Sei sulla pagina 1di 7

Ecological Aesthetics

Ted Toadvine

The emerging subdiscipline of ecological aesthetics of intentionality and his descriptions of the intuitively
concerns the aesthetic appreciation of the world in its given experiential lifeworld, for example, provide a
entirety, including both the natural and built environ- concrete framework for understanding aesthetic expe-
ments, and is consequently the broadest category of rience as a basic and pervasive quality of everyday
aesthetics. This area of study emerged as a distinct life.
field in the latter half of the twentieth century, although MARTIN HEIDEGGER ’s appreciation of the role of
its historical roots may be traced to eighteenth century earth in the formation of the artwork, his critique of
British and Scottish theories of natural aesthetics, espe- the enframing character of modern technology, and his
cially their treatment of the picturesque in landscape description of poetic dwelling as an alternative to mod-
painting, which culminated in Kant’s analysis of the ern technological civilization suggest parallels with
beautiful and sublime in nature. During the nineteenth contemporary environmental concerns and a critique
and twentieth centuries, aesthetic theory tended to of the humanistic limits of modern aesthetic theory.
focus almost exclusively on artworks and other objects MAX SCHELER proposes the aesthetic value of nature
of human design. But encouraged by increasing con- as a paradigmatic example of the nonrelativity of val-
cern with environmental issues among philosophers ues. MAURICE MERLEAU - PONTY’s investigations of
and the general public, a new interest in the aesthetics embodied perception and his later ontology of flesh
of nature and its relationship to the built environment hold implications for the epistemological and meta-
has emerged over the last several decades. Ecological physical foundations of an environmental aesthetics,
aesthetics today incorporates studies of the aesthetics and many of his writings on art address the relation-
of nature, including natural objects and larger wholes ship between the painter’s vision and our perceptual
such as ecosystems, gardens and landscape architec- experience of nature. MIKEL DUFRENNE recognizes in
ture, environmental and earth art, architecture and pure aesthetic experience an incipient phenomenologi-
urban planning, and the relations between the different cal reduction that brings to the fore the intentional bond
modes of aesthetic appreciation appropriate to these between subject and world, suggesting the particular
different domains. This extension of aesthetic consid- appropriateness of the phenomenological approach for
eration to both natural and built environments has led formulating a general aesthetic theory. His description
to a reconsideration of traditional aesthetic categories of aesthetic objects as expressive “quasi-subjects” and
and of central tenets of aesthetic theory. of the sensuous as a common act of the sensing and
Explicitly phenomenological work in ecological the sensed also pave the way for an elaboration of
aesthetics is still in its infancy, but the insights of many aesthetics into a philosophy of nature.
of the major figures in the tradition are applicable to Arnold Berleant, a leading figure in the devel-
this new field of study. EDMUND HUSSERL’s concept opment of a specifically ecological aesthetics, has
been the strongest proponent of the phenomeno-
logical approach in this field. His “aesthetics of
T. Toadvine () engagement,” inspired by Husserlian intentionality and
University of Oregon, Charleston, OR, USA Merleau-Ponty’s descriptions of embodied experience,

H.R. Sepp, L. Embree (eds.), Handbook of Phenomenological Aesthetics, Contributions to Phenomenology 59 85


DOI 10.1007/978-90-481-2471-8_17, © Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010
86 T. Toadvine

challenges core assumptions of traditional aesthetics. the twentieth century devotes considerable attention
According to Berleant, the “doctrine of disinterested- to the phenomenological tradition, especially the con-
ness” that pervades aesthetic theory entails the separa- tributions of Husserl, Heidegger, and Merleau-Ponty
tion of a spectator, conceived as passive and primarily (Casey 1997). Starting from the “originative thinking”
visual, from an aesthetic object lacking any practical of Heidegger, Ingrid Leman Stefanovic (2000) grants
connections with the wider natural and cultural con- an ontological primacy to place in her proposal of
text (Berleant 1988: 1992). In contrast, he holds that alternatives to received notions of sustainable devel-
the human perceiver is embedded in the aesthetic envi- opment. Gary Backhaus and John Murungi (2002)
ronment and continuously interacts with it in an active, present phenomenological analyses of the systemic
engaged, and multisensory fashion. This “participatory transformations of urban and suburban landscapes
model” of aesthetic experience treats the environment through their dialectical interaction with human activi-
as “a field of forces continuous with the organism, a ties. Eduardo Mendieta (2001) maintains that our very
field in which there is a reciprocal action of organ- idea of philosophy, including its account of rationality
ism on environment and environment on organism and and social agency, is informed by urban spatializing
in which there is no real demarcation between them” practices, a point that he illustrates by taking JEAN -
(Berleant 1988: 93). This general model of aesthetic PAUL SARTRE ’s phenomenology as a paradigmatic
experience is equally applicable, he suggests, to works example.
