Sei sulla pagina 1di 38

Mason_62-HLJ-559.

doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

The Un-Creation of Rights:


An Argument Against
Administrative Disclaimers

Josephine K. Mason*

Boilerplate disclaimers appear with some frequency in administrative regulations, yet


there has been a striking absence of discussion as to their validity. This Note argues that
administrative disclaimers threaten two key constitutional concerns inherent in
administrative law—proper government structure and fairness to individuals—and that
courts should therefore approach administrative disclaimers with a high degree of
skepticism.

* J.D. Candidate 2011, University of California, Hastings College of the Law; B.A., Linguistics,
University of California, Berkeley. I would like to thank Professor Evan Lee, Professor Chimène
Keitner, Julia Harumi Mass, Andre Segura, and Matthew Ritchie for their invaluable feedback in the
early stages of this Note. I would also like to thank my family as well as Ian Ellis for their tremendous
support and guidance throughout the writing process.

[559]
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

560 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

Table of Contents
Introduction................................................................................................ 560 
I. Judicial Review, Private Rights of Action, and Agencies’
Duties Under ACCARDI .................................................................... 565 
A.  The ACCARDI Imperative ........................................................... 566 
1.  Background .......................................................................... 566
2.  The Theoretical Basis of Accardi ....................................... 570
a.  Accardi Rights, Duties, and Remedies ........................ 570
b.  Accardi as Constitutional Common Law.................... 572
B.  Three Roads to Court: Procedural Alternatives to
ACCARDI ....................................................................................... 575 
1.  Implied Private Right of Action to Challenge
Regulatory Violations.......................................................... 576
2.  Judicial Review Vel Non of Agency Action ...................... 578
II. The Case Against Administrative Carte Blanche ........................ 580 
A.  A New Look at Administrative Accountability ............... 580 
B.  Disclaimers as Inherently Suspect: The Normative
Case ............................................................................................ 584 
C.  Unlawful Immigration Practices and the Boilerplate
Disclaimer ................................................................................. 587 
Conclusion .................................................................................................. 595 

Introduction
In 2009, a coalition of immigrants’ rights organizations sued the
federal government, alleging that Immigration and Customs
Enforcement (ICE) agents were summarily rounding up and detaining
1
immigrants in violation of immigration regulations. Specifically, the
coalition, in Committee for Immigrant Rights of Sonoma County v.

1. See Second Amended Complaint at 16–20, Comm. for Immigrant Rights of Sonoma Cnty. v.
Cnty. of Sonoma, No. 08-4220, 2010 WL 841372 (N.D. Cal. Sept. 14, 2009). According to the
complaint, the Committee’s membership includes “persons who have been and/or are imminently
susceptible to defendants’ unlawful practices, as well as family members of such persons.” Id. at 2. In
ruling on the original Sonoma complaint, the Northern District of California ruled that the
organization had both representational and organizational standing. See Comm. for Immigrant Rights
of Sonoma Cnty. v. Cnty. of Sonoma, 644 F. Supp. 2d 1177, 1193–96 (N.D. Cal. 2009). The named
defendants included Sonoma County, individual county sheriffs, the United States, the Department of
Homeland Security, the Bureau of Immigration and Customs Enforcement, and individual ICE agents
in their individual and official capacities. Sonoma Complaint, supra, at 1. Although both federal claims
and pendant state law claims were presented in the case, this Note will focus only on select federal
claims and therefore, on only the federal defendants.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 561

County of Sonoma, accused agents of detaining suspected undocumented


immigrants based on their race or surnames alone and jailing them for up
2
to four days without notice of the charges against them. According to
the complaint, the agents routinely failed to give the detainees notice of
their rights under immigration regulations, including their right to a
hearing and counsel and their right to post bond, even though agents are
3
required to do so under the regulations in 8 C.F.R. § 287. Without such
notification, detainees were more easily coerced into waiving their rights
and making inculpatory statements that could be used against them in
4
deportation proceedings.
5
The coalition alleged that ICE’s routine treatment of detainees
6
violated their constitutional and statutory rights. Additionally, the
coalition sought to enjoin the government from continuing to violate its
7
own immigration regulations.
The U.S. District Court for the Northern District of California held
that while the coalition could challenge freestanding statutory and
constitutional violations, the plaintiffs could not sustain a claim based
8
purely upon the agency’s violation of its own regulations. The court
indicated that the claim was barred by boilerplate language included in a
9
disclaimer found in section 287 of the regulations. The disclaimer reads
in relevant part: “[t]hese regulations do not, are not intended to, shall not
be construed to, and may not be relied upon to create any rights,
substantive or procedural, enforceable at law by any party in any matter,
10
civil or criminal.”
In so holding, the court did not meaningfully address why the
disclaimer should be binding. Rather, the court took the disclaimer at
face value, an approach that has two overlapping effects: It eliminates the
immigrant-plaintiffs’ right to challenge the agency’s non-adherence to its
own regulations, and it eliminates judicial review of the agency’s action.

2. Sonoma Complaint, supra note 1, at 11–12, 24.


3. Id.
4. Id. at 13. Some, but not all, of the plaintiffs’ statements had been used against them in
deportation proceedings. Others had successfully excluded the statements in their hearings. Both
groups were seeking, inter alia, injunctive relief against such ICE practices. Id. passim.
5. Until recently, immigration matters were handled by the Immigration and Naturalization
Service (INS). In 2003, the Department of Homeland Security (DHS) took over immigration matters
and established ICE in place of the INS. Homeland Security Act of 2002, Pub L. No. 107-296, 116 Stat.
2135 (codified primarily in scattered sections of 6 & 18 U.S.C.). This Note will refer to ICE and INS
interchangeably, depending on the context in which the organization is discussed.
6. Sonoma Complaint, supra note 1, at 2.
7. Id.
8. Comm. for Immigrant Rights of Sonoma Cnty. v. Sonoma Cnty., No. C 08-4220 PJH, 2010
WL 841372, at *1, *6 (N.D. Cal. Mar. 10, 2010).
9. Id. at *6. As of the time this Note went to print, the case had gone on to discovery.
10. 8 C.F.R. § 287.12 (2009).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

562 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

11
This was the first court within the Ninth Circuit to apply the disclaimer,
and it is one of only five cases to consider the effect of the disclaimer
since its passage in 1994. The only other published cases considering the
issue were in the First Circuit, which also adopted the disclaimers
12
without any meaningful scrutiny.
Although courts have extensively addressed the issue of boilerplate
disclaimers in other legal contexts, particularly in contracts and
commercial transactions, there is a dearth of analysis surrounding
administrative disclaimers. Boilerplate disclaimers do appear with some
13
frequency in the Code of Federal Regulations, yet courts have seemed
14
at a loss for how to deal with them. In the few cases where such a
disclaimer has come up, courts have tended to take it at face value. Given
that courts regularly approach boilerplate disclaimers in other legal
contexts with skepticism, this discrepancy is striking.
In this Note, I propose that courts should consider most boilerplate
administrative disclaimers to be invalid when they attempt to abrogate
substantive rights. Specifically, I argue that disclaimers cannot validly
apply to regulations that are intended to benefit individuals or which
affect the liberty interests of individuals, as opposed to rules or
regulations regarding internal agency matters. I suggest a framework for
approaching administrative disclaimers that draws together principles of
judicial review, the federal common law doctrine of implied private
rights of action, and the well-established Accardi principle, which

11. The Ninth Circuit requested that the Board of Immigration Appeals (BIA) clarify its position
with regard to the effect of the regulations, but as of yet, the BIA does not appear to have issued a
decision as to what 8 C.F.R. § 287.3 requires. 8 C.F.R. § 287.3 (2009); see also de Rodriguez-Echeverria
v. Mukasey, 534 F.3d 1047, 1052 (9th Cir. 2008) (remanding to the BIA for guidance on how to
interpret section 287.3 in light of section 287.12). The case on remand has not appeared on the BIA’s
2009 or 2010 docket, although note that the BIA is not required to publish all of its opinions. Bd. of
Immigration Appeals Practice Manual § 1.4(d) (2004).
12. See Navarro-Chalan v. Ashcroft, 359 F.3d 19, 23 (1st Cir. 2004); Yongo v. INS, 355 F.3d 27, 31
(1st Cir. 2004). The only other case to apply 8 C.F.R. § 287.12 was an unpublished decision by the BIA.
Alessandra de Paula, No. A96 414 623, 2007 WL 2074418 (BIA June 18, 2007) (unpublished).
13. See 10 C.F.R. § 1049.10 (2009) (internal security guidance to officers of the strategic petroleum
reserve); 14 C.F.R. § 1203b.109 (2009) (internal security guidance for NASA security forces); 15 C.F.R.
§ 15.11 (2009) (policies and procedures governing employer testimony and the production of
documents in Department of Commerce legal proceedings); 28 C.F.R. § 0.123 (2009) (general powers
of the DOJ Special Counsel); 28 C.F.R. § 0.17 (internal DOJ guidance); 28 C.F.R. § 600.10 (2009)
(internal organization of the DOJ); 32 C.F.R. § 152.5 (2009) (implementation guidance of the review
of the manual for courts-martial). Courts have not had the opportunity to examine the validity these
regulatory disclaimers.
14. A few regulatory disclaimers have been at issue in litigation, but courts have applied them at
virtually face value. See In re Grand Jury Subpoena, Judith Miller, 438 F.3d 1141, 1152, 1170–74 (D.C.
Cir. 2006) (DOJ prosecutorial discretion); United States v. Myers, 123 F.3d 350, 354–55 (6th Cir. 1997)
(DOJ letter to the target of an investigation); Cal-Almond, Inc. v. USDA, 14 F.3d 429, 443 (9th Cir.
1993) (review of USDA rulemaking); Michigan v. Thomas, 805 F.2d 176, 187 (6th Cir. 1986)
(environmental impact analysis); United States v. Donaldson, 493 F. Supp. 2d 998, 1001–02 (S.D. Ohio
2006) (FBI target letter).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 563

15
requires agencies to follow their own regulations. Broadly speaking, I
propose that these principles taken together mean that when an agency
does not follow its own regulations, those who are negatively impacted
should be able to seek review in court, even if there is no explicit private
right of action provided in the relevant regulation. Administrative
disclaimers implicate two twin constitutional concerns: individual due
process and federal structural coherence. Such concerns cannot be so
easily brushed aside. Under this framework, I argue that the Sonoma
court erred in dismissing the plaintiffs’ request for injunctive relief
against the agency. By holding otherwise, courts are giving agency
officials a virtual carte blanche for their actions, denying those affected
by rogue agency action the opportunity to challenge their treatment in
court.
Agencies may put forth a facially plausible rationale for such a
disclaimer—for instance, agencies are free to engage in rulemaking, and
therefore, have the power to decide which of their own regulations are
binding, or that such disclaimers are necessary for administrative
efficiency and convenience. However, upon closer examination, these
arguments are fundamentally unsound, fly in the face of venerable
precedent, and lead to unjust results. As I discuss, this is especially true
in cases like Sonoma, where the court’s uncritical application of the
disclaimer renders the regulatory safeguards a nullity and makes
immigrants even more vulnerable to misconduct and abuse. Granted,
administrative disclaimers may be appropriate when it comes to strictly
internal regulations, because administrative efficiency and convenience
are valid concerns in that context. However, when it comes to the
substantive rights and liberty interests of individuals, abrogation of those
rights cannot be justified by mere administrative convenience. When it
comes to regulations that affect individuals, agencies must rationally
justify any deviation from their own rules, and a boilerplate disclaimer is
no justification at all.
In Part I, I provide a legal backdrop for analyzing administrative
disclaimers, including administrative agencies’ duties and the right of
affected individuals to challenge an agency action that deviates from the
agency’s regulations. I find two common concerns underlying
administrative authority—structural concerns, in other words, those
regarding the proper delegation of power among branches of
government, and fairness concerns, that is, those regarding the effect
16
upon individuals. I first explicate the Accardi doctrine, under which

15. United States ex rel. Accardi v. Shaughnessy, 347 U.S. 260 (1954).
16. It is settled that immigrants both documented and undocumented are entitled to due process
rights under the Fifth Amendment. See, e.g., Brownell v. We Shung, 352 U.S. 180, 182 (1956); Kwong
Hai Chew v. Colding, 344 U.S. 590, 595–603 (1953); United States v. Fernandez-Antonia, 278 F.3d 150,
156–59 (2d Cir. 2002). For an overview of the constitutional and statutory rights afforded aliens, see
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

564 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

agencies are bound to follow their own regulations, and conclude that the
agency’s duty should, in some cases, translate into an enforceable right. I
then provide two alternatives to vindicating Accardi rights—an implied
private right of action arising from the regulation in question and judicial
review of agency action—and demonstrate how all of these legal
mechanisms implicate the two common concerns.
Building from this framework, I contend in Part II that
administrative disclaimers like section 287.12 are invalid for three
interrelated reasons. As I explain in Part I, the three so-called “roads to
court”—an implied private right of action, judicial review of agency
action, and the Accardi imperative—all involve the twin constitutional
concerns of due process and democratic structure. First, agencies are
required to adhere to their own regulations according to the well-settled
rule of administrative law known as the Accardi principle, and the use of
17
a boilerplate disclaimer undermines this well-settled rule. Second,
Congress alone, and not an agency pursuant to its delegated rulemaking
authority, has the power to create and destroy private rights of action.
Thus, agencies lack the authority to abrogate a private right of action by
means of a boilerplate disclaimer. And third, the overarching principle of
judicial review requires agency action to be reviewable in court, and
agencies cannot avoid judicial scrutiny through simple administrative
fiat. Courts are loath to allow abrogation of judicial review, both for
structural reasons—to preserve the separation of powers—and for
procedural reasons—to ensure that those affected are afforded due
process. I argue that they should maintain this approach in the face of
administrative disclaimers. The fact that these concerns are of
constitutional magnitude militates against courts’ applying an
administrative disclaimer.
I proceed to observe that courts rarely take disclaimers at face value
in other legal areas, although boilerplate disclaimers are prevalent in the
commercial context, for example. Rather than accepting administrative
disclaimers uncritically, I propose that courts should consider the
circumstances, values, conflicts, power relationships, rules, and public
policy considerations underlying such disclaimers, as they have done with

3B Am. Jur. 2d Aliens and Citizens §§ 1842–73 (2010).


