Sei sulla pagina 1di 7

| |

Received: 31 August 2017    Revised: 12 June 2018    Accepted: 31 July 2018

DOI: 10.1111/bioe.12519

ORIGINAL ARTICLE

Designing humans: A human rights approach

S. Matthew Liao

Center for Bioethics, New York University,


New York, USA Abstract
Advances in genomic technologies such as CRISPR‐Cas9, mitochondrial replacement
Correspondence
New York University – Center for Bioethics, techniques, and in vitro gametogenesis may soon give us more precise and efficient
719 Broadway Floor 12 New York, NY tools to have children with certain traits such as beauty, intelligence, and athleticism.
10003.
Email: matthew.liao@nyu.edu In this paper, I propose a new approach to the ethics of reproductive genetic engi‐
neering, a human rights approach. This approach relies on two claims that have cer‐
tain, independent plausibility: (a) human beings have equal moral status, and (b)
human beings have human rights to the fundamental conditions for pursuing a good
life. I first argue that the human rights approach gives us a lower bound of when re‐
productive genetic engineering would be permissible. I then compare this approach
with other approaches such as the libertarian, perfectionist, and life worth living ap‐
proaches. Against these approaches, I argue that the human rights approach offers a
novel, and more plausible, way of assessing the ethics of reproductive genetic
engineering.

KEYWORDS
CRISPR, designer babies, gene editing, gene therapy, genetic enhancement, reproductive
genetic engineering

1 | I NTRO D U C TI O N ‘search and replace’ function in a word processor. 2 In addition, scien‐
tists have also developed mitochondrial replacement techniques
Most people who want to have children would like them to be (MRTs), or ‘three‐parent’ IVFs as they are sometimes called in the
healthy, smart, creative, beautiful, athletic. Advances in genomic popular media,3 which can enable women with mitochondrial dis‐
technologies may soon give us more precise and efficient tools to eases to have children who are genetically related to them but with‐
have children with these and other traits. Indeed, a powerful new out such diseases, by transferring the nuclear genome of the
gene‐editing technology called CRISPR‐Cas9 has made it easy, mother’s egg or zygote into an enucleated egg or zygote with healthy
cheap, and fast to delete certain genes and to insert new ones.1 mitochondria.4 Moreover, in vitro gametogenesis (IVG), which in‐
CRISPR, which stands for clustered regularly interspaced short pal‐ volves the artificial construction of gametes using adult body tissue
indromic repeat, has two components. The first consists of an RNA
guide that can be used to find a specific piece of DNA to be modified. 2
Specter, M. (2015, Nov 16). The gene hackers. The New Yorker. Available at: http://www.
newyorker.com/magazine/2015/11/16/the‐gene‐hackers [Accessed 28 May 2016]
The second is a set of enzymes, Cas9 (CRISPR‐associated proteins),
3
Tingley, K. (2014, June 27). The brave new world of three‐parent IVF. The New York Times
whose function is to cut the DNA as located by the RNA guide. Magazine. Available at: http://www.nytimes.com/2014/06/29/magazine/the‐brave‐new‐
Together, CRISPR‐Cas9 enables the modification or removal of spe‐ world‐of‐three‐parent‐ivf.html [Accessed 28 May 2016]

cific DNA sequences, leading people to liken this system to the 4


Tachibana, M., Sparman, M., Sritanaudomchai, H., Ma, H., Clepper, L., Woodward, J., …
Mitalipov, S. (2009). Mitochondrial gene replacement in primate offspring and embryonic
stem cells. Nature, 461, 367–372; Craven, L., Tuppen, H. A., Greggains, G. D., Harbottle, S.
J., Murphy, J. L., Cree, L. M., … Turnbull, D. M. (2010). Pronuclear transfer in human em‐
1
Ran, F. A., Hsu, P. D., Wright, J., Agarwala, V., Scott, D. A., & Zhang, F. (2013). Genome bryos to prevent transmission of mitochondrial DNA disease. Nature, 465: 82–85. For a
engineering using the CRISPR‐Cas9 system. Nature Protocols, 8, 2281–2308; Doudna, J. discussion of some of the philosophical issues surrounding mitochondrial replacement
A., & Charpentier, E. (2014). The new frontier of genome engineering with CRISPR‐Cas9. techniques, see, for example, Liao, S. M. (2017). Do mitochondrial replacement techniques
Science, 346(6213), 1258096. affect qualitative or numerical identity? Bioethics, 31, 20–26.

