Sei sulla pagina 1di 11

Everyday Surface Aesthetic Qualities: "Neat," "Messy," "Clean," "Dirty"

Author(s): Thomas Leddy


Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 53, No. 3 (Summer, 1995), pp.
259-268
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/431351
Accessed: 22-01-2020 16:02 UTC

REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/431351?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This content downloaded from 190.60.231.2 on Wed, 22 Jan 2020 16:02:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THOMAS LEDDY

Everyday Surface Aesthetic Qualities:

"Nerat, Ad"1\4essy," "C lean,"d "Dirtys"

In the literature of aesthetics there are numer- virtually no discussion of this class of proper-
ous lists of aesthetic qualities.' These lists al- ties in the aesthetics literature.3
most invariably leave off an entire set of items A number of questions will need to be ad-
which will be the topic of this paper. The itemsdressed. Are these really aesthetic qualities?
in their adjectival form are "neat," "messy," How do these qualities stand up against defini-
"clean/unclean,)" "dirty,)" "sloppy,)" "6filthy,tions
" of aesthetic quality that have been offered
"ordered/disordered" (although something can in the past? Do they really form a group, and
be ordered in complex ways, I am referring to a what is it that holds the group together? In par-
certain low-level order, as in "I want these chairs ticular, do everyday surface aesthetic quality
lined up in an ordered fashion"), "cluttered/ terms refer to a different kind of quality in non-
uncluttered," "cleared/not cleared," "blemished/ art contexts than they do in art contexts? What
unblemished," "attractive/unattractive" (again, role do these terms play in artistic experience
something can be attractive or "look good" be- and evaluation? Finally, what is the difference
cause it has other, grander aesthetic qualities: between literal and metaphorical application of
that is, it is beautiful, sublime, or elegant, but, these terms, and how are they applied at differ-
as with "order," there is a kind of base line or ent ontological levels? I will address the latter
low-level attractiveness that I wish to refer to questions in this group first.
here), "pure/impure." Noteworthy about these
qualities is that they are found frequently in I. APPLICATION TO ART AND

everyday life. Moreover, they are concerned not EVERYDAY LIFE CONTEXTS

with the underlying structure or substance of


things but with what might be called surface Most discussions of aesthetic qualities begin
properties. By "surface" I mean what does not with a discussion of art. Although many aes-
heavily influence underlying form or sub- theticians insist that aesthetic qualities are not
stance: this can either be actual physical surface limited to the arts, even those thinkers generally
or some other aspect of the object which may take the arts as the primary focus of their dis-
be distinguished from underlying form or sub- cussion. This explains somewhat the neglect of
stance.2 I will call the listed group "everyday everyday surface aesthetic qualities, since these
surface aesthetic qualities." are not primarily the qualities by which we
My thesis is quite radical. I am not simply praise works of art. However, some everyday
arguing for the recognition of one or two ne- surface aesthetic qualities, such as "neat,"
glected qualities. What we have here is an en- "clean," and "cluttered," do have application in
tire class of neglected properties, one that may the arts. In the visual arts, for example, we
be equal in importance to the class of expres- speak of clean lines, clean edges, muddy color,
sive properties, of which there has been so much neat construction, and cluttered space. Of course,
discussion in the recent history of aesthetics. the lines in a visual work are not literally clean:
Yet, with the possible exceptions of Allen Carl- literal cleanliness has to do with the features of
son's discussion of roadside clutter and David the work qua physical object. A painting is lit-
Novitz's recent account of grooming, there is erally clean if it is free of dirt, dust, food parti-

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53:3 Summer 1995

This content downloaded from 190.60.231.2 on Wed, 22 Jan 2020 16:02:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
260 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

