Sei sulla pagina 1di 12

Intensity and Its Audiences: Notes towards a Feminist Perspective on the Kantian Sublime

Author(s): Timothy Gould


Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 48, No. 4, Feminism and
Traditional Aesthetics (Autumn, 1990), pp. 305-315
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/431568
Accessed: 29-09-2017 18:27 UTC

REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/431568?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This content downloaded from 161.116.100.129 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 18:27:20 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
TIMOTHY GOULD

Intensity and Its Audiences: Notes Towards


A Feminist Perspective on the Kantian Sublime

How does one stand to behold the sublime?


-Wallace Stevens,
"The American Sublime"

It is because her appetite for immediacy is so huge that she feels so powerfully the impossibility
directing it at a listener-even at a reader. Her hunger for direct language turns into a sense of
knowledge, a suppurating consciousness of possessing something dangerous to those about her. This
is the precise breeding ground of the unspeakable. The unspeakable is willed-it has not, that is to say,
a pre-existent content that is itself already unspeakable-but its gratuitousness is grounded in, is
rendered visible in the colors of, the individual obsession and the obsession of the age.
-Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick on Lucy Snowe in Villette

The goal of this paper is to begin a process of re- I shall begin by outlining briefly the first type
assessing Kant's aesthetics and specifically Kant's of criticism of Kant's aesthetics (section 1). I
account of the sublime in ways that are attuned toshall then raise some questions about this ver-
at least some of the feminist critics from whom Ision of the masculinist orientation of Kant's
have learned. I have in mind two sorts of criti- account of the sublime. Without disputing the
cism: the first sort can be characterized as an un- idea that there is something right-and impor-
masking of the gender prejudice and ideology in tantly right-about this picture of Kant's orienta-
the standpoint of philosophers like Burke and tion, I want to nudge the discussion of Kant in
Kant.2 The second sort of criticism is harder to another direction (section 2). And this leads me
characterize, but it can be roughly located among to invoke Sedgwick's accounts of the sublime,
the routes of contemporary American literary especially as she unearths its outlines and details
criticism that have been instructed by recent post- in writers like Charlotte Bronte and Emily Dick-
structuralist philosophy and psychoanalysis. inson. Sedgwick's account makes a theme out of
Terms like "post-structuralist" are often em- the affinity between the experience of the sub-
ployed so as to cover an improbably wide-ranging lime and certain experiences of the unspeak-
multitude of texts. The focus of this essay is a able, of the inexpressible and of things that
narrower segment of writing, including prin- cannot be entirely told (section 3). Finally, I
cipally the work of Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, shall use Sedgwick's discussion to motivate a
along with that of Neil Hertz, Frances Fergu- discussion of a couple of features in Kant's
son, Joshua Wilner and Naomi Schor. 3 Although account of the sublime (section 4).
many post-structuralist currents are beginning My general interpretive suggestion is this:
to circulate through the precincts of English- Kant teaches us that the experience of the sub-
speaking philosophical aesthetics, it seems to lime requires a certain "preparation" of cul-
me that the strands of thought represented by ture.4 Otherwise we experience, for instance, a
these writers have remained largely unknown. repulsion or a shrinking back in terror from the
(Schor's book is probably the most likely to be sublime and not the alternation between repul-
known by American philosophers.) And while a sion and attraction which constitutes the fullest
single paper cannot do justice to the complexity experience of the sublime. Sedgwick's work sug-
of these writers, it remains a secondary aim of my gests that, just as the experience of the sublime
paper to encourage aestheticians and feminists to requires a kind of preparation, so it requires a
encounter this body of work for themselves. kind of completion or aftermath. And if there is

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 48:4 Fall 1990

This content downloaded from 161.116.100.129 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 18:27:20 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
306 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

no suitable space-whether natural, or social, should not make the circumstances any less
or aesthetic-in which this experience can be ex- shameful.
pressed and hence fulfilled, the aftermath will
be extremely problematic. Given what Kant says I. THE SUBLIME: SOME USES AND ABUSES