98  |  wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/bioe
© 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd Bioethics. 2019;33:98–104.
LIAO |
      99

such as skin cells, has been shown to be possible in mice.5 Although being’ plays an important moral role by itself,9 which could also
IVG is still in an experimental phase, it promises to obviate the need serve to explain why all human beings are rightholders. At the
for gamete donation, leading to an unlimited supply of embryos. All same time, other philosophers believe that when we assess who
these novel genomic techniques suggest that the possibility of creat‐ can be a rightholder we should meet the species neutrality require‐
ing humans with very specific traits may not be far off. ment.10 The species neutrality requirement says that an adequate
The prospect of being able to shape and determine the charac‐ account of rightholding should provide some criterion for right‐
teristics of human offspring raises the question of whether it is mor‐ holding that in principle does not exclude any species and where
ally permissible to do so. The ethics of human reproductive genetic the criterion can be assessed through some objective, empirical
engineering, as this area of research is sometimes called, has been method. It might be thought that if the species neutrality require‐
debated extensively, both in public and by academics, and there is a ment were valid, it would not be possible to show all human beings
wide spectrum of views, ranging from those who believe that it is not are rightholders. The reason is that a number of the attributes that
morally permissible to engage in such activities, to those who think philosophers have considered and proposed, such as actual sen‐
that it is morally required to do so.6 In this paper, I shall not attempt tience and actual agency, do not apply to all human beings.11
to discuss all the views that have been canvassed in the literature. Elsewhere I have argued that this need not be the case.12 In partic‐
Instead, my aim is to explore a new approach to reproductive genetic ular, I have proposed that a sufficient condition for being a right‐
engineering, what might be called a human rights approach. This ap‐ holder is having the genetic (or, more generally, the physical) basis
proach relies on two claims that have certain, independent plausibil‐ for moral agency, and that all human beings have the genetic basis
7
ity and that I have defended in greater detail elsewhere: for moral agency.
By ‘genetic basis for moral agency’, I mean the set of physical
1. All human beings have equal moral status; in particular, they codes that generate moral agency. In human beings, this set of
are all rightholders. codes is located in their genome. We know this because a lot of
2. Human beings have human rights to the fundamental conditions complexity is needed as the developmental basis for a complex
for pursuing a good life. adaptive phenotype like moral agency, and the genome contains
a significant proportion of this complexity. At present, we do not
In Section 2, I offer some explication of, and motivation for, these know exactly which set of genes is necessary and sufficient for
two claims. From these two claims, I then develop, in Section 3, the the genetic basis for moral agency. But we can talk about a ge‐
human rights approach, which I argue offers a number of helpful cri‐ netic basis for moral agency as long as there are genes that defi‐
teria for when human reproductive genetic engineering would be im‐ nitely play no role in forming the genetic basis for moral agency.
permissible. In Section 4, I defend the human rights approach further For example, the genes for my toe nails or a gene whose expres‐
by comparing it with some other notable approaches to reproductive sion serves only to produce pigment in the eyes probably play no
genetic engineering. role in the formation of the genetic basis for moral agency. Also,
to have the genetic basis for moral agency, the genes that make
up that moral agency must be activated and be coordinating with
2 | H U M A N M O R A L S TAT U S A N D H U M A N each other in an appropriate way. To illustrate the point about co‐
R I G HT S ordination, consider the following: suppose there is a book con‐
taining many random words, which if put together in the right
There is an intuitive thought that all human beings have equal way, would result in a Shakespeare play. That book would not be a
moral status, in particular, that they are all rightholders. Indeed, Shakespeare play just because it contains the correct words; those
the Universal Declaration of Human Rights explicitly states that words must be organized in the right way.
‘all human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights’. 8 There are good reasons to believe that all human beings have
Likewise, some philosophers have argued that the term ‘human the genetic basis for moral agency. Indeed, we know that all
normal functioning/developing human beings have this genetic
basis because they exercise moral agency or will exercise it; that
most comatose human beings have this genetic basis because
they have exercised moral agency; and that those with learning
5
Nayernia, K., Nolte, J., Michelmann, H. W., Lee, J. H., Rathsack, K., Drusenheimer, N., …
9
Engel, W. (2006). In vitro‐differentiated embryonic stem cells give rise to male gametes See, for example, Diamond, C. (1991). The importance of being human. Royal Institute of
that can generate offspring mice. Developmental Cell, 11, 125–132. Philosophy Supplement, 29, 35–62.; Williams, B. (2008). The human prejudice. In A. W.
6 Moore (Ed.), Philosophy as a humanistic discipline (pp. 135–154). Princeton, NJ: Princeton
For an overview of various positions, see Liao, S. M. (2008). Selecting children: The ethics
University Press.
of reproductive genetic engineering. Philosophy Compass, 3, 1–19.
10
7 Feinberg, J., & Levenbook, B B. (1993). Abortion. In T. Regan (Ed.), Matters of life and
Liao, S. M. (2010). The basis of human moral status. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 7, 159–
death (3rd ed.) (pp. 195–234). New York, NY: McGraw‐Hill.
179.; Liao, S. M. (2015). Human rights as fundamental conditions for a good life. In R.
11
Cruft, S. M. Liao, & M. Renzo (Eds.), Philosophical foundations of human rights (pp. 79–100). Singer, P. (1993). Practical ethics (2nd ed.). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press;
Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Griffin, J. (2008). On human rights. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
8 12
The United Nations. (1948). Universal Declaration of Human Rights. Liao (2010), op. cit. note 7.
|
100       LIAO

