Sei sulla pagina 1di 19

1969, 12, 329-347

JOURNAL OF THE EXPERIMENTAL ANALYSIS OF BEHAVIOR NUMBER 2 (MARCH)

J. R. KANTOR'S OBJECTIVE PSYCHOLOGY OF GRAMMAR


AND PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC: A RETROSPECTIVE
APPRECIA TION'
W. N. SCHOENFELD
QUEENS COLLEGE OF THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK
AND CORNELL UNIVERSITY MEDICAL COLLEGE

I gists who were dabbling in language around


1935 were doing developmental studies for
Sometimes when the work of a man of schol- the most part, and it was not apparent to them
arship and intellectual daring plunges ahead that Kantor was saying anything helpful along
of the learned community he is addressing, it that line. In the years spanning 1945-1950,
does not immediately receive the honor it most behavior theorists who thought of them-
deserves. Instead, as it blends unmarked into selves as part-time logicians were involved in
the scholarly landscape, it becomes somehow narrow debates on the merits of "hypothetico-
taken for granted. Something like this has deductive" versus "positivistic-inductive" con-
happened to the writings of J. R. Kantor, and ceptions of scientific method, and knew little
I should like, if I can, to reverse this course of philosophy or of logic itself. In consequence,
with respect to his Objective Psychology of Kantor's sheer venturesomeness in dealing
Grammar and his Psychology and Logic. with such broad matters as language, grammar,
While these books are not necessarily the and logic, about which it was felt psychology
most important and enduring of his works, "knew" so little, put some people off. What he
they reveal much of Kantor's creative turn of had -to say on all these topics seemed so con-
mind, and expound well the scientific and tentious, so critical of well-known and eminent
philosophical viewpoints of this remarkable names, so unorthodox in flavor, that it all
man-viewpoints by which theorists in psy- seemed better left alone by prudent minds.
chology have already, though often unwit- Also, his prose style is not easy reading.
tingly, been influenced, and from which they But these reasons, even taken all together,
will be taking increasing instruction in the do not seem to me sufficient to explain the
future. neglect of these books. After all, their broad
Judging from the chronology of his writings, scholarship must have been evident to even
Kantor's direct interest in language and logic the most casual examiner; their author clearly
took a little time to bloom after his doctoral was au courant with the best and latest
dissertation-a long time, if measured against thought in the two fields; he was patently try-
the present accelerating flood of scientific ing, and that eagerly, to get down to specifics
writing: 1935 for the Grammar, and 1945 (Vol. and not just to declaim on a program. I think
I)-1950 (Vol. 2) for the Logic. (He paused the final answer may be found in Kantor's
between 1945 and 1950 to put out his Prob- audience, and not in the man himself. It was
lems of Physiological Psychology, and several our wit that was wanting, not his. We de-
smaller works.) Neither work was widely read, manded too little of ourselves, and expected
at least not by psychologists-rarely have I too much from him.
found a colleague who owns these books, or The contributions a scholar makes to the
who can more than vaguely remember hefting general fund of society's knowledge can take
them in a library somewhere. The reasons for various forms. In science, the accolade is
this cool reception and subsequent disregard usually bestowed on a man who offers his
are not difficult to muster. The few psycholo- colleagues the means for extending his line of
work, who describes or designs a set of practi-
'Reprints may be obtained from W. N. Schoenfeld, cal tools or procedures, who suggests a method
Dept. of Psychology, Queens College of the City Uni- for concrete application. Such a man will,
versity of New York, Flushing, New York 11367. everything else aside, stand out in the scientific
329
330 W. N. SCHOENFELD

community, while one who leaves others to fact that this delayed recognition may save
their own inventive resources will reap neither Kantor from canonization as the founder of
the fame nor the followers that are the re- a "school", a leader of disciples-the fate which
wards of science-in-the-market-place. Kantor's has fallen to some past scientists who unlike
position in psychology is to be seen in this Kantor provided guides for others to follow,
light. He was a breaker of intellectual chains or some ringing terms for them to adopt as a
inherited from the past and a clearer of intel- slogan. That is the way fashions and biases
lectual paths into the future; he could detect originate in science, just as they do in any field,
an incorrect direction, and point the one to since scientists are only men after all. For
take. He was a critic and an analyst; he could Kantor, who has valued only the highest
see what was to be avoided, and what to be intellectual standards, such a role would be
done. He was a summoner to work and an offensive.
architect of ideas; but, while he might hint at A retrospective appreciation at this time of
how something was to be done, he too in- these two books by Kantor may be useful,
frequently went on to do it himself. Readers though it cannot cover their range of scholar-
were cast back on their own resources. Even if ship nor anticipate the verdict of future
they agreed with him, they needed to discover science. For present purposes, it must suffice
for themselves how to implement his thinking to select a few of Kantor's topics that illustrate
in research. Thus, Esper, who was a student of his approach. Respecting those thoughts of my
A. P. Weiss, and in the same philosophical own which fringe this retrospect, at least some
tradition as Kantor, considers that Kantor's could well have been godfathered by Kantor.
efforts are only "programmatic".
Of course, this was hardly likely to convert
Kantor's readers into enthusiastic followers. II. AN OBJECTIVE PSYCHOLOGY
It is more encouraging to be shown, to be OF GRAMMAR
given an apparatus and experimental design, The preface to the Grammar reveals the
to be assured of solid achievement if such and author's spirit as well as his goals: "Grammar,
such were done. Kantor offered little or noth- at least in part, is psychological". His pre-
ing like this. He invented no devices, recorded decessors, however, had concentrated instead
few numbers, drew no graphs, used no statis- on the physiology of speech, or on "psycholo-
tics, programmed no computers, demonstrated gizing linguistic phenomena". A genuine con-
no spectacular animal performances, beguiled tribution by psychology to grammar "has had
with no anecdotes. All this he left to his read- to wait upon the development of an objective
ers. Kantor's work generally had this aspect, psychology. As the following chapters will re-
but it was especially true of his Grammar and veal, traditional psychology, which is sub-
his Logic because of their ambitious scope, and jectivistic, is impotent to handle language
because they did try to speak to specific points. behavior."
At the time of their writing, Kantor's readers This censure of subjectivism is characteristic
were not prepared to pick up where he left off of all Kantor's writings. It is an issue that has
and go ahead on their own. This is still polarized the scientific community outside
difficult today. With our present research psychology (witness Schroedinger and Bridg-
capabilities and intelligence, only a little can man, who have announced for mentalism) and
be done with any confidence. Should we for is still vigorously disputed by some psycholo-
that reason continue to ignore what these gists, although many now agree with Kantor's
books offer us? position. There are also psychologists who,
But perhaps the darkness surrounding Kan- while regarding themselves as behaviorists,
tor is beginning to lift, and we may soon be have not thought through the ramifications of
discovering that he has been a "great" scientist that view, and can be heard sounding like
all along. The historical development of mentalists as often as not.
psychology has already paid him the compli- Kantor proposes two goals: .... analysis of
ment that some of his views are accepted today the psychological character of speech con-
more widely than when he set them down, sidered from the angle of grammatical minu-
though it may not be known that he is their tiae; and, the application of the results to
source. To my mind there is also grace in the grammatical problems." These were extraor-
A RETROSPECTIVE APPRECIATION OF KANTOR 331