of art, the built environment, and the natural environ- Other relevant topics of recent phenomenologi-
ment. In fact, given the continuity between the human cal investigation include the intersection of built and
perceiver and the surrounding world, the cultural and natural environments in gardening and environmen-
historical formation of the concept of nature, and the tal art, as well as the representation of the earth
extension of our technological influence to every part within literature and the fine arts. Collections edited
of the natural world, it follows for him that there is by Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka (2001, 2003) address
no real distinction between nature and culture: “the the representation and role of earth in literature and
natural world is no independent sphere but is itself a human existence and the phenomenological experience
cultural artifact” (Berleant 1992: 167). On the basis of gardens, especially as figures of infinity and the
of this aesthetics of engagement, Berleant develops a sublime, across a span of cultural and literary tradi-
theoretical framework for negative aesthetic judgments tions. James Hatley (2003) finds in the Land Art of
and suggests a new model for education and aesthetic Andrew Goldsworthy a renewed interrogation of the
community that gives central place to continuity, “con- relation between technē and physis that, rather than
nectedness within a whole rather than a link between leaving nature untouched, approaches nature “in such
discrete parts” (Berleant 1997). a manner that our touching is also touched by what we
Although Berleant has been the first to offer a touch,” suggesting an aesthetics as well as an ethics of
comprehensive phenomenological theory of ecologi- wilderness (Hatley 2003: 14).
cal aesthetics, other themes relevant to the field have Central to contemporary ecological aesthetics is
also received extensive treatment by phenomenologists the question of the relation between the aesthetic
in recent years. Investigations of the role of place, appreciation of artworks and of nature. Berleant, as
for instance, have combined philosophy with cultural noted above, stresses a continuity of all forms of
geography and environmental design to form a new aesthetic appreciation that is grounded on the activ-
area of study that David Seamon calls “phenomenolog- ity of the engaged and participatory human per-
ical ecology” (Seamon 1993; Seamon and Mugerauer ceiver. In contrast, Allen Carlson (1993, 2000, 2004,
1985). Edward S. Casey (1993) argues for a renewed emphasizes the difference between these two types of
appreciation of the role of place in human experience, appreciation, holding that common sense or scientific
which he sees as long obscured by our cultural and knowledge is necessary for the aesthetic appreciation
philosophical privileging of space and time, and he of nature. According to his “natural environmental
explores the lived body’s role in the formation of place model,” nature is “an environment and thus a setting
and the distinct characters of built, cultivated, and within which we exist and that we normally experience
wild place-worlds. His intellectual history of the hid- with our complete range of senses as our unobtrusive
den role of place from ancient creation myths through background” (Carlson 2004: 72). Nature becomes an
Ecological Aesthetics 87

aesthetic object when we shift our attention to cer- changed by habituation (familiarity with a city changes
tain foci within this all-embracing background, which our spatial context for appreciating the architecture of
are then experienced as forming an “obtrusive fore- a certain building) or conceptual knowledge (aware-
ground.” Conceptual knowledge of nature is needed to ness of geological timescales may alter our aesthetic
guide our selection of appropriate foci and boundaries appreciation of erosion patterns on the rocky Oregon