difficulties, such as children with Down’s syndrome, typically ex‐ beings qua human beings require if they are to be able to exercise
hibit some moral agency, which suggests that they also have this their essential capacities to engage in the basic activities. Some of
genetic basis. Hence, even if the species neutrality requirement these include the option to have social interaction, to acquire further
were valid, there may be ways to show that all human beings are knowledge, to evaluate and appreciate things, and to determine the
rightholders. direction of one’s life.
Suppose that this is correct. What human rights do human beings Having the fundamental conditions for pursuing a good life of
have? In my work, I have argued that human beings have human course cannot guarantee that an individual has a good life; no condi‐
rights to the fundamental conditions for pursuing a good life, where tion can guarantee this. Rather, these goods, capacities, and options
a good life is one spent in pursuing certain valuable, basic activi‐ enable human beings to pursue the basic activities. Also, many of the
13
ties. ‘Basic’ activities are activities that are important to a human fundamental conditions are all‐purpose conditions, in that they are
being qua human being’s life as a whole. Sunbathing, for example, is needed whatever basic activity one aims to pursue. For example, all
an activity, but is not a basic activity, because a human being qua human beings need food, water, the capacity to think, and the capac‐
human being’s life as a whole is not affected if a human being does ity to determine the direction of their lives, whatever basic activity
not go sunbathing. In addition, activities that are very important to they aim to pursue. Also, it is possible that some fundamental condi‐
an individual human being’s life as a whole may nevertheless not be tions are needed just for pursuing particular basic activities. For in‐
basic activities, because these activities may not be important to stance, the capacity to develop deep personal relationships may be
human beings qua human beings’ life as a whole. For instance, being needed only if one aims to pursue deep personal relationships. If so,
a professional philosopher is very important to my life as a whole. we can leave it open whether a particular individual will make use of
But being a professional philosopher is not a basic activity because it all the fundamental conditions when pursuing a particular kind of
is not an activity that is important to human beings qua human beings’ good life. Still, as I shall shortly argue, an individual should have all
life as a whole. Finally, basic activities are ones that if a human life did the fundamental conditions, because having all the fundamental
not involve the pursuit of any of them, then that life could not be a conditions would enable an individual to pursue any basic activity in
good life. An important implication of this point is that a human a good life. This could become important if, for example, an individ‐
being can have a good life by pursuing just some, and not all, of the ual changes his/her mind about pursuing a particular kind of good
basic activities. Some of the basic activities are as follows: deep per‐ life.14
sonal relationships with, for instance, one’s partner, friends, parents, In my view, these fundamental conditions for pursuing a good
children; knowledge of, for example, the workings of the world, of life ground human rights because having these conditions is of fun‐
oneself, of others; active pleasures such as creative work and play; damental importance to human beings, and because rights can offer
and passive pleasures such as appreciating beauty. powerful protection to those who possess them. The former is true,
From these basic activities, we can derive the contents of the because if anything is of fundamental importance to human beings,
fundamental conditions for pursuing a good life. The fundamental then pursuing a characteristically good human life is. It seems clear
conditions are various goods, capacities, and options that human that if we attach a certain importance to an end, we must attach
beings qua human beings need whatever else they qua individuals 14
In other words, while I am a disjunctivist about basic activities, i.e., I do not think that a
might need in order to pursue the basic activities. For example, the person has to pursue all the basic activities in order to have a good life, I am a conjunctivist
fundamental goods are resources that human beings qua human be‐ about fundamental conditions, i.e., I think that a person has a right to all the fundamental
conditions. Also, my notion of fundamental conditions might prompt some to think of Martha
ings need in order to sustain themselves corporeally, such as food, Nussbaum’s central capabilities approach; Nussbaum, M. C. (2011). Creating capabilities: The
water and air. The fundamental capacities are powers and abilities human development approach. Cambridge: Belknap Press; In Liao (2015), op. cit. note 7, I ex‐
plain in greater detail how the two views differ. All too briefly, the hallmark of Nussbaum’s
that human beings qua human beings require whatever else they
approach is her emphasis on our opportunities to choose to do certain things, i.e., capabili‐
qua individuals might require in order to pursue the basic activities. ties, rather than on what we actually choose to do, i.e., functionings. However, many human
rights cannot be adequately explained in terms of capabilities. For example, in the Universal
These capacities include the capacity to think, to be motivated by
Declaration of Human Rights (The United Nations, op. cit. note 8), there are a number of
facts, to know, to choose an act freely (liberty), to appreciate the human rights that protect our moral status as persons, i.e., status rights, such as the right to
worth of something, to develop interpersonal relationships, and to recognition everywhere as a person before the law (Article 6); the right to equal protection
before the law (Article 7); the right against arbitrary arrest, detention or exile (Article 9); the
have control of the direction of one’s life (autonomy). The funda‐ right to a fair and public hearing (Article 10); the right to be presumed innocent until proven
mental options are those social forms and institutions that human guilty (Article 11). Nussbaum’s approach seems to imply that one can sometimes choose not
to exercise these rights, since capabilities are concerned with our real opportunities to
choose. But it does not seem that one can sometimes choose whether or not to exercise
these rights. For instance, it does not seem that one can sometimes choose not to be recog‐
13
Liao (2015), op. cit. note 7. This approach assumes that human rights are those that we nized everywhere as a person before the law; choose not to have equal protection before the
have simply in virtue of being human, and therefore belongs to what might be called a law; choose to be arrested arbitrarily; choose to have an unfair hearing; and choose to be
naturalistic conception of human rights. In recent years, a new and purportedly alternative presumed guilty. Hence, capabilities do not seem particularly well suited to explain these
conception of human rights, the so‐called political conception of human rights, has become rights. In contrast, my approach can explain status rights. When we pursue the basic activi‐
increasingly popular. According to the political conception, the distinctive nature of ties, conflicts with others are bound to arise. If and when such conflicts arise, we need guar‐
human rights is to be understood in light of their role or function in modern international antees that we would be treated fairly and equally. Fair trial, presumption of innocence, equal
political practice. Elsewhere I have argued that the theoretical distance between the nat‐ protection before the law, not being arrested arbitrarily, and so on, serve to ensure that we
uralistic conception and the political conception is not as great as it has been made out to would be treated fairly and equally. As such, they are things that human beings qua human
be (Liao, S. M., & Etinson, A. (2012). Political and naturalistic conceptions of human rights: beings need whatever they qua individuals might need in order to pursue the basic activities.
A false polemic? Journal of Moral Philosophy, 9, 327–352.) As such, the approach I advocate can explain why there are these human rights.
LIAO |
      101

