Sei sulla pagina 1di 12

j Topics in Regulatory Economics

and Policy Series THE ECONOMICS OF THE

Michael A. Crew, Editor ANTITRUST PROCESS

Graduate School of Management


Rutgers University
Newark, New Jersey, U.S.A.

Previously published books in the series:

Hillman, J., and R. Braeutigam:


Price Level Regulation for Diversified Public Utilities
Einhorn, M.:
Price Caps and Incentive Regulation in Telecomnmnications
Crew, M.:
Competition and the Regulation in Telecomnmnications
Crew, M., and P. Kleindorfer:
Competition and Innovation in Postal Services edited by
Thompson, H.:
Regulatory Finance: Financial Foundations oj-Rate of Return Regulation Malcolm B. Coate

Crew, M., and P. Kleindorfer:


Economic Innovations in Public Utility Regulation Federal Trade Commission

Crew, M., and P. Kleindorfer:


The Economics of Postal Service and

Crew, M., and P. Kleindorfer:


Regulation and the Nature of Postal and Delivery Services
Oren, S. and S. Smith.: Andrew N. K1eit

Service Opportunities for Electric Utilities: Creating Differentiated Products Louisiana State University
Kolbe, A. L., W. B. Tye, and S. C. Myers:
Regulatory Risk: Economic Principles and Applications to Natural Gas Pipelines
Pecbman. C.:
Regulating Power: The Economics of Electricity in the Information Age
Gordon, R. L.:
Regulation and Economic Analysis: A Critique Over 1Wo Centuries
Blackmon, G.:
Incentive Regulation and the Regulations of Incentives .....

"

Crew, M.:
Incentive Regulation for Public Utilities
Crew, M.:
Commercialization of Postal and Delivery ServiceS
Abbott, T. A.: KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBUSHERS

Health Care Policy and Regulation


BostoniDordrechtlLondon

Goff, B.:
Regulation and Macroeconomic Performance /qq;;,
References

Baseman, Kenneth C., Warren-Boulton, P. R., and G. A. Woroch. 1995. "MicrolOd Playa
Hardball: Use of Exclusionary Pricing and T""lm.ical Incompatibility to Maintain
Monopoly Power in Markets for Operating System Software." AMmut Bulktin
40(2):265-315.

Berlot, Ed. 1994. Letter to Editor. Byte 19(8):18. Chapter 10


Easterbrook, Frank H. 1986. "On Identii)'ing Exolusionary Conduot." Notre Dame Law
Review 61(5):912-980.

Flynn, Ida M. and Ann M. McHo... 1991. Understanding Operating Systems. Pacific Grove, Predatory Pricing in the Retail Trade:
CA: Brooks/Cole Publishing Company.
The Waf-Mart Case
Fryer, Bronwyn. 1995. "Tho Sof\ware Police." Wired 3(5):88-96.

IcllibiAh, Daniel and Susan L. Knepper. 1991. The Maki:ng ofMWrosojt. Rocklin, CA: Prima Donald J. Boudreaux 1
Publisbing.

Mat.hillen, Tozjo. 1994. "Noven's Newest DOS." Byte 19(7):241.

Ordover,Janusz A. and Solto C. Panzar. 1982. "On the Nonlinear Pricing of Inputs." Inu,....
tional Economic Revi.... 23(3):659-675.
1. Introduction
Posner, Richard A. and Prank H. Easterbrook. 1980. Antitrust: Cases, Economic Notes IJIId
Other Malerials. SainI Paul, MN: West Publisbing Company. In 1987, Wal-Mart began selling pharmaceuticals in Faulkner County, Arkansas.
Consistent with its overall retai1 strategy, Wal-Mart sought to sell a high volume of
Rohm, Wendy G. 1994. "Ob No, Mr. Bill! The Inside Story of the U.S. Government',
pharmaceuticals at low lDHtgins. Wal-Mart's explicit policy was to never be
Aotitrust Case Against Microsoft." Wired 2(4):90ff.
undersold on a pharmacy item. Although the manager of each local Wal-Mart
Salop, Steven C. and David T. Soheffirum. 19&7. "Cost IWsing Strategies." Jo1lrMl of pbB.rmacy had no autlwrity to raise prices above those set at WaI-MJU1.'s
Industrial Economics 36(1):19-34. headquarters, each manager was permitted to lower prices to beat those charged by
rival retailers eVen if these prices were lowered below the wholesale prices paid by
Scherer, F. M. 1992. "Schumpeler and Plausible Capitalism." JOIlT1UlI of Economic Litera1UT' Wal -Mart for the individual items it retailed.
30(3):1416-1433. Predictably - in light of antitrust's history of being used by firms to bludgeoA

their more successful rivals (Bau:mol and Ordover (1985); McChesney and Shughart

Scbulman, Aodrew. 1994. Uno:uJkorit.ed Window. 95. San Mateo, CA: IDG Booka (1995» - WaI-MJU1. was sued in 1991 by three local ph.amuicies for attempting to

Worldwide. monopolim the market for pharmaceuticals and health and beauty aids in Faulkner
County. This suit, American Drugs, Inc. v. Wal-Man Stores, Inc. (hereinafter
Sohumpoler, Jo.eph A. 1950. Capitalism, Soci41ism and Democracy (third ed.). N_ Yort: 'Wal-Mal1 Stores"), was brought in Arkansas state rout! under Arkansas's Unfliir
Harper and Row. Practices Act, a 1937 statute reminiscent of the Robinson-Patman Act. Altlwugh
WaI-MJU1. lost in a bench trial, it narrowly prevailed on appeal to the Arkansas
Wallaee, lames and Jim Erickson. 1992. Hard Dri>e: Bill Gates and 1M Making oj 1M
Microsoft Empire. New York: lohn Wiley and Sons. Supreme Court which found that Wal-Mart's pricing practices could not reasonably
have been intended to destroy rompetition (as is ""luired by the Act).