dinary goals, unprecedented in their bold- Skinner's later "tact", "mand", "audience
ness. We have still not made much progress variable", and "autoclitic"). "Grammar as the
toward them. Fries' Structure of English (1952) science of speech must be an autonomous
made its effort, but by 1957, when Skinner's science . . . [with its] own unique subject-
Verbal Behavior appeared, matters yet stood matter. This subject-matter is not things, but
largely at the level of shrewd guessing, and the speech adjustments of individuals . .
only a small amount of data was on hand (p. 15). Second, the old affiliation of grammar
about the behavioral properties of speech or of with logic must be severed. "Since Aristotle, at
language generally. On the other hand, Kantor least, language has been regarded as somehow
was of the opinion that "psychological gram- connected with thinking. Every grammarian
mar is in no wise a competitor for the gram- wants to be a logician; he regards himself as an
matical field. In many ways it is a distinct expert upon how to think clearly or at least to
discipline with problems different from those express thought lucidly. In the meantime,
of ordinary grammar. At best, psychological grammar has become something other than
grammar is only one type among several others, adjustmental behavior. . . . This subjectivity
each concerned with different phases of lan- led to the notion that speech had . . . to do
guage. Certainly, psychological grammar can with thought.... Words were considered the
deal most efficiently with the grammar of carriers of meanings . . . grammar became the
speech, and less well, if at all, with the histori- discipline for ordering thoughts" (p. 8). Only
cal or comparative facts of language." This by following the new paths of behavior
willingness to acknowledge the complexity of analysis, Kantor urges, will grammar and
verbal behavior occurs throughout the book. linguistics be able to break the death-grip in
Indeed, he believes any theory of language which they have been held fast for so long by
acquires some "fundamental merit" (p. 225) an "occult psychology" (p. 16).
simply by allowing for such complexity. As Part I then expands some topics that Kantor
for the book's mission, Kantor intends "par- regards as background: classifications and
ticularly that whenever conventional grammar definitions of language forms, historical con-
is criticized it is only in order to pave the way nections between linguistics and psychology,
for constructive suggestions and not to indicate arguments from several quarters against the
mere dissatisfaction". It was in this, of course, psychological analysis of language, psycho-
that Kantor was misunderstood. His readers logical misconceptions in linguistics, speech as
did not see his suggestions as constructive- behavior, the patterning of speech into gram-
they did not see what to do with them-and so mar. Controversial or not, there is no college
the book fell into obscurity. course in language which could not profitably
The Grammar is divided into three parts. assign these chapters as a reading for students.
Part I is historical-critical-methodological. It Part II considers "general grammatical prob-
is vintage Kantor for anyone familiar with the lems", dividing them into the recognized
tenor of the man's lifetime work; but, in 1935, branches of phonology, morphology, syntax,
it must have seemed a bit wild. He digs in at and semantics. Kantor criticizes this division,
once along two veins. First, subjective or men- but is willing to adopt it for expository pur-
talistic or psychic theories of language (speech) poses. Aristotle's theories of behavior are de-
must be abandoned in favor of a functional fended as objective (Kantor is the Aristotelian
analysis of the behavior as part of the orga- among modern psychologists), whereas psycho-
nism's interaction with, and adjustment to, its physical dualism is said to have emerged
environment. Words (and gestures) are "ac- dominant from Hellenistic times, particularly
tions ... performances ... not things or instru- after the Alexandrian conquests which
ments"; the classic "definition or interpreta- brought together Greek and Oriental tradi-
tion of speech as instrumental has resulted in tions. This dualism is traced through the
masking the adjustmental character of speech Middle Ages in Europe, through St. Augustine
behavior" (p. 15). In that interaction with the and Descartes and Weber and Fechner and
environment, three variables need to be recog- Wundt. Kantor detects it in each of the four
nized as the sources of controlling stimuli (pp. branches of grammar, and puts his reader on
14-15): the thing spoken of, the person spoken guard against it. The four branches are then
to, and the behavior of the speaker (compare taken up in the order followed below. Kantor's
332 W. N. SCHOENFELD

plan is "to point out in each chapter the search data on these problems, or suggest ap-
present grammatical status of the problem un- propriate study methods wherewith his read-
der consideration. Then we propose an objec- ers might strike out on their own. Here, where
tive psychological interpretation. By following he is making statements of an increasingly
this plan we hope to contrast the conventional empirical character, is where new methods of
grammarian's emphasis of classification, defini- research would have produced advances in real
tion, and redefinition of supposedly fixed knowledge and would have won Kantor dis-
forms with the psychological conception of ciples. But none is ventured. It is enough
multiplexly determined concrete linguistic or to make a reader feel dull-witted when he
reference adaptations" (p. 112). cannot devise such methods himself; such a
"Semantics" is given a brief treatment, un- feeling leads to defensiveness, and defensive
doubtedly because much of the agitation in readers are unlikely to be admirers. If failure
this field came after 1935. Ogden and Richards is to be apportioned in such a situation, it is
had published their Meaning of Meaning in as much ours as Kantor's.
1927, but Kantor apparently did not feel it "Morphology" is an examination of
necessary to deal extensively with it in his "Words": their definitions, lexicons, deriva-
Grammar since he had already spoken out tions, and subunits. Kantor examines such
on such approaches as early as 1921. In the problems as: the syllable as an abstraction, the
Grammar, therefore, he was content to point creation of linguistic artificialities by morpho-
out simply (p. 36 ff.) what he regarded as the logical analysis, the emergence of speech
fundamental error of Ogden and Richards; "style", the comparison of languages, linguistic
that is, that they are "symbolists" who "reify" evolution, and, finally, how words are derived
words and give them "symbolic and emotive (including their behavioral function). Again
function". As I have written elsewhere, it the chapter is short and provocative, with no
seems to me that, from the behavioral view- practical guides to research.
point, the "meaning" of a word is exhaustively "Phonology" feels the blast of Kantorian
given by two specifications: the conditions un- anger against the analysis of behavior into
der which the speaker utters it, and the re- static categories ("grammarians . . . murder a
sponse it produces in the hearer. I think this living action in order to dissect out of it fixed
is the same sense in which Kantor (and Skin- sounds"-p. 159), against the phoneme (de
ner, too) would understand "meaning", and Saussure's term) as a psychic phenomenon,
for that reason he can deal with "semantic against the "abstracted sound" as symbol
change . . . as changes in vocabulary style" (Sapir, and his predecessors and followers, re-
(p. 125). Because he could dispose of the topic ceive their lumps). It is in this chapter that the
in this way, Kantor's chapter on semantics philological problem is raised of linguistic
could be brief. mutation of the type exemplified by Grimm's
"Syntax" must be freed from the shackles of law. Kantor points out that since Grimm used
logic, and freed also from its traditional charac- literary materials his so-called law really dealt
ter of static linguistic categories. It must deal with letter mutations rather than phonetic
rather with the "dynamic unfolding of verbal changes. Credit is given to earlier writers who
play", and not, as present grammatical syntax saw "the need to study actually produced
does, with "the construction of puzzle pictures sounds instead of letters" (p. 175), but the
(sentences) out of its component parts-a work of Grassmann and Verner, while seen
process involving . . . dead materials" (pp. as a movement in the right direction, is criti-
128-9). Kantor's wide-ranging discussion en- cized as not focusing on the proper sound
compasses such problems as syntactic units, units. When I was a graduate student and had
the psychological or behaviorally functional occasion to reflect on these matters, I was led
sentence, sentences as speech patterning, sen- to suppose that spoken languages are most
tences versus propositions, subject and object, susceptible to historical phonetic changes (a)
the syntax of the hearer, the copula, the verb, where the sounds are given varying pronuncia-
ellipsis. Quarrels over whether or not he is tions, forcing hearers to be discriminatively
correct at any point are not of much use. The most tolerant; (b) where the sounds are diffi-
fact is that although his discussions are wealthy cult to produce, so that speakers tend to
in provocations, Kantor does not offer any re- "drift" in their production of those sounds;
A RETROSPECTIVE APPRECIATION OF KANTOR 333

and, (c) where hearers do not discriminate be- ventional words or gestures, if he refers to
tween certain sounds as well as others, so that, some temporal aspect of an adjustment stimu-
when the hearer takes his turn as speaker, he lus, we may and sometimes must describe his
will be more deviant in approximating those behavior as tense" (p. 248). With respect to
sounds to some standard. Kantor recognized direct and indirect speech, Kantor affirms the
(p. 160) such variability in sound production. existence of "answering reactions" and speech-
My thought was to couple linguistic changes referring speech" (p. 297), a type which
with actual behavioral factors, as opposed to Skinner later termed "autoclitic". The knotty
historical or literary processes. Variability in problem of negation brings back in full force
sound production and reception seemed to for Kantor the dilemmas generated by tying
provide a plausible avenue of inquiry then, grammar to logic, and very near the end of the
and it still seems to me to have some promise. book there is an intimation of a question that
Kantor closes his chapter on phonology with will come up again in Psychology and Logic;
a nod to the new techniques of sound record- namely, the possibility of a logic, and of a
ing, oscillography, and such, which. at the calculus of logic, built upon a different set of
time of his writing were just making their rules than those classically employed, since
presence felt in language study. He saw their those rules need not be taken as absolute. In
possibilities, but worried about their possible this category, while treating "negation as a
misuse in the service of false phonologies. It is psychological phenomenon" Kantor would
at this point that the word "interbehavior", put the law of excluded middle, including its
which was later to figure so large in Kantor's application to the copula "be" itself: "In the
armamentarium, makes an inconspicuous ap- field of speech, even more than in others, we
pearance (it is not listed in the book's index): must take account of the fact that aside from
". . . objective psychology . . . looks upon not the withdrawal from absolutes there are all
only the intrinsic organization of speech, but sorts of possibilities in utterance to be allowed
also its origins and operation, as concrete for. We may therefore refer to a series of
phenomena of linguistic interbehavior" (p. degrees in the non-existence of things spoken
178). of. It is not a question always of yes or no, but
Part III of the book gets down to "particular how much, since speakers may refer to all sorts
grammatical problems", the psychological of contingencies" (p. 309).
analysis of the "grammatical minutiae" prom- In retrospect, the Grammar is a stunning
ised in the Preface. With a daring unknown to book-in what it tried to do, in what it did do,
any predecessor in psychology, Kantor comes in what it foreshadowed, and in what it failed
face to face with topics such as: parts of speech, to do. It was re-issued unchanged in 1952-was
person, gender, case, tense, number, voice, there more for Kantor to say of systematic
mood, direct and indirect speech, and nega- value? One would suppose not, although the
tion. His persistent concerns are to free func- author in his brief preface to the new printing
tional speech's "grammar" from logical cate- regretted that "the pressure of other work"
gories, and to hold fast to a non-mentalistic had not afforded him "a favorable oppor-
analysis. His discussion becomes technical at tunity" to include research in the field done in
times, but it can also stick to common sense. the intervening years. In any case, the Gram-
Thus, in speaking of anomalies of person, he mar is an historic book: what one man dared
sees as "peculiar" the statement of F. Boas to try, others after him were sure to try again
that "a true first person plural is impossible and inevitably with more success. But while
because there can never be more than one the book will grow in historical importance,
self". (I thought of how Kantor might have ex- and in the manner of such books will become
pressed himself on a problem such as the "im- a source of quotations, it is to be hoped that
possibility" of the double possessive, as in the spirit of its author will not be lost in the
the phrase "a friend of mine" [see A. G. process. After all, its sentences are a fossil
Hatcher, Word, 1950, 6, 1-25].) Turning to record (cf p. 29) in print of only some of his
tense, he declares "we must face the facts of verbal behavior, and, even when honored,
tense without time and time without tense" should be remembered as only "abstracted
(p. 242), and concludes that "no matter what details of what [was for him] always a very
(the speaker) says from the standpoint of con- complicated event" (p. 165).
334 W. N. SCHOENFELD

III. PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC "response" are as unsatisfactory starting points


for behavior theory as are absolutistic concepts
The Preface to Psychology and Logic opens of logic for logical theory. This is reminiscent
with the declaration: "Two basic theses of his statement in the Grammar (p. 164) that
underly the present work. The first, the analysis (of speech) must not transform
specificity theorem, signifies that logic is living and ever-changing linguistic responses
essentially concerned with specific events and into fixed structures built up from static
not with universal and transcendent systems. materials". "Interbehavior" has by 1945 be-
The second, the interbehavioral theorem, im- come Kantor's most general term, both
plies that no matter how logic is defined it descriptive and theoretical. It is not, however,
entails a psychological dimension which must an easy one for the reader to come to grips
be taken into account." In expounding these with, so the term did not catch on and did
theses, Kantor notes that "though writers on nothing to promote Kantor's popular image.
logic differ in their views concerning the Re-stated, the notion is basically that of the
nature of logic .. they all agree that they are
. "behavior stream" which is a continuous
seeking the one true and valid system. Rarely function without gaps or "holes" in it. This
is it suggested that no such universal system continuity doctrine-which for Kantor made
is available." Rather, "there are many logics", useless any behavioral formulation employing
and we must recognize "that the referents for static S and R terms-was certainly not new,
the term logic are always individual human and was widely favored in one form or
enterprises located in particular fields or another, but it was not recognized that Kantor
frames of reference". Logicians err in that, was basing his proposed behavior analysis on
"although logic is dbviously a human enter- that idea. This same approach to the descrip-
prise (they) inevitably regard it as ultimate, tion and systematization of behavior may
universal, and transcendent". This happens soon be receiving new attention, with some
because, "behind the unsatisfactory assump- workers trying to deal with the stream experi-
tions that logic is infallible, comprehensive, mentally.
and transcendent unquestionably lies unsound The Preface anticipates, and the text fully
psychological theory". displays, Kantor's foundation approach to his
From the outset then, the book promises to subject. It is typically Aristotelian, utilizing
be an exciting one, and it is. The flavor is even an historico-critical summary and analysis as
more strongly Kantorian than that of the its starting point. This method is always en-
Grammar, and more didactic and polemic. lightening, often profoundly so. In psychology,
The vastness of the undertaking, as well as where it is often most needed, Kantor is one
Kantor's intellectual daring, are seen partly of its most skillful exploiters (and has given
in the range of things named in the chapter us a fine example of its use in the first volume
titles and sub-divisions. The author's acquaint- of his recent History of Psychology), but it is
ance with the literature of the area is clear equally profitable in diverse fields in the
from the bibliography, and his grasp of it hands of such skilled practitioners as E. Mach
from the textual uses he puts it to. Interest- and V. I. Lenin. But the vibrant methods of
ingly, the term "interbehavior" has now come the Logic, like those of the Grammar, have not
to the forefront of Kantor's psychological made their proper impression on either
vocabulary. It will serve henceforth as both psychologists or logicians or philosophers of
noun and adjective, and on occasion even as science. As with the Grammar, this book does
adverb, since in Kantor's hands (as they were not offer concrete suggestions or follow-up
in Woodworth's) all psychological nouns are methods to lead the reader on to research work
really action words. In all of its uses, how- of his own. He is left once again with a "where-
ever, the term carries the single Kantorian do-I-go-from-here" feeling. Again the upshot
theme that the behavior of an organism is in has been that Kantor's thinking is judged to
continuous interaction (through feedback be non-productive, when it is rather our own
loops, as contemporary fashionable termin- which has been unresourceful.
ology might have it) with the products of its The exposition of "specificity logic" begins
own behavior and with the environment; as a with an explicit statement of eight postulates.
consequence static concepts of "stimulus" and I should add at once, however, that "postulate"
A RETROSPECTIVE APPRECIATION OF KANTOR 335
here has a different sense from the one usually contemporary beliefs among behavior theo-
understood by psychologists who take Hull as rists about scientific method generally involve
their example of deductive or constructional the very deductive-absolutistic ideas about
system builders. That Kantor's sense is differ- logic and the calculus of propositions that
ent should not, of course, be surprising to Kantor rejects, his position has here also not
readers who recall his view of the interbe- been one which might have added to his
havioral nature of verbal propositions. Thus, popularity over the last several decades.
he says at the opening of Chapter 1: "Of recent It is, of course, not possible to comment
methodological and expository developments here on all the problems and topics that
in logic and science nothing surpasses in merit Kantor treats in the two volumes of Psychology
the increasing practice of setting up postulate and Logic following his statement of his
systems." But the fact that his meaning of postulates. What is feasible is to select a few
''postulate" is other than the usual one is matters which are perhaps of more immediate
plain throughout the book where logical and interest to psychologists today, as well as of
scientific "constructions" (read inventions, some personal interest to me.
fictions, or purely formal elaborations) are
rejected as not profitable. 1. Logic and Language
The eight postulates are: (1) Logic is opera- As was said repeatedly in the Grammar,
tional; (2) Logical theory is continuous with language and logic are closely tied together,
practice; (3) Logical operations constitute but not because the study of language means
interbehavioral fields; (4) Logical interbe- the study of logical propositions or logical
havior constitutes system building; (5) Logical categories, and not because logic determines
interbehavior is specific; (6) Logic is uniquely grammatical units or categories. Rather, logic
related to culture; (7) Logic is inseverably is a set of propositions couched in a construc-
interrelated with psychology; (8) Logic is dis- tional language system (cf Grammar, p. 319).
tinct from language. From these eight proposi- Since language and grammar are inter-
tions, the rest of the book is believed to flow. behavioral, logic in turn becomes behavioral
They are summarized in a thematic statement in two senses. First, to understand either
with which Chapter 1 closes: "Logic is neither classical or modern logical systems as the end-
science nor the theory of inquiry or investiga- products of reacting human organisms, the
tion." This is an amusingly instructive counter- language behavior, training, and context
view to that of such classic deductively minded established in the logician by his social en-
logicians (or as Kantor might say, non- vironment must be known, since he necessarily
interbehavioral, absolutistic logicians) as draws upon those for his thought, his proposi-
Cohen and Nagel who had earlier (1934) tions, and his system. Kantor believes that
emerged from their attack on J. S. Mill's even Aristotle saw this and commented upon
canons of experimental inquiry with the con- it. Second, the interaction between the prac-
clusion that "the experimental methods (of titioner of science (or of logic, or of any verbal
Mill) are neither methods of proof nor play) and his environment is determined by
methods of discovery". Kantor goes on: "The the actual conditions under which he is oper-
notion that logic discovers and applies rules ating and by the data he is in process of
for scientific work is objectionable on at least obtaining; since this interaction or interplay
two grounds. First, such a view is based upon is the "logic" we wish to understand, we can
the idea that system and order, in other do so only by understanding the interactional
words, abstractions and rules, are more behavior itself.
important than the materials and actual What a language can say, as distinct from
investigations. Actually contacts with events what can be done with what it says, can con-
may require new and as yet completely un- fuse the preoccupations of a logician who fails
known techniques. Secondly, the particular to keep the sentence itself separate from its
processes of investigation with their errors and alleged referent. Thus, English can take any
mis-steps are minimized. This view is also sentence and insert a negative somewhere in
fatally reminiscent of formalistic and deduc- it (or re-state it in negative form), but doing
tive ideas of science. There is a science of this does not, of course, create an existential
logic as well as a logic of science" (p. 19). Since or even meaningful referent for the new
336 W. N. SCHOENFELD