this importance to the (essential) means to this end. For example, if The distinction between modification and selection/creation is
we care about making a cake, then we must care about the (essen‐ normatively important because, in the case of modification, the re‐
tial) ingredients that would enter into making this cake such as flour, sulting being could later complain that she was harmed and that she
butter, sugar, eggs, and raising agents. Losing any of these essential could have been different if modification had not taken place.
ingredients is tantamount to losing the cake itself. Given this, since Modification therefore raises issues of narrative identity and per‐
pursuing a good life is of fundamental importance to human beings, sonal autonomy. In the case of selection/creation, the resulting
having the fundamental conditions for pursuing a good life must also being could not later complain that she was harmed and that she
be of fundamental importance to human beings. could have been otherwise, because she would not have existed if a
That rights can offer powerful normative protection to those different being had been selected/created.19
who possess them is well known.15 By their nature, rights secure the Of the different kinds of fundamental conditions, the fundamen‐
interests of the rightholders by requiring others, the duty bearers, to tal capacities are particularly relevant for the ethics of reproductive
perform certain services for the rightholders or not to interfere with genetic engineering. Here is a non‐exhaustive (and not uncontro‐
the rightholders’ pursuit of their essential interests. In addition, at versial) list of the fundamental capacities: the capacity to act, which
least on certain structural accounts of rights, rights typically prevent includes the five senses (sight, hearing, smell, touch, and taste);
the rightholders’ interests that ground rights from being part of a movement; reproductive capacity; the capacity to think; the capacity
first‐order utilitarian calculus. This means that if a rightholder has a to be motivated and to have emotions; the capacity to interact with
right to something, then typically no non‐right considerations can others and with one’s environment; and the capacity to be moral.
16
override the rightholder’s right to that thing. Finally, as some writ‐ Pulling these discussions together, we can derive at least four
ers have pointed out, because the rightholders are entitled to these claims for the ethics of reproductive genetic engineering.
services as a matter of rights, this means that the rightholders can
simply expect the services without requesting them.17 • Claim 1: Other things being equal, it is not permissible deliberately
Given the strong protection that rights can offer for the right‐ to create an offspring who will not have all the fundamental capac-
holders, and given the importance of having these fundamental ities. For example, given a choice between creating an offspring
conditions to human beings, it seems reasonable that human beings who will have the fundamental capacities and creating another off‐
have rights to these fundamental conditions. If this is correct, this spring who will not have the fundamental capacities, we should
provides us with an argument for the idea that human beings have choose the former rather than the latter. For instance, suppose that
human rights to the fundamental conditions for pursuing a good life. we have a choice between creating a healthy offspring and creating
another offspring who will develop Tay–Sachs disease. The human
rights approach says that we should choose to do the former rather
3 | A H U M A N R I G HT S A PPROAC H than the latter. Or, to take a more controversial case, suppose that
TO H U M A N R E PRO D U C TI V E G E N E TI C the capacity to hear is a fundamental capacity. After all, so many
ENGINEERING basic human activities such as listening to beautiful compositions by
Beethoven, a child’s laughter, or the chirping sounds of morning
Drawing on these two claims, I shall now develop a human rights birds depend on our being able to hear such that an argument can
approach to human reproductive genetic engineering. To do this, it is be made that this capacity is an all‐purpose, fundamental capac‐
helpful first to distinguish between modification, on the one hand, ity.20 If so, suppose that we have a choice between creating an off‐
and selection/creation on the other hand. Modification involves alter‐ spring who will have all the fundamental capacities and creating
ing certain genes in an existing embryo or gamete in order to obtain another offspring who will be deaf. The human rights approach
the desired genetic traits. Selection involves selecting certain gam‐ would say that we should choose the former rather than the latter.
etes or embryos that have the desired genetic traits. In the future, it • Claim 2: Suppose that an offspring who lacks some of the fun-
may be possible to create entire gametes or embryos for damental capacities is already created. It can be permissible to
18
selection. bring this offspring to term. Why is this? For one thing, on the
human rights approach, the offspring is a rightholder and there‐
fore has the same moral status as other human beings. Also, the
15
Rights could also have non‐instrumental importance in addition to having instrumental offspring may still have enough of other kinds of fundamental
importance.
capacities to be able to pursue some of the basic activities in
16
Dworkin, R. (1977). Taking rights seriously. London, UK: Duckworth.
a good life. Recall that one may not need all the fundamental
17
Feinberg, J. (1970). The nature and value of rights. In E. L. Bandman & B. Bandman (Eds.),
conditions to pursue some of the basic activities. To illustrate,
Bioethics and human rights: A reader for health professionals (pp. 19–31). Boston, MA: Little,
Brown. suppose that an offspring who will be deaf is already created and
18
A number of scientists have begun exploring the possibility of creating a synthetic 19
This is the so‐called non‐identity problem. Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford,
human genome, that is, using chemicals to manufacture all the DNA in human chromo‐
UK: Oxford University Press.
somes. Swetlitz, I. (2016, Oct 28). Synthetic human genome project releases its draft time‐
20
line. STAT. Available from: https://www.statnews.com/2016/10/28/synthetic‐human‐ge‐ I am not wedded to this example. So if a reader feels that hearing is not a fundamental
nome‐timeline/ [Accessed 11 June 2017] capacity, we can substitute hearing with some other example, e.g., the capacity to think.
102       | LIAO

