Sei sulla pagina 1di 10

Stolnitz's Attitude: Taste and Perception

Author(s): George Dickie


Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , Winter, 1984, Vol. 43, No. 2
(Winter, 1984), pp. 195-203
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics

Stable URL: http://www.jstor.com/stable/429993

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

Wiley and The American Society for Aesthetics are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This content downloaded from


141.2.222.21 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 11:53:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
GEORGE DICKIE

Stolnitz's Attitude: Taste and


Perception

JEROME STOLNITZ has objected in this theory: the eighteenth century theories of
Journal1 to my criticism2 of his interpreta-taste which lack the notion of disin-
tion of certain eighteenth century philoso- terested perception and the later aesthet-
phers as aesthetic-attitude theorists. Stolnitz ic-attitude theories which make disin-
had originally claimed to find descriptions terested perception central. I was orig-
of aesthetic or disinterested perception in inally led to distinguish between these two
the writings of these eighteenth century Brit- kinds of theory by comparing the theory
ish philosophers.3 In my criticism, I had of the eighteenth century philosopher
claimed that the notion of aesthetic per- Francis Hutcheson with present-day aes-
ception had first appeared in the writings thetic-attitude theorists such as Stolnitz.
of the nineteenth century philosopher Hutcheson's theory involves a four-part
Schopenhauer. Unfortunately, my earlier structure:
remarks about Schopenhauer, as Stolnitz
points out, are mistaken in an important 1. External senses (vision, hearing, and the like);
way. Fortunately, this mistake does not 2. An internal sense of beauty (a faculty which
invalidate my main conclusion that Stol- reacts to certain objects of the external senses);
3. Uniformity in variety (the specific characteris-
nitz's attributing of aesthetic perception
tic of objects of the external senses which causes
to the eighteenth century British phi- the internal sense to react);
losophers is wrong. Stolnitz is right that 4. Pleasure (the product of the reaction of the in-
the notion of disinterestedness is pres- ternal sense).

ent in the theorizing of these British phi-


losophers and thus that the association Stolnitz's theory is summed up in his
of disinterestedness with theories con- definition of "the aesthetic attitude"
cerned with beauty and the like beginswhich
in is, he says, "disinterested and sym-
the eighteenth century, but he is wrong in attention to and contemplation of
pathic
thinking that these British thinkers predi-
any object of awareness whatever, for its
cated disinterestedness of perception as own sake alone."4 Stolnitz's theory, ig-
do present-day aesthetic-attitude theorists noring the notion of "sympathic," in-
such as himself. Stolnitz's mistake is the volves a two-part structure:
result of the fact that he does not fully un-
derstand the nature of the aesthetic-atti- 1. Disinterested attention (a prior condition for the
tude theory that he himself holds. occurrence of the action which is the second part of
In criticizing Stolnitz's original claim, I the structure;
argued that there are two distinct kinds of 2. Contemplation of any object for its own sake
alone.

GEORGE DICKIE is professor of philosophy at the Stolnitz sometimes seems to write as if


University of Illinois at Chicago. disinterested attention and contemplation
? 1984 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This content downloaded from


141.2.222.21 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 11:53:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
196 DICKIE