cles, and such. Having clean lines, it seems, is would follow that since aesthetic qualities are
metaphorical. Thus something can be literally perceptual then any aesthetic applications of
clean and fail to have clean lines, or have clean the term "clean" would be secondary. Sure,
lines and fail to be literally clean.4 there are cases in which something is unclean
Yet are we sure where the literal ends and the in a non-perceptual way, for instance, gold that
metaphorical begins? "Clean" could be taken to has impurities or water that has bacteria. But
simply mean "clear or free of that which is we learn the concept of cleanness as children
unwanted," i.e., of impurities, adulterations, by how things look and smell. This gives the
imperfections, blemishes, and other unwanted perceptual meaning of "clean" a certain devel-
things. Cleaning off the table is often simply a opmental primacy. It also seems to privilege
matter of clearing it of materials irrelevant to "neat" and "clean" over "messy" and "dirty."
the next project. "Clean" does not have to refer Yet, interestingly, despite our early training,
simply to absence of dirt. Absence of dirt is "messiness" is not necessarily a negative trait.
neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition That abstract expressionists' brush strokes are
for a room being clean, since a room may have (or at least initially look) messy, and minimalist
a dirt floor. We even speak of clean dirt! It is brush strokes are (or at least initially look) neat,
true that cleaning a painting means getting dirt does not mean that abstract expressionism is
and other unwanted substances off of the sur- worse than minimalism. Perhaps this is because
face. But this is not the only application of the the surface messiness of abstract expressionist
term "cleaning" to painting. One can also speak paintings only hides an underlying order. Thus
of cleaning up the lines during the process of we might speak of de Kooning as having clean
composition. It is just not clear that one mean- edges or crisp lines even though his paintings
ing is literal and the other metaphorical. More- initially look messy. Part of the attraction of
over, both meanings of "clean," in this in- abstract expressionist painting may be due to
stance, are "aesthetic" in the sense that both this tension between surface messiness and un-
have to do with perceptual properties that give derlying neatness.
or do not give pleasure. Architecture provides another kind of case.
This leads me to suggest that there are differ- Modernist architects claimed that their work,
ent domains in which everyday surface aes- with its clean lines and uncluttered surfaces,
thetic quality terms may be applied. Cleaning was superior to the work of the eclectic schools
off dirt from a painting is a matter of physical that dominated nineteenth-century architecture.
surface aesthetic qualities; cleaning up lines or Whatever the case it is certain that everyday
colors within a painting is a matter of art sur- surface aesthetic qualities are not only relevant
face aesthetic qualities. But what about clean- to aesthetics in general but also to the various
ing up the composition of a painting or a musi- arts.
cal work? Composition seems to be well below In a letter, Stan Godlovitch has given me the
the surface features of a work of art. Or is it? following examples from music:
Ontological layerings might be like the layer-
ings of an onion: each layer, even the inner Cleanliness has musical applications particularly in
ones, can have its own surface. The features of jazz and a propos playing style, Joe Pass is consid-
the composition which are cleaned might still ered a "dirty" player because many of his passages
be considered surface features in that they are are "dirty." This means that he is pretty sloppy with
surface features of the composition. There is tonal clarity and abides buzzes and other distracting
something that underlies those features, a more noises which come from a less than "clean" execu-
basic form of the composition, which is cleaned tion. "Clean" players give you all the notes crystal
up. To say that something can be neatened or clear, well articulated, under control. Why is Joe
cleaned implies that there is something underly- Pass's playing accepted? Well, although, technically,
ing that is worthy of neatening/cleaning. dirty playing is sloppy playing and needs cleaning
Someone might want to claim that the literal up, aesthetically dirty playing can have an appeal all
meaning of "clean" has nothing to do with per- of its own much like certain otherwise crappy voices
ceptual properties-that something can be clean [like Jimmy Durante or Louis Armstrong] which win
or not regardless of how it looks or smells. It appeal for their timbral uniqueness. No one plays

This content downloaded from 190.60.231.2 on Wed, 22 Jan 2020 16:02:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Leddy Everyday Surface Aesthetic Qualities 261

dirty the way Joe Pass does, and, he is otherwise so A possible explanation of why everyday sur-
interesting, one would actually feel something was face aesthetic qualities may have been ne-
wrong if he were to clean up his act! This makes for glected by aestheticians may relate to gender
various pseudo-paradoxes. It carries through, I may socialization and stereotyping. The home and
add, to flamenco playing where the authentic original yard are traditionally the domains of the house-
performers do not have the smooth clean execution wife and servant. There are househusbands and
of classical players who turn to flamenco [e.g., Pepe male servants, but most commonly this role
Romero]. For the true aficionados, the "dirty" sound goes to a woman. The office in its aesthetic
of the authentic players is preferable because it lends dimension is traditionally the world of the sec-
the music a raw coarse unrefined energy which some retary, again most commonly a woman. The
people think reveals the true soul or spirit of fla- teaching of personal grooming is traditionally
menco. Perhaps that is true of jazz too; i.e., that clean the domain of the mother. The housewife, ser-
execution represents a value of an anti-folk pro- vant, secretary, and mother are the ones who
aristocratic and pro-technocratic conception of per- are generally concerned with the messy, the
formance which, by its very studied quality, robs the cluttered, the clean, and the neat. I am not sug-
execution of genuine spontaneity. [This is to say that gesting that this is as it should be. Feminists
to imitate dirty playing is as bad as trying to clean it have well argued that these activities should be
up.] And then there is Jimi Hendrix who introduced shared equally between the sexes. Nor am I
the aesthetics of dirt into rock. There are all sorts of suggesting that men never engage in cleaning,
devices called Fuzz Boxes which will dirty up other- neatening, dusting, and so on. However, men
wise clean guitar sounds-for those who just cannot who do have jobs which are primarily con-
dirty it up on their own.5 cerned with these activities, for example, gar-
bagemen, often have low social status. (A possi-
Terms associated strongly with performances ble exception is someone whose job is to clean
of works of art may be added to our list of every- up a corporate structure, but that is not an ex-
day surface aesthetic quality terms. "Sloppy," ample of concern for surface perceptual fea-
"careless/careful," "shoddy," "slipshod," "pre - tures.) This leads to the possibility that aes-
cise/imprecise," "meticulous" are all related to thetics has ignored everyday surface aesthetic
"neat" and "messy" and may all be applied to qualities because of their association with what
performances. They may also be used to de- has been called "women's work." If so, then a
scribe works of art and objects of craft in gen- recognition of the importance of these qualities
eral (a bricklayer's work may be shoddy, slip- should form a part of feminist aesthetics. Per-
shod, imprecise). They may refer to perceptual haps it is a form of sexism to think of these
properties of a performance or work, or to the qualities as outside the noble domain of aes-
activity of the performer, artist, or craftsperson. thetics.
Yet where we find everyday surface aesthetic Women in our culture in the 1950s and the
qualities most often discussed is in practical 1960s were taught to be obsessed with neatness
life: in the home, the yard, the workplace, the and cleanness. Men of the same generation were
shops, personal attire, and personal grooming. encouraged to ignore these things or delegate
Rooms become messy, cluttered. They must be them to others while concentrating on matters
cleaned, cleared, set straight, tidied up. Kitchens that could gain them success in the business or
and bathrooms can be unclean or "filthy." professional worlds. Today it is possible for
Floors must be washed when dirty and unat- some of those same women to gain some aes-
tractive. Shelves may be ordered or disordered. thetic delight in observing clutter in their homes.
Desks can be cluttered. Schedules and organi- I am not speaking here of the situation in which
zational plans can be messy. Products can be a woman thinks "Isn't it great that I no longer
presented neatly and attractively or not. Clothes feel compelled to clean up," which would be
run from messy and dirty to neat and clean. merely consistent with tolerating clutter, but of
People too can be messy or neat, clean or un- the situation in which a woman, or a man for
clean. They are considered messy and unclean that matter, notices the clutter and perceptually
if their clothes, grooming, possessions, prod- enjoys it.7 As I have suggested above, messiness
ucts, or work stations have these qualities.6 and clutter are not necessarily negative aesthetic

