Sei sulla pagina 1di 9

Medical Ethics: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide

JJZ Polaris, Yale Law School, New Haven, CT, USA


LS Lehmann, Harvard Medical School, Boston, MA, USA
r 2016 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

Abstract

This chapter explores the various options that individuals may consider at the end of life. The ethics of
assisted suicide and euthanasia are discussed. Many see assisted dying as an opportunity for individuals to
avoid suffering and exercise their autonomy in the dying process. Those who object to the practice raise
concerns over the sanctity of life, the integrity of the medical profession, changing norms at the end of life,
and the risk of abuse. Finally, the current legal landscape of assisted dying is reviewed. The topic remains
controversial in the medical community and the public at large.

Introduction permitted and how that legal status was achieved. A few
countries and states in the United States have legalized
Discussions about the end of life can be challenging for certain assisted dying practices (see Table 1), but many
patients, family members, and providers. Death and others have considered the issue in the courts or the
dying are emotionally fraught subjects, and people vary legislatures in recent years and maintained the status
immensely in their outlook based on personal tempera- quo of prohibition. Anecdotal and empirical evidence
ment and cultural background. Medicine has tradition- suggests, however, that some physicians and family
ally concerned itself with the preservation and members choose to assist patients with suicide or
prolongation of life, but in recent decades, some patients euthanasia even where such practices are illegal (Meier
have begun to prioritize other goals in their care. et al., 1998; Maitra et al., 2005; Jamison, 1996).
This chapter explores assisted dying, an umbrella A note on terminology: We will be referring through-
term that we use to encompass two distinct methods out to ‘patients’ who consider various options to end their
by which another person (the ‘assister’) plays a role in lives. Assisted dying is often discussed in the context of
ending an individual’s life. Assisted suicide involves terminally ill patients, and some jurisdictions have legal-
passive assistance: the assister provides the individual ized end-of-life options exclusively for that population. In
with the means by which he may end his own life. A addition, many forms of medicalized assisted dying in-
doctor may prescribe a lethal dose of medication, for volve a physician who prescribes medication or adminis-
example, but the patient must take and swallow the pill ters an injection, so the recipient is a patient at least within
on his own. In euthanasia, on the other hand, the assister that relationship. We recognize, however, that individuals
performs the final action in ending the individual’s life, with nonterminal diseases or no medical problems at
such as by administering a lethal injection. all may wish to voluntarily end their lives, and some
This chapter begins with the historical background on jurisdictions permit them to do so (see Table 1).
end-of-life decision making and palliative care (section
Background: Autonomy and Dying). After outlining the
various options individuals may consider at the end of
life (section The Spectrum of Options at the End of Life), Background: Autonomy and Dying
the chapter turns to the ethical debate over assisted
Technological Advancement and the ‘Burden’ of Care
dying (section The Ethical Debate over Assisted Dying).
Many see assisted dying as an opportunity for indi- The last 150 years have produced tremendous advances
viduals to avoid suffering and exercise their autonomy in medical science. The revolution in patient care
in the dying process. Those who object to the practice includes curative medicine such as antibiotics, preventive
raise concerns over the sanctity of life, the integrity of techniques such as antiseptic surgical precautions, and
the medical profession, changing norms at the end of life-sustaining technologies such as ventilators and
life, and the risk of abuse. The topic remains contro- feeding tubes. It was not so long ago that doctors were
versial in the medical community and the public at large. relatively powerless to address many types of common
Finally, the legal considerations of assisted dying are diseases and injuries; by the 1960s, however, the death
discussed (section Legal Considerations in Assisted of a patient came to be seen as a failure of medicine
Dying). Most countries prohibit assisted dying of any rather than an inevitable result of life’s misfortunes.
kind. In places where it is legally permissible, there During this period of rapid scientific progress, the
is extensive variation in the precise details of what is driving goal was to keep patients alive and healthy for as

Encyclopedia of Forensic and Legal Medicine, Volume 3 doi:10.1016/B978-0-12-800034-2.00248-2 321


322 Medical Ethics: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide

Table 1 Details on countries where assisted dying is legal

Country or state/territory What form of assisted How and when was it Details: eligibility requirements, procedural safeguards, and
dying is legal? (Assisted legalized? other notes
suicide, euthanasia, or
both)

