Sei sulla pagina 1di 65

05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

An Enquiry into
Anarchist Jurisprudence

1
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

For Gen and J. Bauer

2
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Table of Contents

CHAPTER 1.............................................................................................................................................5
Introduction......................................................................................................................................6
Kropotkin’s use of rules/norms.........................................................................................................7
Substantively similar constructs ....................................................................................................10
Theories of Human Nature in Law and Authority and Concept of Law.........................................14
Internal Aspect of Kropotkin’s Primitive society............................................................................16
CHAPTER 2...........................................................................................................................................22
Are Kropotkin’s Rules Law?...........................................................................................................22
Secondary Rules in Law and Authority..........................................................................................22
The Question of Coercion..............................................................................................................26
CHAPTER 3...........................................................................................................................................29
Kropotkin’s Use of Law in Other Work..........................................................................................29
The Origins of Kropotkin’s legal theory.........................................................................................29
Human Nature – A continuing problem.........................................................................................31
CHAPTER 4...........................................................................................................................................33
Legal-chauvinism...........................................................................................................................33
Equity: Flexible Law......................................................................................................................36
The State and Evolution: A Problem..............................................................................................37
Evidence from Anthropology .........................................................................................................38
From People to Officials ...............................................................................................................42
CHAPTER 5...........................................................................................................................................44
Tension between Essentialism and Conventionalism.....................................................................44
Politics in Concept.........................................................................................................................46
CHAPTER 6...........................................................................................................................................50
Locating the Union of Rules...........................................................................................................50
Positivism and the Autonomy of Law.............................................................................................51
CHAPTER 7...........................................................................................................................................53
Conclusion......................................................................................................................................53

3
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Introduction

The purpose of this dissertation is to broadly ask the question does an

anarchist society have law? The reason for asking the question is not just to get a

binary yes or no answer it is also a means to enquire into conceptions of law. The

problem with such a question is that there are different definitions for what constitutes

both law and an anarchic society. In this dissertation I will focus on anarcho-

communism and the positivist conception of law so have chosen to compare and

contrast the Herbert Hart and Pyotr Kropotkin’s legal theory, two prominent authors

for their respective schools.

I will present the argument that Kropotkin and Hart share many similarities

although have core differences. In comparing them an interesting light is shed to

many traditional problems of jurisprudence. Questions such as what defines a legal

system? What is human nature? Do rules and/or law need coercion? How do rules

form in the first place? It will be shown that Hart’s Concept of Law is not a politically

neutral account of law but charged in its core axioms on human nature and what

constitutes a legal system. I will also attempt to refine Hart’s theory to garner a more

accurate understanding of when a legal system exists by supplementing it with

empirical evidence from anthropology and sociology so that I may accurately inquire

into the core question: does an anarcho-Communist society have law?

Chapter 1 will show how we must appreciate the political purpose of

Kropotkin’s work before we can make any comparisons and explain the reluctance for

Kropotkin to use the word ‘law’. Despite this I will argue that Kropotkin does actually

have what Hart termed primary rules.

4
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Chapter 2 will ask if Kropotkin has law according to Hart’s concept of law. It

will be shown that while they may share the primary rules the all important secondary

rules and their accompanying traits such as officials, a state and coercion are missing.

Chapter 3 argues that despite Kropotkin’s society not fitting Hart’s concept of

law, he still has law in his society. It will do so by looking at Kropotkin’s other work

where he favourably looks upon the common law in anarchic societies.

Leading on from Chapter 3, Chapter 4 will show that the difficulty in

accepting that anarchist societies have law is due to a problem in positivist

jurisprudence I have termed legal-chauvinism. There is little cultural relativity and

positivist conceptions of law are fixed on state law as their paradigm example. To

support my argument an investigation will be undertaken into anthropological studies

to show Hart’s conception lacks a solid evidential base.

Chapter 5 will show that there is a tension in Concept where Hart attempts to

apply his theory to all legal systems at all times but he also has to construct an

accurate description of state law. It will be argued that Hart initially in Concept put

ordinary people at the heart of law but later law was confined to officials and the state

only.

In Chapter 6 I will attempt to save the theory that some sort of union took

place by locating the union of rules using empirical evidence. The reasons why

positivists protect the autonomy of law from social scientific analysis will be explored

and in doing so a significant problem emerges that may result in general jurisprudence

always being stuck in an analytical frame.

Chapter 1

5
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Introduction

In this chapter I will delve behind Kropotkin’s language into the deeper more

truthful meaning of his text. The task is necessary because we have to appreciate the

political agenda of his pamphlet, Law and Authority1. If we took it at face value there

would indeed be no comparisons to be made with. One could conclude very simply

and quickly that Kropotkin and Hart are talking about very different things and any

further analysis would not be possible. In order to make these comparisons

Kropotkin’s reluctance to use the word ‘law’ will be explored. It will be shown all

anarchists are inherently anti-state and against private property. Law enables and

fundamentally defines the state via constitutionalism and draws property boundaries

in title deeds and the like. That is why anarchists do not like using the term in their

historical analysis or future projections.

Once the political agenda has been exposed I will compare the substance of

Kropotkin’s jurisprudence, specifically the use of ‘social feelings and usage’ to Hart’s

‘rules’. It will be argued that despite the differing language Kropotkin is actually

describing Hartian primary rules. In combining the two it will be shown that

Kropotkin’s primitive society has all three Hartian secondary rule functions and

therefore Hart has unnecessarily attached what I shall call a ‘complexity condition’ to

his secondary rules emerging. This reveals a difference in evolution of the law

between the two. I will show how Kropotkin sees the law as evolving horizontally,

from within society and so does Hart in his primary rules. It will be shown the

difference in evolution is that Hart’s law is vertically imposed by a state and requires

official coercion, while Kropotkin’s law arises from the same method as primary

rules. An analysis of Kropotkin’s use of law in his other work will also be undertaken

to prove beyond doubt that he is talking about law. Finally it will be concluded the

6
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

complexity condition is very helpful in determining the political stance of The

Concept of Law leading to the next chapter where I will argue Hart focuses too

narrowly on municipal law, state law and officials. Going onto argue that Hart’s

theory cannot be an accurate analysis for general-descriptive jurisprudence.

Kropotkin’s use of rules/norms

If we are to make comparisons between Hart’s and Kropotkin’s legal theory

we must look behind Kropotkin’s language and into the heart of his ideas. We should

glean a more holistic interpretation of the key terms he uses by, for example analysing

his other works and using them to aid interpretation and taking into account how his

political agenda affects what words he uses. This is fundamental to the analysis

presented in this dissertation because prima facie Kropotkin and Hart seem to be

discussing different constructs – Hart the law and Kropotkin ‘social feelings and

usage’. This chapter will argue while prima facie different, ‘social feelings and usage’

are very similar to primary rules. Firstly a reason will be given to the difference in

language.

Being an anarchist Kropotkin is naturally anti-authoritarian and anti-state.

While it is very difficult to make generalisations about anarchists due to their own

wide political spectrum2 at their most fundamental all anarchists are inherently anti-

state. As Proudhon writes the aim of anarchism is to create anarchy, which is “the

absence of a master, of a sovereign.3” There is reason behind this goal, as anarchists

see a common thread in history:

Unlike many observers of history, anarchists see a common thread behind


most of mankind's problems: the state. In the 20th-century alone, states
have murdered well over 100,000,000 human beings, whether in war,
concentration camps, or man-made famine.4

7
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

The state is seen as ‘evil’ and the law as merely a servant of the state and capitalism.

Kropotkin puts it well in one of his essays:

Furthermore, the State (State-Justice, State-Church, State-Army) and


Capitalism are, in our opinion, inseparable concepts. In history these
institutions developed side by side, mutually supporting and reenforcing
each other. They are bound together, not by a mere coincidence of
contemporaneous development, but by the bond of cause and effect, effect
and cause.5

Anarchists argue that ‘legal fetishes’ enable capitalists to expand their power and

gobble ever more property leading to greater inequality. Private property is one of the

cores of the anarchist attack on present society, as Pierre-Joseph Proudhon famously

exclaimed ‘property is theft!’ The law defines, enforces and enables private property

to exist it also defines the government and gives them their power and legitimacy.

With the state as dispenser and enforcer of the law it is apparent why anarchists are

unwilling to use the term in both their analysis of history and their future predictions

of an ideal society. Their analysis of history has a point – to empirically prove private

property and state is a relatively modern phenomenon and is not needed in an

anarchist society. The interpretation of history is to counter modern ‘legal fetishism’

as leftists call it where people cannot see society functioning without state apparatus

by proving it once did. To admit law existed in primitive societies would rest uneasily

with their critiques of the legal form since much of that critique is contingent on the

claim private property did not exist in pre-feudal societies.

All anarchists are socialists;6 another term for anarchism is libertarian

socialism7. Perhaps the essence of exactly why they oppose law whatever its form is

best quantified by Evgeny Pashukanis the Marxist jurist (who of course is a socialist),

who saw law as:

8
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

… directed, naturally, at the defence of the basic conditions of the


capitalist mode of production, at the protection and strengthening of
bourgeois private property, and the guaranteeing of the rights of “man
and citizen”, i.e. the right of the owner and the exploiter to suppress the
revolutionary actions of the exploited classes.8

Law is ultimately just a class tool to ensure the right of contract and property –

expropriation of surplus value from the masses9 and the enslavement of the masses to

their masters, or so the anarchist argument goes. A digression into E.P Thompson’s

experience perhaps best illustrates exactly why defence of the law is vehemently

ostracised by Marxists and anarchists.

Edward Thompson, the self-described Marxist historian wrote a defence of the

rule of law in a famous chapter in Whigs and Hunters10. The book concerned

seventeenth and eighteenth century English history in particular the ‘Bloody Code’

where men and women were subject to capital punishment for minor offences such as

poaching, wood-taking and gleaning. Daniel Cole writes “the first 258 pages of

Whigs and Hunters could have led Thompson to a conventional Marxist conclusion:

law is an instrument of brute force which the ruling class consolidates and reinforces

its hegemony”11. Yet Thompson mounted a strong defence for the rule of law, despite

his own research and Marxist predilection. He argued the rule of law is rather an

‘unqualified human good’12 because it curtails sovereign discretion. The merits of his

defence are beyond the scope of this dissertation but some have argued it was neigh

on perfect13. Yet most of his colleagues14 from the left heavily criticised him. Martin

Horwitz is most typical when he failed to understand “how a [m]an of the [l]eft can

describe the rule of law as ‘an unqualified human good’”15 the rationale for doing so

he concluded, might be middle-aged conservatism creeping up on Thompson.

Thompson’s experience vividly depicts the consequences of straying away from the

fundamental principles of the socialist tradition.

9
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

It is no wonder then Kropotkin refuses to use the term law but rather ‘social

feelings and usage’ which form customs. His politics prevents him from doing so and

more fundamentally so does his aim. His pamphlet has a purpose to usher in a

revolution and actively create anarchy. It is what a historian would term a

propagandist source. Its purpose is to oppose law, authority, God and the state, not

provide balanced analysis of general-jurisprudence. While he is analysing law his

purpose is to prove it is not needed. He cannot very well end the pamphlet by

exclaiming “No more laws! No more judges!”16 When his prior analysis of early

society shows they needed law. That is why he consistently uses the term ‘social

feelings and usage’. It enables him to ‘prove’ law is not needed in a utopian society

because it did not exist prior to the rise of the capitalists.

