Sei sulla pagina 1di 15

See

discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/240568119

On Depiction and Language

Article in Current Anthropology · June 1989


DOI: 10.1086/203748

CITATIONS READS

0 34

6 authors, including:

Harold L. Dibble William Noble


University of Pennsylvania University of New England (Australia)
147 PUBLICATIONS 3,285 CITATIONS 137 PUBLICATIONS 3,479 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE SEE PROFILE

Iain Davidson
University of New England (Australia)
199 PUBLICATIONS 1,781 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

On the evolution of mental architectures across the hominin line View project

The Archaeology of the Qld Native Mounted Police View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Iain Davidson on 14 August 2015.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file. All in-text references underlined in blue are added to the original document
and are linked to publications on ResearchGate, letting you access and read them immediately.
On Depiction and Language

Harold L. Dibble; R. L. Holloway, Jr.; Alexander Marshack; Andree Rosenfeld; Garry W.


Trompf; William Noble; Iain Davidson

Current Anthropology, Vol. 30, No. 3. (Jun., 1989), pp. 330-342.

Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0011-3204%28198906%2930%3A3%3C330%3AODAL%3E2.0.CO%3B2-S

Current Anthropology is currently published by The University of Chicago Press.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained
prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in
the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/journals/ucpress.html.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic
journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,
and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take
advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

http://www.jstor.org
Thu Feb 7 17:24:20 2008
330 ( CURRENT ANTHROPOLOGY

A N D A , - M . T I L L I E R . 19860. New data on the origin of modem sented at the international conference "Kontinuitat und
man in the Levant. CURRENT ANTHROPOLOGY 27:63-64. Diskontinuitat in der Evolution des Menschen bis zur
BAR-YOSEF, O., H . LAVILLE, L . MEIGNEN, A.-M. TILLIER, B.
Herausbildung der Urgesellschaft," Lutherstadt Wittenberg,
VANDERMEERSCH, A. BELFER-COHEN, P. GOLDBERG, Y.
October 16-22.
RAK,A N D E . T C H E R N O V 1986b.
.
"La sepulture de Kebara, VANDERMEERSCH, B. 1969. L ~ nOUVeaUX
s squelettes mouste-
Mont Carmel, Israel." Colloque international sur l'homme de riens decouverts a Qafzeh (Israel]et leur signification. Comptes
Nkandertal, Lidge, pp. 135-37. Rendus de I'Acadkmie des Sciences D 262:1434-36.
B I N F O R DL,E W I S R . 1985 Human ancestors: Changing views of VILLA, P., D . HELMER, A N D J . C O U R T I N . 1985. Restes OSSeUXet
their behavior. Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 4:292- structures d'habitat en grotte. Bulletin de la Societb Prdhisto-
327. rique Fran~aise82:389-421.
B O U L EM , . , A N D R . A N T H O N Y . 1911. L'encephale de l'homme VILLA, P., C. BOUVILLE, J. COURTIN, D . HELMER, E. MAHIEU,
fossile de la Chapelle-aux-Saints. L'Anthropologie 22: 129-96.
P. SHIPMAN, G . BELLUOMINI, A N D M. B R A N C A . 1986a. Can-
B O U Y S S O N IAE,,,
A N D J . B O U Y S S O N I E . 1909. La sepulture nibalism in the Neolithic. Science 233:431-47.
mousterienne de la Chapelle-aux-Saints. Cosmos 1275:10-14. VILLA, P., J . COURTIN, D . HELMER, P. SHIPMAN, C . BOUVILLE,
B O U Y S S O N IAE,,, J . B O U Y S S O N IAEN, D L . B A R D O N . 1913. La A N D E. M A H I E U1986b.
. Un cas de cannibalisme au Neoli-
station moustkrienne de la "Bouffia" Bonneval a la Chapelle- thique. Gallia Prdhistoire 29: 143-72.
aux-Saints. L'Anthropologie 24:609-36.
C A P I T A NL, . , A N D D . P E Y R O N Y . 1911. Unnouveau squelette hu-
main fossile. Revue Anthropologique 21: 148-50.
C H A S EP, H I L I P G., A N D H A R O L D L . D I B B L E . 1987. Middle
Paleolithic symbolism: A review of current evidence and inter-
On Depiction and Language
pretations. Iournal of Anthropological Archaeology 6:263-96.
D E F L E U RA., 1987. Les skpultures mousteriennes. Th6se de doc-
torat, UniversitC de Provence (Aix-MarseilleI), France. HAROLD L. DIBBLE
DROSSLER R., 1988. Flucht aus dem Paradies. Halle-Leipzig. Department of Anthropology, University of
F I S C H E RU., 1956 Die Graber der Steinzeit im Saalegebiet. Ber-
lin. Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, Pa. 19104, U.S.A. 24 x 88
L E R O I - G O U R H AAN R,L E T T E1975.
. The flowers found with
Shanidar IV, a Neanderthal burial in Iraq. Science 1go:562-64. I have only three comments to make on Davidson and
MAY,F. 1986. Les sdpultures prdhistoriques. Paris: Editions Noble's (CA 30:125-37) article. First, the paper written
CNRS. by Chase and myself (Chase and Dibble 1987)appears in
M E Z Z E N AF., , A N D A. P A L M A D I C E S N O L A . 1972. Scoperta di
una sepultura gravettiana nella Grotta Paglicci (Rignano Gar- several places to have been misrepresented. One refer-
ganico). Rivista di Scienze Preistoriche 27:27-50. ence to it (p. 128) suggests that we concluded that there
M O R T I L L E TG,. , A N D A. M O R T I L L E T . 1900. Leprehistorique, was good evidence for symbolic behavior in Neandertals.
origine et antiquitd de l'homme. Paris. In fact, we stated (p. 284) that during this time "there is a
MORTILLET P., 1914. Origine du culte des morts: Les skpultures
prdhistoriques. Paris: Gamber. general lack of clear archaeological evidence for the pres-
M O V I U SH, . L., J R .Editor. 1975. Excavations of the Abri Pataud. ence of symbolism." We also argued that many of the
American School of Prehistoric Research Bulletin 30. interpretations of symbolism in early scratch marks and
-. 1977. Excavations of the Abri Pataud: Stratigraphy. the like are really only assumptions about and not con-
American School of Prehistoric Research Bulletin 3 I . clusive demonstrations of the nature of those marks.
R O C H EJ,. 1976. "La dkcouverte de la Chapelle-aux-Saints et son
influence sur l'evolution des idees concemant le psychisme des One of the most important criteria, as stressed by us and
Neandertaliens," in Les sdpultures ndandertaliennes. Edited by by Davidson and Noble, is repeated patterning. Any sin-
B. Vandermeersch, pp. 13-25, Colloque XII, UISPP Congress, gle set of marks on a bone or other material, however
Nice. elaborate or intentional, can only be assumed to be indi-
R O E B R O E KWIL, S , J A N K O L E NA, N D E E L C O R E N S I N K1988.
.
Planning depth, anticipation, and the organization of Middle vidual and idiosyncratic until examples are found that
Palaeolithic technology: The "archaic natives" meet Eve's de- demonstrate the presence of a shared meaning or under-
scendants. Helinium z8:17-34. standing.
R U S S E L LM,A R Y D . 1987 Bone breakage in the Krapina hominid Second, I agree that the early lithic industries (i.e.,
collection. American fournal of Physical Anthropology Lower and Middle Paleolithic) do not show any arbitrary
72:373-79.
S M I R N O VY ,U. n.d. Intentional human burial: Middle Paleolithic patterns that can be linked unequivocally to language or
beginnings. Iournal of World Prehistory. In press. shared "mental templates" (for a more thorough review,
S O L E C KR. I , S. 1960. Three adult Neandertal skeletons from see Dibble 1988). To be fair, however, others, such as
Shanidar Cave, northern Iraq. Smithsonian Institution Annual Sackett (1988)~ point out that some unquestionably lin-
Report for 1959, pp. 603-35.
S T E W A R TT., D A L E . 1977. The Neanderthal skeletal remains
guistically competent groups have made and still do
from Shanidar Cave, Iraq: A summary of the findings to date. make lithic industries with perhaps as little arbitrary
Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 121:121-65. patterning. Thus, the negative evidence based on stone
S U Z U K IH.,
, A N D F. TAKAI.1970 The Amud man and his cave tools does not give positive answers one way or the
site. Tokyo: University of Tokyo. other. On the other hand, the complete absence of any
T I L L I E RA., - M . 1982. Les inhumations d'enfants au Paleolithique
ancien et moyen. Dossiers Histoire et Archdologie 66: 19-22. such patterning preceding modern H o m o sapiens does
T R I N K A U SE R, I K . 1983. The Shanidar Neandertals. New York: make one wonder whether Neandertals and their
Academic Press. forebears used symbols even in other domains.
U L L R I CH, H. 1986 Manipulations of human corpses, mortuary Finally, I would like to emphasize the rather subtle
practice, and burial rites in Palaeolithic times. Anthropos
23:227-36. point made at the end of the paper that there is a differ-
-. 1988. Kontinuitat und Wandel in den Totenriten und Jen- ence between potential behavior and behavior that is an
seitsvorstellungen des palaolithischen Menschen. Paper pre- integral part of a species's adaptation. While we may
Volume 30, Number 3, June 1989 1 331