are the same thing. Sometimes, however, thing may be contemplated because any-
he treats the two as separate: for exam- thing can be isolated by disinterested at-
ple, he writes, "the aesthetic attitude 'iso- tention. For Hutcheson, only uniformity
lates' the object and focuses upon it[s ob- in variety can be the object of beauty be-
ject]-the 'look' of the rock, the sound of cause it is the only kind of object to
the ocean, the colors in the painting."5 which the internal sense of beauty can re-
Here he must be talking about an act or spond. For Hutcheson, anything to which
an occurrence of disinterested attending uniformity in variety stands in relation is
which isolates its object perceptually from just irrelevant to the sense of beauty be-
the things to which it stands in relation. cause the sense of beauty is unable to re-
Once this initiating act of disinterested spond to it.
attending occurs, the perceptually rela- Of course, for Hutcheson, a person is a
tionless object can be focussed on and complex being with many aspects and
contemplated. interests in addition to the sense of
Stolnitz mentions several things which beauty. Consequently, for Hutcheson, the
are supposed to be destructive to disin- effect of uniformity in variety on a person
terested attention. Criticism is one. Of may have to compete with other interests
aesthetic appreciation and criticism, he of that person. For example, he writes,
writes, . . /'they are psychologically op- "Who was ever please'd . . . with un-
posed to each other. The aesthetic and equal legs or arms, eyes or cheeks in a
critical attitudes are such radically differ- mistress? It must however be acknowl-
ent ways of approaching an object that edg'd, that interest may often counter-
when one is uppermost in the mind, it balance our sense of beauty in this affair
drives the other out."6 The reason, on as well as in others, and superior good
Stolnitz' s theory, for the incompatibility qualities may make us overlook such
of the aesthetic and critical attitudes is imperfections."'8 The counterbalancing
that the disinterested attention component by interests Hutcheson has in mind here
of the aesthetic attitude perceptually de- is not one in which the awareness of
taches its object from its relations to other beauty is prevented or even interfered
things whereas criticism involves relating with, it is a counterbalancing in which the
the object to something else. If the critical awareness of a relative lack of beauty
attitude gains the upper hand it relates the of a person is weighed against the per-
object to something and destroys disin- son's other qualities. There is nothing in
terested attention, and, hence, the aes- Hutcheson's theory which necessarily
thetic attitude. Stolnitz has similar things makes interests incompatible with the
to say about the moral content of works appreciation of beauty, as there is in aes-
of art. If we respond to the moral content thetic-attitude theory. Burke makes the
of a work of art, "this disrupts the aes- point of the compatibility of interest and
thetic attitude."7 The reason that the the appreciation of beauty within the con-
aesthetic attitude is disrupted in such text of the theory of taste nicely in a pas-
cases is that the work of art has been re- sage in which he distinguishes between
lated to something else, and this prevents the love caused by beauty and the desire
the occurrence of disinterested attention. caused by sexual attraction. Burke writes,
Hutcheson's theory of taste differs sub- i'.. . the passion caused by beauty,
stantially from Stolnitz's aesthetic-attitude which I call love, is different from desire
theory. In Hutcheson's theory, there is no [sexual attraction], though desire may
such thing as disinterested attention; there sometimes operate along with it. . ..9
is just the effect of a specific kind of fea- There just is not anything in Burke's or
ture on the sense of beauty. On Hutche- Hutcheson's theories which makes inter-
son's theory, the specific feature of a per- est and the appreciation of beauty neces-
ceived object at work is uniformity in sarily incompatible. Of course, Burke and
variety, but on Stolnitz's theory, anything Hutcheson and everyone else would agree
may be contemplated. For Stolnitz, any- that there are "desperate cases" in which

This content downloaded from


141.2.222.21 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 11:53:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Taste und Perception 197