Substantively similar constructs

Despite the above analysis, Kropotkin’s ‘social feelings and usage’ are similar to

Hart’s primary rules. As Kropotkin writes:

As man does not live in a solitary state, habits and feeling develop
within him which are useful for the preservation of society and the
propagation of the race. Without social feelings and usage' life in
common would have been absolutely impossible17

It is my contention that these ‘habits and feelings’ and ‘social feelings and usage’

transform into something very similar to Hart’s rules, more specifically his primary

rules.

Both facilitate the same end goals and are needed for the furtherance of society,

to preserve and propagate it. That is what Kropotkin means by ‘absolutely

impossible’ in the above quotation. Life is indeed impossible without such social

10
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

feelings and usage because humanity would simply have no order. Without these

primary rules which form from ‘habits and feelings’ or social life, life would be

impossible. This is so because for the furtherance of society, society needs to abstain

from certain activities and partake in others. As Hart writes:-

“If a society is to live by such primary rules alone, there are certain
conditions which, granted a few of the most obvious truisms about
human nature and the world we live in, must be clearly satisfied” 18
[such as the restrictions on the free use of violence]

As is evident from these extracts both Hart and Kropotkin agree that something has to

emerge to satisfy the conditions, otherwise society cannot function. Hart uses primary

rules and Kropotkin the customs that emerge from ‘habits and feelings’. But these

two concepts are similar. Abstention from the free use of violence is something which

(for Kropotkin) ‘habits and feelings’ produce much like Hart’s primary rules. As

Kropotkin writes:

Many travellers [sic] have depicted the manners of absolutely


independent tribes, where laws and chiefs are unknown, but where the
members of the tribe have given up stabbing one another in every
dispute, because the habit of living in society has ended by developing
certain feelings of fraternity and oneness of interest 19

The only difference is language, Hart calls them rules and Kropotkin calls them

‘social feelings and usage’. Yet in the end they both have the same goal – an ordered

society. Still the question remains does Kropotkin think these ‘habits and feelings’

eventually formulate into rules and even if he does, are they rules in the Hartian

sense? On the other hand, are they just conditions that anything may satisfy and not

necessarily rules? While they exhibit the same traits, as mentioned above the

abstention of the free use of violence, are they actually rules or more specifically

11
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

primary rules? It could be argued that morality, rather than rules also contain similar

conditions.

It is my argument that Kropotkin thinks that the customs that result from social

feelings and usage are something similar to Hart’s rules and separate from morality.

He argues that the ruling elites fused the customs which the ‘habits and feelings’

eventually formed, into their own code, creating a new code.

the legislators confounded in one code the two currents of custom of


which we have just been speaking, the maxims which represent principles
of morality and social union wrought out as a result of life in common,
and the mandates which are meant to ensure external existence to
inequality. Customs, absolutely essential to the very being of society, are,
in the code, cleverly intermingled with usages imposed by the ruling
caste, and both claim equal respect from the crowd. "Do not kill," says the
code, and hastens to add, "And pay tithes to the priest." "Do not steal,"
says the code, and immediately after, "He who refuses to pay taxes, shall
have his hand struck off."20

Here Kropotkin shows us how ‘social feelings and usage’ form primary rules or

customs as he calls them. Customs/primary rules, Kropotkin contends, result from

both morality and social union as a result of life in common. Indeed the examples he

uses are testimony to the primary rule nature of customs forming out of ‘habits and

feelings’. Kropotkin uses ‘do not kill’ and ‘do not steal’ as an example of a ‘custom’

“absolutely essential to the very being of a society”.

Even so, this argument seems artificial as Kropotkin is not using the term rule

anywhere in Law and Authority. Other anarchists have argued that custom is a more

appropriate word.21 For the purposes of comparing Hart and Kropotkin, however the

equating of customs to primary rules is justified, more so it is required. As Hart

writes, a social structure lacking a legislature, courts or officials “is often referred to

as one of ‘custom’”22 but Hart does not use that term in Concept, “we shall refer to

such a social structure as one of primary rules of obligation” 23. Hart is unambiguously

stating that customs are primary rules for the purposes of his inquiry in Concept. He

12
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

only changes the term because custom “often implies that the customary rules are

very old and supported with less social pressure than other rules”24. So then it is

surely beyond doubt that the ‘habits and feelings’ or ‘social usage and feelings’

eventually form primary rules in the Hartian sense; because primary rules are just

customs. It would be a stretch to see Kropotkin himself disagreeing with this

argument. Primary rules are customs for Hart. They existed prior to the legislation

(which Kropotkin views as a corruption of his customs) and were established by the

people themselves rather than a state. These are key features for Kropotkin’s customs.

Hart’s primary rules and Kroptokin’s customs are one and the same.

13
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Theories of Human Nature in Law and Authority and Concept of


Law

The problem with trying to unify Kroptokin’s and Hart’s primary rules is both

have polar opposite theories of human nature. Kropotkin believes that human nature

means we inherently evolve structures which govern our behaviour - it almost seems

biological; the quotations above are strong testimony to that fact. Anarchists may

have problems25 in believing socio-biology or genetic-determinism is a tenet of any

anarchists work, but research by Noam Chomsky has established26 a clear link to

socio-biology and genetic-determinism in anarchist thought, especially Kropotkin’s.

Chomsky argues that Kropotkin saw humans as altruistic and lacking aggression (at

least in Mutual Aid). This theory and premise of human nature facilitated feasible

anarchist societies due to an inbuilt genetic code to do ‘good’.

Hart is the opposite and very similar to classic thinkers like Hobbes and Locke.

As is well known Hobbes saw the state of nature as a chaotic frenzied competition for

scarce resources which resulted in war of all against all where life was “solitary, poor,

nasty, brutish, and short.”27 Men in the state of nature were thus ‘bad’ and the

Leviathan (sovereign) would have to impose a rule of law to bring order. Similarly

Locke in Essays on Government posits that men subdued to the authority of law

because in the state of nature no body is secure, “the enjoyment of the property [man]

has in this state is very unsafe, very insecure.”28 By property Locke means “lives,

liberties and estates.29” Even more similarly to Hart than Hobbes, Locke requires law

to be imposed on society and even mentions a sort of rule of recognition30 and

adjudication31 arising to halt the chaos in nature. Hart assumes similar conditions of a

state of nature without primary rules, in less dramatic terms:

14
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

rules must contain in some form restrictions on the free use of violence,
theft, deception to which human beings are tempted but which they must,
in general, repress, if they are to coexist in close proximity to each other.32

A critic could argue that in Kropotkin’s society the purported ‘rules’ people follow are

just things they inherently do especially in light of the Chomsky argument. As such

they are not rules properly so called to borrow Austinian terminology. People just

abide by them like they abide by their appetites or follow their hearts. Indeed

Kropotkin seems to be himself from this camp at least in Law and Authority, he

contends:

all these qualities are developed in man anterior to all law,


independently of all religion, as in the case of the social animals. Such
feelings and practices are the inevitable results of social life.33

He is refuting the notion that law established them rather they just ‘sprung’ into

existence. This is where the departure between the two seems to be at its greatest – on

the question of how the rules arose. Indeed Kropotkin’s analysis is in line with Hart

who argues rules are rather “restrictions on the free use of violence to which human

beings are tempted but which they must, in general, repress.”34 Hart is saying human

nature means we are all temped to violent behaviour and rules restrict this.

Restrictions is key to the quotation. In Hart’s society people are restricted by

normative rules of behaviour on actions they would otherwise normally perform, in

Kropotkin’s, or so the critic would contend, there is are no such normative order it

just is the state of nature. A reversal of Hobbes’ state of nature - order comes

ingeniously not exogenously form the rule of law. Indeed rules are seen as

prescribing behaviour. If we are to attach rules to Kropotkin society the critic would

say such rules are mere descriptions of conduct not prescriptions, they cannot be rules

or law. Using Hart’s internal/external aspect of rules we make things even clearer.

15
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Externally in an anarchist/primitive society people would not assault others not

because there was a rule in place stopping such assaults; rather they would just

inherently abstain from violence due to ‘life in common’. It is just something that

they do. Such an analysis overstates the differences between Kropotkin and Hart and

in particular does not appreciate Hart’s ‘internal aspect of rules’. The problem is with

the lack of information for the emergence of primary rules in Kropotkin’s theory. As

stated earlier there is no doubt they are the same, because even if we understand

Kropotkin’s rules to be customs they are still Hartian primary rules.

The difficultly with Kropotkin is him failing to address how exactly his social

feelings and usage exert influence on society. Are they absolute genetic traits like eye

colour? Something we just do? Or are they re-enforced and propagated in

combination with our environment/society? It seems to be the old nature/nurture

argument. If we construct a logical argument as to how the primary rules arose we

can see Hart and Kroptokin are not so dissimilar. It is during the secondary rules

which give a legal system its title of ‘law’ (for Hart) where the concepts of human

nature differ and perhaps we can no longer fuse the two. We would be wise to borrow

Hart’s internal/external divide. Much like Hart’s rules it is from the internal point of

view the ‘social feelings and usage’ acquire their normative character and as such

constrain behaviour from the very fact they are in existence.

Internal Aspect of Kropotkin’s Primitive society

Briefly stated from an internal point of view we would observe that there are

in fact primary rules. The key difference between them is they come from within -

society itself creates them via social life. The critique presented above ignores this

16
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

fact which is understandable because of the tendency to think Kropotkin’s purported

primary rules are just absolute biological traits. Although in many respects he is

arguing biological evolution ordained them:

They are spontaneously developed by the very nature of things, like


those habits in animals which men call instinct. They spring from a
process of evolution, which is useful, and, indeed, necessary, to keep
society together in the struggle it is forced to maintain for existence.35

Thus the ‘process of evolution’ established rules. This process is “anterior to all law,

independent[] of all religion”36 However, it is not just biology that established the

primary rules it is ‘social feelings and usage’ and ‘life in common’; social feelings

require both genetic and environmental factors. To use an analogy we ordinarily

evolve the ability to talk, we have mouths, tongues, voice boxes, intricate areas of the

brain responsible for language and the like. Yet without external environmental

stimulus this ability we all genetically have is not realised; without social life we

would not gain the ability to talk. This is exactly how rules are established for

Kropotkin – a combination of a genetic inbuilt code and the environment. While

Kropotkin’s axiom of human nature as ‘kind’ might lead humans to have a higher

propensity to establish primary rules via genetics, social life is still key in order to

firmly establish the rules since there are still rule breakers. The examples he uses are

proof enough:

members of the tribe have given up stabbing one another in every dispute,
because the habit of living in society has ended by developing certain feelings
of fraternity and oneness of interest37

The habit of living in society gives rise to these ‘feelings of fraternity and interest’

which are primary rules. Habits like living together, farming, hunting and the like.

These ‘feelings of fraternity and interest’ are not purely genetic. Fraternity requires a

17
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

society – it is a learned trait and something which society itself creates. Both

Kropotkin’s primary rules and Hart’s primary rules evolve from the very same thing:

what is customary in social life. The primary rules regulate customary behaviour in

society.