about the experience of those who lack the nec-


essary "preparation" for the sublime, we might The criticism of the masculinist orientation of
go so far as to characterize the deprivation that 18th century is perhaps by now fairly familiar,
Sedgwick describes as a transformation or defor- and it is part of a general critique of the mas-
mation of the experience and not a contingent culine orientation of Western philosophy and
and merely personal fact about the situation of culture. In this line of thought, the category of
the person having the experience. This idea does the sublime is characterized as an especially
not necessarily lead us to abandon the idea of a vivid instance of a tendency in 18th century
transcendental principle that grounds our aes- aesthetics (and indeed throughout the history of
thetic judgments. But it might lead to a greater philosophy) to set up certain experiences char-
appreciation of the historical conditions within acterized in male terms as universally valid norms
which this transcendental hope was formed and a for the experience and judgment of all human
greater understanding of the burdens involved beings. The process is sometimes said to go like
when some individuals undertake to express this: first, certain experiences, in this case, the
such aesthetic judgments. experiences of the sublime, are characterized in
My contention is that the terms of Sedgwick's more or less overtly "masculine" terms (such
analyses-and, of course, the writers that her as "powerful," "active," "threatening," "domi-
terms illuminate-will help us to understand nating," "paternal," "masterful," "warlike," and
these features of the sublime and, perhaps, es- so forth). Second, the experiences are given a
pecially the obstacles to its communication. It is systematic form and a central place in the philos-
my further hope that the critical turns in this opher's vision of the aesthetic, cultural, and
reading of Kant will prove useful to feminist moral education of humanity. Third, women are
critics and to other readers of Kant. Whether or "discovered" to have either no capacity or only a
not this hope is fulfilled, the material I am intro- deficient capacity for undergoing this set of
ducing into the discussion of Kant would seem to experiences. Fourth, the (male) philosopher
possess some immediate pertinence to a feminist therefore feels justified in concluding that women
investigation of aesthetics. For it seems to me are less capable of developing into full-fledged
noteworthy that among Sedgwick's primary sub- human beings in these crucial aesthetic and moral
jects are women writing in the aftermath of dimensions.
the great projects of philosophical Enlighten- Such a pattern of "argument" was not in-
ment, of political revolution and of literary vented by 18th century aestheticians, and, of
Romanticism. This period might be charac- course, the pattern has not ceased to have its
terized in part as a moment when women of the proponents.5 The main outlines of this pattern
middle classes were beginning to absorb the can be found in Burke and at least in the pre-
fact that the aspirations of the 18th century hadcritical Kant, most egregiously in the third sec-
in many ways excluded their own aspirations. tion of Observations on the Beautiful and the
Or else they discovered that their aspirations Sublime.6 But in this paper I am suggesting that
had been included in ways that transformed we need to ask some further questions about the
them almost beyond recognition, transforma- implications that we are to draw from this pat-
tions that made those very aspirations into ve- tern. If we dwell on the pattern too exclusively,
hicles of constraint and isolation. Sedgwick's we are likely to miss something about Kant's
work operates at a moment where an increasing aesthetics. Perhaps more importantly, we may
material comfort was not only consistent with a miss a chance to retrieve for a philosophical
traumatic deprivation of the human need of aesthetics some of the very aspects of a human
expression but may actually have worked to existence that Kant himself is commonly sup-
exacerbate that deprivation. That for some posed to have neglected or distorted.
women these deprivations were involved in an It should be noted that there are now writers
astonishing access of insight and productivity who would deny that any of Kant's projects can

This content downloaded from 161.116.100.129 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 18:27:20 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Gould Intensity and Its Audiences 307

be rescued from the taint of patriarchy or from fact that the initial mapping or modeling of the
the cauldron in which bourgeois aesthetic ide- experience was carried out from a male perspec-
ology was shaped.7 There is not enough room tive does not mean that the experience is some-
here to give these charges the answer they de- how pre-eminently the property of men. To the
serve, but I do want to say a word or two about extent that Burke and the Kant thought other
this sort of critique. Perhaps Kant (or certain wise, we can show that they were wrong. (2) The
influential interpretations of his work) helped fact that the maps of the sublime are inflected
to create intellectual tendencies that serve the towards a masculine perspective does not mean
needs of bourgeois, patriarchal ideologies. But that there is nothing of value to learn from them.
Kant is also the principal philosophical thinker This latter point is philosophically difficult
who demanded a place for the idea that human and politically touchy, especially when made by
freedom is an end in itself and that freedom a male writer. In this context, I will confine
requires no religious or political purposes to myself to the following claim: One of the things
legitimate it. My own sense of the matter is that we may learn from a masculinist account of a
critics of ideology should not dispense with this given set of experiences is something about how
idea too quickly. to explore the tensions within the experience and
Of course, someone may say that such ideas within the account of the experience. I want to
have been perverted by bourgeois and patriarchal cite one place where it seems to me such a
ideologies. And bourgeois and patriarchal ideo- tension is present in Burke and Kant.
logies can-and often do-pervert such ideas, Let us look again at the tendency to charac-
as, indeed, they may pervert any idea they come terize the sublime objects as "active," "power-
into contact with. If any idea can be thus ful," "forceful," and so forth. Suppose we grant
tainted-and I suppose it can be-we are then that these terms carry with them certain conven-
left with the task of sorting out what we can still
tional and historical associations with masculine
use of the past from what is no longer usable. activity (or, more exactly, with paternal power).8
The reason for such an effort is not mere piety Suppose that we grant further that Burke and the
towards the past. Overcoming our tendency to pre-Critical Kant are inclined to exploit the mas-
distort and flatten the past in the name of a less culine drift associated with their characteriza-
oppressive future is connected to a still more tions of the objects of the sublime experience.
specific problem in the critical work of the pres- And suppose, finally, that Burke and Kant
ent. For the tendency to reduce a philosopher to were also sometimes inclined to characterize the
the patriarchal ideologies that he (or she) partici- human male as especially capable of experienc-
pates in is likely to leave us more or less in the ing the sublime.9 But then surely these thinkers
dark about a question that still seems crucial: have thereby introduced a tension into this par-
How does any thinker ever make an advance ticular gendering of the sublime. For it cannot
towards the overcoming of the mystifications really be the case that the object provoking the
that surround us? Unless we imagine that we are sublime experience can be characterized as mas-
somehow less likely than Kant to be deceived by culine in the same sense as the experiencing and
the ideologies and mystifications that we are judging subject is thought to be pre-eminently
subjected to, then the connection between Kant's masculine.
philosophical criticism and its ideological matri- This is not primarily a point about the logic of
ces ought to remain of more than academic inter- their positions. It is not impossible that Burke or
est to us. Kant could have found a way to remove the
tension and to make their accounts consistent on
II. A TENSION IN THE PATERNAL SUBLIME this point. My point is that to have removed the
tensions would have been to have removed some-
Let us assume that the experience of the sublime thing significant about the experience they were
was initially the province of male writers, and trying to account for. (Apparently, neither of
that the accounts which they gave of this experi-
them tried to remove this tension. And my own
ence were marked by the masculine perspectives intuition is that Kant may well have sensed that
within which the accounts were composed. A the tension was endemic to the experience.) The
couple of points are still worth making. (1) The larger point here is that the experience of the