sentence-how many conundrums about non- standing that has broadened in recent times
existing things or non-things have devoured into an issue regarding scientific method. As a
how many Russellian philosopher-man-hours purely formal logical question, deductive pro-
in their imaginary solutions! Again, Indo- cedures and inductive procedures have been
European languages, and the several systems set against each other with respect to validity
of mathematics which can be based on them, of inference. Each is said to have its character-
permit repetitive statements to be made; this istic weakness, though that of induction is the
allows for repetitive operations, such as more widely recognized today because the fash-
division, but also, where the actual referent is ionableness of deduction has caused its diffi-
lost sight of and a different referent is invoked, culty to be blinked. Both before and since its
permits us to be seized by Zeno-esque para- Baconian resurgence, induction has been
doxes, and by. uncertainties as to what is regarded as flawed by the necessity of "leap-
"meant" and how something "can be". Or, ing" from particular to universal propositions.
again (if I may echo C. D. Broad), the copulas For its part, deduction is said to be flawed by
in classical syllogistic premises are indefinite its "petitio principii" character. If each of
about the temporal duration of properties in these flaws is fatal, a submissive scientist might
the predicates assigned to subjects, as if, when truly be in a quandary over whether to con-
we apply the syllogisms to things in the real tinue his research or wait for the logicians to
world, we can ignore time, abstracting the find an anodyne for their headache. Our
"existence" of a thing without considering university courses in behavior theory usually
time as a critical aspect of existence. Our present the deduction versus induction issue
language also permits us in several ways (e.g., in the inescapable lecture on the nature of
by gerundive, or by substituting the article "scientific method" and of "scientific theory".
"the" for the "to" of infinitives) to make verbs That nature is a matter of inquiry, not of
(actions) into nouns. This creates many traps dogma. Contemporary fashion favors the
for scientific thinking in our culture (more, it "hypothethico-deductive" or "constructional"
would seem than making nouns into verbs!). dogma of method and theory, but such fash-
As A. J. Ayer has remarked in another con- ions in science are substitutes for facts, and
nection, "The mere existence of the noun (he flourish where facts are few. This was not
was talking about "god") is enough to foster always the prevailing view (we might recall
the illusion that there is a real . . . entity here Duhem's discussion of styles of theory),
corresponding to it". If these and other nor do I believe that in any concrete scientific
linguistic restrictions and liberties were differ- research situation the dogmatic distinction
ent, how different might our thinking and our between the two is defensible.
logic be. And, if no single representative In any case, debates and polemics about
system of formalized language structures is "scientific method" and "scientific theory",
"correct", if logical systems can be changed both in psychological literature and the class-
simply by altering the initial axioms and room, fail to distinguish between what the
formal rules of language, then no scientist writer or speaker thinks scientific method is,
need apologize for his genuine interactions or what he thinks it should be, between what
with the outside real world, no matter what scientific theory is, or what it should be. In
protest may be raised by the partisans of brief, what is the scientist doing, and what is
special logics. For the scientist, logic must it thought that he should be doing? The
accommodate to science, and not science to former is an empirical question, and it will
logic, just as theory must give ground to fact, take facts to settle it. But, indeed, there is very
and not fact to theory. Kantor was surely right little hard information on the matter. The
in emphasizing this (his examples were differ- usual descriptions, and the oft-used historical
ent from mine), though it is a difficult point to examples, are to my mind ill-drawn reconstruc-
express and can, if one lowers one's guard, tions of what actually happens in the scientist's
reduce to metaphysical quibblings. behavior when he is "making science". They
represent only fashionable misconceptions
2. Deduction and Induction projected onto presumed but defenseless
Psychologists have here inherited, and exemplars (the use of dead scientists as be-
carelessly entered into, an issue of classical havior material recalls Kantor's lament, in the
A RETROSPECTIVE APPRECIATION OF KANTOR 337

Grammar, p. 17, over the use of "lifeless forms" ness of science. This may perhaps satisfy some
of language that are studied in grammatical logicians, but it will not satisfy the true sci-
treatises). The second question-what scientific entist, nor does it Kantor. Those same logi-
method or theory should be-could have an cians, moreover, would not abide matching
indefinitely large number of answers (not one the same argument for the defense of induc-
of them moral) depending upon whether the tion; that is, that the invalidity alleged of the
purpose of the method or the theory is leap is irrelevant, and the allegation ad homi-
aesthetic, practical, didactic, systematic, ex- nem, and that only the final correctness of
ploratory, parsimonious, or whatever. More- the leap is important.
over, to judge how efficiently a given method In truth, of course, the supposed opposi-
or theory meets the criterion of what it should tion of deduction and induction cannot be
be, would require some means of measuring found in the actual living work of scientists.
or evaluating or estimating that efficiency. They not only reduce to a single process in
This is a far cry from how the matter is usually practice, but can be so reduced in verbal de-
portrayed in the debates and classroom lectures scription as well. I mean more by this than
of psychologists. that, as some logicians and philosophers have
Current emphasis upon deductive elabora- held, there is no difference between induction
tions in psychology proceeds from the comfort- and deduction because the former is reducible
ing, but I think mistaken, belief that the to the latter. What I mean is that the latter
physical sciences owe their modern pragmatic is also reducible to the former if one wishes to
successes to their constructional theoretical proceed in that direction. In short, the mutual
systems. Our students are taught that a theory reducibility means identity ab initio and
begins with postulates or axioms that are strictu sensu. Starting from particulars, the
unchallengeable; that these propositions con- inductive universal proposition can be formed
tain terms that need no definition; that deduc- without any delay regarding "validity", either
tions (often claimed to be reducible to the as a mechanical linguistic exercise, or because
classical syllogistic moods) are made within the human scientist, like other animals we are
the self-contained system of propositions; that acquainted with, is subject to some gradients
these deductions are then tested in the labora- of generalization. This universal, once formed,
tory or field; and finally that if the empirical is in no way different functionally from an
findings make it necessary, the propositions assumption or axiom or postulate which is also
anterior to the empirical test are altered to stated in universal form. Once formed, the in-
conform with, and to generate, the new find- ductive universal may be "tested" to see
ing, but that otherwise congruent empirical whether it is applicable to any desired situa-
findings may be declared to be "consistent tion or variable; if the test is failed, an appro-
with", though not to "prove", the system as it priate qualification may be attached to modify
stands thus far. This sequence of practice is the range of the universal proposition, or to
said to be beyond the power and legitimate reduce the breadth of the class (in the manner
scope of inductive procedures or inquiry. The of Newton's Rule IV); but the residual propo-
latter are said to be simply incapable of ration- sition remains in universal form, and does so
alizing the practice because they force an no matter how many qualifications may be in-
inductive leap from particulars to universals. dexed to it. For what is not as yet on the list
What is not often pointed out is the com- of exceptions, the proposition is treated as
panion difficulty of deductive practice when universally applicable.
it is described this way, namely, to say where It is, in point of fact, because the inductive
the axioms or postulates come from in the generalization is universal in linguistic form,
first place. To reject this question as irrelevant just as the postulate is, that "tests" of it are
or ad hominem, and to argue that only the possible. It is not the form of the proposition
ultimate correctness of the postulates is of that is at issue, but how the proposition has
interest, is to deny that human behavior is been arrived at. The inductive generalization
involved. It puts the origin of postulates into openly declares itself to be based on previ-
the sphere of disembodied whimsicality and ously ascertained facts, even if particular ones.
mentalism, and thereby makes it impossible to But where does the postulate come from? It is
instruct anyone in how to go about the busi- plain silly to imagine any rational scientist
338 W. N. SCHOENFELD