It is sufficient to say at this juncture that from the text we can glean: evolution

itself created primary rules in Kroptokin’s society and they do exist. It has to also be

the same in Hart’s society. Primary rules had to be created by evolution because the

other source of rules in his theory is the rule of change. At the primary rule stage

there is no rule of change thus it is evolution by default – society itself. But how

would the primary rules gain authority and compliance with no law? For this we need

to speculate again. Although Hart does give us glimpses into how primary rules gain

authority but Kropotkin does not addresses these issues despite referring to the

primary rules so I shall construct my own theory and use a theory from sociology to

elucidate how social feelings and usage acquire their normative pull. By normative

pull I mean to ensure compliance. This is important to understand for both Kropotkin

and Hart because even with Hart initially there was no law, no rule of change. The

primary rules had to evolve some way.

When society creates rules or customs they assume an inter-subjective

meaning. By this I mean the primary rule enters into the mind of a societal actor, they

then pass it onto others and thus the primary rule acquires an inter-subjective

strength. The external observer would see this as an objective primary rule. But in

fact the rule exists in actors minds only, at least if it stays unwritten. Members of a

society would then be influenced by the inter-subjective meaning and it would

influence their behaviour thus the primary rules acquire their normative character.

18
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

While the original ‘framers’ of the rule, who constituted the rule due to social life (viz

everyday activities) would obey it there would be others who would want to break it,

perhaps a rogue or another generation divorced from the creation of the rule.

However, they see an inter-subjective rule in place, they know they cannot break it or

there would be a resultant punishment. Typically in an anarchist society that would be

exile or diffuse societal action which Hart also acknowledges38 is a valid form of

punishment for primary rule infringement. Children would also presumably told of

such rules and be taught to obey them cementing their inter-subjective strength. Thus

when society forms the habit of doing something, it sometimes takes on a normative

character due to its inter-subjective strength. The reason it has inter-subjective

strength is that others in society will expect compliance and criticise or even coerce if

the rule is not complied with. Similarly Hart reasoned that social rules are

differentiated from mere habits because they have normative pull and demand

compliance due to the criticism when they are breached:

Where there are such rules, not only is such criticism in fact made but
deviation from the standard is generally accepted as a good reason for
making it. Criticism for deviation is regarded as legitimate or justified in
this sense, as are demands for compliance with the standard when
deviation is threatened.39

Depending on the degree of normative pull the ‘habit’ forms it may be a rule properly

so called. This is the key feature of when a rule is born. Hart too had a similar

argument to mine and imagined difficulty in quantifying when a habit becomes a rule

properly so called:

How many of the group must in these various ways treat the regular mode
of behaviour as a standard of criticism, and how often and for how long
they must do so to warrant the statement that a group has a rule, are not
definite matters40

19
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

So then before Hart took the ‘jump’41 away from linguistic analysis in ‘Elements of

Law’, in the internal aspect of society he gave people, not officials or the state, the

sole role in formulation of primary rules. Here it was not the secondary rules that

imposed primary rules onto society, it was the people.

Such analysis is not just confined to Hart’s linguistic philosophy and my

conjecture. Sociologists have theorised how something unique becomes something

common and influences behaviour. My argument is indicative of the angle of repose

or tipping point theory of Morton Grodzins and later Thomas Schelling. The theory

posits how behaviour that was once uncommon becomes common. An example42 is a

neighbourhood of predominantly white painted houses. One day someone decides to

paint their house blue. A neighbour contemplating repainting sees that and also

decides to paint his house blue, effectively the ‘craze’ spreads like a virus. While

some of the newly blue painted houses might be painted white again the general trend

means the total quantity of blue houses increases in the street at an exponential rate.

The applicability to the origins of primary rules is clear. Using Kropotkin’s43 rule of

adjudication for example, once a person appeals to a third person in order to settle a

dispute, other parties having disputes would also do the same. This behaviour then

spreads at an exponential rate. It does not matter if individual parties stop appealing

to third persons any longer. The angle of repose or ‘tipping point’ has passed its

critical value and the trend spreads. The individuals who do not conform to the rule

are in the minority while the majority are conformists. The majority appeal to a third

person. Thus the ‘craze’ acquires a somewhat normative pull because people demand

conformity to it and is thus now a rule properly so called due to its inter-subjective

strength. It is effectively enshrined into a social custom or primary rule as Hart calls

20
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

it. Something once rare, perhaps initially done by a single person, becomes something

common44.

While Kropotkin is arguing in Law and Authority that law does not establish

primary rules, they are established by the necessities of social life (‘life in common’)

the key is such rules do exist and take on the (Hartian) authority of more advanced

law because the primary rules are used and enforced by society even in the absence of

a state. Again it must be stressed that primary rules in Hart’s society are not

established by law either. The only requirement for a primary rule to be valid for Hart

is effectiveness – those who accept the rule must out number those who reject it:

though such a society may exhibit [] tension… between those who accept
the rules and those who reject the rules…. it is plain that the latter cannot
be more than a minority45

At the primary rule level Hart and Kropotkin share many similarities. To summarise:

their conceptions of rules are established both prior to law, exhibit the same goals (to

facilitate social life), the same substantive rules (restrictions on violence, murder,

theft46) and owing to the fact they are established in the absence of a state or the law

are created by society itself and enforced by society. It is unfortunate for our purposes

that Hart jettisoned the use of ‘custom’ and replaced it with primary rules. In an effort

to stop negative associations with custom Hart just created unwarranted associations

with primary rules, mainly that they are coercion from a state or official rather than

something we create. Nonetheless, the only logical origin of primary rules in Hart’s

society is from within society and as shown above he in his internal aspect also

agrees with this. It is only the secondary rules that can be any different.

The question of secondary rules will be investigated in the next chapter, where

I will investigate if Kropotkin’s rules are law, in a Hartian sense.

21
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Chapter 2

Are Kropotkin’s Rules Law?

There are fundamental differences between the two in their emergence of secondary

rules which deny the title of Law to Kropotkin’s society according to Hart’s concept

of law. Broadly speaking this is because of Hart’s requirement for state based

coercion and the lack of secondary rules of change, recognition and adjudication.

Despite Kropotkin having what ostensibly seems like a legal system and he explicitly

himself even calls a system of ‘common law’47 the differences between Hart and

Kropotkin are too great. The differences are useful in showing bias and what seem

like errors in Hart’s theory. I will argue that many disparities are essentially due to

Hart attaching a ‘complexity condition’ to his secondary rules arising which

Kropotkin has no use for. For Kropotkin the functions of Hart’s secondary rules occur

in a primitive/anarchist society anyway. I will then go on to argue that this complexity

condition elucidates the political stance of Concept.

Secondary Rules in Law and Authority

Kropotkin’s theory emanates Hartian secondary rules especially the rule of

adjudication. Hart contends that secondary rules emerged to remedy uncertainty,

inefficacy and stagnancy when a primitive society advances’

“It is plain that only a small community closely knit by ties of kinship,
common sentiment, and belief, and placed in a stable environment,
could live successfully by such a regime of unofficial rules. In any other

22
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

conditions such a simple form of social control must prove defective


and will require supplementation in different ways.” 48

While Hart does not explicitly write the advancement of society creates the problems

with primary rules it is apparent from the extract such an advance is presupposed.

Firstly he emphasises only a small community could work under such a form of

social control. As society advances populations increase for a range of reasons: better

healthcare, advanced farming methods and the like, leading to higher mortality rates.

The quantity of territory inhabited of an advanced society also increases. Both

population and land increase from ‘small’ primitive societies therefore. Secondly ties

of kinship are emphasised in primitive society. Many have agreed that as society

advances people lose social ties and understanding49. They are no longer commonly

joined by activities such as hunting and simple trading (barter). More complex less

fraternal activities not linked to the land or the village take over, mostly relating to

economics and technology. Society increases its demands and consumption, a modern

economy forms to allocate scarce resources to these infinite wants50. This needs a

panoply of legal institutions to be formed in order to regulate such activity. This is

what Hart means by “in any other condition” - the condition of a relatively modern

state. So then Hart adds a ‘complexity condition’ to the secondary rules arising,

conditions such as the advancement of society, the economy and the increase

population and land.

Kropotkin does not presuppose such problems with his equivalent of primary

rules, he argues that at least something like a rule of adjudication developed in a

primitive society.

Many travellers [sic] have depicted the manners of absolutely


independent tribes, where laws and chiefs are unknown, but where the
members of the tribe have given up stabbing one another in every dispute,

23
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

because the habit of living in society has ended by developing certain


feelings of fraternity and oneness of interest, and they prefer appealing to
a third person to settle their differences51

Dispute resolution is a manifestation of a rule of adjudication, although not Hart’s

own. First it will shown why it is a rule. One could argue that it might be adjudication

but it is no rule. The example I used to expound upon the angle of repose theory

describes exactly why it is a rule, in the primary sense52. It will be recalled that the

important feature of primary rules is that they have some normative pull, they make

demands on society for conformity. If a number of ones peers are performing a task,

that of appealing to a third person to settle their dispute, then the ‘craze’ exerts

influence on societal actors. If one did not appeal to a third person to settle a dispute

there would be social pressure to do so ranging from society frowning upon such

behaviour to all out exclusion53.

Kropotkin’s rule of adjudication is not the same as Hart’s though - Hart’s is a

secondary rule. Hart makes explicit that his secondary rules are very different from

the primary rules. Secondary rules are:

On a different level from the primary rules, for they are all about such
rules; in the sense that while primary rules are concerned with the actions
that individuals must or must not do, these secondary rules are all
concerned with the primary rules themselves.54

Essentially they are power conferring rules and not rules of obligation as with

the primary rules. Kropotkin’s rule of adjudication seems to be a primary rule of

obligation, arising for exactly the same reasons as the other rules such as ‘do

not steal’ and ‘do not kill’

It could also be argued that because Kropotkin’s primitive society has a rule of

adjudication it also necessarily has the all important rule of recognition:

24
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

A system which has rules of adjudication is necessarily also committed


to a rule of recognition of an elementary and imperfect sort … because,
if courts are empowered to make authoritative determinations of the fact
that a rule has been broken, these cannot avoid being taken as
authoritative determinations of what rules are. So the rule which confers
jurisdiction will also be a rule of recognition55

Although in the above extract Hart is referring to Courts, in an earlier passage he does

refer to individuals. To solve the problem of primary rules being inefficient,

secondary rules empower:

“individuals to make authoritative determination of the question whether,


on a particular occasion, a primary rule has been broken”

further more

“Besides identifying the individuals who are to adjudicate, such rules will
also define the procedure to be followed”.56

Such an argument is only superficially attractive though. Again the key is a rule of

recognition is a secondary rule which is expressly not just a type of primary rule but

an all together different species of rule. Even more so Kropotkin himself has no

requirement of an explicit rule of recognition. Something that performs the functions

of a rule of recognition is implied since there are primary rules in Kropotkin’s society

and one would need a method of ascertaining which rules are valid, as Hart argues.

This method is most likely as simple asking when a habit forms into a rule. It will be

recalled this point is when the habit exerts sufficient normative pull on society to be

called a rule. However, there is no express Hartian rule of recognition.

The third type of secondary rule, the rule of change, is not in Kropotkin’s

society either. The rule of change alters, adds and removes rules from the stock of

primary rules. Kropotkin makes no explicit mention of a rule of change in his society.