Australia: Northern Both (not legal anymore) By statute in 1995, The repealed law had the following provisions:
Territory repealed in 1997 Eligibility: Competent adults with terminal illness
Procedural safeguards: The patient must make multiple
requests for assisted dying. Three physicians must certify
the patient, including a specialist in the patient’s condition
and a psychiatrist who checks for depression
Belgium Euthanasia By statute in 2002 Eligibility: Competent adults and emancipated minors who
have ‘unbearable suffering’ (no terminal illness required);
children with terminal illness and ‘unbearable suffering’
Procedural safeguards: Standarda
Canada Assisted suicide By judicial decision in In Carter v. Canada, the Supreme Court of British Columbia
2013 (not final) struck down the Criminal Code provision that prohibited
physician-assisted suicide. At the time of writing, the
Supreme Court of Canada had agreed to hear the case later
in 2014
Eligibility: Competent adult with terminal illness
Procedural safeguards: Standarda
Colombia Euthanasia (see details) By judicial decision in Colombia’s Penal Code criminalizes euthanasia, but the
1997 Colombia Constitutional Court found a constitutional right
to euthanasia in certain circumstances. The Congress of
Colombia has considered and rejected bills to formally
legalize euthanasia by statute, leaving the ultimate legal
status somewhat undefined
Eligibility: Competent adults with terminal illness
Procedural safeguards: A physician must administer the
injection
England and Wales Assisted suicide (see By issuance of The UK has not formally legalized assisted suicide. The
details) prosecutorial guidelines simply specify a set of factors that make
guidelines in 2010 prosecution less likely, such as:

• The person was not a competent adult


• The person did not make a voluntary request for assisted
suicide
• The assister was not acting in a medical capacity
• The assister was motivated by compassion
• The assister provided the means of suicide without
advocating for the suicide itself
• The assister reported the suicide to law enforcement
authorities
Note: England, Wales, and Germany are the only jurisdictions
where the law permits nonmedical assisted suicide but
discourages medical-assisted suicide

Germany Assisted suicide Lack of prohibition on Suicide is legal in Germany, so it is not a crime for an
suicide assister to provide the means by which another person
commits suicide. The suicide may not be coerced, and the
assister may not violate other laws on possession of
controlled substances, firearms, etc.
Eligibility: Competent adults
Note: England, Wales, and Germany are the only jurisdictions
where the law permits nonmedical assisted suicide but
discourages medical-assisted suicide

Luxembourg Both By statute and Eligibility: Competent adults with terminal illness
constitutional Procedural safeguards: Standarda
amendment in 2009
(passed in 2008)
(Continued )
Medical Ethics: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide 323

Table 1 Continued

Country or state/territory What form of assisted How and when was it Details: eligibility requirements, procedural safeguards, and
dying is legal? (Assisted legalized? other notes
suicide, euthanasia, or
both)

Netherlands Both By several court Eligibility: Individuals with severe physical or psychological
decisions starting in suffering (no terminal illness required). Competent adults
1973, then codified by may request on their own; teenagers aged 12–16 years
statute in 2002 may request with parental consent; parents may request on
behalf of newborns with severe conditions
Procedural safeguards: Standarda
Switzerland Assisted suicide By update to the criminal Switzerland only criminalizes assisting a suicide for ‘selfish’
code effective 1942 reasons. Both medical and nonmedical assisted suicide are
thus permitted
Eligibility: No requirements. (Note: Switzerland is the ONLY
country where assisted dying is available to nonresidents.)
Private organizations will typically only assist competent
adults
Procedural safeguards: To guard against prosecution, private
organizations often require a written request from the
patient and then have a physician certify the patient’s
hopeless/terminal condition before providing the lethal pills
United States: Montana Assisted suicide By judicial decision in The Montana Supreme Court’s 2009 decision in Baxter v.
2009 Montana provided that any physician who faces criminal
prosecution for providing lethal medication to a terminally
ill patient may raise the affirmative defense of consent.
Montana has not formally codified the legality of assisted
suicide by statute
Eligibility: Competent adults with terminal illness
Procedural safeguards: Physician must provide the lethal
pills
United States: Oregon Assisted suicide By ballot initiative in Eligibility: Competent adults with terminal illness who are
1994 expected to die within 6 months
Procedural safeguards: Standarda
United States: New Assisted suicide By judicial decision in A New Mexico state district court’s 2014 decision in Morris
Mexico 2014 (not final) v. Brandenberg found a constitutional right to assisted
dying, striking down the state statute prohibiting the
practice. At the time of writing, the decision had not been
appealed, nor had the state taken any legislative action
Eligibility: Competent adults with terminal illness
Procedural safeguards: Physician must provide the lethal
pills
United States: Vermont Assisted suicide By statute in 2013 Eligibility: Competent adults with terminal illness who are
expected to die within 6 months
Procedural safeguards: Standarda
United States: Assisted suicide By ballot initiative in Eligibility: Competent adults with terminal illness who are
Washington State 2008 expected to die within 6 months
Procedural safeguards: Standarda
a
Standard procedural safeguards shared by many nations: The patient must make multiple separate requests for assisted dying. Two physicians must certify the patient’s
condition. A psychologist must screen the patient if there are doubts about competency. A physician must administer the pills/injection and report the death.