accept the notion that chimpanzees can be taught sym- thropologists have talked to all these years who have
bolic language, the fact remains that they do not use it in made little in the way of material depictions (such as
the wild; it is not part of their natural adaptation. Like- carvings) for future archaeologists to study and would
wise, it is irrelevant whether or not Neandertals could apparently be judged by Davidson and Noble noncul-
have been taught language. I would assume that they tural and therefore nonhuman. The Australian Aborig-
could, since there is no compelling reason to doubt their ines come to mind in that if we were to focus only on
potential along these lines, but the more important their stone tools, we might have to conclude that these
question is whether they used language as part of their people, whose kinship systems we still have trouble
adaptation. If not, what was the nature of their adapta- understanding, had no language or culture. That would
tion? fit nicely with their well-known smaller brains, and we
What is very interesting to me in the research on pri- could just ignore their well-developed and thoroughly
mate potentials for symbolic vocalizations or gestural modern Broca's areas. We have not a single reliable vocal
communications (Seyfarth 1986, Cheney, Seyfarth, and tract to study from the fossil record, yet Lieberman's
Smuts 1986) is that while many other primates exhibit views are regarded here as dicta.
clear and surprising potentials along these lines, they Once again, an argument on language origins is pre-
never seem to realize these to any significant extent. sented that cannot be tested. Since stone tools are ruled
This suggests that the ability to communicate symboli- out by Davidson and Noble's analyses, they cannot be
cally does not confer so tremendous an advantage on argued to be an example of a particular form of depiction.
these species that it automatically results in increasing For better or worse, stone tools do show invariances of
selection for that trait. For this reason, and regardless of form (standardized)as well as considerable variation. No
how important it is to modern cultural behavior, I would one questions that stone itself may limit the variety of
tend not to see language as the ultimate "prime mover" forms of production by its inherent physical properties
in the origin of hominids. This is exactly what has hap- and prior shape (e.g., oval river cobbles) or that not all
pened to other purported prime movers (such as hunting stone tool forms are arbitrary. The important point is
and tool use) as we have learned more about primate that despite these limitations and wide variation in tool
behavior in the wild. If these behaviors already existed in shapes, standardized and arbitrary forms often emerge
other primates, then they cannot be used to explain our from a series of concatenated perceptual, conceptual,
own evolutionary history. and sensorimotor actions performed by actors within a
social group. The fact that almost any graduate or under-
graduate student in anthropology can make stone tools
R. L. HOLLOWAY, JR. ranging from Oldowan pebbles to Aurignacian points
Department of Anthropology, Columbia University, suggests a set of perceptual and cognitive processes very
New York, N.Y. 10027, U.S.A. 25 x 88 different from those of spiders and birds. (Indeed, nests
and webs are often used as ethological criteria for distin-
Although my earlier article (Holloway 1969) is men- guishing species within these animal groups.)
tioned by Davidson and Noble ("as cited by Falk"), I Perhaps it would be simpler and scientifically more
wonder if it was read. Attempting to weld the psycholog- rigorous to insist that unless one talks to someone else
ical and the archaeological is hardly new. This piece ap- and gets an answer, no cultural exchange by language
pears to be within the new stream of thought that denies has taken place (ignoring deaf mutes and sign language
human status to hominids from the Neandertals down for the moment). This would conveniently place true
to the australopithecines on the basis of a perceived "culture" at about the time of writing (or the recording
stasis in the archaeological record, without careful ex- of conversations) and obviate the need to worry about
ploration of the biologies inherent in the hominid re- Neandertal vocal cords, stone tools and the sites where
mains or the possibilities of cultural elaboration from its they are uncovered, markings on antlers, cave paintings,
own internal resources. Stone tool making (e.g., Oldo- and the 1.8 million years of paleontological evidence re-
wan, Chellean, Acheulean, Soan, Levalloisian, Mouste- garding the evolution of the hominid brain. Davidson
rian) for Davidson and Noble is apparently homologous and Noble simply dismiss the brain, and if we are going
to spider-web and bird-nest building (and, of course, ter- to dismiss thousands of stone tools as suggestive of cog-
mite-nest raiding), despite the fact that some of these nitive and social processes indicative (or not) of language
tools span three continents and roughly 1.8 million capacity, one might as well dismiss the brain, too. Both
years and were clearly products of some form of shared can simply be regarded as "part of the preadaptation for
social consensus, quite possibly vocally articulated with more complex sequencing control necessary in produc-
the help of arbitrary symbols. The possibility remains, tion of speech, the associate of language" (p. 136). Thus,
despite all the argumentation to the contrary, that lan- until we recover Neandertals frozen in blocks of Siberian
guage had early roots, and an essentially human (albeit ice, thaw them out, bring them back to life, and even-
small) brain was available from 1.8 million years ago. tually talk to them, we need never worry about the
The tools themselves depict invariance (apoint I tried to paleoneurological evidence of our hominid ancestors,
make in my 1969 article and my dissertation of 1964 on such as Homo habilis, with its human-like Broca's area,
human brain evolution).I cannot help but wonder about or the petalial configurations discussed by Holloway and
all the preliterate (or nonliterate) human beings that an- de La Coste (1982)~ suggesting righthandedness some 1.8
332 1 CURRENT ANTHROPOLOGY

million years ago and strongly correlated with language mained rare or comparatively crude (as in the Gravettian
and hemispheric lateralization. (If three-year-olds are ca-cultures of central Europe and the Russian plain). Beads,
pable of reflexive thinking and depictions with small in fact, appear in the European record thousands of years
and as yet not fully differentiated cortical structural andbefore any animal or female images. They occur, for in-
fiber connections, why couldn't earlier hominid adults stance, in the pre-Aurignacian Chatelperronian at Arcy-
have been capable of reflexive thought?) sur-Cure, ca. 33,000 B.P., and in the earlier proto-
The problem for most archaeologists-cum-psychol- Aurignacian at Bacho Kiro, Bulgaria, ca. 40,000 B.P.The
ogists seems to be the apparent stasis in the archaeolog- earliest examples appear in a pre-Mousterian, Micoquian
ical record until the advent of the Upper Paleolithic, level of the German site of Bocksteinschmiede, ca.
art, and multiple evidence for behavioral (cultural?) IIO,OOO B.P. (Wetzel and Bosinski 1969; Marshack
diversity. Archaeologically (i.e., on the basis of mate- 1987b; 1988a, e; 1 9 8 9 ~ These
). items of personal decora-
rial culture1 all of the world outside of the Neo- tion are complex forms of visual symboling and com-
lithic centen (e.g., Egypt, Mesopotamia, the Indus, munication and may have marked age, sex, rank, and
China, etc.] shows thousands and thousands of years of status or the role of an individual in a particular cultural
"stasis" associated with biological evidence showing no moment, but thev are not in Davidson and Noble's sense
appreciable change. I wonder how someone living just "depicti;eu or representational. The most primitive of
prior to the Industrial Revolution would react to modern present-day hunter-gatherers, the remnant Pygmies of
attempts at space exploration and how Liuwenoek (or the Ituri Forest of northeastern Za'ire, have no "de~ic-
Mendel) would regard the modern unraveling of DNA tive" art or objects of decoration but do paint patterns on
and tunneling emission microscopy. Has the species face and body (Wilkie and Morelli 1988). They are, of
changed in the last 400 years? There is not a shred of course, fully human and have language. Body painting,
evidence for any biologically based changes accompany- tatooing, and scarification are common among certain
ing the vast acceleration of changes in cultural phenom- human societies, even where "depictive" art is lacking,
ena during the past 7,000 years, although Henneberg has and there is some evidence that it may have occurred in
recently made a convincing case for a reduction of brain the Upper Paleolithic.
size since the Upper Paleolithic. I sincerely doubt that it Items of personal decoration are found as grave goods
is necessary to explain the emergence of the Upper Pa- in European Upper Paleolithic burials from the Aurigna-
leolithic as suddenly depending on language, culture, cian onward, but burials which (despite Chase and Dib-
and thus the brain in some as yet unknown and unde- ble's 1987 caveat and Davidson and Noble's agreement
scribed fashion. Perhaps Stephen Jay Gould's suggestion with them] begin to be widespread in the Mousterian
that language was a spandrel of the human brain de- occur without evidence of such items. Burials them-
serves more attention. selves, however, are symbolic but not "depictive,"
mimetic, or representational in Davidson and Noble's
ALEXANDER MARSHACK sense, unless one wishes to hypothesize a Jungian return
Peabody Museum, Harvard University, Cambridge, of the body to the womb of mother earth. Like beads and
Mass. 02138, U.S.A. 16 XI 88 pendants, they represent a highly variable, arbitrary, cul-
tural usage, usually without "depictive" or mimetic ref-
Lacking firsthand knowledge of the widespread and erence (Marshack 1987b; 1988a, e; 1 9 8 9 ~ ) .
complex Upper Paleolithic materials or traditions, For White (1982, 1985, 1986)) the presence of beads
Davidson and Noble cite a handful of writers who, in the among the anatomically modern early Aurignacians or
main, have dealt ethnocentrically with certain aspects Cro-Magnons is evidence for the beginning of human
of the Franco-Cantabrian symbolic materials and tradi- self-awareness and social complexity and supposedly a
tions. The Franco-Cantabrian cultures, however, repre- crucial impetus to the development of language. David-
sent a purely regional and skewed development (Mar- son and Noble have chosen a different aspect of Upper
shack 1977; 1987a, bj 1988~-e; 1 9 8 9 ~ they ) ~ do not Paleolithic symboling to suggest an "origin" for lan-
represent the beginnings of art or adequately indicate the guage. Simplifying hypotheses such as these, however,
beginnings of image making or language. The gesture- denigrate the extraordinary complexity and variability of
mimesis-depiction model simply does not hold up in language as a neurologically mediated mode of reference,
light of either the available archaeological evidence from the complexity of the Upper Paleolithic symbol record,
the European Paleolithic or the record from other areas and the even earlier origins of nondepictive symboling
of human habitation during the same period. and image making.
Among the earliest symbolic materials from the Euro- The earliest evidence for "decoration" is the late
pean Upper Paleolithic are beads and pendants, items of Acheulian manufacture and use of ochre, ca, zr;o.ooo-
personal decoration that though symbolic are neither de- 300,000 B.P. (Lumley 1966, Wreschner 1480, ~ a r s h a c k
pictive, representational, nor mimetic in Davidson and 1981). Red ochre is nondepictive in Davidson and No-
Noble's sense. These objects are made of fossils, shells, ble's sense, for it can be used to color tools and svmbolic
and animal teeth as well as bone and stone, and they artifacts, dolor the bodies of the living and the dead,
occur in all regions of the Eurasian Upper Paleolithic, color the grave itself and the walls and floors of habita-
even where no early depictive animal art ever really de- tion sites. It can also be used as a material for drawing
veloped (as in Italy) and where depictive animal art re- images and for making notations and non-notational
Volume 30, Number 3, Tune 1989 1 333

sets of marks in the habitation site and on the walls of

"sanctuary caves." The carefully carved symbolic plaque

from the Mousterian site of Tata, Hungary, ca. ~oo,ooo

B.P., for instance, was covered with red ochre on its main

face but not on the back (Marshack 1976; 1988a, e), a

symbolic but "nondepictive" act in the Davidson and

Noble sense of the term.