suppose that hearing is a fundamental capacity. On the human 4 | CO M PA R I N G TH E H U M A N R I G HT S


rights approach, it can be permissible to select and bring this off‐ A PPROAC H W ITH OTH E R A PPROAC H E S
spring to term. The reason is that this offspring is a rightholder
and will have enough of other kinds of fundamental capacities To support the human rights approach further, let us compare it with
to be able to pursue some of the basic activities. Indeed, the some other notable approaches to reproductive genetic engineer‐
resulting offspring will still have the capacity to have emotions, ing. I shall not attempt to be exhaustive and I shall focus on ap‐
be able to move freely, be able to think, and so on. Hence, the proaches that accept that it can at least sometimes be permissible to
human rights approach implies that the claim that ‘it is not per‐ engage in reproductive genetic engineering. 23
missible deliberately to create an offspring who will not have all For instance, consider the libertarian approach, according to
the fundamental capacities’ and the claim that ‘if an offspring which it is morally permissible to create any kind of offspring we
who lacks some of the fundamental capacities is already created, like. 24 The libertarian approach seems too permissive. On this ap‐
it can be permissible to select and bring the offspring to term’ are proach, it would be permissible to create an offspring whose life will
compatible. be full of pain and suffering, e.g., a child with Tay–Sachs disease. In
• Claim 3: Other things being equal, it is not permissible to cause contrast, on the human rights approach, it would be impermissible
an existing offspring to lack some of the fundamental capacities. deliberately to create an offspring who will not have fundamental
Again, suppose that hearing is a fundamental capacity. It would capacities. This means that on the human rights approach, it would
not be permissible, for example, to use CRISPR to cause an off‐ not be permissible to create a child with Tay–Sachs disease.
spring to lack hearing genes. The reason is that human beings In addition, consider the wine capacity case: supposeNext, con‐
have human rights to the fundamental conditions for pursuing a sider the perfectionist approach, according to which there is a prima
good life. Given this, there is a duty not to cause a human being facie obligation to create an offspring who will have the best chance
to lack fundamental conditions. Since hearing is a fundamental of having the best life. 25 In my view, the perfectionist approach is
capacity, it follows that there is a duty not to cause a human being proves too much. 26 For one thing, suppose that being male or white
to lack hearing genes. or tall or heterosexual will provide the best chance of having the best
• Claim 4: Suppose that an offspring has defective genes for certain life in our society. The perfectionist approach implies that there is at
fundamental capacities. Suppose that it is possible to correct least a prima facie obligation to select an offspring with such charac‐
these defects. In some cases, it would be impermissible not to teristics. that you can create an offspring who will have the capac‐
correct these defects. For example, suppose that seeing is a fun‐ ity to enjoy very fine wine or another offspring who will have the
damental capacity and suppose that an offspring has congenital
capacity to enjoy super fine wine. Suppose that the offspring who
blindness. 21 Moreover, suppose that it is really easy to correct this
has the capacity to enjoy super fine wine will have the best chance
genetic defect; one just has to apply certain chemicals, which, let
of having the best life. The perfectionist approach implies that you
us suppose, have no other side effects. It seems that it would be
would have a prima facie obligation to create an offspring who has
impermissible not to correct this defect in such a case. The ratio‐
the capacity to enjoy super fine wine, which seems counterintui‐
nale is that human beings have human rights to the fundamental
conditions for pursuing a good life. In my view, this means that tive. In contrast, the human rights approach does not have these