194
Apart from the attention it received in the popular and business press, Wal-Mart eXClusively on the plausibility of the claim that Wal-Mart attempted to monopolize
Stores raises a host of interesting economic and antitrust issues. I explore some of the relevant market through predatory-pricing practices.
these issues below. In particular, I ask what it means to assert that a retailer intends In partiCUlar, Wal-Mart allegedly violated the following statutory provision:
to monopolize an appropriately defined retail market through predatory pricing:
when, if ever, are such attempts sensible? Can a retailer attempting to monopolize It shall be unlawful for any •.. corporation ..• engaged in business
through a predatory-pricing strategy ever hope to do so by pricing some, though not within this state, to sell, offer for sale, or advertise for sale lilly article or
all. of its retail itetnS below invoice cost'? Perhaps most fundamentally, 1 ask product . • • at less than cost thereof to the vendor . • . for the purpose
whether it can make any sense to distinguish predatory from non-predatory costs, as of injuring competitors aod destroying competition. 4
is now done with the AreOOa-Tumer test. I also explore the still-largely-unexplored
question of the incentives of manufacturers or wholesalers to take steps to keep Thus, a successful plaintiff must prove three separate facts: (1) that the defendant
retailing competitive. I begin, however, with a fuller acoount of the Wal-Mart priced (or offered to sell) a llood 'at less than cost tu' the defendant; (2) that such
Stores litigation. below-cost pricing was done for the purpose of injuring competitors, and (3) that
such below-cost pricing was done for the purpose of destroying competition.
The plaintiffs presented undJsputed evidence that Wal-Mart occa.sionaJly priced
2. The titigation individnal pha.rmaceutic,oJ items beloW these items' iovoice costs. Indeed, Wal-Mart
admitted this much. Wal-Mart, however, dmied that its practice of pricing a
Three local pharmacies in Faulkner County (American Drugs, Balcer Drugs, and bendful of itetnS below invoice amouoted to unlawful belaw-cost sales. Wal-Mart
Mayflower Family Pb.annacy) jointly b'Ued Wal-Mart under an ArIo1nsas statute insisted that the televant product is not any individoal item; rather. the relevant
designed to prohibit predatory pricing. Because plaintiffs sought, in addition to product is a market basket of PharmJlceuticals. Because there was no allegation that
dama~es, to enjoin Wal-Mart's pricing practices, the case was removed to chancery Wal-Mart ever sold any bundle of pharmaceuticals at an aggregate price belaw cost •
court. - in fact, the Faulkner County Wal-Mart's pha.rmacy was continually profitable
Wal-Mart was accused of violating the statute in two distinct ways. The first during the entire period of the alleged predation - if the relevant product was
was a straightforward predatory-pricing allegation based On the AreOOa-Turner defined as a market-basket of pharmaceuticals, then Wal-Mart would win the case
(1975) test: the plaintiffs accused Wal-Mart of attempting to monopolize the outright.
Faulkner County retail market for pharntaceuticals aod health and beauty aids The trial court, however, accepted the plaintiffs' argument that the statole Was
through its policy of retailing a handful of its pharntaceutical items at prices below aimed at below-cost pricing of individoal itetnS and could not sensibly be inletpreted
the invoice costs Wal-Mart paid for these itetnS. Plaintiffs' expert ecooomist to mean 'below-cost pricing of a market basket of goods.' I later discuss this issue
testified that the invoice cost of any pharmaceutical item is less thsn the average in more depth.
variable cost (AVe) of selling this item. It follows that Wal-Mart's below-invoice The trial court then, having concluded that Wal-Mart did indeed price below

prices on a handful of items were also below Ave. Moreover, this expert cost, asked wbether or not such pricing Was intended to injure competitors and

economist argued that failure to maximize profits on any aingle product violates the destroy competition. Recognizing that direct evidence of Ii firm's intent is virtually

Areeda-Turner test and is, thereby, evidence of predatory intent. Under this logic, nonexistent, the trial court understandably sought to decipher intent by examining tru.

the fact that below-invoice prices on pharntaceuticals items might increase Wal­ facts aod circumstances surrounding Wal-Mart's cba1lenged pricing ptactices.

Mart's profits on other items is irrelevant for a predatory-pricing inquiry.3 The court listed six circumstances that in combination strongly suggested to it
Second, Wal-Mart was accused of trapping gullible consumers wbo, lured onto that Wal-Mart's below-cost pricing was meant to harm competitors aod destroy
Wal-Mart's premises by the promise of exceptionally law prices on select items, competition. These six circumstances are:
would also purchase items with exceptionally high retail mark ups. The plaintiff's • The number and frequency of below-cost sales.
pleadings against Wal-Mart lumped the second allegation in with the first; it is as if • The extent of below-cost sales.
the plaintiffs and their attorneys saw no difference between the two allegations. I • Wal-Mart'. stated pricing policy - 'meet or beat the competition without
do not here address the allegation of 'Iow-price luring' because it i. not really an regard to oost••
allegation of predation, and the trial decision as well as the appellate opinion turned • Wal-Mart's stated purpose of below-cost sales - to attract Ii disproportionate
number of customers to Wal-Mart. 5

196
197
• The in-store price comparison of products sold by competitors, including with predatory intent is sufficient- failure to destroy a rival is nevertheless evidence
plaintiffs. against an allegation of predatory intent. Presul!lllbly, a fum with pockets as deep
• The disparity in prices between Faulkner County prices of the relevant as Wal-Mart could well have crushed eacb of the plaintiffs bad it been so inclined.
product-lines and other msikets with more or less competition. Second, the market was served by several other pharmacies in addition to Wat­
With no additiODll! comment, the trial court concluded that the combination of Mart and the plaintiffs. 12 Many of these other pharmacies were national retsilers.
these six circumstances proved that Wal-Mart priced with the requisite predatory Recouping its predatory expenses would bave required that Wal-Mart cbaq:e
intent. Therefore, Wal-Mart was ordered to stop charging below-invoice prices for monopoly prices after rivals bad been destroyed. Ability to Cbarge monopoly prices,
its plw.tma<:euticals, as well as to pay treble damage<! (of $289,407) to the three plaintiffs. bowever, required either that Wal-Mart successfully prey on all of its rivals _
Wal-Mart appealed. In January 1995, the Arkansas Supreme Court voted 4 to including nations! mail-order houses - or that WaJ-Mart successfully conspire to
3 to reverse the trial court and dismiss the case. 6 The bigb court ruled that these cartelize the market with those rivals against whom it did not prey. No aIlegationa
six circumstances provided inadequate grounds for the trial-court's inference of the were I!Illde of either of these additions! tactics. The lesson bere is that aIlegatiDDB
requisite predatory intent. First, the high court was dissatisfied with the failure of of predation against only a subset of rivals should be sufficient grounds for dismissal
the lower court to quantify the frequency, extent, and duration of Wal-Mart's below­ if the statute requires that the plaintiff prove an intent by the defendant to destroy
cost sales. 7 Secondly, the higb court implicitly criticized the trialjudge" failure competition.
to weigb alternative interpretations of Wal-Mart's pricing practices against the anti­ Third, the Arkansas Supreme Court took explicit notice of the statute',
competitive bypothesis advanced by the plaintiffs. The high court ruled that, because depression-era origins. As the ""urt pointed out, the legislature declared the statute
Wal-Mart regularly varied the few items it sold below invoice, its pricing practice to be "an emergency measure' aimed at avoidin! bankruptcies whicb would
was more plausibly one of loss-leading designed to attract greater traffic into the 'increas[e] the prevailing condition of depression. ,I Regardless of the prudential
store. Greater customer traffic increases present profits, and so is not appropriately merits of assisting macroeconomic recovery througb legislation aimed at stemming
descn'bed as predatory; "the chancery court erred in inferring a purpose to destroy below-cost pricing, the court wisely ruled that this statute should not generally be
competition from a loss-leader strategy. ,8 The court proceeded to point out that, available for use by plaintiffs dismayed by rivals' loss-leading policies. Arkansas'.
uuder the lower-court's logic, loss-leading would become prima facie evidence of high court implicitly recognized what the United States Supreme Court explicitly
predatory intent; loss-leading would thus become illegal, "and we are not willing to spelled out nearly a decade earlier in the Matsushita decision: 'cutting price in ord«
invalidate, and indeed render illegal, the technique of using lo....leader products or to increase business is often the very essence of competition. Thus, mistaken
services without a clear directive from the General Assembly that that is now the inferences in [predatory-pricing cases] are especially costf' because they chil1 the
public policy of the State of Arkansas. ,9 very conduct the antitrust laws are designed to protect. ,I
The higb court also fouud no necessary implication of intent to destroy
competition from Wal-Mart's in·store price comparisons, nOr from the disparity
between the prices charged by the Faulkner County store and those charged by WaI­ 3. Broader Economic Issues
Mart stores elsewhere in Arkansas. 'There is certainly nO fault in comparative
pricing. On the contrary, that tactic appears to foster and encourage competition. Stepping back from the details of the Wal-Man Stores ruling, it is interesting to
••• Nor is the fact thet Wal-Mart stores in other localities varied the prices of their investigate more generally some of the economic iSb1JeS raised by this litigation. I
products in response to local competition sufficient to trove that Conway Wal-Mart focus on four. Fint, is predation possible when a firm Cbarges prices below costs
intended to destroy competition in Faulkner County.' 0 on only a handful of items that it and its rivals sell? Second, uuder what conditiOl1ll
In shorl, a bare I!Illjority of Arkansas's Supreme Court understood that evidence will manufacturers wbo distribute through a suspected predator take steps to police
of below-invoice pricing, even combined with local variations in prices, bas a against this downstream predation? Third, does monopolization at one stage of
plausible pro-competitive explanation. As such, any inference of predatory intent production necessarily harm finns upstream or downstream from the monopolist if
from these facts alone is invalid. bargaining between the upstream and downstream monopolists is possible? In a
The high court discussed three additional reasons wbyan inference ofpredatory recent article, Hove.nkamp (1991) argnes that it does not. I argne below the
intent is inappropriate in this case. The first is that the plaintiffs "all continued into contrary. Fourth and most fundamentally, does it make sense to distinguish
1993 making a profit.· ll Although it is not necessary that an alleged predator predatory from non-predstory prices on the basis of costs?
actually destroy a rival in order to violate the statute - below-rost pri= combined