This content downloaded from 190.60.231.2 on Wed, 22 Jan 2020 16:02:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
262 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

qualities, although they are usually cast in this rior decorator are responsible for another do-
role. main or ontological layer to which the terms
Another plausible explanation for the neglect "neat" and "clean" may be applied.9
of everyday surface aesthetic qualities is simply It is arguable that neatening and cleaning
that aesthetics has been mainly associated with contribute to a room being more balanced, har-
transcendent experience afforded by great works monious, and integrated. Perhaps this happens
of art. Everyday surface aesthetic qualities have not simply through revealing these properties
been neglected for the same reason as aesthetic but through clarifying them. But, again, that
qualities associated with body decoration, kitsch, places everyday surface aesthetic qualities on
and the design of everyday objects. another level than Hermeren's gestalt qualities,
although related to them.
II. ARE THEY AESTHETIC QUALITIES? Hermeren's gestalt qualities are generally more
complex (at least on a perceptual level) than
But are the items I have listed really aesthetic everyday surface aesthetic qualities.10 They are
qualities? As I noted in the beginning, they are more complex because they are structural, hav-
virtually never mentioned in the main works ing to do with the interrelation of parts along
on aesthetic qualities. Goran Hermeren's recent more than one dimension. Balance and harmony
book The Nature of Aesthetic Qualities distin- are special kinds of order that require complex
guishes among five kinds (I will give two ex- skills to achieve. Think of what is needed to
amples of each): emotion qualities ("somber," achieve harmony in a musical work. Harmony
"gay"); behavior qualities ("bold," "nervous"); in music is a matter of combining parts, often
gestalt qualities ("unified," "disorganized"); from two or more different lines, to form an
taste qualities ("elegant," "delightful"); and af- ordered and pleasing whole. The term "integra-
fective qualities ("funny," "glaring"). It might tion" is, in turn, closely related to "harmony":
be argued that although Hermeren does not men- it is generally defined in terms of harmonious
tion them, everyday surface aesthetic qualities composition. Achieving balance, harmony, or
can simply be added to the category of gestalt integration in a work of art or some other thing
qualities. Here is the rest of his list of gestalt is quite different and considerably more diffi-
qualities: "coherent," "tightly knit," "com- cult than simply creating order by "straighten-
plete," "simple," "balanced," "harmonious," ing up" or "putting away." Yet these are the
"integrated," "chaotic," and "consonant."8 But typical actions involved in making something
note that most of these qualities, i.e., "com- neat. By contrast, the term "chaotic," insofar as
plete," "balanced," "harmonious," and "inte- it refers to something which is utterly disor-
grated" refer to structure. This is why they are dered, points us to a situation in which all struc-
called "gestalt" qualities. The Oxford English ture is lacking. Although it is not as clearly a
Dictionary describes "gestalt" as "an integrated gestalt term as "harmony" and "integrated," it
perceptual structure or unity conceived as func- is also not an everyday surface aesthetic quality
tionally more than the sum of its parts." Every- term since everyday surface aesthetic qualities
day surface aesthetic qualities border on the require an underlying structure to be neatened,
structural, and sometimes edge into it, but they messed up, cleaned, or dirtied."
are mainly qualities of surface. That distinction Cleanness is even further from Hermeren's
is confirmed by the fact that one of the main gestalt properties than neatness. Something can
functions of neatening and cleaning is revela- be clean without having any of those properties,
tion of underlying form or structure. For exam- and something can have all of them and not be
ple, neatening up or cleaning a facade or a room clean. Yet, like neatness, cleaning can reveal
may reveal an underlying structure with its own underlying structure. Cleaning up a building,
aesthetic properties. The architect and interior sculpture, or painting usually does this.
decorator are responsible for that structure, not Someone might reply that aesthetics has to
the neatener or cleaner. But this does not mean do primarily with art, and that although there
that "neatness" and "cleanness" are inapplica- are uses for everyday surface aesthetic quality
ble to what architects and interior decorators terms in the artworld, they do not pertain pri-
do. As I have indicated, the architect and inte- marily to art and are therefore not aesthetic