actually doing what some have claimed he and to add new knowledge to old, then the
does or should do, or what he is praised for alleged opposition between deductive and in-
doing as a "deductivist-constructionist"; that ductive methods in science disappears. Postu-
is, close his eyes and reach into a grab bag of lates in a deductive system and inductive uni-
possible postulates, come up with whatever versals are generated in the same way and
ones he chances upon, explore their logical operate in the same way in the scientific be-
consequences, put those consequences to ex- havior of scientists. Kantor's own treatment of
perimental test, and then, if necessary, revise the induction-deduction issue involves, typi-
those postulates or go back to the grab bag cally, a rejection of all attempts at solutions
for others. Such a view of scientific method based on logical absolutes. He makes the
anyone can have who wishes it, but both Kan- problem one of specific behavioral conditions
tor and I would beg to be excused. That posi- and outcomes instead of dispelling the alleged
tion, literally irnterpreted, not only removes logical incongruity between the two. "No am-
the choice of postulates from connection with biguity attaches to universals in interbehav-
established knowledge, but it gives the fool ioral logic. Universals are products of system-
equal rights with the scientist in the choice; building operations, but they are something
it means that we yield any hope of acquiring more than end points in the operational pro-
new knowledge, since the chances of pulling cedure; in addition they constitute the raw
a "good" postulate are vanishingly small be- materials of further system-building opera-
cause the contents of the grab bag are infinite tions. This characteristic, it should be noted,
in number; it means that even "good" postu- universals share with relations, classes, kinds
lates, being sentences of finite length, are or species, mathematical functions, and other
doomed to be wrong when endlessly tested constructional forms" (Vol. 2, p. 131). "It is
against an infinite world; it means that our encouraging that (some) philosophers . . .
purpose becomes one of proving propositions suggest abandoning the inductive problem.
right or wrong, rather than of learning some- But something more than logical policy is
thing about the world; and so on. Into blind called for. We must take into account the spe-
alleys of this sort are we led by a defense of cific system-building enterprise. Whether or
the disembodied origin of the postulate. This not the procedure is inductive or deductive
remoteness of origins and sources, their di- depends upon the kind of materials used"
vorce from actual human behavior, is intended (Vol. 2, p. 332).
to give postulates unassailable rational status.
But the intention does not square with reason, 3. Cause and Effect
nor will it succeed in practice. It has been Kantor's discussion of causality should be
said that such views of a postulate only result an attention-catcher for psychologists whose
in reducing it to the level of a "guess" (we science is still half-immersed in pre-natural-
ought to recall here Russell's amusingly con- istic thinking wherein spontaneity and volun-
trapuntal charge that inductions are merely tarism continue to be treated as behavior
plausible guesses from which deduction can sources. Language forms and traditions of
proceedl), and that nothing is gained by usage are among the reasons for the slowness
changing the name of guess to "assumption", with which such "causes" are perpetuated and
"axiom", "prediction", or "postulate". Not to not recognized for what they are: ". . . com-
be dismissed in this way are the questions of merce with mythical subject matter (which)
who is guessing how at what and why. In such is possible by means of linguistic factors. It is
a guessing game, we are as individual scien- possible to construct real existence, systemic
tists naturally concerned with who is the bet- existence, possibilities, and determiners of all
ter "guesser", for he is the better scientist sorts without adequately analyzing acts and
from whom we wish to learn. We may be con- stimulus objects" (Vol. 2, p. 165). Moreover:
fident that he will have more than chance "Everyone who approaches causality from the
guessing to teach us. angle of events must be impressed by the vari-
If, then, a "postulate" emerges from present ety of causal situations.... Conventional doc-
knowledge, just as an inductive generaliza- trine projects the general presupposition that
tion does, and if scientific inquiry is viewed causality constitutes a basic law of nature or
as trying to base itself on present knowledge of science. The assumption is made . . . that
A RETROSPECTIVE APPRECIATION OF KANTOR 339
the universe is constructed on a plan of neces- idea that temporally remote causes can oper-
sary connection. . . . Once more we see ex- ate on present behavior. The latter insist that
hibited the enormous hold of abstractionism it is the present constitution of the organism
and generality on logical thought, as well as which is interacting with presently impinging
on the analysis of science. The result for variables, although reinforcement history may
causal study is such a vaporization of events be the origin at any temporal instant of pres-
as to allow anything to be said about them. ent constitution; causal correlations based on
In such a vacuous causal universe it may be action-at-a-distance are not taken as immedi-
asserted that 'Whatever is, may not be', 'Not ately determinative, and physical contiguity
everything that could happen does happen', of causes and effects is demanded instead.
'The contrary of every matter of fact is still Somewhat the same attitude is exemplified by
possible'. The universalistic claim that the physiological psychologists who, in the cur-
world is a system of necessary connections- rently popular research on "memory", are
namely, 'every effect must have a cause'-is seeking the "engram" in the nervous system.
not condemned by us merely because it is a (It is also an interesting example of the power
vain apothegm. Not at all. The gravamen lies of historical and cultural tradition that they
in assuming that such an assertion is factually do not consider that the engram, or some com-
significant" (Vol. 2, p. 152). ponent of it, may be found elsewhere in the
Kantor's discussion of causality is wide- body, although Kantor was not afraid, as far
ranging, beginning with a survey of the his- back as 1947 in his Physiological Psychology,
torical roots of the idea and coming up to to discard dogmatism about the brain and the
modern writers. A psychologist interested in nervous system generally as the "locus of psy-
the conceptual problem of causality (includ- chological processes"-p. 80.)
ing Piaget's developmental approach to how (b) One aspect of the causation problem
this concept is met in the thinking of a child raised repeatedly by Kantor throughout his
in Western culture), will find a good many Chapter XIX is stated in several ways: "Logi-
places where his own reflections might pause. cians have increasingly inclined toward formu-
Some examples of where I did: lating and transforming propositions (sen-
(a) The familiar Hobbesian view of motion, tences) and away from observations concerned
"There can be no cause of motion, except in with particular existential occurrences. The
a body contiguous and moved" (Vol. 2, p. 151), latter are even spurned as experiential and
raises the problem of action-at-a-distance. In intuitive.... In such a methodological treatise
the history of the science of mechanics can be as Dewey's Logic, the adjective logical, em-
traced the classic conflict between scientists, ployed to qualify the cause category, removes
and between theories of motion, taking op- cause from the domain of existence and actual
posed views as to whether action-at-a-distance things and places it among the constructs....
is possible or not, and whether it is a proper We suggest that the fault of contemporary
basis for theory. Those physicists who accept theories of causation lies . . . in their depar-
the idea that a satisfactory causal theory of ture from objective happenings. . . At the
motion can tolerate distance without con- basis of illegitimate interpretations of causa-
tiguity of bodies believe, in Kantor's words, tion is the absolutistic logical tradition" (Vol.
that "causal events as data consist of particu- 2, p. 147). One is reminded how F. Engels
lar interrelationships of observed happenings" could argue, against certain of his contem-
(the reader may recall Skinner's 1931 defini- poraries, that an electric storage battery must
tion of a reflex as an observed correlation of be functioning in a certain way, and could
stimulus and response). Other physicists (like unerringly call for attention to be focused on
Fourier in his analytical theory of heat, and local physical events occurring on the surfaces
Kelvin and Maxwell in their accounts of of plates, rather than on fanciful invented
electro-magnetic phenomena) are more com- processes presumed to be going on at some site
fortable conceptually with the requirement where there might dwell "causes" that have a
that action be contiguous. In psychology, a lease properly attested by logic. Of course,
related issue has some theorists holding that Engels had to be correct-and therefrom we
"reinforcement history" is a satisfactory causal can draw the lesson that in science sometimes
category; others (like K. Lewin) oppose the the correct analysis of a problem, leading to a
340 W. N. SCHOENFELD
proper identification of where to look and determiners of behavior which is also real.
what to look for, need not depend on expertise Accounts of causality that deny or neglect such
in subject matter or adroitness in logic, but facts in favor of what Kantor calls metaphysi-
can be made by an outsider reasoning along cal or mystical interpretations of causality
proper lines. Engel's performance in sticking cannot fail to be incomplete and misleading.
to specific and present real variables is still an- The sponsors of such accounts exhibit a form
other aspect of a scientific principle not unre- of what Goudge once called "the spectator
lated to Morgan's canon, familiar to all psy- fallacy" of questioning the existence of a real
chologists, which was itself both a re-statement world.
of older maxims (such as Ockham's and New- (d) In some fiery phrases, Kantor excoriates
ton's Rule I) and a forerunner of Russell's the conclusion that the principle of inde-
later "supreme maxim in scientific philosophis- terminism in quantum mechanics somehow
ing . . . (namely), wherever possible, substi- nullifies or compromises causality and the
tute constructions out of known entities for in- predictability of physical events. I recall my
ferences to unknown entities" (Vol. 2, p. 164). own participation at Columbia just a few years
(c) Cause as a dependable relation in time ago in the doctoral examination of a student
(Kantor cites as examples "Hume's constant in philosophy whose dissertation was con-
conjunction, Kant's irreversible succession, cerned with the problem of determinism. He
and Mill's uniform and unconditional se- became much involved with Heisenberg's prin-
quence"; to these we may add Aquinas' "effi- ciple, worrying the concept and discussing it
cient" cause which must precede its effect) is from numerous angles, apparently feeling that
sometimes discussed today as "conditional it might somehow drag scientific determinism
probability", though such verbal substitutions into question. I asked him to consider what
do not solve the classical problems of logic the principle might mean in the daily life
and philosophy regarding causality, including and work of a practicing scientist like myself
worry over the fallacy of post hoc ergo propter or like the physical chemist who was the only
hoc. Kantor's view is that "Causal theory other natural scientist on the examining com-
originates directly from a cultural matrix ... mittee. I wondered aloud about whether and
(during) cultural evolution cause became in what way he thought the principle in-
transformed into a series of conditions requi- truded into what I or the chemist actually
site for explaining observed events. Causes did. My effort to get this young and intelligent
were accordingly regarded as rules of order philosopher to explain what he thought was
and regularity, or as laws describing, or refer- "indeterminate", and in what sense indetermi-
ring to, events. This type of construction had nate, other than as a practical problem of
its peak development when cause was finally measurement, did not get far. He was smitten
conjoined with problems of predicting and with the "elegance" of a "theory" from which
controlling future happenings" (Vol. 2, p. a principle like Heisenberg's could be derived
149). His own position is that "causal knowl- and found to "accord with" experimental ob-
edge (is) knowledge of the pattern of events" servations. I pictured for his imagination a
(Vol. 2, p. 174), that (reminiscent of K. Pear- scientist rising in the morning, having break-
son's Grammar of Science) ". . . causal investi- fast, kissing his wife and leaving for his labora-
gation involves ... the problem 'how' an event tory or office, getting to work on his current
occurs-namely, how the constituent factors problem, and suddenly exclaiming in despair,
of things, their properties and conditions, are "Well, I guess it's indeterminate-I might as
organized in an event situation" (Vol. 2, p. well give up!", and going off to play golf or
156), and that "Causal changes in any field to kiss his wife again. The philosophers
constitute a rearrangement in the simulta- around the table smiled indulgently, plainly
neous coexistence of factors in a unique pat- regarding me as naive, and as not having
tern" (Vol. 2, p. 157). Of course, the human be- grasped the issue. But while I had missed my
ing, scientist or not, who experiences the mark with them, the chemist, I thought, con-
dependable event sequences he calls causal tentedly endorsed my picture and my question.
chains, will come to base his behavior on them; At the close of the examination, he went off
that is, to "believe" them. These real sequences, sadly shaking his head. Kantor would have
occurring in a real physical world, become been amused.
A RETROSPECTIVE APPRECIATION OF KANTOR 341

