Sei sulla pagina 1di 8

LOUISE BARRETT Beyond the Brain: How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds.

Louise Barrett, Beyond the Brain: How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds, Princeton University Press, 2011. 270 pages, ISBN: 978-0691-12644-9, $28.61. Reviewed by Mirko Farina, ARC Centre of Excellence in Cognition and its Disorders (CCD), Institute of Human Cognition and Brain Science (IHCBS), Macquarie University Sydney, Australia. Beyond the Brain: How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds is an eye-opening and thought-provoking book that sets out a much-needed contribution to the study of the relationship between animals, cognition and the environment. The volume provides remarkable new insights into how to understand animal (including human) behavior, raises interesting questions about the role of environmental affordances in the emergence of complex cognitive processes and provides the reader with a refreshing break from the wearisome excess of brain-centric literature that still pervades much of the debate surrounding evolutionary psychology. In embracing the theoretical framework endorsed by proponents of embodied cognition, Barrett adopts an ecological approach to psychology that aims at challenging any attempt to describe complex thinking and flexible behavior as mere by-products of internal cognitive activity. Ecological approaches in psychology typically provide a powerful and coherent alternative to standard information-processing paradigms [see Marr (1982); Poggio (1981) just to name a few], that postulate the existence of distinct and hierarchical theoretical levels to understand complex information-processing tasks such as visual perception. [Rowlands (2006), p.8]. Ecological approaches resist these computational understandings of visual perception and rather explain perceiving as an achievement of the individual, not an appearance in the theater of his consciousness; as a keeping-in-touch- with the world and experiencing of things rather than a having of experiences; as an awareness-of instead of just awareness. Perceiving, they continue, may be awareness of something in the environment or something in the observer or both at once, but there is no content of awareness independent of that of which one is aware. [Gibson (1979), p.239]. On these accounts, visual perception is not therefore the mere reception of stimuli from the environment followed by the construction of internal representations, but rather an active sampling of the optic array, driven by environmental affordances1, that allows an animal to discover the information present in the world. (p.106). In endorsing this Gibsonian perspective, Barrett successfully merges and deeply interweaves different disciplines (ranging from ethology and ecological psychology to artificial intelligence, robotics and philosophy) to create an interdisciplinary space for the study of the evolution of cognition that
1

Affordances are the terms in which perceptual information is made available.

ultimately calls into question any orthodox, brain-bounded, purely intracranialist understanding of the nature of the human mind. Barretts criticism is essentially directed at those views that deny any possibility of bodybrain integration. Such views, she notices, find both their communal ancestor and their theoretical justification in the conceptual palette provided by Cartesianism2. Cartesianism is the idea, affecting much of modern psychology, that the mind is separated from the corporal body and entirely in control of it. In this book, Barrett powerfully questions Cartesianism by presenting a compelling bulk of empirical evidence that shows how heavily animals and humans rely on their bodies and milieus to behave intelligently. The main scope of the volume is therefore to demonstrate that: 1) the brain isnt the sole locus of intelligence and 2) that there isnt, properly speaking, such a thing as a naked brain- an isolated mental substance that dominates the physical from above. A related goal of the book is also to prove that our knowledge cannot be entirely derived, through reason and thinking, from a set of constrained innate ideas but that it rather emerges in the interplay between brain, body and the wider world. To the extent that the book unveils these erroneous conceptions of the mental, it also encourages us to drop our anthropomorphic stance by revealing that intelligent behavior is always profoundly influenced and directly governed by physical and socio-cultural circumstances in a way that has lead both Paul Maclean (1949) and William Blessing (1997) to talk of a visceral brain. For this reason, Barretts book can be taken as a refreshing antidote for anyone who is troubled by old-fashioned tendencies that attempt to describe the human brain as a Swiss army knife, [Cosmides & Tooby (1992)]; a collection of highly modular, domain-specific computational tools. [Fodor (1975, 2008); Pinker (2003), Byrne & Bates (2006) ]. In line with a long-established tradition of writings in phenomenology [see Heidegger (1927 trans. 1962) and Merleau Ponty for (1945 trans. 1962) for instance] and in agreement with more recent works in the cognitive sciences [such as Clark (1997, 2008), Menary (2007), Rowlands(2010), Sutton (2010),Wheeler (forthcoming)] that describe the brain as an integral and inseparable part of the complex loop that accompanies the formation of mental states; Beyond the Brain therefore contributes to further illustrate the importance of the Umvelt the wider world as it is experienced by a particular organism [von Uexkll (1957)]- for the emergence of complex cognitive strategies and successful adaptations. The volume is organized in eleven chapters centering, as we have seen above, around one main theme: the Gibsonian idea that environmental affordances are crucial for the emergence of our cognitive functions. In the course of this review I have already presented standard ecological approaches and quickly explained how they follow Gibson in taking the environment to be the richest source of information we can directly access through perception-action cycles. In what remains of this review I will now try to provide the reader with a full