It is significant, in the light of Davidson and Noble's


universalist approach, that no tradition of personal deco-
ration and no important tradition of the making of
animal or human images is documented in other areas of
anatomically modern human occupation around the
world during the period of the European Upper
Paleolithic. Two minor exceptions indicate the capacity
for such production but not its widespread cultural use.
Animal images and personal decorations do occur at the
late Upper Paleolithic site of Mal'ta, Siberia, among a
Mongoloid people which, however, had derived many of
its cultural and productive traditions from the Russian
plain, and a few crude animal paintings are known, as
Davidson and Noble recognize, from the Apollo I I cave.
These rare examples of depiction outside of Europe do
not establish a major depictive mode among the wide-
spread early human populations and cultures. Davidson
and Noble tend to argue that the rare and idiosyncratic
example from before the Upper Paleolithic cannot be
used as evidence either of capacity or of culture, but they
do not apply that rule to the period of the Upper
Paleolithic. Does the rare and idiosyncratic evidence
outside of Europe or even its total absence in major re-
gions mean that there was no capacity for language or
social complexity? There is, for instance, the rare and
idiosyncratic evidence for early mining of iron-oxide col-
oring material (specularite) in the Middle Stone Age of
South Africa, suggesting, once again, the presence of an
early capacity for the cultural use of color among differ-
ent human groups before the evidentiary beginnings of
manufactured mimetic-gestural depiction.
There is a strong suggestion, in fact, that it may have
been not mimetic-gestural depiction but a symbolic use
of animal skins and parts that immediately preceded the
Upper Paleolithic making of animal images in Eurasia
(Marshack 1987~;1988a, e; 1 9 8 9 ~ )At . the early Auri-
gnacian site of Hohlenstein-Stadel in Germany, ca.
32,000 B.P., there is the rare and idiosyncratic but extra-
ordinarily important mammoth-ivory carving of a lion-
headed therianthrope (fig. I ) . This image, which does
not depict or refer to any object or concept in the real
world (such as the "bison" that Davidson and Noble
offer as an example of depiction), may be the most sym- FIG. I . Lion-headed therianthrope of mammoth ivory
bolically complex image to come from the early Upper from Hohlenstein-Stadel, Germany, ca. 32,000 B.P.
Paleolithic. There is, however, no archaeological evi- Height 28.1 cm.
dence for a preparatory or developmental tradition lead-
ing to this carving or form of imaging. There is an indica-
tion at the late Neanderthal site of Hortus (Valflaunes), carved, engraved, and painted animal parts, at times
France, ca. 40,000 B.P., that a leopard skin may have been used as amulets or pendants (fishtails, seal tails, frogs1
worn as a costume (Lumley and Lumley 1972; Marshack legs, bison and horse hooves, animal jaws, cervid eyes,
1987b; 1988a, e; 1989~).Significantly, the later Upper bovid horns, stag antlers, etc.). Parts of animals (tails,
Paleolithic Magdalenian culture in the Franco-Can- ears, legs, muzzles, eyes, bellies) are often added to
tabrian region provides us with numerous examples of animal images in specialized, particularized acts of re-
334 1 CURRENT ANTHROPOLOGY

newal (Marshack 1987b, 1988d). There are also exam- shack 1984a, 1985, 1988b). These same capacities also
ples of the wearing of animal skins and parts by "sorcer- abetted image making and image use. Biologically,
ers" (Mas dlAzil, Trois Frkres, Abri Mkge, et al.). In this neurologically, evolutionarily, and archaeologically,
regard it is significant, as well, that the private and often however, one must differentiate imaging capacities and
secret shamanistic iconography and symbolic materials processes from linguistic capacities and processes rather
found in the medicine bags of historic times in different than equate them. One can, as a result of ne.urologica1
parts of the world include decontextualized animal and insult to different areas of the brain, maintain the
vegetable parts. These are symbolic but not necessarily learned capacity for syntactical, grammatical speech and
depictive or representational in Davidson and Noble's at the same time lose all reference to meaning" or the
sense. ability to recognize images, objects, processes, relations,
We are therefore faced, in dealing with the Franco- behaviors, and concepts of space and time. The capacity
Cantabrian phenomenon, with a complex regional, his- for language, as it evolved, would have increasingly been
torical development, not with biological or psychologi- able to refer to these other cognized and differentiated
cal universals. The Aurignacian initiated the abundant visual and envisioned nonlinguistic categories. Gesture
use of bone, ivory, and antler for practical and symbolic itself makes reference to visually cognized categories.
purposes, and the manufacture of animal images may The extraordinarily complex folk taxonomies found
thus have been ultimately derived at this time and in among hunter-gatherers, for instance, are based on
this region from an earlier symbolic use of animal skins the integrated use of a suite of diverse and separate
and animal parts. I stress the word "use" rather than categorizing capacities, unified visually as well as
depiction, since symbol systems always represent as- named.
pects of cultural usage rather than the mere "freezing" There are other fallacies in the Davidson and Noble
or encoding of internalized imagery. An analysis of the model. Though it was I who initially indicated the pres-
early animal carvings from the Aurignacian site of ence of "time-factored" cumulative notations in the
Vogelherd, Germany, ca. 32,000 B.P., for instance, has European Upper Paleolithic ( I970j I 972~-cj I 975 ;
shown that, instead of being merely "depictive" and 1987a)and the concept of the attachment of a symbolic
therefore "referential," they were used for different value to unit marks and sets of marks (cf.Davis 1986 and
ritual, symbolic purposes over time (Marshack 1972a, Davidson and Noble here), I have also, for almost two
1984a, 1987a, I 988d).The later Magdalenian animal im- decades, had to stress that this type of "depictive" nota-
ages in the Franco-Cantabrian caves were also often used tional marking represents a small fraction of the sym-
for diverse symbolic purposes (Marshack 1984b, 1988d). bolic marking found in the Upper Paleolithic. Inten-
Depictions were not merely referential, representa- tional marks and sets of marks were made for a range of
tional, and informational but, along with beads, pen- "depictive" and "nondepictive" purposes (Marshack
dants, ochre, and burials, often represented specialized 1g87a). Often participation in a ritual, i.e., the mere act
aspects of visual "nonlinguistic," enactive, symbolic, of participatory marking, resulted in the production of
ritual participatory behavior. While such usage suggests dots, lines, fingermarks, and even handprints. These
the presence of language and cultural complexity, these marks were not necessarily depictive, representational,
forms of visual symboling did not represent linguistic, referential, or even intended to be seen by or to com-
syntactical behavior. municate with others but often the by-product or end
The fact is that both language and symbolic imagery product of a symbolic process in which the ritual act was
are ultimately dependent on a number of neurological the semantic and relevant behavior. Nevertheless, they
visual or "visualizing" capacities, including the evolved often find their way into anthologies as "art." By con-
human capacity for categorization and abstraction, the trast, the incising of gripping marks on a tool also occa-
capacity to provide arbitrary meaning to objects, pro- sionally provides what seems to be a "decoration," and
cesses, relations, and behaviors (Marshack I 984a, I 98 5, these too appear in anthologies as "art." Such behaviors
1988b),and the capacity to model and map processes and and products were no more acts of interpersonal com-
concepts in time and space. It is in this nonlinguistic, munication or intentional depiction than the contempo-
cognitive sense that "depiction functions [ultimately] rary "gestural" modes of kneeling to pray, lighting a can-
. . . as the pivotal practice engendering reflective lan- dle ritually at home or in a temple, fingering rosary
guage." Language almost always refers to nonlinguistic beads, or touching holy water or the remnant evidence of
categories, processes, and relations present or observable work with tools. The Upper Paleolithic mobiliary mate-
in the visual or "envisionable" world, and its ultimate rials and the Franco-Cantabrian sanctuary caves are full
adaptive value is that it makes these categories manipu- of examples of simple modes of marking intentionally
lable syntactically and referentially. But the capacities hidden from others in difficult-to-reach recesses. Nota-
for categorization and depiction are not for that reason tions themselves were apparently a rare and specialized
linguistic or syntactical. The evolving hominid capacity elitist product devised to be used only by the maker. In
for visual categorization and abstraction was only one of fact, their cultural value apparently lay in the fact that
a number of neurological capacities developing in the they were an elitist, private, perhaps "shamanistic" skill
enlarging, networked hominid brain, and it coincided and act of ad hoc problem solving rather than an act of
with a developing capacity for language and speech and public communication (though events scheduled by
ultimately helped make it relevant and adaptive (Mar- their use may have become "public"). While other mem-
Volume 30, Number 3, lune 1989 1 335