a person's interests are so powerful (life- desire for property, and sexual desire; and
threatening cases, for example) that the contents of consciousness such as visual
appreciation of beauty becomes impossi- and auditory objects as well as pleasures,
ble. For the theory of taste, such power- pains, and various other feelings. Vision
ful interests simply crowd out the appre- can inform the person, for example, that
ciation of beauty. (Throughout his article there is a red, round object in front of
Stolnitz misinterprets my view that in him, and vision plus memory and other
theories of taste a specific kind of object cognitive faculties can inform him that
triggers the faculty of taste to mean that there is an apple in front of him which re-
nothing can intefere with the triggering. lates to his hunger. Through vision, the
Of course, the triggering can be interfered apple's complex property of uniformity in
with or even prevented in given cases.) variety can affect the person, and when
The aesthetic-attitude view, however, is that happens the sense of beauty can re-
very different on the score of interest and act to produce pleasure. For the Hutche-
contemplation, because it holds that there sonian person, there is no necessary con-
is an inherent incompatibility between flict between the perception of the two
interest and contemplation. This in- apple properties-its uniformity in variety
compatibility derives from the aesthetic- and its edibility.
attitude theorist's view that contemplationFor Stolnitz, a person has cognitive
requires the antecedent occurence of dis-
abilities such as vision and hearing; de-
interested attention which must first per-
sires such as hunger, desire for property,
ceptually isolate its object from its re- and sexual desire; and contents of con-
lations. Stolnitz says in a discussion of sciousness such as visual and auditory ob-
Hutcheson that Hutcheson ". . . details jects as well as pleasures, pains, and
the conditions which prevent aesthetic various other feelings. A Stolnitzean per-
experience."10 Stolnitz is misreading son has an additional mental ability-he
Hutcheson because he takes him to be can attend either interestedly or disinter-
talking about aesthetic perception. Stol- estedly. When, for example, he sees an
nitz should have written, "Hutcheson de- apple while attending interestedly, he will
tails the conditions which may interfere see it as something to eat, i.e., as relating
with and may even in extreme cases pre- to his hunger. When he sees an apple
vent aesthetic experience." (By the way, while attending disinterestedly, he will see
it is a mistake to import the expression it as an aesthetic object, i.e., as unrelated
"aesthetic experience" into a discussion to any interest. For a Stolnitzean person,
of these eighteenth century theories.) there is a necessary conflict between the
Another way in which Stolnitz's and perception of the two apple properties
Hutchson's theories differ is that while (aesthetic-objectness and edibility) be-
pleasure is mentioned from time to time cause, as Stolnitz says, whichever of
by Stolnitz, it does not seem to play the disinterested attention or interested atten-
central role in his theory that it does in tion is dominants "it drives the other
Hutcheson's and other theories of taste. out.""l
This point is not, however, one of great My conclusion concering Stolnitz's the-
significance. ory is that Stolnitz claims that there is a
I will sum up the previous discussion kind of perception which he calls "aes-
by giving a (partial) description of an ex- thetic perception" which is made up of
perience of beauty as envisaged by Hut- two parts: 1) disinterested attention and 2)
cheson and a (partial) description of an contemplation of an object. So long as
experience of an aesthetic object as en- disinterested attention is maintained, it is
visaged by Stolnitz. guaranteed that its object is perceptually
For Hutcheson, a person has external relationless and, consequently, the con-
senses such as hearing and vision; internal templation of its object must be disin-
senses such as the sense of beauty and terested. The contemplation is disin-
the moral sense; desires such as hunger, terested because its object does not stand

This content downloaded from


141.2.222.21 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 11:53:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
198 DICKIE

in relation to anything else perceptually. of attitude theory as "weak," i.e., as


The reason, according to the aesthetic-at- holding that aesthetic consciousness does
titude view, that the contemplated object not impose an aesthetic character but is
is perceptually relationless is that it is first rather simply a necessary condition for
the object of disinterested perception. the apprehension and appreciation of an
My conclusion about Hutcheson is that aesthetic character which is independent
there is no trace of aesthetic perception in of the mode of perception. The aspect of
his theory, because there is no trace of Kant's philosophy I focused on was a
disinterested attention. On Hutcheson's false lead and mislead me in my interpre-
theory of beauty there can be disinterested tation of Schopenhauer. Schopenhauer's
contemplation, which turns out to be the view is not a "strong" version of the aes-
contemplation of an object which possesses thetic-attitude theory, and neither is
uniformity in variety. In such contempla- anyone else's. What, then, is Schopen-
tion, the object's uniformity in variety is, hauer's view?
from the point of view of the sense of If Stolnitz's view is taken as a model of
beauty, relationless because uniformity in aesthetic-attitude theory, then Schopen-
variety is the only thing to which the sense ofhauer's view is not, strictly speaking, an
beauty can respond. The object itself, how- aesthetic-attitude theory. Schopenhauer
ever, is not perceived as relationless. The maintains that aesthetic consciousness
question, for Hutcheson, of whether the must have as its object some Platonic
interest of a person may crowd such con- Idea, not any object whatsoever, as the
templation out of the domain of the external paradigm view holds. So Schopenhauer
senses is purely contingent. Disinterested has in common with Hutcheson the view
contemplation is a part of both Hutcheson's that a specific kind of object is required.
and Stolnitz's theories, but it is achieved in His view differs from Hutcheson's, how-
different ways. ever, in affirming disinterested attention.
In my 1974 discussion, I was interested Strictly speaking, Schopenhauer's view is
primarily in two questions: 1) what in the neither fish nor fowl, but is a transition
history of philosophy is responsible for between the theory of taste and aesthetic-
the disappearence of theories of taste attitude theory. (One might read Schopen-
such as Hutcheson's and the rise of aes- hauer's theory as an aesthetic-attitude
thetic-attitude theories such as Stolnitz's, view of a certain restricted kind, namely,
and 2) who is the first aesthetic-attitude as the view that aesthetic consciousness
theorist. I pinpointed certain aspects of can take as its object any Platonic Idea
Kant's philosophy as initiating the chain whatsoever. (Aesthetic consciousness can-
of events which ultimately produced aes- not take any object whatsoever, but it can
thetic-attitude theory, and I pointed to take any object whatsoever from a restricted
Schopenhauer as the first aesthetic-atti- domain, namely, Platonic Ideas.)
tude theorist. I was, I believe, right in fo- Whatever the correct understanding of
cusing on Kant and Schopenhauer, but I the historical Schopenhauer is, there is
focused on the wrong aspects of Kant's embedded in the vast, eclectic structure
philosophy, and, consequently, I misinter- which is his philosophy a conception
preted Schopenhauer's theory. which comes very close to being an aes-
I focused on Kant's view that the mind thetic-attitude theory. It was this concep-
imposes on its objects various proper- tion which was subsequently so influ-
ties-spatial, temporal, causal, and so on. ential. Few, if any, were influenced by
Since up to a point, Schopenhauer follows what Schopenhauer said about the place
Kant in this regard, I interpreted Scho- of Platonic Ideas in aesthetic experience,
penhauer as holding that aesthetic con- but many were influenced by his account
sciousness imposes an aesthetic character of aesthetic consciousness. Stolnitz's the-
on its object. I read Schopenhauer as ory, for example, is essentially Schopen-
what I called a "strong aesthetic-attitude hauer's theory of aesthetic consciousness
theorist" and characterized another kind with "any object whatsoever" replacing

