happiness is activity of the soul in conformity with Our examination of the relationship between virtue Virtue culminates in virtuous

period!

and well-being might stop here. action/feeling. thing.

Virtue and happiness may be two aspects of the same

There is much to be said for this position and Aristotle does The data also seem to support it. Reason and

not hesitate to embrace it.

self-control account for 56% of the variance in virtuous behavior (SAS) and virtuous behavior is strongly correlated with well-being. Table 2

clearly shows that the correlations of contra-intellectual virtue, moral virtue and virtuous behavior with the two well-being measures are all highly significant. Virtue alone may bring happiness.

However, Aristotle takes the other side too.

We also need goods. "It is

impossible to do fine acts without a supply of 'goods' "...happiness does seem to requires this external bounty." (NE I, 8. Brambough, p. 296). Aristotle seems comfortable with both sides: virtue is an end, and virtue is a means.

Virtuous action/feeling is a means to the goods we need for growth; for fulfillment and actualization. Table 2 indicates a significant

relationship between our SAS measure of virtuous action and the SI measure of need satisfaction (r = .47, p < .00). Figure 1 tells us

that almost 60% of the variance in need satisfaction comes from virtue. As the eudaimonic theory claims, virtue pays off, both intrinsically, and by moving us toward the perfection that Aristotle believed was in the

reach of everyone. (NE I, 9, Brambrough, p.296)

Figure 1 reveals that virtue, by its intrinsic value, and by the goods it delivers, predicts about 50 percent of the variance in life satisfaction and about 25 percent of our affect. Good thinking and self-control

appear to be much more important to our lives than most of the extrinsic goods we usually dream about. Fortune, youth, education, occupation, and the like, the things we usually equate with the good life, are far less important to our well-being. 1976; Myers, 1992). (Andrews and Withey, 1974; Campbell,

Virtue is an old idea, but it's still a good one.

REFERENCES

Adler, M.J.

(1980) Aristotle for everybody.

New York: Bantam.

Andrews, F. M., & Witney, S. B. (1976). Social indicators of well-being: Americans perception of life quality. New York: Plenum Press. Bambrough, R. (Ed.) (1963). The philosophy of Aristotle (trans. A.E. Wardman & J.L. Creed). New York American Library/Mentor. Bradburn, N.M. (1969). The structure of psychological well-being. Chicago: Aldine. Subjective measures of well-being. American Psychologist,

Campbell, A. (1976). 31, 117-124.

Costa, P.T. Jr., & McCrae, R. R. (1980). Influence of extraversion and neuroticism on subjective well-being: happy and unhappy people. of Personality and Social Psychology, 38 f 668 -678. Costa. P. T. Jr., & McCrae, R. R. (1985). Fl: Psycholgical Assessment Resources, The NEO personality inventory manual. Inc.

Journal Odessa,

Costa, P.T., Jr., Zonderman, A.B., McCrae, R.R., Cornoni-Huntley, J., Locke, B.Z., & Barbano, H.E. (1987) Longitudinal analyses of psychological well-being in a national sample: Stability of mean levels. Journal of Gerontology, 42, 50-55. Dahl, N.O. (1984). Practical reason, Aristotle, and weakness of the will. Univ. Minnesota Press. Diener, E. Diener, E., scale. (1984). Subjective will-being. Psychological Bulletin, 95, Minneapollis: 542-575.

Emmons, R., Larsen, R. & Griffin, S. (1985). Journal of Personality Assessment, 49, 71-75.

The satisfaction with life

Epstein, S., & Meier, P. (1989). Constructive thinking: a broad coping variable with specific componesnts. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57, 332-350. Franklin, S. LaMarca P., & Barton, L. (1991). An examination of Aristotle's eudaimonic theory of happiness. Paper presented at the Western Psychological Association, April 1991, San Francisco. Franklin, S. & Torzynski, R. (1993). Virtue and well-being: evidence for Aristotle's eudaimonic theory of happiness. Paper presented at the Western Psychological Association, April 1993, Phoenix, AZ. James, William (1969). Psychology: Briefer course. London:Col1i er-Macmi1i an.

Klinger, E. Meaning and void: inner experience and the incentives in peeople's lives. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Lazarus, R.S. (1991). Maclntyre, A. (1981). Dame Press. Meyers, D-G. (1992). Emotion & adaptation. New York. Oxford University Press.

After virtue: a study in moral theory. Notre Dame: University of Notre The pursuit of happiness. New York: Avon. The

Ray, J. L.,& Najman, J. M. (1986). The generalizability of deferment of gratification. Journal of Social Psychology, 126, 117-119. Ross, D. (1986). Aristotle: The nicomachean ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ryff, C . (1989). Happiness is everything, or is it? Exploration of the meaning of psychological well-being. Jouranal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57,

1069 - 1081. 51, 473-480.

Tuckman, B. W. (1991). The development and concurrent validity of the procrastination scale. Educational and Psychological Measurement, Urmson, J.O. (1988) Aristotle's ethics. Great Britain: Basil Blackwell. Boston: Little, Brown.

Vaillant, G. E. (1977). Adaptation to life.

Potrebbero piacerti anche