long as possible. Eventually, though, some patients, action was seen as inconsistent with the Hippocratic
families, and physicians began to wonder whether an Oath’s mandate to ‘do no harm.’ Other providers feared
intervention could be so burdensome that the costs legal liability, and indeed, some law enforcement of-
outweighed the benefits. At a deeper level, they began to ficials threatened to bring charges against doctors or
question the longstanding presumption that living longer hospitals who ‘killed’ patients by discontinuing life-
was always better. At first, medical providers resisted sustaining interventions. The Supreme Court of New
requests to discontinue life-sustaining treatment. Such Jersey’s 1976 decision in In re Quinlan was the first in a
324 Medical Ethics: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide

series of cases that established patients’ legal right to general, the level of public controversy and physician
refuse treatment, even where doing so would lead to opposition related to a given practice tends to escalate as
their death. the role of outside actors becomes more prominent
(Curlin et al., 2008; Yun et al., 2011; Maitra et al.,
2005). For the most part, these approaches are con-
Palliative Care
sidered by terminally ill patients who either do not have
Legal cases about the right to refuse medical inter- the option of or have chosen not to pursue further life-
ventions helped frame a broader conversation about prolonging treatments.
end-of-life decision making in the United States. Modern
medicine had become effective enough at preserving life
More Passive: Hastening Death by Removing Medical
to become burdensome to some patients; nevertheless,
Treatment
the growing public faith in the marvels of medicine im-
pelled many seriously ill patients and their families to Withholding and withdrawing treatment
fight death to the last breath, trying every possible Competent patients have the right to decline treatment,
treatment even when the hope of success was slim. Pal- including interventions that could significantly prolong
liative care has responded to these concerns by trying to their lives. These decisions are generally not considered
refocus patient care at the end of life on comfort (Kelly ‘suicide’ because the patient ultimately dies of his
and Meier, 2010). underlying disease rather than an active intervention.
One of the primary goals of palliative care is simply Some ethicists differentiate between refusing treatment
to manage the symptoms of a disease rather than attack entirely and withdrawing it once it has already begun on
the disease itself, a mindset that emphasizes caring for the grounds that the latter scenario involves an active
the patient rather than attempting to cure him. This step that makes the patient worse off than before. The
simple notion was quite provocative, acknowledging as more common view (and the view codified in law in
it did the limits of curative medicine and the real possi- many jurisdictions) is that the two practices are ethically
bility that patients may genuinely wish to trade off equivalent.
the longest possible life in exchange for a more
comfortable and peaceful death. Palliative care offers Withholding and withdrawing nutrition
patients medical monitoring and pain management, as Some patients choose to end their lives by refusing
well as psychosocial support to guide patients and their nutrition, relying on a combination of symptom man-
families through the dying process. agement and limited hydration to keep them
comfortable until they slip into a coma and then pass
Advance directives away. This option is most commonly exercised by
With the advent of medical technology that can sustain terminally ill patients, and is seen by many ethicists as
life and an increased emphasis on patient autonomy, the equivalent to refusing any other medical intervention.
medical profession developed the concept of advance The choice becomes more legally complicated in pa-
directives. An advance directive is a mechanism by tients without a terminal illness, however, because it
which patients can designate an individual to make de- may be construed as suicide, which most jurisdictions
cisions on their behalf, and also allows patients to spe- either prohibit or consider grounds for involuntary
cify in advance their goals, values, and preferences for psychiatric commitment. Forced nutrition has been used
medical care in the event that they are unable to com- in psychiatric and prison settings (Crosby et al., 2007),
municate for themselves (White and Arnold, 2011). For so relatively healthy individuals who choose to stop
example, a patient may specify that she does not wish to eating may find themselves involuntarily kept alive and
be resuscitated if she has a cardiac arrest. By clarifying referred for mental health services.
these difficult choices ahead of time, patients can avoid
leaving their family or clinical care team to guess about
Incompetent Patients: Advance Directives and Surrogate
what the patient would have wanted.
Decision Makers
There is an important qualification to the options dis-
The Spectrum of Options at the End of Life cussed thus far: generally, they are only available to
patients who are competent to make medical decisions,
This section places assisted suicide and euthanasia in a thereby excluding children and the mentally ill. These
broader array of end-of-life options. Patients who wish same competent patients can use advance directives
to expedite their own deaths may consider a number of (described in section Background: Autonomy and
approaches, some of which are illegal in many juris- Dying) to specify in advance how they would like their
dictions. These options exist on a spectrum, from those care to proceed if they lose decision-making capacity
that proceed entirely on the patient’s own initiative to and are unable to communicate (White and Arnold,
those with active involvement from an outside party. In 2011).
Medical Ethics: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide 325