198 199
~

3.1 Single Good or Market Basket? predstion requires that the entire bundle of products comprising the ma:rk:et so
defined be sold at prices that generste revenues below cost. Otherwise, equally
The trial court in Wal·Mart Stores rejected Wal-Mart's argument that below-invoice efficient sellers of this product are not thIestened with bankruptcy by the alleged
pricing of a handful of items does not lUIlDunt to below-cost pricing of the kind the predstor's pricing behavior. Therefore, in Wal-Mart Stores, because all parties
statute aims to prohibit. Claiming to read the statote according to its plain mesning, agreed that the relevant product market was ·pharmaceutical. and health and beauty
the trial court noted that "the Act' applies to 'any article or product' and not aids,' the court misused the Areeds-Tumer test to erroneously fiod that Wal·Mart'.
'market basket' or 'overall product line' cost. ,IS While it is lnle that the statute prices violated the statutory prohibition of below-cost pricing.
prohibits below-cost pricing of 'any article or product,' the trial-court's .reasoning
begs the question of how to define 'article' or 'product.' The statute itself does not 3.2 Manufacturers' Incentives to Keep Retailing Competitive
define these terms. Although it may appesr superficially that the words 'any article
or product' means, literally, any individual article or product, well-accepted It has long been Wlderstood that monopolization of two or more stages of production
priociples of statutory construction require that words be interpreted in accordance of any good reduces the total """,unt of monopoly profits earned by the 'successive
with the overall intention of the statute. 16 The statute claims tu promote monopolists. ,18 That is, if only one stage of production is monopolizlld. all
competition. It follows, then, that the interpretation of 'any article or product' others being competitive, the size of the resulting monopoly profits at that one stage
should accord with the statute's pro-competition purpose. 17 will be llitger than the sum of the monopoly profits earned by two or more
So, it is appropriate to ask which interpretation best promotes the statute's pm­ monopolists within a single vertical chain. It follows that a monopolist at one stage
competitive goal: the trial-court's literal 'individual item' interpretation, or Wal­ of production has an interest in avoiding monopolies at other stages of production.
Mart's 'market basket' interpretation. If it is possible to monopolize a market by Every firm, monopolist or competitur, prefers to p=hase its inputa from
pricing a handful of items below cost, then the court's literal interpretation is competitive suppliers rather than from monopolists; likewise, every supplier prefers
justified. But because success at predetion is impossible UDless the predator's below­ to sell its outputs to co~tive flmlS rather than to monopolists (who mayor may
cost prices threaten rivals' existence -- otherwise competition persists - below-cost not be monopsonists).1 The reason is straightforward: downstream monopolists
pricing of a mere handful of all items comprising the relevant product market is restrict output below levels that would prevail uoder downstresm competition. Thus,
unlikely to promote monopolization. Hence, the proper interpretation of the statute demands for the outputs of upstream firms is lower than otherwise. And note that
in this case requires that the relevant items be defined as a 'market basket' of all this is true regardless of whether the upstream stage is monopolized or competitive.
pharmac<mtical. - a market basket which, if priced below cost, threatens competition i~:j All upstream firms suffer if there is downstream monopoliution.
in the retail phafllUlCy market. f. Thus, any manufacturer will take steps to ensure that the retail sectur remainll
If the product market is appropriately defined as a basket consisting of, say, competitive if the benefits to the manufacturer exceed the manufacturer's costs of
analgesics, antihistamines, and decongestants, then below-cost pricing OCClUli only taking these steps.20 As a practical matter, the likelibood that such steps will be
if the combined revenues received from the sales of these three products fall short worthwhile i. positively correlated with the extent of monopoly power enjoyed by
of the contbined costs to the retailer of these products. If this revenue exceeds the the manufacturer. A monopolist producing 'tiiPirio is more likely to police against
cost, then the retailer's pricing policy does not threaten the existence of equally downstream monopolization of pharmacies than i. an aspirio maker who is one of
efficient rivals. This conclusion holds even if one or two of these three products is hundreds of such producers. Even more generally, whether or not such policing
prieed below invoice cost. As long as the seller's combined revenues on sales of occurs depends on how many manufacturers of retailed products stand to share in
these three products exceed its combined costs of selling these products, all equally the benefits of policing.
efficient rivals can mimic the seller's pricing scheme and avoid los.... Practically, what steps might an upstream monopolist take to help ensure that
Of course, the foregoing discussion presumes the product market to be retailing remains competitive? If we put aside antitrust-law's artificial restrictions
appropriately defined. It may be, say, that decongestants really constitute a market on manufacturers' ability to contract with retailers,21 one possible manufacturer
of their own. If so, it is irrelevant if the combined revenues on sales of analgesics, response comes immediately to mind, ns.mely, minimum resale price maintena:nce
antihistamines, and decongestsnts exceed the combined costs of these three products, (RPM). If a manufacturer suspects a retailer of attempting to monopoli2e the retail
If a firm prices dscongestants below cost. such pricing (were it a real threat to market through predetorially low prices (and if the manufacturer believes that the
competition among sellers of decongestants) would thresten to monopolize an predatory retailer has a substantial chance of success), the manufacturer can insist
appropriately defined market. But once the product market is appropriately defined,