17. In addition, I would note that Chevron deference is inapplicable to the controversy at hand.
While Chevron deference is applied to an agency’s construction of the statute it administers, see
Chevron U.S.A., Inc. v. Natural Res. Def. Council, Inc., 467 U.S. 837, 842–44 (1984), in a case like
Sonoma, the plaintiffs are not challenging an agency’s interpretation of a rule, but rather the agency’s
non-adherence to its regulations and whether the agency has the power to disclaim a potential
plaintiff’s rights via the disclaimer in the first place. This is consistent with the approach taken by the
Sonoma court. See Comm. for Immigrant Rights of Sonoma Cnty. v. Sonoma Cnty., No. C 08-4220
PJH, 2010 WL 841372, at *1, *5–6 (N.D. Cal. Mar. 10, 2010) (giving deference to ICE’s interpretation
of the requirements of 8 C.F.R. § 287.7, but upholding 8 C.F.R. § 287.12 without reference to agency
interpretation).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 565

similar disclaimers in other contexts. With administrative disclaimers, the


public policy stakes are high. Because administrative delegation involves
the twin concerns of proper government structure and fairness to
individuals, these policy interests inherent in administrative law outweigh
any administrative convenience achieved by a boilerplate disclaimer.
In the second half of Part II, I apply my theory to the immigration
disclaimer at issue in the Sonoma case. I illustrate the substantive and
procedural rights upon which immigrants would normally rely to
challenge unlawful immigration practices, with an eye toward
demonstrating precisely what is at stake with agency adherence to its
own regulations. A brief conclusion follows.

I. Judicial Review, Private Rights of Action, and Agencies’


Duties Under ACCARDI
Boilerplate administrative disclaimers implicate two related
concerns arising from the delegation of rulemaking authority: fairness
concerns regarding the due process rights of persons affected by agency
action and structural concerns regarding the proper delegation of
authority between Congress, the executive branch, and administrative
18
agencies. The Supreme Court has drawn this connection between these
two concerns in the context of guaranteeing judicial review, noting that
the presumption of judicial review is grounded in both due process and
19
the separation of powers.
My reasons for rejecting administrative disclaimers are threefold,
and each involves these concerns. First, agencies must follow their own
regulations. This imperative, known as the Accardi principle, exists
because agencies are inherently limited by the authority subdelegated to
them, and agency adherence to its regulations implicates the due process
rights of those affected by agency action. Second, an agency’s failure to
adhere to its regulations gives rise to a cause of action under the violated
regulations, and the agency cannot destroy that cause of action. Because

18. See Gillian E. Metzger, Ordinary Administrative Law as Constitutional Common Law,
110 Colum. L. Rev. 479, 485–86 (2010) (“Excluding such primary decisionmakers from a judicially
enforceable obligation to include significant constitutional concerns in their deliberations is at odds
with the structural imperatives of our constitutional system.”). For an interesting take on the right of
individuals to vindicate what the author calls structural rights, see Steven G. Gey, The Procedural
Annihilation of Structural Rights, 61 Hastings L.J. 1 (2009).
19. Bowen v. Mich. Acad. of Family Physicians, 476 U.S. 667, 670 (1986) (explaining that judicial
review of agency action is presumptively available because of the importance of judicial review in
guaranteeing individual rights and in checking what would otherwise be unfettered administrative
discretion); Abbott Labs. v. Gardner, 387 U.S. 136, 140 (1967) (discussing the strong presumption in
favor of judicial review); see also Metzger, supra note 18, at 496. The Court in Bowen noted that the
presumption that agency action must be reviewable traces its roots back to Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S.
(1 Cranch) 137 (1803), as well as United States v. Nourse, 31 U.S. (9 Pet.) 479 (1832), and to the very
foundations of judicial review. Bowen, 476 U.S. at 670.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

566 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

agencies receive their rulemaking power through subdelegation, only


Congress—and not an executive agency—has the power to create or
abrogate rights. Thus, an agency’s attempt to abrogate a substantive or
procedural right of action to challenge agency action should be held
invalid. Finally, judicial review of agency action is an important structural
mechanism and a means of fulfilling due process. It cannot be
countermanded by the stroke of an agency’s pen. In this Part, I elaborate
upon each of these logical foundations and their deep structural and due
process roots, with an eye toward demonstrating that they cannot be
subverted by boilerplate language in a disclaimer.

A. The ACCARDI Imperative


The Accardi principle requires agencies to follow their own
regulations. The principle has been explained in various ways by courts
20
and the scholarly literature, yet its roots and remedies continue to be
21
elusive. In the following subparts, I provide a background on the
Accardi principle and attempt to clarify its logical foundation. I suggest
that some of the confusion surrounding Accardi may be cleared up if the
principle is theorized as a tenet of constitutional common law, much like
22 23
Bivens or Miranda. Finally, I observe that under some conditions,
Accardi translates into a corresponding freestanding right that is
enforceable through various procedural vehicles, such as the
exclusionary rule, or writs of habeas corpus, and should also be
enforceable through an injunction.
1. Background
The Accardi principle is derived from the landmark immigration
case of United States ex rel. Accardi v. Shaughnessy, a habeas corpus
24
action challenging the petitioner’s deportation. Joseph Accardi was an
Italian national who had entered the United States illegally but was
25
eligible for suspension of his deportation. During his deportation
suspension proceedings, the Attorney General circulated to BIA judges a
list of “unsavory characters” he wished deported, which included
26
Accardi’s name. Accardi challenged his deportation order as
fundamentally unfair, because the procedures followed in his case

20. For an excellent exposition of the Accardi principle and its judge-made contours, see Thomas
W. Merrill, The Accardi Principle, 74 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 569 (2006) [hereinafter Merrill, The Accardi
Principle].
21. “To say that the Accardi principle is poorly theorized would be an understatement.” Id. at
569.
22. Bivens v. Six Unknown Named Agents of Fed. Bureau of Narcotics, 403 U.S. 388 (1971).
23. Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966); see infra Part I.A.2.
24. 347 U.S. 260, 261 (1954).
25. Id. at 261–62.
26. Id.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 567

violated immigration regulations that required the immigration judge to


act independently and to exercise discretion in granting or denying a
27
deportation suspension. The U.S. Supreme Court reversed Accardi’s
deportation order, because the Attorney General’s distribution of the list
28
to the immigration judges violated agency regulations. The Court held
that an agency must follow its own regulations as a matter of due process,
and the BIA’s failure to do so deprived Accardi of his right to a fair
29
hearing. As the Court reasoned, the regulations must be followed not
only because of due process considerations, but also because of the
nature of administrative subdelegation, where the administrative body
charged with following the regulations is a “nonstatutory board
composed of subordinates within a department headed by the individual
who formulated, announced, and circulated such views of the pending
30
proceeding.”
Accardi has come to stand for the principle that agencies must
adhere to their own regulations, especially when the regulations are
substantive or “legislative” in nature and affect the liberty interest or
status of individuals. Since Accardi, courts have repeatedly held agencies
to this standard, even where the agency claimed that the regulations in
question were for internal guidance only and not intended to be
31
mandatory. If an agency makes this claim, courts will generally not
defer to the agency’s claim; instead, the court will inquire into whether
the regulation is of the type that must be followed, which often depends
on whether the regulation implicates the rights or interests of affected
32
individuals. An agency may nevertheless be required to articulate sound
33
reasons for deviating from a rule.

27. Id. at 262.


28. Id.
29. Id. at 268.
30. Id. at 267.
31. See, e.g., Morton v. Ruiz, 415 U.S. 199, 235 (1974); Yellin v. United States, 374 U.S. 109, 115
(1963); Vitarelli v. Seaton, 359 U.S. 535, 545 (1959); Service v. Dulles, 354 U.S. 363, 383–89 (1957);
Bridges v. Wixon, 326 U.S. 135, 174 (1945); Steenholdt v. FAA, 314 F.3d 633, 639 (D.C. Cir. 2003)
(“The Accardi doctrine requires federal agencies to follow their own rules, even gratuitous procedural
rules that limit otherwise discretionary actions.”); see also Montilla v. INS, 926 F.2d 162, 166–67 (2d
Cir. 1991).
32. See United States v. Caceres, 440 U.S. 741, 752–55 (1979) (reversing the suppression of
recorded conversations made in violation of internal agency procedures where the violation of the
regulations was technical and inadvertent, and did not compromise the overall fairness of the
proceedings); W. Radio Servs. Co. v. Espy, 79 F.3d 896, 900–01 (9th Cir. 1996) (finding that Forest
Service manuals and handbooks did not bind the agency); Reich v. Manganas, 70 F.3d 434, 437 (6th
Cir. 1995) (“Internal operating manuals . . . do not carry the force of law, bind the agency, or confer
rights upon the regulated entity.”); Connolly v. U.S. Dep’t of Justice, 766 F.2d 507, 511 (Fed. Cir. 1985)
(“A regulation which by its own definition is permissive, not precatory, cannot be a mandatory
restriction.”); Jolly v. Listerman, 672 F.2d 935, 940–41 (D.C. Cir. 1982) (holding that courts may refuse
to force an agency to comply with pronouncements that were not intended to have binding effect, even
where individual rights are involved, so long as the pronouncement was informative and not intended
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

568 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

As a general proposition, agencies must adhere to their regulations


that are “legislative,” rather than “procedural” or “interpretive.”
“Legislative” regulations are those regulations that are promulgated
34
pursuant to authority delegated by Congress. Moreover, agencies must
adhere to their regulations that implicate a liberty interest, but not
35
necessarily those regulations that do not affect individual liberties. By
contrast, courts do not strictly require agencies to follow their internal
36
regulations, an example of which would be a regulation granting office
space based on seniority. These two independent criteria—whether a
regulation is legislative and whether it implicates a liberty interest—
37
reflect the trend among Accardi cases, and they are consistent with
38
Professor Thomas Merrill’s exposition of the Accardi doctrine.
Perhaps it is not surprising that the Accardi principle first emerged
in the immigration context, because deportation dramatically affects the
substantive rights and interests of immigrants. The Accardi Court cited
prior immigration cases in which it had reversed deportation orders that
were the product of the immigration agency’s non-adherence to the

to be mandatory). But see Morton, 415 U.S. at 235 (“Where the rights of individuals are affected, it is
incumbent upon agencies to follow their own procedures. This is so even where the internal
procedures are possibly more rigorous than otherwise would be required.”).
33. See Utahns for Better Transp. v. U.S. Dep’t of Transp., 305 F.3d 1152, 1165 (10th Cir. 2002);
Mine Reclamation Corp. v. Fed. Energy Regulatory Corp., 30 F.3d 1519, 1524–26 (D.C. Cir. 1994);
Schering Corp. v. Shalala, 995 F.2d 1103, 1105–06 (D.C. Cir. 1993); Shell Oil Co. v. Fed. Energy
Regulatory Comm’n, 664 F.2d 79, 83–84 (5th Cir. 1981) (holding the agency “must articulate valid
reasons for the departure,” rejecting the assertion that it could stray from the rule, because it had
discretion).
34. See Merrill, The Accardi Principle, supra note 20, at 596–603.
35. See id.
36. Id. at 610 (“The Constitution . . . is concerned with real and substantial rights, not with
compliance with procedures for the sake of compliance with procedures.”); see also Olim v.
Wakinekona, 461 U.S. 238, 250 (1983) (“The Court of Appeals thus erred in attributing significance to
the fact that the prison regulations require a particular kind of hearing before the Administrator can
exercise his unfettered discretion . . . Process is not an end in itself.”).
37. See supra notes 31–32.
38. See Merrill, The Accardi Principle, supra note 20, at 596–603. On the other hand, the D.C.
Circuit enumerated four factors that it will consider when deciding whether an agency is bound by its
regulations:
(1) whether in the absence of the rule there would not be an adequate legislative basis for
enforcement action or other agency action to confer benefits or ensure the performance of
duties, (2) whether the agency has published the rule in the Code of Federal Regulations,
(3) whether the agency has explicitly invoked its general legislative authority, or (4) whether
the rule effectively amends a prior legislative rule. If the answer to any of these questions is
affirmative, we have a legislative, not an interpretive rule.
Am. Mining Cong. v. Mine Safety & Health Admin., 995 F.2d 1106, 1112 (D.C. Cir. 1993); cf. Chiron
Corp. & Perseptive Biosystems v. Nat’l Transp. Safety Bd., 198 F.3d 935, 944 (D.C. Cir. 1999) (“The
general test is whether the agency intended to bind itself with the pronouncement.”). It should be
noted, however, that even in the case of the disclaimer, where the agency does not appear to have
intended to bind itself, the “disclaimed” regulations are still on the books in the Code of Federal
Regulations; they affect individual rights, and they are promulgated pursuant to the agency’s
legislative power. Thus, there are factors that overcome the agency’s apparent intent to bind itself.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 569