This content downloaded from 190.60.231.2 on Wed, 22 Jan 2020 16:02:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Leddy Everyday Surface Aesthetic Qualities 263

terms. It is true that these terms do not refer that others cannot. Those people often appreci-
primarily to art. It is also true that qualities ate neatness in ways that others cannot. True,
found primarily in art have a characteristic which people often disagree strongly about whether or
everyday surface aesthetic qualities do not share: not a room is neat. But this need not lead to
perceptual complexity. It is because of this com- total relativism. We generally distinguish be-
plexity that we have professional critics in art tween mere personal preference (whether you
and not in room neatness. (Although amateur like to live in a neat house) and matters of fact
critics of room neatness abound!) (whether the house really is neat). We will of-
One well-known writer on aesthetic qualities, ten, to use Kant's term, demand that others see
Frank Sibley, insists that aesthetic terms or con- the room as we see it: neat or messy.12
cepts are not limited to artistic discourse but may Just as with elegance, some people are good
be used in "everyday life." So everyday surface judges of neatness.13 These people can point
aesthetic quality terms could be aesthetic terms, out features that allow us to see the neatness or
at least on his account. However, like Hermeren, messiness that we did not see before. Others
Sibley fails to mention any of the terms I have seem to be neatness-blind. In any cooperative
listed, even though he does include such unusual household there is a housemate who is messier
items as "flaccid," "weakly," and "washed out" than others. That person may nonetheless insist
in his list of aesthetic terms. Perhaps this is be- that he or she is neat. The others may say that
cause everyday surface aesthetic quality terms this person lacks a certain perceptiveness, that
are not found primarily in artistic discourse. Whyhe or she is insensitive to mess or clutter. Some-
not just say that some aesthetic qualities are one could also lack sensitivity to dirt, filth, and
found primarily in art, and others primarily in grime. Such a person would be cleanness-blind.
everyday life? Moreover, neatness and cleanness, or cleanli-
A definition of "aesthetic quality" would be ness (the disposition to clean up), are often used
useful at this point. Although Sibley does not as gauges of taste. Persons who care about neat-
give such a definition, he does give some char- ness and cleanness often see persons who do
acteristics of what he calls "aesthetic concepts": not as tasteless. Ironically, people who care
aesthetic concepts are (1) often based on, or about maintaining a certain level of clutter in
linked to, appeal to non-aesthetic concepts, (2) their homes, offices, desks, and attire often see
perceptual: a matter of "noticing" and "seeing," neatness or cleanliness in others as a sign of
(3) determined by taste perceptiveness or sensi- lack of taste.
tivity (by "taste" Sibley simply means the abil- Sibley also notes that there are degrees of
ity to discern the aesthetic qualities in things), taste, from rudimentary to refined, and that
and (4) not condition- or rule-governed: they most people learn easily how to make rudimen-
cannot be defined in terms of necessary and suf- tary aesthetic attributions.14 Two examples he
ficient conditions-nor do they have sufficient gives of such attributions are "warm" colors
conditions alone. Sibley also insists that we can- and "gay" pictures. "Neat" and "clean," al-
not derive the presence of these qualities from though not clearly metaphorical like "warm"
the presence of specific non-aesthetic qualities. and "gay," may be rudimentary in his sense.
Let us apply these points to "neatness." Neat- Sibley distinguishes between rudimentary attri-
ness is certainly related to non-aesthetic prop- butions and ones that "more obviously deserve
erties, for instance, the actual physical proper- to be called aesthetic." But why are the more
ties of the neatened room. We sometimes say rudimentary attributions less deserving of the
"The room is messy because there are socks on name "aesthetic"? Sibley does not say.
the floor," or "In order to be neat the clothes Finally, there are no absolute rules by which
need to be lined up straight." Neatness is also we can resolve disputes over the application of
perceptual. We see that the room is neat. But it everyday surface aesthetic quality terms. There
is not perceptual in the straightforward way are no necessary and sufficient conditions for
that "red" is perceptual. Neatness is perceptual determining that something is neat, nor any set
in the way that "elegant" is perceptual: it is a of relevant features some subset of which is
matter of "taste" in Sibley's sense of that term. sufficient for application of the concept. One
Some people are able to notice neatness in ways thing is neat for one set of reasons, another for

