Sei sulla pagina 1di 229

STUDIEN UND TEXTE ROGER BACON

ZUR GEISTESGESCHICHTE
DES MITTELALTERS AND THE SCIENCES
BEGRUNDET VON
COMMEMORATIVE ESSAYS
JOSEF K OCH
W EITERG EFU H RT VON

PAUL WILPERT und ALBERT ZIMMERMANN


EDITED BY

HERAUSGEGEBEN VON

JA N A. A ER TSEN
JEREMIAH HACKETT

IN ZUSAMMENARBEIT MIT

TZO TC H O BOIADJIEV, MARK D. JORDAN


und ANDREAS SPEER (M a n a g in g E d it o r )

BAND LVII

R O G E R BACON
AND T H E SCIEN CES

' >6 8 V

BRILL
LEIDEN • NEW YORK • KOLN
1997

t
This book is printed on acid-free paper.

Library o f C ongress C ataloging-in-Publication D ata


Roger Bacon and the sciences : commemorative essays / edited by
Jeremiah Hackett.
p. cm. — (Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des
Mittelalters, ISSN 0169-8125 ; Bd. 57)
Includes indexes.
ISBN 9004100156 (cloth : alk. paper)
1. Bacon, Roger, 1214?—1294— Knowledge— Science. 2. Science,
Medieval. 3. Science— Methodology—History— 13th century.
4. Scientists— Great Britain—Biography. I. Hackett, Jeremiah.
II. Series.
Q143.B225R64 1997
509.2—dc21 97-29919
CIP To the memory of James A. Weisheipl and A.C. Crombie
and for the education of two children
Thomas J.R. Hackett & Margaret T.R. Hackett.
All spoke much about Roger Bacon.

D ie D eu tsch e B ibliothek - C IP-E inheitsaufnahm e


R oger Bacon and the sciences: commemorative essays / ed.
by Jeremiah Hackett. - Leiden ; New York ; Koln : Brill, 1997
(Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters : Bd. 57)
ISBN 9 0 -0 4 -1 0 0 1 5 -6

ISSN 0169-8125
ISBN 90 04 10015 6

© Copyright 1997 by Koninklijke Brill, Leiden, The Netherlands

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in
a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic,
mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written
permission from the publisher.
Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal
use is granted by Koninklijke Brill provided that
the appropriatefees are paid directly to The Copyright
Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910
Danvers MA 01923, USA.
Fees are subject to change.

PRINTED IN THE NETHERLANDS


CONTENTS

Acknowledgments ................................................................................. ix

Roger Bacon and the Sciences: Introduction ......................................... 1


Jeremiah Hackett
1. Roger Bacon: His Life, Career and Works ................................. 9
Jeremiah Hackett
2. Roger Bacon’s Attitude Toward the Latin Translations and
Translators of the Twelfth and Thirteenth Centuries ................... 25
Richard Lemay
3. Roger Bacon on the Classification of the Sciences ........................ 49
Jeremiah Hackett
4. Roger Bacon and Grammar ......................................................... 67
Irene Rosier-Catach
5. Roger Bacon et la logique ........................................................... 103
Alain De Libera
6. Roger Bacon on Rhetoric and Poetics .......................................... 133
Jeremiah Hackett
7. Roger Bacon’s Knowledge of Mathematics .................................... 151
George Molland
8. Roger Bacon on Astronomy-Astrology: The Sources of the
Scientia Experimentalis .......................................................... 175
Jeremiah Hackett
9. Roger Bacon on Geography and Cartography ................................ 199
David Woodward with Herbert M. Howe
10. Roger Bacon on Music ................................................................ 223
Nancy van Deusen
11. Roger Bacon on Light, Vision, and the Universal Emanation
of Force ....................................................................................... 243
David C. Lindberg
V lll CONTENTS

12. Roger Bacon on Scientia Experimentalis ................................. 277


Jeremiah Hackett
13. An Overview of Roger Bacon’s Alchemy ...................................... 317 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
William R. Newman
14. Roger Bacon and Medicine: The Paradox of the Forbidden Fruit It would be impossible to give a comprehensive account of all those
and the Secrets of Long Life ........................................................ 337 scholars whose interest and encouragement led to the presentation of
Faye Getz this volume. My interest in this project began many years ago when
15. Roger Bacon and the Secret of Secrets .................................... 365 just prior to his death, Denis Bethel, Secretary to the Board of Medi­
Steven J. Williams eval Studies at University College Dublin, handed a visiting student
his own copy of A.G. Little’s Roger Bacon Essays. Many thanks are
16. A Roger Bacon Bibliography (1985-1995) ................................ 395 due to faculty and students at Dublin and Toronto in the areas of
Thomas S. Maloney Philosophy and Medieval Studies. The initial work in Medieval Studies
was done under the direction of Professor F.X. Martin, OSA and
17. Epilogue: Roger Bacon’s Moral Science ....................................... 405
Jeremiah Hackett Dr. Michael Richter. A debt of gratitude is due also to Professor
Bieler and Professor O ’Meara for an introduction to Neoplatonism.
Indices ................................................................................................ 411 My interest in the thought of Roger Bacon owes a great deal to
the late James A. Weisheipl O.P. who introduced me to the History
Index manuscriptorum .................................................................. 413
Index nominum I (Ancient, Medieval and Early Modern) ... 414 of Medieval Science. And acknowledgment of the faculty and students
Index nominum II (Modern) ..................................................... 420 at Toronto is required. James A. Weisheipl was a dedicated researcher
and teacher and he above all is to be acknowledged here.
Index rerum ................................................................................ 426
The actual suggestion for the volume came from Professor David
C. Lindberg. And a challenge to do it came from a fellow student,
List of Authors .................................................................................... 441
William O. Shorten, mathematicus. The editor is also grateful to Pro­
fessor A.C. Crombie for his encouragement of this project. He wishes
to acknowledge Professor A. Hyman and Professor Paul Oskar
Kristeller for much encouragement in the research which led to this
work. Professor Richard Lemay was generous with advice concern­
ing Abu M a'shar and Pseudo-Ptolemy’s Centiloquium.
Many thanks are due to his colleagues at the University of South
Carolina, and to his family. His colleagues may have thought at times
that he had metamorphosed into Roger Bacon, but were kind enough
not to say so. His children did say so and forced him to promise
that for their pains he would dedicate the volume to them. And that
I will do so because I believe that it is important that they learn
the truth about the past in so far as we can learn the truth about
the past. And unlike cheap mythologies, there is no short-cut to the
truth even in the case of one like Roger Bacon, who, on account of
Robert Greene’s Friar Bacon and Friar Bungay, among other things,
came to be seen as a Magus in Renaissance England.
X ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

A special word of thanks is due to the Department of Philosophy


and to its Chair, Professor Davis Whitney Baird, who provided funds
for the translation work from French in the volume. Thanks are also ROGER BACON AND THE SCIENCES: INTRO DU CTIO N
due to the translator, David C. Miller, M.F.A. In the course of pre­
paring this volume, the editor was greatly helped by the Adminis­ Jeremiah Hackett
trative Assistants in the Department of Philosophy, Ms. Joanna
Woodward, and Ms. Joan Spencer-Amado. He wishes to acknowl­
edge the advice and assistance of Ms. Elna Corwin, Mr. Berry Mobley, It is about 700 years since the death of the Medieval scientist, phi­
Mr. Homer R. Steedly Jr. of the College of Liberal Arts computer losopher, and moral-religious author, Roger Bacon. He is known to
laboratory, and Mr. Graham Dennis. modern readers in the profile which was constructed by popular
writers on science in the 19th century. Much of this work, which is
Much gratitude is due to Librarians at London, Oxford, Paris, Rome, now forgotten, is the work of historical fiction and of scientific
Dublin, Toronto, and at the University of South Carolina’s Thomas hagiography. And yet, while it may have been forgotten, it has had
Cooper Library, and the Caroliniana Library. Further, support from a major influence on all early 20th century entries on Roger Bacon
the following institutions enabled the research to be undertaken: The in Dictionaries, Encyclopaedias, and popular works on History. The
American Philosophical Society; The National Endowment for the image of Bacon as the Romantic hero of science who six hundred
Humanities; The University of South Carolina Research and Pro­ years before the Modern Scientific Revolution had anticipated that
ductivity Scholarship; The Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, revolution continued into the popular imagination in the 20th century.
Toronto. Yet, as is well-known, Bacon was a Medieval philosopher, scientist
Finally, an acknowledgment of four high school teachers “the four and commentator on moral and religious topics. He was not a Modem
horsemen”, at Good Counsel, New Ross, a town built by a great or Post-Modem scientist. Still, his contribution to the Liberal Arts
man, William Marshall, just before “the times” of Roger Bacon, is (humanities and sciences) was very significant, although he has come
in order. They instilled a respect for the Liberal Arts in its full scope. down to us in the literature as something of a pariah. There will be
They would have enjoyed meeting Roger Bacon. a measure of revision in these essays but that revision is motivated
by a concern with evidence and with argument. And if there are
places where Roger Bacon seems to anticipate aspects of the Modem
World, they should be evaluated carefully.
Serious work on the recovery and edition of Bacon’s works began
with Victor Cousin and Emile Charles. Brewer’s edition of the Opus
minus, Opus tertium and the Epistola de secretis operibus was published in
1859. In the late nineteenth century, German scholars, particularly
in the fields of optics, philosophy of nature and moral philosophy
made significant contributions to the scientific study of Bacon’s works:
one thinks of Sebastian Vogl, Eilhard Wiedemann and Ludwig Baur
among other.
The new edition of the unpublished works, the Opera hactenus inedita
Rogeri Bacon began in 1905 under the editorship of Robert Steele.
Finally, it appeared to be the case that a truly scientific and histori­
cally grounded account could be given of the life, career and works
of Roger Bacon, known as the Doctor Mirabilis.
2 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON AND THE SCIENCES: INTRODUCTION 3

In 1914, the distinguished scholar of Medieval Franciscan culture, study by William Eamon on the role of secret books in Renaissance
Professor A.G. Little, edited a volume: Roger Bacon Essays (1914). This science details the impact of this medieval tradition on early modern
work was a true landmark in scholarship. Working with a full inter­ science. And yet, much more work is needed in this area. But it is
national body of scholars, A.G. Little presented the public with a becoming apparent that the whole story of the transmission of science
judicious interpretation of the main elements of Bacon’s scientific and philosophy from the 13th to the 17th century is being re-written
interests. Despite the catasthrope of “The Great War,” Robert Steele on the basis of new texts, new questions and new answers. And still,
managed to move ahead with the edited volumes. This enormous old myths, outworn stories and sometimes plain falsehoods still win
task continued in cooperation with Ferdnand M. Delorme OFM, A.G. the attention of modern audiences whose mind has been so de-
Little and F. Withington. In 1940 in the midst of World War II, historicized that they are prepared to accept that last magical sound
volume XVI, the Communia mathematical was completed. bite or image as the truth.
During and after world war I, scholars such as Lynn Thorndike, After World War II, the two important studies of Roger Bacon’s
Roul Carton and Pierre Duhem took a closer look at Roger Bacon’s life and works by Theodore Crowley and Stewart C. Easton gave
science. Due to the iconoclasm of both Thorndike and Duhem, the some new life to Bacon research. F. Alessio, E. Massa and E. Bettoni
romantic image of Bacon as a Modern 19th century scientist before among others presented new studies and editions.
his time was shattered. And yet the myth lived on in the papers, Perhaps, the most dramatic discovery in Bacon studies was the
encyclopaedias and books. However, matters were not so simple. identification of the missing section of the Opus maius, part three, De
Duhem had edited part of the Opus tertium, and thus recognised that signis (Bacon’s semiotics) by the late Jan Pinborg, K.M. Fredborg and
Bacon had in fact done some detailed work in both Natural Philoso­ L. Nielsen.
phy such as Commentaries on Aristode’s Physica and in experimental Still, there was one major lacuna. No critical edition of the center-
science dealing with meteorological phenomena. The whole issue of piece, of Bacon’s work on agency and force existed. This was remedied
the nature and meaning of Medieval Science and its relationship to in 1983 with the publication of David C. Lindberg’s critical edition
the development of Classical Early Modern Science (i.e. the science of the De multiplication specierum and the De speculis comburentibus. This
of Galileo, Descartes and Francis Bacon) was opened up anew by careful work opened up a new era in Bacon studies, and became a
the studies of Annalise Meier, Marshall Glagett and Alastair Crombie. bench-mark for all new editions of Bacon’s works.
The work of A.C. Crombie: Robert Grosseteste and the Origins of Experi­ It became clear from this work that the texts of Bacon (even the
mental Science 1200-1700 was a milestone on this search. In this work, texts of Robert Steele) are in need of serious critical re-edition. Thomas
Crombie effectively demonstrated that the qualitative model of a combi­ S. Maloney has done this for the Compendium studii theologiae, previ­
nation of Mathematical thinking and experimental procedure began ously edited by H. Rashdall. The result of these editions is a deepening
at the Universities of Oxford and Paris in the 13th century, and of our knowledge, a more accurate text, and an expanded interpre­
among the main representatives were Robert Grosseteste and Roger tation based on a closer reading of the texts. There have also been
Bacon. The manner in which greater development in quantification good translations. Among these are the translation with notes by
and in experimentation developed from about 1277 up to Galileo is Thomas S. Maloney on Bacon’s account of Universals and Stanton
a story which is still being written by modem historians of late medi­ J. Linden’s valuable translation with notes of the Mirror of Alchemy.
eval science. And finally, in the light of the research of many schol­ The editor of the present work planned the volume with the inten­
ars, among them Edward Rosen, Edward Grant, the late James A. tion of highlighting two aspects of Bacon’s work. First, it was impor­
Weisheipl, David C. Lindberg, William A. Wallace, John E. Murdoch tant to see how Bacon’s account of the linguistic, natural and moral
and E. Sylla, a greater sense of the complexity of the issues and of sciences mirrored the curriculum of study at the Medieval University.
the historical development of this science is being realized. And still, It was necessary to do this so that the role which University teaching
the old myths continue to haunt the literature. and research did play in Medieval Science would be recognized.
Further, much work is being done on books of secrets. The recent Second, it was important that the volume reflect the development of
4 ROGER BACON AND THE SCIENCES: INTRODUCTION 5
JEREMIAH HACKETT

Bacon’s thought in his Opus Maius (1266-8). There has been no criti­ Rhetoric. Grammar and Logic would roughly correspond to Linguis­
cal study of this work by any modern historian of philosophy, sci­ tics and Logic in a modern university. Irene Rosier-Catach presents
ence, or morals. The present volume is intended as An Introduction to a synthesis of our current knowledge of Bacon’s approach to Gram­
the Opus maius especially and also to related works. It can be jusdy mar. She situates his work in the context of grammatical studies at
claimed that it is the first such study. And it will be obvious from the University of Paris from the 1230’s to the 1260’s.
the present volume why such an introduction had to be a coopera­ Alain De Libera presents an account of Bacon’s contribution to
tive venture. logical theory. The scholarship of the past fifteen years has demon­
strated the central place which Bacon occupied in the teaching on
Chapter one gives a review of the historical record on Bacon’s life Logic and in general reflection on the nature of Logic.
and career. It traces the life of a medieval thinker who for the most Bacon makes many comments on Rhetoric and Poetics through­
part lived in Oxford and Paris and who among Medieval writers out his later works. The most startling one is that he simply rejects
gives us one interpretation of the crises of his times. Bacon’s com­ the division of the Trivium. He thinks that it is a philosophical mis­
ments on his times and on matters of scholarship have been mined take to set rhetoric in opposition to logic. The theoretical part of
by historians of philosophy and science despite the fact that some Rhetoric finds a home in the study of Logic; the practical part
who do not like the man tend to dismiss his testimony tout court. And is closely related to Moral Philosophy. Jeremiah Hackett provides
yet, as Sir Richard Southern has demonstrated in his work on Robert a summary of Bacon’s views and notes his role as an important
Grosseteste, a judicious reading of Bacon’s texts can open up new transitional figure on these topics at the University of Paris (1256-
vistas on the events of his times. 1277).
Chapter two deals with Roger Bacon’s attitude towards Translators We lack a study of the overall scope of Bacon’s mathematical knowl­
in the context of the many Parisian condemnations of Philosophy edge. What were his sources? What was the level of his knowledge?
and science in the period from 1210-1277. Roger Bacon has his own In his overview, George Molland does a thorough review of Bacon’s
interpretation of these events, and it is important to give it a critical works on mathematics and on his debt to the new translations of
assessment. Here, Richard Lemay looks at Bacon in the context of ancient and medieval texts. Bacon did not write on mathematics in
his teaching at the University of Paris. Bacon’s attitudes to the trans­ the systematic way he did on Force and on Perespectiva. In general, as
lators, especially to Hermannus Allemannus and William of Moerbecke he indicates in Opus tertium, he acknowledges the work of well-known
raise serious questions. And since Bacon made use of so much trans­ mathematicians. He did write a Communia mathematical but while it
lated materials, an account of the translation issue is important. does deal with proportion and with quantity, it is more like a treatise
Roger Bacon did not write a treatise on the Classification of the on the scope and applications of mathematics.
Sciences as did his fellow Master in Arts and near contemporary, Roger Bacon developed his concept of a Scientia experimentalis in
Robert Kilwardby. The De ortu scientiarum of Kilwardby marks a turning explicit connection with astronomy and astrology. It is important, there­
point. After 1250, one finds no regular course on the division of the fore, to examine his ideas on this topic as given in Opus maius, part
sciences. From that point on, individual teachers present their divi­ four, and in related works. Which concerns in astronomy/astrology
sions of the sciences at the beginning of particular works. This is led Bacon to the formulation of a concept of a Scientia experimentalist
very apparent in the case of Roger Bacon. This chapter brings together Jeremiah Hackett sets out the scope of this issue.
his thoughts on this topic in the context of the Medieval division of Nancy van Deusen presents an introductory account of Bacon’s
the sciences from Boethius to 1270. And it sets the scene for a discus­ views on Music. And here, one can see just how important Music
sion of Roger Bacon and the Sciences. was as part of the medieval Quadrivium. We learn that Bacon held
the study of music in high regard. Further, this account sheds im­
The next three chapters deal with Bacon and language. In the portant light on the inter-relation of Aristotle and Augustine in the
Medieval curriculum this was the Trivium of Grammar, Logic and thirteenth century.
6 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON AND THE SCIENCES: INTRODUCTION 7

Bacon’s remarks on Geography in Opus mains, part four, provide us gives an outline of Bacon’s influence on later medical writers. And
with evidence for his overall knowledge of geography and cartography. she also details the manner in which Bacon became a hero for English
They also shed light on his attention to Travel Writers. Further, they medicine in the late middle ages.
are of some historical importance since a scholarly consensus holds Bacon wrote on Alchemy and listed it as an example of the second
that this work was known to and used by Christopher Columbus in prerogative of his Scientia experimentalis. William Newman presents a
the 1490’s. David Woodward and Herbert M. Howe present a judi­ critical assessment of Bacon’s writings in Alchemy. Here, again, we
cious assessment of Bacon’s knowledge in these two fields. see the historical profile which has come down the centuries being
changed by good historical method and scholarship. And we get a
The central doctrine in Bacon’s later philosophy is undoubtedly the better estimate of Bacon’s contribution and influence in this field.
doctrine of the multiplication of species (De multiplications specierum) and Indeed, we learn how so many late Medieval texts on Alchemy came
closely tied to it is the doctrine on light and vision. David C. Lindberg, to be attributed to Roger Bacon.
who has just recently completed the critical edition of the Perspectiva Roger Bacon makes much use of the Pseudo-Aristotelian Secretum
(= Opus maius, part five), presents a synthesis of Bacon’s contribution secretorum. This is perhaps, the most important work in the genre
to a doctine of Light, Vision and the Universal Emanation of Force. “Mirror of Princes” written in the Middle Ages. In one version, trans­
Lindberg’s conclusion is important: Roger Bacon was The Philosopher lated from Arabic by Philip of Tripoli, it became the vade-mecum of
and Scientist who taught the Latin West to think about light, vision the prince long before another book with the latter name gained
and force. Pecham and Witelo were his younger contemporaries who fame. Steven J. Williams does a study of this text and its place in
shared in this task. Bacon opened the eyes of Western thinkers to Bacon’s life and works.
the need to do serious mathematical and physical-experimental work
on these topics. And it is here that one notices the extraordinary Bacon, in the Opus maius, very deliberately set out a Stoic division of
deepening of physical and optical knowledge that took place since Philosophy into: a) language study, b) study of nature, c) study of
Grosseteste’s short writings on these topics in the 1220’s. morals. But Bacon lived in the Middle Ages, and he felt obliged to
The topic of Scientia experimental has been one of the most de­ give a concordantium discordantium opinionum. In his Opus maius, part seven,
bated issues in Bacon scholarship. This topic has lead to Bacon being the Moralis philosophic, which is a sizable volume in the modern edi­
identified in the Renaissance as a Magus. Others in the 19th century tion, Bacon presents us with an outline of the scope of Moral Sci­
saw him as one who grasped modem scientific method in a pre­ ence. Moral Science for Bacon encompasses the following: the nature
modern age. In Opus maius, part six, and in related texts, he presents of moral science, metaphysics and morals, a philosophical anthropo­
his views on the nature and methodology of a Scientia experimentalis. logy based on a synthesis of Platonic, Aristotelian and Stoic doctrine,
This term is ambiguous. For Bacon, it means a natural science, but a social ethic based on Avicenna, an extended account of theory of
it can also mean a phenomenology of experience, and it can mean virtue (mostly an anthology of Seneca’s writings), an account of com­
what we mean today by philosophy of science, that is a critical re­ parative religion, the role of persuasion (rhetoric and poetics) in morals
flection on the nature and use of science. This chapter will give a and religion, and legal matter. Jeremiah Hackett presents an Epilogue
summary of Bacon’s views on Scientia experimentalis and will show its on Bacon’s Moralis philosophia as the teleological aim of Bacon’s Opus
connection with language study, mathematics, perspectiva and with moral maius. In other words, language study and the study of nature finds
science. Jeremiah Hackett presents a critical assessment of this issue. its telos in a Moral philosophy. And this Moralis philosophia is inti­
mately tied to political philosophy. One is left with the sense that
Bacon’s edited works contain one volume on medicine (Opera, Vol. IX, Bacon subordinates Ethics to the demands of political necessity. But
ed. A.G. Little and E. Withington) and there are many references to then he was writing for Prelates and Princes and not for the conduct
medical matters throughout his later works. Faye Getz presents a of monastics.
critical assessment of Bacon’s contribution to medieval medicine. She Finally, Thomas S. Maloney reviews new work on Bacon since
8 JEREMIAH HACKETT

the publication of the 1987 addition to the Alessio bibliography of


1959. A review of Bacon’s works and a review of new Manuscript
discoveries will appear in a forthcoming volume of Vivarium on Bacon 1. ROGER BACON: HIS LIFE, CAREER AND WORKS
as an Aristotelian Commentator. This will also include a full list of
Bacon’s authentic works. Jeremiah Hackett

A. Life and Career

There is no complete agreement among scholars on the chronology


of Roger Bacon’s career. Roger Bacon was bom about 1214 or 1220.
Modern scholars tend to argue for the latter date, but even on this
matter there is disagreement. Further, while most scholars are in agree­
ment that Bacon died about 1292, there is a lack of evidence concern­
ing the years from 1278 to 1292. There is evidence that sometime
after 1277-8, Roger Bacon returned to Oxford from Paris, edited
the Secretum secretorum, completed his Compendium studii theologiae and
may have edited other works.
The actual evidence for a firm historical knowledge of the life is
slim. .The modern commonly accepted view is that set out by Theo­
dore Crowley, and more recently developed by David C. Lindberg.1
This framework for his chronology is, however, for the most part
dependent on one piece of reminiscence by Bacon, which he set out
in the Opus tertium (ca. 1267-8). It reads:
I have labored much in sciences and languages, and I have up to now
devoted forty years [to them] after I first learned the Alphabetum; and
I was always studious. Apart from two of these forty years I was always
[engaged] in study [in studio], and I had many expenses just as others
commonly have. Nevertheless, provided I had first composed a compen­
dium, I am certain that within a quarter or half a year I could directly
teach a solicitous and confident person whatever I knew of those sci­
ences and languages. And it is known that no one worked in so many
sciences and languages as I did, nor so much as I did. Indeed, when
I was living in the other state of life, people marvelled that I survived
the abundance of my work. And still, I was just as involved in studies