John Sutton has written a fair bit about how Descartes did allow for this kind of body-brain integration. In Suttons view; modern forms of Cartesianism must be intended as deviations from the Magisters Dictum because they have failed to keep abreast of the spirit of his philosophy. So, Cartesianism would interestingly be not true to the spirit of Descartes! For more specific details see Sutton (1998) and Gaukroger, S., Schuster, J., & Sutton, J. (2000). Thanks to Julian Kiverstein for the hint.

sense of Barretts project by condensing, in a page or two, the most important contents of the volume. In chapters 1 and 2 Barrett mounts a sustained attack on chauvinistic forms of anthropomorphism. Anthropomorphism is basically the attribution of human characteristic to gods, animals, weather(in this case is called pathetic fallacy) or inanimate objects3.Through a series of compelling empirical examples (involving facial recognition in babies [Kanwisher et al. (1997); Gauthier et al. (2000)] and social intelligence in apes [Brothers et al. (1992); Perrett (1999); Barton (2006)], Barrett invites us to renounce our anthropomorphic perspective by demonstrating how, in investigating cognition, a strictly human-centered perspective is not only undesirable but also wrong both theoretically and empirically. This kind of chauvinistic anthropomorphism should be abandoned, Barrett argues, because it invites us to ask scientific questions that simply reflect our own concerns (p.3) and therefore encourages us to think that other creatures are interesting only to the extent that they resemble us (p.5). In essence, in the first chapters of her book, Barrett attempts to resist the idea that the whole of evolution was crafted to produce us as the most supreme creature and rather tries to establish the claim that anthropocentrism is a hazardous bias that considerably endangers scientific enquiry. Chapters 3 ,4 5 are principally devoted to explore and appreciate how much a small brain can achieve. The goal of these chapters is therefore to prevent another bias, what Barrett labels as the big head bias the idea that a big brain can allow us for an assumption of superiority over creatures that possess vastly smaller and less developed brains than ours. Barrett calls into question this idea and effectively demonstrates that there is no connection between the complexity of an observed behavior, and the complexity of the mechanism that produced it. As evidence for this claim, she adduces two interesting examples: 1) the fertile turtles and 2) the behavior of Portia spiders, which she discusses in ch.3 and 4 respectively. In the early 50s, in order to test the idea that complexity of brain functions doesnt necessarily arise from the number of neurons but rather emerges from the richness of their interconnections [Holland (2003)], neurophysiologist and robotics pioneer Grey Walter built two motorized robots (Elsie and Elmer) that looked like tortoises. These tortoises had only two brain cells, which could produce one reflex response each; one for the light, the other for touch. The sensor for detecting the light was a photoelectric cell mounted on the front of the steering column of the robot, the touch sensor was instead an electrical contact that was turned off whenever the shell of the tortoise encountered an obstacle. (p.43). These tortoises could only work in two modalities: 1) seeking light; 2) moving towards it. Despite their relatively simple architectures, these robots, once freed in the environment, were able to explore the surroundings by slowly moving in a series of arches, detecting and hurrying towards sources of light and avoiding or pushing obstacles around. They were also reported, when placed in front of a mirror, to flicker, twitter and jig like clumsy Narcissuses [Grey Walter (1951, 1953)], in a sort of mating dance that led many to attribute them what would have normally been accepted, if observed in living animals, as evidence of self3

For a series of interesting studies see: Guthrie (1997); Datson & Mitman (2005); Horowitz (2007)]. For more popular treatments see also: [Patten (2006) and Myers (2008)].