This content downloaded from 190.60.231.2 on Wed, 22 Jan 2020 16:02:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
264 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

another set. Of course, we can give specific cleaned, we simply appreciate the cleanness of
stipulative definitions of neatness for specific it, particularly if we have just cleaned it. There
contexts. A parent may say: "By neat I mean can be considerable pleasure in contemplating
that everything is off of the floors." But this is something cleaned with great effort. What is
not the same as a definition in terms of neces- appreciated is not simply the object cleaned but
sary and sufficient conditions. that plus a combination of process and product:
It might be argued that neatness, messiness, the cleaning up and the cleaned nature of the
cleanness, and dirtiness are non-aesthetic qual- object cleaned.
ities since their main domain is the merely prac-
tical, and the aesthetic is non-practical. True, III. CLEANING ONE S ROOM AS

our concern for neatness, cleanness, and the un- AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE

blemished is often not aesthetically motivated.


Neatness in our desks, files, computer files, and Monroe Beardsley describes five symptoms of
rooms often helps us to accomplish our goals aesthetic experience. These include object di-
more effectively. Cleanliness prevents disease. rectedness, felt freedom, detached affect, active
Grocery customers are more likely to buy un- discovery, and a sense of wholeness. He thinks
blemished fruits. But, as we have seen, not all that the first is a necessary condition, and that
cases of application of the term "neatness" or three of the others must be present if we are to
"cleanness" are oriented to practical goals. More- have aesthetic experience. Presumably, aes-
over, practical goals are often entwined with thetic qualities are qualities which produce at
aesthetic matters. For example, unblemished least some of these symptoms.
fruits sell more readily because they are more Let us look at cleaning one's room and con-
aesthetically pleasing. (But note also that what templating the cleaned nature of the room (or
the general populace may find to be a blemish the room-as-cleaned) in terms of these symp-
in a piece of fruit may be considered an attrac- toms. (I will assume that the two acts are as-
tion to others. Thus "blemished" apples might pects of one overall experience.) Object direct-
sell better in communities that are sensitive to edness: The object of the aesthetic experience is
possible ecological damage caused by processes the room-as-cleaned. Felt freedom: Whereas
used to insure the clean appearance of an apple. cleaning one's room is usually thought of as a
The apples may even come to look better to chore, there is often a felt sense of freedom
these people. Thus, moral as well as practical when we contemplate the cleaned room. Beards-
issues enter into our aesthetic discriminations at ley describes the aesthetic way of seeing as one
this level.) in which "there is a relaxation, an absence of
Consider this further argument for the status strain, but also a kind of visual fulfillment." 16
of these qualities as aesthetic qualities. We often Contemplating a neatened and cleaned room
think of positive aesthetic qualities as percep- has this effect. Detached affect: There need not
tual qualities which please us in the apprehen- be a strong affect connected with cleaning one's
sion of them and of negative aesthetic qualities room or with contemplating something that is
as ones which do the opposite. When someone neat, clean, ordered, or unblemished. Someone
who values neatness looks at a neat room, partic- who contemplates the neatness of a room might
ularly after it has been "neatened" or "cleaned well do this in a disinterested way so that the
up," he or she will experience a certain pleasure room is "set at a distance." Active discovery: "A
in apprehending that neatness. So it would seem sense of actively exercising constructive powers
that, on this definition, the qualities of "neat," of the mind, of being challenged by a variety of
"messy," etc., are aesthetic qualities. potentially conflicting stimuli to try to make
It might be said that in the case of cleanness them cohere ... a sense of achieving intel-
what is appreciated is not the cleanness itself ligibility."'7 Although we sometimes discover
but the aesthetic qualities of the object cleaned. things in the process of cleaning our rooms
It is true that when a Monet painting is cleaned ("There is the library book I failed to turn in!"),
we are better able to appreciate the underlying this is probably not what Beardsley intended.
structure and the brilliance of the colors. How- Nonetheless, the process of cleaning one's room
ever, it is often the case that when something is may include a low-level sense of active discov-

This content downloaded from 190.60.231.2 on Wed, 22 Jan 2020 16:02:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Leddy Everyday Surface Aesthetic Qualities 265