1 Theodore Crowley, O.F.M., Roger Bacon: The Problem o f the Soul in His Philosophi­
cal Commentaries, (Louvain/Dublin, 1952), 17-78; David C. Lindberg, Roger Bacon’s
Philosophy of Nature: A Critical Edition, with English Translation, Introduction, and Notes of De
multiplicatione specierum and De speculis comburentibus, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983).
See also A.C. Crombie and John North, “Roger Bacon,” in Dictionary of Scientific
Biography, I, 377-85, New York, 1970.
10 JEREMIAH HACKETT
ROGER BACON! HIS LIFE, CAREER AND WORKS 11

afterwards as I had been before. But I did not work all that much,
Sciences, indeed one which seems to have been much longer
since in the pursuit of Wisdom this was not required.2
than the normal. Bacon’s Opus tertium appeal to Pope Clement IV
In the light of this passage, Crowley and more recently, Lindberg, reads like a Grant application. He is saying that he, of all his contem­
favor the view that Bacon was born about 1220. This would mean poraries at the Universities of Oxford and Paris, is best equipped to
that Bacon may have been a student at Oxford from about 1234 to set up a renewed model of University teaching and research. One
1241. Earlier, in 1914, A.G. Little argued that the words in studio will note that other texts support the view that Bacon had been
had to be taken to mean at a University, and that the word alphabetum involved in arts and sciences a iuventute. Further, in the relevant chapter
meant his early education as a whole.3 For entirely different reasons, in the Opus tertium, from which the above passage is taken, it is clear
Charles Jourdain had earlier suggested that Bacon was born about that Bacon uses the word Alphabetum to mean a training in the arts
1210.4 In his new edition of the Compendium studii theologiae, Thomas S. [Alphabetum philosophiae), which in the Medieval University began at
Maloney favors the view of A.G. Little and takes 1214 as the most 13/14 and ended at about 21 years of age. One also notices that in
likely date of birth.5 In a recent study, Jeremiah Hackett presents an his second career, after about 1256 as a Franciscan friar, he remained
analysis of the conflicting interpretations.6 Here, it is important to studious, but he did not hold a public teaching office, since that was
examine some aspects of the problem and to note some consequences not required of him.
of both chronologies for Bacon’s relationship to Robert Grosseteste In reading the above text from the Opus tertium, I am inclined to
and Adam Marsh.7 the view that by 1267 or 1268 he had devoted forty years to studies
The point that Bacon is making for the Pope in the relevant section (he was always given to study during these years). However, apart
of the Opus tertium is that he has had a long career in the Arts and from two years absence from a studium or from formal studies, he
was always in studio, and he had many expenses as scholars normally
do. And he began this work in “the sciences and languages” after he
2 Opus maius, ed. Brewer, 65: Multum laborvi in scientia et linguis, et posui jam
quadraginta annos postquam didici primo alphabetum; et fui semper studiosus; et
first learned the rudiments (the alphabetum) of these studies. That is,
praeter duos annos de istis quadraginta fui semper in studio, et habui expensas about thirteen or fourteen years of age. If this is a correct reading
multas, sicut alii communiter; et tamen certus sum quod infra quartum anni, aut of this passage, we have to conclude that sometime around 1228,
dimidium anni, ego docerem ore meo hominem sollicitum et confidentem, quicquid
scio de potestate scientiarum et linguarum, dummodo composuissem primo scriptum Bacon entered University at Oxford, and therefore would have re­
sub compendio. Et notum est quod nullus in tot scientiis et linguis laboravit, nec ceived his M.A. around 1236. This would mean that he would have
tantum, quia homines mirabantur in alio statu quod vixi propter superfluum laborem; been born ca. 1214 or 1215.
et tamen postea fuit ita studiosus sicut ante. Sed non tantum laboravi, quia non fuit
necesse propter exercitium sapientiae. Regardless of which chronology is correct, it does seem that Bacon
3 A.G. Little, “On Roger Bacon’s Life and Works,” in A.G. Litde, ed. Roger Bacon could not have been a student in the arts under Robert Grosseteste.
Essays: Contributed by Various Writers on the Occasion o f the Commemoration of the Seventh
Centenary of his Birth, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1914), 1-32; See also A.G. Little,
The latter had departed University teaching to become lector to the
“Roger Bacon,” Proceedings of the British Academy 14 (1928). Franciscans in 1229, and in 1235, he became Bishop of Lincoln.
4 Charles Jourdain, “Discussions de quelques points de la biographie de Roger However, it is most likely that Bacon would have seen Robert
Bacon,” Comptes rendus des seances de I’Acadmie des inscriptions et belles-lettres (Paris, O ct.-
Dec. 1874). Grosseteste, and undoubtedly would have been influenced by his
5 Thomas S. Maloney, ed., Roger Bacon: Compendium of the Study o f Theology, (Leiden, reputation as a great scholar and as a patron of the new Franciscan
1988; Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters, 20). Order at Oxford. The constant repetition of Nam vidimus with refer­
6 Jeremiah Hackett, “Roger Bacon,” in Medieval Philosophers (Dictionary of Literary
Biography, Vol. 115, ed. Jeremiah Hackett, Detroit/London, 1992), 90-102; Ibid., ence to Robert Grosseteste, Adam Marsh and other Scholars associ­
“Scientia experimentalis: From Robert Grosseteste to Roger Bacon,” in Robert Grosseteste: ated with Oxford and with Lincoln indicate that he had seen these
New Perspectives on His Thought and Scholarship, ed. James McEvoy, (Dordrecht: Kluwer
Academic Publishers, 1995—Instrumenta Patristica XXVII), 89-120. For Bacon’s
scholars and was clearly influenced by their example.8
career, see 89-103.
7 See R.W. Southern, Robert Grosseteste: The Growth of an English Mind in Medieval
8 See Opus maius, ed. Bridges, Vol. Ill, 88-89: Nam vidimus aliquos de antiquis qui
Europe, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992).
laboraverunt in linguis sicut fuit dominus Robertus praefatus translator et episcopus, et
12 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON: HIS LIFE, CAREER AND WORKS 13

That Bacon picked up his interest in sciences, and especially in and give its cause during the time in which I had been his student
(Disciple) from my youth. But he himself was mislead by arguments
the science of Perspectiva at Oxford seems to follow from some remarks
and false translations, since experience teaches that in every full moon,
penned in 1267. Again, in the Opus tertium, he argues that the science if the moon shines without the impediment of clouds and vapour,
of Perspectiva is the key to a scientific knowledge of all sensible things and the moist material is generated opposite the moon, a rainbow is
and to “the whole machine of the world” \totam mundi machinam, et in necessarily generated.10
coelestibus et in inferioribus]. He continues:
Since it would appear that Bacon disregards Albertus Magnus as
However, this science is not yet taught at Paris, nor among the Latins “the greatest Natural Philosopher and Expert on Perspectiva”, and since
except twice at Oxford in England, and there are not three people there are scarcely any other candidates, one naturally thinks that
who know the power of this science. Whence that one who made him­
Bacon may be giving us a reference to Robert Grosseteste. Indeed,
self an authority (i.e. Albertus Magnus), concerning whom I spoke above,
knew nothing about the power o f this science, as appears in his books,
Bacon in 1267 was not above correcting Grosseteste’s scientific theo­
because he did not write a book about this science and he would have ries, and he does so specifically in regard to the Rainbow.11 It would
done so if he had known it.9 appear then that in some sense of the word, Bacon was a disciple of
Grosseteste a iuventute. But this does not mean that he was a student
Bacon, quite clearly, in 1267, associated the introduction of Perspectiva
of Grosseteste in artibus. At the most, it means that he saw the great
as a fifth subject in addition to the traditional Quadrivium [Arithmetic,
man, that he imitated his program of study and that he, perhaps,
Geometry, Astronomy, Music] with the University of Oxford. By 1267,
made a serious study of his scientific writings. This would definitely
according to Bacon, it had not been formally introduced to the curricu­
be the case if Bacon were bom about 1214. He could have been a
lum at the University of Paris. In another work, the Tractatus de expe-
student at Oxford from about 1227-8 to 1235-36. But if he were
rientia in communi, which is a recension of the Opus maius VI: De scientia
born in 1220, he would not have gone to Oxford before 1234, and
experimentali, Bacon makes a remark about Perspectiva which suggests
by 1235, Grosseteste had become Bishop of Lincoln.
that he connects it with Grosseteste and with Oxford. He states:
There is a reference to a Roger Bacon, Clericus de curia Regis, who
For in the translation of the books o f the Meteorology available among displayed his caustic wit before the King at Oxford in 1233.12 And
the Latins up to the present, it is said that a rainbow is not had from since Roger Bacon had a lifelong interest in the care of the Common­
the rays of the moon except twice in fifty years. And the greatest natural wealth, one ought not lightly dismiss this small piece of evidence.
Philosopher and Expert on Perspectiva whom I saw wished to save this truth

Scholars are unsure about the date of Bacon’s inception as Master of


Thomas venerabilis ansistes Sancti David nuper defunctus, et frater Adam de Marisco, Arts at the University of Paris. David C. Lindberg remarks that: “It
et Magister Hermannus translator, et quidam alii sapientes. See also Compendium was doubtless during the 1240’s that Bacon began to lecture in the
studii philosophise, ed. Brewer, 428: (speaking about how the “saeculares” for forty
years, that is since about 1230 have neglected true and tried methods of study in faculty of Arts at Paris.”13 Thomas S. Maloney suggests that: “Some­
philosophy and theology drawn as they are by honors and riches, he adds): Ita time in or shortly after 1245 Bacon accepted an invitation to teach
quod totaliter dimiserunt vias antiquorum sapientum, quorum aliquos vidimus nostri in the faculty of arts at the University of Paris.. . .”14 The late James A.
temporibus; scilicet, dominum Robertum, quondam episcopum Lincolniensem, sanctae
memoriae, et dominum Thomam, episcopum Sancti David in Wallia, et fratrem Weisheipl reminded us that 1237 was a significant date in Bacon’s
Adam de Marisco, et Magistrum Robertum de Marisco, et Magistros Willelmum mind, and that Bacon attests that he taught in the arts longer than
Lupum, et Willielmum de Schyrewode, et aliquos alios eis similes, quorum vestigia
modemi saeculares omnino dimiserunt. . . .
One should note the connection of all of these scholars with Lincoln. While Roger 10 Jeremiah M.G. Hackett, ed. Tractatus de experientia in communi, in The Meaning of
Bacon may have visited Oxford sometime between 1247 and 1257, it is not impos­ Experimental Science (Scientia experimentalis) the Philosophy of Roger Bacon (Toronto, University
sible that he would have visited Lincoln especially in view of his interest in Logic of Toronto Ph.D., 1983), 292-93.
and the presence there of William of Schyrewode, who Bacon ranked as the best 11 See Jeremiah Hackett, “Roger Bacon on Scientia experimentalis,” below.
representative in philosophia communis. Bacon is well acquainted with the work in 12 Matthew Paris, Chronica majora, III, 244—5.
languages and in the sciences of Grosseteste and his circle. 13 David C. Lindberg, op. cit., xvii.
9 Opus tertium, ed. Brewer, 37-38. 14 Thomas S. Maloney, op. cit.
14 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON! HIS LIFE, CAREER AND WORKS 15

any other Master. Weisheipl notes that “he [Bacon] was undoubtedly Further, there is evidence which places Bacon in Paris in 1247,
one of the earliest Parisian Masters to expound the Aristotelian books 1251 and 1256, so it is unlikely that he was formally a theology
in the faculty of arts after the earlier prohibition was relaxed. One of student at Oxford between 1247 and 1256. This does not mean that
his colleagues in the faculty of arts was certainly Peter of Spain, later he did not visit his own family in England between 1247 and 1256.19
Pope John XXI.”15 Bacon tells us that some twenty years before 1267, At this time, before the Civil War between the Barons and the King,
he had ceased to examine M.A. students on difficult scientific and his family was prominent. One might even suggest (although the
mathematical questions which the other teachers could not examine.16 evidence is not strong) that for a person of Bacon’s scholarly inter­
It is a common assumption among scholars that between 1247 ests a visit to Oxford or, perhaps, to the Bishop of Lincoln or to one
and 1267, Bacon spent two thousand librae on scientific matters, instru­ of his Houses of Study, where translation work was being done, is
ments and on books of Secrets.17 But this is problematic. After 1256, not impossible. In my view, it is a real possibility which future evi­
as a Franciscan friar, he would not have been able to dispose of dence may verify. The evident interest of Bacon in the recovery of
such a sum of money. But since Bacon tells us that he was involved Ancient ethical texts (i.e. Seneca’s Dialogues in the 1260’s) and in the
in “languages and sciences a iuventute, we have to assume that this Mcomachean Ethics (Grosseteste’s translation was completed in 1249)
must have been the ten or twenty years prior to 1256. Moreover, he would point in this direction. However, until more evidence has been
tells us that some of this money was used to seek out the friendship reviewed, and new evidence comes to light, the matter of Bacon’s
of the Sapientes (the Wise). This could mean that Bacon travelled outside whereabouts between 1247-56 should remain an open issue.
of Paris, and especially to Oxford. We can conclude that sometime Bacon tells us that he twice heard William of Auvergne address
around or after 1247, Bacon ceased to be a Regent Master in the the Convocation of the University of Paris. And it is in the context
Arts at the University of Paris. of this remark that he mentions both Adam Marsh and Robert
It has been the common assumption of Bacon scholars that some Grosseteste. He mentions that they “supported the same [teaching of
time between 1247-56 he must have returned from Paris to Oxford, the Bishop of Paris on the agent intellect].” Both English clerics
where he was trained in theology by Adam Marsh. Theodore Crowley departed England on November 18, 1244 and reached Lyons on
presented evidence from the Opus tertium, which, he thought, was proof 7 January 1245 to prepare for the Council of Lyons. Is it not pos­
that Bacon was definitely a student of Adam Marsh in Theology sible that Bacon met them at this time? Certainly, after the Council
during these years. In a recent paper, I analyzed this evidence and of Lyons, Grosseteste hastened to get Adam Marsh back to England
concluded that it enables us to conclude that Bacon did in fact speak
with Adam Marsh, but there is reason to think that he could have 19 See A.B. Emden, “Accounts Relating to an Early Oxford House of Scholars,”
met with Adam Marsh at Paris in 1245 or indeed at a later date Oxoniensia, 31 (1966), 77-81 for the suggestion that Master Nicholas Bacon and a
such as 1259.18 Peter Bacon belonged to a domus scholarum or small household of graduate students
and scholars at the University of Oxford, 1244-49. The former may have been
installed by Bishop Grosseteste as rector of the moiety of Stoke Rochford, Lincoln­
15 James A. Weisheipl, “Science in the Thirteenth Century,” in J.I. Catto, ed. The shire in 1244-45. A.B. Emden makes the following suggestion: “The association of
Early Oxford Schools (The History of the University of Oxford, ed. T.H. Ashton, Vol. I: Nicholas and Peter Bacon with this small graduate household, and Nicholas’s pre­
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), 435-70. See p. 454: Bacon may have begun his sumed ownership of this copy of the treatises of Avicenna and other Arab philoso­
studies in Oxford in the early 1230’s, but he soon went to Paris for his degree in phers invite speculation whether Nicholas and Peter may not have been related to
Arts, and there, he said, he taught longer than any other master. This would cer­ distinguished contemporary bearing their surname, Fr. Roger Bacon, O.F.M., among
tainly be true if he lectured on the “new Aristode” from 1237—a significant date whose many interests, the works of these philosophers were certainly one.” One
for Bacon until his departure from the schools in 1247. He was undoubtedly one might comment that since Roger Bacon did retire from his Professorship in philoso­
of the earliest Parisian masters to expound the Aristotelian books in the faculty of phy sometime around 1247/8, then, a visit to Oxford or Lincoln is a real possibility.
arts after the earlier prohibition was relaxed. One of his colleagues I the faculty of In an earlier study, I simply commented on the lack of hard evidence for his visit
arts was certainly Peter of Spain, later Pope John XXI. and I questioned Crowley’s claim that he was a student in Theology under Adam
16 Opus tertium, ed. Brewer, 139. Marsh in Oxford. A.G. Little suggested that Master Thomas Bacon, who in 1253
17 See Weisheipl, art. cit., 454-5. was recommended by Adam Marsh as a socius for Richard Rufus, may have been
18 Jeremiah Hackett, art. cit., 94-102. One should also note that he could have a brother of Roger Bacon (“The Franciscan School at Oxford in the 13th Century,”
seen Adam Marsh in 1259 since the latter was in France on a diplomatic mission. A.F.H., 19 (1926), 842.
16 ROGER BACON: HIS LIFE, CAREER AND WORKS 17
JEREMIAH HACKETT

lest the University of Paris get him as a successor to Alexander of issue of Poverty, with the split between the Franciscan spirituals and
Hales and John of Rupella.20 the conventuals, and which was resolved temporally by the appoint­
In any event, we do know that after 1247 he continued his scholarly ment of Bonaventure as the Master General in 1257.22 As a Franciscan,
and scientific interests. He assembled a research team, paid for secret Bacon remained studious, but he did not hold a public office as a
books, sought out the friendship of the Wise (he visited great scholars), Teacher. Indeed, his superiors in the Order seem to have ordered
and spent a considerable amount of money in these endeavors. Further, him to desist from some of his scientific and linguistic pursuits, prob­
we know that he used this money to send out requests over-seas and ably because he had the normal duties of a friar: prayer, sermons,
throughout Europe for specimens of natural science, whether medical collations, service to the poor. Finally, at the Council of Narbonne
cures or geological specimens or lens. in 1260, Bonaventure and the other superiors of the Order promul­
Some time ago I suggested that there is no straight line of influ­ gated a statute forbidding Friars to publish any Books or Pamphlets
ence from Robert Grosseteste to Roger Bacon. I argued that Bacon’s without the express permission of the superiors. This, as we will see
attitude to causal determinism and especially to Astrology put him at did deeply affect Bacon’s behavior.
odds with the great hero of his life, namely, Robert Grosseteste, Bishop We know that sometime in 1263-4, Bacon through the mediation
of Lincoln.21 One major intermediary or new influence in Bacon’s of Raymond of Laon, a cleric in the household of Cardinal Guy le
work is found in the De vetula of Richard Foumival, Canon of Amiens. Gros de Foulques, Papal Legate to England during the Civil War,
Foumival had the best collection of scientific and secret books in made contact with the Cardinal. He seems to have spoken about his
Europe. And prior to his death ca. 1260 and the transfer of his educational writings where he proposed a complete reform of educa­
Library to the Sorbonne through the agency of the great opponent tion in the Christian West. The Cardinal had attempted to gain entry
of the Friars, Gerard of Abbeville, on his death in 1272, he carefully to England in order to mediate the Civil War, but entry was refused.
guarded the sections of this library which had to do with Magic and Bacon, however, was affected by the War since his family, who were
Experimental Science. It is not beyond normal expectation to think on the King’s side, was reduced to poverty. One of the oddities about
that sometime between 1247 and 1256, Bacon must have been a Bacon’s own commitment is that his own very great advocates of
reader and visitor at this Library. There is clear evidence in the Opus cultural, religious and scientific reform were the ones invoked by
maius and elsewhere that Bacon is presenting a prose version of the Simon de Montfort as his advisors.23
cosmography which is found in the De vetula, the poem (which is an Sometime in 1266, Bacon, through the offices of the English Ambas­
introduction to the philosophical life) by Richard of Foumival. Indeed, sador to the Papal Curia, William Bonecour, regained contact with
Bacon in his Opus maius is the first major commentator on this poem. Cardinal De Foulques. Since early spring 1265, he (quite unexpectedly)
Unless Bacon had access to this library prior to its transfer into the had become Pope Clement IV. In July 1266, Bacon received an
hands of Gerard of Abbeville, it is doubtful that he could have gained order (mandatum) from Pope Clement IV to write to him concern­
access to the many texts which he cites in his works after 1260. ing the topics of their conversation and to ignore the statutes of his
We do not know where or in what province of the Franciscan order to the contrary. This, however, placed Bacon in a difficulty.
Order Bacon became a Friar Minor. But the evidence that he was He was able to tell his superiors that he was on a mission for the
a Franciscan sometime around 1256 is clear. We do, however, know Papacy, but since the Pope did not supply Bacon with research funds,
that he entered the Order at the time of its greatest crisis over the he had to beg, borrow and cajole his friends to get the parchment,
scribes and writing requirements. And all of it had to be done as
secretly as possible.
20 Jeremiah Hackett, “Scientia experimentalis: From Robert Grosseteste to Roger
Bacon,” art. cit., 98-102.
21 Jeremiah Hackett, art. cit., 113-16. See also Jeremiah Hackett, “Aristotle, Astrologia
and Controversy at the University of Paris (1266-74),” in John Van Engen and
Edward D. English, eds. Learning Institutionalized: Teaching in the Middle Ages, (Forth­ 22 See Weisheipl, art. cit., 455.
coming) [= Papers of the 1992 NEH Colloqium in Medieval Studies, University of 23 See John Maddicot, Simon de Montfort, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
Notre Dame]. 1994.
18 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON: HIS LIFE, CAREER AND WORKS 19

According to Bacon, the Pope had requested him to write concern­ before his time, one will find the real scientific context for Bacon’s
ing the status of Philosophy within Theology. But much more was writings. Sometime in 1267-8, Bacon sent the Opus maius (in four
involved. From various scattered remarks, it is clear that the Pope sections) to the Pope through the agency of his student the “anony­
wanted Bacon’s considered views on the whole academic situation at mous” Iohannes and a companion. He also sent related works such as
the University of Paris, and in particular the wholescale warfare about Opus minus, De multiplicatione specierum, and related works on alchemy
Aristode in the Arts Faculty as well as the in-fighting in the Theology and possibly astrology to the Pope. Unfortunately, by November 26,
Faculty between the Friars and their opponents, the Secular Masters. 1268, Pope Clement IV had died. And there remained an inter­
Part one of the Opus maius presents the reader with the core of regnum in the Papacy until 1271. Still, one cannot help but think
Bacon’s polemic. It can be summed up as follows: Aristode and that the Pope would have passed on these works to his trusted aca­
Astronomy/Astrology. But this is a rubric. What it is stating is that demic advisors. Still, given the present state of Bacon’s texts, and this
the works of Aristode as interpreted by Avicenna and Averroes and despite the great labors of Cardinal Gasquet, A.G. Little, Fr. Delorme,
all the works of Arabic science then available in translation should L. Withington and especially Robert Steele, it is extremely difficult
be studied by the Christian scholars at the University of Paris. One to be precise about the dating of all of Bacon’s works after 1260.
can see that Bacon, like the author of the Speculum astronomiae, was We know that the polemic entitled Compendium studii philosophiae was
concerned the task of separating books in Magic from true works in written ca. 1271-2. Further, it is becoming more evident that Bacon’s
Science and Art. works from the 1260’s have a close connection with the issues lead­
Further, it is clear that Bacon is attempting to provide the Pope ing up to the Parisian Condemnations of 1270 and 1277. According
with an interpretation of Aristotle which is more comprehensive than to a report in the Chronicle of the Twenty-Four Generals, Roger Bacon
that of the young Masters in Arts. In particular, while they seemed was formally condemned sometime between November, 1277 and
willing to juxtapose Aristotle and Theology, with the obvious lack of Pentecost, 1279 by Jerome of Ascoli, the Master-General of the
detailed resolution of conflicting propositions concerning: Creation, Franciscan Order “on account of certain suspected novelties.” And
Providence and the individuality of the intellect, Bacon wished to because of these he was confined to prison (house-arrest). The doctrine
show how Aristotle and Science (i.e. Astronomy plus the other sci­ of Roger Bacon was forbidden in the Order and Papal approval
ences) could be taken up and transcended in a new kind of Theo­ was sought.26
logy, one which took the sciences of Language, Nature and Morals
seriously. In Bacon’s view, however skilled the dialectics of the Arts College Press, 1997), 15-44 [Papers from the 1993-4 SSIPS/SAGP Conference on
Masters, they were like the blind leading the blind even in the area Ancient and Medieval Philosophy, Binghamton University, SUNY].
26 Chronica X X IV Generalium Ordinis Minorum, in Analecta Franciscana, III, 360: Hie
of natural science. Generalis frater Hieronymus de multorum fratrum consilio condemnavit et reprobavit
Whether or not the Masters of Arts held a Double-Truth theory doctrinam Fratris Rogerii Bachonis Anglici, sacrae theologiae magistri, continens
has received much discussion.24 In any event, it is clear that Bacon aliquas novitates suspectas, propter quas fuit idem Rogerius carceri condemnatus,
praecipiendo omnibus fratribus ut nullus illam teneret, sed ipsam vitaret, ut per
personally believed that they did hold such a position, and that they Ordinem reprobatum. Super hoc etiam scripsit Domino Papae Nicolao praefato, ut
did so in a deceitful manner.25 If we read the later works of Roger per eius auctoritatem doctrina ilia periculosa totaliter sopiretur.
Bacon (1263-92) in the light of his attack on the so-called Latin Aver- Naturally, one wants to know which doctrine was dangerous. It is most likely to
have been the astrology, alchemy and sdentia experimentalis as used in Moralis Philoso-
roists or Radical Aristotelians, rather than as a 19th century Scientist phia, that part of Bacon’s thought which related closely to theology. Again, his pos­
sible links to the Spiritual Franciscans, and his intemperate attacks on almost every
scholar of the age, but especially against the Dominicans and against the “Seculares”
such as Gerard of Abbeville would have caused problems. But perhaps, the most
24 Richard C. Dales, “The Origins of the Doctrine of the Double Truth,” Viator accurate answer is the one suggested long ago by Pierre Mandonnet: Bacon was
15 (1984), 169-79. condemned within the Franciscan O rder as a consequence of the general Condem­
25 Communia naturalium, Fasc. Ill, 286; See Jeremiah Hackett, “Aquinas, Roger nation of Philosophy and the Sciences by the Bishop of Paris in 1277. After all,
Bacon and the Problem of the Intellective Soul (anima intellectiva) 1266-77,” in these sciences included topics which touched on Magic and Occult science. See
Jeremiah Hackett, ed. Aquinas on Mind and Intellect: New Essays, (New York: Dowling Jeremiah Hackett, art. cit., 100-103.
20 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON! HIS LIFE, CAREER AND WORKS 21