For incompetent patients, a designated healthcare their own lives. Despite the legal consequences, some
agent or surrogate must make these important decisions. doctors, family members, and friends choose to provide
The process is straightforward when there is someone lethal doses of medication or other means to help pa-
legally designated to make decisions on the patient’s tients end their life (Meier et al., 1998; Maitra et al.,
behalf, such as a legal guardian or someone with durable 2005; Jamison, 1996).
power of attorney.
Without a clear decision maker under the law, med- Euthanasia
ical teams may defer to family members with strong In euthanasia, the assister moves from passively pro-
evidence of what the patient would have wanted. In viding the means of death to actively causing the death
some cases, however, there may be disputes among po- itself. Medical euthanasia typically involves a lethal in-
tential deciders such as family members and close jection (similar to the injections used in capital punish-
friends. Decision makers (legally designated and other- ment). Nonmedical euthanasia may involve more violent
wise) may also disagree with clinicians over how to methods like a gunshot or smothering, which can be
proceed, pushing for treatment the medical team views traumatic for the assister, even when performed at the
as futile or ill advised. Such disputes may be referred to patient’s request (Jamison, 1996).
an institutional ethics committee for discussion, and may Most jurisdictions prohibit euthanasia of any kind.
ultimately involve legal action. The highly publicized Those that permit it (see Table 1) may require an explicit
case of Terri Schiavo, for example, involved several request by the patient, or may allow physicians to pro-
rounds of litigation between Ms. Schiavo’s spouse and ceed with euthanasia where they deem it to be in a pa-
parents to determine whether her feeding tube could be tient’s best interests.
withdrawn (Schwarz and Coyle, 2006).

More Active: Providing or Administering the Means of Death The Ethical Debate over Assisted Dying
Palliative sedation
Our understanding of pain management has improved Assisted dying is a controversial subject that raises
in recent decades, but some patients nonetheless ex- deeply personal questions at the intersection of medical
perience severe chronic pain or discomfort that cannot technology, ethics, and spirituality. In this section, we
be addressed by conventional palliative strategies. explore the main arguments advanced to support legal-
Terminally ill patients with severe pain may request ization of assisted dying and the main ethical objections
palliative sedation (also called terminal sedation), where raised by those in opposition.
a physician induces a coma using powerful narcotics.
Most patients who receive palliative sedation are not
Arguments in Favor of Permitting Assisted Dying
kept alive with life-sustaining technologies like venti-
lators and artificial nutrition, and some have argued that Autonomy and dying
the practice is equivalent to a slow form of euthanasia Assisted dying is predicated on the notion that patients
(ten Have and Welie, 2014; Jansen and Sulmasy, 2002). have the right to control their own dying process. Some
The heightened doses of medication used in palliative patients want dying to be something they do rather than
sedation risk reducing patients’ expected life span, but something that happens to them. They have the right to
the practice is permitted under the law in many countries withhold or withdraw life-saving treatment, but that is
because it is seen as a pain-management strategy. an inherently reactive form of autonomy: the option to
choose death is triggered by an acute condition (e.g.,
Assisted suicide refusing resuscitation for cardiac arrest) or a particular
Assisted suicide is precisely what the name suggests: kind of chronic care (e.g., discontinuing artificial
another person (the ‘assister’) provides the means by nutrition).
which an individual takes his or her own life. Medical- Some patients with a terminal illness face neither
assisted suicide involves a physician prescribing a lethal an immediate health threat nor dependence on life-
dose of medication to be self-administered by the pa- sustaining technology. As a further distinction, assisted
tient. This practice has been legalized in several countries suicide by a self-administered pill is not an option for
and US states (see Table 1). More generally, assisted patients who cannot swallow or self-administer medi-
suicide may include the provision of prescription medi- cation, such as those with advanced amyotrophic lateral
cations, illegal drugs, or a weapon with the under- sclerosis or quadriplegia. Given the existing right to re-
standing that the recipient plans to commit suicide. Most fuse treatment, some claim that prohibitions on assisted
jurisdictions outlaw these types of actions. suicide and euthanasia draw arbitrary lines, allowing
The literature suggests that even in jurisdictions that certain types of patients to control the time and manner
prohibit assisted suicide, patients with terminal illnesses of their death and leaving others to wait until their
or severe chronic disability request assistance in ending illness takes its toll.
326 Medical Ethics: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide

Physical and emotional suffering limitations can be interpreted as endorsing the view
Patients may seek assisted dying for many different that a life with a disability is a life not worth living
reasons that span the physical, emotional, existential, (Behuniak, 2011). Legally sanctioning assisted suicide
and spiritual aspects of their lives. Individual patients thus implicitly denigrates all the similarly disabled peo-
often cite multiple motivations across these domains ple who nonetheless manage to live rich and full lives.
(Oregon Public Health Division, 2013; Dees et al., 2011;
Fischer et al., 2009). The role of the medical profession
Advances in palliative medicine have produced many Many physicians see their role as one of healing and
effective management strategies, but some patients preserving life. They view assisted dying as incompatible
nonetheless experience chronic pain or simply express a with the Hippocratic Oath’s principle of ‘do no harm,’
preference for death over continued existence. Many just as many physicians and medical societies officially
terminally ill or disabled patients are dependent on oppose physician involvement in torture or executions.
others for basic care, and may lose control of their Some doctors also worry that allowing assisted dying
bodily functions. Those who pursue assisted dying ex- may erode public trust in the medical profession. Other
plain that they suffer at this perceived loss of dignity, doctors see assisted dying as consistent with medicine’s
declining independence, and inability to enjoy the ac- broader goal to alleviate suffering. Nonetheless, the
tivities that give their life meaning. Others comment medical profession overall typically opposes assisted
on feelings of despair or hopelessness; living with a fatal dying practices at a higher rate than the general popu-
disease means accepting that their condition is only lation, though in both groups, religious belief in a strong
going to continue getting worse until they die. predictor of opposition to assisted dying (Curlin et al.,
Some patients would prefer to decide when and how 2008; Yun et al., 2011; Smets et al., 2011; Lee et al.,
that death will occur, to combat feelings of powerless- 2009; Maitra et al., 2005; Lisker et al., 2008). Medical
ness in the face of disease and death by exercising their professional societies are often vocal players in debates
own will in dying. Some patients find solace simply in over legalization of assisted dying practices.
knowing that they have the option to determine their
own death. In Oregon, for example, a large minority of Uncertainties of medical prognostication
patients who request and receive lethal medication never In many jurisdictions, assisted dying is only available for
use it (Oregon Public Health Division, 2013); they patients who are terminally ill. Critics of assisted dying
ultimately die of their disease, but they found comfort in argue that prognoses at the end of life are often in-
knowing they had the option to take the medication at accurate and fear that patients may cut their lives short
any time if the suffering grew too great. based on a grim prognosis when they might have lived
much longer than expected (Glare et al., 2003; Twomey
et al., 2008).
Objections to Assisted Dying
The sanctity of life The risk of abuse
One of the main objections to assisted dying stems from Critics of assisted dying express concerns over the effects
a belief that we undermine the sanctity of life by taking of legalization on patients themselves. Patients may feel
actions to hasten death. Those who hold this belief may pressured by family members or physicians into choos-
view all forms of suicide as morally wrong, and they ing a premature death, whether because of explicit co-
often oppose other practices like withholding and with- ercion or out of a desire not to be a burden on others.
drawing treatment or nutrition. Across countries, op- These fears are particularly acute as applied to margin-
position to various forms of assisted dying is correlated alized groups like patients who are elderly or less edu-
with strongly held religious beliefs (Curlin et al., 2008; cated, since they may be more susceptible to outside
Yun et al., 2011; Smets et al., 2011; Lee et al., 2009; influence in their medical decision making. Patients with
Maitra et al., 2005; Lisker et al., 2008). In political de- mental illnesses such as depression may be more likely to
bates over legalization of assisted dying, religious groups request assisted dying, but are not permitted to do so in
are often among the most vocal opponents. many jurisdictions; however, their disease may be dif-
One variation of the argument about the sanctity of ficult to recognize, particularly in the emotionally
life applies specifically to those living with disability. As fraught context of terminal illness (Ganzini et al., 2008).
discussed above, a primary motivation for seeking as- There is also the question of how to handle requests for
sisted dying is the suffering arising from loss of auton- assisted dying made on behalf of incompetent patients
omy and dignity: some patients with impaired mobility by family members or guardians.
or severe medical symptoms would rather end their Jurisdictions that have legalized assisted dying often
life than persist in such a state. Many people with dis- did so with strict procedural safeguards in place to guard
abilities, however, live with those same types of bodily against these types of concerns (see section Legal Con-
limitations and symptoms. They argue that allowing siderations in Assisted Dying). The data suggest that
patients to kill themselves because they have physical those who choose assisted dying tend to be more affluent
Medical Ethics: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide 327