bers of a group may have known the meaning of the questions and problems involved in the origins of hu-
notational tradition, any single notation could be read man language and image making and use.
only by its maker. In a number of major papers (Marshack 1987b, 1988e,
I have shown, as well, that the so-called serpentine 1989a) I have indicated that the Neanderthals had a ca-
and zigzag macaroni motif, ubiquitous throughout the pacity for symboling and could speak, though they left
European Upper Paleolithic in both habitation sites and us no record of depiction. The recent excavation of a
caves, was apparently water-related and used in ritual. In Neanderthal skeleton at Kebara (Bar-Yosef et al. 1985)
the case of this motif, "depiction," "mimesis," and ab- with the hyoid bone in an anatomically modern position
straction of the image of water and the concept of flow lends clear morphological support to the idea of a capac-
are clearly involved (Marshack 1975a, b; 1987a; 1988d). ity for speech.
Significantly, however, these acts of ritual marking were
often private, occurring on discarded fragments of bone
and stone or upon walls hidden in deep recesses of a ANDREE ROSENFELD
cave. They were not intended for communication with Prehistory and Anthropology, Australian National
others but were acts of individual, nonlinguistic com- University, GPO Box 4, Canberra, A. C.T. 2601,
munication with an internalized cultural semantic. I as- Australia. I XI 88
sume, of course, that language was involved in the nam-
ing of the motifs and in construction of the myths or Probably few would disagree with Davidson and Noble
expianations surrounding their use, but the artifact it- that there are significant analogies between linguistic
self, though "depictive" and "mimetic," was clearly and other symbolic communication systems, including
nonlinguistic. The beginning of art, symbol, and depic- the visual arts, but the developmental relationship be-
tion cannot be ascribed to any single mode or process. tween language and art is more contentious. They argue
It cannot be derived by reference to any one class of that depiction became meaningful as the transformation
Paleolithic image or to the development of skill in de- of physical reality into an image and conclude (p. 132)
piction in children. It cannot be explained in terms that it is the persistence of the image beyond the gesture
of Davidson and Noble's gestural-mimetic-depictive that created it that "provokes the reflectivity that in
model. More important, it cannot be explained by selec- turn permits referential utterance" (i.e., language). In
tive and subjective reference to aspects of the skewed this way they develop a theoretical proposition about
and inadequate Franco-Cantabrian Paleolithic record. the primacy of visual communication and especially of
The human visual, neurologically mediated capacities overtly iconic visual systems. The latter in particular
for categorization, abstraction, marking, imaging, mod- appears to contradict the available archaeological evi-
eling, and mapping are extraordinarily complex, cross- dence.
modal, and networked and have a range of potentially In support of their argument Davidson and Noble
variable referential modes and uses. Language as a ref- point out that a similar sequence of referential use of
erential mode is ultimately dependent upon these other, image and language is observed in the development of
nonlinguistic capacities and modes. The nonlinguistic infants. Though they rightly reject observations on the
capacity to map and model events and processes in the acquisition of language in children as a model for the
real world, for instance, extends to the nonlinguistic ca- origins of language, they proceed to suggest parallels for
pacity to "visualize" or "envision" events, processes, the development of iconic pictures in children's draw-
and relations in imagined worlds. These capacities are ings with the origins of the referential use of images. Just
not dependent on language but are, of course, abetted by as children grow up in language-rich cultures, so also
it. Language, as a referential mode, can refer as easily to they grow up in a world awash with images. Contempo-
these nonlinguistic categories and processes as to purely rary child studies cannot illuminate the origins of art-
linguistic, syntactical, grammatical modes, rules, and or, indeed, of any sphere of cultural activity-any more
structures. But language is not, for this reason, necessar- than those of language, for precisely the reasons they
ily depictive, and depiction is not, for this reason, neces- state.
sarily linguistic or syntactic. It is the archaeological evidence that must give us our
The origins of art and language require an understand- primary clues. Davidson's rejection of any symbolic be-
ing of the neurology of the suite of separate, specialized haviour in pre-Upper Palaeolithic times (in Europe) is
but hierarchically integrated capacities of the human unconvincing, resting as it does primarily on negative
brain. These are currently under intense investigation evidence and reference to an unpublished paper. Sym-
within more disciplines than are noted by Davidson and bolic action is demonstrated in the Mousterian by burial
Noble. A knowledge of language and imaging origins (and perhaps by the collection of pigments and fossils
will require, in addition, an understanding of the cul- [though not, I agree, by the bear cult!]).Further, if the
tural, historical, and adaptive contexts within which recurrence of standard forms among stond artefacts im-
these capacities functioned and developed (Marshack plies the concept of categories of flaked stone objects,
1 9 8 8 ~ )Logical
. modeling of universalist "psychologi- categorisation was most probably also applied to other
cal" theories and selective, subjective citation of the ar- facets of the human environment. The conceptual order-
chaeological literature to support a preconceived model ing of the environment-bringing nature into culture-
will not produce a theory capable of answering the many is a uniquely human trait which requires symbolic ex-
336 1 CURRENT ANTHROPOLOGY

pression and a measure of what Davidson and Noble formally restricted traces which acquire identities in
refer to as a reflective language. I remain unconvinced by their own right, not merely as visible traces of gestures.
their denial of the possibility of some form of language The development of such manual skills may well be
as a component of "Mousterian" cultures. archaeologically instantaneous. We need not expect to
They list the few examples of pre-Upper Palaeolithic be able to discern the sequential process from techni-
artefacts which appear to have a visual rather than a cally simple to technically more controlled forms in vi-
technological purpose (including some very doubtful sual systems which, because of repetition, can be
ones) but conclude that in the absence of repetition of identified as art, that is, visual systems of communica-
the visual forms the existence of a communication sys- tion.
tem cannot be demonstrated. True. However, if not for
communication, then what was the rationale for inten-
tionally marking or shaping objects with no technologi- GARRY W . T R O M P F
cal intent? Or are the few marked objects of non- Department of Religious Studies, University of Sydney,
perishable materials the remnant traces of symbolic Sydney, N.S.W. 2006, Australia. 12 XI 88
gestures only part of which impinged on the artefacts we
recover? If a strong and clearly argued case has ever been made
The visible traces of gestures abound among the later connecting the emergence of language with the human
arts, such as the macaroni and analogous painted marks capacity to depict signs manually, then Davidson and
of the European Palaeolithic and the finger markings of Noble have made it. There is an alluring application of
the Australian caves. They occur very widely in more Occam's razor in their reasoning: since no objects before
standard form as hand and other stencils. The trace of (select)engraved bones, figurines, and cave paintings of
the gesture persists right up to the present and operates the Upper Palaeolithic appear to communicate accord-
alongside more complex visual means of expression. The ing to some "system of recognizable meanings," there is
crucial question, then, is when and how the trace of the no necessity to posit language before depiction. Clarity
gesture became recognised as expressive of that gesture and attractions aside, however, not a few problems re-
and hence sharing in its meaning. The putative recogni- main with their inferences, and I will confine myself to
tion of footsteps that Davidson and Noble cite amounts the major ones.
to recognition of a mark left by an individual which has First, Davidson and Noble "cover their tracks" by sug-
only a partial iconic relationship with that person and gesting that we can expect to find older examples of
herlhis activity. This formal relationship is not sig- communicative depiction than we already possess. We
nificantly different from the relationship between per- are not told how much older (naturally),and their insis-
sons and their activities when creating finger tracings or tence that early Palaeolithic tool-making repertoires are
macaroni in later contexts. The difference lies in the in no sense depictions (i.e., mimicry of useful sharp ob-
presumed (but undemonstrated) intentionality of the jects in the natural environment),let alone evidence of a
finger tracings, etc., as visible marks which outlast "communicated tradition" (cf. Narr 1964:6-7), simply
the gesture. tantalizes. We are apparently not supposed to believe
I agree that it is "the achievement of meaningful . . . that hosts of depictions could have been made on per-
tracing [that] is the essential first step" (p. 131) in the ishable materials or on the ground thousands of years be-
development of a visual system of communication, viz., fore people dared to enter the eerie hideaways of Niaux
art. A fundamental flaw in Davidson and Noble's argu- and Trois-Frhes, and so any claim for an earlier than
ment, however, is the assumption that in order to be Upper Palaeolithic dating of language can be made only
meaningful such a trace must be iconic-must have a on the basis of extant remains. This position is method-
formal resemblance to its referent. In making this as- ologically safe and keeps arguments ex silentio to a
sumption they sidestep the entire question of the per- minimum; yet I still keep asking myself whether it is
ception of iconicity in marks and the degree to which methodologically sound.
such perception is culturally determined by style-the Second, Davidson and Noble have not given a com-
shared conventions which give meaning to marks. There plete account of the biological debate over the origins of
is no fundamental difference in the symbolic operation language and depiction. They do not discuss the limits of
of iconically perceived and apparently non-iconic im- ape "art" (Morris 1962)~ studies of vocalization frequen-
ages. cies among primates (Hockett 1960),or the evolution of
Thus if we follow the logic of Davidson and Noble's a two-tubed vocal tract crucial for speech located lower
own argument about the development of reflective com- down the throat than in primates (Lieberman 1988:24).
munication through posture and gesture, one might ex- Presumably, if there is no biological evidence against
pect essentially structured but non-iconic images that pushing the power of speech back well before good evi-
arise from only that part of the symbolic gesture which dence for depiction, there is no reason to discount other
leaves a visible trace. Such marks need not be highly conceivable reasons "talkers" might have wanted to
standardised in form or in degree of completeness. By communicate-to survive in the face of hostile compo-
extension, the concept of a trace as a controllable feature nents of an environment, work out a hunting strategy,
that can be subjected to intentional modification of form move from one spot to another-and thus might have
may then open the way to more controlled and more spoken (albeit probably simple) languages.
Volume 30, Number 3 , Tune 1989 1 337