In the light of recent research, it has now become apparent that a new kind of thinking about nature. That Bacon himself in the
some time after 1278, Bacon returned from Paris to Oxford. It was 1260’s did not do much humanistic research and scientific experi­
at the Franciscan House in Oxford that he completed his Edition of mentation is simply due to the sociological and historical conditions
the important Secretum secretorum,27 of his life at that time. He acknowledges this explicitly in Opus
Bacon has been idolized and praised as the founder of Modern maius, part six. He would not be the first or last humanist and sci­
Science. Hagiography of Science presents us with a man of 19th entist who, due to political correctness of one kind or another, had
century interests long before that time. This is the image which has their research cut and their long term vision of reform curtailed.
entered the scholarly and popular literature. And yet beginning with Yet, despite wars, upheavals, narrowmindedness, and the general
Lynn Thorndike, Pierre Duhem, A.G. Litde, Robert Steele, Theodore change of things, Bacon’s works did survive, and they did have some
Crowley, F. Alessio, E. Bottom, and Stewart C. Easton, the romantic influence in the Renaissance and in the early modern period. But
image gave way to the more realistic portrait. More recently, through that is another story.
the new works of critical edition and translation, a better sense of
the evidence is being won.
Bacon was a person of his time, a 13th century Scholastic philoso­ B. Bacon’s Works: Brief Introduction
pher, a Medieval scientist, a savant of very great scope, the one who
taught Western Europe to think about light, force and species. And Here, it is important to gain some sense of Bacon’s academic work
in the context of Medieval Science, Religion, Philosophy and Magic, as witnessed by his remaining authentic writings. As will become
he is a towering if neglected figure of great importance. Coming as apparent later in the volume, there is considerable disagreement con­
he does toward the end of the great Translation Movement (1140- cerning the authenticity of Bacon’s works. For most of the items in
1280), he was in a position to absorb and take advantage of almost the Steele edition, especially those works which Bacon scholars have
everything which had been handed on from the ancient world in dated to the 1240’s, we rely on one single MS: MS Amiens 406.
Science, Religion, Philosophy and Magic.28 These works are generally held to be authentic reportationes of Bacon’s
John North has pointed out that the three “greats” of medieval lectures on Aristotelians and Neo-platonic texts in the Arts Faculty
theory of Perspective Bacon-Pecham-Witelo, developed the subject in at the University of Paris in the 1240’s. There is one major problem
its basic outlines such that it would retain the structure given it by concerning these texts which has not been confronted by the scholar­
these three great scholars until late Renaissance would open up new ship. These lectures on Aristotelian and Neoplatonic texts are very
vistas29 Bacon was the one who wrote the first synthesis of this mate­ sophisticated, indeed, more complex than one would expect from an
rial. He is, therefore, a major influential figure in Medieval Science. Arts Master in the 1240’s.30 Each of these works needs to be studied
He is the one who set out a particular science, Perspective and used carefully and critically re-edited.
it and its subordinate science, the scientia experimentalise as a Model for As we have seen above, beginning in 1264, Bacon set about writ­
ing his new works on scientific topics, but was unable to do so due
to the prohibitions of the Council of Narbonne in 1260. He made
27 Steven J. Williams, “Roger Bacon and His Edition of the Pseudo-Aristotelian Secretum
secretorum,'1'1 Speculum 69 (1994), 57-73. an “end-run” around these restrictions by appealing to the academic
28 See recent works by Charles B. Burnett on Arabic-Latin translators in the interests of Cardinal De Foulques. The order by Pope Clement IV
12th century.
29 John North, “Natural Philosophy in Late Medieval Oxford,” in J.I. Catto and
Ralph Evans, eds., Late Medieval Oxford (The History of The University of Oxford, ed. cit.
Vol. II), 96: To appreciate the full measure of Bacon’s influence we must turn to 30 Once in a conversation, Fr. Allan B. Wolter, O.F.M. suggested to me that this
the sixteenth century and the printing of works by those whom he direcdy influ­ whole issue of the authenticity of the Parisian Quaestiones needs to be re-examined.
enced, Pecham and Witelo in particular. They, with Alhazen and Maurolico, were He expressed doubt that some of the items in the Steele edition of these Quaestiones
subsequendy used by Kepler and possibly by Descartes at the outset of the next were works by Bacon. A first step in this direction will be made in a forthcoming
crucial phase in the subject’s evolution. issue of Vivarium, 1997.
22 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON! HIS LIFE, CAREER AND WORKS 23

to Roger Bacon in 1266 to send his works immediately found the Opus maius needs a full critical edition, as do the related works. At
Friar unprepared and in a difficult circumstance. Nevertheless, be­ present, there is a critical edition only for parts five, seven and the
tween July 1266 and sometime in 1268, Bacon managed to send the De signis section of part three. It will therefore be some time before
Opus maius, Opus minus, De multiplicatione specierum, some works on the scholarly public will be able to have available a complete edition
astrology and alchemy, possibly the De speculum comburentibus to the of all the Bacon corpus such as is now available for the critical study
Pope. There is considerable controversy as to whether or not he sent of William of Ockham.
the Opus tertium. This is an issue whose resolution will await a new
critical edition of this text.31 Bacon wrote the notoriously polemical
piece, Compendium studii philosophiae in 1271-2. The dating of the
Communia naturalium is very problematic. Part one seems to have
begun in the early 1260’s, but later sections such as Book One, parts
3 and 4 as well as Book Two, seems to have been written after
1268, and may have been written in stages between 1268 and 1274.32
It has become apparent in recent scholarship that Roger Bacon
began his edition of the Secretum secretorum in Paris during the 1260’s
and that sometime after 1278 when he returned to the Franciscan
house of studies in Oxford, he completed his edition.33 The Compen­
dium studii theologiae must, on the basis of internal evidence, have been
completed at Oxford in the 1290’s. However, the reader will note
that apart from these specific references to forty years earlier in the
case of Richard Rufus, and other such dates, the text and content is
quite similar to that found in the Opus maius from the 1260’s. Per­
haps, Bacon or an assistant simply re-edited old material.
For an overview of the state of these works, the reader is advised
to look at the studies of modern Bacon scholars. However, it is now
the task of Bacon scholarship to look at the MSS tradition of each
of work inorder to set about making truly critical estimates of the
authenticity of each text. That this is an absolute requirement has
been shown recently by the proof by A. Paravicini-Bagliani that some
of the writings on medicine Steele edition (Vol. IX, ed. Withington
and Little) are not authentic works of Roger Bacon.34 Further, the

31 Professor George Molland is preparing a critical edition of this text.


32 See Jeremiah Hackett, “Aquinas, Roger Bacon and Latin Averroism: The Prob­
lem of the Intellective Soul (Anima intellectiva) 1266-77,” in Jeremiah Hackett, ed.
Aquinas on Mind and Intellect: New Essays, (New York: Dowling College Press, 1997),
15-44. Jeremiah Hackett is preparing a new text and english translation of the Com­
munia naturalium.
33 See Steven J. Williams below.
34 A. Paravicini-Bagliani, “II mito della prolongatione vitae e la corte pontifica del
Ducento: il De retardatione senectutis,” in his Medicina e science della natura alia corte dei
papi nel Ducento (Spoleto, 1991), 281-326.
2. ROGER BACON’S ATTITUDE TOWARD TH E LATIN
TRANSLATIONS AND TRANSLATORS OF THE
TWELFTH AND TH IRTEENTH CENTURIES

Richard Lemay

Roger Bacon’s testimony regarding the role of Latin translations in


the formation of scholastic thought was long taken at its face value
as coming from a contemporary witness. For it was presumed to
mirror through personal experience the historical process by which
Aristotle’s philosophy emerged as the backbone of Latin scholasti­
cism. Closer scrutiny of his assertions on the subject, however, inclined
some historians more recently to question the accuracy of Bacon’s
testimony and even to charge him with gross ignorance or disregard
of the realities of the case. In 1923 L. Thorndike reviewed in extenso
Bacon’s statements on the subject of translations and translators in
his times and found them to be marred by innumerous errors of
fact, insufficient information and often extremely partisan judgments.1
Shortly afterwards a thoroughgoing study by S.D. Wingate2 of the
Latin translations of Aristotelian scientific works during the Middle
Ages amply documented the deficiencies in Bacon’s testimony already
pointed to by Thorndike.
In the more than sixty years since, Bacon’s peculiar conceptions of
nature and of experimental science have continued to attract attention,
yet without the finger ever being laid on the probable cause of Bacon’s
vagaries on the subject of translations and translators. This predica­
ment of scholarship appears to be due in the first place to a prevalent
trend which is satisfied with reading all too casually the significant
documents and related cultural context signaling the emergence of
Aristotelian science and philosophy in European thought from the

1 Lynn Thorndike, A History of Magic and Experimental Science, Vol. II (1923) Ch. LXI
pp. 616-691, especially 630-649. Cf. Ibid., pp. 312-313.—Thorndike had sounded
a first alarm in 1914, “Roger Bacon and Experimental Method in the Middle Ages”.
Philosophical Review. XXIII 271-298. For an account on this topic since Thorndike,
see Jeremiah Hackett below.
2 S.D. Wingate, The Medieval Latin Versions of the Aristotelian Scientific Corpus, with
Special Reference to the Biological Works, London 1931. [Repr. Reprint Library. Iowa.],
Ch. V, pp. 112-119 and passim, see Index s.v. Bacon.
26 RICHARD LEMAY LATIN TRANSLATIONS AND TRANSLATORS 27

beginning of the twelfth century. In our view the case hinges around time. The assertion is repeated often enough but most clearly with
a saner perception of the events at the University of Paris in 1210- respect to Alexander of Hales, who taught theology at Paris in the
1215 which saw the condemnation and proscription of books propa­ first decades of the thirteenth century and who is charged by Bacon
gating the metaphysics and natural science of Aristotle, the so-called with abject ignorance of metaphysics and natural science which by
libri naturaks in medieval parlance. And here Bacon’s testimony is now [i.e. ca. 1270] constitutes the pride of the University [underlin­
both instructive, for his experience was acquired under the drastic ing is ours for later discussion]:
effects of these condemnations, and at the same time misleading
He [Alexander] did not teach nor study the natural sciences and meta­
because of Bacon’s heavy bias which made him ignore some central physics because the “principal works” for these sciences or their commen­
features of the culture of his milieu. taries had not yet been translated when he taught in the Faculty of Arts.
We must first recall the main features of Bacon’s account of the These works were condemned [excommunicati] and banned [suspensi]
emergence of aristotelian studies in the Paris of his student and teach­ for a long time afterwards in Paris where he received his education.
ing days (1230-1250), and hence his understanding of the impact of And he entered the [Franciscan] Order before the time these books
began to be read. This is obvious since his joining the Order coincided
the prohibitions of the libri naturaks at Paris in his own times.
with the “dispersion” of the University of Paris (masters and students
strike of 1229-1231). For during his time and till the end of the strike at
the University these books were proscribed. Indeed Alexander was already
1. Bacon’s Account of the Arrival of Aristoklian Science an elderly man and had been a magister in Theology when he joined
at Paris in his own Times the Order. To sum up: this man knew nothing of the sciences now
commonly studied [“nunc vulgatas”], namely natural philosophy and
metaphysics which are presently the pride of the studium.3
We may reserve for later examination his intemperate denunciations
of the Latin translations, despite the fact that the latter were so instru­ This first hand testimony illustrates a situation which Bacon knew at
mental in giving the fresh impetus to aristotelian studies recorded close range since Alexander of Hales, a celebrated “secular”4 teacher
by him. of theology at Paris before the crisis of 1229-1231, subsequently
The spade work done by Thorndike and Wingate in pointing the entered the Franciscan Order to which Bacon himself belonged when
inadequacies of Bacon’s judgment on the historic movement of aristote- writing these lines. Yet Bacon’s testimony is befuddled by a certain
lianism in thirteenth century scholasticism will dispense us from retell­ animus5 and requires sober interpretation. His main points however
ing the story from scratch. We need only stress a couple of distinctive hold true and are corroborated by several contemporary witnesses,6
features of Bacon’s opinions bearing on our present thesis, namely
the limited time period covered in his testimony on the one hand,
and secondly his stress on the disastrous and widespread effects of
the Parisian condemnations which according to him stifled the study 3 “Non legit naturalia nec metaphysica nec audivit ea quia non fuerunt libri
principales harum scientiarum nec co m m en tan i translate quando rexit in artibus.
of science and philosophy for so long among students and teachers Et diu postea Juerunt excommunicati et suspensi Parisius ubi ipse studuit. Unde citius ordinem
at Paris. intravit antequam fuerint hi libri semel perlecti. Istud notum est per eius ingressum
On the first point, namely the short time period assumed in his in ordinem et per dispersionem Universitatis Parisiensis; nam usque ad eum fuerunt
libri prohibiti et usquequo rediit Universitas, post quem reditum ipse intravit religionem
statements, it is remarkable that Bacon seems to be very poorly jam senex et magister in theologia. Unde et breviter dicam: ipse ignoravit has scientias
informed beyond the forty years preceding his specific utterings on nunc vulgatas, scilicet naturalem philosophiam et metaphysicam in quibus est tota
the subject in the Opus Maius (ca. 1266) and in the Compendium Studii gloria studii modemorum”. Opus minus Ed. Brewer 1859, p. 326.
4 That is, a secular cleric though not yet belonging to a religious order.
philosophise (1270/1271). Whenever he has an opportunity to refer to 5 He wishes to combat the tendency in franciscan studia to rely blindly on the
the fate of the libri naturaks at Paris up to his own times, Bacon Summa Jratris Alexandri which he claims was falsely ascribed to Alexander of Hales
and further lacks the foundation of science.
invariably asserts that books dealing with “metaphysics and natural 6 Rigord’s chronicle, documents concerning the University of Paris in the Chartu-
science” were long condemned and proscribed at Paris before his larium, Caesarius of Heisterbach’s Dialogus miraculorum etc.
28 RICHARD LEMAY LATIN TRANSLATIONS AND TRANSLATORS 29

namely that the major books (“libri principales” in Bacon’s judgment, the curriculum at Paris after the turmoil,10 which condemnations were
that is “textus” or authoritative sources) of natural science and of renewed up to the formal admission of Aristotle into the Arts cur­
metaphysics and commentaries thereon were prohibited during the riculum in 1255.
teaching career of Alexander of Hales which spanned the early decades Throughout his statements on the rise of aristotelian studies at
of the thirteenth century at the University of Paris. Paris, and incidentally on the fate of translations which had made it
Yet in his testimony about the situation of the libri naturaks in happen, Bacon seemed to envisage no other time perspective than
Paris at the time of Hales’ training and teaching, and therefore bear­ the period of forty years (1230-70) of free flight, preceded by a long
ing on the fate of translations of scientific works in thirteenth cen­ one (1210 to 1230) of abject igorance of natural science forcibly
tury Paris, Bacon evidences an astounding degree of ignorance with imposed by the condemnation of the libri naturaks in 1210/1215. The
respect to capital factors in the case. In one instance7 he makes the inaccuracies in Bacon’s dating of events and the notable gaps in his
beginning of the study of Aristotle in Paris coincide with the arrival information were sufficiently documented by Thorndike and Wingate
of Michael Scot ca. 1230 with his translations of many of Aristotle’s so as to render superfluous belaboring of the charges. Yet while these
works. Wingate has no trouble pointing to the exaggeration, even critics seem timid or embarassed, there may exist more fundamental
falsehood of Bacon’s assertion, as did Thorndike but with some feeble factors behind the shortcomings in Bacon’s assertions. For if we realize,
attempt at justification.8 In addition, Bacon’s choice of time sequence as we must, that the 1210 condemnations included in their broad,
for the emergence of aristotelian studies in Paris brings the case back indiscriminate sweep nearly all writings on natural science made
to no further than the early thirties of the thirteenth century. In available to European scholars in translation from the Arabic since
accordance with this somewhat arbitrary chronology, which is con­ the early twelfth century, the fuzziness in Bacon’s information may
tradicted by the actual facts as we know them, Bacon declares that then be seen as one patent example of the blight these condemna­
previous to the forty years since the revigoration supposedly gene­ tions, cast upon the memory of scholars a generation later concerning
rated by Michael Scot’s arrival, the study of metaphysics and of the history and role of these translations. Bacon’s surprising igno­
natural science were proscribed for a long time at Paris under threat rance of the facts is but a mirror of such damage.
of most severe sanctions:
Scimus enim quod temporibus nostris Parisius diu fuit contradictum
naturali philosophiae et metaphysicae Aristotelis per Avicennam et
2. The Parisian Decrees of 1210/1215 and the libri naturales
Averroym expositis, et ob densam ignorantiam fuerunt libri eorum
excommunicati et utentes eis per tempora satis longa.9 To be true, in order to assess the veracity or limitations in Bacon’s
assertions we must fit them into the larger context of the fate of the
As in the earlier passage respecting Alexander of Hales, Bacon is no
so-called libri naturaks in the schools of his time. In view of the impasse
doubt referring to the condemnation of Aristotle’s natural science reached in this direction by modern scholarship, there has long sub­
and of its Arabian commentators issued by an ecclesiastical coun­
sisted a need to re-appraise the significance and long lasting impact
cil at Paris in 1210, reissued and made more specific in 1215 by
of the condemnation and proscription of Aristotle’s “metaphysics”
Cardinal Robert de Cour^on acting as papal legate to reorganize and natural science and its “commentators” in the Parisian decrees
of 1210-15. We therefore beg to offer here a fresh approach to the
situation from the perspective of a broader canvas than one concerned
7 Opus Maim. Pars II, cap. XIII, quoted by Wingate p. 116.—C f also L. Thorndike,
Michael Scot. p. 27. with the fate of Aristotle’s writings exclusively as has been the tradition
8 L. Thorndike, op. cit. p. 27 considers the possibility that Bacon’s assertion meant
primarily that having brought with him his new translations of Aristotle’s works,
Michael may have made it possible for Parisian scholars to circumvent the condem­ 10 All pertinent documents will easily be found in Denifle-Chatelain’s Chartularium
nations of the older translations. Universitatis Parisiensis. I pp. 70-79 (for the period 1210/15), and pp. 129-139 (for
9 Opus Maim. Pars la, cap. X. Bridges p. 21. 1230/31).
30 RICHARD LEMAY LATIN TRANSLATIONS AND TRANSLATORS 31

heretofore. It may provide a fairer understanding of Bacon’s vagaries works of Aristotle proper such as the Metaphysics or the Physics. The
concerning the role of translations and translators in medieval latin decree of 1210 mentions only “natural science of Aristotle” without
aristotelianism. specifying any work in particular.13 Robert de Courgon, however,
Aristotelianism indeed stood in the forefront of the commotion cites the Metaphysics by name among the prohibited books of Aristotle,
aroused among parisian scholars by the condemnation and proscrip­ and its inclusion is explicitly assumed by Bacon speaking of these
tion of books of natural science, assorted with severe sanctions threat­ interdictions. Such an extension is easily explained by calling to mind
ened against its transgressors. It was so perceived by Bacon many the testimony of William Brito in his continuation of Rigord’s royal
decades later when he was testifying to the damaging effects of these Chronicle (ca. 1220). Indeed, writing about the proscriptions of 1210
condemnations on studies of natural science among his contempo­ in Paris, William tells of books of Aristotle recently imported from
raries. Indeed, the status of the libri naturales, not only those of Aristotle Constantinople (conquered by the Latin Crusaders in 1204) and trans­
but in general all books dealing with natural science based on aris- lated from Greek into Latin, which “taught metaphysics” and which
totelian doctrines, appears to have been the underlying, festering issue were condemned at Paris because their “subtle doctrines” seemed to
in the scholastic world during the first half of the thirteenth century. lend support to heresies, present ones and others that may arise in
O n the other hand, their connection with Arab learning had been the future.14
made explicit by the addition of “commenta” in 1210, but “summe” In his slightly confused testimony William Brito may hold the
in Robert de Courgon’s regulations of 1215. Surely no “classical” solution of most ambiguities concerning the nature of the condemna­
(greek) commentaries could have been intended for they were utterly tions of Aristotelian writings in Paris in 1210. William does not seem
unknown among Latins at that time. Whereas the term “summa”, to be much informed about the Metaphysics of Aristotle proper, but he
already used by Arab authors in the form of “jam a'a” (collectio), knew, apparently from hearsay, that in Paris, scholars were reading
and translated “summa” by John of Seville in the Great Conjunctions of boo^s “purported to have been written by Aristotle” and “teaching
Abu M acshar, stood for a “gathering of basic doctrines” in any dis­ metaphysics” which had been brought recently from Constantinople
cipline. The shift from “commenta” to “summe” would indicate closer and translated from Greek into Latin, and that these books were
approximation to reality tendered to Robert de Courgon by the “boni deemed to supply water to the mill of heretics, present and possibly
viri” whom he said he had consulted on this point. Hence the numer­ future ones. On account of which they were ordered to be burned,
ous Arabian “introductions” to the science of the stars such as Abu and explicit injunction was issued forbidding their reproduction or
M a'shar’s, Alchabitius’, Zael’s (Sahl ben Bishr), Masha’allah’s among even possession in the future.
others most aptly fit the category of works of natural science and From this we may conclude that some knowledge of the doctrines
metaphysics designated under the terms of “commenta” or “summe” of Aristotle’s natural science was already diffused among Latin scholars,
in the decrees of 1210/15.11 Surely neither the classical greek commen­ evidently not from the books recently brought from Constantinople,
tators of Aristotle could have been signalled by the theologians of 1210
in Paris, nor even the commentaries by Averroes on Aristotelian genu­ 13 M. Grabmann doubted that the theologians who drafted the decree of 1210
ine works because absolutely none were known or translated by 1210. would have been sufficiendy informed to go that far in identifying any work in
particular on natural science by Aristotle.
We have been striving for some decades now12 to show that the 14 “In diebus illis legebantur Parisius libelli quidam ab Aristotele, ut dicebantur
libri naturales in question did not at first include directly the basic compositi qui docebant metaphysicam, delati de novo a Constantinopoli et a Graeco
in Latinum translati, qui quoniam non solum praedicte heres sententiis subtilibus
occasionem praebebant, imo et aliis nondum inventis praebere poterant, iussi sunt
11 An unmistakable sign of this appears from Albertus Magnus’ Speculum astronomiae omnes comburi et sub poena excommunicationis cautum est in eodem concilio ne quis
in which absolutely all books of natural science there reviewed and on which judgment eos de caetero scribere aut legere praesumeret, vel quocumque modo habere”. Recueil
is passed are translations from the Arabic. As we shall soon demonstrate, Albertus’ des Historiens des Gaules et de la France. XVII p. 84. Quoted by Du Boulay [Bulaeus]
exhaustive bibliographical review and sanction of the libri naturales provided forty Historia Universitatis Parisiensis III 1666 (Repr. 1966) p. 51, who borrows quotation
years later the actual solution to the crisis created by the parisian decrees of 1210. from De Launoy, De Varia Aristotelis in Academia Pansiensi Fortuna. Parisiis 1662. cap. 1.
12 Since Tokyo 1974 and henceforth, See note below. Reproduced by A. Jourdain. Recherches critiques. .. (1843) p. 187.
32 RICHARD LEMAY LATIN TRANSLATIONS AND TRANSLATORS 33