(e) Scientists get caught up in the problem are metaphysical and divorced from the reali-
of cause-and-effect via such statements as "simi- ties of the events being observed. As support
lar causes have similar effects" (Newton's Rule for him, one can think of half a dozen or more
II was such a statement), and "order is the reasons why those "causes" are not having
essence of nature". A related problem in the "effects" in our specific experimental situation
history of philosophy is reflected in the propo- and with our specific procedures. If it be ar-
sition that "like produces only like" (perhaps gued, as it has been across history, that all
reminiscent of genetics); this latter idea, at those reasons assume the very thing that is
least as far back as Ibn Gabirol, led in turn to being questioned, namely, that different causes
the idea that, when two or more different sub- should and do have different effects, then it
stances have some similar properties, the simi- can be countered that one can never know
larities must stem from common elements or that, and so the arguments would fly. Kantor's
substrata which are their "cause", while the tack would be to cut through these arguments
differences stem from differentiating elements by asking what they have to do with the reali-
or principles. Kantor's reaction is predictable. ties of the scientific situation, with what the
"Generalized causal systems on the formal ... scientist is doing and what he is finding ob-
level are built primarily out of words.... jectively.
Formal systems . . . in some cases are com-
pletely removed from things. Since word or 4. Evidence
symbol systems have no referents, the systems Although he does not discuss "evidence" or
themselves constitute the only things in the "proof" under those special headings, these
situation. When concrete things are- forcibly categories frequently crop up in Kantor's
dragged in to illustrate the systems, they are treatment of grammar and logic. "Science"
clearly only descriptive analogies to actual ob- grows out of interaction with (read "knowl-
jects and events" (Vol. 2, p. 170). "Logical edge of") the environment; "evidence" grows
necessity and causation are close to classical out of that same interaction, but also out of
metaphysics. . . . Certainly logical necessity is the scientist's interaction with (read "formula-
remote from any causal system of concrete tions of") his accumulated and coded previous
happenings. It has nothing to do with such interactions. Both "science" and "evidence"
factual necessity as providing oxygen for are abstractions from these continuous inter-
stratospheric flying or an adequate diet to active processes. Neither, however, is to be
maintain growth. The domain of formal logic regarded as the handmaiden of absolutistic
allows for such mystic ideas as a deterministic doctrines of logic. What science and evidence
or indeterministic universe, a causal or an try to do, but logic alone can never do, to
acausal cosmos. . . . Formal logic comprises, paraphrase Samuel Johnson on the value of
in fact, a stock of sentences containing the foreign travel, is to regulate imagination by
word cause-sentences which have no connec- reality, and instead of thinking how things
tion with the interrelations of things, their may be, to see them as they are.
properties, and relations in concrete event Science is sometimes said to look for "ex-
systems.... Causal events are clearly different planations" of phenomena, but it is now well
from the constructional systems connected understood that there are many varieties and
with them" (Vol. 2, pp. 154-155). levels of "explanation". Assignment to generic
Unless he unremittingly attends to the disci- classes, the uncovering of ontology or etiology,
pline of his thought, the problem of causality the correlation with a criterion ("validity",
intrudes into the work of the experimental in the lexicon of psychological testing), the
scientist. Suppose that, having applied some discovery of properties, the plotting of func-
independent variable to his material, he finds tional relations, all these and still other sub-
that it has had no effect at all, or no different sumptive procedures are all varieties of "ex-
effect at one value of the variable than at an- planation". Sometimes, though unnecessarily,
other. How can this be-causes without effects? one or another of these varieties is asserted to
Some scientists cannot resist the feeling that be a "higher" or a "lower" level of explana-
there are effects, but that we may simply not tion, and pari passu is thought to bestow a
have fine enough instruments to measure them higher or a lower level of "understanding".
yet. To Kantor, such questions and answers But "understanding" is a term that needs
342 W. N. SCHOENFELD

some analysis itself, perhaps along the lines such questions can be instructive. One thing
(a) that it represents a behavioral interaction to be learned is that a bad idea cannot be
with either objects in the environment, or clarified-indeed, that is why it is "bad".
with the verbal formulations of those objects, Within a Kantorian frame of reference,
and, (b) that the behavior called "understand- such problems and difficulties are seen in the
ing" may or may not be verbalizable in whole perspective of other contingent questions:
or in part by the "understander". It follows what does the scientific questioner (or any
that there are many kinds of "understanding", other) want to know, and what answer will
both in and out of science. The topics of evi- satisfy him? to what degree is a question to be
dence, explanation, and understanding come clarified before we try to answer it? clarified by
together under the single category of "belief", whom? at what stage of history? Because he
to which I will return. would argue that there is no absolute or fixed
What is less readily agreed upon by con- scale by which to judge the fitness of a ques-
temporary scientists, including psychologists, tion to be asked, Kantor gives his reader no
is the distinction between facts and fictions, epistemological anchor from which he can
between data and constructs, between things derive a measure of intellectual security. But
and models, between things and their measure- if he is correct-and his viewpoint, so far as
ments, between the "phenomena" and "hy- we can tell, still seems defensible-then he does
potheses" of Newton when he wrote: "Hith- teach us something of the nature of the prob-
erto I have not been able to discover the cause lem, and something about how to live with
of those properties of gravity from phenomena, it in science.
and I frame no hypotheses; for whatever is As for the "evidence" which can be brought
not deduced from the phenomena is to be to any question, it must be acknowledged
called an hypothesis; and hypotheses, whether again that it can be of different kinds and put
metaphysical or physical, whether of occult to different uses. It will not do to say that evi-
qualities or mechanical, have no place in ex- dence consists of "facts". Not only are facts
perimental philosophy". From the failure to of multiple natures and properties, but the
make such distinctions comes also the confu- long-standing precept is recalled that a fact is
sions regarding prediction and discovery in only a fact within some system. As Lakatos
science, between prediction and control, be- has tried to show, even ideas about proof, and
tween tests of relations among facts and processes of proving, have undergone develop-
among fictions, between things and analogues. mental changes in the history of the sciences
On problems like these, any psychologist, and mathematics. Nor will it suffice to say that
whatever his viewpoint, can read Kantor with evidence must be "logical" or valid; Kantor
profit as well as pleasure. again presses the admonition that we ought
The problem of evidence, in science and to avoid the ". . . fallacy that logic is some sort
out, is inseparable from the question on which of infallible process invariably attaining . . .
evidence is sought. Scientists are certainly well truth" (Vol. 1, p. 339). Besides, modern devel-
aware of the importance of a question's form opments in logic and mathematics-if the two
and specificity. A question that is not prop- can be distinguished-show how many logical
erly asked cannot be answered, or to say it systems are possible, and thus raise the prob-
otherwise, the way a question is put will de- lem in any specific case of just which logic
termine how it can be, let alone how it will ought be used since there are now many to
be, answered. To tell whether a question is choose from. Kantor hailed these develop-
"properly asked", we may need to know what ments, and the demonstration of multiple
the purpose of the asker is, what the concept possible structurings of logic, as healthful for
imbedded in the question is, whether any science. He tried to show how they could be
evidential answer at all is possible, and so on. incorporated into the attitudes of a scientist
Psychological questions are often so broad as so as to lift old dilemmas from his shoulders
to preclude a useful answer within the scope and to free him for his work.
of present knowledge; or, they contain latent Evidence and proof are not absolute, then,
ideas or implicit definitions of terms which but are related to the question they are ad-
the questioner himself may not understand or dressed to, how they are gathered, and so on.
even agree with. Even to attempt to clarify These characteristics of evidence hold in all
A RETROSPECTIVE APPRECIATION OF KANTOR 343