Third, they make much of the modern-child/primal- humans. We also examine aspects of the theoretical and
human analogy to supplement their argument but pay empirical bases for some beliefs about early symbolism.
next to no attention to modern ethnographic materials Dibble seems to have misunderstood our reading of his
which run against it. This analogy is methodologically and Chase's work (Chase and Dibble 1987). Davidson
risky in any case if we are apparently left with no choice (1987) covered almost the same ground and drew the
but to imagine a long "pre-lingual" phase of human de- same conclusions about the quality of the evidence for
velopment in which verbal communication is compara- Middle Palaeolithic symbolism. It was precisely the im-
ble to that of modern three- or four-year-olds and homi- possibility of attributing intention to single sets of
nids are producing "Acheulian" and "Mousterian" marks or of attributing meaning to things when there is
artifacts. As for modern ethnography, it is surely of no possibility of sharing that meaning that set us off on
significance that some known cultures are very rich lin- the line of reasoning we have produced. We therefore
guistically but engage in depiction or design hardly at seem to agree almost completely with his published
all. I think immediately of the Papuan Highland Fu- work.
yughe, whose language is the subject of a 500-page dictio- Dibble's interpretation of primate potentials is differ-
n a b (Guivarc'h n.d. [1930])but who are known only for ent from ours. We are concerned not with hominid ori-
rough wood carvings, fairly crudely painted pole decora- gins but with human ones. He correctly recognises the
tions, and poker-worked bamboo pipes (seealso Hallpike importance of the American experiments with chimpan-
1977:I, 27, 63; Beier 1978).The northern regions of Tas- zees and gorillas in indicating that there is a potential
mania present a comparable Australian Aboriginal situ- which can be stimulated by symbol-using experiment-
ation (John Clegg, personal communication, 1988). It ers. In the origin of such symbol use in the evolutionary
should be added here that much art work in traditional record, there can have been no equivalent tutors. The
society as we know it from ethnography was meant to be question, then, becomes how creatures with potential
destroyed after ritual action (see, e.g., Marrie 1987:3 and but no comparative experience could have stumbled
the literature referred to there and Strathern 1971), yet upon the production of symbols. We have sought to
we cannot rule out such (or other relevant) principles' speculate about this in the context of the same ar-
having radically affected the archaeological record. chaeological record and interpretation of it as Dibble and
Fourth, these writers, both from an Australian univer- a theory of the nature of perception. As is foreshadowed
sity, leave one wondering about the prehistoric peopling at the end of the paper, we are currently working on
of Australia, clearly a rather special case. One implica- understanding the ways in which the differing ecological
tion of their paper is that those who first crossed "an and social conditions of humans as linguistic beings are
unknown stretch of water" to discover a "habitable con- the source of human diversity.
tinent" (ca. ~o,oooB.P.)might not have possessed a lan- Dibble's support on the matter of stone tools shows
guage. Our earliest dates for artistic activity in Australia that we are not alone in opposing Holloway about them.
are ca. 30,000 B.P.(tobe safe, and to anticipate a paper on Of course, the fact that some fully modern humans
the Panaramittee rock engraving "tradition" by Nobbs make stone tools without apparent patterning is irrele-
and Dorn [1988]), and yet, even with the absence of vant to our evolutionary argument, since linguistic com-
available data between this dating estimate and the petence has already given these groups a measure of
probable time of first arrival, the onus is on Davidson choice and innovation unknowable before.
and Noble to explain the peopling of Australia without Holloway's position is curiously contradictory. His
language, that is, in the absence of the evidence they contention that biology has not contributed to the mas-
deem necessary to establish its presence. The Australian sive cultural changes in the past 7,000 years can only be
case confirms the dictum (Clegg, personal communica- construed as an argument for the existence of some non-
tion, 1988) that "the closer we approach the most inter- biological source of variability on which natural selec-
esting questions, the harder it is to find the relevant tion can operate. We are suggesting that this is lan-
data, and even methods." guage-late in evolving, not early as Holloway would
have it. And what are we to make of his comparing con-
temporary undergraduates with Aurignacians? One of
our undergraduates prefaced his thesis with a photo-
graph of his three-year-old son imitating the actions
WILLIAM NOBLE AND IAIN DAVIDSON needed to make stone tools. Does this child have the
Department of PsychologylDepartment of same perceptual and cognitive capacities as Holloway's
Archaeology and Palaeoanthropology, students? Surely this argument is the wrong way around:
University of N e w England, Armidale, N.S. W. 23 5 I , it is the difficulty which students have in reproducing
Australia. 6 I 89 the products of prehistory that might be used in the ar-
gument. And the difficulty arises because there are gen-
This set of comments concentrates on archaeological as- erally no other stone flakers to imitate. Spiders and birds
pects of our argument about the process of emergence of cannot make stone tools either, because they do not
language. This gives us the opportunity to enlarge upon have hands. Does Holloway think that the problem is
our interpretation of the data relating to claims for sym- how hominids could have figured out that they needed
bolic behaviour before the emergence of fully modern to make stone tools? The fact is that for almost half of
the period in which hominids have been able to walk problematical. Thus, the Tata tooth is unique in the con-
upright (Laetoli 3.6 million years ago) they did not make text of modified objects because of its extreme antiquity.
stone tools. In the Upper Palaeolithic it would be unique but not
Marshack's work in describing and analysing both por- unusual, because we know that pieces of bone were mod-
table and cave "art" is without equal in its care and ified in various similar ways at that time.
attention to detail, but this does not automatically give Marshack mentions another unique case, the pla-
him authority in the theoretical aspects of the interpre- quettes from the Apollo 1 1 cave (Wendt 1976). For him,
tation of its significance in human evolution. Thus, we such rare occurrences "do not establish a major depic-
do not deny that objects as old as those from Bock- tive mode among the widespread early human popula-
steinschmiede could be beads, although we note that tions and cultures." We do not believe anyone has said
holes can be pierced in objects in a variety of ways, with that they do, but any such argument would exactly par-
and without human intervention and for a variety of allel his equally unestablished suggestion of such a
discoverable reasons. The rapid experimental replica- mode based on the early objects in Europe. The images at
tion of such holes that Marshack reports elsewhere Apollo 11 are recognisably iconic paintings and bear
( 1 9 8 9 ~reinforces
) the view that these need represent no comparison with the plaquettes from ~ a r ~ a l lin o , east-
more than idle manipulation, with no meaning attached. ern Spain (Pericot 1942, Davidson 1989),many of which
The scarcity of such objects suggests just that. To go on are much "cruder" although the dates are rather later
to state that they involve "complex . . . . symboling and (Bofinger and Davidson 1977). The Apollo 11 finds are
communication" is unwarranted in itself, but to attach separated from the next dated occurrence of depiction in
to them fully modern behaviours such as the marking of southern Africa by less than 15,ooo years; the tens of
"age, sex, rank, and status or the role of an individual in scattered instances of non-iconic objects in Europe are
a particular cultural moment" is to beg the question spread over more than I 50,ooo years.
with a romantic allusion (Davidson 1 9 8 8 ~ ) . The lion-headed ivory piece of Marshack's figure I is
Part of the problem with Marshack's critique is that he in the same category of finds as the Vogelherd figurines,
concentrates on materials from the Upper Palaeolithic which we consider to be later than the origins of lan-
with which he is most familiar as if they could credibly guage. We do not deny that complex symbolism may
be regarded as part of a single tradition. By our argument, exist once language does. To appeal to the suggestion of
they are not relevant to the question of language origins, leopard-skin costumes at Grotte de I'Hortus, based on
and that is why we hardly referred to them. If, as we finds of parts of these animals, seems to us misleading.
believe, they post-date the emergence of language, then spec- Many fragments of carnivore bone at the site are said
ulations about "time-factored notations," "participa- by de Lumley and his collaborators (1972:608-9) to
tory marking," "intention," "elitism," "shamanism," and have been collected for their attached skins. These in-
"water rituals" are at least in order, whether or not they cluded several leopard metacarpals and phalanges (Pil-
are supported empirically (see e.g., Rosenfeld 1971). lard 1972:174) that were found scattered in Level I I C
Butzer (1980)has argued that all of the early pieces of (Lumley at al. 1972:596), assembled by the palaeontol-
ochre seem to be modified. Marshack's list of things that ogist as a fragment of a single paw, and then shown
might be done with ochre is interesting but relevant schematically (p. 597)as complete. (Marshack elsewhere
only if it has been demonstrated that those things were [1989a, b] refers to this reconstruction as though it had
done and that meaning was "attached" to such actions. survived in that form.) The discovery of these fragments
It is, after all, the search for meaning that we are em- in the region of the "Grand Fosse" at that site, which we
barked upon. Reference to the Tata tooth brings us back regard as unlikely to represent primary contexts of depo-
to where we started this search. Marshack's (1977)de- sition, might explain the incompleteness and the scat-
tailed description of this object was one of the begin- tering: it also suggests that less importance was attached
nings of our project. The tooth is remarkable in being to such a skin than Marshack attributes to it. No doubt
flaked, polished, and coloured, but the puzzle, given its the argument by association is supposed to show a tradi-
uniqueness, is how it could have been symbolic. Our tion from the leopard bones of the Mousterian of Hortus
paper was repeatedly explicit that meaning must be (undated but older than 40,000 years ago) through
shared to be meaning and that a sign of such sharing is the sculpture of Hohlenstein-Stadel (~o,oooyears later
the repetition of production. How can a unique object [Hahn 1983]),and the (probably)Magdalenian paintings
have meaning at all? (a further 20,000 years later) of so-called sorcerers to the
It is impossible to explain a unique event, but some historic medicine bags (another ~o,oooyears and a conti-
understanding may be reached by considering the con- nent awav). This is the onlv evidence which could be
text in which the uniqueness is recognised. In one sense, used to claim such a traditioh, and it does not strengthen
all objects and events are unique, but our habitual, post- any part of Marshack's argument to juxtapose curiosities
lingual, systems of categorisation associate them with from different periods and different places. As Conkey
others which are recognised as sufficiently similar by (e.g., 1986) has argued, there can be no continuity on a
some criterion or other. The unique object or event can scale of analysis as gross as this. In the end, such a pre-
be recognised as such only by its difference from other sentation may be preferred to ours as a story, but as
objects or events which are not unique in that sense. an argument about the origins of particular human be-
Which universe of events or objects to compare it with is haviours we prefer some theory about how a capacity for
Volume 30, Number 3, lune 1989 1 339