39
regulation. In United States ex rel. Bilokumsky v. Tod, the Court
reversed the petitioner’s deportation order, reasoning that “one under
investigation with a view to deportation is legally entitled to insist upon
40
the observance of rules promulgated by the Secretary pursuant to law.”
And in Bridges v. Wixon, the Court held that the immigration agency
must adhere to its regulations, because they are “designed to protect the
interests of the alien and to afford him due process of law” by providing
41
“safeguards against essentially unfair procedures.” The Court in Bridges
also emphasized the gravity of deportation, noting that although it is not
technically a criminal sanction, “it may nevertheless visit as great a
hardship as the deprivation of the right to pursue a vocation or a
calling. . . . [D]eportation may result in the loss ‘of all that makes life
42
worth living.’”
The Accardi doctrine has since figured prominently in immigration
cases. For instance, the Second Circuit in Montilla v. INS held that
immigration judges must comply with INS regulations designed to
safeguard immigrants’ right to counsel, even when the regulations
provide more protection than the bare minimum afforded by the Fifth
43
Amendment. As the court reasoned,
The notion of fair play animating [the Fifth A]mendment precludes
an agency from promulgating a regulation affecting individual liberty
or interest, which the rule-maker may then with impunity ignore or
disregard as it sees fit. The INS may not fairly administer the
immigration laws on the notion that on some occasions its rules are
44
made to be broken.
The court emphasized that Accardi requires strict adherence to the
45
regulations regardless of prejudice to the immigrant plaintiff. The court
explained,
The seeds of the Accardi doctrine are found in the long-settled
principle that the rules promulgated by a federal agency, which
regulate the rights and interests of others, are controlling upon the
agency . . . . The Accardi doctrine is premised on fundamental notions
46
of fair play underlying the concept of due process.
The court distinguished Montilla from cases such as United States v.
47
Caceres, where the agency departed from strictly internal procedures,
48
not from regulations that implicated a liberty interest. Thus, unlike

39. See United States ex rel. Accardi v. Shaughnessy, 347 U.S. 260, 265 n.7, 268 n.8 (1954).
40. 263 U.S. 149, 155 (1923).
41. 326 U.S. 135, 152–53 (1945).
42. Id. at 147 (quoting Ng Fung Ho v. White, 259 U.S. 276, 284 (1922)).
43. 926 F.2d 162, 164 (2d Cir. 1991).
44. Id. at 164.
45. Id. at 166–67.
46. Id.
47. 440 U.S. 741, 752–55 (1979).
48. Montilla, 926 F.2d at 167.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

570 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

Caceres, cases such as Accardi and Montilla involved regulations that


directly implicated the liberty interests—in those cases, the plaintiffs’
interest in avoiding deportation. It is this distinction that drives the
Accardi principle’s requirement that agencies follow their own
regulations when they affect substantive rights and liberties.
2. The Theoretical Basis of Accardi
At the heart of Accardi is the principle that the act of subdelegating
by the executive branch to administrative agencies creates new procedural
rights not present in congressional legislation. As Professor Merrill
explained, “[s]ubdelegation, at least by rule, creates new procedural
entitlements, which will be enforced by courts against the
49
subdelegator.” Professor Merrill observed that courts have “variously
suggested that [Accardi] is inherent in the nature of delegated ‘legislative
power’; that it is required by due process; and that it is a principle of
50
administrative common law.” In this Part, I propose that Accardi
creates a freestanding right with a correlative duty on agencies, and I also
propose that Accardi’s foundation may best be explained as a tenet of
constitutional common law, which would make adherence to Accardi all
the more imperative.
a. Accardi Rights, Duties, and Remedies
The Accardi principle is well entrenched in administrative
51
jurisprudence, but there remain questions about its enforceability. The
principle clearly confers a duty on administrative agencies to adhere to
their regulations, especially when the regulations are “legislative” in
nature or implicate a liberty interest—but does it create a right that is
enforceable by affected individuals? While it is generally accepted that
52
the existence of a right creates a duty, it is less obvious when a duty
53
gives rise to a right. Some scholars have posited that the existence of a
54
duty presupposes the existence of a right, while others have contended
55
that not all duties correspond to an actionable right. One formulation of
the connection between rights and duties is that duties are enforceable

49. Merrill, The Accardi Principle, supra note 20, at 576 n.49.
50. Id. at 569.
51. As discussed in greater detail in this subpart and in Part II.B, the question of how Accardi is
to be “enforced,” both in terms of a cause of action and a legal remedy, is still very much an open
question, and one I hope to clarify in this Note.
52. See, e.g., Donald H. Zeigler, Rights, Rights of Action, and Remedies: An Integrated Approach,
76 Wash. L. Rev. 67, 105 (2001) (“A legal right imposes a correlative duty on another to act or to
refrain from acting for the benefit of the person holding the right.”).
53. See, e.g., Henry T. Terry, The Correspondence of Duties and Rights, 25 Yale L.J. 171 (1916)
(defining “rights” and “duties” and discussing the intersection between them).
54. See id. at 174.
55. See, e.g., Jack Donnelly, How Are Rights and Duties Correlative?, 16 J. Value Inquiry 287
(1982) (making the normative case that rights and duties are sometimes reciprocally correspondent,
sometimes merely correspondent, and other times not correlated).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 571

when they are undergirded by a “protected right,” which is a passive


right to maintain current conditions against the actions of others, as
opposed to a “permissive right,” which the holder must actively exercise
56
to secure.
This formulation proves useful in the context of Accardi, because
the duty of agencies to follow their binding regulations can be translated
into a right against agency non-adherence to its own regulations. Thus,
Accardi creates a “protected right” that is correlative to the duty of
agencies to adhere to their regulations. This conclusion is compelling in
light of the Supreme Court’s holding, in Golden State Transit Co. v. City
of Los Angeles, that an enforceable federal right exists where (1) the
provision in question creates obligations binding on the government,
(2) the interest asserted by the plaintiff is not so “vague and
amorphous . . . [to be] beyond the competence of the judiciary to
enforce,” and (3) the provision in question was “intended to benefit” the
57
plaintiff. Courts have interpreted the Accardi imperative to include only
binding regulations and those that implicate the liberty interests of those
affected by the regulation, which satisfies the first and third elements of
the Supreme Court’s test. Therefore, in a case where the plaintiff had
standing to challenge the agency action—and therefore, was asserting an
interest that is not “vague and amorphous,” under the second
58
element —it would seem that agencies’ duties under Accardi do in fact
give rise to an enforceable right on the part of affected individuals.
Even if Accardi gives rise to a freestanding right, this does not
address how Accardi is to be enforced in court. A right is not the same as
59
a cause of action, which in turn is not the same as a remedy. A cause of
action could potentially arise out of the particular regulation that is
60
allegedly violated in an Accardi action. In most cases, plaintiffs have

56. Terry, supra note 53, at 173–74. On the other hand, there may be rights that are violated in
the absence of a duty; such rights are known as damnum absque injuria. Id. at 175.
57. 493 U.S. 103, 106 (1989).
58. Prudential standing requirements limit a court’s role in disputes involving generalized
grievances and the legal rights or interests of non-litigants. See Warth v. Seldin, 422 U.S. 490, 498–99
(1975). Thus, the requirement that a plaintiff assert an interest that is not “vague and amorphous” is
little more than a reiteration of the standing requirement. See supra note 56 and accompanying text.
59. See generally Zeigler, supra note 52. Professor Zeigler explains that the Court’s jurisprudence
currently holds that rights, or causes of action, and remedies are analytically distinct, but he
nevertheless exhorts a return to ubi jus, ibi remedium. Id. at 68 (“Traditionally, courts equated legal
rights and remedies. A right without a remedy was said to be ‘a monstrous absurdity.’” (citing Kendall
v. United States ex rel. Stokes, 37 U.S. (12 Pet.) 524, 624 (1838))); see also John C. Jeffries, Jr., The
Right-Remedy Gap in Constitutional Law, 109 Yale L.J. 87, 87 (1999) (“Ever since John Marshall
insisted that for every violation of a right, there must be a remedy, American constitutionalists have
decried the right-remedy gap in constitutional law.”); Donald H. Zeigler, Rights Require Remedies: A
New Approach to the Enforcement of Rights in the Federal Courts, 38 Hastings L.J. 665, 665–66
(1987). But see Sam Kamin, Harmless Error and the Rights/Remedies Split, 88 Va. L. Rev. 1, 3–4 (2002)
(surveying doctrines that drive a wedge between rights violations and remedies).
60. See infra Part I.B.1.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

572 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

been able to vindicate their rights under Accardi via built-in procedural
vehicles. Such instances have included a motion to suppress under the
61
exclusionary rule, a writ of habeas corpus, petition for review of agency
action under the Administrative Procedure Act (APA), a motion to
quash a subpoena, an appeal from a criminal conviction, and a motion to
62
enjoin agency action under the Due Process Clause. However, the right
should also be enforceable through injunctive relief not dependent upon
63
the Due Process Clause and its attendant requirements, because
Accardi furnishes a freestanding right. Moreover, the Supreme Court has
observed that courts should have “a measure of latitude to shape a
sensible remedial scheme” where a right or cause of action is judicially
64
created. Because Accardi constitutes a judicially created right, courts
should be able to fashion appropriate remedies, including discretionary
equitable relief. Under this formulation, courts facing claims like those in
Sonoma should entertain the possibility of vindicating Accardi through
65
injunctive relief.
b. Accardi as Constitutional Common Law
Before moving on, there is a further observation to be made
regarding Accardi’s theoretical foundation and its status as a judicially
created duty, or duty-cum-right. In expounding upon the Accardi
doctrine, Professor Merrill characterized the theoretical basis for Accardi
as, to say the least, unclear, describing its theoretical foundation an
untidy combination of administrative common law, the Due Process
Clause, and structural concerns regarding the separation of powers and
66
subdelegation of rulemaking authority. However, some of the confusion
and jurisprudential disarray surrounding Accardi may be cleared up if

61. This includes the immigration counterpart of the exclusionary rule. See infra Part II.C
(discussing Lopez-Mendoza and the abolition of the exclusionary rule in deportation proceedings).
62. Merrill, The Accardi Principle, supra note 20, at 603.
63. Namely, the attendant requirements include that
(1) the government (2) is threatening to deprive the claimant (3) of a recognized interest in
life, liberty, or property (4) in a proceeding that turns on facts individual to the claimant
(5) without observing the package of procedures that the judiciary determines are required
by “due process of law.”
Id. at 607–08.
64. Gebser v. Lago Vista Indep. Sch. Dist., 524 U.S. 274, 284 (1998) (discussing a judicially
implied private right of action under Title IX).
65. If by no other mechanism, then they should do so under the All Writs Act, 28 U.S.C. § 1651
(2006), which may serve as a catch-all remedial vehicle. It states,
(a) The Supreme Court and all courts established by Act of Congress may issue all writs
necessary or appropriate in aid of their respective jurisdictions and agreeable to the usages
and principles of law. (b) An alternative writ or rule nisi may be issued by a justice or judge
of a court which has jurisdiction.
Id.
66. See generally Merrill, The Accardi Principle, supra note 20.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 573

the principle is conceived as a tenet of constitutional common law on par


with Bivens, the exclusionary rule, or Miranda.
Federal common law can be described as any federal judge-made
law that is not mandated by a source of positive federal law, such as a
67
statute or constitutional provision. In 1975, Professor Henry Monaghan
posited the existence of constitutional common law as “a substructure of
substantive, procedural, and remedial rules drawing their inspiration and
authority from, but not required by, various constitutional
68
provisions . . . .” Interestingly, Professor Gillian Metzger has recently
argued that administrative law is itself a type of constitutional common
69
law. As she explained, constitutional common law, as set forth by
Professor Monaghan, and ordinary administrative law are “inextricably
linked”:
Statutory and regulatory measures are created to address
constitutional requirements; constitutional concerns, particularly those
sounding in separation of powers, underlie core ordinary
administrative law doctrines . . . . Although some administrative law
requirements are plainly constitutionally required and others clearly
rooted only in statutory or regulatory enactments, a number of basic
doctrines occupy a middle ground. The latter are simultaneously based
in ordinary law and constitutional law, and these two dimensions are
too overlapping and interactive to be isolated. . . . [T]his overlapping
and interactive relationship between the constitutional and ordinary
dimensions of administrative law, combined with Congress’s broad
control over the latter, is what serves to transform ordinary
70
administrative law into a species of constitutional common law.
Although neither Professor Monaghan nor Professor Metzger
produces Accardi as an example, Accardi fits solidly into this