200 201
in its contracts with the renegade retailer on minimum resale prices above predatory price in a way antagonistic to the manufacturer's interest. If, say, an independently
levels. owned Texaco service station sought to monopolize the retail market for Texaco
Other upstream strategies include refusing to deal with a suspected downstream gasoline in a particular town, Texaco could quite easily thwart this retailer'.
predator, charging higher wholesale prices to the suspected predator than those scheme. 25 Free-rider problems do not here exist, and Texaco could be certain
charged to the predator's rivals (or otherwise giving the prey discounts on products that whatever retaliation it takes against the retailer would have a substantial effect
and special assistance with retailing efforts), and threatening a downstream predator on the retailer's ability to successfully conduct business.
with maximum RPM or sales quotas if the downstream stage becomes But manufacturer policing against retailer monopolization becomes less effective
monopolized. 22 with increases in the number of different manufacturers whose products are handled
While minimum RPM directly blocks a retailer's ability to sell below cost those by a predatory retailer. The reason is twofold. First, free-rider problems might
items covered by RPM contracts, these other strategies raise the costs of attempted block policing efforts. Even if a manufacturer could effectively threaten to penalize
monopolization. Refusals to deal might do so in one of two ways. First, the a predatory retailer, efforts to free-ride on the policing efforts of other similarly
manufacturer of the predatorially priced product might refuse to sell this product to situated manufacturers might block all policing efforts. Second, a manufacturer may
the suspect retailer. The retailer must then find a less-desirable item to use in price have inadequate clout to punish a predatory retailer. When retailers carry the
predation. 23 Second, because a monopolist retailer harms several manufacturers, products of several manufacturers, only manufacturers whose goods are essential to
an individual manufacturer suspicious of a retailer's motives might pull its products retailing success have sufficient clout to police effectively against monopolizing
even if this firm's products are not those on which the retailer is charging efforts by retailers. 26 A supermarket contractually bound to sell okra at a price
predatorially low prices. If the manufacturer's brand is important enough to the no lower than invoice cost is unlikely to be dissuaded from pursuing its
retail trade that any retailer not carrying this brand is at a substantial competitive monopolizing ways. Io contrast, a supermarket contractually prohibited from
disadvantage, then refusals to deal by this manufacturer can play an important role charging a predatory price on Coca-Cola may well find that it cannot now as easily
in policing against downstream monopolization. (I address below the ince1llives of monopolize the retail grocery trade as it would were it able to sell Coca-Cola at
upstream firms to police.) For example, if Coca-Cola believes that Kroger is a predatorially low prices.
serious threat to monopolize grocery retailing in a particular (and appropriately A corollary of this second consideration is that policing by manufacturers is
defined) geographic market, then Coca-Cola could thresten to pull its products from more likely when retail success depends upon being a "full-service" retailer - that
Kroger if Kroger continues its monopolizing efforts. Coca-Cola may do so whether is, when consumers punish retailers who do not carry consistently adequate stocks
~,
Kroger charges predatorially low retail prices on Coca-Cola products or on other of a minimally wide range of retail goods. Io such situations, anyone manufacturer
items.
The same is true for price discrimination. Rather than refuse to deal, a
t will more likely be able to stymie a retailer's predatory success by refusing to deal
with a retailer (or by dealing only on unfavorable terms)27 .
manufacturer might charge higher wholesale prices to the monopolizing retailer. The retail pharmacy market seems to be especially of this type. Each major
Rivals of the predator are thereby advantaged relative to the predator and are, hence, drug manufacturer is the exclusive producer of several patented drugs; failure of a
better able to survive a predatory price war. retailer to carry anyone of these drugs might substantially disadvantage a retail
Finally, the threat of maximum RPM or sales quotas makes predation less pharmacy relative to its rivals. Although retail pharmacies in Faulkner County each
attractive to retailers. Mwmum RPM or sales quotas can force a monopolist carried the products of dozens of manufacturers, failure to stock one particular
retailer to price competitively. Consequently, a retailer that succeeds in ousting product from anyone of these manufacturers might exl'ose a pharmacy to serious
rivals will be unable to recoup its predation losses through monopoly pricing. market discipline: if a customer asks for, say, Suprax,28 and the pharmacy does
Predation, therefore, is less attractive as a business strategy to the extent that not carry Suprax, this pharmacy may well suffer a substantial diminution of
maximum RPM or sales quotas are available to manufacturers. 24 customer patronage if there is nO good substitute for Suprax produced by any other
Of course, as suggested above, free-rider problems may well frustrate efforts pharmaceutical manufacturer. Thus, the clout of each pharmaceutical supplier to
by suppliers to police against downstream monopolization. I do not here investigate police against retail monopolization is argusbly strong enough to render untenable
in full the details of market arrangements that promote downstream policing by any inference of predatory intent on the part of Wal-Mart. Putting aside other
manufacturers. I am content now to suggest the possibility, and to make a few reasons why Wal-Mart's actions were not plausibly predatory, each drug
general remarks. One obvious implication of this discussion is that a retailer who manufacturer would plausibly have had incentives to police against monopolization
distributes exclusively one manufacturer's products is in no position to predatorially of pharmaceutical retailing.

202 203
I assumed away, in the above discussion, existing antitrust prohibitions. Under rulings - that this fact does not imply that firms at one stage of production have
a legal regime with no antitrust restrictions, it is possible in many circumstances ­ incentives to destroy monopoly power at another. Hovenkamp's conclusion is
and plausible in some - that policing by upstream suppliers against retailers will inspired by the Coase Theorem, which "suggests that vertically related firms would
adequately thwart downstream monopolization attempts. Matters are different under prefer to share the profits of monopoly rather than to compete them away.
the existing antitrust regime. While antitrust law does not now discourage all Vertically related firms tend to make bargains that maximize joilll profits."
varieties of policing efforts - unilateral refusals to deal and sales quotas are (Hovenkamp (1991, 1371) (original emphasis).) Hovenkamp concludes from this
examples of supplier strategies available under existing law - many other policing fact that monopolist suppliers do not necessarily wish to sell to competitive retailers,
methods are illegal. For example, the proscription against both minimum and and that monopolist buyers do not necessarily wish to purchase from competitive
maximum RPM bloclcs what may well be the single most effective tool potentiaIl9' suppliers. Rather than eliminate monopoly power at stage n of the production
available to upstream suppliers to keep retail markets free of predators. 2 process, a monopolist at stage m will allow the monopoly at stage n to persist if the
Similarly, the Clayton Act (as modified by Robinson-Patman) prevents suppliers monopolist at stage n shares its monopoly profits with the monopolist at stage m.
from assisting with differentially lower wholesale prices the prey of a suspected Hovenkamp's conclusion is incorrect. Maximizing joint profits requires that
retail predator. Indeed, Sherman Act §1 prohibitions against collusion may obstruct all stages of the production process, save one, perform competitively. Although
cooperation among suppliers to coordinate and share the costs of disciplining Hovenkamp correctly suggests that vertically related monopolists may have
predatory retailers. Whatever benefits are served by existing antitrust laws must be incentives to cooperate, such cooperation will result in one or the other pricing
weighed against these (as well as other, better-known)30 costs. competitively. Failure to cooperate in this way among vertically related monopolists
- or failure of one monopolist to compel the other to behave competitively - results
3.3 Hovenkamp on Vertical Agreements in the "double marginalization" problem. When two or more vertically related firms
each skim off monopoly profits, each taking the outputs and demands of all other
The claim that firms at one stage of production might discipline monopolists at other vertically related firms as given, aggregate monopoly profits in this industry are
stages is not new (e.g., Kleit and Coate (1993», although I am unaware of any lower than if only one stage of the production process behaves monopolistically.33
argument that such discipline might obstruct predation. Typically, this claim is made Of course, competitors as well as monopolists want their vertically related
in the context of a buyer with some monopsony power forcing down prices charged brethren to behave competitively. But unfortunately for firms in competitive
by a supplier garnering monopoly power through merger. If the buyer has industries, free-rider problems may prohibit them from challenging the exercise of
substantial bargaining power, there is less need to worry about monopolization at the monopoly power by a buyer or supplier. In contrast, firms with monopoly power
supply stage. A handful of recent antitrust decisions explicitly rely upon this insight have not only unsullied interests in the competitive behavior of each of their
to strike down attempts to block mergers. For example, in U.S. v. Country Lake vertically related firms, they also are more likely than competitors to possess
Foods,31 a U.S. District Court refused to condemn a merger of fluid-milk effective means of forcing vertically related firms to behave competitively.
processors. Although this merger resulted in high concentration among fluid-milk One or the other of two vertically related monopolists might, with sufficient
suppliers, the court focused on the fact that the three largest customers of these bargaining skills, force the other to behave competitively. If no one firm can prevail
suppliers purchase 90 % of these suppliers' output of fluid milk. The court was on the other to behave competitively, a vertical merger may result. 34 In either
persuaded by the defendant's claim that the dominance and sophistication of its case, vertically related monopolists have both the incentive and the ability to solve
buyers would stifle any attempt by the defendant to behave anticompetitively the double-marginaIization problem by getting rid of monopoly effects at all but one
following the merger. stage of production.
A similar conclusion was reached in U. S. v. Syufy, 32 although in this case
a merger among buyers was challenged. In Syufy, Judge Alex Kozinski rebuffed the 3.4 'Predatory'versus 'Non-predatory' Prices
government's efforts to block a merger of u.s Vegas movie exhibitors. Judge
Kozinski held that the substantial market power of movie producers is sufficient to Until now, I have not questioned the use of some measure of cost (e.g., AVe) to
check any monopoly power that might exist among u.s Vegas theaters. distinguish predatory from non-predatory prices. However, cost-based distinctions,
Hovenkamp challenges the logical bases of these rulings. After rightly pointing most notably the Areeda-Turner test, are biased in favor of false-positive findings­
out that "[t]irms generally prefer neither to purchase from monopolists nor to sell - i.e., falsely identifying low prices as predatory prices. 35
to them," Hovenkamp argues -- contrary to Country Lake Foods, Syufy, and similar