there is a positive duty on the part of everyone to see to it that implications. On the human rights approach, other things being
human beings have all the fundamental conditions, especially equal, there are only moral obligations to create offsprings who
when the duty is not too demanding. 22 In this case, it is stipulated will have fundamental capacities (should one decide to create any
that it is not too demanding to see to it that the offspring has all offspring at all). Being male or white or tall or heterosexual is not a
the fundamental capacities (one just has to apply some chemi‐ fundamental capacity. Nor is being able to enjoy super fine wine a
cals). Given this, it seems that there would be a duty to correct the fundamental capacity. As such, on the human rights approach,
defects in this offspring by applying the chemicals, and that it there are no obligations to create offsprings with such traits.
would be impermissible not to do so. Lastly, consider the life worth living approach, according to which it
is morally permissible to create an offspring whose life is worth liv‐
As one can see, these claims primarily provide a ‘lower bound’
ing. ‘A life worth living’ can be understood as a life that contains
of when reproductive genetic engineering would be permissible. Is
23
For critical assessment of approaches that are more restrictive, see Liao, op. cit. note 6.
there an upper bound? Would it be permissible, for example, to create
24
In Children of Choice, John Robertson defends a strong procreative liberty (Robertson, J.
an offspring who will be superintelligent or greatly enhanced in some A. (1994). Children of choice: Freedom and the new reproductive technologies. Princeton, NJ:
other way? There is not enough space here to explore this issue, but Princeton University Press.) There are questions about whether Robertson or anyone else
would endorse something as extreme as the libertarian approach. Still, it is useful to men‐
as far as I can tell, other things being equal, the human rights approach
tion the libertarian approach in order to contrast it with the life worth living approach,
does not in principle object to the creation of such an offspring. which we shall discuss shortly.
25
21
Again, the reader is welcome to use a different example if the reader believes that being Savulescu, J., & Kahane, G. (2009). The moral obligation to create children with the best
able to see is not a fundamental capacity. chance of the best life. Bioethics, 23, 274–290.
26
22
Liao, S. M. (2015). The right to be loved. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, Chapter 5. See also Liao, op. cit. note 6.
LIAO |
      103

some positive values and the amount of negative values that this life Relatedly, suppose that an offspring has congenital deafness and
contains, e.g., pain, is not sufficient to negate the positive values that it would be very easy to correct the genes that undermine the devel‐
this life has. For instance, Jonathan Glover asks, ‘Can it be right to opment of hearing in this offspring (e.g., by applying certain chemi‐
bring a child into the world so long as we expect the child to have a cals). On the life worth living approach, it would be permissible not
quality of life at least at the zero line just above that “very terrible” to correct this defect, as long as the resulting offspring can still have
level?’ His answer is that ‘how can it be that we owed it to the child a life worth living (and provided that this is done early enough so that
to prevent his or her life?’27 Likewise, some writers in the literature the offspring does not experience transition costs).31 Again, as we
on disability, who believe that disability is not in itself something that have seen, on the human rights approach, it would be impermissible
makes people’s lives go worse, may also be amenable to this not to correct this defect, given that it would be easy to do so.
28
approach. Here it is worth discussing how the human rights approach dif‐
An implication of the life worth living approach is that if an off‐ fers from both the perfectionist approach and the life worth living
spring with a particular disability has already been created, it can be approach. The perfectionist approach and the life worth living ap‐
permissible to continue to bring this offspring to term, as long as this proach are both in some ways concerned with an individual’s well‐
offspring can have a life worth living. In contrast, some advocates of being, in particular, how well an individual’s whole life can go. Indeed,