but by means of astrological works translated from the Arabic. Now Hermann fully suffices to explain how in the minds of the parisian
the use of genuine books of Aristotle recendy translated from the theologians of 1210 works of Arab science, especially of astrology,
Greek and which “taught Metaphysics” revealed the unmistakable available in translations since the first half of the twelfth century did
connection between the “theology/metaphysics” embodied in Ara­ appear to teach the metaphysics of Aristotle and hence were deemed
bian astrology as Hermann of Carinthia had explained ca. 1150 on dangerous to orthodoxy, without need of any direct knowledge of
the one hand, and Aristotle’s natural science expressed in the Meta­ Aristotle’s original writings.
physics on the other. It was probably this abrupt revelation dawning The “dispersion” alluded to in Bacon’s report is undoubtedly the
on the parisian theologians shortly after the arrival and translation of strike by Masters and Students in 1229-1231 which was finally re­
the Metaphysics, which suggested to them the danger to orthodoxy solved only after Pope Gregory IX issued the Bull “Parens Scientiarum”
hidden in Aristotle’s metaphysics and natural science. Before the turn usually considered as the formal act of creation of the University at
of the century, Alanus de Insulis, a theologian teaching in Paris, had Paris. A major grievance of the striking masters and students was the
already considered Abu Ma'shar as the new auctoritas in “scientific” intolerable situation16 created by the 1210 prohibitions of the libri
astrology. It is no less true that modern scholarship has ever been naturales which obviously in Bacon’s view included “metaphysics
hard put to trace any substantial case of a latin translation of any and natural science” in general, and not the books of Aristotle only.
writing of Aristotle on metaphysics or natural science which would Coupled with his statement that genuine interest in aristotelianism
fit the uproar at Paris in 1210. arose among scholars at Paris around 1230 with the arrival of Michael
With respect to the broad category of Aristotle’s libri naturales aimed Scot bringing his translations of Aristotle, Bacon’s truncated account
at in the said decrees Bacon’s statement rings more or less true, namely of the historical stages of the rise of aristotelianism in scholasticism
that their principal texts in these sciences had not yet been trans­ seems more like a rehash of gossip held in fashion forty years before.
lated at the time of Alexander of Hales’ education and teaching in There is no doubt that the arrival of Michael Scot at Paris touting
Paris. We have seen that Averroes’ commentaries, which at the time Aristotle’s natural science would have attracted the keenest of interest.
of Bacon’s writing had become so instrumental in the domination of After all Scot was known as the astrologer and familiar of Emperor
latin aristotelianism by the averroistic brand, could not have been Frederick II, himself an ardent promoter of aristotelian studies despite
involved in 1210. As for Avicenna’s paraphrases of Aristotle’s Meta­ active Church resistance, and a brazen opponent of Popes Gregory IV
physics, they had been available in Latin for nearly a century since and Innocent IV on this score. The famous letter dispatched about
the translation by the team John of Seville/Gundissalinus ca. 1145. that time by the Emperor to the University of Bologna17—and later
And we know from the writings of William of Auvergne,—teacher of to the University of Paris by his son Manfred18—strongly advocating
theology then and later bishop of Paris (1228-1249)—that Avicenna’s the study of Aristotle’s natural science in the Universities reflects the
commentaries were attentively read before 1230. The confusion in mentality prevailing at Frederick II’s court.19 As Frederick showed
Bacon’s report about these realities appears therefore to be attribut­
able more to ignorance than to bias. Indeed, the meaning of the l’histoire . . in La diffusione delle science islamiche.. . Roma. Accademia Nazionale dei
term “metaphysics” as designating the science of ultimate causes of Lincei 1987, p. 438 and note 57, p. 458.
16 This issue is brought into sharp focus in the propaganda letter issued by John
motion and of being in the cosmos could be gathered from Hermann of Garland ca. 1229 aiming to attract the distraught students of Paris to the new
of Carinthia’s preface to his translation of the Almagest (ca. 1150) in University at Toulouse where the books prohibited at Paris could be read without
which he explained the etymology of the term metaphysics from the fear of sanctions. Such propaganda would not have held the slightest attraction had
not the critical situation in Paris been felt “intolerable”.
Greek as equating theology.15 This nearly unnoticed statement by 17 Huillard-Breholles. Historia diplomatica Friderici Secundi. . . IV, 1 p. 383: “Encyclica
Friderici Romanorum imperatoris qua magistris in philosophia docentibus libros
quosdam sermoniales et mathematicos, ab Anstotele aliisque philosophis sub graecis
15 “.. . dehinc vero robore hoc [previous stages of trivium and quadrivium] animati et arabicis vocabulis conscriptos, nunc in latinum ipso curante translatos, mittit”.
in theologica exercitate mentis aciem fiducialiter intendebant. Unde et ab ordine docendi 18 Martene et Durant. Amplissima collectio iudiciorum. II col. 1220.
et discendi theologiani metaphysicam nominabant”. Cf. R. Lemay, “De la scolastique a 19 Despite some errors in dates or attribution, Antonio De Stefano’s La outturn alia
34 RICHARD LEMAY LATIN TRANSLATIONS AND TRANSLATORS 35

himself so determined and active in sponsoring aristotelian studies in Nor did the prohibitions (1210-1215) long remained effective in Paris.
In 1231, Pope Gregory IX appointed a commission consisting of William
the Universities at that time, one wonders whether Michael Scot’s
of Auxerre, Stephen of Provins . . . and a third member,22 with the
appearance in Paris in 1230 was not an element of Frederick’s cam­ object of revising the Aristotelian corpus prior to the lifting of the ban.
paign in favor of aristotelian studies. Michael Scot joined Frederick’s This body seems to have succeeded, after the manner of commissions,
court in 1227, and in 1228—1229 he may have accompanied the in burying the whole matter in a decent obscurity. Nothing more is
excommunicated emperor on his Crusade to Jerusalem.20 At his death heard of the revised edition of Aristotle, (op. cit. p. 19).
in Germany in 1236 Michael had returned to the court sometime The situation imagined by Wingate in the first portion of our quota­
before. Hence the suggestion that his short trip and stay in Paris tion is in flat contradiction with the opinion of a contemporary like
ca. 1230 may have been part of the Emperor’s counter-propaganda Bacon who stated that for his entire teaching career, the renowned
to compete with the Papacy (Gregory IX) in re-orienting the study Parisian teacher of the first half of the thirteenth century Alexander
of natural science and of aristotelianism in the medieval Univer­ of Hales could not read these books because they had remained
sities. On the other hand, in his stressing Michael Scot’s allegedly proscribed all along. If it were true that the prohibitions of 1210 did
capital role in enhancing aristotelian studies in Paris since 1230, Bacon not long remain effective, one wonders why should Gregory IX bother
may have yielded to some bias toward a Scottish savant who had on the one hand to provide in 1231 for the absolution of contraven-
ostentatiously become the “brain” of the imperial intelligentsia on ers, and on the other to establish a commission to “expurgate” the
the one hand, and who in his writings provided considerable support said condemned books? As regards the work of the “expurgation
to “occult”, “magical”, or “experimental” science cherished by Bacon. commission”, Wingate could have easily ascertained that it probably
At any rate the papal struggle against the emperor’s aristotelian cru­ never met: Simon of Authie (de Alteis) died the same year, and
sade, twice heightened by excommunication of the Emperor appears Stephen of Provins probably shortly after,23 while the third member,
to have been at the core of papal policy to maintain its supremacy William of Beauvais seems to have been nominated to a benefice in
in Christendom under the two successive Popes: Gregory IX (1227— a farther place. The obscurity seems rather to lie in Wingate’s infor­
41) and Innocent IV (1243-54). Hence the importance of the Bull mation. The quip in the last portion of our quotation from Wingate
“Parens Scientiarum” actually making the University of Paris the is unavailing, for as we shall now indicate, Pope Innocent IV in
standard-bearer of orthodox culture, against Frederick’s ambition to 1245 used exactly the same words as did Gregory IX in extending
raise Bologna (or Naples) to the status of leading (lay) cultural insti­ the proscription of the libri naturales to the University of Toulouse.
tution of medieval society. The tenor of Innocent’s order reveals that the “expurgation” had
Wingate’s recital21 of the limitations in Roger Bacon’s testimony not as yet taken place as late as 1245, though promise for its imple­
about Latin translations of scientific works from Greek and Arabic mentation was again uttered.
seems quite plausible, corroborating as it does Thorndike’s severe Wingate further comments:
earlier indictments. Her own description of the fate of aristotelian
works in Paris ca. 1230, however is quite implausible in face of the By 1234 we have definite [our underline] evidence in the writing of
Johannes of Garlandia, Philip of Greve and others that the Aristotelian
situation revealed by contemporary documents rightly interpreted.
writings were freely studied in the schools of Paris, and it was not long
Wingate states:
before they were prescribed by the faculties as subjects of examination.24

22 Simon of Authie by name, cf. Chartularium. I. p. 143, doc. 87.


cork di Federico II Inperatore provides a substantial conspectus of the intellectual activi­ 23 Cf. Chartularium U.P. ibid., notes 1 and 2.
ties at the imperial Court in the first half of the thirteenth century. 24 Wingate’s evidence is Grabmann 1911 and 1916. Grabmann came again later
20 L. Thorndike, Michael Scot, 1963, pp. 34ff.—A. de Stefano, La cultura alia cork on the subject with improved information and notably altered judgment: 1936
di Federico I I Imperatore, pp. 35ff. Mitklalterliches Geisksleben. II. pp. 183ff., and 1941 and 1946 I Papi del duecento e
21 S.D. Wingate, op. cit. ch. V, pp. 112-119. I’aristoklismo.
36 RICHARD LEMAY LATIN TRANSLATIONS AND TRANSLATORS 37

Far from testifying that the Aristotelian writings were freely studied parisian clerics especially empowered for this. Another form of relief
in the schools of Paris, John of Garland’s letter on the contrary makes lay in the prospect of the proposed “expurgating commission” on
it clear that the 1210 prohibitions, renewed by Pope Gregory in 1231, which a notable aristotelian like Stephen of Provins was to sit (Michael
were still being enforced at Paris, a fact which allowed him to stress Scot dedicated to him his translation of the De Cclo). It must also
the advantage of coming to Toulouse where the proscribed books have contributed materially to assuage the frustration of the parisian
could be read without fear of sanction. Wingate does not provide scholars. For by 1230, some twenty years after the decrees, a saner
further support for her “definite evidence”, while her sole reference view of the relation of aristotelian natural science and metaphysics to
to the “free study of Aristotle” is a statute of 1254 at the University. the use made of them by the Arabian astrologers must have become
It must be stressed that, contrary to a common assumption that the common place. This view can be sustained from the discreet and
Church authorities showed some laxity on this point, the proscrip­ certainly non-obtrusive confession by eminent “aristotelians” such as
tion of the libri naturales from the curricula at the University of Paris William of Auvergne and Albertus Magnus himself. For both state
was explicitly maintained at least until about the time of the Council rather incidentally that they did read the said works “in their youth”,
of Lyon in 1245, for within two months (September 22, 1245) after presumably wanting to convey the impression that it was before the
the session of the Council (June 28-July 17) Pope Innocent IV prohibitions were issued in 1210. Thus it can be concluded that the
extended to the University of Toulouse the proscriptions edicted at prohibitions and sanctions of 1210 ceased in some fashion to be a
Paris in 1210.25*It must be clearly understood then that down to the major hindrance shortly after 1230. And here Bacon’s testimony gets
statutes of the Arts at the University in 1254, the proscriptions of closer to the facts. The end however did not come by virtue of any
1210 held sway at all time, although with varying conditions of severity formal decision of ecclesiastical authorities. Indeed, in accordance with
which can easily be ascertained through the relevant documents of the sequence of events at the University and in the schools at large,
the University of Paris. it appears that it was the completion of his Speculum Astronomic by
Finally, the confirmed presence of Albertus Magnus in Paris dur­ Albertus Magnus which at last opened the gates for an unrestricted
ing the Council of 1245, added to the revelation by the Franciscan study of and comments on Aristotle’s natural philosophy and meta­
Bonaventure de Iseo that Albertus had received direct permission physics which we observe at Paris after 1250.
from the Pope to read the books of good and evil and to pass judg­
ment on their acceptability (a mission resulting in the production of
the celebrated Speculum Astronomic), a task which Bonaventure asserts 3. Bacon’s Critique of Translations and of Translators
Albert did merge with his on-going enterprise of commenting all the
works of Aristotle, all these converging circumstances make it obvi­ As it is well known, Bacon’s opinion on the worth of translations
ous that this was the moment when the effective solution to the 1210 and on the merits of individual translators who had produced the
ban on aristotelian works in natural science was found at last in crop of foreign texts as manna for high scholasticism is persistently
Albertus Magnus’ Speculum astronomic. negative. He went as far as considering their use by the young gen­
For one, and most importantly perhaps in view of their inhibiting eration of teachers, especially members of the Orders, to lead to
effect, the severe sanctions attached to the said decrees could even­ abomination and desolation of true learning. This historical reality
tually be attenuated by way of easy absolution obtainable from two has been effectively demonstrated and amply documented in recent
studies thanks to an approach definitely more sober than the enthu­
25 It is striking that Innocent IV uses exactly the same terms as did Gregory IX
siastic but blind admiration adopted by his editors in the nineteenth
in renewing the proscription: . . libris illis naturalibus qui in Concilio provinciali and early twentieth century (Brewer, Little, Steele among others).
ex certa causa prohibiti fuere non utantur om nino T olose quousque examinati We need not retell the story in all its details, for scholarship has now
fuerint et ab omni errore purgati”. L. Saltet. L ’ancienne Universite de Toulouse 1912.—
Gregory IX had said “Parisiis non utantur”; this the only difference between the made it plain that like his information about the origin of aristo-
two pronouncements. telianism in Paris in the 1230, Bacon’s knowledge of and judgment
38 RICHARD LEMAY LATIN TRANSLATIONS AND TRANSLATORS 39

on the translations feeding scholastic thought were very defective, or also well known but no less misplaced. Without any serious exami­
worse, negative out of personal irritation or envy. His own claim to nation of their translations, Bacon declares ex cathedra that these
a knowledge of “languages of the science” as he labels them is clearly translators ignored both the sciences they were handling in the trans­
exaggerated in view of the demonstrations he supplies at length in lations and the languages from which they were translating. Such a
the Compendium Studii Philosophiae for instance. As compared to the serious charge should have been thoroughly documented to escape
direct and detailed knowledge of translations of scientific works from being considered absolutely unconscionable. The only grounds on
the Arabic displayed by Albertus Magnus in the Speculum Astronomiae, which Bacon bases his sweeping criticism are purely subjective: “sicut
Bacon’s strictures on the value of translations seem mean and largely ego expertus sum omnino”.28 To re-inforce his judgment Bacon does
unavailing. We shall not tarry too long on this aspect of Bacon’s not hesitate to proclaim that he had read more than any one else in
attitude toward translations, only summarizing a few interesting points these matters: “et audivi diligenter plures, et legi plus quam aliis, ut
in his utterances, such as his lame recapitulation of the story of trans­ omnes qui nutriti sunt in studio non ignorant” (ibid.). Bacon’s own
lations since Gerard of Cremona (1114-1187), his sharp but shallow pretense at knowing these languages is never properly substantiated
criticism of his contemporaries Hermann the German and William and there seems to lurk more personal animosity than truth in the
of Moerbeke, and above all his incorrect account of Robert Grosseteste wild accusations against contemporary translators.
attitude toward translations and the Latin form they produced of 3. Bacon’s lavish praises on the translator competence of his model
Aristotle’s writings. Most important however in this review will be and master Robert Grosseteste is most revealing of his gross partiality.
an enquiry into Bacon’s reasons for his staunch hostility toward On the one hand Bacon claims that Robert neglected all translations
Albertus Magnus. of Aristotle’s works—presumably because of their defectiveness ac­
1. Bacon’s apparent neglect of the massive movement of transla­ cording to Bacon—but attained at a true understanding of Aristotle’s
tions of scientific works from the Arabic since the beginning of the thought by following alternative and presumably more secure routes:
twelfth century cannot but be astonishing, especially on the part of
The lord Robert one time bishop of Lincoln of blessed memory [Gros­
one who made such uninhibited use of them. He nearly incorpo­ seteste died 1253] set entirely aside the writings of Aristotle and their
rated the work of Gerard of Cremona into the contemporary scene, methods, while through his own experience and different authors and
he decidedly confused Hermann of Carinthia (whose translation of different disciplines he managed aristotelian scientific principles. So that
Abu Ma'shar he freely used; all manuscripts of this version mention he knew and wrote about the contents of aristotelian writings hundred
Hermann as translator) with Hermann the German with whom Bacon thousand times better than can be grasped in vicious translations.29*
held direct conversations etc.26 No inkling about the importance of Now, as was amply noted before (Thorndike, Wingate), Bacon omits
translations done in the twelfth century, v.g. by Plato of Tivoli,27 any mention of Grosseteste translations of the Ethics of Aristotle for
John of Seville, Adelard of Bath, Robert of Chester and still others,
although Bacon does acknowledge the importance of Adelard’s atti­
28 “Sic translatae sunt et scientae communes, ut logica, naturalis philosophia,
tude to new science. He markedly contrasts the new rational science mathematica ut nullus mortalis possit aliquid dignum de eis intelligere veraciter,
of Adelard with the blindness of mere appeals to authority. sicut ego expertus su m om nino”. Compendium studii philosophiae, p. 468; “et quanto
2. Bacon’s strictures against the competence of his contemporaries plus laborant tanto minus sciunt sicu t ego probavi in om n ib u s qui libris
A ristotelis a d h a eseru n t. . . ” ibid.
Hermann the German and William of Moerbeke as translators are 29 “Unde dominus Robertus quondam episcopus Lincolniensis sanctae memoriae
neglexit omnes libros Aristotelis et vias eorum, et per experientiam propriam et
auctores alios et per alias scientias negotiatus est in sapientialibus Aristotelis; et melius
26 These patent shortcomings in Bacon’s information have been fully documented centies millesies scivit et scripsit ilia de quibus libri Aristotelis loquuntur quam in
by Thorndike and by Wingate as shown above; to whom we may refer without ado. ipsius perversis translationibus capi possunt”. Compendium . .. p. 469. See R.W. South­
27 Yet Baon’s laments about the scientific poverty of latin literature [Compendium ern, Robert Grosseteste: The Growth of an English Mind in Medieval Europe, 2nd ed.,
studii philosophiae, p. 465] clearly echoes similar complaints by the twelfth century (Oxford, 1992), 16 on this passage. “This passage has often been quoted, and as a
translators Plato of Tivoli [prologue to his translation of al-Battani] and Hermann factual statement it is absurd. Grosseteste did not neglect Aristotle; and he was not
of Carinthia [Astronomia, 4 prologues]. unduly bothered by the short-comings of the existing translations” etc.
40 RICHARD LEMAY LATIN TRANSLATIONS AND TRANSLATORS 41

instance, and of his many studies of aristotelian works.30 On the other Although the identity of “that one” singled out for abuse by Bacon
hand the works of Grosseteste in natural science quoted by Bacon has been hotly disputed there does not seem to have been anyone
(on the Rainbow, on Comets) depend entirely on translations from but Albertus Magnus to fit this description of one who is held as a
the Arabic, many of which were presumably included in the parisian “doctor” at Paris and who is quoted as an “auctor” in lectures and
prohibitions of 1210. Bacon feigns to ignore this aspect of Grosseteste’s disputations.33 Albertus Magnus is known as the only medieval scho­
scientific production which is otherwise full of astrological orientations, lastic who was held as an “auctor” during his lifetime, a circum­
all of them culled in translations from the Arabic. Thus Bacon’s claim stance unheard of till then according to Bacon and to the judgment
that Grosseteste neglected all translations of aristotelian writings must of posterity. We venture to suggest that it was precisely writing the
be taken with a grain of salt. In addition, the claim that Grosseteste Speculum astronomiae—undertaken at papal instigation and on the ground
reached at the heart of Aristotelian science by “following other ways” of his sound learning, as attested by Bonaventure de Iseo, which
could be justified exclusively on extensive use of translations from earned Albertus the title of an “auctor”, that is more than the one
the Arabic. Bacon is less than candid about his praise of Grosseteste’s who can “determine” a question in virtue of his title of magister at
method in respect to the existing translations. the University, but one whose opinion ranks with “authorities”, that
4. The opinion which R. Bacon entertains toward Albertus Magnus is ancient authors, especially Church Fathers and is therefore unques­
is a disparaging one, to say the least, if Albertus is the character tioned. This was indeed the role played, from the time of its appear­
aimed at in Bacon’s diatribe against eminent members of the reli­ ance till the end of the Middle Ages, by Albertus’ Speculum Astronomiae
gious Orders who he thinks are held in undeserved esteem. Hav­ as authoritative guide about the acceptability of books of natural
ing formulated severe strictures about the poor philosophical training science.34 The Speculum furthermore was known to contemporaries to
in his fellow Franciscan St Bonaventure,31 Bacon declares himself have been instrumental in finally lifting the ban of 1210 against the
scandalized at the reputation and authority they enjoy among their libri naturales.
supporters, in particular “that one who is still alive” and receives On this score we may ponder how much of a rivalry or envy lies
the title of doctor at Paris and who is quoted as an “author” at the in Bacon’s failure ever to mention the Speculum Astronomiae. Having
University: been requested by his friend Guy Foulques, who had become Pope
Clement IV in 1265, to explain his conception of scientific research
The crowd [vulgus] credit them with knowing everything and adhere
and methodology,35*Bacon must have seen in this opportunity a coun­
to them as if to angels. Indeed they are quoted as “auctores” in dispu­
tations and lectures. In the first place that one [Albertus] who is still terpoise to Albertus’ reputation and credit in the world of scholars.
living bears the title of doctor in Paris and is cited in the University as Henceforward Bacon imagined he could speak, perhaps with the credit
an “auctor”. This cannot occur without serious threat of confusion and
ruin of learning because his writings are replete with an infinite num­ 33 Cf. Jeremiah M.G. Hackett, “The Attitude of Roger Bacon to the Scientia od
ber o f errors and much shallowness [vanitatibus]. Such monstrosity Albertus Magnus” in James A. Weisheipl, O.P. ed. Albertus Magnus and die Sciences.
[abusio] never occurred before.32 Commemorative Essays. Toronto 1980, pp. 53-72. Whereas previous literature did review
the case but partially, Hackett goes over all Bacon’s utterances criticising the “unnamed
Master”, only to conclude that this unnamed Master is really Albertus Magnus,
30 Cf. Wingate, op. cit. p. 115. here however openly named.
31 Calling him a saint is irrelevant in our argument, but it is useful in order to 34 Hence the apposition of Philip the Chancelor’s name not as author but as
distinguish him from that other Franciscan fra Bonaventure de Iseo mentioned earlier owner of the unique copy that bears Philip’s name. A quite plausible condition
as familiar of Albertus Magnus. The alternative would be to call the former Bona­ which was unwisely seized upon by P. Mandonnet in his futile attempt to remove
venture de Bagnoreggio. authorship of the “scandalous book” from Albertus Magnus, despite the unchallenge­
32 “Vulgus credit quod omnia sciverunt et eis adhaeret sicut angelis. Nam illi able testimony of the medieval tradition where the authority of Albert and of no
allegantur in disputationibus et lectionibus sicut auctores. Et maxime ille qui one else is ever invoked for the judgments inserted in the Speculum.
vivit habet nomen doctoris Parisius et allegatur in studio sicut auctor. Quod non 35 “Unde ad im perium dom ini d e m e n tis praedecessoris istius Papae [Gregory X
potest fieri sine confusione et destructione sapientiae, quia ejus scripta plena sunt 1271-1276], collegi in tractatu speciali electas sententias Scripturae et Sanctorum
falsitatibus et vanitatibus infinitis. Nunquam talis abusio fuit in hoc mundo.” (Opus juris canonici et philosophiae, et praeposui omnibus libris quos misi”. (Comp. Stud.
Minus, ed. Brewer, p. 322). Phil. cap. Ill; Brewer p. 414).
42 RICHARD LEMAY LATIN TRANSLATIONS AND TRANSLATORS 43