and educated (Lindsay (2009). A lack of recorded in- recognition may also be used to formally recognize and
stances of specific patient abuse is a positive sign, but clarify assisted dying rights that were legalized by other
there may nonetheless be instances of pressure on pa- mechanisms described in this section.
tients that go unreported and instances of patients with
depression who go undiagnosed. By judicial decision
In a jurisdiction where assisted dying is illegal, a person
Shifting social norms may bring a lawsuit challenging the constitutionality of
Embedded within arguments about the sanctity of life that prohibition. The Montana Supreme Court’s 2009
and the risk of abuse is a concern about the ‘slippery opinion in Baxter v. Montana, for example, de-
slope,’ the fear that legalizing one controversial practice criminalized assisted dying under the state constitution.
will eventually lead to other, more problematic social Courts in the Netherlands similarly decriminalized as-
consequences by shifting the boundaries of what we sisted suicide and euthanasia in a number of decisions
consider morally acceptable. Some view the current de- issued through the 1970s and 1980s, and the legislature
bate over assisted suicide in many Western nations as an codified those decisions with legislation in 2002.
inevitable result of the debate a few decades ago over
withdrawing life-saving treatment. They may fear that By referendum
legalizing assisted suicide will ultimately lead to the Some jurisdictions allow citizens to vote directly on
legalization of voluntary or involuntary euthanasia. policy questions. In the US states of Oregon and
Commentators point to euthanasia performed by the Washington, for example, assisted suicide was legalized
Nazis as an indication of how disregard for human life by successful citizen ballot initiatives.
can contribute to greater atrocities.
There is also concern that legalization of assisted Lack of prohibition
dying will change our social norms and expectations, The 1942 version of the Swiss Criminal Code crimin-
such that the right to die could eventually start to feel alized assisted suicide for selfish motives, but said
like a duty to die. Advocates worry that choosing to wait nothing about assisted suicide for unselfish reasons.
for death from natural causes to occur would come to be That silence has been interpreted as legalization, and
seen as a selfish use of resources, and that the elderly and assisted suicide has been practiced in Switzerland ever
individuals with disabilities or terminal illnesses may feel since. Similarly, Germany does not criminalize suicide,
pressured to opt for assisted dying. so assisted suicide is not a crime as long as the assister
A related concern pertains to the state of palliative does not coerce the decision.
care more generally: if patients have the option of ending
their lives due to great suffering, there may be less of Prosecutorial discretion
an incentive to push for advances in treating physical The United Kingdom has not formally legalized assisted
and psychological pain. Thus far, however, experience dying, but the Crown Prosecution issued guidelines in
has shown that legalized assisted dying correlates with 2010 that permit prosecutorial discretion in cases of
greater overall investment in palliative services (Lindsay, assisted suicide in England and Wales (Scotland and
2009). Ireland have not followed suit). The guidelines outline
various factors that make prosecution more or less likely
(see Table 1).
Legal Considerations in Assisted Dying
What Is Legalized?
There is no single approach to legalizing assisted dying.
Jurisdictions have legalized different types of practices, Table 1 reviews the specific practices legalized by each
relied on different legal mechanisms to do so, and tar- country or state.
geted different groups of patients and assisters. This
section reviews the various legal considerations that Assisted suicide versus euthanasia
jurisdictions must grapple with, along with examples Some countries, like Luxembourg, have legalized both
from various countries that exemplify the different ap- assisted suicide and euthanasia. The Netherlands has
proaches. See Table 1 for an overview of each juris- also legalized both practices, as well as permitting both
diction where some form of assisted dying is legal. voluntary euthanasia (where a competent patient makes
the request) and nonvoluntary euthanasia (where a
physician or guardian decides on behalf of an in-
Mechanisms for Legalization
competent patient).
By statute or regulation Other jurisdictions, like Switzerland and several US
The most straightforward path to legalizing assisted states, have legalized assisted suicide while maintaining
dying is for the government to pass a law, as Lux- prohibitions on euthanasia. In these jurisdictions, the
embourg’s parliament did in 2008. Official statutory only legal methods of assisted dying are those that the
328 Medical Ethics: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide

patient can administer himself. Belgium, on the other patient must make three requests with mandatory
hand, has legalized euthanasia but not assisted suicide. waiting periods in between to ensure that the decision is
not a hasty one.
Who is eligible?
Some jurisdictions tightly limit the option of assisted
Additional medical certification
dying. In Oregon, for example, assisted suicide is only
Several jurisdictions require that patients seeking as-
permitted for competent adults who are legal residents
sisted dying must have their conditions certified by an
of the state, diagnosed with a terminal illness, and ex-
additional medical professional. Where assisted dying is
pected to die within 6 months. Switzerland, meanwhile,
only permitted for terminally ill patients, the medical
requires neither legal residency nor a terminal illness; it
professional must certify the diagnosis and potentially a
has thus become a destination for ‘suicide tourism,’ since
prognosis of death within a specified time period (e.g.,
anyone may travel to Switzerland and receive assisted
6 months in Oregon). In Belgium, where the eligibility
suicide. Belgium recently legalized euthanasia for term-
criterion is not terminal illness but rather ‘unbearable
inally ill children. The Netherlands permits assisted
suffering,’ the medical professional must attest that the
suicide and euthanasia for teenagers (with or without
patient meets that definition.
terminal illness) who have parental consent, as well as
euthanasia of newborns with severe medical conditions
when requested by the parents. Mental health screening
Many jurisdictions require mental health screening for
Who can assist? any patient who is suspected of having a mental health
Most jurisdictions with legal assisted dying either re- problem, whether because of medical history or recent
quire or emphasize a medical model: physicians perform behavior. Sweden and the Netherlands permit some
assisted suicide by prescribing a patient a lethal dose of mentally ill individuals to seek assisted dying, as long
medication, and perform euthanasia by lethal injection. as they are found to be competent to make medical
Luxembourg and all relevant US states require medical decisions. Jurisdictions like Oregon attempt to screen
involvement in assisted dying. Switzerland does not out patients with conditions like depression or bipolar
mandate the presence of a doctor, since any form of disorder that may be affecting the choice to pursue
unselfish assisted suicide is legal, though medical staff assisted dying.
are involved in most assisted deaths. England, Wales,
and Germany are outliers in that their prosecutorial
Centralized reporting
guidelines favor assisted suicide performed by a non-
Most jurisdictions require centralized reporting so they
medical person rather than a physician.
can monitor details like the number of requests made,
the number of patients deemed ineligible and why, how
What Procedural Safeguards Are in Place? many patients actually ingested the medication (as op-
posed to dying from natural causes), where a patient
Many jurisdictions impose procedural safeguards on
chose to die (home, hospice, hospital, etc.), and the
assisted dying to protect patients from abuse and to
length of time from ingestion of the medication to un-
ensure compliance with eligibility criteria.
consciousness and death.
The Netherlands was the first country to codify a set
of safeguards developed by the Royal Dutch Medical
Association. As other nations legalized assisted dying
The Role of Private Organizations
practices, they looked to the Dutch model for guidance.
Oregon included many similar provisions in the Death In most jurisdictions with legalized assisted dying, pri-
With Dignity Act in 1994, and that legislation has in vate organizations have been founded to provide edu-
turn become the standard for other US states seeking to cation and to help patients and clinicians meet the
legalize assisted suicide. As a result, though eligibility necessary procedural requirements. The most prominent
criteria for assisted dying vary extensively across juris- examples include Exit (Switzerland), Dignitas (Switzer-
dictions, the procedural safeguards display a high degree land), and Compassion and Choices (Oregon, USA).
of consistency. (These common features are listed as These ‘right to die’ organizations may have been in-
‘standard’ procedural safeguards in Table 1.) volved in political activity that promoted the legalization
Some critics of assisted dying, however, point to em- of assisted dying, and then shifted to an advisory and
pirical evidence that these safeguards are not always support capacity for the practice of assisted dying. They
followed (Pereira, 2011). answer questions, assist with paper work, help patients
find doctors who are willing to participate in the process
Written requests and waiting periods by certifying medical conditions or prescribing lethal
It is not uncommon to require that a competent patient medication, and facilitate the required data reporting
make a written request for assisted dying. In Oregon, a (Ziegler and Bosshard, 2007).
Medical Ethics: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide 329

In re Quinlan, 355A.2d 647 (N.J. 1976).


