Sei sulla pagina 1di 6

The laws of thermodynamics form an axiomatic basis of thermodynamics.

They define fundamental physical quantities, such as temperature, energy, and entropy, to describe thermodynamic systems and describe the transport and conversion of heat and work in thermodynamic processes. Classical thermodynamics describes the thermal interaction of systems individually in thermodynamic equilibrium. Non-equilibrium thermodynamics may be considered separately as an extension to classical theory using the tools of statistical thermodynamics which describes all systems as ensembles of microscopic states. The four principles, or laws, of thermodynamics are:[1][2][3][4][5][6] The zeroth law of thermodynamics provides a basic definition of empirical temperature based on the principle of thermal equilibrium. The first law of thermodynamics mandates conservation of energy and states in particular that the flow of heat is a form of energy transfer. The second law of thermodynamics states that the entropy of an isolated macroscopic system never decreases, or, equivalently, that perpetual motion machines are impossible. The third law of thermodynamics concerns the entropy of a perfect crystal at absolute zero temperature, and implies that it is impossible to cool a system to exactly absolute zero. There have been suggestions of additional laws,[7] but none of them achieve the generality of the accepted laws, and they are not mentioned in standard textbooks.[1][2][3][4][5][8][9] The laws of thermodynamics have become some of the most important fundamental laws in physics and other sciences.

Contents
[hide]

1 Zeroth law 2 First law 3 Second law 4 Third law 5 History 6 See also 7 References 8 Further reading

[edit] Zeroth law


Main article: Zeroth law of thermodynamics

If two thermodynamic systems are each in thermal equilibrium with a third system, then they are in thermal equilibrium with each other. When two systems, each internally in thermodynamic equilibrium at a different temperature, are brought in diathermic contact with each other they exchange heat to establish a thermal equilibrium between each other. The zeroth law implies that thermal equilibrium, viewed as a binary relation, is a transitive relation. Thermal equilibrium is furthermore an equivalence relation between any number of system. The law is also a statement about measurability. To this effect the law establishes an empirical parameter, the temperature, as a property of a system so that systems in equilibrium with each other have the same temperature. The notion of transitivity permits a system, for example a gas thermometer, to be used as a device to measure the temperature of another system. Although the concept of thermodynamic equilibrium is fundamental to thermodynamics, the need to state it explicitly as a law was not widely perceived until Fowler and Planck stated it in the 1930s, long after the first, second, and third law were already widely understood and recognized. Hence it was numbered the zeroth law. The importance of the law as a foundation to the earlier laws is that it defines temperature in a non-circular logistics without reference to entropy, its conjugate variable.

[edit] First law


Main article: First law of thermodynamics Energy can be neither created nor destroyed. It can only change forms. In any process in an isolated system, the total energy remains the same. For a thermodynamic cycle the net heat supplied to the system equals the net work done by the system. The first law of thermodynamics states that energy cannot be created or destroyed; rather, the amount of energy lost in a steady state process cannot be greater than the amount of energy gained. This is the statement of conservation of energy for a thermodynamic system. It refers to the two ways that a closed system transfers energy to and from its surroundings by the processes of heat and mechanical work. The rate of gain or loss in the stored energy of a system is determined by the rates of these two processes. In open systems, the flow of matter is another energy transfer mechanism, and extra terms must be included in the expression of the first law. The first law clarifies the nature of energy. It is a stored quantity which is independent of any particular process path, meaning it is independent of the system history. If a system undergoes a thermodynamic cycle, whether it becomes warmer, cooler, larger, or smaller, then it will have the same amount of energy each time it returns to a particular state. Energy is a state function and infinitesimal changes in the energy are exact differentials. All laws of thermodynamics but the first are statistical and simply describe the tendencies of macroscopic systems. They are only strictly valid in the thermodynamic limit when a system has

many states. For microscopic systems with few particles the assumptions of thermodynamics become meaningless. The first law may be expressed by several forms of the fundamental thermodynamic relation: Increase in internal energy of a system = heat supplied to the system + work done on the system

where U is the internal energy, Q is heat and W is work. The definition of the work is also often given in terms of the work performed by a system on its surroundings.

This is a statement of conservation of energy. The net change in internal energy is the energy that flows in as heat minus the energy that flows out as the work that the system performs on it environment. This is also often stated as a definition of the amount of heat of a process: Heat supplied to a system = increase in internal energy of the system + work done by the system The definition of work and its sign is a matter of convention in particular fields of science. In either case, a resulting increase of the internal energy of a system is represented by a positive amount of work. The energy Q (heat) is the product of the temperature (T) and it conjugate variable entropy (S), Q = TdS, and similarly work is the product of pressure (p) with volume (V) change, W = -pdV. The internal energy then may be written as