of an “auctor”, surely with a renewed zeal in favor of his idiosyn­ science and of the primacy of astrology were easily amalgated with
cratic perception of experimental science and of aristotelian lore. Hence rampant averroism with which it will share the brutal shock of the
also Bacon’s unrelented trashing of existing trends in translations and parisian condemnations issued by bishop Etienne Tempier in 1277.
in aristotelian interpretation.
Bacon’s new ambition of rising to eminence in scholarly authority
was cut short by the death of his papal sponsor (1268), his rough 4. Translations Favored by Bacon
handling of contemporary leading scholars and unsparing criticism
of the role undertaken in aristotelian interpretation by the younger Respecting the existing Latin translations of Aristotle’s works Bacon’s
generation of scholars, especially among Mendicants, seems to have criticism is unsparing, for the most part exaggerated and unfair. As
antagonized the whole rostrum at the University and in the Orders. stated above it has no serious grounds generally and his tendency to
Hence the sharper tone of criticism levelled against them in the extend minor points to stand for the vast field of translations is clearly
Compendium studii philosophiae (1272) than in the Opus Maius addressed unacceptable. An apt example may be taken from Bacon’s comment
to Clement IV (1266). Adding to the antagonism, Bacon’s insistence on the presence of foreign or dialectical words or expressions intrud­
on his “experimental science” which was much more accurately ing in translated texts. Bacon illustrates his point concerning the term
perceived by Bacon’s contemporaries for what it was in reality: a “belenum” appearing in the translation of (ps.-) Aristotle’s De vegeta-
substitution of “iUuminism” in lieu of the preeminence of noetics (nous) bilibus38 from which a number of errors are supposed by him to have
of aristotelian epistemology. Bacon’s preference for “illuminism” is affected understanding of Aristotle. And Bacon concludes: “de qua
made quite clear in his definition and description of what he under­ causa est perversitas translationis, maxime in libris Anstotelis et scientiis
stands by experimental science. For according to him there are two ejus, quae sunt fundamentum totius sapientiae”.3839 From this relatively
kinds of “experientia”,36 one through external senses and it is by it minor, case Bacon soon passes on to a universal condemnation: “it
that we have access to all reality in the universe. By this kind of were better for the Latins if the science {sapientia) of Aristotle had not
“experientia” Bacon means the classical sense encountered in all Greek been translated instead of being transmitted with such obscurity and
philosophy. But there is another kind wich consits in “internal illu­ perversion”.40 Bacon finally crowns his stricture with this drastic propo­
minations” and it has been tested by Christian (fideles) as well as by sition: “If I had any power in the matter, I should order all books of
pagans all over.37 Bacon makes no bone about the source from which Aristotle to be burned because their use in study is mere waste of
he conceived this kind of experientia: it is in the extremely popular time, source of errors and spreading of ignorance beyond what could
and widespread Centihquium or Liber Fructus by Abu Ja'far Ahmad ibn be expressed”.41*Yet he had declared earlier that Aristotle’s science is
Yusuf [ps.-Ptolemy, and ps. Hali or Ali] in which knowledge from the fountain of all wisdom. How would Bacon then propose to fill
inspiration is placed far above knowledge obtained through reason, the gap?
and is much more powerful and keen in grasping the profound With naive ingenuity Bacon thought that any proper understand­
meaning of nature. O f course, the source of these inspirations is placed, ing of Aristotle’s science can only be acquired through use of the
according to the Centihquium in the intelligences of the heavenly bodies. original Greek texts: “Quicumque vult gloriari de scientia Anstotelis,
Hence the close, unavoidable connection with the averroistic thesis
of the unity of the intellect. Averroes’ De substantia orbis has no other
aim. In addition to all other motives of deception for Bacon after 38 Compendium studii philosophiae. Cap. viii. Brewer p. 467.
the disappearance of his papal patron in 1268, his conception of 39 Ibidem p. 468. Cf. p. 469: “Et quoniam labores Aristotelis sunt fundamenta
totius sapientiae, ideo nemo potest aestimare quantum dispendium accidit Latinis
quia malas translationes receperunt philosophi”.
40 Ibidem p. 469.
36 Opus Maius. VI, cap. I. 41 “Si enim haberem potestatem super libros Aristotelis ego facerem omnes cremari,
37 Ibid. For a critical discussion of this issue, see Jeremiah Hackett, “Roger Bacon quia non est nisi temporis amissio studere in illis, et causa erroris et multiplicatio
on Scientia experimentalis” in this volume. ignorantiae ultra id quod valeat explicari”. Ibid., p. 469.
44 RICHARD LEMAY LATIN TRANSLATIONS AND TRANSLATORS 45

oportet quod earn addiscat in lingua propria et nativa.”42 (p. 469). substituting for them the “astrologicized” Aristotle of the Arabs. The
This was clearly an impractical counsel, which he did not follow number of such works was legion and their bent quite similar. The
himself for sure, no more than his ideal scholar Grosseteste for that fullest and most accurate account of this variety of translations is
matter. On the contrary, both English scholars depended heavily on found in Albertus Magnus’ Speculum astronomiae.
Latin translations from the Arabic of works of science loudly claimed It may thus be appropriate to point out that R. Bacon never cites
by their authors to be interpreting Aristotle’s thought. And no won­ the Speculum Astronomiae. He would rely instead on the authority of
der, for both doctors in some fashion were continuators of the cen­ Isaac De febribus, or on Aristotle’s Secretum Secretorum, on the Ethics,
tury old English line of seekers after Arabic learning (Adelard of Bath, even on the Meteorologica for guidance as to how the scientist wishing
Robert of Chester, Daniel of Morley, Roger of Hereford, Alfred of to remain within bounds of reasonableness will choose between good
Sareshel etc.), a tradition which came to be centered at Oxford some and bad books of “natural science”. The criterion may seem nearly
time before Bacon’s birth, and could further progress unhindered by identical with the one suggested by Albertus in the Speculum, namely
the condemnations issued in 1210 by the “provincial council” at Paris. that the presence of invocation of demons, of incantations or “carmina”
Hence it remains an unfulfilled task of modem scholarship to ascer­ and other kind of recourses to “evil” spirits should beckon the sincere
tain the degree to which Grosseteste’s scientific production is depending Christian to shun such books. Bacon trusts the reader to rely on his
on Arabic sources directly. For some of Grosseteste’s characteristic sense of piety to be the sole judge.43 The criterion is much less strict
themes of natural science are directly modeled on Arabic sources: or precise, however, than in the Speculum Astronomiae.
his work on Comets is a mere expansion of the appendix added to While maintaining that the originals, either greek or Arabic, are
Verba 99 and 100 of Ahmad ibn Yusuf (ps.-Ptolemy, ps.-Haly) Centih- much better than what the Latin translators offered, Bacon never
quium. His theory of the tides is in direct dependance of the treat­ produced credible example of what he would deem a good transla­
ment of the topic by Abu Ma'shar in his Introductorium Maius, Tract tion. Conversely, the stress he lays on the superiority of the spurious
III. Finally Grosseteste’s “metaphysic of light”, though based on Genesis Aristotle is nowhere supported by a valid demonstration. Compounding
and the Hexaemeron literature as it has seemed to some, is in fact an his arrant ignorance—or was it deliberate oversight?—, Bacon laments
expansion of the central notion of Arab astrology that heavenly bodies, the fact that the Latins are far from possessing all of Aristotelian
being of a fifth essence, therefore immaterial in a way, produced science. He illustrates his point by citing a work of Aristotle of alleg­
their efficiency through light and motion exclusively. Hence the essence edly major importance entitled De impressionibus calestibus which the
of being (as bestowed by the stars) could be described as light and Latins did not yet possess, urging the pontiff (Clement IV) to provide
therefore constitute the core of the study of metaphysics, i.e. of the for its translation.44 As it happens, this is the standard title given by
nature of being, a concept which fitted admirably the “ishriqiyya” Arab translators to Aristotle’s Meteorologka, a Latin translation of Book
(oriental) philosophy of Avicenna, quite accessible to Grosseteste. IV of which already existed since approximately the middle of the
Concerning Roger Bacon’s choice of translations that would pre­ twelfth century in a translation from the Greek by Henricus Aristippus,
sumably provide more direct access to aristotelian science, the case and of the first three books in translation from the Arabic by Gerard
is an open and shut one. Bearing directly on his conception of experi­
mental science, they are his favorite Arab authors, especially in astro­ 43 “Considerandum est tamen quia multi libri reputantur inter magicos qui non
logy such as the Secret of Secrets of (ps.-) Aristotle to Alexander, or the sunt tales, sed continent sapientiae dignitatem. Qui igitur sunt suspecti et qui non,
ps.-Ptolemaic Centiloquium, or the spurious Ovid De Vetula (of Richard experientia cujuslibet sap ien tis docebit. Nam si quis in aliquo illorum opus
naturae vel artis inveniat, illud accipiat; si non, relinquat velut suspectum, et sicut
of Fournival) and its inspiration the Introductorium Maius in astronomiam indignum est sapienti et illicitum magica pertractare, sic superfluum est nec est
of Abu M acshar. So that Bacon’s unrelenting assault on the current necessarium”. Epistola de Secretis operibus Artis et Naturae. Ed. J.S. Brewer. Opera hactenus
translations of aristotelian writings would seem aimed principally at inedita 1859, vol. I, p. 531.
44 “Aristoteles certificavit hoc in libro suo De impressionibus c<elestibus qui liber est melior
tota philosophia Latinorum et potest per vestram iussionem transferri”. Opus Maius.
42 Ibid., p. 469. Ed. Jebb, p. 246, as quoted by A. Jourdain, Recherches, p. 387.
46 RICHARD LEMAY LATIN TRANSLATIONS AND TRANSLATORS 47

of Cremona.45 Bacon must have culled his title from some Arabic by S.D. Wingate in her frequently quoted book. What seems to be
work in Latin translation, probably the Centiloquium of Abu Ja'far missing in her kind of approach is the failure to take into account
Ahmad ibn Yusuf which had been translated five times during the the predominantly astrological and “deterministic” character of aris­
twelfth century and which contained under this label an explicit totelian science as received in the first waves of translation from the
reference to the Meteorologica of Aristode.46 Obviously Bacon failed Arabic, and the guarded attitude of ecclesiastical authorities toward
to realize this was the same as the Meteorologica of which the Latins its full acceptance, beginning of course with the fateful condemna­
already possessed a fairly reliable translation, while his suggestion to tions and prohibitions of 1210 and 1215. Oxford (and perhaps
Clement IV to provide for its translation verges on crude philistinism. Toulouse at the time of its foundation in 1229) could freely indulge
For Bacon was wont to use both the Meteorologica and the Centiloquium, their attachment to the new science from the Arabic and strive to
the latter offering the primary inspiration for his singular notion of integrate it with the science lore surviving in late Roman compila­
experimental science. tions like those of Macrobius, Capella, Chalcidius and Boethius, not
The strictures Bacon placed upon the kind of aristotelian interpre­ to mention Seneca, Pliny and Bede, traditional authorities in science
tation favored by the younger generation of friar-scholars may very which to some extent did maintain their credit beside the new Arab
well have been meant as a retort to the suspicion of “heresy” felt by sources. When by the middle of the thirteenth century the publica­
“orthodox” philosophers, including Albertus Magnus and Thomas tion of Albertus Magnus’ Speculum Astronomiae rendered inoperative
Aquinas, toward the “arabic” orientation of aristotelianism rooted at the prohibitions and sanctions of 1210, it opened the gates to unbridled
Oxford since the late twelfth century and now carried to Paris in the speculation about Aristotle’s natural science, mostly of the fatalistic
midst of the averroistic flourishing. Bacon may be seen as upholding kind fostered by astrological principles. As Avicenna’s and Averroes’
in his own way the arabic orientation which long prospered at Oxford, influence grew in importance, their own version of aristotelian science
while its parallel in Paris47 was being stifled. Aversion toward recep­ sent down to a lower level that of Abu Ma'shar and of the major
tion of “arab” science is rampant throughout the thirteenth century Arabian astrologers like Alchabitius and Haly al-Imrani (author of the
at Paris. A similar warning was sounded in 1270 in the condemna­ book on Elections, not the false Haly commentator of the Centiloquium)
tion of certain propositions, but the main crisis erupted in 1277 with viewed till then as authoritative carriers of aristotelian metaphysics
bishop Etienne Tempier damning as either heretical or nearly hereti­ and natural philosophy. Roger Bacon for his part remained attached
cal some 219 propositions, the bulk of which aimed at aristotelian to the older, “oxfordian”, unchecked strain of arabian aristotelianism
metaphysics and natural philosophy interpreted along astrological filtered through astrology. Hence his diatribes against the “new” devel­
(averroistic) lines. opments in aristotelianism after the crisis of 1229—1231 at Paris and
Some strains of this underlying current can be detected in Bacon’s his relentless disparaging afterwards of the translations on which they
utterances decrying the translations of aristotelian works available in were nourished. This is indeed a marked characteristic of the Roger
his time. The problem has been honorably but not definitively explored Bacon of the 1260’s. He attempts to defend the role of Abu Ma'shar,
Pseudo-Ptolemaic and other “experimental” books, when the younger
generation of University teachers were providing new and controver­
45 From which Bacon himself quotes frequently.
46 Under various latin titles such as liber de operibus altis in the “iam scripsi” ver­ sial interpretations of the Aristotle’s texts, and when the younger
sion, liber de hiis que superius accidunt in the “mundanorum”, liber de superioribus signis in theologians like Bonaventure among the Franciscans were highly criti­
Hugh of Sanctalla’s version. Only the “abugafarus” translation clearly identifies the cal of the deterministic tendencies in the astrology and alchemy in
work as liber metheororum, which could be an indication that the translator or “revi­
sor” involved in this manuscript tradition might be Gerard of Cremona. The usual the new translations of scientific works.
arabic title is fdtab al-athar al-culwiyya, the exact translation in Latin being precisely
liber de impressionibus altis.
47 Early traces of this trend at Paris can be gleaned in the works of Alanus de
Insulis, in his commentator Raoul de Longchamp and perhaps others. Henri d’Andeli’s
poem, ca. 1230 seems to echo the drawback at Paris.
3. ROGER BACON ON THE
CLASSIFICATION OF THE SCIENCES

Jeremiah Hackett

I. Bacon and the Reform of Studies

The later works of Bacon, especially those written after 1266, are
not for the most part systematic and disinterested treatises. They are,
rather, a mixed collection of small tracts on a diversity of topics.
These tracts are linked together in the service of a polemic about the
education of university students in Paris in the mid-thirteenth century.
The reform of education and society is a theme which was close
to the interests of Bacon in his later years, that is, from about 1266
to 1292. His criticism of the scientia of Albertus Magnus, his stric­
tures against Alexander of Hales and Richard of Cornwall, and his
general condemnation of the young friars of his times, were all part
of his belief that studies in the arts, medicine and theology had
degenerated in the course of his life-time.
Bacon saw himself as a spokesman for an older form of study,
namely, the kind of secular and sacred study which had been fos­
tered by Robert Grosseteste, Bishop of Lincoln (ca. 1168-1253), who
had been the first lecturer to the Franciscans at Oxford from 1229-
1235. Bacon also praised scholars who had some association with
Oxford and Lincoln such as Adam Marsh, Robert Marsh, William
Lupus, William of Shyrewode, and Thomas of Wales. His praise of
these scholars is repeated many times in contrast to his condemna­
tion of the vulgus studentium.
The criticism of individual aspects of studies by Bacon is informed
by a vision on his part of the ultimate purpose of education. In the
manner of Robert Grosseteste, Adam Marsh and the English Fran-
ciscian tradition, Bacon saw a practical unity and purpose in educa­
tion. The pursuit of a moral and religious fife gave a finality to the
many diverse forms of study in the arts. John H. Mundy, among
others, has drawn attention to the presence in Bacon of “a utopian
vision of the world and man’s relation to his neighbour.” He char­
acterized this vision as follows:
50 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON THE CLASSIFICATION OF THE SCIENCES 51

. . . the Christian idea of progress never lost its appeal. It flourished in review of moral philosophy as the goal of the other areas of study.
a final burst o f glory at the end of the thirteenth century, when, in the
There is much repetition of material in the above mentioned works.
work o f Roger Bacon and others, this historical vision was combined
with the natural history and moral sociology of the Aristotelians. In Bacon continued to repeat and also to make additions in all of his
Roger, mechanical inventions like flying machines and optical devices, later writings.
astral and geographical influences, the correct ordering of law and The deficient state of studies was, in his view, reflected in the
society, the abolition of sexual and moral irregularity, and the reform corruption of society. Bacon listed the vacancy in the papacy (1268—
o f education, were all necessary to defeat the Tartars, the Sacracens,
1271), the conflict among the religious orders, the success of the
and the soon-to-appear antichrist.1
lawyers in drawing students away from the arts, and the conflict
In his account of Bacon’s idea of reform, Mundy gives a composite between the religious and secular clerics at the University of Paris.4
quotation from the Opus maius of Roger Bacon which expresses in He traced the corruption of studies to a practice which had been
clear terms the essentially practical purpose of Bacon’s attitude to common since about 1230 in which young theologians went out to
education.2 preach and teach without the benefit of a full liberal arts training.5
The structure of Bacon’s works about 1266-1272 reflects both this In the Opus minus,6 Bacon placed the blame for the decline of
central vision of a reformed life and the particular changes that he studies on the shoulders of Alexander of Hales and Albertus Magnus.
thought were necessary in studies. From the introductory letter to In this same work, he gave an outline of the decline of studies in
the works for the pope,3 it is evident that the organization of the terms of six major sins (errors).7
Opus maius, Opus minus, and the Opus tertium, follows a distinct pattern. The first error (sin) in theology, for Bacon, concerns the place of
Moreover, this pattern is repeated in the Compendium studii philoso- philosophy. He claimed that the method of philosophy in the phihsophia
phiae and in the Compendium studii theologiae. The pattern consists of communis of his time had come to dominate the study of theology,
(i) a critique of the errors in studies, (ii) a study of the relation of especially through the book of the Sentences. For Bacon, the error
philosophy to theology, (iii) a review of the deficiencies in language consisted in replacing Sacred Scripture with the book of Sentences as
study, (iv) a study of the role of mathematics, especially geometry, the primary text for lecturers. It was Bacon’s belief that such a philo­
and astrology in learning, (v) a review of the place of perspectiva in sophical treatment of the fundamental truths of theology led to a
studies, (vi) the relation of experimental science to theology, (vii) a neglect of Sacred Scripture.8
The second error in theology consists in the lack of the sciences.
The “greater sciences” in Bacon’s view were ignored by the theolo­
1 John H, Mundy, Europe in the High Middle Ages 1150-1309, New York, 1973
p. 492. gians. By these, Bacon meant perspective, astronomy, the science of
2 Ibid., p. 493: “I do not wish ‘to set my mouth against the heavens’, but I know weights, medicine, experimental science, alchemy and agriculture.
that if the Church would study Holy Scripture and sacred prophecy and the foretellings These sciences deal with the practical good of the body, the soul,
of the Sibly, of Merlin, of Aquila, of Joachim and many others, and also of the
histories and books of the philosophers, and would order the ways of astronomy to and fortune.9
be studies, a sufficient suspicion or even certitude of the time of the antichrist will The third error has to do with ignorance of the philosophia communis
be discovered.. .. And it is believed by all the wise that we are not far from the on the part of young theologians. In Bacon’s view, many of the young
times of the antichrist. . .. And because individuals, cities and whole regions can be
changed for the better according to the aforesaid, life should be prolonged as long friars did not have an adequate training in the arts. He believed that
as necessary, all things should be managed functionally, and even greater things can
be done than are mentioned in this book not only in the natural sciences, but
also in the moral sciences and arts, as is evident in Moses and Aristotle.” (Taken
from the Opus maius, pars quarta, ed. Bridges, Vol. 1, pp. 269, 402.) For a study 4 Compendium studii philosophise, ed. Brewer, pp. 399, 418-425.
which treats the idea of reform in Adam Marsh and Roger Bacon but which relates 5 Ibid., pp. 425-429.
it to the apocalyptic-millenial expectations, see Davide Bigali, I Tartari E “Apocalisse, 6 Opus minus, ed. Brewer, pp. 322-350.
Richerche sull’escatologia in Adamo Marsh e Ruggero Bacone” (La Nuova Italia Editrice) 7 Ibid., pp. 326-327.
Firenze, 1971.
8 Opus minus, ed. Brewer, p. 322.
3 F.A. Gasquet, “An Unpublished Fragment”, pp. 507-517. 9 Ibid., p. 323.
52 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON THE CLASSIFICATION OF THE SCIENCES 53

their teachers such as Alexander of Hales and Albertus Magnus learned Bacon’s program of studies in the Opus minus and in his other
the philosophy of Aristotle in the course of their preaching life.10 works postdating 1266 is one in which secular learning is seen to be
Bacon blamed Alexander of Hales for introducing the book of the essentially of service towards the interpretation of Sacred Scripture.15
Sentences into lectures in place of the Bible and the Histories. He objected For him, philosophy is not seen as a totally self-sufficient pursuit.
to Albertus Magnus because he was self-taught in common philoso­ Rather, it finds its goal in the service that it renders in being an
phy, was lacking in his knowledge of the “special sciences” and did ancilla for the study of theology. The account of the sciences and
not have an adequate knowledge of ancient languages, especially of philosophy in Bacon’s later works is largely a polemic for the uses of
Greek and Hebrew. They did not have the kind of arts training that the liberal arts in the reading of Sacred Scripture.
Bacon thought to be a requirement of any valid theology.
Further, Bacon claimed that young scholars of his time knew the
works of Aristotle only on the basis of translations, which, in his II. Bacon and die Traditional Classification of the Sciences
view, were very inadequate.11
The fourth error in theology is due to the fact that the book of In the three works for the pope, Bacon does not spell out any new
the Sentences had replaced the book of the Histories as an aid in the curriculum of studies for the universities though he did criticize the
study of Sacred Scripture.12 That is, the familiar Historia scholastica of existing one. He merely identified some problems on studies, and
Peter Comestor, which narrated biblical stories simply, was replaced proposes certain remedies. In the Communia naturalium, however, which
by terse allusions to incidents that happened to be maintained by was probably written later in the 1260’s, Bacon gives an exposition
Peter Lombard. of “the greater sciences”. He also notes in the Opus minus16 that the
The fifth error has to do with the terrible state of the Vulgate study of foreign languages and moral science, together with mathe­
version of the Bible. Bacon said that “The text of Scripture is for the matics, experimental science and alchemy, are more conductive to
most part horribly corrupt in the Vulgate exemplar, that is, the Paris the advancement of the mind, the body and society than are some
exemplar.”13 In his view, this text ought to have been corrected in other sciences. By these latter, Bacon meant the study of Latin gram­
the light of the most ancient copies of the biblical text, and with the mar, logic, the more insignificant part of natural philosophy and a
aid of a knowledge of Greek and Hebrew. part of metaphysics.
The sixth error is related to the fifth. Bacon believed that the Yet, Bacon was not the first teacher in the thirteenth century to
young theologians were not able to understand the literal meaning propose a study of the sciences. He, like other thirteenth century
of Scripture, and as a result, they were not able to understand the scholars, had inherited a tradition of the classification of the sciences
spiritual meaning. This, according to him, was due to an ignorance that mapped out the vast range and ordering of human knowledge.
of Greek and Hebrew on the part of both teachers and students. To appreciate Bacon’s emphasis on the seven special sciences, namely
These teachers and students also lacked a knowledge of Latin and “the greater sciences,” a short review of this traditional classification
the auxiliary sciences such as natural history, astronomy, medicine is required.
and alchemy, which were necessary for a critical reading of the Bible. Medieval scholars had inherited the Boethian division of the sci­
These sciences were essential aids for the theologian in the interpre­ ences in terms of speculative and practical spheres.17 Speculative
tation of the sacred text.14
15 Ibid., pp. 322-323; see estpeciaUy F.A. Gasquet, “An Unpublished Fragment”,
10 Opus minus, ed. Brewer, p. 326. This is in reference to Alexander of Hales; See p. 509: “Nam sum certus quod solum illud de philosophia est utile et dignum quod
Compendium studii phibsophia, ed. Brewer, pp. 425-429 for an expanded view. sapientia sacra dignatur, sicut ab ancilla, requirere: totum enim residuum stultum
11 Ibid., p. 325. See also the following: Compendium studii philosophise, ed. Brewer, est et insanum.”
pp. 468-473 and Compendium studii theobgiae, ed. Rashdall, p. 34. Bacon presents this same position in the Opus maius. See Opus maius, ed. Bridges,
12 Opus minus, ed. Brewer, pp. 328-330. III, pp. 36-79.
13 Ibid., p. 330. 16 Opus Minus, ed. Brewer, pp. 323-4.
14 Opus minus, ed. Brewer, pp. 349-350. 17 Boethius, The Theobgical Tractactes, (Loeb Library), Cambridge, 1973, De trinitate,
54 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON THE CLASSIFICATION OF THE SCIENCES 55

philosophy was divided into physics, mathematics and theology. Prac­ Robert Grosseteste, the first known Latin commentator on the Pos­
tical philosophy was concerned with the ethics of the individual, family terior Analytics,20 this work gave scholars a scientific method which could
and society. be applied to a knowledge of experience in order to attain causes
Other divisions of the sciences, such as those of Gassiodorus (ca. and scientific explanations. The influence of the Posterior Analytics on
485—580) and Isidore of Seville (ca. 570—636) were also in use in the Bacon’s notion of scientific method and on his notion of experimen­
early Middle Ages. In the case of Isidore,18 one finds that his division tal science, can be seen from his own texts.21
of the liberal arts is placed alongside the traditional Stoic division of The gradual reception of the works of Anstode on natural phi­
philosophy into logic, physics, and ethics, as well as the “Boethian” losophy into the curriculum of the universities in the thirteenth cen­
division. tury did not, however, make a radical change in the division of the
In the twelfth century a new classification of the sciences emerged. sciences which had existed since the twelfth century. James Weisheipl
James Weisheipl describes this synthesis of the two traditional divi­ describes the process of incorporation as one in which “the new
sions of philosophy as “a successful combination of the Boethian and Aristotelian learning was simply tacked onto the liberal arts.”22*
Stoic divisions of ‘science’”.19
The introduction of the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle into the Latin
West brought a new influence to bear on scientific method in the Theology—deals with forms truly separated from matter
Theoretical Arithmetic — deals with forms of bodies
early thirteenth century. As can be seen from the commentary of or Music conceived apart from
Mathematics —
Speculative Geometry matter
(= naturalis) Astronomy
Physics- deals with forms in matter and motion
pp. 8-10, The following diagram of Boethius’s division is taken from James A.
Weisheipl, “The Nature, Scope and Classification of the Sciences”, in David C. Practical Ethics of the individual
Iindberg, ed., Science in the Middle Ages, Chicago, 1978, p. 471: or active Ethics of the family (economics)
(= moralis) Ethics of the state (politics)
Physics—material bodies in motion both Fabric-making
In reality and in mental definition. Arm am ent-m aking
Mathematics— changing material bodies, Mechanical Commerce
considered apart from their or Agriculture
matter and motion; “Adultrine Hunting
Speculative Subdivided into arithmetic, arts” Medicine
Geometry, music and Theatrics
astronomy.
Philosophy — Theology—changeless, immaterial things Logic Grammar
both in reality and in mental (= sermocinalis) Dialectics (logic)
consideration. Rhetoric
Practical Ethics of the individual (monastics)
Ethics of the family (domestics) 20 Pietro Rossi, Robertas Grosseteste— Commentarius in Posteriorum Analyticorum Ubros,
Ethics of society (politics) crit. ed., Florence, 1981. Grosseteste wrote his commentary on the version by James
of Venice around 1228-1230. It was apparently written as the commentaries of
18 Ibid., p. 472. Averroes became available in Latin about 1225—30. The importance of this work
19 Ibid., pp. 473-4: “In the twelfth century a more thorough synthesis of the two can be seen from the large number of extant manuscripts and printed editions. See
ancient classifications was presented in the various Didascalia, or general introduc­ A.C. Crombie, Robert Grosseteste and the Origins of Experimental Science, 1100—1700, Oxford,
tions to the artes. These summary treatises follow the general pattern of the tradi­ 1953 Ch. 3, pp. 44—60 for an account of this method.
tional Disciplinarum libri, discussing the nature and classification of learning, and briefly 21 Ibid., p. 140 for a fist of Bacon texts in which there is a marked influence of
explaining the nature of each art. The best known of these is the Didascalicon of Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics.
Hugh of St Victor (1096-1141). In this remarkable treatise seven mechanical arts 22 James A. Weispheipl, “The Nature, Scope and Classification of the Sciences”,
are introduced as parts of ‘philosophy’ in order to balance the seven liberal arts; all p. 476: “When the books of the new Aristotelian learning were incorporated into
seven liberal arts, including grammar, find a place in this classification.” The schema the medieval universities, it was simply a matter of adding physics, ethics and first
which on the next page, which represents this combination, is taken from Weisheipl, philosophy (metaphysics) to an existing structure of the seven liberal arts. There was
ibid., p. 474. not need for a new mathematics, for Euclid, Ptolemy, and Boethius were already
56 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON THE CLASSIFICATION OF THE SCIENCES 57