67. Martha A. Field, Sources of Law: The Scope of Federal Common Law, 99 Harv. L. Rev. 881,
890 (1986) (“‘Federal common law’ . . . refer[s] to any rule of federal law created by a court . . . when
the substance of that rule is not clearly suggested by federal enactments—constitutional or
congressional.” (emphasis omitted)); Thomas W. Merrill, The Common Law Powers of Federal
Courts, 52 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1, 5 (1985) [hereinafter Merrill, Common Law Powers of Federal Courts]
(“‘Federal common law’ . . . means any federal rule of decision that is not mandated on the face of
some authoritative federal text—whether or not that rule can be described as the product of
‘interpretation’ in either a conventional or an unconventional sense.” (emphasis omitted)); Martin H.
Redish, Federal Common Law, Political Legitimacy, and the Interpretive Process: An “Institutionalist”
Perspective, 83 Nw. U. L. Rev. 761, 761–62 (1989); cf. Erie R.R. Co. v. Tompkins, 304 U.S. 64, 78
(1938) (“There is no federal general common law.”).
68. Henry P. Monaghan, Foreword: Constitutional Common Law, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1, 2–3 (1975).
Professor Monaghan originally included another element in his definition of constitutional common
law: “and subject to amendment, modification, or even reversal by Congress.” Id. Note, however, that
this last aspect of the definition—being subject to legislative reversal—is now arguable in light of
Dickerson v. United States, 530 U.S. 428 (2000). Professor Monaghan included the Miranda warnings
as an example of a constitutional common law principle, Monaghan, supra, at 2, yet the Supreme
Court in Dickerson struck down Congress’s attempt to alter the Miranda requirements in 18 U.S.C.
§ 3501(a) (2000). 530 U.S. at 432.
69. See Metzger, supra note 18.
70. Id. at 484–85.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

574 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

constitutional “middle ground”: the administrative imperative, arrived at


through common law reasoning, is firmly grounded in constitutional
concerns, but it is not apparent on the face of any constitutional
provision or statutory test. Accardi fits into the body of constitutional
common law, because it has roots in constitutional concerns—namely,
due process and separation of powers—yet no court has suggested that
the principle is derived directly from any statute or constitutional
provision. Moreover, it involves concerns arising from the process of
subdelegation and the creation of new procedural rights, which in turn
are intertwined with structural and due process considerations. Thus, I
would describe it as both administrative common law, which Professor
Merrill acknowledges in his Accardi article, and also as a constitutional
common law principle on par with Bivens, Miranda, and the exclusionary
rule.
Even after thoroughly explicating the Accardi principle, Professor
Merrill ultimately explained that it was just one of those principles that
make our system work:
The most honest answer [to the question of Accardi’s status] is that it is
just one of those shared postulates of the legal system that cannot be
traced to any provision of enacted law. In this sense, it is like the rule
of stare decisis, or the understanding that majority rule prevails in
multimember courts, or that later-enacted statutes prevail over
previously enacted statutes in the event of a conflict. These rules are
not written down in any authoritative text. They are simply
foundational assumptions vital to the operations of our legal system—
they are constitutional principles in the small “c” sense of the term.
Similarly, the understanding that statutes bind enactors and enforcers
as well as subjects—extended now to the context of legislative
regulations—is a shared assumption about the nature of our legal
system; it is, if you will, part of the collective understanding of what it
71
means to identify something as a “statute”—or a legislative regulation.
While this “it’s just one of those things” account of Accardi is not
inaccurate, it is not entirely satisfying. And the description that Professor
Merrill applies, “one of those shared postulates” that “cannot be traced
to any provision of enacted law,” sounds strikingly like that of the
constitutional common law as judge-made law, drawing its authority
from the Constitution but not directly traceable to any particular
72
provision of enacted law. Indeed, it is consistent with being
73
“constitutional . . . in the small ‘c’ sense of the term.” Professor Merrill
would likely disagree with my characterization of Accardi as
constitutional common law, given that he has disapproved of Professor

71. Merrill, The Accardi Principle, supra note 20, at 598–99.


72. Id. at 598.
73. Id. at 599.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 575

74
Monaghan’s formulation of the constitutional common law, but it offers
an elegant solution to the problem of Accardi’s theoretical foundation
with which so many courts have grappled. If this is true, then it is critical
for courts to recognize and enforce the Accardi imperative.

B. Three Roads to Court: Procedural Alternatives to ACCARDI


While Accardi should be the principal mechanism for challenging an
agency’s non-adherence to its regulations, there are other possible means
of vindicating an affected individual’s interests in court. The Supreme
Court’s jurisprudence supports the proposition that rights, causes of
action and implied rights of action, remedies, and judicial review are
75
analytically distinct. Accardi creates a duty on the part of an agency
and, as I have posited, a correlative right against an agency’s non-
adherence to its own regulations. At the same time, the regulations
themselves, in some cases, will provide a cause of action, whether express
76
or in the form of an implied private right of action. Moreover, judicial
review should be presumptively available to individuals affected by
77
agency rulemaking and action.
As Professors William Timbers and David Wirth observed, there is
considerable “conceptual overlap” between an implied private right of
action and an action seeking judicial review in suits against a federal
78
agency; in a way, judicial review and an implied private right of action
are Janus-like counterparts. In the case of an administrative disclaimer,
an affected party could seek judicial review of an agency’s rulemaking
that resulted in the disclaimer; under an implied private right of action,
an affected party could also seek injunctive relief against the agency’s
non-adherence to its regulations or against the “exercise” of the
disclaimer. To use the example of section 287.12, this dichotomy is also
implicated in court proceedings to suppress evidence obtained in
79
violation of the agency’s action. In this subpart, I explore this
dichotomy between judicial review and implied private rights of action as
it bears upon the right to challenge agency non-adherence to its
regulations. Like Accardi, these two legal avenues implicate the twin

74. See Merrill, Common Law Powers of Federal Courts, supra note 67, at 54–56 (“[A] body of
common law rules ‘inspired’ but not ‘required’ by the Constitution presents far more serious problems
of legitimacy than Monaghan acknowledges.”).
75. See Davis v. Passman, 442 U.S. 228, 239 (1979); see also Zeigler, supra note 52, at 87.
76. See infra Part I.B.1.
77. See Administrative Procedure Act, 5 U.S.C. § 702 (2006) (judicial review).
78. William H. Timbers & David A. Wirth, Private Rights of Action and Judicial Review in
Federal Environmental Law, 70 Cornell L. Rev. 403, 410 (1985).
79. Immigrants are not entitled to the Fourth Amendment’s exclusionary rule in deportation
hearings. INS v. Lopez-Mendoza, 468 U.S. 1032, 1045–46 (1984). However, immigrants may seek to
suppress evidence in a deportation hearing if the evidence is the fruit of the immigration agency’s
violation of its own regulations. See infra note 149 and accompanying text.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

576 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

concerns of due process and administrative structure—two deeply


entrenched constitutional concerns—and they may not be subverted by
boilerplate language in the Code of Federal Regulations.
1. Implied Private Right of Action to Challenge Regulatory
Violations
An agency’s non-adherence to its regulations may be challenged if
the regulations create a cause of action through an implied private right
of action. The implied private right of action is a federal common law
doctrine that allows courts to find a cause of action in a source of positive
80
law, including statutes and regulations. The seminal case for the
doctrine of implied private rights of action is the Supreme Court’s
opinion in Cort v. Ash, where the Court identified four factors for finding
81
such a right. The test considered the following factors: (1) whether the
plaintiff is part of the class for whose special benefit the statute was
enacted; (2) whether there is any indication of legislative intent, explicit
or implicit, to create or deny such a remedy; (3) whether it would be
consistent with the underlying purpose of the legislative scheme to imply
such a remedy for the plaintiff; and (4) whether it is a cause of action
82
relegated to state law, and thus inappropriate for federal adjudication.
Although the scope and application of Cort are unclear, it has never
83
been overruled. In recent years, however, the Supreme Court has
moved toward a narrower application of the federal common law, finding
that fewer statutes support an implied private right of action. The recent
approach has been to inquire into whether Congress intended to create a
private right of action using the factors identified in Cort as indicia of
84
such possible intent.
The jurisprudence of implied private rights of action arising under
federal regulations is not as well developed as those arising under federal
statutes. The scant jurisprudence on this topic suggests that federal
courts will look to substantially the same factors—most importantly, the

80. E.g., Erwin Chemerinsky, Federal Jurisdiction § 6.3.3, at 394–97 (5th ed. 2007).
81. 422 U.S. at 66.
82. Id. at 78; see also Cannon v. Univ. of Chi., 441 U.S. 677, 688–709 (1979) (applying the Cort
four-factor test to find a private right of action in Title IX).
83. See Thompson v. Thompson, 484 U.S. 174, 188 (1988) (Scalia, J., concurring) (expressing
distaste for the Cort analysis); Chemerinsky, supra note 80, at 396.
84. See California v. Sierra Club, 451 U.S. 287, 293–94 (1981). The Court subsequently read Sierra
Club to mean that the inquiry into congressional intent does not mean that Congress need have an
actual intent to create a private action. See Thompson, 484 U.S. at 179. This approach rather echoed
the Court’s liberal approach in J.I. Case Co. v. Borak, 377 U.S. 426, 434 (1964). But in Karahalios v.
National Federation of Federal Employees, the latest Supreme Court case on implied private rights of
action, the Court held that the ultimate issue is whether Congress intended to create a private cause of
action. 489 U.S. 527, 532–33 (1989). “Intent” on the part of Congress means evidence that Congress
intended to do so in the language of the statute, the statutory structure, or “some other source.” Id.
But the Court will not merely rely on statutory interpretation alone, because it would render the
doctrine a dead letter. See Thompson, 484 U.S. at 179.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 577

apparent intent of Congress in passing the enabling statute—but are


more willing to find an implied private right of action where substantive
rights are involved.
The Supreme Court has issued few decisions with regard to implied
private rights of action based on federal regulations. Famously, the
Supreme Court found an implied private right of action in SEC Rule
85 86
section 10b-5 to recover damages resulting from securities fraud. More
recently, the Court in Alexander v. Sandoval held that regulations
promulgated pursuant to Title VI do not give rise to an implied private
87
right of action. In Sandoval, a non-English speaker challenged
Alabama’s policy of administering the driver’s license exam in English
88
only. The applicant sought to enjoin the English-only policy, arguing
that the regulations promulgated under Title VI prohibiting intentional
89
discrimination barred such a policy. The Court denied his claim, holding
that there is no implied private right of action to enforce disparate
impact regulations promulgated under Title VI, because Title VI itself
90
does not give rise to an implied private right of action. The Court held
that a federal regulation creates a private right of action where Congress
evinced an intent to create a private right of action, not where the agency
evinced such an intent in promulgating its rules:
Language in a regulation may invoke a private right of action that
Congress through statutory text created, but it may not create a right
Congress has not. Thus, when a statute has provided a general
authorization for private enforcement of regulations, it may perhaps be
correct that the intent displayed in each regulation can determine
whether or not it is privately enforceable. But it is most certainly
incorrect to say that language in a regulation can conjure up a private
91
cause of action that has not been authorized by Congress.
Thus, following Sandoval, the existence of a private right of action under
a federal regulation depends upon the enabling statute, not the
92
regulations themselves.
Lower courts have only occasionally addressed the issue. In Rolland
v. Romney, a First Circuit case, a class of developmentally disabled
nursing home residents in Massachusetts sought to compel Massachusetts
to provide specialized services under the Nursing Home Reform

85. See 17 C.F.R. § 240.10(b)5 (2009).


86. Superintendent of Ins. v. Bankers Life & Cas. Co., 404 U.S. 6, 13–14 (1971).
87. 532 U.S. 275, 278 (2001).
88. Id. at 279.
89. Sandoval, 532 U.S. at 278 (citing Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. § 2000(d)–
(d)(7) (2006); 28 C.F.R. § 42.104(b)(2) (2000); 49 C.F.R. § 21.5(b)(2) (2000)).
90. Id. at 293.
91. Id. at 291 (citation omitted).
92. Presumably, the same combination of factors identified in Cort and its progeny would be used
to determine whether a private right of action exists pursuant to an enabling statute.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