for this shift of attention. coast). The spatiotemporal limits prescribed by human
Stan Godlovitch (2004), on the other hand, holds perceptual organization may also be expanded tech-
that such positions as Berleant’s and Carlson’s arbi- nologically, e.g., by microscopes and telescopes or by
trarily adopt the human scale of perception, thereby time-lapse photography, which requires the translation
failing to appreciate nature on its own terms. As an or annexation of these broader or narrower spatial and
alternative, he proposes an “acentric” aesthetic aloof- temporal contexts to those that we are able to experi-
ness, the leveling of all viewpoints to an anonymous ence directly. In addition to such spatial and temporal
uniformity within which the human standpoint holds contexts, the sensory aspect of our aesthetic experience
no particular privilege. Only such an acentric view essentially involves “framing,” the selection of certain
is capable of grounding moral respect for nature, foci as aesthetically relevant against a broader back-
Godlovitch holds, since it leaves nature “fundamen- ground or horizon. Such selection reflects traits of the
tally inaccessible and ultimately alien” (Godlovitch perceiver, such as concentration, attention span, expec-
2004: 113). Clarification of this debate requires, first, tations, personal history, and habituation, and it may
a phenomenological account of aesthetic experience also be guided by cultural norms and conventions.
in general, and second, an account of what apprecia- Framing of artworks is typically guided by con-
tion of nature “on its own terms” can mean within the vention, as with the literal frame of a painting or the
context of human experience. edge of a theatrical stage, and cultural framing con-
Aesthetic experience always involves a perceptual ventions are not entirely absent when we look beyond
or sensuous core, which may take as its focus one the world of art: directional markers and rain gut-
sense in particular or a combination of senses and ters are not the intended objects of appreciation on
corporeal experiences. When viewing a painting or lis- a nature trail, and signs along the highway mark the
tening to a symphony, for instance, cultural convention appropriate stops for a “scenic overlook” of the land-
teaches us to exclude as irrelevant everything but what scape. But aesthetic experience often extends beyond
the single focal sense conveys. By contrast, a stroll objects designed for that purpose or scenes that are
through a stand of old-growth Douglas fir combines culturally endorsed, leaving us with less well-defined
sights, smells, sounds, tactile impressions, and the guidance in our framing selections. The appreciation
kinaesthetic sense of movement in a single aesthetic of sounds in nature, for instance, involves numerous
experience. (This sensuous core of aesthetic experi- selections that may be shaped as much by individual
ence may also be supplied by memory or imagination as by cultural preferences: how long we should lis-
rather than by present perception, e.g., remembering ten, what counts as a foreground or background sound,
a musical performance or imaginatively anticipating a whether human-produced sounds should be excluded,
walk through the forest.) and even whether we should parse natural sounds into
Because the core of an aesthetic experience is relatively distinct melodies in a serial structure (Fisher
always sensuous, such experience is always relative to 2004). The appreciation of landscape also highlights
the perceiver’s spatial and temporal scale. The range the importance of such framing, since a landscape
of human spatial and temporal perception is a function exists only as seen from a particular point of view; the
of our sensory organization and may differ signifi- landscape scene is a “subjective object” rather than a
cantly from the spatial or temporal organization of real part of nature (Crawford 2004b: 257).