Although one could argue it is inferred because Kropotkin’s legal theory constantly

25
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

shows how his primary rules change to fit any societal problem.57 The change in

Kropotkin’s primary rules is because they are created out of society for the purpose of

society via social life. In many ways an extreme level of direct democracy as

anarchists call it where the whole society effects decisions and the rules and norms

they live by.58 This change is not derived from any formal rule at least not in a

secondary sense. Kropotkin’s anarchist society acts ad hoc to circumstances so there

is no need for a formal rule-changing process. The primary rules spontaneously

change because cases are decided on justice and society’s mores rather than fixed

rigid rules which are the epitome of western legal systems. There would be no

requirement of a specific rule of change when the change occurs anyway. I will argue

later this combined with other factors is perhaps evidence of Hart’s bias towards fixed

and rigid rules as a requirement for law which may not be an essential requirement of

law.

To summarise this section, while Kropotkin has something similar to a rule of

adjudication and perhaps recognition, he specifically does not have a rule of change.

If we are to use Hart’s definition of law as a union of primary and secondary rules

then one of the essential secondary rules is missing so Kropotkin cannot have law

under Hart’s definition. The more important question is the lack of coercion with

Kropotkin rules, Hart needs rules to be coercive.

The Question of Coercion

As already detailed Hart’s conception of human nature means man is ‘bad’.

Rules are necessarily coercive because man ordinarily seeks to break them. Kropotkin

views things very different as Chomsky has shown Kropotkin has a premise of

26
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

human nature that is peaceful. At the primary rule level the difference between Hart

and Kropotkin can be resolved because Hart’s coercion has to come from societal

pressure59 (since there is no state) and so does Kropotkin’s60. Even here though there

is the question of the level of coercion. Kropotkin’s society would not have the level

of disobedience against the rules as Hart’s.. While the varying levels of coercion are

important differences between Kropotkin’s version of primary rules and Hart’s it does

not mean they are different species of rule. The most important element is the rules

are coercive in nature and without a state this coercion is only social pressure. Social

pressure can be as little as society frowning upon a breach of a rule or using physical

forest to arrest or expel the rule breaker from the community.

The minor discrepancy at the primary rule level is exacerbated at the

secondary rule stage when law becomes the domain of state and official coercion61.

No longer can we fuse the two because they are truly are talking about very different

things. Now Hart’s rules are coercive in nature. More importantly they are in the

domain of official state coercion and seem to be wholly divorced from the people. So

then, while Kropotkin may have a tenant of coercion to his primary rules this is to a

different level to Hart’s coercion at the secondary level. More importantly it is a very

different bread - official rather than societal coercion.

This argument combined with the lack of Hartian secondary rules shows

beyond doubt that Kropotkin cannot have law under Hart’s concept of law. What is

interesting to note for Hart is the jump from a pre-legal society to a legal one is a

jump from primary to secondary rules. Parasitic to the jump is the requirement of

officials, a state and coercion. According to Hart then one of the fundamental

identifying characteristics of law is official state coercion. This is diametrically

opposed to any anarchist philosophy. I will argue, in the next chapter, that Kropotkin

27
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

does have law and Hart has attached unnecessary conditions in his theory which is

too specifically based on state law. In comparing and contrasting the two authors I

will show that Concept is a politically charged theory of law and not a neutral general

theory. First we need to understand that Kropotkin does have law in his society.

28
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Chapter 3

Kropotkin’s Use of Law in Other Work

In this chapter I will demonstrate how Kropotkin’s other works show that he

himself saw law as present in an anarchist society. In attempting to do so though

there is the nagging element that Kropotkin insists that the rules arose ‘anterior to all

law’. However, one has to appreciate Kropotkin’s other work before a full

understanding of rules arising anterior to law can be appreciated. In fact such rules

are established by law, again language and history are key. In looking into other

works apart from Law and Authority we can also show Kropotkin was not wary of

using the term ‘law’ favourably and as existing in an anarchist society.

The Origins of Kropotkin’s legal theory62

In Modern Science and Anarchism63 Kropotkin argued that throughout history

there were two trends at odds with each other “on the one hand, the masses were

developing, in the form of customs, a number of institutions which were necessary to

make social life at all possible – to ensure peace amongst men, to settle disputes” 64.

On the other hand, “there appeared sorcerers, prophets, priests and heads of military

organisations, who endeavoured to strengthen their authority over the people.”65 He

linked anarchism positively with the former and went as far as to say the first

tendency is “aimed at developing institutions of the common law in order to protect

them from the power-seeking minority”66 In Law and Authority Kroptokin argues that

these institutions are established prior to law, yet here he is arguing anarchists were

29
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

active in the formulation of the common law. His argument in Law and Authority is

that the second type of law did not establish rules but the first type did – the common

law. Eventually though popular/common law had a historical tendency to transform

into governmental law.67 Elites, or so the argument goes, took the common law and

shaped it to their will. This law, divorced from its common law roots is not the type of

law that established rules. It was the grass roots common law that established them.

Earlier in Mutual Aid he also made reference to the common law.

“Their whole behaviour is regulated by an infinite series of unwritten


rules of propriety which are the fruit of their common experience as to
what is good or bad … the savage obeys the prescriptions of the common
law… [h]e obeys them even more blindly than the civilized man obeys
the prescriptions of written law… [h]is common law is his religion”68

It is important to understand that to Kropotkin the corruption of the common law by

the elite minority garnered their power, “customary law did much more to create …

authority … than did the power of the sword.”69 Law not conquest gave birth to

authority. It was mans desire for punishment ‘according to the law’ that ushered in

governmental authority. The elites could entangle their norms, their goals, their

philosophies into the law and the masses were willing to accept it; law was the

proverbial Trojan horse.

It is no wonder then Kropotkin is insistent rules are not established by law in

its modern setting. He sees that a blind servitude to the law and an almost cult like

obsession to it has created governmental authority and thus the very origin of the

state. Yet he is not saying rules are not established by law per se. The rules are not

established by governmental law but the people (the common law). Nonetheless this

is still law and it is correct to speak of law in an anarchist society.

30
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

The actual substance of law in Kropotkin’s primitive society is quite advanced

too, “respect for human life”70 implies human rights and “the sense of reciprocal

obligation”71 implies the law of obligations and contract. Indeed in another work The

Conquest of Bread72 for his future projections Kropotkin formulated a quasi contract73

that may be agreed between members of a communalist society to remove idlers

(those who do not work out of choice, not incapacitation). It is much like a contract

because it stipulates individual’s requisite hours of work in exchange for the free

enjoyment of benefits of a society. Even under English law this constitutes offer,

acceptance and consideration.

Human Nature – A continuing problem

In this dissertation I have argued that Kroptokin’s primary rules are Hart’s

primary rules and vice versa with one core difference being differing conceptions of

human nature which lead to a range of problems some of which already detailed most

of which will be discussed in the next chapter. They share many similarities, yet when

one tries to tie to two frustratingly it seems like putting a circular peg into a square

hole. Hart talks of rules as if they are autonomous concepts divorced from society, at

least his secondary rules. Kropotkin is at the other extreme; he argues that they are

created from the very collective genetic fabric of society. Both seem to identify the

salient features of law: (restriction of violence, theft, deception, resolution of disputes

etc.) yet the rules differ because Hart after the union of rules requires officials to

impose coercive power to enforce rules and Kropotkin is satisfied with diffuse

societal pressure to act as a coercive influence to ensure rule compliance and

enforcement. As will be seen in Chapter 4 initially Hart gave much weight to the role

of people in creating and enforcing the rules, it is their internal aspect that is so key to

31
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Hart’s jurisprudence and their critical reflective attitude; yet after the union of rules

law becomes official coercion. So then what can we glean from this unification? It

seems that any concept of law requires a parallel concept of human nature. The sum

is equal to its parts. Law is a human endeavour so we then need theories on humanity

to explain it. The problem is neither author adduces evidence to prove their concept

of humanity. This results in politics colouring descriptive accounts. The next chapter

will show how Hart’s account is especially tainted by something I have termed legal-

chauvinism. Future accounts of general jurisprudence need to be aware of this danger.

32
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Chapter 4

Legal-chauvinism

The problem with not accepting an anarchist society has law is an example of

what I have termed legal-chauvinism. By that I mean projecting the modern concept

of law onto an anarchic society and refuse to accept they have law because it does not

conform to how law operates presently. Recently I had a debate with a friend on

morality having absolute values, he took the traditional enlightenment stance that

morals are relative to the society you live in - they cannot be absolute without an

absolute entity in the universe. I argued that while that is true in all societies murder

is ‘wrong’ and therefore murder is an absolute moral wrong. Since I view morality as

a societal construct and if all societies criminalize murder, then surely it is an absolute

wrong. The merits of this argument aside he countered “wrong, murder is acceptable

in some societies. In many middle eastern societies, blood revenge is an acceptable

act”. This is what I mean by chauvinism, he is projecting the western concept of

murder which applies to all acts of unlawful killing to another society. When in fact

in that society revenge killing is no murder but justifiable, it is not an unlawful

killing. This idea is hard to grasp, precisely because of legal-chauvinism and lack of

cultural relativity. Most positivists like Hart are removed from the genesis of rules

and law so their theories cannot accept law exists in Kropotkin’s society. Positivists

are used to discussing sovereigns, statutes, the judiciary, modern litigation and the

like and so cannot fully analyse how law initially started. Although Hart himself is

confusing on this point as I will discuss later, he gives people a very high status in his

33
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

theory up until the secondary rules emerge when law because the sole domain of the

official.

This is not a unilateral accusation against positivists; anarchists themselves

exhibit signs of legal-chauvinism. This is surprising because their philosophy is full

of relativism elsewhere and they are fully aware that the present world is very

different to how we used to live and may well live in the future. Harold Barclay

serves as a good example of this type of anarchist. In a chapter in Culture and

Anarchism74 he accuses those who argue anarchist societies have law confuse “the

term law with norm or custom in which a way to claim that anarchist societies have

law”.75 Barclay defines law as “rules which are imposed by the state through its

government.”76 He goes onto cite his previous work People Without Government

where he pointed out that A.R Radcliffe-Brown suggested that

“[d]iffuse and religions sanctions are universal to all human societies,


whereas penal sanctions are found only where there is a state and a
government. This is because in penal sanctions there exist specialised
‘enforcers’ who lay some claim to monopolising the uses of violence so as
to enforce rules. Penal sanctions are therefore law” 77

Such statements are chauvinistic. They attribute our modern concept of law which

requires a state and police force to enforce it as the only form of law. ‘Custom’ or

customary law is alienated from law because it lacks a state and specialised enforcers.

His idea that laws are only those rules which are penally enforced is very similar to

Austin’s idea of an order backed by threat. This breaks down under Hart’s analysis

which does not need to be transcribed here but notably we cannot say the law of

contract, wills, marriage and the like are such penally enforced laws. Barclay and

other anarchists who adopt his stance have a very narrow view of the law, very much

an Austinian one. Even Hart keeps one strand of Austinian thought in his theory as

34
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

has been stressed throughout this dissertation he requires officials and state coercion

to ensure rule compliance.

Other anarchists also refuse to take custom as true law. For example:

What anarchists propose instead of the current legal system… is custom -


namely the development of living "rules of thumb" which express what a
society considers as right at any given moment.78

This differs from law because:

The difference is that the "order of custom" would prevail rather than the
"rule of law". Custom is a body of living institutions that enjoys the
support of the body politic, whereas law is a codified (read dead) body of
institutions that separates social control from moral force79

Such statements are legally-chauvinistic. The law is currently codified and rigid

because our society sees legal certainty as of paramount importance, but these are not

essential traits of law. It is merely a trait of what law currently is. Anarchists like

those above cannot seem to see past this. It is only a modern trait of the law, it does

not define it. We do not need to make arguments that appellate litigation in common

law systems shows that the law is not fixed and rigid and that our common law is

flexible. The majority of cases do not reach the higher dimensions of litigation and

even when they do, it is only in narrow areas such as the tort of negligence where

legal certainty is at a minimum and flexibility is maximal. Rather we can look back

into legal history.