This content downloaded from


141.2.222.21 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 11:53:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Taste and Perception 199

"any Platonic Idea" as the description of quired for the purely objective appre-
the object of aesthetic consciousness. hension of the true nature of things . . .
Stolnitz writes of Schopenhauer, "One of [Platonic Ideas]"'18 Finally, the aesthetic
the best brief descriptions of the aesthetic .. state is conditioned from the out-
attitude to be found anywhere is in the side by our remaining wholly foreign to,
writings of the nineteenth century German and detached from, the scene to be con-
philosopher Schopenhauer."'12 Stolnitz is templated, and not being at all actively in-
quite right that a description of the aes- volved in it."9
thetic attitude is to be found ". . . in the First, Schopenhauer's account of aes-
writings of . . . Schopenhauer," even if, thetic consicousness does not involve any
it may be added, Schopenhauer himself is sort of noncognitive faculty of taste as
not quite an aesthetic-attitude theorist. does Hutcheson's theory of taste; the
What, then, is the nature of aesthetic whole account is in terms of intellect and
consciousness, according to Schopen- its objects. Second, aesthetic conscious-
hauer? It does not involve, I now admit, ness depends on or is conditioned by the
imposing an aesthetic character on some- intellect's ability to act in such a way as
thing. The picture he gives of ordinary to detach the object of its perception from
consciousness is of intellect (the cognitive its relations and make it perceptually rela-
faculties) totally in the service of the will. tionless. Stolnitz's notion of disinterested
Consequently, in ordinary consciousness attention is the lineal descendant of Scho-
the objects of perception are simply the penhauer's notion of the intellect's ability
intersections of sets of temporal, spatial, to disengage its object from its relations.
and causal relations because it is through Third, for Schopenhauer, once the de-
knowledge of these relations that the will taching and isolating act occurs, disin-
is served. Aesthetic consciousness is very terested contemplation of an object of
different and rare. The infrequent transi-perception becomes possible. Fourth, if
tion to aesthetic consciousness '. . . any trace of the will manages to breach
can happen only by a change in the sub- the isolating action of the intellect, aes-
ject."13 This change in the subject oc- thetic consciousness is destroyed; there is
curs when a person is ". . . raised up by an absolute antagonism between aesthetic
the power of the mind. . . [tol . . . relin- consciousness and interest.
quish the ordinary ways of considering Schopenhauer did not, however, make
things...."14 The change ". . . takes the transition to this new way of con-
place suddenly, . . . [when] . . . knowl- ceiving of the experience of beauty all by
edge tears itself free from the service of himself. Kant's account of the way in
the will. . . . "15 When aesthetic con- which beauty is experienced, although
sciousness is achieved, what previously formulated in the old terminology of the
was perceived as the intersection of rela- theory of taste, differs in an important
tions is then perceived as a perceptually way from the accounts of the British
relationless Platonic Idea. The Platonic theorists. The difference that Kant intro-
Idea then becomes the object of aesthetic duces closely resembles Schopenhauer' s
contemplation. Aesthetic consciousness is notion of aesthetic consciousness.
not only infrequent, it is precarious. Scho- The relevant aspects of Kant's theory
penhauer writes, "What makes this state are developed in the first and third mo-
difficult and therefore rare is that in it the ments of his "Analytic of the Beautiful."
. . . intellect . . . subdues and eliminates Kant writes,
the . . . will, although only for a short
time."'6 Furthermore, the aesthetic state The delight which we connect with the represen-
can be maintained " . . . only when we tation of the real existence of an object is called
ourselves have no interest in . . . [the ob- interest. Such a delight, therefore, always in-
volves a reference to the faculty of desire. . ..
jects of perception, i.e.,] . . . they stand
Now where the question is whether something is
in no relation to our will."17 "[T]he ab- beautiful, we do not want to know, whether we,
solute silence of the will . . . [is] . . . re- or anyone else, are, or even could be, concerned