This content downloaded from 161.116.100.129 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 18:27:20 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
308 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

sublime involves both a certain passivity in as we bear in mind three further features in
the subject's relation to the sublime object and, Kant's account of the spectator's situation: (1)
then, ultimately a certain active overcoming of Kant's particular conversion of the spectator into
that passivity, a triumph of the spirit in recogniz- something more than a spectator can only take
ing the aesthetic and moral "elevation" that the place after the simplistic picture of the mas-
judging subject is capable of.'0 The relation culine-as-active has been at least to some extent
between "activity" and "passivity" is thus ren- challenged (whether overtly or not). (2) The
dered to some extent problematic, at least for movement of conversion, as we shall see, leaves
any simplistic equation of masculinity and ac- residual difficulties in the fact of the spectator
tivity. and his or her need of further expression. For
An analogy might be useful: The fact of rela- Kant describes the experience of the sublime as
tively sedentary men watching active, physically in certain ways incomplete until further mental
or naturally dominant men (and other powerful, activity and reflection have occurred. (In the last
quasi-natural embodiments of force)-and more- section of this essay, I will examine a related
over watching these activities from a position of version of this incompleteness.)
some kind of safety-remains central to the (3) The recovery of a mode of activity on the
masculine side of American bourgeois, petit- part of the judging subject is not primarily en-
bourgeois, and working class culture. Let us acted as a successful "recuperation," in the
even suppose that there is a certain continuity post-structuralist sense of a compensation whose
between the 18th century concern with the mas- deficiencies are covered over by some further
culine or the paternal sublime and the relation of ideological mystification. The human imagina-
many American men to football, boxing, racing tion (and not just the male imagination) must
cars, and the movies of Brian de Palma. Putting renounce certain connections or identifications
moral and political questions aside for the mo- with nature in order to claim its heritage of
ment, what is missing from the modern versions sublimity and its consequent heightened capac-
of male spectatorship is precisely the Kantian ity for moral action. Hence, to the extent that
shift towards an emphasis on the significance of the self-definition of the 18th century male de-
the spectator's judgment. Of course, various pended on certain relations to nature (dominion
claims are made about the spiritual benefits of over nature, conqueror of new lands, new scien-
loyalty to particular teams or particular cars. tific realms, etc.), this self-definition is at least
And certain beer commercials seem designed to partially undermined by Kant's critical philoso-
promote a sense of male camaraderie which is phy. It is not just that the spectator of the sublime
all but indissolubly linked to football and is, is the true home of the sublime, and that certain
apparently, otherwise unavailable to American kinds of activity are not as sublime as we thought
men. But so far as I know, no theorist sym- (or as we men thought). For Kant, every action
pathetic to the modern male spectator has gonethat is not commanded by the moral law or
so far as to claim that the true sublimity of allowed in the free-play of certain spontaneous
football is to be sought in "the mind of the activities of the mind will turn out to be passive.
judging subject." But this is what Kant does For passivity is one feature of heteronomy. One
claim about the ultimate location of the experi- may attack these conceptions of morality and of
ence of the sublime. 1I1 beauty on other grounds. But one should not
Someone might wish to respond by suggest- miss the tendency of these conceptions to sub-
ing that the difference in Kant's move is only a vert conventional 18th (or 20th) century pictures
matter of degree. The modern celebrations of of masculine "activity" lurking in Kant's idea of
(male) spectatorship stop short of examining its the sublimity of moral action. And this idea of
inherent passivity (perhaps especially its pas- moral action as having to overcome false (and
sivity in relation to more active men). But Kant often masculine) pictures of what genuine activ-
is nevertheless engaged in a related evasion, ity amounts to is closely tied to the role of the
namely that of converting the passive spectator sublime in his aesthetics. 12
into something ultimately more significant and
even, in a sense, more active.
I would not deny a level of continuity, so long

This content downloaded from 161.116.100.129 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 18:27:20 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Gould Intensity and Its Audiences 309