ery insofar as one is challenged by choices con- But perhaps everyday surface aesthetic qual-
cerning what is to go where. Certainly the room ity terms refer to complex properties when they
becomes more intelligible as a result of the pro- are applied to works of art even though they do
cess. Sense of wholeness: "A sense of integra- not refer to complex properties in non-art con-
tion as a person." Many people report an in- texts. Up to now I have assumed that everyday
creased level of integration after they have surface aesthetic quality terms refer to the same
cleaned their rooms, desks, or files. There is a kinds of qualities when they are used in art
sense of being ready for the next task. The level contexts as when they are used in non-art ev-
of sense of personal integration may not be very eryday contexts. It might be countered, how-
great, but it might be greater than what we get ever, that in the context of artworld discourse
from seeing some good paintings, movies, or when someone says that a line is "clean" this
dances. claim comes with a number of connotative re-
Objections may be raised against some of verberations, suggesting perhaps that the work
these points (for instance, the one about active in which the line occurs, or at least a significant
discovery): however Beardsley requires only part of that work, is harmonious and integrated.
that three out of the four symptoms be present, I accept this modification of my thesis, with the
including the first one, for us to have an aes- understanding that everyday surface aesthetic
thetic experience. So, cleaning one's room and quality terms still refer primarily to non-complex
contemplating it as cleaned seems to be an aes- properties. It follows then that if these terms
thetic experience on Beardsley's definition, al- can refer to complex perceptual qualities in art
though probably not a profound one. And aes- contexts then they would, in these instances,
thetic experiences are experiences of aesthetic refer to complex regional qualities, which would
qualities. also be, on Beardsley's view, aesthetic qualities.
In another of his articles Beardsley argues
that aesthetic qualities must be regional quali- IV. CAN EVERYDAY SURFACE AESTHETIC

ties which may serve as a basis for aesthetic QUALITIES EXEMPLIFY?


evaluation.18 A regional quality is defined as a
quality that a complex object has as a result of Nelson Goodman proposes four symptoms of
the relation between its parts. Above, I argued aesthetic: syntactic density, semantic density,
that although everyday surface aesthetic quali- syntactic repleteness, and exemplification.19
ties may be used for aesthetic evaluation, they Non-art everyday surface aesthetic qualities do
are unlike gestalt qualities in that they are not not show any of the first three symptoms. How-
perceptually complex. But Beardsley has not ever, I will argue that they may show the fourth.
argued that the regional quality itself must be Goodman's symptoms of the aesthetic are actu-
complex. Many everyday surface aesthetic qual- ally symptoms of the artistic aesthetic: they are
ities are qualities of objects which themselves characteristics of symbol systems, and Good-
are complex. Still, it is arguable that everyday man's special interest is the symbol systems used
surface aesthetic qualities are not qualities that in artistic production. Everyday surface aes-
a complex object has as a result of a complex thetic qualities are not constituted by symbol
relation between parts-and that is perhaps systems, so it is not surprising that they fail to
what Beardsley meant. If so, then the qualities I have the first three symptoms. Goodman insists
have described would not be aesthetic qualities that the first three features call for "maximum
on this Beardsleyan account of aesthetic quali- sensitivity of discrimination." Although neatness
ties. Neatness is a matter of relatively simple calls for some sensitivity of discrimination, it
relations between parts. If my pants are hung so does not call for a maximum.
that there are no inappropriate creases, and the There is, however, a possible argument that
lines of the legs are parallel, then my pants are everyday surface aesthetic qualities can exem-
hung neatly. Cleanness may also be a quality of plify in Goodman's sense. Exemplification, for
a complex object, but it is generally not seen as Goodman, is possession plus reference (p. 53).
a matter of relation between the object's parts, In certain circumstances, a clean room can re-
even though cleaning sometimes clarifies rela- fer to its own cleanness. A room can serve as an
tions between parts. exemplar of cleanness (for example, the neat

This content downloaded from 190.60.231.2 on Wed, 22 Jan 2020 16:02:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
266 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

brother's room expresses cleanness in the con- the music gets "down and dirty." Children, how-
text of a parent's inspection). In such an in- ever, seem sometimes to value dirtiness aesthet-
stance the cleanness of the room comes to the ically: sometimes it looks good to them.
fore, whereas other features are backgrounded. "Clutter," in particular, is a term that allows
If a clean room does not refer to cleanness then itself to be taken in a positive sense. Many peo-
we cannot really aesthetically appreciate its ple like to temper neatness with some clutter.20
cleanness. But I do think we sometimes aesthet- They take pleasure in their clutter. Some people
ically appreciate the cleanness of a room. Thus, take pleasure in considerably more clutter than
contra Goodman, a symbol system is not neces- others. Front yards in the California Sierra foot-
sary for exemplification. All we need is specifi- hill country are generally much more cluttered
cation given by context of what is to exemplify than front yards in the suburbs. People there
what. Any feature of an object or field of ob- prefer this lifestyle and may have even moved
jects can be taken as exemplifying itself by the to that part of the state in part so that they can
viewer. This is somewhat like what has been be free to have a yard full of clutter. They would
traditionally called "taking the aesthetic atti- not want to live in the town where a family was
tude." A viewer can take the cleanness of a recently sued for allowing their front yard to
room as exemplifying cleanness. return to its natural state.
Here is an example that supports my point. A Debates between advocates of neatness and
messy roommate is wise to clean up one area of advocates of clutter often take the form: natural
the house quite well rather than cleaning all vs. artificial. Advocates of clutter and messi-
areas moderately, since the clean roommate will ness often claim that these properties are more
appreciate the cleanness of the one clean area natural and hence more valuable. The hippies of
but will ignore the moderate cleanness overall. the 1960s argued that messiness and even dirti-
The reason for this is that the clean roommate ness were more natural than neatness and clean-
values cleanness and takes the one clean area as ness. However, advocates of neatness and
a symbol of this. Thus for the clean roommate cleanness may also refer to these qualities as
this area exemplifies cleanness. Since Good- more natural. They might refer to the way cats
man only insists that one of the symptoms of lick themselves and chimps engage in groom-
the aesthetic be present, then it is arguable that ing. It all depends on how one sees nature.
even on hisprimarily art-centered interpreta-
tion of the aesthetic it is true that everyday VI. CONCLUDING COMMENTS