symbolism became possible in a creature which had The first issue is the fundamental one. In the case of
none. Shanidar 4 it is at least likely that the same taphonomic
As does Davis (1986:201), Marshack has a theory processes as led to the belief in a bear cult (Kurten
about the visual system as being able to "abstract," I 976:85 ) have operated to preserve an individual who
"categorise," "discover," or "recognise" features of the died naturally. The body was found surrounded by
environment. The problem with this has been identified rocks-in Leroi-Gourhan's words, "placed in an enclo-
by Coulter (1979)in connection with writings about the sure of stones." We have no evidence that it was placed
brain, in which characteristics only ascribable to per- by any creature other than itself, sleeping normally on a
sons, such as "thinking," "deciding," etc., are attributed nest (other primates make nests [Groves and Sabater Pi
to this part of their bodies. It is evident that the mamma- 19851) of branches and flowers. The argument is en-
lian visual system is sensitive to contrasts and fluctua- hanced (or confused) by reference to the flowers as an
tions of the sort that specify the boundaries and facets of "offering" (e.g., Trinkaus 1983:I 5 ) and as having been
surfaces and the various ways in which they are trans- "carefully placed" (Leakey 198I : I 5 3). It was, of course,
formed geometrically and morphologically (Gibson the pollen samples, and not the pollens or their flowers,
1966, 1979).That ascription does not warrant the further that were carefully taken from select places around the
assertion that the visual system "categorises" or "recog- skeleton (Leroi-Gourhan I 975 : 5 62).
nises" or "sees resemblance." These are achievements of What is it about a burial which marks it off from the
persons, able to see and also able to make claims about preserved remains of other dead creatures, and what
recognising, seeing resemblance, or assigning to catego- about it enables us to recognise it? Modern mortuary
ries. Such claims can only be made, it need hardly be practices (e.g.,Haglund 1976)involve the disposal of the
stressed, by members of linguistic communities, i.e., dead in a wide variety of ways. Some result in the im-
modern human beings. The capacity to make such mediate destruction of the skeleton (e.g., cremation),
claims is delivered not simply by the capacity to vocalise some in delayed destruction (e.g., exposure in a tree);
but by the discovery that meaning is conveyable in some are more conducive to preservation of the skeleton
vocalising or other bodily sign. As with Broca's area, so (e.g., burial in a crypt). The point is that we cannot be
with the Kebara hyoid bone, structure must evolve be- sure that the disposal of dead bodies is a symbolic act in
fore function. a simple way. In an argument about the evolution of
Marshack mentions pre-Upper Palaeolithic burial, an distinctive human practices involving symbolism we
issue taken up by Rosenfeld, who specifically challenges would have to determine that the body was deliberately
our archaeolom on this ~ o i n t Rosenfeld
. is correct in separated from the living and self-consciously (e.g.,cere-
saying that ~ G i d s o n ' s( 1 6 8 ~paper
) is unpublished; this monially) disposed of. We should not accept as evidence
is because it has been superseded by the one under dis- of this any claim which can be accounted for in another,
cussion. As did Chase and Dibble's (1987)paper but in- non-cultural way, hence the importance of signs of de-
dependently of it, it concluded that there is no evidence liberate emplacement and of grave goods.
for symbolism or other culturally defined values in the The Shanidar case illustrates the nature of the prob-
burials of the Middle Palaeolithic. The case about burial lem. Solecki (1961)argued that Shanidar I died in a rock-
has been well made also by Harrold (1980),and it is clear fall, and Philip Smith's notes (Solecki 1961:72) at the
at least that none of the Middle Palaeolithic skeletal time of discovery stated explicitly, "No signs of burial
finds is associated with grave goods other than tools, except for thin dark streak on west side of skull." Sol-
animal bones, or manuports (a point conceded here by ecki suggested (p. 74). that the brown streak might have
Marshack); all such finds could have become associated been caused by a rodent burrow. Solecki further argued
with the skeletal remains by means other than deliber- that Shanidar z and 3 were also victims of rockfall, and
ate burial of them or even of the bodv. The same is true Trinkaus (198327) commented, "As with the other
for finds associated with ochre (see Bouyssonie, Bouys- Shanidar adults, Shanidar 5 was wedged between rocks
sonie, and Bardon 1908:5 17, quoted by Chase and Dibble and appears to have been killed by rockfall." Yet Trin-
1987274).There seems to be no find associated with any kaus elsewhere (pp. 16-17~ Trinkaus 1985:211, 213) re-
object which could be called symbolic, yet many such fers to all of these as "burials" (as does Harrold (19801, de-
objects are found in Upper Palaeolithic burials. One ex- spite his careful assessment of the burial status of Nean-
ception seems to be the flowers from Shanidar 4 (Solecki dertals). They were undoubtedly "buried" under the sed-
1971, Leroi-Gourhan 1975). Whilst we were initially iments from which they were excavated, but whether
sceptical of Solecki's report, especially in view of his anything other than natural sedimentation (including
mentioning that the workers at the site decorated them- rockfall) was involved in such burial is another question.
selves and their wheelbarrows with brightly coloured The imprecision in Trinkaus's account is symptomatic
flowers (Solecki I 97 I :68),Leroi-Gourhan's ( 1975 ) careful of much of the belief in early burials. We do not deny
account makes a much stronger case that flowers were that there are some cases in which care has been taken
introduced into the cave close to the time of the death of to establish that the recognition of burial involved more
this creature. The issues are whether this was a burial than "association of skeletal elements in a partial skele-
and whether the flowers were part of the burial process ton" (Trinkaus I 985 :ZIZ). Burial pits were described at
and therefore in any way to be related to the uses of La Ferrassie (see, e.g., Heim 1982:7, fig. 4), but this is
flowers at present-day funerals. relatively rare amongst Neandertals. We suspect that ap-
340 1 CURRENT ANTHROPOLOGY

plication of the same taphonomic rigour to other her about the rapidity of the effect of depicting and about
claimed burials as can be applied to Shanidar might re- the ways in which systems of depiction may develop.
duce the numbers further.' Trompf mistakenly equates vocalising with language
We regard the absence of evidence for symbolism in and, with Marshack, advances a teleological argument
Middle Palaeolithic burials as positive, not negative, evi- about creatures' "wanting" to improve their commu-
dence in the context of our theory. We concede that we nicative capacity (Marshack conceals his "drive to-
cannot offer other positive evidence that burial was not a ward language" in the "developing" brain). If, instead,
"symbolic action," but we think that the onus is on one adopts an evolutionary approach to the problem, it
Rosenfeld to demonstrate that it was. The remains at is necessary to restrain the urge to picture any aspect of
Krapina might be taken as evidence for her argument the system as "heading" anywhere. Biological characters
because of Russell's (1987) demonstration that some of that pre-date modern human (cultural)capacity to plan
the skeletal elements appear to have been cleaned of ahead and hence attempt to control future contingencies
flesh before disposal. Russell argues that this was done have to be explained in terms of capacities already se-
in a manner comparable with at least one example of lected for.'
modern secondary burial and that the cut marks on the Trompf does not confront our argument about why it
bones are distributed differently from those produced by is unlikely that the earliest depiction was exclusively in
caribou butchery. It does not, however, seem necessary perishable media, and he distorts our position on the
to argue for anything beyond the removal of flesh from abilities of modern human children. We are verv careful
the bone. The removal of flesh for whatever reason to limit what we say might intelligibly be learnkd about
would still have permitted its consumption, and such hominid evolution from the development of children's
activity becomes "cannibalism" only in a cultural set- skills. It is fanciful to suggest that a case for comparabil-
ting. The fact that a particular form of defleshing takes ity between adult and hominids and modern children
places now in a cultural context of secondary burial can be derived from our argument.
without consumption does not require that a similar The modern ethnographic issues regarding depictive
behavioural context inevitably was associated with the practices that Trompf mentions are not germane to an
defleshing at Krapina, given the absence of any cultural argument about origins. Depiction's prehistoric power is
sign. its instantiation of context-free reference, the basis of
Rosenfeld considers it a flaw in our argument that the symbol and language. Once depicting has had this trans-
earliest traces must be iconic and also argues that "icon- forming effect upon communication, cultural selection
icity" must itself be perceived in order to be effective as will determine the nature of its histories.
an information source. Her precise point here may be Trompf considers that our argument "leaves one won-
akin to Davis's (CA 3o:141--42),to which we have al- dering" about the linguistic capacity of those who first
ready responded (CA 30:148-49). If it is not, then our settled in Australia. We assume that the initial colon-
response must be as follows: our argument is that only ists, more than 40,000 years ago, did have language (p.
iconic imagery can deliver the perception of resem- 137).We would argue (see, e.g., Davidson 1988b)that the
blance that is necessary for the whole enterprise of sym- first colonists of Australia made one of the earliest docu-
bol production to get a foothold, whatever happens mented sea voyages, and we cannot imagine how that
thereafter. We do not argue that perceivers of resem- happened unless these were language-using people capa-
blance must go to the metaconceptual level of perceiv- ble of planning and constructing a raft. The early sea
ing that it is the iconic quality of the image that does the voyages in Melanesia suggest that they were (Allen et al.
trick. Does Rosenfeld have a theory about how meaning 1988, Wickler and Spriggs 1988). The earliest-known
could come to be attached directly to non-iconic traces? tracing in Australia is not iconic (White with O'Connell
Iconicity in historic times exhibits varieties of style that 1982:61-63), and on our model this must follow from
are culturally determined, but how did any of this activ- the emergence of language, whereas a hypothesis of a
ity come about? We have sought to account for this in a non-lingual colonisation of Australia would presumably
context of theorising about perception and conscious- have language evolve within Australia as well as else-
ness. where. The burials at Lake Mungo (White with O'Con-
Rosenfeld suggests that our argument allows for non- nell 1982:34-39) can hardly be construed as other than
iconic traces from "only that part of the . . . gesture deliberate interments, with one dated at 26,000 years
which leaves a visible trace." In our reply to commen- ago being a partial cremation, smashed and reburied, and
tators (which she had not seen when she wrote) we lay the other, really undated but probably older on strati-
out in more detail a possible path from gesture to trace graphic grounds, an extended burial with red ochre. It is
that emphasises their morphological relatedness as es- simpler to interpret all of this as following a colonisation
sential to the trace's initiating function of "reflectively by language-using humans.
of reference." We see nothing in Rosenfeld's point that
precludes our scenario; at the same time, we agree with 2. We note, for example, Clark and Lindly's (CA 30:179) observa-
tion that "evidence for symbolic behavior cannot be correlated
with hominid taxa." This is to be expected-otherwise we might
need to invoke a gene for language. everth he less, it is undoubtealy
I . See, for example, the paper by Gargett (CA 30:157-90),which the case that subseauent emergence of modem-i.e., svmbolic-
came to our attention after the composition of this reply. behaviour favoured ;he selection of the modern morphology.
Volume 30, Number 3, June 1989 1 341