the perfectionist approach have argued that it would be wrong to the perfectionist approach is interested in the offspring’s having the
continue to bring such an offspring to term, given that the offspring best life possible, while the life worth living approach is interested
would not have the best chance of having the best life. 29 in the offspring’s attaining a minimally decent life. In contrast, the
On this point, the human rights approach sides with the life human rights approach is concerned with an agent’s powers and
worth living approach. The reason is that on the human rights ap‐ abilities, that is, the fundamental capacities, to do certain things at
proach, an offspring with disability would still be a rightholder and particular moments in a life. Having these fundamental capacities
may have enough of other kinds of fundamental capacities such that cannot guarantee that an individual would have a life worth living
the offspring can pursue some of the basic activities. Given this, on let alone the best life possible, since someone with the full set of
the human rights approach, it would be permissible to continue to fundamental capacities could end up in a car crash the next day or do
bring this offspring to term. terrible things with those capacities. Hence, having these fundamen‐
Still, there are several differences between the life worth living tal capacities does not have direct implications for an individual’s
approach and the human rights approach. One difference pertains to well‐being. What having the fundamental capacities does is enable
when an offspring has not yet been created. The life worth living ap‐ an individual to pursue the basic activities at particular moments in
proach implies that it can be permissible to create an offspring who a life.
lacks certain fundamental capacities as long as the resulting off‐
spring can have a life worth living. For instance, suppose that hear‐
ing is a fundamental capacity. The life worth living approach implies 5 | CONCLUSION
that it can be permissible to create an offspring who will be deaf,
since those who are deaf can have lives worth living. On the human Advances in reproductive genetic engineering have the potential to
rights approach, it would be impermissible deliberately to create an transform human lives. Not only do they promise to allow us to se‐
offspring who lacks a certain fundamental capacity such as hearing. lect children free of diseases, they can also enable us to select chil‐
A starker difference between the life worth living approach and dren with desirable traits. In this paper, I outlined what I call a human
the human rights approach pertains to certain cases of modification. rights approach and I argued that this approach allows us to make at
In particular, on the life worth living approach, it seems permissible least four claims about reproductive genetic engineering:
to cause an embryo to lack certain fundamental capacities such as
hearing, as long as the resulting offspring can still have a life worth 1. It is not permissible deliberately to create an offspring who
living (and provided that this is done early enough so that the off‐ will not have all the fundamental capacities.
30
spring does not experience transition costs). As we have seen, on 2. If an offspring who lacks some of the fundamental capacities is
the human rights approach, such an action would be impermissible, already created, it can be permissible to bring the offspring to
because there is a duty not to cause a human being to lack funda‐ term.
mental conditions such as hearing. 3. Other things being equal, it is not permissible to cause an existing
offspring to lack some of the fundamental capacities.
27
Glover, J. (2006). Choosing children: The ethical dilemmas of genetic intervention. Oxford, 4. If it is possible to correct certain defects in the fundamental ca‐
UK: Oxford University Press., p. 52. However, because it is difficult to determine when a pacities of an offspring, and if it is not too demanding to do so, it
life is not worth living, Glover eventually proposes that what parents should aim at is to
have only children with ‘a decent chance of a good life’ (Ibid: 63). can be impermissible not to do so.
28
See, for example, Barnes, E. (2016). The minority body: A theory of disability. Oxford, UK:
Oxford University Press.
29
Savulescu & Kahane, op. cit. note 25.
30 31
See, for example, Barnes, op. cit. note 28. Ibid.
104       | LIAO