III. SEDGWICK ON THE SUBLIME sion that is itself too intense for the normal
AND THE UNTELLABLE channels of human expressiveness and of ordi-
nary communication.
Some of the criticisms that I have examined in One version of such blockage goes like this:
the first part of this paper have shared a willing- "The hunger for direct language" becomes greater
ness to reduce the complexity of the relations than the wish to express any particular feeling. 1 5
between the subjects and the objects of aesthetic Indeed, in some cases, the need for expression
experience. Applied to Kant's aesthetics this itself becomes the content of the state of mind
seems to be especially ironic, since it is here that (and body) that is seeking expression. But this is
Kant was at the greatest pains to reinstate the very likely to make any specific expression all
complexities and indeed the legitimacy of our but impossible. The experience of this need for
subjective responses to nature. It would be unfor- expression abolishes-or appears to abolish-
tunate if this side of Kant's work were slighted or any place "outside" the subject, in which an
missed entirely in the general move to denounce audience for her feelings might exist. The very
the "rationalist" or "universalist" aspects of intensity of the need refuses to allow the kind of
his vision of human freedom and its aesthetic re- distance that ordinary human beings require, if
quirements. This brings me to the second type of they are to be the audience for our expressions of
feminist critic and the second part of my topic. feeling. (Despite the renewed emphasis on the
For here we will be discovering a feminist criti- importance of sympathy and the "sharing" of
cism that might render Kant's account at once experiences, we still do not possess much work
more complex and more responsive to the on the social and epistemological space in which
various situations in which our feelings seek the "good listener" can exist.)
expression. 13 Now suppose we think of someone having
The work of Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick only such experiences, while living in the social sit-
infrequently discusses philosophical texts di- uation of a middle-class woman in the first half
rectly. Yet I think her work is of great impor- of the 19th century. I am thinking here-not
tance to current aesthetics. I want now to follow exhaustively-of an existence surrounded by the
out some of her clues about the location of the genteel encouragement to expand your capaci-
sublime in relation to regions of the unspeakable ties for self-expression and cultivation-but only
and the unutterable. It is of course no secret that so far; encouragement to speak your mind-but
the experience of the sublime is bound up in only on certain topics; encouragement to learn
certain issues of the limits of representation. It certain things about the life of the mind-but
would certainly be worth exploring the relation- never to think of yourself as contributing to
ship between the ways in which Kant character- that life; encouragement to have certain delicate
izes the sublime as bound up in the "inadequacy feelings-but never to exceed a certain point of
of nature" to represent or to exhibit ideas of decorum and never to display the wrong kind of
reason (p. 124 [265]).14 J want to use Sedg- intensity or to aspire to certain regions of ex-
wick's analyses as a means of isolating a some- hilaration.
what different sort of "unrepresentability" and a Suppose we add to this sphere of an all-too-
different sense of the inexpressibility of certain discouraging encouragement (sometimes politely
aspects of the experience of the sublime. called the "socialization" of women), an intima-
Crudely and provisionally, here is an account tion of someone who possesses what Virginia
of one strand of her work: She focuses attention Woolf called "the heat and violence of a poet's
on the various rifts that may be created between heart when caught and tangled in a woman's
the one who experiences the sublime and those body. "'6 This seems a formula for producing the
other human beings who might otherwise have kind of freighted and desperate explorations and
been the natural audience for her account of her experiments in expression that Sedgwick is in-
experience. I follow Sedgwick in thinking that vestigating. And, indeed, in one direction, the
the very intensity of the experience of the sub- sense of suffocation that is produced by the
lime contains in it the wish to communicate that failure of so intense a drive to expression lends
experience to others. Taken together, the inten- itself to the imagery of the Gothic, with its live
sity and the wish can generate a need for expres- burials and its uncanny terms of imprisonment

This content downloaded from 161.116.100.129 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 18:27:20 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
310 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

in equally uncanny places. (Sedgwick has been such intersections of the formal and the psycho-
justly acclaimed for her efforts to understand logical are not merely the special concern of a
the Gothic in something other than reductive or certain individual called perhaps "a writer" (or
merely historical terms.) In another direction, called perhaps, from another angle, a "mad-
this drive to expression-at once self-inhibited woman in the attic" 19 ). These intersections and
and self-sustaining-becomes embodied in radi- these perplexities are representative of perplex-
cally new forms of poetry and the novel. Such ities in us, which we may only rarely find the
writing transcends distinctions between Roman- resources and the willingness to fathom.
tic and modern (let alone between either of these
and the so-called "postmodern"). And it equally IV. SOME IMPLICATIONS OF SEDGWICK'S
transcends distinctions between experimentation ACCOUNT FOR THE KANTIAN SUBLIME

with artistic forms of expression and the experi-


enced violence of a character's (or author's) ef- Sedgwick's account seems to me to have implica-
forts to create a kind of rift between her con- tions beyond the terms that it proposes for itself
sciousness and ours. 17 and its subjects. It helps our understanding of
For Sedgwick, it is the creation or "invention" the sublime and of other intensities in human
of such rifts that are among the most aesthet- experience. It points to an ordinarily less visible
ically shocking and humanly violent accom- edge of our need for expression. And it gives us
plishments of Bronte and Dickinson. Indeed, ona chance to think about the circumstances that
her account, these rifts are the means by which form the obstacles as well as the means for both
these writers unleash their capacity for a genuine human and artistic expression. I would like to
sublime of art-or as she puts it, they manage to open up a few further lines of communication
free up the "impersonal authorial energy of the between her work and the work of philosophers
true sublime." 18 Kant says very little about the concerned with a philosophical aesthetics.
sublime of art, hardly more than that such a As I suggested at the beginning, Sedgwick
sublime must be "confined to the conditions that teaches us to pay attention to the aftermaths of
[art] must meet in order to be in harmony with our experience as well as to its prerequisites.
nature" (#23, p. 98 [245]). Sedgwick's account More exactly, she teaches us to think about the
provides one way of thinking about one of the connection between "having" certain experi-
most persistent issues concerning the Kantian ences and being able-and being allowed-to
sublime within the realm of art. For it can seem express them and to talk about them in an appro-
as if the audience of a work art is, generally priately receptive setting. Kant suggests that a
speaking, too safe to be subjected to the alterna- certain "culture [Kultur]" is a necessary "prep-
tion of terror and attraction that is required for aration" for experiencing the sublime (#29,
the sublime experience to take place. On Sedg- p. 124 [265]). Sedgwick's account suggest that
wick's account, Bronte creates a rift between certain human beings in the grip of their experi-
audience and narrator, far greater than the merelyence of sublimity will also experience a need for
conventional distance between novel and reader. expression that, for various reasons, is likely to
And then she provides the means by which this go unmet. One may lack the empirical company
distance can be all the more vividly and pain- which permits such expressions, or one may feel
fully apprehended, if not quite entirely over- that the possibility of expression is lacking, or
come. one may even come to speak (or write) and act in
Such discoveries about the relation of the for-
ways which undermine that possibility. Under
mal means of artistic expression to the narrow those circumstances, the experience of the sublime
circumstances in which a human existence must will undergo modifications or even something
seek expression are often described as some like deformation. (This is a range of possibilities
combination of the "psychological" and the "for- that I have been trying to characterize in section
mal." But such descriptions are inclined to miss3.) These modified versions of the sublime can
both the intensity and the confusion of the inter-
be cognitively and aesthetically revealing, and
section between these realms, and the realms they can be the spur to a fantastic artistic inven
themselves are anything~but clearly understood. tiveness (though these advances are likely to
Such descriptions also miss the ways in which contain significant human costs).