This content downloaded from


141.2.222.21 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 11:53:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
200 DICKIE

in the real existence of the thing, cognitive


butfaculties
rather function
what determines
estimate we form of it on mere contemplation an aspect of its object, namely, whether
20

or not the percipient is aware of the ob-


ject's relations. For Hutcheson, the facul-
An object's real existence involves it in ty of taste is involved with a specific kind
relations to other objects, and it is of object-form of purpose. Whether, on
through these relations that desire can get Kant's view, the form of purpose triggers
a foothold. Thus, when Kant claims that the faculty of taste is not clear, but I shall
the beautiful object has no involvement make no attempt to clarify this point.
with real existence, he is saying that the Kant's theory is similar to Schopenhau-
object's being beautiful does not involve er's in that both theories focus only on
having relations to anything else. The cognitive faculties and on those faculties'
beautiful object can, therefore, involve no struggle with desire (will). Kant's theory
reference to desire. This is the Kantian differs from Schopenhauer's in that Kant
account of the disinterested nature of the retains virtually all of the terminology of
contemplation of the beautiful. the earlier theories of taste. Kant's and
Kant tries to ensure universal validity Schopenhauer's theories can both be seen
of judgments of taste by having the facul- to have a close and important relation of
ty of taste consist of the cognitive facul- the later aesthetic-attitude theories.
ties of imagination and understanding My earlier account contained a discus-
functioning in a secondary way. Since sion of Schiller's aesthetic theory. It did
everyone has these cognitive faculties, so because I was trying to find a philos-
universality is assured. For Kant, when opher whose theory provides a transition
one has an experience of the beautiful, from Kant's theory of taste to Schopen-
the object of the experience is contem- hauer's aesthetic-attitude theory. Since I
plated as unrelated to anything else (not now think that Kant's and Schopenhau-
experienced as an object having real exis- er's theories are more similar than I
tence). Underlying the experience of the thought earlier, I have no need to find a
beautiful is the imagination and the under- transition theory. I am relieved of the ne-
standing functioning in the secondary way cessity of discussing Schiller's exceed-
that Kant calls "free play." Free play is ingly obscure views.
to be contrasted with the primary func- I turn now to Stolnitz's claim that he
tioning of the imagination and the under- finds the notion of aesthetic perception in
standing in which objective knowledge is the theories of the eighteenth century
produced and in which real existence is at British philosophers of taste. I shall con-
issue. The harmonious, free play of the sider the theorists he discusses in chrono-
cognitive faculties produces pleasure, and logical order, beginning with Shaftesbury.
this pleasure is disinterested because it is In my earlier account, I devoted only a
cut off from the real existence of objects, few lines to Shaftesbury, although I ac-
and, hence, from interest. knowledged his influence on the theorists
The Kantian notion of the harmonious, of taste. Stolnitz takes exception to my
free play of the cognitive faculties which remark about ' 'Shaftesbury's concern
effectively cuts off its object from its rela- with the Platonic Form of Beauty ..."
tions to other things strikes me as being as the object of contemplation,21 and he
very similar to the Schopenhauerian no- goes on to claim that aesthetic perception
tion of intellect acting to sever its object's is central to Shaftesbury's view.22
relations to other objects. It is not central to my concern to deter-
Kant's theory differs from Hutcheson's mine whether Shaftesbury was writing
in that the Kantian faculty of taste is the about the Platonic Form of Beauty or not.
cognitive faculties functioning in a secon- I was led to believe that he was by the re-
dary way whereas The Hutchesonian fac- mark he makes just before the passage on
ulty of taste is a noncognitive, reflex fac- disinterestedness which is so frequently
ulty. For Kant, the way in which the quoted. He writes there, ". . . whatever