35
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Equity: Flexible Law

Equity in England developed to remedy the rigidity and procedural hurdles of the

Law Courts which begun freezing the claims they would hear in the 13th century. As a

result the Court of Chancery developed which had an emphasis on fairness and

flexibility, it was a ‘Court of conscience’. It was only at the end of the 17 th century

that lawyers were the sole people to be appointed to office of Chancellor, prior to that

judges not versed in the law decided cases. The eminent 17th century jurist John

Selden’s dictum “Equity varies with the length of the Chancellor's foot” typifies the

state of affairs80. It meant that cases were decided by each Chancellor’s reading of the

equitable maxims. Rigidity and certainty were foreign to the Courts of Chancery prior

to the late 17th century. Yet there is no doubt this was the law of England. The Courts

of Chancery are empirical proof that law can be flexible and lack specialised judges

well versed in the law, yet still be law. While the flexibility in England was down to

the Chancellor, his position in an anarchist society could be replaced by someone

who represents the norms of society who decides cases on ‘anarchist maxims’ or

‘societal maxims’ rather than maxims of Equity. These could even flux in time so

they would not be a ‘dead body’. Kropotkin actually refers to maxims himself to

describe the common law of primitive and anarchist societies.81

It must be remembered the rigidity that statutes bring are relatively modern

and are not a necessary part of law. The anarchist critiques are better targeted at

statutes which are inherently fixed, rigid and governmental in nature. They should not

critique the law in toto because the common law, even in a modern state, is ever

changing.

36
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Benjamin Tucker and Peter Kropotkin seem to be the only anarchists who see

past the chauvinism and combines all of what I have argued. Tucker puts it best and

most explicitly:

"under anarchism all rules and laws will be little more than suggestions
for the guidance of juries which will judge not only the facts but the law,
the justice of the law, its applicability to the given circumstances, and the
penalty or damage to be inflicted because if its infraction . . . under
Anarchism the law will be so flexible that it will shape itself to every
emergency and need no alteration. And it will be regarded as just in
proportion to its flexibility, instead of as now in proportion to its rigidity.82

Law can be flexible and lack a statutory base. It can wholly embrace the common law

tradition without statutory interference or concerns of legal certainty. Indeed it is

correct to say an anarchist society will have law, just a different type.

The State and Evolution: A Problem

The strength of Hart’s theory is its ability to be applied to all legal systems at all

times. Rather than picking out modern legal systems traits it identifies the union of

rules as constituting a legal system. Hart too exhibited chauvinism because he could

not accept that a primitive society had law and thought them only to have primary

rules. Primary rules which could not be changed, were inefficient and uncertain due to

a lack of state and coercion. It is the insistence that the state or someone in power

administers rules that causes such problems. Even in Kropotkin’s work (Law and

Authority) he cannot see past the state or a hierarchal institution administering rules,

even though it is his own work (Mutual Aid) that precisely shows such rules are

administered and created from within. Most assume that rules are oppressive in

nature, they stop people from performing activities they would normally perform,

Hart thinks so too. They are usually handed down in a hierarchical fashion from top

37
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

down, they impose themselves upon society. Yet is it true to say that most of society

does not end up killing each other because of a rule in place that is enforced by the

state? Or steal because of fear of punishment? That is a very nihilistic concept of

human nature which Hart has. In a society if the law significantly overlapped with

society’s core morals it would command respect without the threat of organised

punishment. One has to look at the origins of rules; they do not exist in some state

above society, but in society itself. In an anarchist society where there is no state to

perform secondary rule functions, the people do. Society itself collectively ‘legislates’

for itself, it enforces its rules via social pressure and changes them dynamically.

The union of Krotpotkin’s and Hart’s jurisprudence shows Hart’s more

politicised background. The complexity condition shows us Hart jurisprudence

exhibits signs of Weberian, Hobbesian and even Austinian theories on why exactly

the rule of law arose and was needed. It will be recalled the complexity condition is

Hart’s assumption that law arises when society advances. This will be investigated in

Chapter 5. First I will see whose theory is correct, Kropotkin or Hart? For this an

investigation into empirical anthropology will be undertaken. This is important

because we must see if Hart has attached unnecessary conditions for his secondary

rules arising. If the secondary rules, or whatever performs the function of secondary

rules, can be shown to exist without officials, the state and state coercion then we will

have proof that Hart’s theory is too specific to be a general theory of law. It will also

help us in answering the core question of this dissertation: does an anarcho-

Communist society have law?

Evidence from Anthropology

38
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

It has been a long settled that Hart’s speculative anthropology of the union of

primary and secondary rules is, “if taken as a historic claim… inaccurate”83 as Nicola

Lacey puts it. However, despite over forty years of consensus on the inaccuracy of

Hart’s claim I will advance the argument that perhaps the anthropologists and

historians are not looking far back enough through human history to find evidence of

when man existed in a state of Hartian primary rules alone. Where the primary rules

could not be changed quickly, were inefficient and uncertain. My argument is that

such a union did take place. It was not where Hart located it, but precisely where

Kropotkin located it, at the start of human social relations though biological evolution.

Although in Kropotkin’s work he makes no such claim that a union had taken place,

as the last chapter shows he speculates that law and primary rules emerged as soon as

social life sprung up. So then it is my contention that Hart’s core thesis is correct: a

union takes place, however I submit Hart’s placement in time of such a union seems

to be clouded by his legal-chauvinism and western perspective. The union took place

prior to the ‘complexity condition’ arising and before courts and a legislature. It took

place soon as advanced social life emerged from animalistic habitual norms - far

earlier than Hart supposed. Removing the complexity condition (and thus the legal-

chauvinism) from Hart’s union of rules, the union theory can be saved from the

critiques imposed on it. Although in doing so it ceases to be Hart’s theory rather a

significant modification of it. In doing so a latent motive in all of positivist

jurisprudence will also emerge - positivists (at least those like Hart) want to preserve

the autonomy of law and divorce it from sociological analysis, despite Hart’s claim

his theory can be seen as descriptive sociology.

39
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Jonathan Cohen as early as 1962 argued certain secondary rules “appear in

almost every pre-legal system”84. He noted that Hart cited Malinowski’s Crime and

Custom in a Savage Society85 and Diamond’s Primitive Law86 as examples of a society

where there are no courts, officials or a legislature.87 Using such studies, Cohen points

out that even primitive societies had rules on marriage. Hart insists that such rules

only come about from the addition of secondary rules. Malinowski mentions a culture

he studied in which :

“marriage establishes not merely a bond between husband and wife, but it
also imposes standing relation of mutuality between the man and the
wife’s family, especially her [the wife’s] brother”88

Diamond too89 observed a society where there were rules of marriage in a society that

did not possess courts. Thus Cohen reasons “the moral institution of promise is thus

far from being the only form of ‘power-conferring’ rules that are to be found in a pre-

legal society, as Hart implies”90 Although Cohen does not explicitly say it in the terms

we have adopted here he can be seen as accusing Hart of legal-chauvinism91,

“Hart’s claim that his distinction between primary and secondary rules is
the key to the science of jurisprudence and has great explanatory power
must be reduced here to the somewhat less exciting proposition that the
addition of a constitution, setting up legislature, judiciary and executive,
is the most important element in the transition from a [pre]-legal to a
[]legal system.”92

It is imposing a western viewpoint if we presume the union to occur in a modern

society which Hart does, as demonstrated in the last chapter with the ‘complexity

condition’ and Cohen’s argument here of setting up a constitution and modern

government. Furthermore, in the very opening of the ‘Elements of Law’ Hart

imagines that, only a “society without a legislature, courts, or officials of any kind”93

lacks secondary rules. As Cohen goes onto argue the only escape from the dilemma is

to assume as Hart does

40
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

“not only that the law of wills, contracts, marriages, property, etc. consist
of power-conferring rules, but also that wills, contracts, marriages,
property, etc. are intuitions which exist only in a fully developed legal
system, just like legislature and law-courts94”.

However “this assumption is not in accordance with the findings of modern

anthropology.95” Study after study96 has proven this conclusion correct. All the

studies show that a legislature, courts and officials are not required for secondary rule

functions to be present. The theory can be saved however if we take a relativist

approach and remove the western concepts from the union of rules. An anarcho-

capitalist97 has strictly applied Hart’s union of rules, without the complexity condition

nor with government/constitution requirements to prior anthropological studies.98 In

an effort to empirically prove private property rights and law can exist in the absence

of the state. The author is tweaking Hart’s union theory and removing the

requirement of official state coercion.

If a theory is inconsistent we do not change the facts – we change the theory;

thereby constructing a better theory. After all, a theory’s utility is in its ability to

conceptualize reality. Hart seems to have taken Einstein’s oft cited quote to heart, “if

the facts don't fit the theory, change the facts.” In changing the facts and indulging in

speculative anthropology Hart coloured his theory with legal-chauvinism. The best

example of the chauvinism is Hart’s transition from the first section to the second

section of Concept. Initially he relied on linguistic philosophy, he emphasises the

ordinary people, it is their internal viewpoint, and their customs/primary rules that

help elucidate problems of jurisprudence and eventually give rise to law. But in the

second half after union of rules law is confined to officials only. For the purposes of

an account of anarchist jurisprudence this leap from people to officials is key -

41
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

anarchists cannot have state officials in their society. It is also useful in showing

latent Weberian ideas in Concept

From People to Officials

Hart’s internal/external aspect divide is arguably the biggest advancement in

20th century Jurisprudence. Indeed MacCormick’s assessment is typical, it is “the

most distinctive and valuable element in Hart’s work as a jurist.”99 Drawing on

linguistic philosophy Hart analysis the context in which people use rules. Unless we

understand the internal aspect of rules:

[W]e cannot properly understand the whole distinctive style of human


thought, speech, and action which is involved in the existence of rules and
which constitutes the normative structure of society100

The most important aspect of the internal aspect is it has a social dimension. Some

phrases Hart uses in describing them are indicative: “demands for conformity made

upon others”101, or “a standard to be followed by the group as a whole”102 or a social

“group which accepts and uses them as guides to conduct.”103 The internal aspect is

from within society, from the people. However, later Hart introduces other

requirements for the existence of legal rules104 that have nothing to do with the

internal aspect. The rules have to be concerned with officials. A division of labour

takes place where “law-making, law-identifying and law-applying operations” are

matters for “the officials or experts of the system” and not “the mass of the

population” or “the ordinary citizen.”105 Hart now sees the citizen as “ignorant and

inadequate”106 as Fitzpatrick strongly puts it. However, if we understand why Hart

confines the internal aspect to officials things are much clearer and Hart’s modified

theory can still be applied to anarchic and simple societies because we remove its

42
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

inaccuracies. The process of removing the inaccuracies also shows the political

character of Concept. As Hart notes:

In referring to our simple society we spoke as if most ordinary people not


only obeyed the law but understood and accepted the rule… [i]n a simple
society this might be the case; but in a modern state it would be absurd to
think of the mass of the population, however law-abiding, as having any
clear realization of the rules”107

Hart’s argument is sound. It makes no sense that, in a complex constitutional system,

every element of society has a clear realization of all the rules. It would put “into the

heads of ordinary citizens an understanding of constitutional matters which they

might not have.”108 It is at this juncture that Hart’s politicised jurisprudence shows its

head. But first the conflict between Hart’s more general theory and more specific

state theory needs to be explored so we can better understand the politics.