This content downloaded from 161.116.100.129 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 18:27:20 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Gould Intensity and Its Audiences 311

I would like to go a little further and to work that it enables. The range is intended, for
describe the possibility of communication or instance, to include the work of the writers that
expression as in a certain sense the completion Sedgwick has discussed. But it is also intended
of the experience of the sublime, as Kant to include the work of writers who are otherwise
describes a certain kind of education as the as different as, for instance, Sylvia Plath, Alice
appropriate preparation for this experience. I Walker, and Samuel Beckett. Since I cannot
recognize that there is an asymmetry in this prove the relevance either of my intuition or of
formulation, which renders it unclear and some- the perspective that I would like to develop out of
what paradoxical. It is as if I am trying to this intuition, I will try at least to exemplify its
describe as a prerequisite of the experience a importance in relation to a few other aspects of
possibility that occurs only after "the experi- the sublime.
ence itself" has already taken place. Some of the If the possibility of expressing the sublime is
air of paradox might vanish if we could get a as integral a part of the experience as I am taking
more adequate picture of what I have been call- it to be, then I suspect that its effects will be
ing "the experience of the sublime" or "the wide-ranging. This is because, whatever one's
aesthetic judgment of the sublime." Already in external possibilities of communication and ex-
Kant's account these are far from simple experi- pression may be-whatever empirical aesthetic
ences. And the experiences of the sublime will company one keeps-there are already reasons
certainly be hard to describe on any model which internal to the experience of the sublime that
takes the flow of experience to be, so to speak, make expressions of it quite difficult. Two of the
one-directional. In fact, Kant's sublime should reasons were mentioned at the beginning, and I
be equally problematical to those empiricist ac- will now conclude this essay by trying to elabo-
counts which see the subject as the passive recip- rate on these "internal" obstacles to the expres-
ient of experiences from the "outside" and those sion of the sublime and on their possible connec-
more recent accounts which see the subject tion to the (comparatively) external difficulties
as constructing its experiences (and its own self- of expression that we have been considering.
hood) from the materials provided by an essen- (1) There is the sense, as I put it, that there is a
tially passive world. To think of the communica- kind of uncertainty or oscillation about the loca-
tion of an experience as a kind of completion of tion of (the experience of) the sublime. (This
the experience will entail further modifications uncertainty is related to what I characterized in
of our sense of what an experience is. But I think section 2 as an "undermining" of the conven-
that these modifications and disruptions will tional masculinity of the sublime.) Our experi-
turn out to be continuous with those entailed by ence of the sublime has two poles, one of them
Kant's account. My sense that the experience of pointing towards natural objects (or events) and
the sublime requires a kind of completion as well one of them pointing towards a heightened activ-
as a preparation is still largely on the level of an ity within the mind of the judging subject. I am
intuition. But I can say at least say a little more suggesting that it is a significant feature of the
about how we might work with this intuition. sublime, and of the judgment or experience of
The claim that the various expressive after- sublimity, that we are not always able to locate
maths of the experience of the sublime are to be its characteristic heightening of our feelings.
conceived of as part of that experience is not We may as Kant insists, seek the sublime most
intended as an empirical prediction about how "properly"-most appropriately-in the "judging
people will in fact experience the sublime. Nor subject." But as Paul Guyer has convincingly
is it intended as an invitation to reclassify cer- demonstrated, we cannot dispense with the natural
tain experiences as, for instance, not really of object that provokes or instigates the sublime.20
the sublime but merely somehow marginally Thus our analysis of the sublime may set up a
related to the sublime. It is intended rather to relatively stable model: first, we are aware of the
provide a kind of perspective on a whole range natural object or event that provokes our experi-
of experiences and of the associated possibilities ence of sublimity, and then comes the recogni-
and impossibilities of communication and ex- tion that the true or authentic subject of the
pression. The perspective can only be shown to sublime, resides in us. At any given moment,
have validity by the critical and philosophical however, our experience of the sublime may