the Umwelten of other sentient creatures. The aes- The sensuous core of the aesthetic experience is
thetic appreciation of works of art generally dictates a therefore essentially relative to the perceiver. But aes-
certain spatial or temporal context: we look at a paint- thetic appreciation is not reducible to this sensuous
ing from a certain distance and listen to a musical core, since evaluation, at least of a tacit sort, must be
performance at a certain tempo. We may alter these involved. Although both Berleant and Carlson restrict
contexts at will in some cases, and they may also be aesthetic appreciation to humans, we clearly share with
88 T. Toadvine

many animals such sensory pleasures as basking in of nature in its own right, or is it merely an anthro-
the sun or enjoying a thirst-quenching drink, which pocentric projection? Donald Crawford (2004a) distin-
are candidates for rudimentary aesthetic apprecia- guishes between three senses of nature: (1) unrestricted
tion. In many cases, human aesthetic experience will nature, a metaphysical view of nature as “unlimited
also include what Ronald Hepburn calls a “thought- and all-encompassing” dating from the mid-nineteenth
component,” which is introduced “as we implicitly century and including humans and cultural creations
compare and contrast here with elsewhere, actual with such as works of art; (2) Aristotelian nature, charac-
possible, present with past” (Hepburn 1993: 66–67). terized by having an internal rather than an external
This “thought-component” is not limited to conceptual source of change and consequently to be contrasted
thought and need not involve self-conscious awareness with the artifactual, which would include human nat-
or reflection. Rather, it indicates that the sensuous core ural functions but exclude contingent natural events
is accompanied by a mixture of emotion, imagination, or “accidents” as parts of nature; and (3) pure nature,
conceptualization, and metaphorization, and may also defined negatively by the absence of any human influ-
include elements of what Hepburn terms “metaphys- ence whatsoever, which would exclude our bodies,
ical imagination,” a “seeing as...” that interprets the works of art, and culture, but would include what
present perception in terms of its metaphysical rele- Aristotle considered to be “accidents.” The claim of
vance for the whole of experience (Hepburn 2004). Godlovitch that subjecting nature to our human per-
Watching a frog have its innards sucked out by a giant ceptual scale thereby degrades it therefore takes nature
water bug, as Annie Dillard describes in Pilgrim at in the latter sense as its ideal.
Tinker Creek, may provoke a grim realization of the But nature in the pure sense cannot function as a
“chomp or fast” law of life, extending to a view of standard for aesthetic appreciation. It is questionable,
the cosmos as essentially conflictual. A swim in the first, whether any part of the earth remains unaltered
warm and calm waters off the Florida coast, on the by human activity, and the activities that we consider
other hand, might carry with it a sense of metaphysical to be aesthetic appreciation of nature are often directed
immersion and fluid interconnection with all things. toward objects that bear the mark of human influence
Such metaphysical imagination, and the “thought- (Crawford 2004a). More fundamentally, the emphasis
component” more generally, cannot be treated as a on “pure nature” suggests a questionable metaphysi-
superficial addition to the aesthetic experience; “it is cal division between humans and nonhuman nature,
fused with the sensory components, not a medita- as Berleant (1992) has noted. Finally, if respecting
tion aroused by these” (Hepburn 2004: 128). Despite “pure nature” excludes any relationship with a per-
the terminology, such “components” are not separa- ceiver or experiencer, then there would not seem to
ble parts or layers added on to an unchanged per- be any reason to consider this relationship “aesthetic”
ceptual substratum, but integral aspects of a single, or even an “experience,” since the aesthetic relation
holistic experience from which they are separable is an intentional one and involves a sensuous aspect.
only abstractly. Emotions, imagination, and conceptual Nevertheless, the notion of “pure nature” does have
knowledge may even guide the sensuous framing of a foundation in our experience. Our aesthetic experi-
experience by directing one’s attention to what may ence recognizes a relative distinction between objects
have otherwise escaped attention, so that the sensu- of human design and those relatively free from human
ous components and the thought-components of an intervention: an old-growth forest trail will show signs
aesthetic experience engage in a mutually informing of human intervention, but it remains less designed
dialectic. than an arboretum, and this in turn is relatively more
This account of aesthetic experience incorporates natural than a potted Norwegian spruce. “Pure nature”
in a limited way both the perceptual engagement arises as an ideal extension of the experience of per-
described by Berleant and the influence of concep- ceived naturalness, much like the examples of meta-
tual information stressed by Carlson. But the emphasis physical imagination discussed above. Godlovitch’s
on spatial and temporal scale and the role granted to characterizations of nature as mysterious and aloof
framing underscores Godlovitch’s concerns: does aes- thus remain tacitly indebted to our perceptual experi-
thetic experience so described allow for appreciation ences of nature.