awareness. Without any kind of internal, programmed knowledge or computerlike structure, these tortoises were able to exhibit remarkably complex behaviors and these emerged as a direct result of their interaction with the environment. Barrett uses the tortoises example to show that sometimes the structure of the environment and the physical shape of the animals body can play a highly active role in forging and moulding adaptive strategies4. Analogous results are also observed in the animal kingdom. In chapter 4, Barrett takes us into a fascinating journey in the world of spiders and invites us to focus on the behavior of the Portia. Portia spiders are spiders that have brains with the size of a pin, yet this doesnt impede them to exhibit one of the most complex and flexible hunting behavior displayed in the animal kingdom. Portia spiders in fact, while chasing their prey, successfully engage in a series of intricate stalking strategies (including aggressive mimicry, detouring to break visual contact and smoked-screen behavior), that have led many scientists to accept the idea that they behave intelligently, being capable of learning on the fly and of deploying complex hunting tactics. [Wilcox & Jackson (2002); Ross (2007)]. Again, Barrett uses the case of Portia spiders to further demonstrate that articulated behavior isnt necessarily tied to big brains but may indeed be triggered by relatively simple internal mechanisms responding to complex environments. Chapters 6,7,8 and 9 are probably the most crucial in the book, as they are used to introduce, critically assess and ultimately endorse the case for the ecological approach in psychology that Barrett wants to establish. Though crucial, this isnt however the only key-theme that span across these four chapters. Additional topics worth a mention are those that relate to other important aspects of embodied approaches to cognition [such as the critique of classical computationalism conducted through the analysis of the so-called Watt governor metaphor (Van Gelder 1995) and through the idea of softassembly. (Thelen & Smith (1994)]. The Watt governor metaphor is a metaphor used by Barrett to attack the brain as a computer analogy- the idea that our brains work in the same way as digital computers work by means of symbolic manipulations carried out by dedicated mechanisms or pre-specified modules. The Watt-governor was introduced by the Australian philosopher Tim van Gelder (1995) as an alternative metaphor better able to capture the dynamic interactions between animals and the surrounding world. Cognition, in his view, is described as a dynamical process arising when, inputs, internal processes and outputs are tightly coupled like the spindle, angle arm, and throttle valve in the centrifugal governor (p.129-130). Barrett takes dynamical approaches to be in competition with computational accounts of brain function but this opposition may well be more apparent than real. Clark (2008) and Wheeler (2005) in fact both talk of dynamical computationalism. Dynamical
4

This seems to provide nice empirical evidence for what Mark Rowland (1999) has called the barking dog principle:If it is necessary for an organism to be able to perform a given adaptive task T, then it is differentially selectively disadvantageous for that organism to develop internal mechanisms sufcient for the performance of T when it is possible for the organism to perform T by way of a combination of internal mechanisms and manipulation of the external environment [Rowlands (1999), p.80]. This principle is very similar to the 007 principle formulated by Clark in 1989. It is important to note that the 007 principle has been consistently used, in the literature directed at the extended mind thesis, to endorse the case of cognitive extension. For an interesting analysis of the relationships between the two see [Shapiro (2010)].