204 205
A price is predalnry if it is reasonably intended In secure a monopoly. But the knowledge, and production techniques. Among the real-world phenomena this model
symptoms of predation are strikingly similar In those of healthy competition. To cannot explain are firms' product-selection and marketing decisions. Product­
relieve courts of the impossible task of divining defeodants' intent, Areeda-Tumer selection choices are anslytically prior In the model, while marketing decisiollll are
(1975) constructed a cost-based test that allegedly offers courts an objective way In implicit!y as';umed In be lWllecess&ry (because consumer demand for the industry
identify predation. Under the Areeda-Tumer test, prices above average lntal cost output is exogenous In the model). However, in reality firms must decide which
(ATe) are per se legal, prices lower than ATe but not below AVe are kinds and qualities of products to produce as well as how In market these products.
presumptively non-predalnry, and prices below AVe are presumptively predalnry. If pricing decisions are often part of a firm's prnduct-development and marketing
While the Areeda-Tumer test improved courts' treatment of predation claims plan, prices below conventionally measured costs are not Validly classified as
by abifting attention away from belligerent language often found in internal company predatory simply because the conventional model has no room fur such pricing
memoranda (Elzinga and Mills (1994», this test is fundamentally flawed. The legal practices. Such prices may be a legitimate investment in marketing.
treatment of predation would be further improved if aU pricing practices were per For example, a firm may decide that if it can lnday build up strong and Iong­
se legal. No one should bave stsnding In sue for predation based upon a defeodant's lasting consumer loyalty, constroction lnmorrow of a larger and more efficient
low prices. The reasons are fourfold: (1) misidentifying competitively low prices faclnry will be justified. But how In get the required consumer loyalty? One way
as predalnry chills competitive behavior; (2) costs are inherently difficult In measure might be In charge, for a time, prices below AVe. Or, as was probably true for
because they are only imperfectly proxied by accounting data;36 (3) firms will Wal-Mart, a firm can charge prices below A VC on some products in an attempt In
almost never pursue monopolization through below-cost pricing; and (4) the strengthen consumer loyalty as well as In increase current cuslnmer flow through its
relationship between price and cost at any moment says nothing about predalnry alnres.
intent or likelihood of predatory success. Under the Areeda-Tumer test, such prices are predalnry. However, suppose
The first two reasons are widely recognized and will not be discuased further. the firm seeks In engender consumer loyalty by some means other than pricing below
Although much has been written about the third reason (Easterbrook (1981a», sti1I AVe, such as by spending extra funds training sales clerks In be singularly hiendly
more can be said. But saying more requires first an understsnding of the fourth and knowledgeable. There is no economically relevant difference between these
reason - that is, why the relationship between price and cost yields no information alternative means of building consumer loyalty.39 In both cases, the firm "loses"
about predatory intent. money lnday in the hopes of recouping these "losses" lnmorrow. Also in both cases,
The Areeda-Tumer test rests squarely on the belief that P <Ave conveys rivals are harmed if the firm succeeds; in both cases, rivals may go out of business
relevant information about the firm's predatory design. The reason P < AVe is allngethor. And yet predation is declared only when a firm charges price below
believed In announce clearly a firm's predalnry design is that such a price causes A VC. If training sales clerks is regarded as a healthy competitive exercise, it is not
lWllecessary losses for the firm and, hence, "is not a reasonable way for a firm In clear why pricing below Ave is undesirable: both investments help the firm, harm
increase profits - unless the increase is the present value of fulnre monopoly rivals, and benefit consumers (at least until the firm becomes a monopolist).
pricing" (Hovenkamp (1985, 173». Because a firm in conventional partial­ Because the Areeda-Tumer test ignores possible efficiency justifications for prices
equilibrium price theory has no good reason In charge prices below AVC, a firm below Ave, it lno quickly labels all such prices as predalnry.
observed charging such a price must be doing something other than maximizing None of the foregoing denies that. firm's pricing practices can ruin rivals and
profits. That something is concluded In be attempted monopolization.37 leave the firm with a monopoly. But it does point out not only that prices below
This conclusion (of a type pln1osopbers label "the fallacy of the residual") is AVe are an investment, but that these investments differ in no fundamentsl way
invalid. Due In its unavoidably limited scope, the partial-eqoilibrium model defInes from other investments that attract corurumers at the expense of rivals. Pricing
only a limited number of profit-maximizing reasons for firms In reduce prices, and below cost is a particnlar form of investment, and nothing in the conventional model
no reasons at all for " firm to cut prices below cost. But it does not necessarily suggests that investments in the form of prices below A VC are any more (or less)
follow that an observed price decrease, inexplicable within the model on profit­ likely than other investments In generate monopolized markets. A gemtine theory
maximizing grounds, is predatory. Predation is only one among several possible of predation must plausibly distingnish investments likely In generate welfare­
residual explanations for an observed reduction in price below AVe. 38 reducing monopolies from investments unlikely In do so. Focus on the Ielationship
The conventional model upon which Areeda-Tumer relies is designed In explain of price In cost does not adequstely distingnish predalnry from nonpredatory
pricing and output decisions by .firms producing given products In satisfy £iven investments~
demands within the confines of well-defined and £iven constraints on re8O~,