theaters of human life, in law as well as in Historically, the problem of evidence has
science, in everyday affairs as well as in the been closely linked with the syllogism. It has
laboratory. Our jury system has evolved out been held that this Aristotelian invention pro-
of problems of indictment and evidence; its vides the model for reasoning, for inference,
successes in the administration of "correct" for evidence, and for proof. The valid syllo-
justice have occasionally produced the sugges- gistic moods were enshrined, and every stu-
tion in science that the consensus of opinion dent was warned against the invalid ones, as
confers meaning and credibility upon facts, well as against some related "errors of
measures and theories. But such a carryover, thought" such as affirmation of the consequent.
Kantor would surely say, is unfortunate and But several things cloud this picture, as we
serves little constructive purpose. A somewhat realize. Undistributed middles may be anath-
opposite and newly emergent trend (which ema to the syllogist, but hardly to the poet
Kantor would resist, vide Vol. 1, p. 154), show- (for whom "John is a lion" is a useful blend
ing how persistently the old problems of sub- of John's and a lion's courage) or even to the
jectivism and introspectionism can lurk in the scientist (who will take correlation as evi-
wings of psychological history, is the agree- dence). As J. Guttmann pointed out, in phi-
ment of some psycholQgists with the existence losophy what is a metaphor to one philosopher
of "public vs. private" events (read public vs. may be a reality to another. Even prominent
private stimuli and responses), thereby admit- scientists will illegally convert propositions,
ting the possibility of public vs. private evi- confuse sufficiency and necessity, and affirm
dence. consequents (thus one hears statements, with
Because evidence is never absolute, it is possibly a hint of apology in the inflection of
never perfect. To some, this means that proba- the voice, such as: color-seeing animals have
bility and statistics must come upon the stage such-and-such a receptor system, this animal
as the bases of evidence; even more radically, does not have a system like that, therefore this
and perhaps inevitably, some have even come animal does not, or probably does not, see
to think that "truth is a form of probability" color): If it be protested that in these instances
(Vol. 2, p. 208). Thus, Peirce believed: even the offenders really know what they are
saying, and will admit the error if pressed,
All positive reasoning is of the nature of still they do it; they proceed on such bases in
judging the proportion of something in a their work, and in these ways do they get ideas
whole collection by the proportion found in and postulates for their theories. What more
a sample. Accordingly, there are three things evidence would one wish for the importance
to which we can never hope to attain by rea- of such processes than that they exist and func-
soning, namely, absolute certainty, absolute tion in living scientists, often profitably for
exactitude, absolute universality. their work, despite the prohibitions of abstract
logic? These possibilities Kantor never found
The great modern developments in probabil- surprising. He found place for them in his
ity theory, including Bayesian prediction, have insistence on the multi-faceted nature of be-
produced in philosophy and logic some intel- havior, or "interbehavior", which he opposed
lectual indigestion, and some of the fuzziest to rigid classificatory systems: "In specific in-
scientific thinking of our day is to be en- stances nonlogical thinking may be much more
countered here. In psychology there is great valid than thinking accepted in logical situa-
reliance on statistics, a reliance unfortunately tions" (Vol. 1, p. 177).
attendled by confusion about how experiments
ought to be designed, how evidence is to be 5. Belief
evaluated, how conclusions are to be drawn, Discussions of. evidence, and indeed of all
the meanings of "significance" and their rela- the foregoing topics, merge finally into discus-
tion to inverse probability, the relative places sion of "belief". Thus, it may be said, the
of statistical control and experimental repli- purpose of evidence is to convince, and evi-
cation. For the pains of this bewilderment, dence is that which convinces. But conviction
an acquaintance with Kantor's thought- does not lie or inhere in facts or logic. Rather,
which was ahead of his time in psychology- conviction is behavioral. Conviction is a prop-
may provide some relief. erty of the observer whose characteristics are
344 W. N. SCHOENFELD

as much to be considered as any "evidence", derided-each comes from experience and is


since what it takes to convince one man will based on some type of "knowledge". Further,
not convince another, and two men of equal each of us is familiar with instances when our
intellectual force, confronted with the same attitudes or habits made us persist in saying
facts and the same arguments, will arrive at something in a certain way, or in working
different conclusions and convictions. This is with a particular method, long after our rea-
not to say that any belief is as tenable objec- son, or newly acquired knowledge, should
tively as any other belief, but only to recog- have persuaded us to change. Often, too, in
nize that the human factor is one condition of our scientific careers we may "discover" some
human enterprises. The latter fact, of course, fact or idea actually known to us, but which
is one of the pillars of Kantor's interbehavior- we had before not found convincing and there-
ism. fore had dismissed. We may well inquire what
While Kantor does not draw together in one experience we can have had, in what situa-
place his views of belief, he returned to the tions, and under what reinforcement schedule,
theme often in the Logic, and a student of his which created in us such crippling persistence
would not be unprepared to anticipate what of behavior.
more he might have said. Peirce was attracted Belief, Hume taught, comes from experi-
to the subject and also returned to it many ence. Agreeing with this, modern behavior
times, tying the problem of belief to those theory has taken the organism's "reinforce-
of "truth" and "reality", but handling the ment history" as the sum of its experiences,
latter two problems in ways that Kantor and therefore the source of its beliefs. Where
would dismiss as absolutistic and transcen- once folklore, maxim, and craftsmanship had
dental. Belief cannot be equated with "knowl- to be relied upon to inform us about the be-
edge", Kantor would say. Even if it could, ab- havioral outcomes of different reinforcement
solutistic definitions of knowledge cannot help histories, much more is now known about
us to understand the nature of belief. Only these matters in the lawful way we call sci-
metaphysical or religious minds can frame a ence. This new knowledge, and our beliefs
concept like "belief is the end-point of knowl- about it, stem in turn from our new experi-
edge, and knowledge the end-point of belief", ences in-our "interbehavior with", Kantor
since human experience of the world does not would say-the scientific laboratory. Both for
reach any such "end-points". On the level of the laboratory psychologist as a behaving ob-
the mundane, of course, both knowledge and server, and for the experimental subject whose
belief are the results of experience, but experi- behavior is being observed under a given rein-
ence may be of many sorts among which a per- forcement schedule, it is the experience of
son's "interbehavior" with logical systems is what works that determines "knowledge" and
only one. It is for this reason that "attitudes" "belief". This is the footing on which prag-
are agreed by all to be determiners of how we matism as a philosophy stands. Experience of
think, what we think about, what we think what works ("reinforcement") gives direction
we know, and what we believe. Philosophers to behavior, and the patterning of those ex-
and logicians ever unsuccessfully wish-save periences ("schedules of reinforcement", and
when they are being healthfully pragmatic- the "response requirements" for reinforce-
to abstract and systematize the timeless and ment) gives responding its properties of per-
non-human essence of knowledge and belief. sistence, temporal distribution, and the like.
Yet the more fallible forms of human knowl- "Belief" subsumes all this when once it is
edge and belief are not without benefit in seen as a word describing behavior. Thus,
science. Sometimes, in psychology as in other Bain defined belief as "that upon which a man
sciences, the scientist has an "intuitive feeling" is prepared to act", and with that notion both
(or, as current argot has it, a "gut reaction") Peirce ("our beliefs . . . shape our actions";
about some thing or some process by which he ". . . belief . . . involves the establishment of
directs his research and which he wants to a rule of action") and Kantor ("Truth . . .
make rational. Contrariwise, he sometimes has refers to knowledge and belief-in short, to
before him a rational proposition or empirical reactions to things . . ."; "Believing implies a
finding which he cannot "intuit" and wants to readiness to do some particular thing with re-
make "gut". Neither feeling deserves to be spect to some object or situation . . .") would
A RETROSPECTIVE APPRECIATION OF KANTOR 345