This content downloaded from 161.116.100.129 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 18:27:20 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
312 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

very well be in transition from one pole of the adorn himself with them. Only in society does it occur
experience to the other. It seems to me that the to him to be, not merely a human being, but one who
analysis of the sublime (as anchored in the judg- is refined in his own way [nicht bloss Mensch, son-
ing subject but still occasioned by something in dern auch nach seiner Art feiner Mensch zu sein.
nature) can enable self-perceptions that end up (This is the beginning of civilization.) For we judge
by becoming part of the experience itself. If I someone refined if he has the inclination and the skill
seek the sublime in my own mind, considered as to communicate his pleasure to others, and if he is not
a judging subject, surely this is not merely a satisfied with an object unless he can feel his liking
piece of analysis that I can keep at arm's length for it in community with others (p. 164 [297]).
from my experience of the sublime. This per-
ception and this seeking become part of my It looks as though Kant is suggesting that, al-
experience of the sublime that provoked them. though the judgment of beauty might exist in
And this effort to understand my self as contrib- some rudimentary form in a state of isolation,
uting to the sublimity of the experience will human beings would do nothing to cultivate it-
enter into the difficulties of expressing that ex- or indeed to cultivate themselves. On Kant's
perience. (These difficulties seem to me analo- account, isolation seems to prevent us not so
gous to the difficulties confronting Lucy Snowe much from having the capacities for beauty or
in Sedgwick's account of her.) for human expression but from caring about
(2) Aesthetic judgment, though invariably char- those capacities. There is more than a hint that
acterized by Kant as containing a transcendental such capacities can continue to exist only by
principle or moment, also apparently contains being developed. And without at least the pres-
the material for various empirical employments. ence of the possibility of the accord of other
In section 41, Kant describes a possible use for human beings, no one would care enough to
the judgment of taste as furthering our ability to develop those capacities within themselves.
"communicate our feeling to everyone else," Now it seems to me that if there were an
hence as furthering the satisfaction of what he empirical interest in communicating our sense
calls a "natural inclination." Kant is clearly of the sublime, the stakes would be at least as
aware of the need and the wish to communicate high. Instead of thinking of someone abandoned
our feelings. He discusses it under the heading on some actual, desert island, let us think of
of "the empirical interest in the beautiful" and someone like Lucy Snowe. Sedgwick's account
he characterizes it as "something that everyone's of Villette teaches us, among other things, that
natural inclination demands" (#41, p. 163 [297]). the desolation within society has its greatest
Moreover, he connects this need to our "fitness effect on us not only at the moment of greatest
and propensity" for society, or what he calls deprivation but often at the moment when it
"sociability" (p. 163 [296]). Kant never explic- looks as if rescue-or company-might actually
itly discusses this sort of empirical interest as be at hand. Whereas on Kant's account, isolation
separately occasioned by the sublime. But he seems to prevent us from caring about the refine-
does isolate what he characterizes as the com- ments of human expression or adornment, on
mon, "natural inclination" to communicate our Sedgwick's account, the experience of the sub-
feeling to everyone else. There is no obvious lime may itself prove isolating. And it is likely to
reason why this should not apply to our feeling make us care so much about the possibility of
for the sublime.2' human expression that we are swamped by the
What kind of aesthetic and personal costs specific occasions in which the possibility is
would there be for human beings trapped in uncertainly realized.
circumstances which denied any likelihood of Moreover, under the conditions of an isolation
fulfillment to such natural human inclinations? that cannot be known to be permanent and irre-
Kant is pretty explicit about our relation to beauty mediable-which might provide a kind of relief-
in a state of isolation: the pain and perplexity of the sublime would
become acute. Under such conditions, who can
Someone abandoned on some desolate island would afford the knowledge of the sublime? Who could
survive its promise of community and commu-
not, just for himself, adorn either his hut or himself;
nication, in the midst of an isolation whose
nor would he look for flowers, let alone grow them, to

This content downloaded from 161.116.100.129 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 18:27:20 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Gould Intensity and Its Audiences 313

sources cannot be traced either to society's ex- These questions may seem to end up taking us
clusions of you or to your withdrawal from beyond the realm of aesthetics and into ques-
society? tions about what sustains us, in the press of our
Kant may have wished to claim that our access own circumstances and in the knowledge that
to a transcendental ground for such judgments is our capacities for creative withdrawal are some-
sufficient to sustain us in our continuing aes- what less than those of Emily Dickinson, Char-
thetic education and practices (as he would lotte Bronte, or, for that matter, Immanuel Kant.
certainly wish to claim that it was enough to But I hope to have suggested that such question-
validate our judgments of the beautiful and the ing at least begins in a region that admits of
sublime). But would he have been right about systematic study. Moreover, this region ought to
this? Is it quite human to think that we can live be of interest to those who are looking for con-
on so slim a promise of future accord and com- nections between 18th century aesthetics and the
munity, surrounded by the disappointments and broader issues of isolation and expression, as
even disasters of our actual efforts at commu- these issues have been formulated by a feminist
nication? At such a moment, we may wish to criticism.
turn to the other writer whose version of the
sublime was rendered thematic in Sedgwick's TIMOTHY GOULD

account: Department of Philosophy


Box 49
The soul's Superior instants Metropolitan State College
Occur to her-alone- Denver, CO 80204
When friend-and Earth's occasion
Have infinite withdrawn.

1. Eve Kosofksy Sedgwick, The Coherence of Gothic


Or She-Herself-ascended Conventions (New York: Methuen Press, 1980), p. 138. For
To too remote a Height their encouragement and for their suggestions about earlier
versions of this essay, I want to thank Mary Devereaux,
For lower Recognition
Karen Hanson, Christine Korsgaard, Paul Mattick, Barbara
Than her Omnipotent_22 Packer, Eve Sedgwick, Garrett Stewart, Kathleen Whalen
and Joshua Wilner. My work on this material was supported
This is indeed a version of a sublime past "Earth's by a grant from the National Endowment for the Humanities.
2. See Paul Mattick, "Beautiful and Sublime: 'Gender
occasions," which is also, to say the least, be-
Totemism' and the Constitution of Art" in this issue of the
yond any specific interest in some piece of
Journal pp. 293-303. Some of my thoughts about these
nature, which might have occasioned the experi- matters were presented as a response to Mattick's paper
ence of the soul's "height" or elevation. The when portions of it were delivered to a panel on Feminist
poem charts a geography that transcends our Aesthetics at the 1988 meetings of the American Society for
Aesthetics. See also my "Engendering Aesthetics: Sublim-
capacity to recognize anything spatial. And the
ity, Sublimation and Misogyny in Burke and Kant" in Aes-
poem takes its speaker beyond anything other thetics, Politics, and Hermeneutics, eds. Gerald Bruns and
than the soul's autonomous power over herself. Stephen Watson [SUNY Press, forthcoming, 1991], and
(I must at least mention Dickinson's hint that this Robin Schott, Cognition and Eros: A Critique of the Kantian