Between the years 1170 and 1270 a variety of works on the classifi­ The beginning of his work, the Communia naturalium,24 is of interest in
cation of the sciences were translated into Latin. Among the more this respect. It presents us with a list of sciences which Bacon held
important works were De scientiis and De ortu scientiarum of al-Farabi, to be an essential part of philosophy, and some of which were not
translated from the Arabic by Dominic Gundissalinus. Dominic Gun- included in earlier divisions of science, including that of Bacon’s near
dissalinus also composed a work of his own on the division of the contemporary, Robert Kilwardby. It also presents us with Bacon’s
sciences, entitled De dwisione philosophiae. Perhaps, the most ambitious criticism of the natural philosophy of Aristotle.
and methodic consideration of the classification of the sciences in the In the Communia naturalium,25 Bacon gives his account of the order
thirteenth century was the widely known work De ortu scientiarum by and classification of the sciences under the following headings: (a) de
Robert Kilwardby. As will be seen from the following chart by James ordine scientiae naturalis ad differentiae \sic\ (on the order of the natural
Weisheipl, Kilwardby’s schema was “more sophisticated, rich, and sciences in regard to the differences of the sciences), (b) de numero et
thorough than any of the twelfth century divisions of the sciences.”23 ordine scientiarum naturalium (on the number and order of the natural
The introduction of the new Aristotelian learning is reflected in sciences), (c) de modo procedendi in tractando de naturalibus (on the method
Bacon’s own concern for the order and classification of the sciences. of proceeding in dealing with the natural sciences).
In the first paragraph of the Communia naturalium, Bacon remarks
that he had treated grammar and logic in an earlier volume, and the
taught as parts of the quadrivium; similarly, logic, grammar, and rhetoric were al­ parts of mathematics in a second. In this third volume, he remarks
ready in the universities as the trivium. The new Aristotelian learning was simply
tacked onto the liberal arts program as ‘the three philosophies’: natural philosophy, that he is presenting the study of natural philosophy, and in a fourth
moral philosophy, and first philosophy (metaphysics). With the addition of these volume, he proposed to join together the exposition of metaphysics
new ‘sciences’ the faculty of arts became known as the faculty of arts and sciences.”
23 Ibid., p. 480:
and moral philosophy.26
Bacon, then, begins with a brief account of the division of learn­
Old Testament ing in his own works. This is best seen in the following schema:
Divine
New Testament
I. First in the order of exposition is grammar in regard to Latin and
(physics) foreign languages, together with logic. II. Mathematics, which is
Natural Science divided into common and special. III. Natural philosophy, which
Divine Geometry
Things Astronomy is divided into common (the exposition of Aristotle) and special (the
(= specu­ Mathematics Perspective outline of the seven sciences). IV. metaphysics. V. moral philosophy.
lative) Music Bacon sees moral philosophy as the end of all the other sciences. It
Arithmetic
supplies the practical good and the goal towards which the other
Philosophy — Metaphysics, first philosophy “speculative” sciences are to be directed.27 One will note from this
Monastics text too that Bacon sees astrology as a science which establishes the
Ethics Domestics
Politics unity of the first cause and the multiplicity of the intelligences.
Operative _ The brief account of the subject matter28 of the natural sciences in
(= practical) Farming
Cooking
Human — Human Mechanical Medicine
Things Tailoring 24 Communia naturalium, I, ed. Steele, pp. 1-14.
Armament­ 25 Ibid., pp. 1-2.
making 26 Ibid., p. 1. This was to be his four-fold division of all of philosophy: Grammar
Building and Logic; Mathematics; Natural Philosophy; Moral Philosophy.
Verbal Grammar 27 Communia naturalium, I, ed. Steele, pp. 1-2: “Postquam tradidi Grammaticam
(= Sermoci- Logic secundum linguas diversas prout valent immo eciam necessarie sunt studio Latinorum,
nalis) Rhetoric et Logicalia cum hiis expedivi; atque in secundo volumine tractavi.. . .”
Magic—to be avoided. 28 Ibid., 2.
58 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON THE CLASSIFICATION OF THE SCIENCES 59

the Communia naturalium begins with the statement that the natural adds that it is “almost the same everywhere in all other books on
sciences (naturalia) deal with those things in which there is a principle natural things.”32
of motion and rest (principium motus et quietis), such as minerals, plants, From his introduction to Communia naturalium, it is evident that Bacon
and animals. In these, one finds the principle of motion and rest levels two charges against Aristotle: the first charge is that Aristotle
existing naturally (naturaliter). Bacon then lists the kinds of change did not pay sufficient attention to the details of the particular sci­
that occur in the natural world, namely local motion, generation, ences, and the second is that even in his account of what is common
alteration, augmentation and diminution. The heavens however, to all the natural sciences, he was deficient. For Bacon, it was the
although they do have a principle of motion in themselves, do not task of metaphysics to set out the origin, division and order of all the
have a principle of rest like other natural things. Thus, it is not sciences so as to display the limits of each science. In the Communia
appropriate to refer to them as natural things (inaturalia) in the strict­ naturalium, and also in the Communia mathematica, Bacon singled out
est sense of the word. But they can be called natural on account of seven special sciences which he regarded as superior to the traditional
the motion and rest that they cause in the elements. They move sciences taught in the schools. They are fisted as perspective, astronomy
inferior natural things voluntarily and not by necessity. (judicial and operative), the science of weights, alchemy, agriculture,
In the second chapter, Bacon discusses the number and order of medicine, and experimental science.33 Bacon does not go into any
the natural sciences {De numero et ordine scienciarum naturalium). He tells detail in his presentation here. He merely fists the names and then
us that in his Metaphysics, he demonstrated that need for a science gives a brief description of each science.
which considers the common aspects of the natural things, that it, a Among “the seven special sciences”, Bacon first mentions perspec­
scientia which is de communibus naturalium.29 He argues that just as tive. He regarded this science as the means by which one can under­
Aristode composed a work on the common elements of natural things stand the structure of the universe.34 Bacon devoted the whole of
in the Physica, so it is necessary to do the same for other areas of part five of the Opus maius to perspective. This treatment covers the
study. He had written, he says, a Communia mathematica before he general area of vision, structure of the eye, and the nature of colour.
presented the special parts of that study.30 The central role of perspective in Roger Bacon’s conception of hu­
At this stage in his exposition, Bacon begins his criticism of man knowledge has been recognized by modern scholars of optics.
Aristode’s natural philosophy. His first criticism charges that even in In his study of Theories of Visionfrom Al-Kindi to Kepler, David C. Iindberg
special tracts such as De caelo et mundo, Aristode does not give a de­ assessed various influences on Bacon, gave an account of Bacon’s
tailed account of the phenomena of the heavens. In Bacon’s view, he originality, and examined the metaphysical basis of fight in Bacon’s
merely gives “common conclusions” (conclusiones communes). By this, work.35 He acknowledged in passing that the insight of Fisher and
Bacon means that Aristode teaches nothing in particular about the Unguru regarding Bacon’s purposes in writing about perspective is
substantial natures of the heavens, the stars, their influence on the “precisely the right emphasis.”36 They point out that all of Bacon’s
inferior bodies, the nature of fight in these planets, the obscurity of works are directed towards presenting a unity of knowledge that is
the eclipse, or the movement of certain planets.31 Neither, in his view, teachable in systematic form. And Bacon’s purpose in writing a tract
does Aristotle teach about the number of planets, the contiguity on perspective was to set forth the traditional teaching on perspective,
of the orbs or their number or about the altitude of the heavens or
the stars. Nor does Aristotle give an account of the habitable parts 32 Ed. cit., 4.
of the earth in terms of magnitude, figure and place, the complex­ 33 Ed. cit., 5: Declaravi igitur in ilia parte Mathematice quod preter scienciam
ions of natures of the elements, or their qualities and powers. Bacon communem naturalibus sunt septem speciales: videlicet, Perspectiva, Astronomia
(judicaria et operativa), scientia ponderum de gravibus et levibus, Alkimia, Agncultura,
Medicina, Scientia experimentalis.
34 Opus tertium, ed. Brewer, 37.
29 Communia naturalium, I, ed. cit., 3. 35 David C. Iindberg, Theories of Vision from Alkindi to Kepler, Chicago & London,
30 Ibid., 3. 1976, 107-116.
31 Ed. cit., 4. 36 Ibid., 112.
60 JEREMIAH HAGKETT ROGER BACON ON THE CLASSIFICATION OF THE SCIENCES 61

especially that of Alhazen (Ibn al-Haytham) in a teachable form. number of tracts on this subject and to have included treatments of
The second science mentioned by Bacon, astronomy, is divided it in the three works for the pope. In the Opus tertium (ed. Little), one
into three parts in the Communia naturalium,37 Parts one and two are finds mention of a tract entitled De enigmatibus alkimiae, and in the
concerned with the quantity of the heavenly bodies. Part three is Opus maius and Opus minus, one finds polemics in favour of alchemy.
known today as astrology. The first part deals with the mathematical But he seems not to have written a detailed exposition of this science,
principles involved in giving a theoretical account of celestial motions, at least none that we know of now. According to Bacon, the vulgus,
such as is given by Ptolemy in his Almagest. This is sometimes called using the authority of Aristotle at the end of the Metheora, claim that
“speculative astronomy”. Bacon calls the second part “practical astro­ alchemy is impossible. Bacon, using the authority of pseudo-Aristotle’s
nomy”, and says that it involves the uses of canons, astronomical Secretum secretorum, argues that Aristotle himself had a positive teach­
tables and instruments. The third part of astronomy is concerned with ing on alchemy.40
the natural powers of the heavenly bodies, and with their influence Agriculture, the fourth special science, is generally discussed by
on inferior bodies. Bacon in his works on medicine. In doing this, he points to the effi­
Bacon, however, does not name any authors he has in mind on cacy of certain plants and herbs. He does not, however mention a
astrology; he simply notes that Averroes in his commentary on De separate work on agriculture.
caelo et mundo says that Aristotle handed on this part of astronomy Bacon’s treatment of medicine, the sixth special science, is very
in his scientia de impressionibus.38 Bacon refers to various parts of astro­ extensive. Apart from the collection of tracts on a variety of medical
nomy in numerous texts: and he devotes to it the whole of part four topics, edited by Little and Withington,41*other references to medical
in his Opus maius. matters abound throughout Bacon’s works. He was of the opinion
Bacon mentions the science of weights as the third in his list of that teachers of medicine in the schools (ca. 1266) neglected math­
seven special sciences, and in his prefatory letter39 to the Opus maius ematics and experiment in their teaching and study of medicine. From
he notes that the scientia de ponderibus was treated by him in the later this work too, it is clear that Bacon envisaged an essential connec­
work in the section on mathematics. But we not have this section in tion between medicine and scientia experimentalis, the last and most
the modern editions. important special science.
Alchemy was regarded by Bacon as an important science which In Opus maius, part six, Bacon summarized his doctrine of experi­
was not studied at all in the schools. He seems to have written a mental science. This science which he does not describe in detail in
the Communia naturalium, is seen as a kind of practical Logic by means
of which one can distinguish true science from the frauds of magic.
37 Communia naturalium, I, ed. cit., 6: Nam ut prius in Mathematicis habitum est,
Astronomia est triplex. Due sunt de quantitate celestium et parcium habitabilis This science has three main prerogatives of functions. They are:
(habitilium!) una speculative ut in Almagesti tradita, alia practica, ut in Canonibus et a) the ability to verify experientially the conclusions of the other sci­
Tabulis et Instruments, que due non descendunt ad naturales virtutes celorum et ences which are based on argument or authority; b) the discovery by
stellarum, nec ad alteraciones inferiorum naturalium, neque ad judicia, neque op­
era, quia horum consideracio pertinet ad philosophiam naturalem. Et ideo est tertia experience of truths in the other sciences which are hidden from
Astronomia, que hec naturalia in celestibus et inferioribus investigat, quam tradidit those sciences themselves; c) the prognostication of future events and
Aristoteles in Scientia de impressionibus, sicut docet Averoys secundo Celi et Mundi the discovery of the secrets of nature. (Bacon regarded the third
et Liber novem judicum, et alii hoc cercius attestantur. Hec autem Astronomia traditur
perfecte in libro Plurimum judicum, et in multis aliis libris de hac sciencia,. . . See also function as scientia experimentalis secundum se et absolute. It alone was
Communia mathematica, 49-50. experimental science absolutely speaking. The first two functions had
38 See Opus maius, part four, ed. Bridges, I, 389-90 on this work. See Thorndike,
A History o f Magic and. Experimental Science, II, 248, 256; Sarton, op. cit., 577-78. See
to do with the use and application of experimental science in the
Lemay above. other sciences.)
39 F.A. Gasquet, “An Unpublished Fragment. . . ”, 514: Unde in ilia parte tanguntur
radices magne scientie que vocatur scientia de ponderibus. Bacon could have drawn
his information from various treatises entitled scientia de ponderibus dealing with statics, 40 Communia naturalium, ed. cit., 7. See William Newman’s chapter below.
notably the one composed by Jordanus de Nemore. 41
See Faye Getz’ chapter below.
62 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON THE GLASSIFICATION OF THE SCIENCES 63

Some of these special sciences, for example, medicine, astronomy quantitative parts and astrology, should be included in the normal
and optics, were already listed in Kilwardby’s De ortu scientiarum. In the course of study.
case of perspective, Bacon makes the point that this science “is not Bacon’s main point seems to be that the omission of the seven
yet taught at Paris, nor among the Latins, except twice at Oxford.”42 special sciences from the schools led to a deficiency in the teaching
In his view, not even ille, qui fecit se auctorem (Albertus Magnus), knew of the liberal arts, and as a consequence to a deficiency in the study
this science. Bacon’s discussion of astronomy in the Opus maius, part of philosophy and theology. The following is a schema44 of Bacon’s
four, would seem to show that although the works of Ptolemy and sciences, including the seven special sciences which he wished to
other astronomers were taught in the schools, there was considerable emphasize in the Christian education of his time.
debate, particularly among theologians, about the status of astrology.
It is evident from the later works of Bacon (post 1266) that astrology Geometry
was not acceptable to many theologians of his time. Mathematics ^ — Arithmetic
Bacon does not give much information about the teaching of the V V ^ Music
\ \ P prsnprtivp*
science of weights in his extant works. In the case of medicine, he 1) Specuhtwa:
mainly criticized the content and methods of the common medical (Almagest)
teaching in the schools. In the case of sciential experimental and al­ 2) Practical (Canones,
chemy, however, Bacon strongly argued for their inclusion in the Astronomy Tabula, Instrumental).
3) Astrobgia seu judicialis*:
curriculum of studies. While the inclusion of alchemy in the univer­ De impressionibus.
sity curriculum was strongly opposed by Bacon’s contemporaries, as (Liber novem Judicum,
is clear from his writings, no one, it would seem, thought of scientia Liber plurimum Judicum)
experimental in the unique way that Bacon did.
Science of Weights
Perhaps the best way to see what is new in Bacon’s account of the Alchemy*
sciences would be to set out his seven sciences in diagram form, and Special Natural Sciences Medicine* (Experimental)
compare them with the list proposed by his contemporary, Robert Experimental Science
Kilwardby. In Kilwardby’s account of the sciences above (n. 23) one (.scientia experimentalis)*
finds geometry, astronomy, perspective, music and arithmetic listed
as worthy of study. In his list of the seven special sciences, Bacon A stormy debate arose between theologians and arts teachers during
does not include geometry, music or arithmetic. He assumes they the thirteenth century about the status of such subjects as astrobgia
were part of the Quadrivium. He does include astronomy, perspective, (the third part of astronomy), alchemy, and implicitly scientia experi­
music and arithmetic listed as worthy of study. Yet, it is clear from mentalis. These latter forms of study were regarded by many as fall­
the Opus maius, part four,43 that Bacon saw a central place for geom­ ing under the category of natural magic. They were not included by
etry, music and arithmetic in the study of nature. Thus, the fact that Kilwardby under the heading of philosophy.
he did not list them among the seven special sciences does not mean The critical points in Bacon’s schema, therefore, are not those
that he did not give them an important role in his plan of education. sciences which had been in common use in the universities by 1266.
In presenting his case for perspective and astronomy as two special They are, rather, astrology, alchemy and scientia experimentalis. And of
sciences, Bacon was not just recognizing the existence of these stud­ the three, the latter was the most important for Bacon. It alone had
ies in the curriculum. He was setting out an argument for a new the function of experimental verification of truth in the other sciences.45
kind of perspective, namely that of Alhazen (Ibn al-Haytham). But Further, Bacon argues that sciences such as medicine, alchemy and
even more: he insisted that all three parts of astronomy, the two
44 I have constructed this schema from a combination of Communia naturalium and
42 Opus tertium, ed. Brewer, 37. Opus maius, part four. The asterisk indicates a new science.
43 Opus maius, part four, ed. Bridges, I, 178-9. 45 See Roger Bacon, Tractatus in quo jit sermo de experientia in communi, Jeremiah
64 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON THE CLASSIFICATION OF THE SCIENCES 65

other had only imperfect experiences.46 Even astrology and the com­ for Astrology. And of course, Grosseteste does allow a place for
mon astronomy lacked full certainty without scientia experimentalist1 Astrology in both human and natural concerns.
And this is of course the problem for Roger Bacon’s relationship Roger Bacon looked back to Grosseteste from the complex world
to his Hero, Robert Grosseteste.48 As I have argued elsewhere, this of the University of Paris in the 1260’s. And he saw in Lincolniensis
issue together with the issue of the eternity of the World marks the inspiration for a renewed linguistic, natural and moral philoso­
departure from the views of Robert Grosseteste. And yet, having phy. But, as we have seen, much had happened in the whole classifi­
acknowledged this difference, we should briefly look back at Robert cation of the sciences since the De artibus liberalibus of Grosseteste in
Grosseteste’s own proposals for a classification of the sciences in De the early part of the century. Yet, Bacon took over Grosseteste’s vision
artis liberalibus in order to discover whether or not Roger Bacon is of studies as his own crusade. And the Paris of the 1260’s was no
influenced by his Hero. less hostile to “experimental” books then than it was in 1210 and
As was argued in chapter one, there is no straight line of influence 1215. And in order to deal with this problem, Roger Bacon was to
from Robert Grosseteste to Roger Bacon. And yet, as the De artibus return to sources from an earlier age than that of Grosseteste and
liberalibus of Grosseteste shows, there is core of a classification of the Kilwardby. That source was the master-work in Hermeneutics from
sciences in this latter work which Roger Bacon took up and devel­ Late Antiquity, the De doctrina Christiana of the North African roman
oped.49 First, the causes of error are set out. The liberal arts are seen philosopher, Augustine.51 That, however, is a matter for the chapters
as a means to overcome ignorance and to develop the moral person. which follow.
Aspectus et qffectus. Grammar, logic and rhetoric inform and remove
error; rhetoric persuades. What is emphasised most of all is the Tran­
scendental role of Music: it affects all aspect of the micro and macro­
cosm. It covers everything from sound in Speech to the harmony of
the spheres. This introduces the importance of number and the other
members of the Quadrivium: arithmetic, geometry and astronomy.
He then presents the Moralis scientia has that which teaches what is
to be sought and what to be avoided. He adds: “Indeed, Rhetoric
teaches the desiring self what to seek and the angry self what to
avoid. On account of this, Moral Science with the help of Rhetorical
style seeks to know and teach in order to provice moral knowledge.”50
Grosseteste then turns back and examines the application of the
Quadrivium to Philosophia naturalis. Again, he emphasises Music, and its
role in health care of body and mind. Astronomy helps us with
agriculture. And it helps with the choice of times in alchemy. Above
all, it helps in Medicine. And here, Grosseteste emphasises the need

Hackett (Toronto Ph.D. 1983), 281: Considerandum oportet igitur certificari omnino
per veritatem experientiae.
46 Ibid., 291.
47 Ibid., 330-32.
48 See Jeremiah Hackett, “Scientia experimentalis: From Robert Grosseteste to
Roger Bacon”, art. cit., 113-119.
49 De artibus liberalibus, ed. Baur, Die philosophischen Werke, 1-6. 51 Augustine, De doctrina Christiana, ed. Joseph Martin, (Aurelii Augustini Opera,
50 Ibid., 4. pars IV, 1: Turnholt, 1962) [Corpus Christianorum Series Latina].
4. RO GER BACON AND GRAMMAR

Irene Rosier-Catach

Knowledge of languages is the first gateway to


wisdom, especially for the Latins, who possess no
theological or philosophical texts other than those
composed in a foreign tongue. For that reason,
everyone ought to know languages, needs to study
them and understand their science. One cannot
come to know them by natural means, because they
are dependent on persons’ pleasure and they vary
according to their will.1

For Roger Bacon, grammar does not have one single meaning, much
less a meaning coinciding exacdy with that given the word by his
contemporaries. For him, the discipline starts with the elementary
teaching of Latin, goes on to the reasoned grammar such as is taught at
the university, to culminate with the knowledge of languages, a term
which includes the wisdom languages as situated within the diachronical
perspective of the translatio linguarum, the science of signs and the
debates on the magical power of the spoken word. The Summa
grammatica distinguishes itself from later works in that it is typically a
product of the Faculty of Arts circa 1245, being based on argumen­
tative reasoning and on both grammatical and philosophical sources.
The knowledge of languages to which Bacon will devote himself begin­
ning in the years 1267-8 was in no way a university discipline.
Knowledge is extolled not just of one language, but of the wisdom
languages as a whole. Located within the project of a renovation of
learning in general, knowledge of languages is viewed as propaedeutic
to sapientia as a whole, whether sacred or profane, with the aim of
accomplishing practical goals, first among which is the preaching of