206 207
There are, though, seveml well-known reasons for doubting that predation ever Ihst constitute predation, and _ing their likelihood of success along with the
takes the form of below-(:ost pricing (Easterbrook (1981.». To these well-known prospects of policing against such predation, are matters for another investigation.
reasons, I add others suggested by the realization thet a would-be predator typically
has available investment opportunities thet can substitote for beIow-<:oS! pricing as
a means of harming rivals. Given that a predator can harm rivals on numerous nOD­ 4. Conclusion
price margins, there is reason to be skeptical that an aspiriog monopolist will charge
prices below cost as a means of monopolizing a market. Economics provides Iittlejustificationfor the suit alleging thet Wal-Mart's low prices
Consider the advantages of harming rivals on non-price margins (say, by were part of a predatory scheme to monopolize pharmaceutical retailing in Faulkner
offering higher product quality) relative to predatory pricing: County, Arkansas. The traditional argument pointing to the futility of predatory
(1) Non-price improvements are more difficult than price cuts for rivals to pricing applies in this case: ifWal-Mart priced predatorially, continued competition
n:u.n:u.c. What can be easier to imitate than a price cut? No special sk:ilIs, from Kroger and other pharmacies (including mail-order pharmacies) would have
organizatioual sophistication, or technical know-how is required to lower prices. assured th.t Wal-Mart's losses would have swamped any future monopoly profits.
Rivals need to know only how to read numbers. In contrast, matching an increase Less familiar arguments, however, also support the Arkansas Supreme Court's ruling
in product quality or an improvement in production or distribution techniques that Wal-Mart was not, in fact, engaged in predatory behavior. Because suppliers
inevitably requires some skill on the part of rivals. Indeed, while the dullest rival of pharmaceuticals have an interest in competition among phannaceutical retailers,
will have no trouble mimicking a price cut, some rivals mighl never be able to these suppliers might have policed against any genuinely predatory attempts by WaI­
mimic a non-price cbange. Mart. Failure of these suppliers to discipline Wal-Mart (or even to compIainabout
(2) Non-price improvements take more time to mimic thm do price cuts. The Wal-Mart's retailing practices) suggests, though it does not prove, that Wal-Mart
longer il takes for rivals to mimic a predator, the greater are rivals' losses duzing was in fact nOI behaving in a way that promoted monopolization.
the period of predation. Thus, exit of rivals in the face of non-price predation will Unfortunately, it is impossible to tell if poliCing by pharmaceutical
be more sure and more quick than in the f""e of price predation (under which rivals manufactorers against a predatory Wal-Mart would have ensued. More needs to be
can quickly, certainly, and precisely mimic the predatory tactic). Also, re-entry into known about the effects of the number of suppliers, the role of brand names, an.d the
the monopo1ized industry will be slower under non-price predation. Because rivals effects of different varieties of distribution contracts before We can identify with
are, by hypothesis, as efficient as the predator, only a genuine non-price some assurance wheD suppliers will, and when they will not, actively and effectively
improvement has my cbance of giving the predator a durable advantage over rival. ­ police against predation attempts by retailers. But the possibility of policing by
- an advantage that not only is difficult or impossible to mimic today, but may be suppliers exists. It is one that stodsnts of antitrust ought to investigate.. The fruits
difficult or impossible to mimic in the future. of such investigation may well prove useful to courts in future predation cues.
(3) Non-price improvements might yield profits to the predator even before
rivals are run out of the iodustry. An improvement in product quality by a predator N....
migbt increase consumer demands for the predator's output so substantially that the
predator recovers all costs of product improvement even before all rivals are driven 1. 1M author wrote aa amlCIU bri4 eubmittod by rhe InstiUolie for Justice, in eupport of Wa.1~Mutt.
from the industry. No such profits are available during predatory price wars. appeal. Malcolm Coate. DoD DcW1:'Y f KeD Elzinga, David FontIw, Dave :K.uerma.n, Andrew Klcit,
Moreover, the future demand for the product may be higher when the predator Dwight Lee, John Lopatb, Fred McCheaney~ R.oger Meiners, Adam Prit.cbard. Curti. Simon, Swve
Walters, and Bruce Yandle aU offered valuable diaounioo and commeJD.
improves the quality of its product than when the predator simply charges below~t
prices. 2. American Drug', Inc. V. Wa./-Yarl SIc"'" Inc., 1\-92-1158 (Oct. 1993).
In short, if there is predation, it will typically not take the form of easy-to­
mimic price cuts. Savvy predators will likely choose non-price predatory tactiC8. 3. Trial ~cord. at 1844, 1855. Thus, the plaimiff'a. expert ~, Dr. Ralpb Sc~ diBmi:uod the
'This fact does not mean that courts should search more earnestly for instances of ugumenr.Ih•• W.l-Msrt', pricing policy ohould be anaIy:r.ed OQ • marlr.eI-b••b:lnlhcr!ban individual­
non-price predation. Questions of the real-world likelihood of predation and of the product basis.. 'I'his expert t'C&IOtlCd that "diose arc revenue iasue8 nther than ¢OIl. issue••" la. In other
ability of courts to police against it are 8eparnte from the question of the form worda. beeauK IOn» iteIll! were priced below avenge variable cost, predatory intent is eltabliahed.
regardle88 of any ef'&clthat such pricing might have had on che profitl Wal·Mart earned on Alol of othR'
predation will take if and when it occurs. All I argue here is that if predation ever produetlil.
occurs, it will likely be in non-price form. 40 Determining the kinds of activities
4. Arb.o.to. Code I 4-75·209(0)(1).

208 209
S. The: trial court reported all an undisputed fact that Wal-Mart's purpose was tD attract a Irdiaproportionatc
15. Trial court opinion, at S.
number of c:ustomcn to Wal-Mart." But thi. concluaion wail utUustified. Wal-Mart'. exccutive. never

testified that Wal-Mart lIOugbt tD au.mct a ~disproportionatc number of cuatolllMa, " nor wu any e~
16. Otherwiae. e.g., no store could ever give away ,oodi a, priz.ca in promotional c;ampaigna. On
offered (0 IUpport thia finding. Apparently, the lrial judge miauaed an innocen.t atAtcment from tho
principles of statutory COnst.n.K:tioD, ICe Sutherland (992).
teat.imony of Wal-Mart". expert e:conomiat aa the basi. for :finding that Wal-Mart acughtto attract

d'Uproportionate aumfuo of customers.


17. See alao. e.g., Westem UrtianF1nanciaJ Services, Inc. v. First DakI Corp.~ el aJ. 25 Cal. Rptr~2d341
At trial, Wal~M.rt·a expert explained why bigb~votume retailers might price aome: items below

(Dec. 14,1993). W....m Uoionaued V"'" D,.. C"'!'. underCallfurnio', Uafak Pnwticc. ata"'te (which
invoice cost. The context ofthia testimony makes cte.ar tha[ Wal-Mart'. witn.ei& WI. not tcltlfYiJli about
j, aimilar. though GOt identical, to the ArkallSl. atatute at iHue in WaJ-Mmt Starn). The cb.a:tge WI.
Wal-Matt'. fonnaI company policy. Rather, the witneill meant only to explain that beJO"N..mvolcc pricing
predatory pricing ofmoney-U'anafer service.. In Wutem Union thc< California appd1atc court ltated that
j
i.a • way to help attract a number of cuatom£.rs into the store who otherwiae would not come to the stole. the proper definition of the product in queation must accord with the atatutc', pro-compctition inten.tioD.