surface aesthetic qualities are genuinely aes-


thetic. What role should everyday surface aesthetic
qualities play in a general aesthetics? Some as-
V. THE VALUE OF EVERYDAY SURFACE sistance can be found in looking at the develop-
AESTHETIC QUALITIES ment of an aesthetic sense in children. Many of
our first aesthetic experiences are associated
We often assume that "neat," "clean," "unclut- with everyday surface aesthetic qualities. Chil-
tered," and "unblemished" are always posi- dren are taught to be neat, clean, orderly, and
tive; and that "messy," "dirty," "cluttered," andnot to be messy, sloppy, and unkempt.2' And
"blemished" are always negative aesthetic qual- perhaps as a form of rebellion, children often
ities. However, people hold differing views con- choose to value the opposite qualities. These
cerning the value of everyday surface aesthetic concepts are learned long before such tradi-
qualities. Some people value neatness highly. tionally recognized aesthetic concepts as "grace"
Others, not necessarily the same people, value and "delicacy." Does that make them distant
cleanness highly. Others again do not value ei- from such concepts? Not necessarily. Sibley
ther of these very much. These people may ac- gives an account of how children learn complex
tually value messiness and clutter. I know art- musical terms which can help us here. He ar-
ists who revel in the messiness of the creative gues that parents and teachers begin to teach
process, who literally enjoy the messiness of aesthetic concepts by suggesting that simple
paint. Few adults value dirtiness, although some-pieces of music are "hurrying" or "running."
times "dirty" is valued metaphorically, as when From there they move to concepts like "lively"

This content downloaded from 190.60.231.2 on Wed, 22 Jan 2020 16:02:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Leddy Everyday Surface Aesthetic Qualities 267

and "gay." Finally, they teach more complex called everyday surface aesthetic qualities and
concepts like "solemn" and "dynamic."22 He the qualities that have traditionally been called
implies that learning the simpler concepts pro- aesthetic are remarkable and should not be ne-
vides the basis for learning the more complex glected in the future.23
ones. Perhaps "neat," "clean," and "orderly"
are simpler concepts which provide a basis for THOMAS LEDDY

developing more complex notions such as "har- Department of Philosophy


monious," "organized," and "beautiful." Note San Jose State University
that young musicians are encouraged to learn San Jose, California 95192
how to be neat, clean, and ordered first before
more complex abilities are developed. Later, a INTERNET: LEDDY @ SJSUVM 1.BITNET

little messiness or disorder might be allowed in


order to better show off underlying structure.
1. Consider the lists in the following well-known articles
Some readers of this paper may balk at the
and books. Frank Sibley, "Aesthetic Concepts," Philosophical
idea of calling the qualities I am discussing aes- Review 68 (1959): 421-450, (reprinted in William Kennick,
thetic qualities. They might insist that aesthetic Art and Philosophy [New York: St. Martin's Press, 1979],
qualities should have complex features which pp. 542-564); Monroe Beardsley, "What is an Aesthetic
Quality?," The Aesthetic Point of View (Cornell University
make them accessible only after much training.
Press, 1982), pp. 93-110; Peter Kivy, Speaking of Art (The
They might even argue that something distinc- Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973); Ted Cohen, "Aesthetic/Non-
tively new emerges at the level of such concepts aesthetic and the Concept of Taste: A Critique of Sibley's
as "elegant," "beautiful," and "sublime," which Position," Theoria 39 (1973): 113-152, (reprinted in Ken-
nick); Roger Scruton, Art and Imagination (London: Me-
just is not there in such concepts as "neat" and
thuen, 1974), pp. 30-31; Goran Hermeren, The Nature of Aes-
"clean." Those same readers, however, may be
thetic Qualities (Lund University Press, 1988).
willing to grant the status of aesthetic quality to 2. There is a problem with calling "dirty" a surface qual-
everyday surface aesthetic quality terms when ity. Something can be dirty not just on the surface but
these terms are applied by critics and other through and through. However, this exception seems to
prove the rule, since we still tend to think of dirt as acciden-
knowledgeable persons to works of art, since
tal to that which it covers or soils. So even if dirt is not
at that level, through connoting such gestalt literally on the surface alone it is still on the surface on-
qualities as "harmonious" and "integrated," tologically speaking. This leads us to a second difficulty.
these terms may take on a degree of complexity "Purity" and "impurity" do seem to refer to the entire sub-
stance and not just the surface. So perhaps these are not
which they lack at the everyday level. I accept
surface qualities. But they are clearly related to the qualities
both of these points and suggest that it might be
I have mentioned and in particular to clean and unclean.
more appropriate to call everyday surface aes- 3. Allen Carlson, "Environmental Aesthetics and the Di-
thetic qualities proto-aesthetic qualities when lemma of Aesthetic Education," The Journal of Aesthetic
found at the level of everyday life (given that Education 10 (1976): 69-82. David Novitz, The Boundaries
of Art (Temple University Press, 1992), chap. 6: "Keeping
they are taught in childhood and provide some
up Appearances." However Novitz is mainly interested in
of the basis for more complex aesthetic con- the social implications of personal appearance and the de-
cepts), whereas at the level of art they may have pendence of aesthetic perceptions on socially held values,
sufficient complexity to be called aesthetic which is not my concern here.