This content downloaded from


141.2.222.21 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 11:53:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Taste and Perception 201

in nature is beautiful or charming is only that two different enjoyments are involved
the faint shadow of that first beauty." He in this kind of case. In the second case,
then goes on to speak of the contempla- Shaftesbury asks a question about the
tion of beauty '. . . in itself or as it ap- contemplation of a tract of land and the
pears imperfectly in objects which strike ownership of the land. He asks if one
the sense. .. .23 I took "the first beauty" "... should, for the enjoyment of the pros-
to be a reference to the Platonic Form of pect, require the property or possession
Beauty. If it is a reference to something of the land."26 The answer is, "No," be-
else, that is fine with me. cause one can look at and contemplate
I am not, however, indifferent to Stol- the tract without owning it. The third and
nitz's claim to discover that Shaftesbury fourth cases also involve distinguishing
writes about aesthetic perception. Stolnitz the enjoyment of the contemplation of
quotes several passages which are sup- beauty from the enjoyment of anticipated
posed to be about aesthetic perception. benefit, but in these two last cases there
He quotes from a passage in which is also a suggestion of conflict between
Shaftesbury speaks of the pleasure one the two enjoyments. The third case in-
might take in contemplating a mathemat- volves distinguishing between the enjoy-
ical proof. Stolnitz, embedding part of ment of the contemplation of the beauty
Shaftsbury's sentence in his own, writes of a grove of trees and the enjoyment
'"The joy that accompanies the perceptionof the eating of the fruit of the trees.
'turns wholly upon what is exterior and Shaftesbury suggests that the enjoyment
foreign to ourselves'. "24 First, Stolnitz of the fruit may divert one from the beau-
speaks of perception, but the word "per- ty of the grove. And so it may. The fourth
ception" does not appear in Shaftesbury's case involves distinguishing between the
passage. Second, in this passage, Shaftes- enjoyment of contemplating human beau-
bury is simply distinguishing between dif- ty and the desire for sexual possession.
ferent kinds of joy: the joy of contemplat- Shaftesbury suggests that the ". . . eager
ing a mathematical proof and the joy of desires, wishes, and hopes . . ." for sex-
anticipated benefit. He makes this distinc- ual possession are ". . . no way suitable
tion to counter the view that there is only ... to [the] rational and refined contem-
one joy involved in cases such as this, plation of beauty."27 He is saying that the
namely, the joy of anticipated benefit. desire for sexual possession may interfere
There is nothing in this passage which in- with the contemplation of human beauty.
dicates that Shaftesbury has in mind cog- And so it may, but Shaftesbury nowhere
nitive faculties which perceptually sever even suggests that there is a mental ca-
their object from its relations in order that pacity which can function to perceptually
it can be contemplated. isolate the beautiful object and thereby
Stolnitz mentions only the last of the preserve the contemplation of it from the
four examples from the famous passage in interference of competing interests of the
which Shaftesbury is frequently said to perceiver. Shaftesbury is free to agree
have introduced the notion of disinterest- with Burke that ". . . desire may some-
edness in the discussion of the experience times operate along with . . ." the appre-
of beauty, but I shall discuss them all ciation of human beauty, although he gives
briefly. In the first case, Shaftesbury con- the impression of being less optimistic
trasts the enjoyment of contemplating the than Burke is, that this will happen with
beauty of the ocean with the enjoyment of great frequency.
owning the ocean. Shaftesbury's remarks Stolnitz, citing the affinities between
that the enjoyment of ownership is ". . . Addison's theory of taste and Shaftes-
very different from that which should nat- bury's view, claims to discover the notion
urally follow from contemplation of the of aesthetic perception in Addison's writ-
ocean's beauty."25 He is here making the ing. But, as the notion of aesthetic per-
same point that he makes in the passage ception is not to be found in Shaftes-
about the mathematical proof, namely, bury's work, the citing of affinities be-