computationalism, they argue, is a view that merges dynamical systems theory with old-fashioned computationalism and asserts that in order to provide with the right kinds of temporal coordination needed to trigger the temporally rich adaptive behaviors typical of forms of higher cognition, the brain needs to span the body-world boundaries creating crossing architectures that encompass these two realms. The other important point that Barrett tries to make in these central chapters of her book is related with the idea that embodied systems are preferable to classical computational systems because they can express more variability. In order to illustrate this point Barrett introduces the idea of soft-assembly. Softlyassembled systems are provisionally assembled units working in the service of successful phenotypic transmission. They are made up via temporary bioecological operations of assemblage that occur between neural and non-neural resources and are characterized by operations that deal with specific problems arising in the course of ones experience. Softly-assembled systems are richly variable systems that act as pacemakers and rhythm-setters [Wheeler (2005)] to couple an animal with its own world. These systems are systems in which there is no central controller and no planning and according to Thelen and Smith(1994), they should be taken as the defining feature of a dynamical account of development. Barrett deploys the idea of soft-assembly in the context of human babies (ch.10), to show that 1) our knowledge is tailored to the specific environment we encounter (p.176), and 2) to demonstrate that the environment is an equal partner in producing cognitive behavior. [Clark (1997)]. The book ends (ch.11) with a final chapter in which Barrett discusses the idea of the body schema and the incorporation of tools. In recalling a series of studies involving the plasticity of the body schema (Iriki et al. (1996), Maravita & Iriki (2004)], Barrett focuses on the negotiability of our own bodies and tries to demonstrate that organism are always mutually entangled with their environments and do not stand apart from them as some kind of hermetically sealed, disembodied cognisers. (p.200). Although I am very sympathetic with this line of argument [see Kiverstein and Farina (in preparation)], in this book Barrett fails to address and rule out alternative and competing approaches (such as the embedded view), that invites us to distinguish the fairly acceptable claim that incorporation yields new agentworld circuits, entangled and re-engineered bio-mechanical architectures; from the more radical assumption that buys the inference to extended cognition and therefore envisages literal cognitive extension. In particular, Rupert (2009, ch.8) grants the existence of the former but gives an embedded account of cases of incorporation on the grounds of his notion of brain-centred realisers of the body schema. Barrett surprisingly doesnt discuss this objection. To conclude. The impressive sheer of wealth and breadth of information presented in this book combined with a charming and engaging prose, makes this volume very enjoyable reading. Beyond the Brain is indeed an amusing and entertaining read, but one with an extraordinary analytical rigor and eloquence of argument. Very accessible, enticing and lucidly written it can be enjoyed both by professional academics and laypeople. Readersbe they novice or seasonedwill certainly find the volume uplifting and inspirational, Barretts style brisk and delightful and her intellectual playfulness quite solacing. An intriguing, illuminating, very ambitious and stylish book that will

zealously and passionately set the stage for the next round of academic speculations by becoming an essential source of discussion for some time to come. A must read for the next generations of cognitive scientists and for all those who are interested in the study of comparative cognition. Acknowledgements I am deeply indebted to Julian Kiverstein and John Sutton for their continuous guidance and invaluable support throughout my doctoral studies. My warmest gratitude also goes to Andy Clark and Richard Menary for their stimulating feedback on earlier drafts of this review. Thanks also to Joel Krueger for the precious assistance through the editorial process. Last but not least, I would like to express my appreciation to the ARC Centre of Excellence in Cognition and its Disorders (CCD) and to Macquarie University for generously financing my research. Needless to say, any remaining errors are mine and mine alone.

References
Barton, R.A. (2006). Primate Brain Evolution: integrating comparative, neuropsychological and ethological data. Evolutionary Anthropology, 15, pp.224-236. Blessing, W. (1997). The Lower Brainstem and Bodily Homeostasis. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Brothers, L., Ring, B., & Kling, A. (1992). Response in neurons in the macaque amygdala to complex social stimuli. Behavioral Brain Research, 41, pp.199-213. Byrne, R.W., & Bates, L. (2006). Why are animals cognitive?. Current Biology, 16, R445-R448. Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action and Cognitive Extension. Oxford,UK: Oxford University Press. Clark, A. (1989). Microcognition: Philosophy, Cognitive Science and Parallel Distributed Processing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Clark, A. (1997), Being there: putting brain, body, and world together again, Cambridge: MIT Press. Cosmides, L. & Tooby, J. (1992). The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture. New York: Oxford University Press. Datson, L., & Mitman, G. (2005). Thinking with animals: New perspectives on anthropomorphism. New York: Oxford University Press. Fodor, J.A. (2008). LOT2: The Language of Thought Revisited. Oxford University Press, USA. Fodor, J.A. (1975). The Language of Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Gaukroger, S., Schuster, J., Sutton, J. (2000). Descartes Natural Philosophy. Routledge.