43
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Chapter 5

Tension between Essentialism and Conventionalism

There seems to be a tension throughout the whole of Concept where it grapples

with essentialism and conventionalism. By essentialism I mean to borrow Brian

Tamanaha’s phrase109 where it means the very essence of law, that all of law wherever

it may be is a system of rules (secondary) about rules (primary). Jules Coleman

describes it best:

it begins by asking whether there are features of law that are essential, or,
in appropriate sense, necessary to law or to our concept of it: essential to
our concept in the sense that a social practice that fails to have them could
not qualify as law110

Essentialism is imperative in an account in general-jurisprudence. By

conventionalism I mean Hart’s stipulation that municipal law is to be what he means

by ‘law’111. State law is to be Hart’s central paradigm case.

Essentialism and conventionalism conflict (this been pointed out before112) but

what has not been shown is how Concept seems to conflict on itself. Hart makes

clear:

“We shall not indeed claim that wherever the word ‘law’ is ‘properly’
used this combination of primary and secondary rules is to be found; for it
is clear that the diverse range of case of which the word ‘law’ is used are
not linked by any such simple uniformity”113

Yet wherever the union is to be found there is law (see Chapter 2). There is tension

here where Hart perhaps foresaw that his essentialism may not apply to all legal

systems. Yet the union of rules is the “key to the science of jurisprudence”114. As seen

44
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

in the last chapter Hart sometimes mentions courts and sometimes mentions

individuals in elaborating the rule of adjudication.115 Hart somehow has to make the

theory essential and conventional. He has to be wary not to indulge in legal-

chauvinism for the essentialist tenant of his theory so he mentions individuals. He

also has to bear in mind his conventionalist goal (make his theory apply to state law)

and therefore mentions courts more often. The result is an awkward grappling in the

theory which satisfies neither camp.

The theory has been described as too general - we can even apply it to little

league soccer116. In this dissertation I have criticised it for being too specific and

attaching unnecessary conditions for the secondary rules arising. In the introduction

to Concept Hart made explicit he was not going to define law because such questions

were fundamentally misconceived117 yet his union of rules provided such a definition

for his theory. He stated his work could be seen as a work in ‘descriptive sociology’,

yet indulged in speculation without empirical evidence for his union of rules theory.

Hart was silent on these inaccuracies118. His postscript never addressed the issue nor

did any of his later work. Nicola Lacey as Hart’s biographer is perhaps the only

person we can glean any useful information from as to why. She was a close friend

and has access to all his notes and annotations:

“Hart’s defence against these objections was clear, if unlikely to satisfy


his critics. It was simply that these sociological and historical questions
were not ones which he set himself to answer. Rather, his was essentially
a philosophical project, its allusion to ‘descriptive sociology’ an
unfortunately misleading attempt to signal his move away from more
rigid conceptual theories of John Austin and Hans Kelsen.” 119

Such an answer is unsatisfactory. A 1961 Hart positively acknowledged that for

Jurisprudence to leave behind theories of old it should embrace sociology. Yet when

the sociological aspect of his theory is challenged he retreated to a weak defence of

45
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

arguing his project was a work of analytical jurisprudence. A division of labour was

stressed – the sociologists have their job and analytical jurists have theirs. But his

entire book is a fusion of analytical jurisprudence and descriptive sociology. He

cannot continue his theory without the fusion. A 1961 Hart realised for a strong

theory of law you need both. Early on Concept relies on linguistic philosophy; the

differences between the internal and external aspect, the difference between having an

obligation and being obligated etc. It then progresses to speculative anthropology and

sociology with Hart being witness to the union of rules. Peter Fitzpatrick has bluntly

described the early section of Concept, “whatever else this antique story may be, it is

not linguistic philosophy.”120 Indeed it is speculative sociology.

Hart’s retreat later on in life away from sociology was not entirely

unprincipled. Lacey has an interesting interpretation of the famous Hart/Devlin

debate where Lord Devlin forwarded an argument that required testing empirically

(sociologically):

This essay is of particular interest in that it represents an attack not merely


on Devlin’s argument but on sociological method in general: Hart
suggested that sociology can never match the test of empirical rigour
which it sets for itself. His view boiled down to the idea that because the
social sciences can never produce evidence as compelling as the natural
sciences, they are not worth pursuing. This is a convenient rationalisation
for staying firmly within an analytic philosophical method.121

The merits of this argument will be explored later but if Hart wants to stay in the

analytical method he cannot also speculate on empirical evidence and expect a strong

theory. Yet a 1961 Hart knew that jurisprudence needed sociology and anthropology

for a complete general theory of law. That fact has not changed to this day.

Politics in Concept

46
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

The jump from the linguistic analysis in the internal aspect to a more

sociological method in ‘primary and secondary rules’ is a political one. Hart’s

linguistic analysis of law in its context is essentialist since it’s primarily concerned

with ordinary people and does not mention officials or the state. His sociological

analysis - his theory on why the secondary rules emerged - is a firm thrust to

conventionalist state theory. It is concerned solely with officials, the state and

coercion. It focuses on modern legal phenomena, he repeatedly mentions ‘the queen

in parliament’ and statutes. Even here, though, as seen earlier there is tension where

Hart attempts to make his theory essentialist (for example sometimes mentioning

people, sometimes courts). But as Fitzpatrick puts it “with that step the creativity of

the mass of society is exhausted and the legal dynamic is thereafter confined to the

ranks of officials”122 The internal aspect is only necessary for officials and as such

mark the triumph of official determinations.

The division of labour between officials and the rest of society is similar to

Weber’s rational bureaucracy. The features to make bureaucracy rational are (1)

functional specialisation (2) clear lines of hierarchical authority, (3) expert training of

managers, and (4) decision-making depending on rational rules aimed at effective

pursuit of organizational goals123. As Hart noted above124 in a complex society the

constitution and the laws are so complex so specialisation takes place – the officials

are experts in the law. Clear lines of authority are also established in Hart’s theory

especially with the rule of recognition. The one way projection of power and lack of

societal discourse up the chain of command is indicative of Weber’s bureaucracy

theories too (point 2). Lon Fuller also saw this (although did not mention Weber) the

legal positivist, “does not see the lawgiver and the citizen in interaction with one

another, and by virtue of that failure he fails to see that the creation of an effective

47
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

interaction between them is an essential ingredient of the law itself125” Although

Fuller had in mind modern systems, in an anarchist or simple society the discourse

between society and those who administer the law will be at its greatest. In

Kroptokin’s society the people will themselves administer the law. Hart’s theory

simply disagrees with this after the union of rules, when before the emphasis on

people was great.

In the jump from linguistic philosophy to sociological theory and the

secondary rules Hart’s essentialism is lost – western concepts of law show and ruin

the general-descriptive arm of what was an essentialist theory to this point. Law

becomes a one way projection of power, indeed a Weberian hierarchy; it is divorced

from society, it holds a status above society enduring changing sovereigns and even

political systems. Some commentators126 have claimed that the union of rules marks

Hart’s deference to the maxim ‘a government of laws not men’. Prior to the radical

departure from the linguistic and internal analysis Hart gave people, in the internal

aspect, a critical reflective attitude to the rules, he gave people the ability to act and

assess standards of behaviour. An anarchist reading this area of Hart might well be

surprised that a legal scholar indeed a (ex) practicing lawyer saw law as a dynamic of

the people. Law was created from the very fabric of society. It seems Hart had

foreshadowed the economist Fridrich Hayek’s future suggestion:

legal history proper begins at too late a state of evolution to bring out
clearly the origins. If we wish to free ourselves [of this] pervasive
influence … we should begin with a look at the primitive … beginnings
of social life’127

Kropotkin’s contention is similar to Hayek’s. We are not looking far back into history

to see where law developed from. A union did take place between primary and

secondary rules. Kropotkin was aware of this - he identified law as coming into being

48
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

soon as social life emerged. It seems to me that Hart in a very small way somehow

agreed. That is why there is so much tension in his theory and that is why the union of

rules was ‘the key to the science of jurisprudence.’ But the tension in his own mind

between the conventional and essential elements of his theory clouded this fact. He

constructed conditions on law emerging that did not need to be there (officials, state,

coercion).

If we just isolate the rules and construct a deductive argument on when they

could logically exist we can see a union theory agrees with Kropotkin and Hayek.

49
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Chapter 6

Locating the Union of Rules

One of the key characteristics of primary rules is that they were static in nature.

They could be changed but only by

“the slow process of growth, whereby courses of conduct once thought


optional became first habitual or usual, and then obligatory, and the
converse process of decay, when deviations, once severely dealt with, are
first tolerated and then pass unnoticed”128

As shown in Chapter 4 this is not in line with the empirical evidence. Primitive

societies change their rules within short time spans. Hart himself accepted that there

may be no human societies that live in a state of primary rules alone.129 But for non-

advanced social creatures this is the only way they can change norms of conduct – it

seems to me that it is a process of biological evolution. Man living in social life never

needs to rely on these slow changes. He or she can implement their own rapid

changes. But animals without the advantage of complex social relations have no

choice but to change their customs and habits over a longer time span. When man

(homo sapien) was in his devolved state as Homo neanderthalensis (‘cave man’;

Neanderthal) perhaps here he lived in a state of primary rules alone. His hunting,

mating, feeding and social relations must have been primitive and would be worthy of

being regulated by Hartian primary rules alone which were static in nature. Homo

neanderthalensis being half way between a true primate and modern man means they

might have had some sort of primary rules which were above animalistic norms, but

far below law. Yet as soon as man evolved and developed more complex social

relations, he had to have law and something that has the functions of secondary rules.

It is important to stress the difference between Hartian secondary rules and the

50
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

functions they perform. To be true Hartian secondary rules they would need officals,

the state and coercion and be a differenet species from primary rules. To be

functionally like secondary rules they would only need to enable changes, settle

disputes over when a rule has been broken and a method of recognising a rule as

authoratitative.

My interpretation of the science show us that as soon as man evolved and

developed complex social relations, he had to have law because he had the functions

of secondary rules. That is why Hart explicitly accepts that perhaps no society lived

in a state of primary rules alone. Hart also knew it was unlikely that any human lived

without secondary rules (and therefore law). We can change that to no homo sapien

society lived in a state of Hartian primary rules alone. It must be remembered the

theory I have posited here is purely theoretical and needs testing empirically.

Unfortunately it is far beyond the scope of this dissertation to attempt to do so.

Positivism and the Autonomy of Law

The ulterior motivation for the desire to confine the law to officials is the

positivist inclination for the autonomy of law. Positivists do not wish the ‘muddy’ the

waters by treating law as a social scientific concept. As has already been argued

views on the autonomy of law are unhelpful. Although in saying that we must come

back to Lacey’s interpretation of the Hart/Devlin debate. I submit her interpretation

has some worrying conclusions for the future of jurisprudence if my argument that

general jurisprudence needs empiricism is correct.