This content downloaded from


141.2.222.21 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 11:53:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
202 DICKIE

tween the views of the two men supplies show that all the phenomena are reducible to the
no ground for interpreting various re- same general principle and that the qualities of
matter are not beautiful or sublime in them-
marks by Addison as being about aesthet- selves, but as they are, by various means, the
ic perception. signs or expressions of qualities capable of pro-
Stolnitz objects to my classification of ducing emotion.3'
Burke as a taste theorist. I had asserted
that for Burke the faculty of taste isI sim-
am aware that on Alison's view a qual-
ply the disposition to respond with disin- ity of matter may become an expression
terested pleasure to the perception of of mind or a sign of a quality of mind
certain qualities. Stolnitz rejects my clas- merely by association. How a quality of
sification and writes, "Burke vigorously matter comes to be an expression or a
repudiates any reactive faculty of taste, sign for someone is irrelevant. The point
such as an inner sense. . .28 It is true is that once it is taken as an expression or
that Burke explicitly denies that the facul- sign it can trigger the faculty of taste. I
ty of taste is a special internal sense as am also aware that through association
Hutcheson had maintained, but he cer- any quality of matter may become a sign
tainly conceives of it as reactive. Burke but it is not the quality of matter simpli-
writes, "Beauty . . . is no creature of our citer which triggers the faculty of taste, it
reason, since it strikes us without any ref- is the quality of matter seen as an expres-
erence to use, . . . we must conclude that sion or sign. The specification of signs of
beauty is, for the greater part, some qual- qualities of mind or expressions of mind is
ity in bodies, acting mechanically upon a complex although still specific kind of
the human mind by the intervention of the object. Alison himself regards such a
senses."29 It seems perfectly reasonable specification as a reduction "to the same
to me to say that Burke is here referring general principle." Alison's view is that
to the same general sort of mental func- the specific kind of object which triggers
tion that Hutcheson and others referred to the faculty of taste is more complex
as a faculty of taste. Burke claims that a (much more complex) than Hutcheson or
complex of aspects of mind reacts to Burke imagine.
certain specific properties of perceptual Stolnitz insists that he finds the notion
objects, and Hutcheson claims that a sin- of aesthetic perception in Alison's theory.
gle aspect of mind reacts to a certain spe- He claims to find passages in which Ali-
cific property of perceptual objects. son distinguishes ". . . the mode of atten-
Concerning Alison, I had maintained 1) tion requisite to such feelings [feeling in-
that he was a taste theorist in part be- volved in the experience of beauty] from
cause he claims that a specific kind of other modes of attention or, specifically
complex object, namely, an expression of disinterested from interested attention
mind or a sign of a quality of mind, trig- ...."32 But there are no such passages, and
gers the faculty of taste and 2) that his Stolnitz thinks that he finds them only be-
theory does not involve aesthetic per- cause he does not understand what disin-
ception. Stolnitz writes concerning the no- terested attention is supposed to be. What
tion of a specific kind of object, "In Hut- Alison does say, in the passages Stolnitz
cheson, it is uniformity in variety; in cites, is that the functioning of the
Burke, smallness or delicacy or . . ., and imagination is required for the experience
so on. The inference cannot be drawn in of beauty and that insofar as anything in-
Alison. There is no limit in principle to terferes with the functioning of the
the properties possessed by beautiful imagination, the experience of beauty is
things or to such things."30 reduced. If one attends solely to some-
Concerning the first point, I simply thing other than the beautiful object, then
quote Alison. He writes concerning the there is no experience of beauty at all;
one is totally distracted. If one attends to
. . . origin of the beauty and sublimity of the both the beautiful object and to some
qualities of matter .... I shall endeavor to other thing, the functioning of the