Gauthier, I., Skudlaski, P., Gore, J.C., & Anderson, A.W. (2000). Expertise for cars and birds recruits brain areas involved in face recognition. Nature Neuroscience, 3, pp.191-197. Gibson, J.J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Grey Walter, W. (1951). A machine that learns. Scientific American, 185, pp.60-63. Grey Walter, W. (1953). The Living Brain. W.W. Norton, New York. Guthrie, S. E. (1997). Anthropomorphism: A definition and a theory. In Mitchell, R.W., Thompson, N.S., & Miles, H.L.(Eds.). Anthropomorphism, anecdotes, and animals. (pp. 50-58). Albany, NY: State University New York Press. Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and Time. London: SCM. Holland, O. (2003). The first biologically inspired robot. Robotica, 21, pp. 351-363. Horowitz, A. (2007). Anthropomorphism. In Bekoff, M. (Eds.). Encyclopedia of Human-Animal Relationships, (pp 60-66). Greenwood Publishing Group, Westport, CT. Iriki, A., Tanaka, M., & Iwamura, Y. (1996). Coding of Modified Body Schema during Tool use by Macaque Postcentral Neurones. NeuroReport, 7, pp. 2325-2330. Kanwisher, N. McDermott, J., & Chun, M. (1997). The fusiform face area: a module in human extrastriate cortex specialised for the perception of faces. Journal of Neuroscience, 17, pp. 4302-4311. Kiverstein, J., & Farina, M. (in preparation). Integration and The Extended Mind Thesis (Provisional Title). MacLean, P.D. (1949) Psychosomatic disease and the visceral brain: recent developments bearing on the Papez theory of emotion. Psychosom Med., 11, pp. 338 353. Maravita, A., & Iriki, A. (2004). Tools for the Body (Schema). Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, pp. 79-86. Marr, D. C. (1982). Vision: A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Visual Information. New York: Freeman. Menary, R.(2007), Cognitive Integration: Mind and Cognition Unbounded, New York: Palgrave Macmillian. Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of Perception. New York: Humanities Press, 1962. Myers, B. (10 June 2008). Why we are all animal lovers. The Guardian. Retrieved 6 May 2010. Patten, F. (2006). Furry! The World's Best Anthropomorphic Fiction. ibooks. pp. 427 436. Perrett, D.I. (1999) A cellular basis for reading minds from faces and actions. In Hauser, M., & Konishi, M. (Eds.), Behavioral and Neural Mechanisms of Communication. (pp.159-185). Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

Pinker, S. (2003). How the Mind Works. Penguin, London. Poggio, T. (1981). Marrs Computational Approach to Vision. Trends in Neurosciences, 10, pp. 258-262. Ross, P. (2007). Extraordinary Animals: An Encyclopedia of Curious and Unusual Animals. Greenwood Publishing Group, Westport, CT. Rowlands, M. (2010), The new science of the mind: from extended mind to embodied phenomenology, Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. Rowlands, M. (2006). Against Methodological Solipsism: The Ecological Approach. Philosophical Psychology, 8 (1), pp.5-20. Rowlands, M. (1999), The body in mind: understanding cognitive processes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rupert, R. (2009). Cognitive Systems and the Extended Mind. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Shapiro, L. (2010). James Bond and The Barking Dog: Evolution and Extended Cognition. Philosophy of Science, 77, pp. 400-418. Sutton, J. (2010), 'Exograms and Interdisciplinarity: history, the extended mind, and the civilizing process, in Richard Menary (eds). The Extended Mind. (pp. 189-225). MIT Press. Sutton, J. (1998). Philosophy and Memory Traces: Descartes to Connectionism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Thelen, E., Smith, L.(1994). A Dynamic Systems Approach to the Development of Cognition and Action. Cambridge, MA. MIT Press. Van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? Journal of Philosophy, 92, pp.435-381. Von Uexkll, J. (1957). A stroll through the worlds of animals and men. In Shiller, C.H., & Lashley, K.S. (Eds.). Instinctive Behavior: The Development of a Modern Concept. (pp.5-82). International Universities Press, Madison, Conn. (Original work published in 1934). Wheeler, M.(forthcoming). Extended X: Recarving the Biological and Cognitive Joints of Nature. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the Cognitive World: the Next Step. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. Wilcox, S., & Jackson, R. (2002). "Jumping Spider Tricksters". In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G.M.. (Eds.). The Cognitive Animal: Empirical and Theoretical Perspectives on Animal Cognition. (pp. 27-34). Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

Potrebbero piacerti anche