[edit] Second law


Main article: Second law of thermodynamics When two isolated systems in separate but nearby regions of space, each in thermodynamic equilibrium in itself, but not in equilibrium with each other at first, are at some time allowed to interact, breaking the isolation that separates the two systems, and they exchange matter or energy, they will eventually reach a mutual thermodynamic equilibrium. The sum of the entropies of the initial, isolated systems is less than or equal to the entropy of the final exchanging systems. In the process of reaching a new thermodynamic equilibrium, entropy has increased, or at least has not decreased. In a few words, the second law states "spontaneous natural processes increase entropy overall." Another brief statement is "heat can spontaneously flow from a higher-temperature region to a lower-temperature region, but not the other way around." Nevertheless, energy can be transferred

from cold to hot by the expenditure of external work, for example, when a refrigerator cools its contents while warming the surrounding air. Entropy is increased also by processes of mixing without transfer of heat. A way of thinking about the second law is to consider entropy as a measure of ignorance of the microscopic details of the motion and configuration of the system given only predictable reproducibility of bulk or macroscopic behavior. So, for example, one has less knowledge about the separate fragments of a broken cup than about an intact one, because when the fragments are separated, one does not know exactly whether they will fit together again, or whether perhaps there is a missing shard. Solid crystals, the most regularly structured form of matter, with considerable predictability of microscopic configuration, as well as predictability of bulk behavior, have low entropy values; and gases, which behave predictably in bulk even when their microscopic motions are unknown, have high entropy values. This is because the positions of the crystal atoms are more predictable than are those of the gas atoms, for a given degree of bulk predictability. The entropy of an isolated macroscopic system never decreases. However, a microscopic system may exhibit fluctuations of entropy opposite to that stated by the Second Law (see Maxwell's demon and Fluctuation Theorem).

[edit] Third law


Main article: Third law of thermodynamics As temperature approaches absolute zero, the entropy of a system approaches a minimum.

[edit] History
See also: Philosophy of thermal and statistical physics It is fair[10][11][12][13] to say that Aristotle seems perhaps to have helped science consider the concept of an underlying constitutive undetermined entity that appears in different forms as natural processes evolve but is not itself changed, and fair to say that energy is the present-day notion that fits Aristotle's conception. To Aristotle's conceptual genius we can perhaps attribute the scientific articulation of the distinction between the form, , which changes, and the underlying constitutive undetermined entity, , which does not change, in the course of natural process. The distinction between and came to Aristotle partly from Plato who wrote of 'the receptacle', , and 'the idea', [14][15]. In the modern era, the historically first established thermodynamic principle which eventually became the Second Law was formulated by Sadi Carnot during 1824. By 1860, as formalized in the works of those such as Rudolf Clausius and William Thomson, there were two established "principles" of thermodynamics, the first principle and the second principle. As the years passed, these principles were termed "laws." By 1873, for example, thermodynamicist Josiah Willard Gibbs, in his Graphical Methods in the Thermodynamics of Fluids, clearly stated that there were two absolute laws of thermodynamics, a first law and a second law. Some textbooks

throughout the 20th century have also numbered the laws slightly differently. In some fields removed from chemistry, the second law was considered to deal with the efficiency of heat engines only, whereas what was called the third law dealt with entropy increases. (And directly defining zero points for entropy calculations was not considered to be a law.) Gradually the older second and third laws have been combined into the second law and the more modern third law has become widely adopted.

[edit] See also


Conservation law Heat death of the universe Laws of science Philosophy of thermal and statistical physics Table of thermodynamic equations Ginsberg's Theorem

[edit] References
1. ^ a b Guggenheim, E.A. (1985). Thermodynamics. An Advanced Treatment for Chemists and Physicists, seventh edition, North Holland, Amsterdam, ISBN 0-444-86951-4. 2. ^ a b Kittel, C. Kroemer, H. (1980). Thermal Physics, second edition, W.H. Freeman, San Francisco, ISBN 0-7167-1088-9. 3. ^ a b Adkins, C.J. (1968). Equilibrium Thermodynamics, McGraw-Hill, London, ISBN 0-07084057-1. 4. ^ a b Kondepudi D. (2008). Introduction to Modern Thermodynamics, Wiley, Chichester, ISBN 978-0-470-01598-8. 5. ^ a b Lebon, G., Jou, D., Casas-Vzquez, J. (2008). Understanding Non-equilibrium Thermodynamics. Foundations, Applications, Frontiers, Springer, Berlin, ISBN 978-3-54074252-4. 6. ^ Chris Vuille; Serway, Raymond A.; Faughn, Jerry S. (2009). College physics. Belmont, CA: Brooks/Cole, Cengage Learning. p. 355. ISBN 0-495-38693-6. http://books.google.ca/books?id=CX0u0mIOZ44C&pg=PT355. 7. ^ For example: Honig suggests an upper limit to temperature: [1]; Jrgensen suggests that ecosystems will take advantage of exergy sources [2] 8. ^ De Groot, S.R., Mazur, P. (1962). Non-equilibrium Thermodynamics, North Holland, Amsterdam. 9. ^ Glansdorff, P., Prigogine, I. (1971). Thermodynamic Theory of Structure, Stability and Fluctuations, Wiley-Interscience, London, ISBN 0-471-30280-5. 10. ^ Aristotle, Physics ii 2 193a 28-30. 11. ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics vii 3 1029a 2. 12. ^ Graham, D.W. (1987). Aristotle's Two Systems, Clarendon Press, Oxford UK, ISBN0198249705, section 3.1.1 . 13. ^ Lang, H.S. (1998). The Order of Nature in Aristotle's Physics: Place and the Elements, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge UK, ISBN 978052164534, page 52. 14. ^ Plato, Timaeus, 50D-51B5. 15. ^ Lang, H.S. (1998). The Order of Nature in Aristotle's Physics: Place and the Elements, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge UK, ISBN 978052164534, page 50.

Potrebbero piacerti anche