578 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

93
Amendments in the Medicaid Act. Under the Amendments, patients
94
are screened for the purpose of determining which services they need.
An issue in the case was whether the Act and its implementing
regulations created an implied private right of action to demand
95
specialized services that were denied. The court held that there was an
implied private right of action, finding that the statute and legislative
96
history contained sufficient “rights-creating” language. The Court
looked to House comments that discussed the potential adverse effect on
individuals should they be denied certain nursing-home services, and
determined that Congress viewed the screening process as “vesting
97
individuals with rights to the services deemed necessary.”
Thus, in contrast to Sandoval, the First Circuit in Rolland found an
implied private right of action because the enabling statute evinced
98
legislative intent, though not explicit legislative intent, to create a
private right of action. In both cases, the court found that the power to
create private rights of action rests with Congress alone.
2. Judicial Review Vel Non of Agency Action
In addition to implicating an affected person’s private right of
action, agency action may often implicate questions of judicial review.
Although judicial review was not at issue in the Sandoval and Rolland
cases, it arises when an individual seeks to challenge agency action in
court, and the agency argues that its action is unreviewable. With the
administrative disclaimer, this is precisely the case. The next subpart
deals with judicial review of agency action, including agency non-
adherence to its regulations.
The ability to seek judicial review of agency action has been called a
bona fide right of those affected by the action. In his series of articles on
the subject, entitled The Right to Judicial Review, Professor Louis Jaffe
argued that judicial review of administrative action should be
presumptively available, as a matter of procedural legitimacy, delegation
of power, and, indeed, as central to the concept of separation of powers
99
familiar in common law democracies. Professor Jaffe explained this
right in sweeping terms: “[D]elegation of power implies some limit.
Action beyond that limit is not legitimate. . . . [T]he availability of

93. 42 U.S.C. § 1396(r) (2006 & Supp. III 2009); 318 F.3d 42, 44 (1st Cir. 2003).
94. See § 1396(r)(b)(3)(A); Rolland, 318 F.3d at 44.
95. Rolland, 318 F.3d at 51–52.
96. Id. at 52, 56; cf. S. Camden Citizens in Action v. N.J. Dep’t of Envtl. Prot., 274 F.3d 771 (3d
Cir. 2001) (ruling that even though there was no freestanding private right of action to enforce
disparate-impact regulations promulgated by the EPA under Title VI, the regulations were
enforceable under 42 U.S.C. § 1983).
97. Rolland, 318 F.3d at 49–50 (citing H.R. Rep. No. 100-391, at 462-63 (1987), reprinted in 1987
U.S.C.C.A.N. at 2313-282 to 2313-283).
98. See discussion supra note 84.
99. Louis L. Jaffe, The Right to Judicial Review I, 71 Harv. L. Rev. 401, 401–06 (1958).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 579

judicial review is, in our system and under our tradition, the necessary
100
premise of legal validity. . . .” He reasoned that because the function of
agencies is to carry out their administrative functions and not to
scrupulously observe due process, they require judicial oversight:
From the point of view of an agency, the question of the legitimacy
of its action is secondary to that of the positive solution of a problem. It
is for this reason that we, in common with nearly all of the Western
countries, have concluded that the maintenance of legitimacy requires
101
a judicial body independent of the active administration.
Professor Jaffe ties this imperative to a deeply rooted right:
The guarantee of legality by an organ independent of the executive
is one of the profoundest, most pervasive premises of our system. . . .
....
. . . [I]n our system of remedies, an individual whose interest is acutely
and immediately affected by an administrative action presumptively
has a right to secure at some point a judicial determination of its
102
validity.
While the Accardi line of cases has somewhat obviated the need to
103
resort to the right of judicial review, it is still important to keep in mind
the structural, as well as individual importance of judicial review of
agency action affecting individuals. Accardi and judicial review are
interrelated mechanisms: “[E]ven if the applicable statutes confer
complete discretion on agency actors, if those actors have the authority
to constrain their discretion by promulgating legislative rules, and they
choose to do so, they have created law that can serves as the basis for
104
judicial review of their actions.” As Professor Gerald Neuman
explained, these concerns are of such consequence that courts must
invalidate any limitations that would prevent meaningful judicial
105
review.

100. Id. at 401, 403.


101. Id. at 405.
102. Id. at 406, 420. Professor Jaffe’s position has been remarkably well received in the courts,
having garnered hundreds of citations over the years.
103. “[T]he injection of an Accardi argument magically transforms what is unreviewable into
something that is reviewable.” Merrill, The Accardi Principle, supra note 20, at 605 (citing Frizelle v.
Slater, 111 F.3d 172, 178 (D.C. Cir. 1997); Ortiz v. Sec’y of Def., 41 F.3d 738, 741 (D.C. Cir. 1994);
Vietnam Veterans of Am. v. Sec’y of the Navy, 843 F.2d 528, 530, 538 (D.C. Cir. 1988); Dilley v.
Alexander, 603 F.2d 914, 920 (D.C. Cir. 1979); Geiger v. Brown, 419 F.2d 714, 715, 717–18 (D.C. Cir.
1969); Roberts v. Vance, 343 F.2d 236, 237, 239 (D.C. Cir. 1964); Coleman v. Brucker, 257 F.2d 661,
661–62 (D.C. Cir. 1958)). But see Charles H. Koch, Jr., Judicial Review of Administrative
Policymaking, 44 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 375, 376 (2003) (arguing that while courts dominate statutory
interpretation, they must give considerable deference to agency policy decisions).
104. Merrill, The Accardi Principle, supra note 20, at 605.
105. See Gerald L. Neuman, Habeas Corpus, Executive Detention, and the Removal of Aliens,
98 Colum. L. Rev. 961, 1058–59 (1998); see also Louis L. Jaffe, Judicial Control of Administrative
Action 339–53 (1965); John F. Duffy, Administrative Common Law in Judicial Review, 77 Tex. L.
Rev. 113, 121 (1998).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

580 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

The Supreme Court has affirmed the importance of judicial


review of administrative action and reiterated a strong presumption that
106
judicial review of agency action will be available. When promulgating
the APA, Congress undertook a “comprehensive rethinking of the place
of administrative agencies in a regime of separate and divided
107
powers . . . .” In a most fundamental way, judicial review implicates
core constitutional concerns and must not be abrogated by the mere
existence of boilerplate language in a disclaimer.

II. The Case Against Administrative Carte Blanche


In the next Part, I propose that the principle of judicial review, the
theory of implied private rights of action, and the Accardi imperative,
taken together, indicate that agencies are not free to disregard their own
regulations, and that administrative disclaimers should be found to be
void as a matter of law. I also make a normative case for disregarding
boilerplate administrative disclaimers, stemming from the observation
that courts rarely apply disclaimers at face value in other legal contexts. I
then apply this proposal to the boilerplate disclaimer found in section
287.12 of the immigration regulations at issue in Sonoma, to demonstrate
how and why courts should not hold administrative disclaimers effective
in abrogating rights protected by Accardi—namely, those rights that are
“legislative” in nature or that implicate an individual liberty interest.

A. A New Look at Administrative Accountability


As we have seen, the delegation of rulemaking authority implicates
what I have called the twin concerns of administrative structure and
procedural fairness. This subpart demonstrates that boilerplate
administrative disclaimers run afoul of these twin concerns both by
attempting to subvert the Accardi imperative as well as by attempting to
abrogate individuals’ private right of action and right to judicial review
when the agency does violate Accardi.
The Accardi principle can be framed in terms of these twin
concerns. In terms of administrative structure, agencies must be trusted
to carry out their delegated functions, because if they do not, the
distribution of authority between Congress, the executive branch, and its
federal agencies would become unbalanced. As for procedural fairness,
the process of subdelegation of power to administrative agencies creates

106. See, e.g., Bowen v. Mich. Acad. of Family Physicians, 476 U.S. 667, 670–71 (1986).
107. Id. at 671 (citing S. Rep. No. 79–752, at 26 (1945)) (“Very rarely do statutes withhold judicial
review. It has never been the policy of Congress to prevent the administration of its own statutes from
being judicially confined to the scope of authority granted or to the objectives specified. Its policy
could not be otherwise, for in such a case statutes would in effect be blank checks drawn to the credit
of some administrative officer or board.”).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 581

new procedural entitlements that are enforceable against the


subdelegatee—namely, that the agency must follow its own regulations
or risk annulment of its action. Moreover, if an agency is permitted to
regard its regulations as “made to be broken,” as would be the case if
administrative disclaimers were widely held to be operative, then those
affected by the regulations can hardly be said to enjoy the minimum
notice and opportunity to be heard required by procedural due process.
Because agencies are bound to follow the regulations they
promulgate, courts should carefully scrutinize cases for attempts to
circumvent this duty for their effect on individual liberty interests.
Agency determinations are often dispositive in a person’s life and
livelihood—a fact that can be seen in greatest relief in the immigration
context. When faced with regulatory disclaimers, courts should enforce
the agency’s duty to follow its regulations and hold that agencies may not
shake off the heavy burden imposed by Accardi simply by invoking a
boilerplate disclaimer.
The rationale underlying Accardi is an important ground for
distinguishing disclaimers found in federal statutes from those found in
regulations. Indeed, an immigration disclaimer similar to the one found
in section 287.12 was upheld in the statutory context in the Tenth Circuit
108
case of Hernandez-Avalos v. INS. In Hernandez-Avalos, the immigrant
plaintiffs convicted of deportable offenses were serving prison sentences
109
in the United States. Rather than serve their sentences in federal
prison, the immigrants preferred to be deported to their home countries,
and they sought to compel the INS to initiate deportation proceedings
110
under the federal mandamus statute. The plaintiffs argued they had an
enforceable right under 8 U.S.C. § 1252(i), which provides that the
Attorney General “shall begin any deportation proceedings as
111
expeditiously as possible . . . .” The Attorney General, however, argued
that the government had no duty under § 1252(i), because Immigration
112
and Nationality Technical Corrections Act of 1994, had introduced a
disclaimer. The disclaimer reads: “nothing in [this] section . . . shall be
construed to create any substantive or procedural right or benefit that is
legally enforceable by any party against the United States or its agencies
113
or officers or any other person.” The court agreed with the
government, reasoning that the disclaimer in § 1231(h) imposed a

108. 50 F.3d 842, 843 (10th Cir. 1995).


109. Id. But see Zadvydas v. Davis, 533 U.S. 678, 682 (2001) (rejecting the government’s
interpretation of federal immigration statutes as authorizing indefinite detention of deportable
immigrants). Later, in Clark v. Martinez, the Court also held that Zadvydas protects even deportable
immigrants who were never eligible to enter the United States. 543 U.S. 371, 378 (2005).
110. 28 U.S.C. § 1361 (2006); see Hernandez-Avalos, 50 F.3d at 843–45.
111. 8 U.S.C. § 1252(i) (1994); Hernandez-Avalos, 50 F.3d at 843.
112. 8 U.S.C. § 1231(h) (1994); see Hernandez-Avalos, 50 F.3d at 844.
113. Hernandez-Avalos, 50 F.3d at 844 (quoting § 1231(h)).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

582 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

mandatory rule of construction, compelling the conclusion that the


114
expeditious deportation statute created no enforceable right or benefit.
The court’s ultimate holding was that the plaintiffs lacked standing
because they did not fall within the zone of interest of the mandamus
115
statute. However, the court’s statement about the statutory disclaimer
is relevant to the present discussion. I contend that the court’s reasoning
would be inapplicable to a similar administrative disclaimer.
Following the reasoning of Accardi and Montilla, the Tenth Circuit’s
dicta in Hernandez-Avalos cannot extend to disclaimers in the regulatory
context. There is a greater need to ensure agency adherence to its rules
in the regulatory context than there is in the context of federal statutes,
which by their very nature have the force of law and do not run the risk
of being arbitrarily disregarded. A statutory disclaimer is subject to
116
bicameral review and presentment, whereas a regulatory disclaimer is
117
subject only to notice and comment under the APA. Indeed, the
Supreme Court has emphasized the difference between statutes and
regulations, noting that regulations are not entitled to a presumption of
118
constitutionality as statutes are. Also, the ability of an agency to
exercise more discretion implicates due process concerns, which was one
119
of the rationales cited for the Accardi principle in Bridges v. Wixon and
120
in Accardi v. Shaughnessy itself. This reasoning is consistent with the
argument put forth by Professor Merrill, who surmised that the Court in
Accardi
seemed to suggest that because of the “nonstatutory” delegation from
the Attorney General to the BIA, Accardi was entitled to more rights
than he would have had if the Attorney General had reserved the
decision to himself. Subdelegation, at least by rule, creates new
procedural entitlements, which will be enforced by courts against the
121
subdelegator.
The federal common law principle of implied private rights of action
also implicates these twin concerns. Structurally, because agencies
receive their rulemaking power through subdelegation, only Congress,
and not an executive agency, has the power to create or abrogate rights.
The due process concern is also at play with implied private rights of
action: If agencies violate the Accardi imperative, affected individuals