References Cited HO CKETT, C. F . 1960. T h e origin o f speech. Scientific American


203:88-III.
ALLEN, J . , C . G O S D E N , R. J O N E S , A N D J . P . W H I T E 1. 988. Pleis- H O L L O W A Y , R. L., J R . 1 9 6 9 Culture: A h u m a n domain. CURRENT
tocene dates for h u m a n occupation o f N e w Ireland, n o r t h e m ANTHROPOLOGY IO:395-412.
Melanesia. Nature 33 1:707-9. H O L L O W A Y , R. L., JR., A N D M. C . D E L A COSTE-LAREYMON-
BAR-YOSEF, O., B. V A N D E R M E E R S C H , B. A R E N S B U R G , P . D I E .1982. Brain endocast asymmetry in pongids and hominids:
G O L D B E R G , H . L A V I L L E , L. M E I G N E N , T. RAK, E. T C H E R N O V , S o m e preliminary findings o n t h e paleontology o f cerebral
A N D A - M . T I L L I E R . 1985. N e w data o n t h e origin o f m o d e m dominance. American Iournal of Physical Anthropology
m a n i n t h e Levant. CURRENT ANTHROPOLOGY 27:63-64. 58:101-10.
B E I E R , K . 1 9 7 8 Squatters' art i n Port Moresby. Gigibori ~ I : I - 1 3 . K U R T E N , B . 1976. T h e cave bear story: Life and death o f a van-

B O F I N G E R , E., A N D I . D A V I D S O N 1977. . Radiocarbon age and


ished animal. N e w Y o r k : Columbia University Press.

depth: A statistical treatment o f t w o sequences o f dates f r o m


L E A K E Y , R. E . 1981. T h e m a k i n g o f m a n k i n d . London: Michael

Spain. Iournal of Archaeological Science 4:23 1-43.


Joseph.

B U T Z E R , K . W . 1980. C o m m e n t o n : Red ochre and h u m a n evolu- L E R O I - G O U R H A NA.,


1975. T h e flowers found w i t h Shanidar IV,
tion: A case for discussion, b y Emst E. Wreschner. CURRENT AN- a Neandertal burial i n Iraq. Science 1go:562-64.

THROPOLOGY 21:635. L I E B E R M A NP .. 1988. Voice i n t h e wilderness: H o w h u m a n s ac-

C H A S E , P H I L I P , A N D H A R O L D D I B B L E1987.
. Middle Paleolithic quired t h e power o f speech. T h e Sciences 2823-29.

symbolism: A review o f current evidence and interpretations. L U M L E Y , H . D E . 1966. Les fouilles d e Terra A m a t a a Nice. Bulle-

Iournal of Anthropological Archaeology 6:263-96. t i n au M u s t e d ' h t h r o p o l o g i e d e Monaco 13.

C H E N E Y , DOROTHY, ROBERT SEYFARTH, A N D BARBARA L U M L E Y , H. D E , M-A. D E L U M L E Y , R. B R A N D I , E. G U E R R I E R , F .


S M U T S . 1986. Social relationships and social cognition i n nonhu- P I L L A R D , A N D B . P I L L A R D 1972. . "Haltes et campements de
m a n primates. Science 234:1361-66. chasseurs ntandertaliens dans la grotte de 1'Hortus (Valflaunes,
CONKEY, M. W. 1986. "Interpretive problems i n hunter-gatherer
Herault)," i n La grotte d e 1'Hortus (Valjlaunes, Herault). Edited
regional studies: S o m e thoughts o n t h e European Upper
b y M - A . d e Lumley and Henry de Lumley, pp. 527-624. Etudes
Paleolithic," i n T h e Pleistocene Old World: Regional per-
Quatemaires, Memoire I .
spectives. Edited b y 0 . Soffer, pp. 63-77. N e w Y o r k : Plenum
L U M L E Y , M - A , , A N D H E N R Y D E L U M L E YE . ditors. 1972. La
Press.
grotte d e I'Hortus (Valjlaunes, Herault). Laboratoire de Paleon-
C O U L T E R , J . 1979. T h e brain as agent. H u m a n Studies 2:335-48. tologie Humaine e t d e PrChistoire, Marseilles, Etudes Quater-
D A V I D S O N , I . 1983. Beating about t h e bush? Aspects o f t h e his-
naire, MCmoire I .
tory o f Australian archaeology. Australian Archaeology
M A R R I E , A. I 987. A topical bibliography o f Australian Aborig-
17~136-44.
inal visual arts. Melbourne: A . P. H. Marrie.
-. 1987. Hello, goodbye: Aspects o f t h e origins o f art, becom- M A R S H A C K , A. 1970. Notation dans les gravures d u PalBoli-
ing h u m a n , and t h e colonisation o f Australia. Unpublished thique supbrieur. UniversitC de Bordeaux, Institut de PrChis-
seminar aiven at t h e Unversitv o f N e w Enaland - and t h e Univer- toire, M t m o i r e 8.
sity o f sfdney, ~ u g u s t - s e p t e & b e r . -. 1972a. T h e roots of civilization. N e w Y o r k : McGraw-Hill.
. 1988a. " T h e naming o f parts: Ethnography and t h e inter- -. 1972b. Upper Paleolithic notation and symbol. Science
pretation o f Australian prehistory," in Archaeology with eth- 178:817-32.
nography: An Australian perspective. Edited b y B. Meehan and . 1 9 7 2 ~Cognitive
. aspects o f Upper Paleolithic engraving.
R. Jones, pp. 17-32. Canberra: Department o f Prehistory, Aus- CURRENT ANTHROPOLOGY I3 :445-77.
tralian National University. . 1974. Reply [ t o Littauer and McCarthy]. CURRENT AN-
. 1988b. "Migration o f peoples: T h e arrival o f t h e Aborig- THROPOLOGY I5 3327-32.
ines," i n T h e Australian Encyclopedia, vol. I , pp. 29-33. Syd- . 1975. Exploring t h e m i n d o f Ice Age m a n . National Geo-
ney: Australian Geographic Society. graphic 147(1):62-89.
. 1989. "Freedom o f information," i n Animals i n t o art.
. 1976. S o m e implications o f t h e Paleolithic symbolic evi-
Edited b y H . Morphy. London: U n w i n Hynman.
dence for t h e origins o f language. CURRENT ANTHROPOLOGY
D A V I S , W . 1986. T h e origins o f image making. CURRENT AN-
17:274-8%
THROPOLOGY 27:193-215.
-. 1977. " T h e meander as a system: T h e analysis and recog-
D I B B L E , H A R O L D .1988. " T h e implications o f stone tool types for nition o f iconographic units i n Upper Paleolithic composi-
t h e presence o f language during t h e Middle Paleolithic," i n T h e tions," i n Form in indigenous art: Schematization in t h e art o f
h u m a n revolution: Behavioural and biological perspectives o n Aboriginal Australia and prehistoric Europe. Edited b y P. U c k o ,
t h e origins of m o d e r n h u m a n s . Edited b y P. Mellars and C . pp. 286-317. London: Duckworth.
Stringer. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. In press. . 1979a. Upper Paleolithic symbol systems o f t h e Russian
G I B S O N , J . J . 1966. T h e senses considered as perceptual systems. Plain: Cognitive and comparative analysis o f complex ritual
Boston: Houghton Mifflin. marking. CURRENT ANTHROPOLOGY 20:271-3 I I .
. 1979. T h e ecological approach t o visual perception. Bos- . 1979b. Reply [to Boroneant and Frolov]. CURRENT AN-
ton: Houghton Mifflin. THROPOLOGY 201607-8.
G R O V E S , C . P . , A N D J . S A B A T E R P I . 1 9 8 5 From ape's nest t o h u - -. 1981. O n Paleolithic ochre and t h e early uses o f color and
m a n fix-point. M a n 20:22-47. symbol. CURRENT ANTHROPOLOGY 2 2 : 188-91.
G U I V A R C ' HF, - X . n.d. (1930).Dictionnaire fujuge-fran~ais.MS, . 1984a. " T h e ecology and brain o f two-handed bipedalism:
Mafula. An analytic, cognitive, and evolutionary assessment," i n
H A G L U N D , L. 1 9 7 6 Disposal o f t h e dead among Australian A n i m a l cognition. Edited b y H . L. Roitblat, T . G. Bever, and
Aborigines: Archaeological data and interpretation. Stock- H . S. Terrace, pp. 491-511. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum.
h o l m : University o f Stockholm Institute o f Archaeology. . 1984b. Concepts thkoriques conduisant a de nouvelles
H A H N , J . 1983. "Eiszeitliche Jager zwischen 3 5,000 und I 5,000 methodes analytiques, de nouveau procedes d e recherche et ca-
Jahren vor Heute," i n Urgeschichte in Baden- Wurttemberg. tegories de donnCes. L'Anthropologie 88:5 73-86.
Edited by H . Miiller-Beck, pp. 273-330 Stuttgart: Konrad . 1985. Hierarchical evolution of t h e h u m a n capacity: T h e
Theiss Verlag. Paleolithic evidence (Fifty-fourth l a m e s Arthur Lecture o n T h e
H A L L P I K E , C . R. 1977. Bloodshed and vengeancein t h e Papuan Evolution of t h e H u m a n Brain, 1984). N e w Y o r k : American
mountains. Oxford: Clarendon. M u s e u m o f Natural History.
H A R R O L D , F . B . 1980. A comparative analysis o f Eurasian . 1987a. T h e evolution and transformation o f "decoration":
Palaeolithic burials. World Archaeology 1 2 :195-21 I . Early Aurignacian t o t h e Terminal Magdalenian. Paper deliv-
H E I M , J - L . 1982. Les enfantsnkandertaliens d e l a Ferrassie. Paris: ered at t h e Colloque International d'Art Mobilier Paleolithique,
Masson. Foix and Mas dlAzil.
342 1 CURRENT ANTHROPOLOGY