Ecological Aesthetics 89

Furthermore, the relativity of aesthetic experience (Carlson 1993, 2001). This emphasis on natural-
to a perceiver does not entail that such experience is an historical knowledge follows in the tradition of John
anthropocentric projection. The aesthetic significance Muir, Henry David Thoreau, and Aldo Leopold, who
of a part of nature depends on the elements revealed tied the aesthetic value of nature to its ecological har-
by the perceiver’s perspective and framing, but these mony and integrity, a position that has been refined
elements are still features of nature, not subjective pro- in Baird Callicott’s “land aesthetic” (Carlson 2004,
jections. Crawford makes this point concerning the Callicott 1987). Because of its prioritization of sci-
appreciation of natural scenery: “A landscape, as an entific knowledge, the cognitive approach has drawn
object of aesthetic appreciation, is in fact an expanse criticism for underestimating the importance of non-
of the surface of the earth...; and although its quali- conceptual factors in our aesthetic appreciation of
ties are those we determine by looking at it from a nature, such as emotions (Carroll 2004), imagination
particular viewpoint, that does not preclude it from (Brady 2004, Hepburn 2004), and the ambient dimen-
being a part of nature” (Crawford 2004b: 257). We may sion of experience (Foster 2004). Debate has also
become aware, of course, that our perceptual experi- centered on what forms of knowledge may be appro-
ences are framed in an inappropriate way by limited priate for aesthetic guidance, with suggestions that
or inaccurate conceptual knowledge, or by the impo- scientific knowledge be complemented by Indigenous
sition of personal or cultural expectations that fail to traditions, folklore, and myths (Saito 2004), as well
accord with what nature actually presents. For exam- as by literary treatments of nature (Sepänmaa 1993).
ple, our appreciation of English ivy in a Northwestern Carlson has refined his position in light of these sug-
forest may alter when we learn that it is an invasive gestions and proposes that the cognitive approach be
species crowding out native trilliums, and we may lis- extended beyond consideration of natural aesthetics to
ten to birdsongs differently after becoming aware of provide a model for aesthetic appreciation of the world
the Western tendency to privilege narrative musical at large (Carlson 2000, 2001).
structures. But this ability to revise our concepts and Carlson criticizes Berleant’s “aesthetics of engage-
framings relies on an expansion of experience, not ment” for focusing primarily on sensory and formal
on the rejection of experience altogether in favor of qualities, thereby making aesthetic appreciation of
aloof mystery. Even our awareness of the limitations of nature trivial and subjective and potentially isolat-
human spatial and temporal scale takes our perceptual ing the appreciation of art from that of the larger
experience as its starting point, varying this imagi- world, since contemporary art appreciation clearly
natively as we conceive of other possible scales and involves conceptual knowledge and understanding
perspectives. There is no contradiction, then, between that goes beyond the merely sensuous and formal
holding that all aesthetic appreciation is experiential, qualities of the object (Carlson 2001: 429). The
i.e., relative to a perceiver, and that it may engage phenomenological approach to aesthetic experience
with nature on its own terms. Each particular aesthetic sketched above avoids these criticisms while incorpo-
experience is open to evaluation concerning its success rating the best features of both Berleant’s and Carlson’s
in taking nature on its own terms, and our judgments positions. Since all aesthetic experience is founded
along these lines will always be open to revision in on a sensuous core, Berleant’s descriptions of our
light of further experience. continuous perceptual engagement with an aestheti-
Among non-phenomenological contributions to cally charged surrounding world are appropriate. But
ecological aesthetics, the dominant line of develop- Berleant overlooks the phenomenologically valid dis-
ment has been the cognitive approach espoused by tinction between objects of human design and those
Carlson, according to which scientific knowledge is relatively free of human intervention. This distinction
central to aesthetic appreciation of nature. He argues suggests that aesthetic appreciation of these different
that twentieth century philosophy of art downplayed objects, and of the cases that range between them, may
formal qualities to emphasize the role that art his- be informed by conceptual knowledge, and even that
tory and criticism play in art appreciation, so our such conceptual knowledge may direct our perceptual
appreciation of nature should be guided predomi- scale and framing of these objects. Contra Carlson, the
nantly by natural-historical and scientific knowledge phenomenological view does not prioritize conceptual
90 T. Toadvine

knowledge over the many other aspects of our com- Carlson, Allen. Aesthetics and the Environment: The
plete aesthetic experience, including emotional, imag- Appreciation of Nature, Art and Architecture. New York:
Routledge, 2000.