114. Id.
115. Id. (citing 28 U.S.C. § 1361).
116. U.S. Const. art. I, § 7.
117. 5 U.S.C. § 553 (2006).
118. See Motor Vehicle Mfrs. Ass’n of the U.S. v. State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co., 463 U.S. 29, 43
n.9 (1983).
119. 326 U.S. 135, 153 (1945).
120. 347 U.S. 260, 268 (1954).
121. See Merrill, The Accardi Principle, supra note 20, at 576 n.49; see also Ann Woolhandler,
Delegation and Due Process: The Historical Connection, 2008 Sup. Ct. Rev. 223, 225–26 (analyzing the
effect of legislative delegation on procedural due process).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 583

should have an implied private right of action to challenge the agency’s


action. Without it, those affected by an Accardi violation would be
substantially without redress, and they would be deprived of an adequate
122
opportunity to be heard. For these reasons, an agency’s attempt to
abrogate a substantive or procedural right of action to challenge agency
action should be invalidated.
123
I propose that the holding in Alexander v. Sandoval indicates that
the power to create or to destroy private rights of action is with Congress
alone—that Congress’s intent must prevail in either case where private
rights of action are at stake. This proposition, that agencies not only lack
the power to create a private right of action, but also lack the power to
destroy it, is a logical extension of the reasoning the Court employed in
Sandoval. In Sandoval, the Court emphasized that it is the proper
function of common law courts, and not of “federal tribunals,” to
124
establish causes of action. It should hold true, then, that if Congress did
evince an intent to create a private right of action, as was held in Rolland,
the agency should not be able to abrogate that right by administrative
fiat. In such a situation, the power to destroy a cause of action is arguably
even more consequential than the power to create one. Especially in light
of Rolland, courts should not give deference to an agency’s attempt to
create or destroy a cause of action, particularly where the enabling
statute contains “rights-creating language” or where the regulations
affect the substantive rights of individuals.
However, this is not the end of the story. Courts are interpreting
implied private rights of action in statutes more narrowly than they once
125
did. Thus, the first and third Cort factors, (1) whether the plaintiff was
part of the class for whose special benefit the statute was enacted and
(3) whether it would be consistent with the underlying purpose of the
126
legislative scheme to imply such a remedy for the plaintiff, are no
longer likely to be dispositive in finding an implied private right of
action.
But given that the Accardi principle requires agencies to follow their
own regulations, I would venture a step further. I contend that there are
two possible sources of a private right of action to challenge an agency’s
non-adherence to its regulations: In addition to an implication in the
enabling statute, under Sandoval, the Accardi imperative itself created a

122. I say without “substantial” redress, because there may be, in some cases, the possibility of
administrative review, although agency review is usually treated as a prerequisite to filing a claim for
relief in federal court. See 28 U.S.C. § 2675 (2006) (stating that disposition by federal agency as a
prerequisite to relief in an Article III court).
123. 532 U.S. 275 (2001).
124. Id. at 287.
125. Chemerinsky, supra note 80, § 6.3.3, at 392–93.
126. Cort v. Ash, 422 U.S. 66, 78 (1975).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

584 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

protected right. Indeed, the whole line of Accardi cases involved


plaintiffs who were challenging agency non-adherence to its
127
regulations.
To the extent that Accardi and Sandoval may be at odds, I propose
that Accardi should trump other considerations. To begin, Accardi and
its progeny constitute the more on-point precedent with respect to
challenging an agency’s non-adherence to its own regulations. In
contrast, Sandoval and the implied private right of action cases generally
apply to challenges of a private party’s action that is at odds with a
presumably valid regulation. I argue that Sandoval may be read as
prohibiting agencies from creating or destroying private rights of action,
and that Sandoval may not be read to abrogate an affected person’s right
to challenge an agency’s non-adherence to its own regulations.
This result is especially compelling, given that the disclaimer also
raises the issue of judicial review. Judicial review of agency action is
important to the separation of powers, and by providing an impartial
forum in which to be heard, which is the quintessential means of fulfilling
due process. Professor Jaffe called judicial review of agency action a
bona fide right because of its exceptional importance in maintaining the
structure of our three-branch democracy and in enabling individuals to
128
vindicate their rights in court. Boilerplate disclaimers should be held
inoperative, because the right to judicial review should not be so easily
abrogated.

B. Disclaimers as Inherently Suspect: The Normative Case


Boilerplate disclaimers are not an unfamiliar phenomenon in the
law. Courts often find boilerplate disclaimers to be inoperative,
especially where observance of the disclaimer would be contrary to
public policy. In light of the strong skepticism courts usually show toward
other disclaimers, it is particularly striking that courts have approached
administrative disclaimers so uncritically. Courts have rejected parties’
arguments that a disclaimer should be taken at face value in a variety of
129 130
contexts, ranging from rent-to-own contracts, products liability cases,
131 132
and implied warrants of habitability, to employment contracts and
133
Establishment Clause challenges.

127. See supra notes 31–33.


128. See Jaffe, supra note 99, at 420.
129. See, e.g., Williams v. Walker-Thomas Furniture Co., 350 F.2d 445, 449 (D.C. Cir. 1965)
(finding the boilerplate disclaimer and fine print in a rent-to-own contract unenforceable, because it
was deemed unconscionable).
130. See, e.g., Ruzzo v. LaRose Enters., 748 A.2d 261, 268–69 (R.I. 2000) (rejecting attempts to
disclaim liability for injurious products); Henningsen v. Bloomfield Motors, Inc., 161 A.2d 69, 87, 95
(N.J. 1960) (rejecting a defense made by the manufacturer of a defective car that the buyers waived
any right to sue for consequential damages by accepting the fine-print boilerplate disclaimer).
131. See, e.g., Gym-N-I Playgrounds, Inc. v. Snider, 220 S.W.3d 905, 913–14 (Tex. 2007) (holding a
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 585

For instance, in Ruzzo v. LaRose Enterprises, the Rhode Island


Supreme Court refused to give effect to the standard boilerplate
disclaimer in a products liability case, where the user of the product
134
sustained injuries from a strong electric shock. The court found that the
user had little control over the product prior to its use, could not be
expected to insure against injury from use of the equipment, and had no
135
effective means of bargaining for a change in the product’s disclaimer.
136
Although the disclaimer was quite exhaustive and conspicuous, the
court held as a matter of law that such disclaimers must be deemed
ineffective because of the “policy considerations” implicated in
protecting the vulnerable user, who had little or no bargaining power nor
137
ability to protect himself from the manufacturer’s negligence.
This skepticism toward boilerplate disclaimers has been echoed in
the scholarly literature. In his article on environmental regulations,
Professor Robert Fischman opined that a disclaimer of judicial review in
the Federal Register may not override the statutory rights granted by the
138
APA. Professor Fischman noted that such boilerplate disclaimers are
commonly found in executive orders, but he distinguishes rules found in
the Code of Federal Regulations from those in executive orders. While

disclaimer inoperative in an implied warrant of habitability case).


132. See, e.g., Swanson v. Liquid Air Corp., 826 P.2d 664, 674 (Wash. 1992) (“We reject the
premise that this disclaimer can, as a matter of law, effectively serve as an eternal escape hatch for an
employer who may then make whatever unenforceable promises of working conditions it is to its
benefit to make.”).
133. See, e.g., ACLU v. Wilkinson, 895 F.2d 1098, 1104 (6th Cir. 1990) (rejecting a government
disclaimer of endorsement in an Establishment Clause case).
134. Ruzzo, 748 A.2d at 268–69.
135. Id. at 268.
136. Id. at 269. The disclaimer read: “THE BACK OF THIS CONTRACT CONTAINS
IMPORTANT TERMS AND CONDITIONS[,] INCLUDING TAYLOR’S DISCLAIMER FROM
ALL LIABILITY FOR INJURY OR DAMAGE AND DETAILS OF RENTER’S OBLIGATIONS
FOR RENTAL AND OTHER CHARGES AND RESPONSIBILITIES TO CARE FOR AND
RETURN THE ITEMS RENTED. THEY ARE PART OF THIS CONTRACT—PLEASE READ
THEM.” Id. at 264. On the back of the form, the disclaimer provided:
3. RESPONSIBILITY FOR USE AND DISCLAIMER OF WARRANTIES[.] You are
responsible for the use of the rented item(s). You assume all risks inherent in the operation
and use of the item(s) and agree to assume the entire responsibility for the defense of, and
to pay, indemnify and hold Taylor harmless from, and hereby release Taylor from, any and
all claims for damage to property or bodily injury (including death) resulting from the use,
operation or possession of the item(s), whether or not it be claimed or found that such
damage or injury resulted in whole or in part from Taylor’s negligence, from the defective
condition of the item(s) or from any cause. YOU AGREE THAT NO WARRANTIES,
EXPRESSED OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR
A PARTICULAR PURPOSE HAVE BEEN MADE IN CONNECTION WITH THE
EQUIPMENT RENTED.
Id. at 264.
137. Id. at 268.
138. Robert L. Fischman, From Words to Action: The Impact and Legal Status of the 2006 National
Wildlife Refuge System Management Policies, 26 Stan. Envtl. L.J. 77, 127 (2007).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

586 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

federal regulations create policies that are part of legislative frameworks,


and therefore have the force of law, executive orders do not, because
they are usually non-binding expressions of the President’s “personal”
139
policy preferences.
According to Professor George Wright, as a general proposition,
“the law should rebuttably presume that disclaimers—both their texts or
terms—should not be given significant legal weight in their own right,
apart from the relevant surrounding circumstances, social conflicts,
power relationships, independent rules, and other considerations of
140
public policy.”
Professor Wright explains that disclaimers should not be taken at
face value, because they tend to arise in situations involving disparate
power relationships, where one party seeks to circumvent meaningful
review of its actions:
These underlying questions cannot be meaningfully addressed by any
judicial reading of the text or terms of the disclaimer itself. The courts
should instead be asked to treat the litigated disclaimer merely as an
invitation to consider the underlying relevant circumstances, values,
conflicts, power relationships, rules, and public policy considerations
apart from the disclaimer itself. . . . [Disclaimers are] typically ‘bare[]’
and not self-justifying in cautioning against any inference that might be
141
drawn from the pre-existing evidence.
Accordingly, judges should routinely “look behind” such disclaimers and
inquire into the underlying circumstances and power relationships
between affected parties, which the court “may or may not want to
142
validate, given the interests and policies at stake.” Professor Wright
thus concluded that “every disclaimer is merely a purported disclaimer
143
until it somehow becomes effective.”
Professor Wright’s observation rings particularly true with respect
to administrative disclaimers. As observed in Part II, administrative
disclaimers implicate the two related concerns that arise from the
delegation of rulemaking authority: fairness concerns regarding the due
process rights of persons affected by agency action and structural
concerns regarding the proper delegation of authority between Congress,
the executive branch, and administrative agencies—interests and policies
that are weighty indeed. Agencies should not be permitted to insulate
their actions from judicial scrutiny, because this would undermine the
legitimacy and proper functioning of the administrative system. They

139. Id. at 127–28 & n.199 (citing Peter Raven-Hansen, Making Agencies Follow Orders: Judicial
Review of Agency Violations of Executive Order 12,291, 1983 Duke L.J. 285, 353).
140. R. George Wright, Your Mileage May Vary: A General Theory of Legal Disclaimers, 7 Pierce
L. Rev. 85, 87 (2008).
141. Id. at 88–89.
142. Id. at 88, 92.
143. Id. at 90.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 587

also should not be permitted to dispose of individuals’ grievances in a


manner that deprives those individuals of meaningful notice and
opportunity to be heard.