6. Wal-Man Stores, Inc. v. American Drugs, Inc., 819 S.W. 2d 30 (1995). Plaintiff" petitio. for 18. SpcDjilor(l950); Bark (1954); M""hlup and Taber (1960); and Blair and Ka..nnan (1983). Sullivall
rebearing was denied. and Hovenbmp (1989. 368) IUm up: "Any finn, even a monopoliit. is but off if aU other firma in th6
d1at.ribution chain are behaving competitively."
7. -"The lndividuaJ itemt acid below cost. the frequency of lhofiC. salea, the duration of those Ales. and
the extent of auch salea an:. not revealed in the chancery court~s opinion. And that i.a a critic:al poinl in 19. ne labels "downst.ream" and ·upstream'" ate aroltrary in many ~IC'! "down.st.ream" fuma Cd often
thi. caN." [d., at 34. be n:.caa' . t uplJlream IUpp1icrs of serviccs (e.g., retailers .upplying retail ICt'Vices to "do'\tlJlitt'e.am"
manu(acture"'). See Krattorunaker and Salop (1986,226-27).
8. Id., at 34.
20. For a general model &howing how a sophiaticated .ller whose salea are • large portion of an iDpu1
9.ld., at 34-5. market might encourage compc<titive entry by buyera in the face of IUJl.k: co...., ace Klett &.ad Coale (1993)•

10.ld. at 35. .1
21. Contractual provilrions between suppUera &.ad distributors arc pet" IC illegal if these proviaiona trpccity
; the price. at which - or the pricing panme1crs within which - diatributDra can reseU goodtl. Se6 Dr.
11. [d. at 36. Indeed, 000 pJaintiffvinuaUy admitted at trial that WalwMart cauaed him tD behave mol'll Miks Medical Co. v. John D. Part '" Sons Co., 220 U.S. 373 (1911).
effillliently:
22. To help maintain competitive retailing, D'lAtwfacturers can Also enter IetaUing, finance the prey duri.nJ
Q. [from Wal-Mart's attorney1 Your grou proflt in the yeat tha' Wal-Mart went into
the price war. or finance new enttanti after the price Wat. I here ~n:. these atrategiel because I wiall
busin... against you in the pharmacy, your gro.. ptotil. increased by $1I0,OOOdollara. Do
1:0 focus on atrategies unique (0 .uppliers to Ihwan attempted down.stn:am monopolization.
you ICe that?

23. A rational predatory retailer wilt lower pricea tD ptedal:oty levela on tho. itcma that are mOft likely
A. I may have done. lot of bell tighten.ltia during that yc.at. to alU'act the laIleat amounta of II8.les revenuea away from the pced&tor'. rivals. Such iteml arc probably
thoac wjth aignificant brand-name t¢(;ogniuon .nd whose aiel account thr a relatively lar:e:e portion of
Trial record, at 1634. overall sales by rivala. If the predatory retailer ia denied the ability to price such items prod.e.toriaUy, the
predator must of neceujty either abaadon ib predatory plam or price predal:orialty ircma of leu
12. The court lumped thi. second rcaaon in with the rU'lt. WaJ-MilI't Stares, at 36. 'I'beie reuotU are~ aignifielll.llCC to Ihe IUf'I'ivai of rivals.
however~ distinct. Failure to run the plaintiffs from the market i. evidence supporting the claim chat the
defendant - oapcci.ally one .. wealthy •• Wal-Mart - never acted with a specific deaign tD banbupl the 24. For a clear discuasion of the role of rccoupmCQI: in predauon analy,ia, JeO B.l7.i.osa &.ad Mill, (1989).
plabniff.. Thc llXiat.ence of other eatahliahed rlvali i.. evidence a,ainal the proposition that the defendant
acted with an intent to destroy competition gencnlly in the market. It i.a more coady to run many rivala
25. Of coune, the Texaco retailer could lower ita pricea to predatory levels hoping 1:0 fDOIlOP()W the
from an i.ndustry than tD bankrupt only a mw. Or t what may be the IIlmC thing, an induatry with acvcra.l
lDWn?s entitc retail gasoline market. In Ihia case t Ihcrc would be no conf'lkt between Texaco and ill
finna wggeats that the optimal-aize firm 10: that induatry minimlzea ill coats at an output level fat below
rctaUer. But we do not expect to ' " IUch price cutting initiated by the retailer; al1cmpu to monopolize
100II market demand. MainIaining a mooopoly in ." industry .haracteriud by OIUply inc.,...;",g .0....
Lhe retail trade excluaively for one braod al'll mole likely 1:0 begin wilb a wboJcaale price cut by tbb
and whcn the optimal number of minimum--co&l firma it two or more, la unUkcJy to be profitable.
manufacturer. The rN.QOll ia 'that price cutting by the manufactu.tor bc11er entUr'H that aD of the
manufacturer~a n:.taUera charge the IIiUU predatory price. If the optimal num.l:ter of retailers lbr a
13.ld., at 36. manufacturer in a particular locale is gruter than one, price cutting initiated at the wholesale level better
coordinate. all of tho manufacturer', retailcrs. Retailers actiDJ on their OWQ run the ri&k of drivin:g other
14. MlflSushiUJ Elecrric lndusrrial Co. y. Zmilh lWdio Corp., 475 u.s. 574,594 (1986; Powell,S.). rot&i1ea of the aamc brand into bankruptcy. And thia the ma.nufacturu dOt. not wan!,

210 211
26. Of course. policing by manufaetutera might still be pouib1c even when the predatory retailer carriet 39. Or, if there is an cconoroio;:al1y relevant differe~ between theae two mean.a, thla difference it not
the products of thousand. of diffcrentmanuf&,Nm'$~ if the producuofone Or two oftheae JmtJlUwcturera exposed by the convontionalmodel withjn Which predatory pricing ill analyzed. Again. bclo'llt"«:M pricing
arc ~eucntial' to ~taiting IUCCess (e.g., .. Kellogg" breakfa31 cereals arguably are to the retail grocery within the modeJ: ia read u evidence of predation for no Ml80n other than that below-(:o" pricing iI
trade). then a threat to pull such products might be tufficient to discipline the :reWler. ~j&tenz. with WrtlUil of profil-maJtimizing bchaviora identified within the model. Moreovct~ even if
predation Were the only reuon a real-world firm would ever charge priCCI below AVC, nothing in the
27. More generally. policing by a manufacturer iA more likely the fewer the number of compelins' brands conventional model augpsls that below~oat pricing il more or le.alikely than other fonna of inVCltmcnLI
• retailer carriel of lny product the .tacking of which i. critical to retail IUCCCII. (e.g .• product-quatity improvements) to result jn monopolies•

23. Suprax. manufaelU«:d exclusively by LederJe Co., i, .n antibiotic prescribed by phy.icia.ns fur ear 40. For the record, I do not. believe that non-price predation, appropriate.ly defined. ocQUra with any
infections. &cqueno;:y in reality. My intuition il buutesscd by the recent retcarch of Lopatka and Kleit (199S)~
Moreover. to the extent that non"Pr1ce predation docl tlICO;:Ut, traditional tort. eonuact, and o;:riminal....w
29. It is weD understood that the law~& prohibition of rnaximumIU"M weaUo.a mppWta* abilitica to bcp n:mcdie. are adequate. to combat it.
dlstributors from exttaoting monopoly profita from cOlWuncra. Sec Easterbrook (1981b) and Blair and
KaSCtman (198l). The .rgument here build. upon thia insight: if' maximum RPM Were legal, a fUpptier
behaving pt:eda.torially today has leu chance of oocouping itt predation loasea tomo.m)W (even if it drivu
an rivals from the market) because of the threat of maximum RPM. Therefore, predation today is Ie..
likely.