agree. (The common thrust of these doctrines be separately trained has become glaring in
may be evaluated against St. Thomas' ap- our present-day society in the area of race re-
proach to "believing" as an act of the intellect lations: thus, a person may say he is not biased
consenting to divine truth under the guidance racially, but that need not square with how
of a will impelled by God through grace.) he acts in a given situation. The same holds for
But we can say more than this. We know scientists in their discussions of "scientific
today better than formerly how much be- method": what they say about it in their
havior, how much readiness to act, can be polemics and debates, as Kantor did not tire
under the control of "unconscious" or unver- of pointing out, may be quite different from
balized influences, so that we would not so what they do in their laboratories.
unequivocally accept Peirce's notion (ante- Considerations like these cut very deeply
dating Freud) that one of the three earmarks into affairs of human social life, including
of belief is that "it is something we are aware language, logic, and science. In the social
of". It is a commonplace of modern psychiatry milieu where his life is played out, the scien-
to accept a person's action, for which he may tist is to be understood as a behaving orga-
not be able to give reasons, as expressing his nism just as much as any of his fellow men in
belief as to "how things are". Moreover, the any other arena of human activity. Terms like
word "belief" (and "knowledge" and "truth", "evidence", and "truth", and "belief", and
of course) carries a heavy burden of histori- "science", and "scientific method", can for
cally accrued meanings, marginal nuances, and him be subjects of dogma, when they should
everyday usage. Kantor would point out that rather be subjects of inquiry. Scientists are no
a person's experience and behavior training strangers to weakness. In their own disciplines
can have verbal materials or language as its they have prejudices, but about different
condition. We can experience our own verbal things than do laymen, and different even
behavior; certain of our verbal performances from their colleagues in other sciences; they,
can be reinforced; the verbal behavior of other too, are irrational, but in different ways; and,
people can stimulate our own; our verbal in the end, their behavioral directions and
reactions to non-verbal things are trained; and characteristics, including their flexibility and
so on. Language and linguistic materials, our their rigidity, have their origins, as do every-
tendency to speak and to utter sentences man's, in their personal histories and the fac-
whether of natural or metaphysical reference, tors which shaped them. Outside their disci-
are themselves the objects or conditions plines, in areas such as politics or religion or
around which a reinforcement history is built. art, the training of scientists, despite the "halo
An animal, of course, can also have "belief" effect" with which they may be invested, does
or "knowledge" in the sense of behavioral not carry over, and their competence is ordi-
direction and persistence based on his experi- nary.
ences with the environment, what the environ- A better understanding of the behavioral
ment is, how it acts, what it can provide. But bases of evidence and belief may prove of para-
humans can learn what to say as well as what mount importance for mankind's future. It
to do, or more correctly, speaking is one form seems to me that we are making a beginning in
of the behaving we learn. The same "readiness the case of scientific behavior with contempo-
to do some particular thing" which is "believ- rary studies of reinforcement schedules, of
ing" for Kantor, also "may . . . attach to the stimulus control, of "matching" behavior, and
acceptance of the belief itself" (Vol. 1, p. of verbal behavior. What we learn will be
174). This has interesting variations in social validated by how well it matches pragmatically
education, notably in politics, in social mores, against the events in the world we call "the
and in religion. In religion, for example, we behavior of scientists". We must make the
may observe related problems in the training same kind of beginning with religious be-
of catechism, or the biblical distinction be- havior, which is also based on a history of
tween "believing in the heart" and merely experience (organized, as Santayana argued, by
having on the tongue, or Tertullian's declara- man's best possible use of both reason and in-
tion "I believe it because it is impossible" tuition, just as in science), but the final vali-
(what was "evidence" to him?). The fact that dation may be almost entirely social and
our social talking and our social acting can verbal (metaphysical) and less pragmatically
346 W. N. SCHOENFELD

tied to the non-social physical environment. of students coming to them needs to be intro-
Man is, of course, part of the world at the duced to it. It has been said that, while on
same time that he is its "observer" (that is, a some university campuses the naturalistic at-
speaking reactor in a linguistic social environ- titude might be taken for granted, no more
ment), and it is this duality of role that has than a few steps away the ocean of super-
historically created both the overlap, and the naturalism and transcendentalism engulfs the
conflicts, between his religious and his scien- intellectual journeyman.
tific activities and systems. But man is a uni- For Kantor, the defense of naturalism in
tary organism, and his behavior can be studied behavioral science especially cannot be let
from that premise notwithstanding how any down for an instant, and he assumed the bur-
one individual person may be talking about den staunchly. He has been correct, if we may
or reacting to his behavior at present, or how surmise from the attacks upon naturalism, in
he has in the past. Man's behavior both as psychology and the other sciences, which are
"scientist" and as "religious" is a crucial tar- today coming from many new quarters: by
get for scientific analysis. In either role, we Krutch and Chomsky in the areas of human
can ask what the conditions are of man's "be- behavior and language, by Polanyi in logic
liefs". and psychology, by Jaki and Heitler in physics,
At the heart of these problems, language is to name only a few. As this counteraction to
an indispensable and ever-acting ingredient, naturalistic psychology builds up, one can well
and the analysis of language must be high on imagine the violence of future onslaughts
the agenda of behavioral science. It was really against any effort to extend a behavioral analy-
this goal that informed both Kantor's Gram- sis from relatively neutral areas to one like
mar and his Logic. No scientist has ever under- religion. Since threat is not Newtonian, a
taken a nobler task. movement by natural science toward the anal-
ysis of religious behavior will very likely pro-
IV duce a more-than-equal opposite reaction.
A reader of these volumes comes away with Kantor would not be dismayed, however, by
an imbued feel for the core attitudes and prin- the fact that there are conflicts between sci-
ciples that Kantor sought to implant in an ence and religion-conflicts of presupposition,
aborning science of behavior. A reader who of proposition, of choices of what is to be
is also a teacher, no matter what his personal studied-because such conflicts do not negate
views, can do no better for his students than the possibility of equally real and important
to make them at least for a time students of agreement among the disputing parties as to
Kantor, knowing they will find it an enriching how they actually behave in everyday "scien-
interlude, one that will contribute to their tific" and "religious" life. They may agree, as
growth as psychologists. much as they conflict, in the conduct of their
Kantor was a natural scientist. That is a studies and researches, what they actually do
difficult laurel to earn in psychology. He never in their methods and procedures, how they
flagged in his devotion to naturalism as a phi- handle and describe their findings. Both con-
losophy applicable as much to behavior as to flict and agreement are intrinsic to the multi-
any other subject matter. His criticism of plicity of forms that interbehavior can take.
mentalistic and dualistic doctrines was unre- The study of interbehavior will impartially
mitting, but, more importantly, were insight- include the conflicts and the non-conflicts, and
ful and elucidating. A naturalistic approach the bases of both; in so doing, it may be
to behavior, especially human behavior, is not learned how conflict and non-conflict mingle,
easy to frame and to maintain, as we can see what the interground between them is, and
from the several millenia during which think- how the resolution of conflict on one level
ers have fretted over the issue. Even in con- may lead to conflict on another. The critical
temporary "radical" countries on every conti- study of history would further our instruction.
nent, though they preen themselves on being Always it is our understanding that will in-
science-oriented, a knowledgeable sponsorship crease. And that, rather than dogmatic peace,
of naturalism in psychology is rarely, if ever, is our goal.
encountered. Individual psychologists who To this conclusion was Kantor led by his
support it are surprised that each new group naturalistic and interbehavioral emphasis
A RETROSPECTIVE APPRECIATION OF KANTOR 347
upon man's language as behavior under spe- measure of that agreement is almost a measure
cific conditions, and upon man's verbal systems of how far we have come to meet him, or, per-
(philosophies) as conditional products. Be- haps, of how much of his teaching has filtered
cause language and logic were both interbe- into our education without our being quite
havioral, there was no room for absolutism in aware of it. Foremost among his qualities,
thinking about either of them. He repeatedly and not often matched among behavior theo-
stressed the distinction between facts and their rists, is that intellectual restlessness and drive
formulations, between abstractions and the and breadth, combined with a capacity for
full flood of the world as we observe it. In contemplation and reflection, that Aristotle
these volumes, language and logic were his called theoria. Fittingly enough, it was il mae-
broadly taken subjects, but he tried to move stro di color che sanno to whom Kantor dedi-
from generalizations to particular cases and cated his Psychology and Logic. But no reader
problems. Any student with an appetite along need fear that he will lose his personal identity
these lines will find in the Kantorian field in Kantor's train, because the man is, in the
wheat to make bread with. The challenge will end, a good student of il maestro, and would,
be to add to the acreage, to stand upon the in all modesty, include his own "system"
ground he tried to clear and to see farther within the statement that closes his Psychology
than he did. History's judgment on this work and Logic:
of Kantor's will depend, as it does for all
thinkers, on what those who came after him . . . systemizing means creative operations.
were able successfully to make of him. It is a Systems imply selection, the application of
fair challenge, considering how much of a criteria of use or of completeness. Under no
start he has given us. circumstances must we lose sight of the op-
Reading these books, it is revealing to see erational field. There is always a plenum-
how much of what their author teaches a a set of events, things, and entities-which
modern psychological theorist can agree with. can never be exhausted by the structuring
Since his voice was among the rare ones in the operations.
history of naturalistic behavioral science, the

Potrebbero piacerti anche