This content downloaded from


141.2.222.21 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 11:53:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Taste and Perception 203

imagination is enfeebled and the experi- stroyed, thereby preventing the conjunc-
ence of beauty is reduced. Alison writes tion Alison allows.
of a person in pain or grieving ". . .
whose mind, by these means, is attentive 1 Jerome Stolnitz, "'The Aesthetic Attitude' in the
Rise of Modern Aesthetics," The Journal of Aesthet-
only to one object or consideration, the
ics and Art Criticism, XXXVI no. 4, (1978), p. 409-
[beautiful] scene, or the [beautiful] form, 23.
will produce no feeling of admiration, 2 George Dickie, Art and the Aesthetic (Cornell
which, at other times, when his imagina- University Press, 1974), pp. 53-77.
tion was at liberty, would have produced 3 Jerome Stolnitz, "On the Origins of 'Aesthetic
Disinterestedness'," The Journal of Aesthetics and
it in its fullest perfection."33 Alison is Art Criticism, XX, no. 2 (1961), p. 131-43.
here writing of total distraction, and he 4 Jerome Stolnitz, Aesthetics and Philosophy of
does not speak of different kinds of atten- Art Criticism (New York, 1960), pp. 34-35.
tion, only of attention to different kinds of 5 Ibid., p. 35.
6 Ibid., p. 377.
objects.
7 Ibid., p. 36.
Consider now this famous passage from 8 Francis Hutcheson, An Inquiry into the Original
Alison. of our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue (London, 1726),
Second Edition, p. 77.
9 Edmund Burke, A Philosophical Enquiry into the
Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and the Beautiful
It is upon the vacant and the unemployed [mind] (London, 1759), Second Edition, p. 163.
. . . that the objects of taste make the strongest 10 Stolnitz, 'The Aesthetic Attitude," p. 416.
impression. ... The seasons of care, of grief, or " Stolnitz, Aesthetics, p. 377.
of business, have other occupations, and de- 12 Ibid., p. 43.
stroy, for the time at least, our sensibility to the 13 Arthur Schopenhauer, The World as Will and
beautiful or the sublime, in the same proportion Representation, E. F. J. Payne, trans. (New York,
that they produce a state of mind unfavorable to 1969), vol. 1, p. 176.
the indulgence of imagination.34 (Italics mine) 14 Ibid., p. 178
15 Ibid.
16 Ibid., vol. 2, p. 369.
17 Ibid.
18 Ibid., p. 370.
Notice that the objects of taste are said 19 Ibid., p. 373.
by Alison to make the strongest impres- 20 Immanuel Kant, The Critique of Judgment, J.
sion on a mind unemployed in anything C. Meredity, trans., (Oxford, 1928), p. 42.
else. This statement clearly implies that 21 Dickie, p. 59; Stolnitz, 'The Aesthetic Atti-
tude," p. 415.
an object of taste can make a less strong
22 Stolnitz, 'The Aesthetic Attitude," p. 414.
impression on a mind which is not wholly 23 Anthony, Earl of Shaftesbury, Characteristics
vacant and unemployed. Notice also that of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times (New York,
later in the passage Alison says that care, 1964), vol. 2, p. 126.
24 Stolnitz, "The Aesthetic Attitude," p. 414.
grief, and the like interfere with the expe-
25 Shaftesbury, 127.
rience of beauty "in the same proportion" 26 Ibid.
that they interfere with the function of the 27 Ibid., pp. 126-27.
imagination. 28 Stolnitz, "The Aesthetic Attitude," p. 416.
Alison does not mention different kinds 29 Burke, pp. 209-210.

of attention. Furthermore, he allows for 30 Stolnitz, "The Aesthetic Attitude," p. 418.


31 Archibald Alison, "Essays on the Nature anc
the appreciation of beauty at the same Principles of Taste" in What is Art? Alexander Se-
time that a person is attentive to other sonske, ed. (New York, 1965), p. 184.
things, and this conjunction is supposedly 32 Stolnitz, "The Aesthetic Attitude," p. 418.
ruled out by disinterested attention. Sup- 33 Alison, p. 185.
34 Ibid.
posedly, disinterested attention percep-
tually disconnects its object from its rela-
tions to other things, thereby preventing
the conjunction Alison allows. Also, if I wish to thank Peter Kivy and Suzanne Cun-
ningham for their very helpful comments on an ear-
interest in something related to the object
lier version of this paper. I also wish to thank
of disinterested attention arises, disin- Byung-nam Oh for our conversations on the topics
terested attention is supposed to be de- of this paper.

This content downloaded from


141.2.222.21 on Mon, 03 Aug 2020 11:53:05 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Potrebbero piacerti anche