30. Schwartz (1986) offers a particularly persuaaive indict.tnont of the Robinson-Patman Act - the fcde.n:l
version of the atate Ratutc underwhicb Wa.I-Mart WiiI81.led in WoJ-Man Szoru. Afte-r aurveyit.1s: a varlfiy
of real-world comlequencea of Robinson-Patma~ Schwart2. concludel that ..What i. c1eac i. that the Ac:l
haa produeed numerous perver:ie relUla .•.•- [at 756].

31. 754 F. Supp. 669 (D. MllUl. 1990).

32.903 F.2d 659 (9Jh Ca. 1990).

33. See Kaserman and Mayo (1995, 306..()7): "Th.uB, with a separate mODopoIiat .t each of lb. two
Rlcceuive ltagu ofproduction, consumeaare worse off than they were with a lingle monopoly at either
Rap or an intc:gntte-d monopoUst that eonlfols hom lUges. Fi.o.al output price is higher, and quantity i.a
lower.
-In addition. the sum of profits of the two separate monopoliab ill leu dum the proota that QQUJd be
earned by a single vertical monopolist.·

34.10. at l07. s... aloo Klein, Cmwford, and Akhlan (1978).

35. The A:ceeda-Tu.mer test bu been ACcuaed by earlier critic. of bias in favor of faJ.se-.negadn .findings.
See, e.B., Scherer and Rosa (1990), 472-479. None of these earlier critio;:s question the IIOUDdocu of coat~
baaed distinctions between predatory and Don-pNdatory pricCI.

36. Boudreaux. Elzinga, and.Mill. (1995) relate an example from a re.ceot a01ib:ust 98& oftbe exorbitant
eomp1exity of estimating o;:Oil.a from AC~ data.

31. Ide• •i rufOning waa uaed by the plainUffJ~ expert economial in the Wal-Matt case. s.. Trial
RIloord, 111844, 1855.

38. 1bt is, bccau&e the ococlauic.tl pattial-cquilibrium model (llke aU useful model.) doca DOt explain
everything, it iJ illegitimate to cooolude th.t actiOml i.nc:onsiste01 with what the model doci explain are
neccasarily irntLional, inefficient, or IIOCwly noxious.

212 213
K1eit, Andrew N. and MalCOM B. Coate. 1993. "Are Judges Leading Economic Theory?
Refer"""", Sunk Casts, the Tbreat of Entry and the Competitive Process.' SoUlhern Ecozwmi<;
Journal60(l):l03-11S.
An:cda, Phillip and Donald F. Turner. 1975. "Predatory Pricing and Relate<! Pxactices Under
Seetion 2 of the Sherman Act." Harvard Law Review 88(4);697-733. Kratterunsl:er, Thoma. G. and Steven C. Salop. 1986. "Anticompetitive Exclusion: R.alsing
Rivals' Costs to Achieve Pawer over Price.' Yale Law Journal 96(;2):209-293.
Baumol, William 1. and Janusz A. Ordaver. 1985. "U•• of Antitrust to Subvert Competition."
Journal ofLaw and Economics 28(2);247-265. Lapatka, John E. and Andrew N. Kleit. 1995. "The Mystery of Lara;. Jourtla/ and Ibe Qucsl
for Foreelosure in Antitrust.' T""as Law Review 73(6):1255-1306.
Blair, Roger D. and David L. Kaserman. 1981. 'TheAlbrtchlRule and ConsumerWelfa.rc:
An Economic Analysis." University of Florida Law Review 33(4):461-484. Macb!up, Fritz and Martha Taber. 1960. 'Bilateral Monopoly, Successive Monopoly, and
Vertical Integration. " Economica 27(1):101-119.
Blair, Roger D. and David L. Kasennan. 1983. The Law and Economics of Vertical
Integration and ConJrol. New York: Academic Press. McChesney, Fred S. and William F. Shughart II. (cds.) 1995. Th. Causes and Conseqll.eru:..
ofAnlirrust· The Public Choice Perspective. Chicago; University of Chicago Pteu.
Bork. Robert H. 1954. 'Vertical Integmtion IUld the Shenrnm Act: The Legal History of an
Economic Misconception.' University of Chicago Law Review 22(1):157-201. Seberer, F. M. and David Ross. 1990. Industrial Markel Strucrure IIIld Econamlc
Perfo17TUl1lCe, 3rd cd., Boston: Houghton Mifilin Co.
Boudreaux, Donald J •• Kenneth G. Elzinga, and David E. Mills. 1995. "From Fruit Pie& to
Cigarettes: The Supreme Court's Predation Odyssey ... Supreme Court Economic Review SchWl!rtz, Marius 1986. 'The Perverse Effects of the Robinson-Patman A<:t.' An1i1nut
4(1);57-93. Bulltlin 31(3):733-757.

EAsterbrook, Frank H. 1981•. 'Predatory Strategies and Counterstrategies.· University of Spengler. Joseph 1. 1950. "Verticallntegmtinn and Antitrust Policy." Journal of Poli1ical
Chicago Law Re';... 48(2);263-337. Economy 58(4);347-352.

Easterbrook, Frank H. 1981b. 'Maximum Price Fixing." University of Chicago Law Review Sullivan, E. Thomas and Herbert Hovenksmp. 1989. AlllitrusJ Law, Policy IIIld Procedure,
48(4):886-910. 2nd cd., Charlottesville, VA; Michie Publishing CO.

Elzinga, Kenneth G. and David E. Mills. 1989. "Testing for Predation; Is Recoupment Sutherland, LB. 1992. Sta/uJory Construction, 5th cd., New York: Clark Boatdman
Fea.ible?" Anlirrus/ Bulletin 34(4);869-893. Callsgllsn.

Elzinga, Kenneth G. and David E. Mills. 1994. 'Ttumping the Areeda-Tumer Test: Tbe
Recoupment Standard in Brooke Group." Antitrust Law Journal 62(3);559-584.

Hovenl:amp, Herbert. 1985. Economics and FederalAnlirrust Law. St. Paul: Weat Publishing
Co.

Hovenkamp, Herbert 1991. 'Mergers and Buyers." Virginia Law Review 77(7):1369-1383.

Ksaerman, David L. and John W. Mayo. 1995. Government and Business. Fort Wottll:
Dryden Press.

Klein, Benjamin, Robert A. Crawford, and Armen A. Alew. 1978. 'Verticallntegration,


Appropriable Rents. and the Competitive Contracting Process." Journal of Law IIIld
Economics :/-1(:/-):297-326.

214 215

Potrebbero piacerti anche