It will be recalled that Lord Devlin forwarded an argument that required

empirical testing. Hart suggested that sociology can never match the test of empirical

51
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

rigour which it sets for itself. Unfortunately Hart is on the whole correct. The events

we are discussing have long since passed us. Even taking an orthodox interpretation

of the union of rules we may be talking anywhere between 6-10,000 years ago. In the

interpretation I presented above in the section marked ‘locating the union of rules’ it

is anywhere in the period of about 230,000 to 29,000 years ago.130 If my argument is

correct in that we need empirical evidence in order to formulate a logical argument in

any general theory of jurisprudence it is perhaps an early death in the empirical

analysis of the origins of law before it has even begun properly. We simply do not

have the information available to help us obtain evidence. The same can be said of

theories of human nature131 as well as origins of law. That does not mean to say all

hope is lost. Archaeologists, anthropologists, sociologists and biologists can help us

but they will never provide definitive answers. Much will be down to conjecture from

shaky empirical data. Unfortunately there is no effective way for jurists to look back

through time like a cosmologist does when he observes the far edges of the universe

through his telescope. In effect there is a lack of evidence and information which may

never be resolved. So theories of general jurisprudence which invariably inquire into

the very origins of law may, unfortunately, be forever stuck in a predominantly

analytical method. All we can effectively do is posit theories using sound arguments

from the available evidence like I have (very briefly) attempted to do in ‘locating the

union of rules’ and test if they are correct using the available evidence.

52
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

Chapter 7

Conclusion

Anarchism while arguably an unrealistic political goal in the current political

climate contributes immeasurable analytical stock to social science research.

Anarchism’s potential reach is much restricted though by its insistence that it does not

require law. This leaves it open to wild accusations that anyone arguing for an

anarchist society is ‘crazy’ or ‘mad’.132 From this dissertation then anarchists can take

away two conclusions especially for those from the anarcho-communist school. Law

exists in Kropotkin’s society there can be no doubt of that. In all his work apart from

Law and Authority he specifically refers to the common law and looks upon it

favourably. His primary rules even have an element of coercion and my arguments

above should be proof enough that it is simply inaccurate to argue that the rules arise

purely from an inbuilt genetic code. The major factor denying his society the status of

law is the lack of state, coercion and officials. As my investigation into anthropology

has found, these are not required for secondary rule functions. Secondary rule

functions can exist in a stateless society and without a monopolising coercive force. It

is only if you define law as being a state phenomena that you can deny the title of law

to Kropotkin’s society. Simply put: all the functions that the secondary rules perform

are present in Kropotkin’s society just without a state and state coercion. The more

sensible conclusion is state law or perhaps even ‘the positivist conception of law’

does not exist in an anarchist society.

Perhaps the fact that an anarchist of the stature of Kropotkin favourably saw

the common law evolve as a societal construct to help social relations will force a

53
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

great deal of anarchist academics to turn their minds to the old questions of

jurisprudence. Future research would especially be useful in the area of exactly how

rules arose. Anarchists by their natural predication would most likely find this a

fruitful research avenue. This can only be a positive influence in legal theory and

perhaps even go far as opening a school of ‘anarchic jurisprudence’. So to answer the

question this dissertation set out to answer: anarcho-Communist societies will have

law.

More significantly to jurists the arguments in my dissertation need to be taken

into account in future work. Jurists must be wary of legal-chauvinism because of the

negative effects it has on a general theory of law. This can most effectively be

stemmed early on by deciding if a theory is going to be essentialist or conventionalist.

Mixing the two causes significant problems as is evident in Concept. Positivism also

needs to relax its insistence on states and officials, such requirements taints any

essentialist character positivism has. Most importantly positivism needs to stop

insisting on its autonomy. Work by Lacey and Tamatha is currently trying to bridge

the gap that has divided sociology and analytical jurisprudence for over half a century

and the work in this dissertation fits into that school. Unfortunately this is not a new

problem ever since Oliver Wendell Holmes Jnr. suggested that in 1897 The Path of

Law133 lawyers should turn to an external discipline (that of economics) to better

understand their profession, the tension between an ‘external legal theory’ as

Dworkin134 puts it and analytical jurisprudence has been manifest. Oliver Wendell

Holmes Jnr, Eugen Ehrlich, Ronald Dworkin, Herbert Hart (at least in 1961), the

entire CLS school, Nicola Lacey, Brian Tamanaha, Freidrich Hayek, Richard Posner

and most Law and Economics scholars and countless more have argued for more

sociology and anthropology in law. It is unlikely that an undergraduate dissertation

54
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

will do much to aid the effort that has with stood devastating analytical barrages

though history. Nonetheless for a logically valid account of general-jurisprudence I

have identified there to be core axioms: human nature and temporal location of when

law/rules exactly arose. If these two variables are to be quantified accurately we need

evidence. However, as my dissertation also shows the there is a problem with

obtaining evidence. While the two schools are currently being merged a division of

labour will always remain. Unfortunately it looks like we will never have a complete

accurate general theory of sociological law; more so, it looks as if theories of general

jurisprudence which aim to be essentialist and apply to all legal systems at all times

will forever be stuck in an analytical school and thus will always be theories of

philosophy not sociology.

55
05212804 An Enquiry into Anarchist Jurisprudence

References

56
1
Kropotkin, Kropotkin's Revolutionary Pamphlets (Kessinger Publishing: 2005)
2
For example, there is a wealth of difference between the anarcho-capitalists, anarcho-individualists, anarcho-minimlists,
anarcho-communists (which Kropotkin is), and anarcho-minimlists. See generally: Anarchist FAQ: Section A.3 ‘What
Types of Anarchism Are There’
3
Proudhon, P-J, What is Property: An Inquiry Into The Principle Of Right And Of Government, William Reeves Bookseller
Ltd., London, 1969, p264
4

Bryan Caplan, Anarchist Theory, online: http://www.wjaz.net/n/html/article.php?sid=24 [emphasis added]


5

Kropotkin, Anarchism: A Collection of Revolutionary Writings, (Courier Dover Publications, 2002), p181 “Modern
Science and Anarchism”
6

Not all socialists are anarchists of course, see generally: An anarchist FAQ Section H - “What are the key differences
between anarchists and Marxists” p26.

Anarcho-capitalists are not socialists but it is debateable whether they are ‘true’ anarchists see generally An anarchist FAQ–
section “Section F - Is "Anarcho"-Capitalism A Type Of Anarchism?”.

**Note: The anarchist FAQ is an outstanding source work on anarchist political philosophy and economics it is over a
thousand pages long, has been constantly redrafted over 10 years and is excellently referenced. It compares all the major
classical anarchists and new ‘eco’ anarchists etc. While it is an online eBook it is an accurate analysis of the subject matter
not found in any text book. The reluctance to publish the works is obviously due to copyright concerns of the original texts
cited in it and the authors political stance (anti profit). So it is freely available on the internet.
7

The term encompasses a wide range of beliefs all linked with a common goal – opposition to hierarchal domination
Ideologies include: anarchism especially anarcho-communism and anarcho-syndicalism, council communism, autonomist
Marxism, and social ecology.
8

Pashukanis, Selected Writings on Marxism and Law (eds. P. Beirne & R. Sharlet), London & New York 1980, p314
[emphasis added]
9

While the labour theory of value is a Marxist theory Kropotkin fully endorses it – “like every anarchist, Kropotkin attacked
the "appropriation of the produce of human labour by the owners of capital," seeing its roots in the fact that "millions of
men have literally nothing to live upon, unless they sell their labour force and their intelligence at a price that will make the
net profit of the capitalist and 'surplus value' possible."” – from anarchist FAQ Section C p17
(http://www.infoshop.org/faq/sectionC.pdf) and see generally Law and Authority IV.
10

E.P Thompson, Whigs and Hunters: The Origins of the Black Act (1975)
11

Cole, An Unqualified Human Good': E.P. Thompson and the Rule of Law, Journal of Law and Society, Vol. 28, No. 2,p181
12

Thompson Op. Cit , p266


13

See generally Daniel Cole’s analysis (note 8)


14

Morton Horwitiz, Adrian Merritt, Robert Fine and others. See Cole Article at n8
15

M.J. Horwitz, 'The Rule of Law: An Unqualified Human Good?' (1977) 86 Yale Law Journal. 561
16

Peter Kropotkin Op. Cit. p218


17

ibid p202
18

Hart, H.L.A., The Concept of Law (Oxford, 1994). Second Edition, p91
19

Peter Kropotkin Op Cit n5 p202 [emphasis added]


20

ibid p205
21

Harold Barclay, Culture and Anarchism, (Freedom Press: 1997). In his chapter ‘Law and Anarchism’ strongly reinforces
this point. Although his grievance was relating to the equating of ‘custom’ to ‘law’ rather than ‘rule’.
22

Concept p91
23

ibid
24

ibid
25

For example “we are not fatalists or genetic determinists, but believe in free will.” [anarchist FAQ Section A p 26] and
Which Way for the Ecology Movement in anarchist FAQ p26
26

Chomsky, Rollback, Z Magazine, Jan 1995, Available online: http://www.chomsky.info/articles/199505--.htm [no page
numbers but see around footnote 25 for the discussion of Kroptokin’s socio-biology]
27

Hobbes, Leviathan¸ Chapter 13 (Penguin Classics:1982) p186


28

Locke, Two Treatises of Government (Cambridge University Press: 1988), p350 (para 123)
29

ibid
30

ibid para 124, p351


31

ibid para 125


32

Concept p91, emphasis added


33

Kropotkin Op Cit n5. p203, emphasis added


34

Concept, p91, emphasis added


35

Kropotkin Op Cit. n5 p202


36

ibid p203
37

ibid p202
38

Concept p93, Hart attacks this form of enforcement as causing “inefficiency” problems, however.
39

ibid p55-56 emphasis in original


40

ibid p56
41

See p48 infra , ‘Politics in Concept’ for a more detailed explanation of the jump from linguistic analysis to sociological.
42

Shelling in, 'Dynamic Models of Segregation' Journal of Mathematical Sociology 1 (1971) p143-186. Uses the example of
a multi-racial street and how it slowly changes so that eventually it is dominated by one ethnicity. The example I have
adapted is far simpler so is methodologically advantageous.
43

See p23-24 supra onwards.