I also argued that the human rights approach is more plausible C O N FL I C T O F I N T E R E S T


than the libertarian approach, the perfectionist approach, and the
The author declares no conflict of interest.
life worth living approach. A more comprehensive discussion of the
ethics of reproductive genetic engineering would need to consider
ORCID
other approaches.32 Still, I hope to have shown that the human rights
approach offers a promising new way of thinking about when and S. Matthew Liao  http://orcid.org/0000-0001-6579-8656
whether reproductive genetic engineering is permissible and that
this approach deserves further consideration in the lively debate S. Matthew Liao is Arthur Zitrin Professor of Bioethics and
about designing humans. Director of the Center for Bioethics at New York University. He
is the author of The right to be loved (Oxford University Press,
2015) and over 60 articles in philosophy and bioethics. He has
AC K N OW L E D G E M E N T S
given TED and TEDx talks in New York and Geneva, and his work
I would like to thank Frances Kamm, Sarah Gokhale, Wibke has been featured in the New York Times, The Atlantic, The
Gruetjen, two anonymous referees at Bioethics, and the audience Guardian, the BBC, Harper’s Magazine, Sydney Morning Herald,
at the Inaugural Arthur Zitrin Lecture at New York University, Scientific American, Newsweek and other media outlets.
NYU Shanghai, the Center for Research on Ethical, Legal & Social
Implications of Psychiatric, Neurologic & Behavioral Genetics at
Columbia University, the New York Bar Association, the Colloquium
How to cite this article: Liao SM. Designing humans: A human
on Ability and Enhancement at University of Richmond, and the New
rights approach. Bioethics. 2019;33:98–104. https://doi.
York Hall of Science for their helpful comments on earlier versions
org/10.1111/bioe.12519
of this article.

32
I have assessed some other approaches in Liao, op. cit. note 6.

Potrebbero piacerti anche