1 Op. tert., ed. Brewer, ch. xxvii, 102: Notitia linguarum est prima porta sapientiae,
et maxime apud Latinos, qui non habent textum theologiae, nec philosophiae, nisi
a linguis alienis; et ideo omnis homo deberet scire linguas, et indiget studio et doctrina
harum, eo quod non potest ea cognoscere naturaliter, quia fiunt ad placitum hominis,
et variantur secundum hominum voluntatem.
Note: The body of the text was translated by D.C. Miller. It was edited/reviewed
by Jeremiah Hackett. The latter, with the advice of D.C. Miller, translated and
edited the notes.
68 IRENE ROSIER-CATAGH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 69

the word “to the faithful or the infidel, to the clergy or the laity” are addressed to the principles behind the most common construction,
(Op. tert., ch. lxxv, 303). These practical goals necessitate the knowl­ subject and verb; and secondly, the principles behind figurative con­
edge of both the nature and the functioning of language as a semiotic structions, in the case of which it is important to show that although
system which is instituted by persons and subject to change accord­ these constructions infringe against the general rules, they represent
ing to their will; and of the spoken word as natural and physical nonetheless, secundum quid, a certain kind of correction which renders
phenomenon, inscribed in the networks of multiple causalities, deter­ them acceptable. This second set of questions constitutes in fact
mining effectiveness and effect. an amplification of the “general” (in generali) principles governing the
analysis of the figurative constructions, all of which will be completed
by a “specific” (in speciali) exposition on each of the five figures of
1. The Summa grammatica construction (antithesis, synthesis, prolepsis, syllepsis, and zeugma).
This amplification in generali is a partial repetition, quite literally so
The Summa grammatica of Roger Bacon is a treatise typical of the for some of the arguments, of the introduction to the section on
teaching at the University of Paris in the years 1240-50. Like others figures in Robert Kilwardby’s commentary (Institutiones grammaticae, xvii,
of the same genre, this Summa constitutes a systematic exposition of 153).4 In a second part of the Summa, it will be the non-figurative
the principle points of syntax using “sophisms”, that is, examples chosen constructions which are addressed, posing as they do a special difficulty
to illustrate the points set out in the form of the disputatio.2 These (impersonals, gerundives, ablative absolutes, interjections). In a third
Summae were intended to complete the Commentaries on Priscian pre­ section (S.G., 119fT.) Bacon goes on to analyse a certain number of
scribed by the university statutes— and more particularly, in our case, examples, without their appearing particularly ordered with regard
what was called Priscian Minor, that is, books xvii—xviii of the Institutiones to treatment of subject-matter. Some of them are quite cursory, for
grammatical of Priscian—with the presentation in logical form of some they draw back from difficulties previously grappled with; others receive
subject found haphazardly in the original text. Bacon’s Summa is a more extensive treatment, within the typical structure of the disputed
confirmation of the supplementary role played by the commentaries question. For the most part these are sophisms to be found elsewhere
on Priscian and by the collections of sophisms. Bacon in fact drew in other collections. Finally, in the last section (S.G., 15ff.), there is
fully and literally from one of the most famous commentaries of his an analysis, albeit quite cursory, of a collection of short sentences,
time and of the 13th century as a whole, namely, that of his contem­ including most notably adverbial constructions (e.g. lupus est in fabula),
porary, Robert Kilwardby.3 Bacon’s Summa grammatica belongs to a and also—and this is somewhat rare—liturgical formulae (In nomine
genre quite typically known as speculative grammar such as it was de­ patris et Jilii et spiritu sancti; ita missa est), which present problems be­
veloped at the University of Paris in the first half of the 13th century, cause of their elliptical character.
culminating in the treatises De modis significandi in the second half of A characteristic feature of the method of the speculative grammar­
the century. It is clear that Bacon’s grammar does not comply with ians is that the reasoning leans systematically on the Physka of Aristotle.
the requirements of an elementary grammar such as Bacon himself This parallel between grammar and physics is justified by the adage
defines the genre (cf. below, par. 5), in part because it appeals to “art imitates nature to the extent that it can” (Phys. II, 219 4a 21;
notions borrowed from disciplines appearing in the syllabus subsequent S.G., 35:4). It is difficult to determine to whom the paternity of the
to this elementary teaching; and partly because Bacon’s grammar is introduction of this method should be attributed, evident from the
located within the context of an investigation of the causes or rationes first half of the 13th century as attested by the famous Student’s Guide
of language. The Summa opens, as is the case with other summations in MS. Ripoll 109.5 Whatever the case, the elements which we will
of contemporary sophisms, with some general questions. The first set
4 O n Kilwardby’s theory of figures, see M. Sirridge, “Robert Kilwardby.. . .”
2 See I. Rosier, “Les sophismes gramm aticaux. . 1 8 8 - 1 9 7 . This is used by Bacon and by many contemporaries. See I. Rosier, La parole. . .,
3 See C.H. Kneepkens, “Roger Bacon . . A. de Libera & I. Rosier, “Intention ch. 1, with sources and cited bibliography.
de signifier. . . . ” 5 See C. Lafleur (with assistance of Joanne Carrier), Le “Guide de I’etudiant” d’un
70 IRENE ROSIER-GATACH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 71

present, beginning with the Summa are not unique to Bacon, and pre­ “grammatical” subject. Finally, the organizing principle for the com­
liminary investigation reveals that they are to be found for the most bination of terms is the notion of dependencia: “every combination of
part in Robert Kilwardby. It is in Kilwardby that one encounters words is a natural relation of dependence” (S.G., 52). This relation
notably the idea that the opposition between the permanent and the traces the natural dependence between the accidental with regard to
successive grounds the distinction between the noun (and the pronoun) its subject (S.G., 134), of which the linguistic prototype is the con­
and the verb (and the participle), an idea which is explicitly claimed struction of the adjective with its substantive (S.G., 143).
as a borrowing from Averroes (Phys. v, ch. 9) by later authors.6 Bacon At yet a third level, these physical principles define a mode of
puts these oppositions to good use (S.G., 126). But given the aim of argumentation which rests on a physico-grammatical parallel, legiti­
his treatise, he exploits them less within the context of the definition mate in itself since it is by beginning with nature that grammar defines
of grammatical category (cf. S.G., 148) than within the analysis of its own principles (S.G., 151). However, the grammarian needs con­
syntactical function. The construction of words is conceived as a move­ stantly to define the limits of this parallelism: the fact that here one
ment.7 The verb, the pivot of the sentence, signifies action and move­ deals with operations of reason and not operations of nature makes
ment and needs for that reason two terms, a terminus a quo or principium in effect for divergence in function. It is only in quantum potest, Bacon
and a terminus ad quern or terminus (S.G., 65, 78). On one level, physical reminds us, that art imitates nature, not in any absolute way. Let us
conceptualization is used to re-define certain notions. Cases are prop­ take for example the figure urbern quem statuo vestra est (the city which
erties allowing an expression to function as a term of movement (S.G., I found is yours) (S.G., 33). The incorrectness comes from the fact
34); in this way the accusative expresses the terminus ad quem. At a that the subject is in the accusative. The “physical” analysis is devel­
second level, Bacon’s conceptualization allows him to state some very oped into a syllogism: “everything which brings movement to an end
general rules for the combination of categories. For example, begin­ is something fixed; no accusative is ever something fixed; therefore,
ning with the premise that “nothing which is in movement can come the accusative cannot be the subject”. The accusative cannot “termi­
to rest in something in movement, no movement being able to com­ nate the movement of the verb”, because it expresses, as does every
plete itself in something in movement” (nullus jluens terminatur adJiuens oblique case, the property of “dependency”, which is contrary to
nec motus ad motum), Bacon deduces the argument that neither the par­ that of “fixity” or “stability” necessary for a word to be a term of
ticiple nor the infinitive, by their verbal signification, have a sufficiently movement. This construction could be validated by an argument
“stable” character to be a term of movement and thus, linguistically, drawn from the comparison with other types of movement, whose
to occupy the function of the subject (S.G., 60, 62). Similarly, a phe­ terms can be inversed, such as the movement of location (one can
nomenon as simple as grammatical agreement raises difficulties in go from Athens to Thebes or vice versa) or the movement in gen­
respect of the principle that “the action is in the patient as in a eration (fire becomes air and air becomes fire). In this way, it would
subject” (S.G., 10, 151). One might ask therefore why the verb does be possible to account for the fact that the accusative which properly
not take its number according to its relation to this “subject”, which expresses the terminus ad quem can also function as the terminus a quo
grammatically is the object in the oblique case, rather than with its (,S.G., 39:15-20). But this argument is invalid, for in movement in
nature the fact of being terminus a quo or ad quem is accidental (it is
accidental for Thebes to be either point of arrival or point of departure
maitre anonyme de la faculte des arts de Paris au xiiie siecle, ed. critique provisoire (Laval, as to local movement). However, in arte, things are different. It is essen­
Faculte de Philosophic, 1992); see I. Rosier, “La grammaire dans le Guide de I’etudiant,” tial for words in a construction to have one function or another (S.G.,
in L ’enseignement de la phihsophie au x iti siecle: Autour du “Guide de I’etudiant” du ms. Ripoll
109, ed. C. Lafleur (Leiden: E.J. Brill, in preparation). 40:29-41:5). The legitimacy of the construction is susceptible to differ­
6 See for example, Siger of Courtrai, Summa modorum significandi, ed. J. Pinborg ent proof: there exists in the accusative an element of independence
(Amsterdam, John Benjamins, 1977); Siger’s reference to Averroes (p. 56) is an almost
literal summary of a passage from the commentary on the Physica, v, ch. 9, ed. 1552,
and fixity which comes not from the fact that it is an oblique case but
f. 125ra, cited in the introduction to the edition, ibid., xvii. from the thing that it signifies, which allows it to be a principle of
7 S.G., 124:18, constructio sit quidam motus et operacio racionis. movement (S.G., 39:15-20). It is for this reason that the subject can
72 IRENE ROSIER-CATACH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 73

be in the accusative in infinitive propositions (S.G., 39:14—40:3). For these latter, the “reasons” one assigns to linguistic constructions
Traditional grammatical reasoning is thus paralleled not only with cannot be mechanically deduced from an application of their rules,
arguments borrowed from the physical world but equally with argu­ for they are dependent also on the will or more exactly the signifying
ments drawn from logic. Nevertheless, the logica consideratio is often intention on the part of the speaker (intentio proferentis). In the prelimi­
different from the grammatica consideratio. The construction est dies nicely nary questions of the Summa, Roger Bacon refers to the principles of
illustrates the way in which what is strictly grammatical analysis is to intentionalist analysis such as had been identified by Robert Kilwardby
be located between the two models, physical and logical, which appar­ and such as one finds their application in numerous analogous texts,
ently dominate it. This expression raises difficulties: why is there only most notably the Sophisms. The correctness of a statement does not
one term and not two; and what is the function of dies? In every depend solely on its conformity with the rules of grammar but equally
movement in fact, as in every dimension (for example a line), the on its adequateness with its signifying intention. Sometimes indeed,
two terms need to be distinct, not only secundum rationem but also because the speaker wishes to signify some precise idea, he may legiti­
secundum substantiam (S.G., 124:20—31). The comparison does not hold mately distance himself from the normal rules. The proferens therefore
in any absolute way, precisely because what is under consideration has the choice of whether or not to express his intention in linguis­
here is an operation of reason, whereby reason can discern a diver­ tic forms which conform to common usage. However, his liberty is
sity where in reality there is an identity. With regard to the present not an absolute one and deviations require some legitimate justifica­
example, reason can quite easily distinguish in the one term dies the tion. A figurative statement containing an “impropriety” needs, to
two functions which are necessarily present in every assertion (S.G., make it acceptable, a “reason which makes it possible” and a “rea­
127:33-128:9). Moreover, logic requires that the subjectum be different son which makes it necessary” (S.G., 68, 133, 171, etc.). Likewise
from the predicatum. But grammar, Bacon says, is a “positive science” with elliptical sentences such as liturgical formulae. Ita missa est, by
which introduces the element of “will”, whereas logic depends on virtue of its elliptical character alone, is quite adequate: the fact that
“intellect and on reason”. And so the grammarian is able to distin­ no attribute is expressed constitutes a semantic richness, since the
guish different functions within the one term (the ratio supponentis and phrase contains potentially all these attributes which could be added,
the ratio specificantis) whereas the logician will require that these func­ cantata for example, or dicta etc., all of which allow the formula to be
tions materialize in two actually distinct terms secundum substantiam applied in diverse circumstances. The rule-governed nature of lan­
0S.G., 128:10-21). guage functions is to be found not only in common usage but also
Let it be noted that this grammatical reasoning leans on principles in those “authorized” variations. It is precisely this principle which
borrowed from other parts of the philosophical register. For example, Bacon will put to work at the semantic level when he conducts his
beginning with the idea that the intellect proceeds from the better analysis of signs. Beyond the ordinary usage of the sign, derivable
known to the less known, one might argue that the order of terms in from its institution, the speaker always has the liberty to use it in the
the appositive construction should be homo animal rather than animal translated way, the variation being in the majority of cases explainable
homo. But Bacon chooses the opposite solution, on the principle of and for this reason comprehensible by the listener. In the case of
Avicenna that the intellect proceeds regularly from what is more con­ figurative constructions and of metaphorical meanings the variation
fused to what is more specific (S.G., 46-47). As we have said, the var­ arises from the signifying intention of the speaker. It is the speaker
ious elements which we have just described are not unique to Bacon who, knowing the rules of language, can decide consciously and
and they are to be found in most of the University production of knowingly to exempt himself from the rules, for the sake of some
the 13th century. Those elements which we are now going to high­ particular signifying intention, thus adapting the intelkctus significatus
light are the concern of only one part of his output, representing a to the intelkctus intentus. As Bacon puts it nicely elsewhere, it is not
tendency among the grammarians which one might term Intentionalist.8 the sign which signifies but rather the speaker by means of the lan­
guage—in the same way that it is not the stick which hits but he
See I. Rosier, La parole. .. . who uses it. In other words, language is for man an instrument, a
74 IRENE ROSIER-CATACH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 75

means.9 This voluntarist conception is to be seen likewise in the context language.” For that reason, it is necessary to know the languages in
of Bacon’s treatment of the magical power of words.101 which this wisdom was originally written down {Opus maius, part three,
ch. i, 80; Op. tert. ch. xxv, 89; CSPh., ch. viii, 473ff). The Latins, he
insists time and again, “did not write one original text, either in
2. The Third Part of the Opus maius theology or in philosophy,” with the exception of Law {CSPh., ch.
viii, 465). (2) To understand the original texts, which cannot be ade­
The third part of the Opus maius has as its object “language or quately translated because of the poverty of the Latin language and
grammatical usage in three languages, Hebrew, Greek and Latin” because of the impossibility of rendering in another language the
(ed. Bridges, Vol. Ill, 80ff.).u Bacon gives a summary in the Opus “genius” (proprietas) of the source language (Ibid., 81; CSPh., ch. viii,
tertium (ed. Brewer, 88ff.). It contains three sections which we will 466). (3) To know exactly what the translated texts talk about, and
present first of all briefly, while later dealing in greater detail with then it is a question of also knowing the sciences which these texts
some of his particularly original treatments. treat of (Ibid. 82; CSPh., ch. viii, 466). (4) To be able to read the
2.1 The first section {Opus maius, ch. i-x; Op. tert. xxv) is dedicated texts, religious or philosophical, which have not been translated, a
to the knowledge of languages such as is useful to the sciences, both knowledge of which would be most useful (Ibid., ch. ii, 84). (5) To
secular and divine. In his other works such as the Grammaticagraeca show oneself a worthy “son and successor” of the ancient thinkers,
or the Compendium studii philosophiae, one finds very similar remarks on whether those of Antiquity itself or Antiqui of the present century
Greek, Hebrew, etymology etc. This “science of Wisdom-Languages” such as Robert Grosseteste who have a good knowledge of different
is the primary science, ignorance of which constitutes a factor impeding languages and who do not hesitate to use foreign expressions (Ibid.,
knowledge. This science is placed alongside the science of Mathematics, ch. iii, 89; CSPh., ch. vi, 435). (6) To be able to correct the mistakes
the science of Perspective, Alchemy, and the Experimental Sciences which .are present in the books of theology or philosophy with regard
(CSPh., 433). to letter and meaning (Ibid., ch. iv-v, 94). (7) To understand the
This discipline has first of all as its goal the knowledge of wisdom meaning and the correct interpretation of words, both in Theology
{propter studium sapientiae) {Opus maius, ch. xi, 115) and the reasons in and Philosophy (Ibid., vi, 101). (8) Because Latin and Latin grammar
favor of this apprenticeship, eight in all, are enumerated in the first come from Greek and Hebrew (Ibid.,'ch. vi-x, 105).
section of the Opus maius, part three, and taken up again in the sum­ 2.2 The second section has as its aim the knowledge of languages
mary of the Opus tertium (ch. xxv), but in a different order.12 in so far as it can be useful in the “Church of God and the Republic
(1) Knowledge of languages is a requirement both in the religious of the Faithful” (Opus maius, part three, 115). But here the summary
domain and in the philosophical domain because all the wisdom of of the Opus tertium (ch. xxvi, 85) does not coincide exactly with treat­
the Latins, Bacon says, has its origin in books written “in a foreign ment in the Opus maius, which suggests either some missing sections
or a reorganization of the material.
9 Roger Bacon, Summa de sophismatibus et distinctionibus, ed. R. Steele, 153-154. 2.2.1 In the first place, Bacon enumerates the practical reasons
10 See below, par. 2.2.4. for a knowledge of languages such that it is concerned with the func­
11 The title of this third part varies from passages to passage: Scientia linguarum tion of the Church (Opus maius, part three, ch. xvi). Bacon presents
sapientialium (CSPh., vi, 433); grammatica aliarum linguarum (Ibid., 438); de Unguis seu de
utilitate grammaticae (Op. tert., ch. xxv, 89; see also Opus maius, part three, ed. Bridges, four applications: (1) For the divine offices in which one uses words
Vol. Ill, 81, n. 1); tractatus de Unguis (Op. min., 325); grammatica secundum linguas diversas from the Greek, Hebrew and Chaldean (Opus maius, part three, ch.
(Communia naturalium, liber primus, ed. Steele, fasc. ii, 1). [NOTE: All reference to the xv, 115; cf. Op. tert., ch. lxxi, 275ff). (2) For the collation of the
Opus maius with the exception of part seven, the Philosophia moralis is to the Bridges’
edition. It will be cited as follows: (1) Title: Opus maius; (2) Part i.e. Part one; (3) sacraments. In these two cases there are priests (and sometimes even
Volume, i.e. Vol. Ill; (4) Page no. The reason for this is that Bridges published a Bishops!) who neither know the origin nor the meaning of the words
supplementary volume (= Vol. Ill) in which is found a better text for parts one, two
and three. The citations for these parts are always from Vol. III. The name “Bridges”
in the ritual, pronouncing them like magpies or parrots, without either
will not be repeated in the citations.] knowing the exact meaning or the correct pronunciation and without,
12 The list in CSPh. has thirteen reasons. See Ibid., ch. vi, 425ff. as a result, being able to supply their ennunciation with the required
76 IRENE ROSIER-GATAGH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 77

appropriate intention (Opus maius, part three, ch. xi, 116-177).13 teaching of Arabic. Bacon’s own colleague, Raymond Lull, was striv­
(3) To be able to preach to other peoples in their mother tongue, ing towards the same ends, giving permission for the institution of a
which is the only way to achieve a sincere adherence (Opus maius, Franciscan Studium for Arabic at Miramar on the island of Majorca
part three, ch. xi, 118). (4) The fourth reason invokes a certain Liber in the year 1270.15
de seminibus scripturarum, likewise mentioned in the Opus tertium. This is 2.2.4 Finally, still working from the premise of the “pacific” con­
a work composed in 1204/5 of uncertain attrribution, in which one version of the Infidel on “the paths of wisdom,”16 Bacon invokes the
finds deliberations on the Apocalypse and the period of decadence “power of letters” and the “power of words” for the refutation of
which is to come. These thoughts lead the author to defend the im­ their beliefs. We have already identified a source of his reflections on
portance of reframing knowledge and the necessity of converting the the “power of letters” {supra 2.2.1.). He takes up the theme of the
Jews and the Gentiles. We might note that the author seeks to explain “power of words” in a somewhat detailed manner in the summary
history, both future and past, with the help of a method which asso­ of the Opus minus, whereas its treatment is very brief in the Opus
ciates a particular century to each of the letters of the cross in three maius (part three, Vol. Ill, ch. xxiv, 124—25). By contrast, the theme
different languages, according to the characteristics of these letters. reappears in the Opus maius, part four, in the section on astrology,
Bacon makes direct reference to this method when he talks about where it finds a natural home in the middle of the reflections on the
“the power of letters” (Opus maius, part three, ch. civ, 128; Op. tert., influence of the workings of nature (including the faculty of the human
ch. xxvi, 95; cf. below par. 2.2.4). The association presented in De will) on the actions of men {Opus maius, part four, Vol. 1, 395-396
seminibus between the Apocalypse, the struggle against the Antichrist and 398-399). One supposes that Bacon chose to treat this question
and the Infidel and the reform of knowledge most certainly consti­ of the power of words first of all in his chapters on astrology and
tuted for Bacon an important source of inspiration.14 that secondarily he wished to bring together everything connected
2.2.2 In the second place, Bacon indicates three practical justifi­ with language, integrating in this way in the second section his re­
cations for the learning of languages, concerning the relation of the flections on the power of words. Thus one finds in the Epistola de
church with other peoples: (1) the demands of trade and the fraud secretis operibus artis et naturae et de militate magiae (ch. ii-iii) a parallel
which results from having recourse to interpreters {Opus maius, part treatment in which the power of words is viewed in connection with
three, Vol. Ill, ch. xii, 119) (2) disputes that missionary brothers can diverse magical practices such as incantations.
run into with the judiciary of these foreign countries {ibid. p. 12); We will restrict ourselves in this connection to two remarks.17*For
(3) the negotiation of peace treaties {Ibid.). Bacon the efficacy of the spoken word is thought of in the manner
2.2.3 Bacon sets out, in the third place, the usefulness of the of a physical process. The word in fact, in so far as it is made up of
knowledge of languages for the conversion of Infidels “the whole world different elements which confer on it its value, acts on the listener by
over.” The Jews, the Saracens, Pagans and Schismatics would easily way of a multiplicatio specierum analogous to the process operating in
be persuaded of our Faith, Bacon says, if the preachers could present human sight. Certain elements are themselves of the natural order—
it in their foreign language rather than having recourse to violence the conjunction of the stars, the disposition of the body of the
and war {Opus maius, part three, Vol. Ill, 120-122). Roger Bacon speaker—but others are dependent on the speaker’s mental disposi­
picks up here on the preoccupations of the Preaching Friars, such as tion. Words pronounced with “a definite intention, firm resolution,
Humbert of Romans who, as early as 1255, recommended the study strong conviction” will be all the more effective {Opus maius, part
of languages to advance the spread of Christianity; and of Raymond
of Penafort, whose efforts contributed to the founding of the studia 15 See G. Dahan, I. Rosier, L. Valente, “L’arabe .. 275ff.; G. Dahan, “Les
linguarum, the first being the one he set up in Tunis in 1250 for the intellectuels . . .,” 258-63.
16 See also on this theme CSPh., 395.
17 See E. Massa, Ruggero Bacone, ch. xiii; I. Rosier, La parole. .., ch. 6 and bibl.;
13 O n this point, see also Greek Grammar, 25, 81, 83, 195; CSPh., ch. ii, 413. On Roger Bacon and Magic, see M.M. Pattison Muir, “Roger Bacon: His relations
14 E. Randolph Daniel, “Roger B acon.. . . ” to Alchemy and Chemistry,” and A.G. Molland, “Roger Bacon as Magician.”
78 ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 79
IRENE ROSIER-CATAGH