See also: Consent: Mental Capacity Assessment. Death Jamison, S., 1996. When drugs fail: Assisted deaths and not-so-lethal drugs.
Investigation Systems: Murder, Manslaughter, Homicide, and Journal of Pain and Symptom Management 4, 223–243.
Jansen, L.A., Sulmasy, D.P., 2002. Sedation, alimentation, hydration and
Attempts − Definitions. Deliberate Self-Harm Patterns: Patterns of
equivocation: Careful conversation about care at the end of life. Annals of
Injury. Deliberate Self-Harm Patterns: Psychology. Medical Ethics: Internal Medicine 136, 845–849.
Advance Directives ('Living Will'). Medical Ethics: Principles of Kelly, A.M., Meier, D.E., 2010. Palliative care − A shifting paradigm. New England
Medical Ethics. Medical Ethics: Withholding or Withdrawing Life- Journal of Medicine 363, 781–782.
Sustaining Treatment. Murder−Suicide (Dyadic Death). Religious Lee, W., Price, A., Rayner, L., Hotopf, M., 2009. Survey of doctors’ opinions of the
legalisation of physician assisted suicide. BMC Medical Ethics 10, 2.
Attitudes to Death. Suicide: Etiology, Methods, and Statistics. Lindsay, R.A., 2009. Oregon’s experience: Evaluating the record. American Journal of
Suicide: Self-Harm. Suicide: Youth Suicide Bioethics 9, 19–27.
Lisker, R., del Rio, A.A., Villa, A.R., Carnevale, A., 2008. Physician-assisted death.
Opinions of a sample of Mexican physicians. Archives of Medical Research 39,
452–458.
Maitra, R.T., Harfst, A., Bjerre, L.M., Kochen, M.M., Becker, A., 2005. Do German
References general practitioners support euthanasia? Results of a nation-wide questionnaire
survey. European Journal of General Practice 11, 94–100.
Baxter v. Montana, 224 P.3d 1211 (Mont. 2009). Meier, D.E., Emmons, C.A., Wallenstein, S., et al., 1998. A national survey of
Behuniak, S.M., 2011. Death with “dignity:” The wedge that divides the disability physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia in the United States. New England
rights movement from the right to die movement. Politics and Life Sciences 30, Journal of Medicine 338, 1193–1201.
17–32. Oregon Public Health Division, 2013. Oregon’s Death with Dignity Act annual report
Crosby, S.S., Apovian, C.M., Grodin, M.A., 2007. Hunger strikes, force-feeding, and − 2012. Available at: http://public.health.oregon.gov/ProviderPartnerResources/
physicians’ responsibilities. Journal of the American Medical Association 298, EvaluationResearch/DeathwithDignityAct/Pages/index.aspx (accessed 08.03.14).
563–566. Pereira, J., 2011. Legalizing euthanasia or assisted suicide: The illusion of
Curlin, F.A., Nwodim, C., Vance, J.L., Chin, M.H., Lantos, J.D., 2008. To die, to safeguards and controls. Current Oncology 11, e38–e45.
sleep: US physicians’ religious and other objections to physician-assisted Schwarz, J., Coyle, N., 2006. Can we know what Terri Schiavo would have wanted?
suicide, terminal sedation, and withdrawal of life support. American Journal of Palliative & Supportive Care 4, 129–133.
Hospice and Palliative Care 25, 112–120. Smets, T., Cohen, J., Bilsen, J., et al., 2011. Attitudes and experiences of Belgian
Dees, M.K., Vernooij-Dassen, M.J., Dekkers, W.J., et al., 2011. ‘Unbearable physicians regarding euthanasia practice and the euthanasia law. Journal of Pain
suffering’: A qualitative study on the perspectives of patients who request and Symptom Management 41, 580–593.
assistance in dying. Journal of Medical Ethics 37, 727–734. Twomey, F., O’Leary, N., O’Brien, T., 2008. Prediction of patient survival by
Fischer, S., Huber, C.A., Furter, M., et al., 2009. Reasons why people in Switzerland healthcare professionals in a specialist palliative care inpatient unit: A
seek assisted suicide: The view of patients and physicians. Swiss Medicine prospective study. American Journal of Hospice and Palliative Medicine 25,
Weekly 139, 333–338. 139–145.
Ganzini, L., Goy, E.R., Dobscha, S.K., 2008. Prevalence of depression and anxiety in White, D.B., Arnold, R.M., 2011. The evolution of advance directives. Journal of the
patients requesting physicians’ aid in dying: Cross sectional survey. British American Medical Association 306, 1485–1486.
Medical Journal 337, a1682. Yun, Y.H., Han, K.H., Park, S., et al., 2011. Attitudes of cancer patients, family
Glare, P., Virik, K., Jones, M., et al., 2003. A systematic review of physicians’ caregivers, oncologists and members of the general public toward critical
survival predictions in terminally ill cancer patients. British Medical Journal interventions at the end of life of terminally ill patients. Canadian Medical
327, 195. Association Journal 183, E673–E679.
ten Have, H., Welie, J.V.M., 2014. Palliative sedation versus euthanasia: An Ziegler, S., Bosshard, G., 2007. Role of non-governmental organisations in physician
ethical assessment. Journal of Pain and Symptom Management 47, 123–136. assisted suicide. British Medical Journal 334, 295–298.

Potrebbero piacerti anche