inative, ambient, and metaphysical aspects, and does
Carlson, Allen. “Environmental Aesthetics.” In The Routledge
not exclude other sources for conceptual knowledge Companion to Aesthetics. Ed. Berys Gaut and Dominic
apart from the scientific, such as traditional knowledge McIver Lopes. London: Routledge, 2001, 423–36.
or literature. Carlson, Allen. “Appreciation and the Natural Environment.” In
The Aesthetics of Natural Environments. Ed. Allen Carlson
While for Carlson, “Science is the paradigm of
and Arnold Berleant. Ontario: Broadview Press, 2004a,
that which reveals objects for what they are and with 63–75.
the properties they have” (Carlson 1993: 219), phe- Carlson, Allen, and Arnold Berleant, eds. The Aesthetics of
nomenology sees natural science as an abstraction Natural Environments. Ontario: Broadview Press, 2004b.
Carroll, Noël. “On Being Moved by Nature: Between Religion
from lifewordly experience oriented toward certain
and Natural History.” In The Aesthetics of Natural
theoretical and practical pursuits. The most funda- Environments. Ed. Allen Carlson and Arnold Berleant.
mental disclosure of objects as what they are is as Ontario: Broadview Press, 2004, 89–107.
they are experienced pre-theoretically within the life- Casey, Edward S. Getting Back into Place: Toward a Renewed
Understanding of the Place-World. Bloomington: Indiana
world, although this experience may be informed
University Press, 1993.
by the conceptualizations and sedimentations of the Casey, Edward S. The Fate of Place: A Philosophical History.
natural sciences. The contributions of the cognitive Berkeley: University of California Press, 1997.
approach to ecological aesthetics are therefore not at Crawford, Donald. “The Aesthetics of Nature and the
Environment.” In The Blackwell Guide to Aesthetics. Ed.
odds with phenomenological insights, starting from a
Peter Kivy. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2004a, 306–24.
basic description of aesthetic experience that would be Crawford, Donald. “Scenery and the Aesthetics of Nature.” In
applicable both to art and nature. The two accounts The Aesthetics of Natural Environments. Ed. Allen Carlson
may be fruitfully combined for a richer understanding and Arnold Berleant. Ontario: Broadview Press, 2004b,
253–68.
of our holistic aesthetic engagement with the world.
Fisher, John A. “Environmental Aesthetics.” In The Oxford
Handbook of Aesthetics. Ed. Jerrold Levinason. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2003, 667–78.
Fisher, John A. “What the Hills are Alive With: In Defense
Bibliography of the Sounds of Nature.” In The Aesthetics of Natural
Environments. Ed. Allen Carlson and Arnold Berleant.
Ontario: Broadview Press, 2004, 232–52.
Backhaus, Gary, and John Murungi, eds. Transformations Foster, Cheryl. “The Narrative and the Ambient in
of Urban and Suburban Landscapes: Perspectives from Environmental Aesthetics.” In The Aesthetics of Natural
Philosophy, Geography, and Architecture. Lanham, MD: Environments. Ed. Allen Carlson and Arnold Berleant.