C. Unlawful Immigration Practices and the Boilerplate


Disclaimer
In this subpart, I apply my theory of administrative accountability to
the boilerplate disclaimer in section 287.12 of the immigration
regulations. This disclaimer is a particularly apt example, because it
purports to disclaim important substantive and procedural rights upon
which immigrants would normally rely to challenge unlawful immigration
practices, such as those alleged in the Sonoma case. This subpart
provides background for what is at stake with the particular disclaimer in
section 287.12, as a means of demonstrating how important agency
adherence to its regulations can be when the disposition of substantive
rights and interests is involved.
Immigrants’ rights groups have long fought for the ability to
144
challenge government action that deprives them of their rights. An
implied private right of action to vindicate their rights and interests has
been an important feature of immigration law, because immigrant groups
tend to be vulnerable: They are frequently targeted for discrimination
and violence, popular opinion is often against them, and they are not
145
accorded the same rights or privileges as citizens are. Immigration
regulations comprise a key factor in preventing such misconduct. But
because immigration laws intended to protect immigrants rarely provide
explicit mechanisms for enforcement, immigrants have relied on federal
courts to find implicit provisions allowing immigrants to vindicate their
146
rights in court. These legal conditions make immigrants particularly
dependent upon agency adherence to its immigration regulations.
In 1984, the Supreme Court held in INS v. Lopez-Mendoza that
immigrants are not entitled to the protection of the exclusionary rule at
147
deportation hearings. Notably, the Court indicated that invoking the
exclusionary rule would be unnecessary, because the INS had instituted
regulatory safeguards that largely fulfilled the function of protecting

144. See, e.g., United States ex rel. Accardi v. Shaughnessy, 347 U.S. 260, 261–62 (1954).
145. Unlike Fourth and Sixth Amendment protections, immigrants both documented and
undocumented are entitled to due process rights under the Fifth Amendment. See sources cited supra
note 16.
146. E.g., Brownell v. We Shung, 352 U.S. 180, 182 (1956), Accardi, 347 U.S. at 269; Kwong Hai
Chew v. Colding, 344 U.S. 590, 595–603 (1953).
147. 468 U.S. 1032, 1045–46 (1984) (holding that the exclusionary rule does not apply in
deportation proceedings). Immigrants also lack other constitutional protections, such as the right to
government-provided counsel. See Michelson v. INS, 897 F.2d 465, 467 (10th Cir. 1990) (holding that
there is no Sixth Amendment right to government-provided counsel in a deportation proceeding).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

588 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

148
immigrants and deterring unlawful government conduct. Historically,
at a deportation hearing, an immigrant was able to file a motion to
suppress evidence in three limited circumstances: (1) if an immigrant’s
inculpatory admission was involuntary, (2) if immigration officers
violated their own regulations in their efforts to obtain the evidence, or
(3) if the means used to acquire the evidence were so egregious as to
149
offend fundamental fairness. These were likely the regulatory
safeguards the Court had in mind in Lopez-Mendoza when it held that
the Constitution does not require the exclusionary rule in deportation
150
hearings. The holding in Lopez-Mendoza has meant that immigrants
will rely even more than ever on immigration regulations. If courts
continue to find that the disclaimer renders these last remaining
safeguards a nullity, it will render immigrants even more vulnerable to
misconduct and abuse.
Thus, prior to the enactment of the disclaimer, immigrants could
seek to exclude evidence obtained in violation of the regulations in
section 287. For example, among immigrants’ statutory protections is the
limitation on warrantless arrests. According to 8 U.S.C. § 1357, ICE
agents are authorized to arrest individuals without a warrant only if they
(1) have reason to believe that the individuals are in the United States in
violation of immigration law, and (2) have reason to believe that the
individuals are likely to escape before a warrant can be obtained for their
151
arrest. This basic rule is elaborated upon in the Code of Federal
Regulations at 8 C.F.R. § 287, which limits the circumstances under
which ICE agents may detain or arrest those they suspect of immigration
violations. The provisions in section 287 afford undocumented
immigrants rights similar to those afforded citizens in the Bill of Rights,
152
including the right against unreasonable searches and seizures, the right
not to be arrested without probable cause or reasonable suspicion of
153 154
wrongdoing, the right to be advised of the reasons for an arrest, and

148. Id.
149. 1 Bill Ong Hing, Handling Immigration Cases ¶ 8.39, at 361 (2d ed. 1995) (citing Garcia, 17
I. & N. Dec. 319 (BIA 1980); Garcia-Flores, 17 I. & N. Dec. 325 (BIA 1980); Toro, 17 I. & N. Dec. 340
(BIA 1980)).
150. See 468 U.S. 1032, 1045–46 (1984); see also Victor C. Romero, Note, Whatever Happened to
the Fourth Amendment?: Undocumented Immigrants’ Rights After INS v. Lopez-Mendoza and United
States v. Verdugo-Urquidez, 65 S. Cal. L. Rev. 999, 1005 (1992).
151. 8 U.S.C. § 1357 (2006).
152. See 8 C.F.R. § 287.9 (2009); id. § 287.8(f)(2) (2009) (“An immigration officer may not enter
into the non-public areas of a business, a residence including the curtilage of such residence, or a farm
or other outdoor agricultural operation, except as provided in Section 287(a)(3) of the Act, for the
purpose of questioning the occupants or employees concerning their right to be or remain in the
United States unless the officer has either a warrant or . . . consent . . . .”).
153. Id. § 287.8(c)(2)(i) (“An arrest shall be made only when the designated immigration officer
has reason to believe that the person to be arrested has committed an offense against the United
States or is an alien illegally in the United States.”); see also id. § 287.8(c)(2)(ii) (“A warrant of arrest
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 589

155
the right to be notified of these enumerated rights. The regulations also
state that the “standards for enforcement activities contained in this
section must be adhered to by every immigration officer involved in
156
enforcement activities . . . .”
Courts have differed in their approaches in determining whether
deportation proceedings should be invalidated when the immigration
agency violated its own regulations. Even before the disclaimer was
introduced in 1994, there was already a circuit split as to this issue. In
United States v. Calderon-Medina, the Ninth Circuit developed a two-
prong test for whether deportation proceedings should be invalidated
when an INS regulation was violated: First, the regulation in question
must serve a “purpose of benefit to the alien,” and second, if it does, the
regulatory violation will render the proceeding unlawful only if the
undocumented immigrant can show that she or he was prejudiced by the
157
violation.
In contrast, the Second Circuit takes a liberal approach and
categorically excludes from deportation hearings all evidence that was
the fruit of a regulatory violation. In Montilla v. INS, the Second Circuit
158
explicitly rejected the Ninth Circuit’s prejudice test. The court
explained that the test was fundamentally unfair, and that “the INS may
not fairly administer the immigration laws on the notion that on some
159
occasions its rules are made to be broken.”
While the trend has been to take the disclaimer largely at face value,
160
I contend that the Second Circuit’s more skeptical approach in Montilla
would yield a different result—and that a more critical approach is
desirable. Under the rule enunciated by the Second Circuit in Montilla,

shall be obtained except when the designated immigration officer has reason to believe that the person
is likely to escape before a warrant can be obtained.”).
154. Id. § 287.3(c) (2009) (“Except in the case of an alien subject to . . . expedited removal
provisions[,] . . . an alien arrested without warrant and placed in formal proceedings . . . will be advised
of the reasons for his or her arrest and the right to be represented at no expense to the Government.
The examining officer will provide the alien with a list of the available free legal services . . . and
attorneys . . . . The examining officer shall note on Form I-862 that such a list was provided to the
alien. The officer will also advise the alien that any statement made may be used against him or her in
a subsequent proceeding.”).
155. Id.; id § 287.8(c)(2)(v) (“The fact that a person has been advised of his or her rights shall be
documented on appropriate Department forms and made a part of the arrest record.”).
156. Id. § 287.8.
157. 591 F.2d 529, 531 (9th Cir. 1979). The BIA adopted the Ninth Circuit’s approach in Garcia-
Flores, 17 I. & N. Dec. 325, 328–29 (BIA 1980).
158. 926 F.2d 162, 167 (2d Cir. 1991).
159. Id. at 164. In so doing, the Second Circuit held that the Accardi doctrine required strict
adherence to the regulations, regardless of prejudice to the immigrant plaintiff. Id. at 166–67 & n.6
(“The Accardi doctrine is premised on fundamental notions of fair play underlying the concept of due
process.”). The effects of the Accardi doctrine on the boilerplate disclaimer are discussed in Part II,
infra.
160. Id. at 167.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

590 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

agency adherence to its own regulations is mandatory when the


161
regulations affect the rights or interests of the objecting party. Many, if
not all, of the provisions in section 287 are intended to benefit
undocumented immigrants, as distinguished from internal agency
procedures that do not affect undocumented immigrants. The provisions
in section 287 concern individual rights and so, by their nature, are
mandatory.
Unlike internal, non-binding agency rules, such as manuals on
162
bureaucratic matters, the regulations in section 287 affect the treatment
of undocumented immigrants. Among other things, they require legal
163
proceedings to be promptly initiated; they require officers to have
164
reasonable grounds for a warrantless arrest; they limit the use of lethal
165
and non-lethal force against undocumented immigrants; they require
166
officers to advise detained undocumented immigrants of their rights;
and they prohibit officers from conducting warrantless and non-
167
consensual searches. These provisions are akin to substantive rights,
and, in fact, mirror the types of protections guaranteed by the Bill of
168
Rights. Therefore, they must be adhered to under the Accardi doctrine,
because they affect the rights and interests of undocumented
169
immigrants.
Indeed, prior to its passage, the BIA indicated that the provisions of
section 287 are intended to benefit undocumented immigrants. In
Garcia-Flores, an undocumented immigrant appealed the immigration
judge’s order for deportation based on entering the country without

161. Id.
162. E.g., W. Radio Servs. Co. v. Espy, 79 F.3d 896, 900–01 (9th Cir. 1996) (Forest Service manuals
and handbooks); Reich v. Manganas, 70 F.3d 434, 437 (6th Cir. 1995) (internal operating manuals); see
also supra note 32 for a more exhaustive treatment.
163. 8 C.F.R. § 287.2 (2009).
164. Id. § 287.8(c)(2)(i) (2009).
165. Id. § 287.8(a)(1)(iii); id. § 287.9(b) (2009).
166. Id. §§ 287.3(c), 287.8(c)(2)(v).
167. Id. § 287.8(f)(2).
168. For instance, section 287.2 is similar to the Speedy Trial Clause; section 287.8(c)(2)(i) is
similar to the Warrants Clause; sections 287.8(a)(1)(iii) and 287.9(b) are similar to Eighth Amendment
protections; sections 287.3(c) and 287.8(c)(2)(v) are similar to the guarantees reflected in the Miranda
warnings; and section 287.8(f)(2) is similar to the Warrants Clause and the Search and Seizure Clause.
And all or most implicate the Due Process Clause. See supra notes 158–62 and accompanying text.
169. A mandatory reading of section 287 is especially compelling given the general rule of
construction that statutes are to be read as mandatory where they confer the power to perform acts
that concern the public interest or affect individual rights. 67 C.J.S., Officers and Public Employees
§ 238 (2010); see also Bd. of Educ. of Floyd Cnty. v. Moore, 264 S.W.2d 292 (Ky. 1953) (holding that a
statute imposing a positive duty on a public officer will be construed as mandatory, especially where it
concerns the rights of individuals); Flick v. Gately, 65 N.E.2d 137 (Ill. 1946) (explaining that the rule
holds, even if the language of the statute is merely permissive); Novak v. Novak, 24 N.W.2d 20 (N.D.
1946); Hersh v. Welsh, 18 A.2d 202 (Md. 1941) (explaining the rationale for this rule is that such
statutes are construed as imposing duties rather than conferring privileges).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 591

170
inspection. The evidence was based on her statements to an INS
investigator while detained, although she had not been warned of her
171
rights. At the time, section 287.3 required immigration investigators to
notify undocumented immigrants that they had a right to an attorney,
and that any statements they made could be used against them in
172
subsequent proceedings. On appeal, Garcia-Flores contended that the
evidence of her statement to the investigator should have been
suppressed, because she had been arrested without a warrant and had
173
not been advised of her rights under section 287.3. Applying the
Calderon-Medina test, the court held that section 287.3 was intended to
benefit undocumented immigrants and remanded to the immigration
judge for evidence of whether Garcia-Flores was prejudiced by the
174
failure of the INS to follow its regulations.
While the BIA applied the more conservative Calderon-Medina test,
rather than the Accardi-inspired Montilla test, the BIA nevertheless
acknowledged that the regulations are intended to benefit
undocumented immigrants, and that therefore, the agency must adhere
175
to its own regulations. Since the disclaimer entered the picture in 1994,
the government has argued that section 287.12 dispenses with the
176
agency’s duty to adhere to its regulations.
However, although the government now argues that section 287.12
is a complete defense to a regulatory violation, it was not clear at the
time the disclaimer was passed that the agency intended this to be the
effect. The legislative history of section 287.12 (originally published as
section 287.11) acknowledges, if obliquely, the Accardi principle as
binding authority. In her notes accompanying the promulgation of the
disclaimer, Attorney General Janet Reno asserted that the disclaimer
would not interfere with an immigrant’s rights under Accardi:
The commenters claimed that § 287.11 would preclude victims of
unlawful Service enforcement practices from pursuing remedies for
regulatory violations. However, this disclaimer merely states that the

170. 17 I. & N. Dec. 325, 325 (BIA 1980).