autonomy is depicted as almost identical to the Paradigm (Boston: Beacon Press, 1988), esp. chs. 11 and
12. I would also like to thank Barbara Freeman for sending
soul's capacity to recognize herself, without inter-
me a chapter of her dissertation entitled "Femininity and the
mediaries.) Here is the Kantian sublime, with- Sublime," submitted to the Stanford University Program in
out the instigation of nature-but also without Western Culture. This work provides a kind of bridge be-
much possibility of being communicated to an tween the two categories that I have somewhat artificially
imposed on the criticism that I am discussing.
audience. To congratulate Dickinson on achiev-
3. See especially Sedgwick, The Coherence of Gothic
ing these heights would be beside the point, and Conventions. Thanks to her, I was also able to consult a draft
not merely because she wouldn't be listening. of her Epistemology of the Closet, forthcoming from the
The harder question is to ask where we are University of California Press and an early unpublished
located when we are attempting to recognize her essay called "Emily Dickinson's Sublime." Also relevant is
her Between Men: English Literature and Male Homosocial
achievement. Or in the words of my epigraph
Desire (Columbia University Press, 1985). See also, Neil
from Wallace Stevens, how do we stand to behold Hertz, The End of the Line: Essays on Psychoanalysis and
her sublime? The Sublime (Columbia University Press, 1985). Hertz's

This content downloaded from 161.116.100.129 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 18:27:20 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
314 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

work shares a region of concern and procedure with Sedg- usual Kantian obscurity about the object and its representa-
wick's. Moreover, since Hertz explicitly addresses Kant's tions, what seems especially unclear is the supposed connec-
Critique of Judgment, his work provides a useful set of tion between this aspect of "disinterestedness" and any
connections between Sedgwick's characteristic concerns and ordinary sense of impartiality-a connection that Kant and
the language of Kant's analyses. On the issues of gender, his critics seem to be equally convinced of.
sublimity and the lyric in de Quincy and Baudelaire, consult 8. I have been convinced by those accounts that suggest
Joshua Wilner's "The Stewed Muse of Prose," Modern that the sublime occurs in the shapes first of all not of
Language Notes 104 (1989): 1085-1098. De Quincy (and masculine power as such but of paternal power. That is, for
Coleridge) are some of the obvious places where the con- instance, what makes the experience of the sublime so suit-
cerns of German Idealism could have been transmitted to a able a successor to the experience of God's power and anger.
writer like Charlotte Bronte, a connection that Sedgwick See, e.g., Neil Hertz, The End of the Line, especially chap-
also suggests in the first book cited. See also Naomi Schor's ters 1 and 3. These issues go beyond the scope of the present
Reading in Detail: Aesthetics and the Feminine (New York: essay.
Methuen, 1987) and Frances Ferguson's Solitude and the 9. See Mattick, "Beautiful and Sublime," note 2, for ex-
Sublime: The Aesthetics of Individualism (New York: Me- tensive identifications of such masculinist language and in-
thuen, 1987). clination. See also Gould "Engendering Aesthetics," pp. 7-
4. Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. Werner S. Pluhar 9, for a depiction of Burke's slide into a specifically male
(Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987), section 29, p. 124 [265 in the vantage point on the objects of aesthetic experience.
Academy edition]. All further references will be incorpo- 10. Kant, of course, insists on the connection between the
rated in the text as follows: "#29, p. 124 [265]." sublime or "the elevated" (das Erhabene) and the subject's
5. One of the first thinkers to diagnose this pattern seems corresponding 'elevation." In section #28, p. 121 [262], he
to have been Mary Wollstonecraft in her Vindication of the suggests that nature is called sublime because it elevates
Rights of Women, first published in 1792. See, for instance, [erhebt] the imagination."
the passages reprinted in The Norton Anthology of Literature 11. Kant is often attacked for making too much of the
by Women, eds. Sandra M. Gilbert and Susan Gubar (New spectator's relation to the arts. Nietzsche goes so far as to
York: W.W. Norton, 1985), pp. 142-143, passim. accuse him of "unconsciously introduc[ing] the spectator
6. Kant, Observations on the Beautiful and Sublime, trans. into the concept 'beautiful'," Genealogy of Morals, third
John T. Goldthwait (University of California Press, 1960). essay, section 6. This becomes part of Nietzsche's accusa-
One quotation may serve to indicate the flavor of the chapter: tion that Kant has "emasculated" and "effeminized" aes-
thetics, in part by the very notion of disinterestedness.
However partial a criticism this remark turns out to be in
The virtue of a woman is a beautiful virtue. That of the male sex
relation to the beautiful, Nietzsche here at least seems to be
should be a noble virtue. Women will avoid the wicked not because it
is unright, but because it is ugly; and virtuous actions mean to them quite indifferent to Kant's entire discussion of the sublime.
such as are morally beautiful. Nothing of duty, nothing of compul- There is nothing "unconscious" about the way Kant charac-
sion, nothing of obligation! Woman is intolerant of all commands and terizes the spectator's mind ("the judging subject") as the
all morose constraint (p. 81). ultimate location of the sublime.
12. On heteronomy as passivity, see, e.g. Kant, Founda-
tions of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. L.W. Beck (New
Though paternalistic, this is not, of course, an entirely
York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1959), p. 77. On the relation of sub-
negative thing to say. It would be interesting to compare such
limity and morality, see, for instance, the conclusion to the
thoughts to the work of Carol Gilligan, Nell Noddings and
second Critique, about the starry heavens and the moral law.
other writers, who present gender-based contrasts between
But the idea of moral awakening as a sublime moment runs
ethical sensibilities. It would also be interesting to compare
throughout the book, especially in the discussion of the
Kant's pre-critical thoughts on these matters with the devel-
moral incentive. One should also bear in mind the ever-
opment of his moral thought in the third Critique and in later
perplexing notion that "beauty is a symbol of morality" (CJ,
work. Paul Guyer has pointed out to me the existence of a
section 59.) I am indebted to Christine Korsgaard for a
Schillerian strain in Kant's later work, a strain which con-
timely reminder about these passages. The role of false
ceives of a greater role for feeling in the moral life. We might
pictures of the active and the passive in philosophical and
try conceiving of this line of thought as partially anticipated
literary accounts of freedom and of originality is the subject
in distorted form in some of Kant's paternalistic reflections
of investigations I am currently pursuing.
on women.
13. Unfortunately, those who have been most fruitfully
7. Apart from various feminist critiques of the very idea
influenced by post-structuralist thought are often excessive-
of universality or "disinterestedness" in ethics or aesthetics,
ly casual about the details of arguments and philosophical
Terry Eagleton and Pierre Bourdieu have argued for what
texts. For instance, Naomi Schor's otherwise fascinating
they take to be the class origins of the very idea of taste.
book Reading in Detail: Aesthetics and the Feminine be-
Most such accounts seem to be working with a very crude
gins by dismissing the entire issue of what she calls "meth-
and unKantian notion of "disinterestedness." Specifically,
odology":
they seem to underrate the significance of the fact that part
of Kant's contrast is between my disinterest in the object
all literary methodologies, all critical theories and histories of critical
conceived as my capacity to make something of the repre-
theory serve to validate idiosyncratic relationships to the text. Unless
sentation of the object "within myself" and, on the other
the poetician or hermeneut be mad, however, the laws she abstracts
hand, my interest in the object conceived as "the respect in from her personal storehouse of myths and the interpretations she
which I depend on the object's existence" (p. 46 [205]). translates from the hieroglyphs of her unconscious will encounter in
Nothing much is clear about this distinction. And beyond the
other readers recognition and response.

