Sei sulla pagina 1di 2

The Common Sense Case for Liberty

by Bryan Caplan

Let me begin with a disclaimer: Despite his moral views, Robin is an incredibly nice, decent
person. He wouldn’t hurt a fly. To know Robin is to love him. Robin Hanson, you complete me!

Nevertheless, Robin endorses an endless list of bizarre moral claims. For example, he recently
told me that “the main problem” with the Holocaust was that there weren’t enough Nazis! After
all, if there had been six trillion Nazis willing to pay $1 each to make the Holocaust happen, and
a mere six million Jews willing to pay $100,000 each to prevent it, the Holocaust would have
generated $5.4 trillion worth of consumers surplus.

Let’s consider another example. Suppose the only people in the world are Hannibal the
millionaire, a slave trader, and 10,000 penniless orphan slaves. The slave trader has no direct
use for his slaves, but likes money; Hannibal, on the other hand, is a ravenous cannibal.
According to Robin, the “optimal outcome” is for Hannibal to get all 10,000 orphans and eat
them.

If you’ve ever taken a class in moral philosophy, you’ve probably heard weird examples like
these before. Normally, these examples lead people to back away from their pet moral theories.
Robin’s devotion to efficiency is so strong, however, that he will bite any bullet you present. The
most he’ll say in his own defense is that he is “Merely serving as an advisor to help people get
what they want,” but the fact remains that faced with the preceding examples, he’d advise
genocide and cannibalism.

Frankly, I think my grostesque examples reveal a fatal flaw not just in Robin’s efficiency
standard, but in all one-sentence moral theories. It is absurd to latch on to an abstract grand
moral theory, and then defend it against every counter-example.

Here’s my alternative: Sensible moral reasoning begins with concrete, specific cases. For
example: It would be wrong for me to walk over to Robin right now and punch him. From there,
we can start to generalize. It would probably be wrong for me to walk over and punch any of the
people in this room. At the same time, we can note exceptions. If Robin had consented to box
me, then punching him would be OK. In fact, it would probably be wrong not to try to punch him,
because I’d be cheating you, the audience.

How far can you get with my approach? Very far. One straightforward moral generalization is
that it is normally wrong to start using or threatening physical violence against others. Another is
that it is normally wrong to take people’s property without their consent. Even children
understand these norms: “Use your words,” and “That doesn’t belong to you.” On reflection,
though, these norms are equivalent to the libertarian principles of respecting the life and property
of others.

But isn’t libertarianism just another “abstract grand moral theory” subject to all kinds of
devastating counter-examples? If you take libertarian principles as absolute, then the answer is
Yes. As I speak, everyone in this room is shooting carbon dioxide molecules at other people
without their consent.

Note, however, that I was careful to say that it is “normally” wrong to violate the liberty of others.
If you’ve got a good reason to violate liberty, I’m open to it. “We’ll all die if we stop breathing” is
a pretty good reason. In contrast, “Most of us want to rob them,” is an embarrassingly bad
reason.

If this is really my view, why bother to study economics? My answer: When someone says there
is a “good reason” for a regulation or a tax, we can use economics see whether the story holds
water. If someone says that we need to restrict the liberty of American consumers to buy
Japanese goods in order to prevent the destruction of the U.S. economy, we can see if the
textbook chapter on international trade agrees. The same applies if someone says it would be
more efficient to raise taxes and spend the revenue on education. Maybe the economics will
check out, and we’ll have to think about whether we have a good enough reason to violate
liberty. More often, though, the economics doesn’t check out – and we avoid violating the liberty
of another human being for less than no reason at all.

If you ask me, “Can you prove that your moral view is correct?,” I could answer your question
with another question: “Can Robin prove that his moral view is correct?” But I don’t want to
dodge this challenge. The strength of my position is precisely that I’m not offering you a phony
seventeen-step “proof that murder is normally wrong.” Instead, I begin with concrete, specific
cases where morality is obvious, and reason from there. I don’t have a mathematical formula
like “Maximize the sum of willingness to pay.” That’s OK. Unlike Robin, I’d rather be vaguely
right than precisely wrong.

Potrebbero piacerti anche