171. Id. at 327.
172. See id.
173. Id. at 326.
174. Id. at 328–29.
175. See id.
176. See Brief for Respondent at 42, Martinez v. Keisler, No. 06-75098, 2007 WL 4592036 (9th Cir.
Nov. 9, 2007); Brief for Respondent at 30, Rodriguez-Echeverria v. Gonzales, No. 06-73670, 2007 WL
3033041 (9th Cir. July 6, 2007); Brief for Respondent at 54, Chen v. Gonzales, No. 06-1143-AG(L),
2006 WL 4877812 (2d Cir. Dec. 18, 2006); Brief for Respondent at 25, Mosqueda-Arajuo v. Ashcroft,
No. 03-71706, 2003 WL 23334597 (9th Cir. Dec. 29, 2003); Defendant’s Motion to Dismiss the Second
Amended Complaint at 8–9, Comm. for Immigrant Rights of Sonoma Cnty. v. Sonoma Cnty., No. 08-
4220-PJH, 2009 WL 5002633 (N.D. Cal. Nov. 3, 2009); Proposed Reply Brief in Support of the United
States’ Motion to Dismiss at 6–7, Villegas v. Metro. Gov’t of Davidson Cnty., No. 309-0219, 2009 WL
5052990 (M.D. Tenn. June 10, 2009).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

592 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

regulations provide no independent grounds for relief in any civil or


criminal proceeding by any party. It does not prevent any party from
pursuing relief for alleged violations of the Constitution or laws of the
United States. As such, the disclaimer is consistent with the holding in
United States v. Caceres, 440 U.S. 741 (1979). This disclaimer is a
standard element for all regulations affecting substantive federal
criminal law enforcement authority and is only intended to ensure that
177
the regulations do not create rights not otherwise existing in law.
Caceres was an Accardi case in which the Court found that the
regulations violated in that case did not affect substantive rights and
178
therefore, did not require strict adherence. Thus, after the notice-and-
comment period, the agency felt compelled to announce that it would not
deliberately violate its own regulations. Even though the Attorney
General chose her precedent carefully, announcing a policy of
conforming to Caceres, rather than to the more liberally worded Accardi
case, she still evinced a willingness to comply with the Accardi
imperative. Because the Accardi right (or duty-cum-right) has existed
since 1954, it is a right already “existing in law.”
As a result, I propose that courts should go even further in enforcing
ICE’s duty to follow its regulations than the Court did in enforcing the
IRS’ duty to do so in Caceres. Because the regulations in section 287
affect the legal status and liberty interests of immigrants, the agency may
not shake off the heavy burden imposed by Accardi simply by invoking a
boilerplate disclaimer. Agencies are bound to follow the regulations they
promulgate, and courts should view attempts to circumvent this duty—
for example, by passing a boilerplate disclaimer such as section 287.12—
carefully scrutinizing them for their effect on the liberty interests of
undocumented immigrants.
Undocumented immigrants should also continue to have an implied
private right of action to challenge an agency’s non-adherence to section
287. Both the Accardi imperative and the text of the enabling statute,
8 U.S.C. § 1357, support the conclusion that there is an implied private
right of action. Section 1357 authorizes ICE agents to arrest individuals
without a warrant only if they (1) have reason to believe that the
individuals are in the United States in violation of immigration law, and

177. Enhancing the Enforcement Authority of Immigration Officers, 59 Fed. Reg. 42,406, 42,413
(Aug. 17, 1994) (notes accompanying final rule codified at 8 C.F.R. § 287.12). Note, however, that
deportation proceedings do not technically constitute criminal law enforcement at all. See Bridges v.
Wixon, 326 U.S. 135, 147 (1945).
178. See 440 U.S. at 752 (reversing the suppression of recorded conversations made in violation of
internal agency procedures, where the violation of the regulations was technical and inadvertent and
did not compromise the overall fairness of the proceedings). Note, though, that Professor Merrill has
argued that Caceres is not a proper Accardi case to begin with; as he explained, “There is no indication
in the opinion or the briefs that the rule [in Caceres] was the product of delegated authority from
Congress. This should have stopped the Accardi analysis in its tracks.” Merrill, The Accardi Principle,
supra note 20, at 601.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 593

(2) have reason to believe that the individuals are likely to escape before
179
a warrant can be obtained for their arrest. Moreover, the statute
imposes requirements upon ICE, which it must observe before arrest
180
authority vests in the agency.
Further, agents are permitted to detain an immigrant who is
arrested by a federal, state, or local law enforcement official for a drug-
related offense, only if the official:
(1) has reason to believe that the alien may not have been lawfully
admitted . . . or present in the United States, (2) expeditiously informs
an appropriate officer . . . of the arrest and of facts concerning the
status of the alien, and (3) requests the Service to determine promptly
181
whether or not to issue a detainer to detain the alien.
Under the factors identified by Cort, and even by Cort’s more
conservative progeny, there is ample basis for a court to find an implied
private right of action in the enabling statute. As in Rolland, § 1357
contains “rights-creating language” that is put forth in mandatory terms.
Together, the fact that courts have already held that the regulations in
182
section 287 are intended to benefit affected persons, along with the
Accardi principle, indicate that the regulations are mandatory.
The right to judicial review also applies with particular force in the
immigration context. As Professor Jaffe observed, the Supreme Court
held in Yamataya v. Fisher that the resident alien was entitled to a
183
deportation hearing under the Due Process Clause, and in Gegiow v.
184
Uhl, the Court held that the alien seeking admission to the United
States was entitled to enter, notwithstanding the agency’s decision to the
185
contrary and statutory language that the Commissioner’s decision

179. 8 U.S.C. § 1357 (2006).


180. Id. § 1357(a)(5) (“The authority to make arrests under paragraph (5)(B) shall only be
effective on and after the date on which the Attorney General publishes final regulations which
(i) prescribe the categories of officers and employees of the Service who may use force (including
deadly force) and the circumstances under which such force may be used, (ii) establish standards with
respect to enforcement activities of the Service, (iii) require that any officer or employee of the Service
is not authorized to make arrests under paragraph (5)(B) unless the officer or employee has received
certification as having completed a training program which covers such arrests and standards
described in clause (ii), and (iv) establish an expedited, internal review process for violations of such
standards, which process is consistent with standard agency procedure regarding confidentiality of
matters related to internal investigations.”).
181. Id. § 1357(d).
182. E.g., Garcia-Flores, 17 I. & N. Dec. 325, 329 (BIA 1980).
183. 189 U.S. 86, 100–01 (1903) (“[T]his [C]ourt has never held . . . that administrative officers,
when executing the provisions of a statute involving the liberty of persons, may disregard the
fundamental principles that inhere in ‘due process of law’ . . . .”).
184. 239 U.S. 3, 10 (1915) (“We cannot suppose that so much greater a power was entrusted by
implication in the same act to every commissioner of immigration . . . .”).
185. Specifically, the Act of Feb. 20, 1907, ch. 1134, § 25, 34 Stat. 907. See Jaffe, supra note 99, at
425 n.80.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

594 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

186
would be final in all cases. Judicial review played a key role in both
cases, even where the agency declared its actions to be categorically
unreviewable.
In the case of section 287.12, the disclaimer threatens to remove one
of the last remaining safeguards in deportation proceedings. Prior to the
passage of section 287.12, immigrants had a number of other remedies
which are now threatened by the disclaimer. Previously, if ICE violated
its own regulations, immigrants affected by that violation could have had
the evidence suppressed in their deportation proceedings, either in
187
immigration court or on appeal to an Article III court. In addition, they
could have sought injunctive, declaratory, and habeas corpus relief in an
188
Article III court. Now, the agency’s same argument against injunctive
relief seemingly can apply to other forms of relief. If the agency is not
beholden to its rules, as it argues it is not because of the disclaimer, then
it is conceivable that there would also be no enforceable duty in the
other remedial contexts, as well.
Indeed, this possibility is on the horizon. Despite the fact that
immigrants facing deportation could seek to exclude evidence that was
the fruit of a regulatory violation, the First Circuit and the BIA have
189
applied section 287.12 to prevent the suppression of evidence. The
Sonoma case now threatens the future possibility of injunctive and
190
declaratory relief, although the Ninth Circuit has yet to rule on the
191
issue. If future courts follow the reasoning in these cases, it is entirely

186. See Jaffe, supra note 99, at 425–26 (“[W]hen the record shows that a commissioner of
immigration is exceeding his power, the alien may demand his release upon habeas corpus.” (quoting
Gegiow, 239 U.S. at 9)).
187. An immigrant can seek to have evidence suppressed in deportation proceedings in the
immigration courts and before the BIA, if certain conditions are met. See Hing, supra note 149. If the
immigration courts refuse to exclude the evidence at the deportation hearing, the immigrant may
appeal directly to a circuit court of appeals and seek to have the evidence suppressed. See, e.g., Navia-
Duran v. INS, 568 F.2d 803, 811 (1st Cir. 1977) (suppressing evidence in Article III court on appeal
from the BIA).
188. Damages could potentially be available as well, but the plaintiff must first file an
administrative claim with the Department of Homeland Security as a prerequisite for seeking money
damages in court. 28 U.S.C. § 2675 (2006).
189. See, e.g., Navarro-Chalan v. Ashcroft, 359 F.3d 19, 23 & n.3 (1st Cir. 2004); Yongo v. INS, 355
F.3d 27, 31 (1st Cir. 2004); Alessandra de Paula, No. A96 414 623, 2007 WL 2074418, at *2–3 (BIA
June 18, 2007) (unpublished).
190. Comm. for Immigrant Rights of Sonoma Cnty. v. Sonoma Cnty., No. C 08-4220 PJH, 2010
WL 841372, at *1, *6 (N.D. Cal. Mar. 10, 2010).
191. In de Rodriguez-Echeverria v. Mukasey, the Ninth Circuit entertained the issue of the legal
effect of section 287.12, but ultimately remanded the case to the BIA. 534 F.3d 1047, 1050 (9th Cir.
2008). The court requested the BIA’s guidance on the matter, “[g]iven the considerable changes to the
law since the BIA last interpreted this regulation and the apparent disagreement among government
agencies as to what Section 287.3 requires.” Id. at 1052. The court mentioned the addition of section
287.12 as one of the changes—or perhaps as the primary change—that may affect the meaning of
section 287.3. See id. at 1052 n.2. As of yet, the BIA does not appear to have issued a decision as to
what section 287.3 requires. The case on remand did not appear on the BIA docket for 2009 or 2010.
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

December 2010] THE UN-CREATION OF RIGHTS 595

possible that a regulatory violation will no longer be grounds for habeas


192
corpus relief either. In the cases that have emerged since the disclaimer
was passed, all of these remedies have been threatened.
Alternatively, it is possible that under the particular wording of
section 287.12, none of this is necessary. Even if we were to accept
section 287.12’s claim that the regulations govern “internal agency
procedures” (which, as I have argued, should not be the case), they still
implicate a liberty interest. The language in the disclaimer, that the
regulations “do not create any rights not already existing,” could be such
that they still recognize the rights created by the Accardi imperative.
While courts have thus far declined to adopt this reading of the
disclaimer, it is consistent with the incorporation of United States v.
Caceres, an Accardi case, into the legislative history of the disclaimer.
This interpretive move could allow courts to circumvent the
constitutional difficulties raised by administrative disclaimers, while still
enforcing Accardi.
Because of the considerations of structural coherence and due
process, and because of the particularly devastating effect section 287.12
could have on the fates of undocumented immigrants, courts should find
that the boilerplate immigration disclaimer cannot abrogate rights
protected by the Accardi imperative.

Conclusion
193
No agency is an island. At the most fundamental level, my reasons
for rejecting administrative disclaimers involve due process and the
proper structuring of the administrative state. I have argued that these
twin concerns bear upon two pillars of legitimacy: order and fairness. As
Professor Thomas Franck observed, order and fairness are indispensable
to legitimacy:
Legitimacy . . . expresses the preference for order, which may or may
not be conducive to change. Nevertheless, it is a key factor in fairness,
for it accommodates a deeply felt popular belief that for a system of
rules to be fair, it must be firmly rooted in a framework of formal
194
requirements about how rules are made, interpreted, and applied.

192. Professor Neuman anticipated the argument that habeas corpus relief should not be available
to challenge deportation, refuting it on the grounds that the Suspension Clause limits Congress’s
ability to abrogate that right of action. Neuman, supra note 105, at 1044–57.
193. Louis L. Jaffe, Judicial Review: Question of Law, 69 Harv. L. Rev. 239, 274–75 (1955) (“An
agency is not an island entire of itself. It is one of the many rooms in the magnificent mansion of the
law. The very subordination of the agency to judicial jurisdiction is intended to proclaim the premise
that each agency is to be brought into harmony with the totality of the law; the law as it is found in the
statute at hand, the statute book at large, the principles and conceptions of the ‘common law,’ and the
ultimate guarantees associated with the Constitution.”).
194. Thomas M. Franck, Fairness in International Law and Institutions 7–8 (1995).
Mason_62-HLJ-559.doc (Do Not Delete) 1/13/2011 10:46 AM

596 HASTINGS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 62:559

This “deeply felt popular belief” is arguably what lies at the heart of
due process. Agencies will contend they are entitled to promulgate
regulations, and they are consequently entitled to disregard them as they
please. In this Note, I demonstrated why this reasoning is reductive and
profoundly unfair. An agency cannot give with one hand what the other
hand then takes away. An agency’s attempt to insulate itself from review
by means of a boilerplate disclaimer undermines the legitimacy of agency
action and threatens what is at the very core of due process.

Potrebbero piacerti anche