qualities in the fullest sense of the term. Purity and impurity have, of course, been discussed in
relation to Aristotle's theory of catharsis.
I have by no means exhausted this subject
4. Current debate over the restoration of such works as
matter. It is striking, for instance, that such terms
the frescoes of the Sistine Chapel would be relevant to an
as "dirty" and "filthy" are strongly associated extended discussion of this issue. The main problem here is
with the obscene, the lewd, and the porno- that some art historians believe that the cleaning of the
paintings also involves an intervention into aesthetic quali-
graphic. "Polluted" and "fouled" are terms
ties of the painting itself. Much of the modeling of Mi-
which we use for the extreme of impurity. Some chelangelo's figures seems to have been lost in the cleaning
forms of neurosis, such as obsessive hand- process.
cleaning, involve everyday surface aesthetic 5. Stan Godlovitch: e-mail letter of November 20, 1993.
qualities. A full analysis of the aesthetics of 6. Interestingly, these are often the properties non-aes-
theticians are thinking of when they refer to the "aes-
everyday surface aesthetic qualities would need
thetics" of something.
to explore these dimensions. I only wish to 7. I owe this example to MaryAnn Shulkait. Arthur Danto,
stress that the similarities between what I have in "Symbolic Expressions of the Self," in Beyond the Brillo

This content downloaded from 190.60.231.2 on Wed, 22 Jan 2020 16:02:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
268 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Box (New York: Farrar Straus Giroux, 1992), pp. 56-57, 13. There is an interesting connection between neatness
speaks of how a disordered room might be an expression of and elegance in English. In slang "neat" is often used to
a feminist point rather than simply a manifestation of cul- refer to something like "elegant" or "stylish." This points
tural background or a psychological condition. His point to the possibility that neatness is a more primitive cousin to
that order and disorder can carry some semiotic charge is elegance.
an exception to the rule that aestheticians do not discuss 14. Sibley, p. 560.
everyday surface aesthetic qualities. 15. Monroe Beardsley, "In Defense of Aesthetic Value,"
8. Hermeren, p. 106. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical
9. However, although putting a chair in one place rather Association 52 (1979): 723-749.
than another might seem to be "straightening up" to one 16. Beardsley, "What is an Aesthetic Quality?," p. 100.
person, it might seem to be "redecoration" to someone else. 17. Beardsley, "In Defense of Aesthetic Value," p. 741.
10. Of course, everyday surface aesthetic qualities may 18. Beardsley, "What is an Aesthetic Quality?"
well be complex on other levels or in other respects. For 19. Nelson Goodman, Languages of Art (Indianapolis:
instance, attributions of "neatness" in a particular sub- Hackett Publishing Company, 1976), pp. 252-255.
group of a particular culture may depend on complex social 20. Of course, it might be the case that two people
traditions. It is also arguable that these qualities are on- equally dislike clutter, and yet what A considers to be clut-
tologically complex and therefore that an adequate philo- ter B considers not to be clutter. Under these circumstances
sophical analysis of them must be complex. A might come to believe that B values clutter even though B
11. Cheryl Foster, in comments on a version of this paper would deny it.
given to the Pacific Division Meeting of the American So- 21. Sibley, p. 559.
ciety for Aesthetics, April 1994, intriguingly argues (along 22. Sibley, p. 560.
Sartrean lines) that "chaotic" can be an everyday surface 23. I would like to thank the members of the Philosophy
aesthetic quality if one applies it to a perceptually absent Department at San Jose State University, the referees of this
structure when we perceive that absence. journal, and Cheryl Foster for helpful comments on earlier
12. The issue of realism vs. antirealism of aesthetic qual- versions of this paper. I also would like to thank Stan God-
ities is raised here. My own view is that aesthetic qualities lovitch for allowing me to quote his letter.
are socially constituted and do not exist outside a specific
social context. Nonetheless they are real within that frame.
But this is too large an issue to discuss here.

This content downloaded from 190.60.231.2 on Wed, 22 Jan 2020 16:02:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Potrebbero piacerti anche