44

Interestingly the tipping point theory also tells us that there are optimum conditions for propagation of a rule. Hence
‘tipping point’; some event or chain of events occurs which means the social, economic, environmental etc. factors are
prime for propagation for the ‘craze’ viz rule.
45
Concept p91-92
46

Theft is shaky ground for an anarchist to object to since they do not have traditional property ideas. However, I have in
mind Kropotkin’s requirement that those who can work but who choose not to be driven out of the community. Since there
is no monetary wage in his envisioned society a type of theft would be to not work while enjoying the fruits of others
labour. See below p25. Kropotkin also uses ‘do not steal’ as a type of custom ‘wrought out a result of life in common’. See
Kropotkin Op Cit p202
47

See Chapter 3 infra


48

Concept Op Cit., p92


49

See Émile Durkheim, Suicide: A Study in Sociology (New York: Free Press, 1951). Durkehim successfully argues that a
reduction in social ties increases suicide rates. Finding the reduction in social ties to be greatest in big cities where there is a
high rate of population turnover. Big cities are the epitome of advancement as in population turnover due to labour market
mobility, a specifically modern neo-classical economic concept. He also argued rapidly industrialising societies are prone to
individualism reducing social ties. Also see generally the theories of ‘mass culture’ and ‘mass society’ which a short
definition is “a society in which industry and bureaucracy have eroded traditional social ties” from: Macionis, J. (1996).
Society: The Basics Chapter 16. (New Jersey: Prentice Hall)
50

Interestingly both Hobbes and Locke use a sort of economic rationale for the rule of law being imposed too. In a state of
nature everyone has a free for all, law needs to arise to bring order. What is order? Allocating goods effectively which
would halt violence.
51

Kropotkin Op. Cit n5. p202


52

See p18-19 supra


53

See p27 for my argument that ‘social pressure’ as Hart termed it could be anything from societal frowning to exclusion.
54

Concpet p94
55

ibid p97
56

ibid p96-97
57

See p32 infra


58

See generally Anarchist FAQ: A.2.11 ‘Why are most anarchists in favour of direct democracy?’ p45 onwards.
59

Hart explicitly argues that primary rules only method of enforcement is ‘diffuse social pressure” Concept p93. Although of
course he criticises this method for being inefficient.
60

Kropotkin’s coercive method of excluding idlers who refuse to work is though societal pressure. See Conquest of Bread
p168-170
61

See below the section entitled ‘From people to Officials’


62

Much of the work cited in this section is based on Cahm’s extracts. C. Cahm, ‘Kropotkin and Law’ in Holterman & Henc
Van Maarseveen, Law and Anarchism (Black Rose Books, Montreal: 1984) p106-121. Cahm cited an early translation of
Anarchism and Science (Baldwin 1912) and my references are to the text as it appears in Anarchism: A Collection of
Revolutionary Writings Op Cit. n5.
63

Op Cit n5
64

ibid, p146
65

ibid, p147
66

ibid [emphasis added]


67

ibid
68

Kropotkin, Mutual Aid, (Kessinger Publishing: 2004) p77 [emphasis added]


69

ibid p150
70

Kropotkin Op. Cit., n5 p203


71

ibid
72

Kropotkin, The Conquest of Bread, (Penguin Press: 1972)


73

ibid p168-70
74

Harold Barclay, Op Cit n21, Chapter 12 “Law and Anarchism”


75

ibid, p154
76

ibid
77

ibid
78

An anarchist FAQ Op. Cit. Section I p217, emphasis in original


79

ibid
80

Although this of course was a criticism for more legal certainty


81

“the maxims which represent principles of morality and social union wrought out as a result of life in common.” Op Cit
n25
82

Brook, The Individualist anarchists: An Anthology of Liberty, (Transaction Publishers: 1994) p160-1
83

Lacey, ‘Analytical Jurisprudence versus Descriptive Sociology Revisited’ (forthcoming, 2006) but available online:
http://www.utexas.edu/law/news/colloquium/papers/NicolaLaceypaper2.doc
84

Cohen ‘The Concept of Law’, Mind, New Series, Vol. 71, No. 283 (Jul., 1962), 395 at 409
85

Malinowski, Crime and Custom in Savage Society, (Routledge: 2001)


86

Diamond, Primitive Law, Past and Present, (Routledge: 2004)


87

Cohen Op Cit p409


88

Malinowski p35
89

Diamond p192
90

Cohen Op Cit n84 p410


91

Note: the thesis of his argument was that the union of rules cannot be given such a high elucidating power as Hart accords
it. His criticism in this quote is rather than being novel, it is mere constitutional law to which he has to be referring.
92

Cohen Op Cit n84 410-411. Note the original text reads: “from a legal to a pre-legal system”. I assume that this is a typo
and have corrected the error in the main body of my text
93

Concept p91
94

Cohen Op Cit n84 p411


95

ibid
96

Geertz, Local Knowledge: Further Essays in Interpretive Anthropology (Basic Books, Inc: New York, 1983) See Chapter 8
‘ Local Knowledge: Fact and Law in Comparative Perspective’ other examples from Fitzpatrick, The Mythology of Modern
Law (Routledge: 1992); Goldsmidt, “Ethics and the Structure of Society: An Ethnological Coontribution to the Sociology of
Knowledge” American Anthropologist 53 1951 – 5-6-524 analysed in Benson, ‘Enforcement of Private Property Rights in
Primitive Societies: Law without Government’, Journal of Libertarian Studies Vol IX No1 (Winter 1989)
97

Benson ibid. Although strictly speaking a ‘libertarian economist’ but an advocate of no state
98

ibid p7 ‘Primary and Secondary Rules Among the Yurok Indians and Their Northern California Neighbours’
99

MacCormick, H.L.A Hart (Edward Arnold :1981) p29


100

Concept p88
101

ibid p57
102

ibid p56
103

ibid p89
104

Idea taken from Fitzpatrick


105

Concept p61-62
106

Fitzpatrick Op Cit n96 p191


107

Concept p60
108

ibid
109

Tamanaha, 'Socio-Legal Positivism and a General Jurisprudence' Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol 21, No 1 1-32 p3
110

Coleman, 'Incorporation, Conventionality, and the Practical Difference Thesis' (1998) 4 Legal Theory 381 p189-90 cited in
Tamanaha p4
111

Concept p17 see also Moore, “Hart’s Concluding Scientific Postcript’ 4 Legal Theory 301-313 p313
112

See generally Tamanaha Op Cit


113

Concept p81
114

ibid
115

p20 supra
116

many legal pluralists have strangely assert society has a multitude of legal institutions with rule making and enforcing
powers, “from corporations to universities, to community associations, and even including little league soccer” ‘Socio-Legal
Positivism and a General Jurisprudence’ Op Cit p6
117

Concept p13-17
118
I assume considering the volume of responses and Lacey’s argument Hart had an idea that his union theory was being
challenged.
119

Lacey Op Cit n83, p7


120

Fitzpatrick Op Cit n96 p194


121

Lacey Op Cit, p10


122

Fitzpatrick Op Cit p195


123

Stark , Sociology With Infotrac (Wadsworth: 2003) p589


124

p44 supra
125

Fuller, The Morality of Law 2nd ed (New Haven and London, Yale University Press: 1969) p193
126

Ketchen, ‘Revising Fuller's Critique of Hart - Mangerial Control and the Pathology of Legal Systems: The Hart-Weber
Nexus’, University of Toronto Law Journal Vol LIII, No1, 2003. Available online:
http://www.utpjournals.com/product/utlj/531/531_ketchen.html
127

Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty, Vol. 1 Rules and Order (University of Chicago Press :1973) p73
128

Concept p92
129

living by primary rules alone is “never perhaps fully realized in any actual community” Concept p93
130

S Alters, Biology: Understanding Life (Jones and Bartlett Publishers: 2000) p559
131

Of course we can posit a current theory of human nature but if we are enquring into the origins of law we have to have a
theory of human nature when law begun.
132

For example on a Political internet message the author frequents this is often the case. Typical examples of counter
arguments include:

“1) If you're in an anarchic country there's no Government and therefore no constitution, and THEREFORE no rights to
uphold.
2) If everyone's doing whatever the [expletive] they like it's going to impinge on your rights anyway.”

“You take away the Government and the police force and no amount of threat of "mutual un-aid" will stop people from
looking, burning, and killing each other.”

From http://www.offspring.com/forums/showthread.php?p=630149
133

I look forward to a time when the part played by history in the explanation of [legal] dogma shall be very small, and instead
of ingenious research we shall spend our energy on a study of the ends sought to be attained and the reasons for desiring
them. As a step toward that ideal it seems to me that every lawyer ought to seek an understanding of economics. Holmes,
The Path of Law, (Kessinger Publishing: 2004), p17
134

Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire (Hart Publishing: 1998) p75


Bibliography
Alters, Biology: Understanding Life (Jones and Bartlett Publishers: 2000)

Barclay, Culture and Anarchism, (Freedom Press: 1997)

Brook, The Individualist anarchists: An Anthology of Liberty, (Transaction Publishers: 1994)

Caplan, Anarchist Theory, online: http://www.wjaz.net/n/html/article.php?sid=24 [accessed 10/03/06]

Chomsky, Rollback, Z Magazine, Jan 1995, Available online:


http://www.chomsky.info/articles/199505--.htm [accessed 10/03/06]

Cohen, ‘The Concept of Law’, Mind, New Series, Vol. 71, No. 283 (Jul., 1962), 395

Cole, An Unqualified Human Good': E.P. Thompson and the Rule of Law, Journal of Law and Society,
Vol. 28, No. 2, 181

Coleman, 'Incorporation, Conventionality, and the Practical Difference Thesis' (1998) 4 Legal Theory
381 p189-90

Diamond, Primitive Law, Past and Present, (Routledge: 2004)

Durkheim, Suicide: A Study in Sociology (New York: Free Press, 1951)

Dworkin, Law’s Empire (Hart Publishing: 1998)

Fitzpatrick, The Mythology of Modern Law (Routledge: 1992)

Fuller, The Morality of Law 2nd ed (New Haven and London, Yale University Press: 1969)
Geertz, Local Knowledge: Further Essays in Interpretive Anthropology (Basic Books, Inc: New York,
1983)

Hart, H.L.A., The Concept of Law (Oxford: 1994). Second Edition

Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty, Vol. 1 Rules and Order (University of Chicago Press :1973) p73

Hobbes, Leviathan¸ (Penguin Classics:1982)

Holterman, T., & van Maarseveen Law and Anarchism (Black Rose Books, Montreal: 1984)

Horwitz, 'The Rule of Law: An Unqualified Human Good?' (1977) 86 Yale Law Journal 561

Ketchen, ‘Revising Fuller's Critique of Hart - Mangerial Control and the Pathology of Legal Systems:
The Hart-Weber Nexus’, University of Toronto Law Journal Vol LIII, No1, 2003. Available online:
http://www.utpjournals.com/product/utlj/531/531_ketchen.html [accessed 10/03/06]

Kropotkin, Anarchism: A Collection of Revolutionary Writings, (Courier Dover Publications, 2002),

Kropotkin, Kropotkin's Revolutionary Pamphlets (Kessinger Publishing: 2005)

Kropotkin, Mutual Aid, (Kessinger Publishing: 2004)

Kropotkin, The Conquest of Bread, (Penguin Press: 1972)

Lacey, ‘Analytical Jurisprudence versus Descriptive Sociology Revisited’ (forthcoming, 2006) but
available online: http://www.utexas.edu/law/news/colloquium/papers/NicolaLaceypaper2.doc [accessed
10/03/06]

Locke, Two Treatises of Government (Cambridge University Press: 1988)

MacCormick, H.L.A Hart (Edward Arnold :1981)

Macionis, Society: The Basics Chapter 16. (Prentice Hall: 1996)

Malinowski, Crime and Custom in Savage Society, (Routledge: 2001)

Moore, “Hart’s Concluding Scientific Postcript’ 4 Legal Theory 301-313

Multiple Authors, An Anarchist FAQ, available online: http://www.infoshop.org/faq/pdf.html [accessed


10/03/06]

Pashukanis, Selected Writings on Marxism and Law (eds. P. Beirne & R. Sharlet), London & New York
1980

Proudhon, What is Property: An Inquiry Into The Principle Of Right And Of Government,

William Reeves Bookseller Ltd., London, 1969


Shelling, 'Dynamic Models of Segregation' Journal of Mathematical Sociology 1 (1971) 143-186

Stark , Sociology With Infotrac (Wadsworth: 2003)


Tamanaha, 'Socio-Legal Positivism and a General Jurisprudence' Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol
21, No 1 1-32

Thompson, Whigs and Hunters: The Origins of the Black Act (1975)

Potrebbero piacerti anche