. 1987b. Early hominid symbol and evolution of the human -. 1986. Toward a contextual understanding of the earliest
capacity. Paper prepared for the symposium "The Origins and body ornaments. Paper presented at the conference on "The
Dispersal of Modem Humans," Cambridge, U.K. Origins of Modem Human Adaptations," School of American
-. 1988a. "L'homme de ~ k a n d e r t a l L:; pensee symbolique et Research, Albuquerque, N.M.
l'art," in L'homme de Nbandertal, pp. 80-90. Dossiers Histoire W I C K L E Rs.,, A N D M. S P R I G G S . 1988. Pleistocene humanoccu-
et Archeologie 124. pation of the Solomon Islands, Melanesia. Antiquity 62:703-6.
. 1988b. "The species-specific evolution and contexts of the WILKIE,D. s., A N D G. A. M O R E L L 1988 I. Pitfalls of the Pygmy
creative mind: Thinking in time," in The creative mind: To- hunt. Natural History 97(12]:32-41.
wards an evolutionary theory of discovery and innovation. W R E S C H N E R , E R N S T E . 1980. Red ochre and human evolution: A
Edited by C. S. Findlay and C. J. Lumsden, pp. 116-19. Journal case for discussion. CURRENT ANTHROPOLOGY 21:631-44.
of Social and Biological Sciences I I ( I ) .
-. 1 9 8 8 ~"Paleolithic
. image," in Encyclopedia of human
evolution and prehistory. Edited by I. Tattersall, E. Delson, and
J. Van Couvering, pp. 421-29. New York: Garland Press. On Issues in Treponemal
. 1988d. Theory and methodology in the study of the Upper
Paleolithic signs. Paper delivered at the First International Con- Epidemiology
gress on Rock Art, Darwin, Australia, August 29-September 2.
-. 1988e. "The Neanderthals and the human capacity for
symbolic thought: Cognitive and problem-solving aspects of HENRY F . D O B Y N S
Mousterian symbol." L'homme de Nbandertal: Actes du Col- Department of Anthropology, University of Oklahoma,
loque International, 1986, Likge, vol. 5. Edited by M. Otte, pp.
5 7-91. Likge. Norman, Okla. 73019, U.S.A. 30 XI 88
-. 1989a. Evolution of the human capacity: The symbolic
evidence. Yearbook of Physical Anthropology. In press. Baker and Armelagos (CA 29:703-37) have clarified
. 1989b. The Neandertals and the human capacity for sym- many issues "for the continuing debate" on treponemal
bolic thought: Cognitive and problem-solving aspects of
Mousterian symbol. Etudes et Recherches Archeologiques de epidemiology. Focusing on the origin and antiquity of
I'Universitb de Liege. In press. syphilis, they understandably do not identify all of the
M O R R I SD, . 1962. The biology of art. London: Methuen. significant issues concerning Treponema predation dur-
N A R R K. , J. 1964. Approaches to the religion of Early Palaeolithic ing the Columbian exchange (Crosby 1972). One major
man. Translated by N. E. Auer. History of Religions ~ ( I ) : I - 2 2 . additional issue is the chronology of treponemal preda-
N O B B SM , . F., A N D R. Z . D O R N 1. 988 Age determinations for
rock varnish formations with petroglyphs. Rock Art Research tion on Native Americans. Baker and Armelagos accept
5:108-46. at face value the dates published with skeletal remains,
P E R I C O TL,. 1942. La cueva del Parpallo. Madrid: Consejo but such dates are not necessarily accurate. The signifi-
Superior de Investigaciones Cientificas. cance of accurately dating Native American skeletal re-
P I L L A R DB. , 1972. "La faune des grands mammiferes du Wurmien
I1 de la grotte de 1'Hortus (Valflaunes, Herault]," in La grotte de mains judged to exhibit sequelae of Treponema infection
I'Hortus (Valflaunes, Herault). Edited by M-A. de Lumley and appears dramatically in the same CA issue as the Baker-
Henry de Lumley, pp. I 63-205. Etudes Quatemaires, Memoire Armelagos review. Lewis (1988) argues that 23 Upper
I. Mississippi River Valley archaeological sites, including
R U S S E L LM., D. 1987. Mortuary practices at the Krapina Neander- both Upper and Middle Nodena, date to the 16th cen-
tal site. American Iournal of Physical Anthropology 7x381-97.
S A C K E T TJ A , M E S1988.
. "The Mousterian and its aftermath: a tury. Baker and Armelagos (p. 714) date Nodena culture
view from the Upper Paleolithic," in Upper Pleistocene prehis- at A.D. 1400-1700; they do not, however, differentiate
tory of western Eurasia. Edited by H. Dibble and A. Montet- the issue of the antiquity of New World syphilis from
White, pp. 41 3-26. Philadelphia: The University Museum. the issue of its historic epidemiology. Ramenofsky
S E Y F A R T HR , O B E R T1986.
. "Vocal communication and its rela-
tion to language," in Primate societies. Edited by B. Smuts, D. (1987:177-99) has redated 49 Mississippi River and
Cheney, R. Seyfarth, R. Wrangham, and T. Struhsaker, pp. 440- tributary-stream ruins north of the Yazoo-Mississippi
51. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. confluence to the 16th century and concluded (p. 71)
S O L E C K IR., S. 1961. Three adult Neandertal skeletons from that in the lower valley "catastrophic population loss
Shanidar Cave, northern Iraq. Sumer 17:17-1 12 began in the sixteenth century." Smith (1987:2, 54-85)
-. 1971. Shanidar: The humanity of Neandertal man. Lon-
don: Allen Lane. has dated interior montane Southeastern population col-
STRATHERN A., J. 1971. Self-decoration in Mount Hagen. Lon- lapse to the same 16th -century. As methodologically
don: Duckworth. innovative archaeologists date artifacts and site occupa-
T R I N K A U SE., 1983. The Shanidar Neandertals. New York: Aca- tions with increasing precision, scores of places thought
demic Press.
. 1985. Cannibalism and burial at Krapina. lournal of Hu- to have been populous in pre-Columbian times are being
man Evolution 14:203-16. identified as having been populous until the widespread
W E N D TW. , E. 1976. "Art mobilier" from the Apollo I I Cave, 16th-century Native American collapse. Thus post-1492
South West Africa: Africa's oldest dated works of art. South Af- Treponema epidemiology among Native Americans is a
rican Archaeological Bulletin 3I: 5-1 I. topic ripe for analysis.
W E T Z E LR., , A N D G . B O S I N S K I . 1969. Die Bocksteinschmiedeim
Lonetal. Veroffentlichungen der Staatlichen Amtes fiir Denk- Williams (CA 29:72) stresses that analysis of hundreds
malpflege Stuttgart, A. of Plains skeletons "has yet to turn up a single case of
W H I T E J. , P., W I T H J. F. O ' C O N N E L L 1982.Aprehistory
. of treponemal infection (Gregg and Gregg I 987)." This
Australia, New Guinea, and Sahul. Sydney: Academic Press. finding points to a second important issue-the extent
W H I T E R, . 1982. Rethinking the MiddleIUpper Paleolithic transi-
tion. CURRENT ANTHROPOLOGY 2:95-I 1 5 . of regional variation in pre-1492 Treponema distribution
. 1985. Thoughts on social relationships in hominid evolu- and its post-1492 predation. The need for regional analy-
tion. Iournal of Social and Personal Relationships 2:95-I 15. sis is apparent from Baker and Armelagos's (pp. 7 I 5 -I 6)

View publication stats

Potrebbero piacerti anche