This content downloaded from 161.116.100.129 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 18:27:20 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Gould Intensity and Its Audiences 315

14. The sublime is also bound up with "the inadequacy of woman in the Attic (Yale University Press, 1979). The title
the imagination" for representing or exhibiting ideas, e.g. signifies a particular historical way of conceiving the fate of
the idea of certain wholes (p. 109 [252]). Jean-Francois women writers, of female creativity and indeed of feminine
Lyotard has put forward an extended idea of the sublime as sensibility, held in certain kinds of 'domestic' confinement
involved in a much wider range of efforts to represent the in the 19th century.
unrepresentable. See also Peregrinations: Law, Form, and 20. Paul Guyer, "Kant's Distinction Between the Beau-
Event (Columbia University Press, 1988), pp. 40-43, passim. tiful and the Sublime," Review of Metaphysics 35 (1982):
15. This paraphrase is drawn in part from the paragraph 753-783.
quoted in the epigraph to this essay. 21. A possible reason is this: Kant thinks that we "require"
16. Virginia Woolf, A Room of One's Own (1929; New a "greater culture" of the cognitive faculties (especially of
York: Harcourt, Brace and World, 1957), p. 50. This phrase the faculty of ideas, namely, reason) in order to experience
is part of her imagining the figure she calls "Shakespeare's the sublime, and that therefore the experience of the sublime
sister." In the light of Sedgwick's work, we should consider is rarer than the experience of the beautiful (#29, p. 124
Woolf's later comments about Jane Austen and the Brontes, [264]). So Kant may think that we have less inclination to
here and on pp. 77-78. communicate this experience, since we may think that even
17. I am here primarily summarizing her analysis of Lucy the possible audience for our expressions is more restricted.
Snowe, the narrating character of Villette. Part of Sedg- But in fact Kant's claim about the relative rarity of the
wick's complex and powerful reading-which needs to be experience of the sublime may be false. And even if it is true,
studied in detail-is centered on Lucy's capacity for a some- the moral I am imputing to him may not be the right moral:
times willful silence and the connection of this capacity to we may have as great or a greater stake in wishing to com-
the author's ability to present her own various versions of the municate the sublime than in wishing to communicate the
sublime. beautiful.
18. Sedgwick, Gothic, p. 153. 22. The Complete Poems of Emily Dickinson, ed. Thomas
19. See Susan Gubar and Sandra M. Gilbert, The Mad- H. Johnson (Boston: Little Brown, 1960), #306.

This content downloaded from 161.116.100.129 on Fri, 29 Sep 2017 18:27:20 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Potrebbero piacerti anche