Lexington Books, 2002. Ontario: Broadview Press, 2004, 197–213.
Berleant, Arnold. “Aesthetic Perception in Environmental Godlovitch, Stan. “Icebreakers: Environmentalism and Natural
Design.” In Environmental Aesthetics: Theory, Research, Aesthetics.” In The Aesthetics of Natural Environments. Ed.
and Applications. Ed. Jack L. Nasar. Cambridge: Cambridge Allen Carlson and Arnold Berleant. Ontario: Broadview
University Press, 1988, 84–97. Press, 2004, 108–26.
Berleant, Arnold. Art and Engagement. Philadelphia: Temple Hatley, James. “Technē and Physis: Wilderness and the
University Press, 1991. Aesthetics of the Trace in Andrew Goldsworthy” (2003).
Berleant, Arnold. The Aesthetics of Environment. Philadelphia: International Association for Environmental Philosophy
Temple University Press, 1992. Website (http://www.environmentalphilosophy.org/).
Berleant, Arnold. Living in the Landscape: Toward an Aesthetics Hepburn, Ronald. “Trivial and Serious in Aesthetic Appreciation
of Environment. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1997. of Nature.” In Landscape, Natural Beauty, and the Arts.
Brady, Emily. “Imagination and the Aesthetic Appreciation of Ed. Salim Kemal and Ivan Gaskell. Cambridge: Cambridge
Nature” In The Aesthetics of Natural Environments. Ed. University Press, 1993, 65–80.
Allen Carlson and Arnold Berleant. Ontario: Broadview Hepburn, Ronald. “Landscape and the Metaphysical
Press, 2004, 156–69. Imagination.” In The Aesthetics of Natural Environments.
Callicott, J. Baird. “The Land Aesthetic.” In Companion to A Ed. Allen Carlson and Arnold Berleant. Ontario: Broadview
Sand County Almanac: Interpretive and Critical Essays. Ed. Press, 2004, 127–40.
J. Baird Callicott. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, Kemal, Salim, and Ivan Gaskell, eds. Landscape, Natural
1987, 157–71. Beauty, and the Arts. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Carlson, Allen. “Appreciating Art and Appreciating Nature.” In Press, 1993.
Landscape, Natural Beauty and The Arts. Ed. Salim Kemal Mendieta, Eduardo. “The City and the Philosopher: On the
and Ivan Gaskell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Urbanism of Phenomenology.” In Philosophy & Geography
1993, 199–227. 4, 2001, 203–218.
Ecological Aesthetics 91

Saito, Yuriko. “Appreciating Nature on its own Terms.” In The Stefanovic, Ingrid Leman. Safeguarding our Common Future:
Aesthetics of Natural Environments. Ed. Allen Carlson and Rethinking Sustainable Development. Albany: State
Arnold Berleant. Ontario: Broadview, 2004, 141–55. University of New York Press, 2000.
Seamon, David, ed. Dwelling, Seeing, and Designing: Toward Tymieniecka, Anna-Teresa, ed. Passions of the Earth in Human
a Phenomenological Ecology. Albany: State University of Existence, Creativity, and Literature. Analecta Husserliana
New York Press, 1993. 71. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2001.
Seamon, David, and Robert Mugerauer, eds. Dwelling, Place, Tymieniecka, Anna-Teresa, ed. Gardens and the Passion for
and Environment: Towards a Phenomenology of Person and the Infinite. Analecta Husserliana 78. Dordrecht: Kluwer
World. New York: Columbia University Press, 1985. Academic Publishers, 2003.
Sepänmaa, Yrjö. The Beauty of Environment: A General
Model for Environmental Aesthetics. 2nd ed. Denton, TX:
Environmental Ethics Books, 1993.

Potrebbero piacerti anche