four, Vol. I, 399; Ibid., part three, Vol. Ill, ch. xiv, 124-125; Op. tert. theology.” “It is of importance for the composition of languages, the
ch. xxvi, 96). This thinking is the extension of an idea of Avicenna’s giving of names and for the manner in which names signify through
which Bacon in the context of languages raises to the level of a maxim, their being given and in diverse other ways” (Op. tert., ch. xxvii,
viz. that “nature will sometimes obey the thoughts (cogitationes) of the p. 100). Bacon insists greatly on the originality of this third section.
soul” (De Animalibus, VIII, 7, Opera philosophica, ed. Venise 1508). But He asserts that this science of languages was not formulated by the
our Doctor seems to draw inspiration from another source as well, Latins, and above all that this science has not yet been translated.
viz. the De radiis of Al-Kindi, where one finds a long exposition on What might be then this foreign source which could have given Bacon
the functioning of the virtus verborum which likewise treats of physical his inspiration? He himself identifies the source in a much earlier
and mental conditions, these latter being as with Bacon conviction work, his commentary on Metaphy. V, written ca. 1240-47. There he
and will (desire).18 Additionally, the fact that Bacon, at the point of raises the question, which in time will become a favorite of the Modists,
drawing up his summary in the Opus tertium “extracts” from his chapter whether it is in the province of the grammarian or the metaphysician
on astrology (Opus maius, part four) these sections on the power of to give names to things. After asserting first of all that the grammar­
words seems significant. It shows in fact that for Bacon it is a ques­ ian can only consider names which have already been established, so
tion of finding one more weapon for the battle he wishes to join as to posit the rules behind their formation, he goes on to mention
with the Infidel, a weapon which will render redundant wars and the opinion of others who maintain that there does exist a a science of
violence and which he thus places on the same level as persuasio, of languages and idioms, adding, however, that “we do not possess it.”21
the rhetorical order, expounded upon not only in these same pas­ The parallel with the passage in the Opus tertium is obvious. In the
sages in the Opus maius, part three, but also in the Philosophia moralis, commentary on Metaph., Bacon clearly identifies his source, viz. the
which constitutes the final part of the Opus maius. In both these cases De divisione scientiarum.22 Al-Farabi in the De ortu scientiarum which is
the effectiveness of the spoken words depends in part on the will of attributed to him mentions in fact that the primary science is the
the speaker. Bacon is at pains in fact not to conceive of this treat­ “science of language, that is the giving of names to things,” a science
ment on the virtus verborum as being the same as certain dubious magical which is anterior to grammar, logic, and poetics.23 This presentation,
practices. This virtus does not act in any mechanical way. It rests, as which paves the way for a breaking with the traditional exposition of
we have said, not only on the will and the intention of the speaker the trivium is also to be found in an introduction to philosophy con­
but above all on the “inciting” effect that words have when they are temporary with Bacon’s commentary, a treatise entitled Philosophica
pronounced. “The will can not be constrained,” our author repeats disciplina (ca. 1245), which mentions, as with Al-Farabi and Bacon,
time and again, thus taking issue with the “fakes” or “fake math­ the relationship of reciprocal subordination obtaining between the
ematicians” who posit a necessity to all these practices.19 Bacon thus “science of language” and “grammar.”24
avoids the charge of determinism which befell Al-Kindi.20
21 Quaestiones supra libros prime Phihsophk Aristoklis, ed. Steele, 97, (11. 24-8): ideo
2.3 The third section is missing from Bridges’ edition, but the dico quod gramaticus non habet considerare impositiones nominum set solum modum
summary in the Opus tertium (ch. xxvii) gives the contents in detail. rectificandi et regulandi et formandi illas impositas. Alii dicunt quod est alia que est
Bacon is dealing with a part of grammar he says did not exist with scientia lingue et ydyomatum, et subaltemat sibi gramaticam, et subaltematur ei, set
illam non habemus. Et tunc dicendum quod gramatici, communiter loquendo, est
the Romans and which is extremely useful “in the service of the imponere nomina, non metaphysici. And again, further below, 11. 37-8: Set de ista
research and understanding of speculative truths in philosophy and non audivimus nec vidimus aliquid.
22 Ibid., 97:33-38.
23 Al-Farabi, De ortu scientiarum, 2, ed. C. Baeumker, Aljarabi. Ueber den Ursprung der
18 Alkindi, De radiis, ed. M.T. d’Alvemy & F. Hudry, Archives d’Histoire Doctrinak et Wissenschaften, (BGPM xix, 3; Munster 1916), 22 (11. 8-10): primum principium omnium
Litteraire du Moyen Age, 41 (1974-75), 139-260; See ch. 5, 232-33 and I. Rosier, La scientiarum est scientia de lingua, id est de impositione nominum rebus, scilicet
parok. .., ch. 6.2. substantiae et accidenti.
19 See for example Opus maius, part four, Vol. I, 393. 24 Philosophica disciplina, ed. Lafleur, Quatre introductions a la phihsophk au X IIP suck,
20 See Giles of Rome, Errores philosophorum, ed. Joseph Koch (1944); See I. Rosier, (Montreal: Institut d’Etudes Medievales Paris: Vrin, 1988), 11. 317-333: .. . Secundum
La parok . . ., ch. 6.3. vero Alfarabium additur quinta, que est scientia lingue, que est de impositione
80 IRENE ROSIER-CATACH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 81

Bacon gives a detailed description of the contents of this third the most part works on grammar, logic, and philosophy, and notably,
section. It deals with signs and signification, natural and conventional, written in the same hand, anonymous Quaestiones on modi significandi and
as a whole; then with questions of signification which are of interest the Syncategoremata of William of Sherwood.25 The fact that the same
to theology—the question of divine names, the relationship between manuscript also contains two graduation speeches for bachelors pre­
literal sense and spiritual sense, the “typological” relationship which senting for the licentia docendi confirms the content of the collections
connects the Old to the New Testament, sacrament as sign, the giv­ of texts gathered in this codex as belonging to the Arts faculty.26
ing of names by Adam, the original language which infants left to Bacon insists on the originality and importance of this third section
themselves in the desert would speak. A part of the corresponding of the Opus maius, part three; “it is a part of the science of grammar
section in the Opus maius, part three has been found as a separate which is in the highest degree necessary to theology, philosophy, wis­
entity, viz. the De signis, dealing with everything concerning signs in dom in general.” He insists also that the section belongs to grammar
general, a subject taken up later by the Compendium studii theologiae and on the fact that it was by way of this “grammatical” (grammatice)
written by Bacon right at the end of his life (1292). The section on mode that Augustine approached these questions, in the second and
the application of these considerations to theology is missing in both third books of his De doctrina Christiana. It is worth noting that the
works. It is possible that the analysis of signs in general, containing necessaria cognitio linguarum which Bacon states as the main aim of this
numerous discussions of interest to logicians, such as the debate on section is the exact wording used by Augustine to describe his own
univocity (cf. Chapter below by Alain de Libera) has been detached work in the De doctrina ckristiana (1. Ill, xix, 40).
from those only of interest to theologians. It should also be noted
that the Ms. Oxford Digby 55 which conserves De signis contains for
3. The Knowledge of Languages27
nominum. Set, quia ista et poetica sunt valde annexe gramatice, ideo communiter
loquendo continentur sub grammatica. Distinguntur tamen ab ea sicut subaltemans 3.1 The Different Types of Languages
et subaltemata, ut dicit Alpharabius. Nam scientia lingue primo est, secundo gramatica,
tertio poetica, quarto rhetorica, quinto logica. Istius autem divisionis sic patet Bacon distinguishes three groups of languages.
sufficientia: quia oportet rebus nomina imponere, et hoc fit per scientiam lingue;
secundo, recte ordinare et componere . .. et hoc docet gramatica; deinde debet sermo
delectare . . . et hoc fit per poeticam . . . deinde est sermo ad hoc quod persuadeat.. . (1) The “wisdom” languages, most often three in number, although
et hoc docet retorica, quinto fidem debet facere ut proferenti credatur, et hoc fit per they come in two distinct groupings. The first is made up of the
logicam.
This “science of language” is here a source of confusion, because of two distinct
three languages of the Gross, Hebrew, Greek, and Latin, the three
Arabic sources from which it arises: (1) It is the general name under which Al-Farabi languages of the Bible, expressing the “divine mysteries” (Opus maius,
followed by Gundisallinus, orders the seven linguistic disciplines in their De scientiis: part three, III, ch. xi, 119, ch. xiv, 125; Op. tert., ch. xxv, 88). These
elsewhere, they assign five parts to Logic: demonstration, topica, sophistica, rhetorica, poetica
(Liber Alfarabii de scientiis, ed. A. Gonzalez Palencia, Alfarabi, Catalogo de las Sciencias three languages are often grouped together, notably in the Liber trighssos
(Madrid, 1932), 122, 137; Dominicus Gundisallinus, De scientiis, ed. P. Manuel Alonso
Alonso, (Madrid-Granada, 1954), 62, 72); (2) However, in the De ortu scientiarum,
Al-Farabi makes linguistic science to be one apart, preceding Grammar, Logic and 25 See O. Lewry, “Grammar, Logic and Rhetoric”, in J.I. Catto (ed.), The Early
Poetics (De ortu scientiarum, ed. cit., ch. 2, 22). One will also note that according to Oxford Schools (The History of the University of Oxford, vol. 1), Oxford, Clarendon
Algazel, the first part of Logic is that which is concerned with “the meaning of Press, 402-433, esp. 420.
words”; or in fact, it is concerned with three types of signification, such as that of 26 See O. Lewry, “Four graduation speeches from Oxford manuscripts (c. 1270—
“concomitance” (for example roof in reference to wall), Ch. H. Lohr, ed., “Logica 1310)”, Mediaeval studies 44, (1982), 138-180; see the description of the ms. pp. 141—
Algazelis. Introduction and Critical Text,” Traditio 21 (1965), 223-90; (see 243-44). 146, which is more complete than the one given by G.D. Macray, Catalogi codicum
These three modes are found already in the Logica of Avicenna (Avicenna, Opera manuscriptorum bibliothecae bodleianae pars nono, (Oxford, 1883). We can add that this
philosophica [Venice: 1508, rept. Louvain: 1961], f. 5va). Albert the Great repeats ms. also contains the Tractatus de grammatica of Pseudo-Grosseste (see infra), as long as
this development in distinguishing five of these modes of signification (De predicabilibus, extracts from Aristotle’s Rhetoric (in Guillaume de Moerbeke’s translation).
tract. 1, ch. v, ed. Jammy (Lyons: 1651), 9). One should note the proximity here 27 Several studies, already dated but not yet surpassed, are devoted to this topic:
with the analysis of connotation which Bacon will present in De signis which arises out E. Nolan & S.A. Hirsch, The Greek Grammar. . ., Cambridge: Cambridge University
of this “science of language,” as he states in the precis in Opus tertium, and after­ Press, 1902, introduction; S.A. Hirsch, “Roger Bacon and Philology . . .”; Charles B.
wards in the Compendium studii theologiae. Vandewalle, Roger Bacon .. ., and more recently, P. Bourgain, “Le sens de la langue. . . . ”
82 IRENE ROSIER-GATACH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 83

of the Flemish Franciscan Gerard de Huy who probably had contact ing or as opposed to Latin, the “language of the clergy” (Op. tert.,
with Bacon.28 The second grouping of three languages most often ch. xxviii, 103). With regard to the matter of preaching, these are the
mentioned joins Hebrew, Greek, and Arabic (to which latter is some­ optimal languages, for only he who knows how to talk to those he
times added “Chaldean”). These are the languages of philosophy. wishes to convince in their “mother tongue” is able to obtain a sincere
For Bacon, all wisdom comes from God and has been revealed to and lasting conviction. By contrast, as far as learning is concerned,
the faithful and the infidel alike. He takes up the theme of the franslatio these latter languages are quite deficient and incapable sometimes of
studii again, which he conceives as a franslatio philosophise. Philosophy expressing knowledge because of the poverty of vocabulary. While it
was given (transjusa) first of all by God to his saints, in Hebrew. Then is true that lay people have a natural logic of their own, it would still
it was “renewed” by Aristotle in Greek, and subsequently in Arabic be impossible to translate the science of logic into their language; in
most notably by Avicenna.29 this case it would be necessary to invent new words, rendering it
unintelligible except to the translator (Opus maius, part three, ch. I,
(2) Latin has a unique place. It grounds the identity of the Latins, 81; Op. tert., ch. xxv, 90, 103).31*These languages therefore are inferior
that is the Christians of the west, a community both of knowledge in rank to Latin which by distinction authorizes the translation of
and of faith. Latin is not seen as a “foreign” language. Bacon even the languages of learning. Bacon sometimes sets those lay languages
describes it as a “mother tongue” (lingua matema latine), on the same in opposition to Latin as “foreign languages” by way of deploring,
level as English and French (CSPh., ch. vi, 433). It is true that Dante most notably, the fact that translators introduce words from their
will take up the opposite position, because of the “artificial” nature own mother tongue into a Latin translation, when they do not know
of Latin (De vulgaris ehquentia I). This depreciative judgment of Latin the Latin word (Opus maius, part three, ch. I, 81-82; Op. tert., ch. xxv,
comes from the fact that as a language it is in large part derived 91; CSPh., ch. viii, 467).
from Greek, on three different grounds: first the language is derived Even if Bacon has a clear understanding of the historical evolu­
from Greek (O.G.G., 59; Opus maius, part three, ch. vi, 105-6) and from tion of languages, on the phonetic or semantic levels, he doesn’t seem
Hebrew (CSPh., ch. vi, 441), whether it is a question of its letters or to distinguish between the written classical language, the liturgical
vocabulary; second its grammar—the manner in which it has been language, and the vernacular [spoken] language, when he puts on
analysed (ratio tractandi), including the description of its letters, its parts the same level, while promoting the cognitio linguarum, scientific knowl­
of speech—all of this was borrowed from the Greeks by Priscian edge on the one hand which entails the recourse to the original texts,
(Opus maius, part three, ch. vi, 105; CSPh., ch. vii, 402; ch. viii, 464- and the mission to the Infidel on the other, which demands knowl­
5). Last and most important, nothing original has been written in edge of the language as it is actively practiced. The rules he gives for
this language, which is merely a repository of “foreign” learning. the pronunciation of Greek in the Grammatica graeca apply to the lan­
guage of his contemporaries, not the language of Aristotle.
(3) A third group of languages has the feature in common of not
belonging to the first two groups. These are the languages which
Bacon often calls the “languages of the laity”—known at the time 3.2 Substantial Unity and Accidental Diversity
as the “vulgar languages,”30 in distinction to the languages of leam- For Bacon there exist families of related languages. To be more exact,
one language which is one “substantially” diversifies itself “accidentally”
28 See R. Weiss, Medieval and Humanistic.. ., 140.
into different idiomata. Bacon thus constitutes groups of languages:
29 Op. tert., ch. x, 32: Placuit autem Deo dare sapientiam cui voluit; nam omnis Greek, along with its best known idioms—Attic, Aeolian, Doric, Ionian
sapientia a Domino Deo est; et ipse philosophis, tam infidelibus quam fidelibus, (O.G.G., 27); the gallicana language with Burgundian, Picardian,
earn revelavit; Ibid., ch. xxiv, 80-81.
30 See S. Lusignan, Parler vulgairement. . who cites many examples, most notably
Giles of Rome, 43-44; see also B. Bischoff, “The Study of Foreign Language in the
Middle Ages,” Speculum, 36 (1961), 209-224. 31
See S. Lusignan, “Le L atin...
84 IRENE ROSIER-CATAGH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 85

Norman, Parisian, Francian (gallicus) (O.G.G., 27; CSPh., ch. vii, 438 As the examples given demonstrate, for instance Greek, Bacon seems
or 467); “Chaldean,” Hebrew and Syriac (CSPh., 438-439; ch. vi, 445). in fact to think of the idiomata as dialects with regard to the mother
On the section on geography in the Opus maius Bacon mentions as language. Sometimes, however, they are simply described as being
well the sclavonica language spoken by different nations, Russian, Polish, the manner proper to each nation of writing or pronouncing the
and Bohemian (Opus maius, part four, I, 360). As for Latin, which is “tongue,” that is, the manner of “using” it. An especially clear passage
a language as related to Picardian, French, Provencal, or, as he says in the Grammatica Graeca, which associates the Italians, Spaniards,
elsewhere, to Spanish, Italian, French (O.G.G., 27), it is the same from French, Germans and the English, leaves no doubt on this matter
“the extremities of Apulia to the limits of Spain” (Op. tert., ch. xxv, 90). (O.G.G., 27). When he defines the substance of the Latin language as
Each idiom has its own distinctive characteristic (proprietas). The term being that “by which the clergy and the learned communicate” (O.G.G.,
idiom, Bacon explains, from which the word idioma is derived, means 26) he probably has in mind these variations in the use of Latin as
what is proper to something in Greek.32 Whence the word idiota, language of the learned which had been identified by grammarians
designating precisely someone who contents himself with the proper­ from the beginning of the twelth century at the latest.35 We should
ties of his own idiom without knowing other idioms (O.G.G., 26). note that exactly in the same period Thomas Aquinas is likewise
This proprietas, the genius proper to each language, makes literal trans­ making the observation that different locutiones exist within the one
lation impossible. What rings well in one language becomes ridicu­ lingua; and if he cites the case of France, along with Burgundy and
lous in another; that which is well said in one language can never be Picardy, it is because he mixes, as does Bacon, two different ideas,
transfered to another while maintaining its unique properties. This viz. linguistic kinship and variation in usage.36 It is easy to see the
proprietas includes, beyond the vocabulary, the rhythmic and musical intersection of philology and ideology, for it is essential to justify the
characteristics which Bacon considers an integral part of a language.33 unity, both religious and cultural, of the Latins, above and beyond
His criticisms with regard to bad translations, in the sacred and profane the diversity of the spoken speech and nations. But Bacon’s reflec­
domains, are numerous and virulent, and he does not baulk at citing tions go further, in the fact that he considers different groupings of
his contemporaries by name.34 The gravest consequence in his eyes languages. The “substance” of a language therefore is that which
is the “corruption” of the Paris Vulgate, and his formula is well known: guarantees the unity of a language beyond accidental differences which
“tot sunt lectores per mundum, tot sunt correctores, seu magis corrup- are imputable to the variety of usage in accordance with the different
tores” (Op. min., 330). places where the language is spoken (CSPh., ch. vi, 438-439). Sub­
stance likewise is that which maintains identity in time, in spite of
phonetic or semantic variations.37*O n occasion Bacon indulges in a
32 Op. tert., 90; O.G.G., 26-7; CSPh., 438-439, 468. veritable comparatist analysis: Latin transforms (mutat) e to an a, and
33 Opus maius, part three, I, 81; CSPh., ch. viii, 467; Op. tert., ch. xxv, 89-90 and
267: Sed translatores Latini non habuerunt illam musicae potestatem, quam n to m, and so has malum (apple) for the Greek malon. But, says Bacon,
patriarchae et prophetae, qui omnes scientias adinvenerunt; et nimis difficile esset “this variation does not change the word in its substance or its root
ilia metra Hebraica et rhythmos Latino sermone secundum proprietatem eorum (radix) because [the Latin word] is derived from the Greek although
explicari. Et ideo non remanserunt haec in textu Latinorum; Communia mathematica,
ed. Steele, 17-18: Cum igitur transferri non possit nisi per hominem qui metrorum it is pronounced differently” (Opus maius, part three, III, ch. 9, 112).
et rithmorum causas noverit. . .; On this issue of the translations, see G. Dahan,
I. Rosier, L. Valente, “L’arabe . . .”, par. 2 & bibliog.
34 Op. tert., ch. xxv, 91: Alii vero qui infinita quasi converterunt in Latinum ut 35 Cf. M. Fredborg, “Universal G ram m ar. . 75.
Gerardus Cremonensis, Michael Scotus, Alvredus Anglicus, Hermannus Alemannus 36 Thomas Aquinas, Lectura super Mattheum, (ed. Marietti, 1951), 26, 76, text cited
et translator Meinfredi nuper a domino regi Carolo devicti; hi praesumpserunt in S. Lusignan, Porter vulgairement. . ., 61: in eadem lingua saepe diversa locutio fit,
innumerabilia transferre, sed nec scientias nec linguas sciverunt, etiam non Latinum. sicut patet in Francia et Picardia, et Burgundia, et tamen una loquela est. On this
Nam in locis quasi innumerabilibus ponunt linguam m aternam .. . . Et ideo isti male issue of the substantial unity of languages, see Ibid.., 64ff, and E. Hovdhaugen, “Una
et pessime transtulerunt, et conturbaverunt totam philosophiam per perversitatem et eadem . . . ”, who opposes this idea and the “universal grammar” defended by the
translationis. Et maxime libri Aristotelis sunt destructi per hoc, qui tamen aestimantur grammarians of the University.
in philosophia tenere principatum; nemo potest scire quid velit dicere, quia quod 37 See O.G.G., 20: significata dictionum variantur apud homines secundum quod
unus dicit, alius negat; CSPh., ch. viii, 471-72, etc. tempora variantur.
86 IRENE ROSIER-CATACH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 87

In exactly the same way, Dante will insist on the unity, at one geo­ Voces enim sunt ad placitum in omni lingua, et ideo greci posuerunt
graphic and historical, of Latin, an identity he calls grammatica, de­ voces pro sua voluntate, sicut nos pro nostra et secundum racionem
picting it as an “inalterable identity of language” which is maintained nostre lingue sicut ipsi secundum racionem sue lingue (O.G.G., p. 164).
independently of the variations of time and place.38
The fact that languages are related explains that the derivative 3.3 Instruments and Methods in the Analysis of Languages
character of Latin concerns both the spoken language and the gram­
mar. There is something substantially identical in the various spoken Not to know the diversity of languages and their diachronic relation­
languages as there is something substantially identical in the different ships leads to innumerable errors in translation and interpretation.
grammars (O.G.G., 26-27). This linguistic “substance” is revealed in The Latins, Bacon says, often do not know the origin of a word in
universal features common to all languages. Bacon says most notably their language; they make up fantasy etymologies and ignore the
that in any language there can only be five vowels, whereby the “power spelling and the pronunciation of borrowed words. Those respon­
or the principal sound is identical, even although the accidental or sible foremost for such errors are the lexicographers, “Papias, Hugutio
secondary sound may vary” (O.G.G., 3, cf. infra para. 5). It is these et Brito,” et alii grammaticellae idiotae (CSPh., ch. vii, p. 447, p. 450).
accidental variations (aspiration, stress, length) which explain the fact Bacon seeks to remedy these deficiencies in several ways. In the first
that the Greeks have more than five vowels (O.G.G., p. 4, 30), an place he produces descriptions of the languages “because it is neces­
idea previously expressed more than a century earlier by William of sary for the Latins to have short useful treatments of those foreign
Conches.39 Bacon cites elsewhere the classic example of the article, languages which they use” {Op. tert., ch. xxv, p. 88). It is well known
which the Modists will pick up on, albeit on a very different basis, that the study of languages was particularly encouraged by Robert
to demonstrate that grammar is eadem apud omnes. It is a part of speech Grosseteste who himself composed a short introduction in Greek in
which exists in Greek, and indeed in most languages, notably in gallicus, the preface to his translation of the De divinis nominibus. According to
and if it doesn’t exist in Latin, one uses in its place the articularia the testimony of Matthew Paris, John of Basingstoke wrote a Donatus
pronomina that is hie, haec, hoc (Opus maius, part three, Vol. Ill, ch. iii, Graecus, a short introduction to grammar, with Greek and Latin ex­
94; O.G.G., 14-15; Cambridge Hebrew Grammar, 207). amples.40 But Bacon’s Grammatica Graeca is the first of its kind in the
For Bacon, substantial identity and accidental diversity are two west. It seems to have been inspired by a Byzantine model and un­
inseparable elements, both equally important. The substantial identity dertakes a systematic comparison of Greek and Latin, following the
of languages legitimates the methodology of description borrowed Institutiones of Priscian.41 Extant also are fragments of a Hebrew gram­
from Priscian, which compares Latin to Greek, and in this case also mar, mostly from the section on phonetics. As with his Greek gram­
to Hebrew. The diversity of each spoken language or dialect is none mar, the treatments consists of a comparison with Latin.42*Although
other than the manifestation, on a linguistic level, of the variety of he announces that he “will treat Arabic when the time comes,” we
mankind, in “their customs and their dispositions,” as a function of
place and climate. But above all this diversity derives for Bacon from 40 See R. Weiss, “The Study of the Greek in England during the Fourteenth
what is a fundamental feature of the use of language, viz. its ad placitum Century,” Rinascimento 11, 209-39; rept. in R. Weiss, Medieval and H um anistic...,
character, which the De signis will examine in greater depth: each 80-107; E. Nolan & S.A. Hirsch, The Greek Grammar. .. , introd., xxxviiiff.; Vandewalle,
Roger Bacon . . ., 40-50. O n the study of Greek, see also M.W. Herren, ed. The Sacred
nation has had to choose its linguistic means and has thus bestowed Nectar of the Greeks: The Study of Greek in the West in the Early Middle Ages, (London, 1988).
the particular virtues and distinctive properties to its own language. 41 See S.A. Hirsch, “Roger Bacon and Philology,” 134ff.; Vandewalle, Roger
Bacon . .., 107ff.
42 O n this work, see S.A. Hirsch, “Roger Bacon and Philology . . . ”; on the knowl­
edge of Hebrew, see S.A. Hirsch, “Early English Hebraists: Roger Bacon and his
Predecessors,” Jewish Quarterly Review 12 (1899-1900), 34-88; rept. in A Book of Essays
38 Dante, De vulgari eloquentia, I, 9, 11: grammatica nichil aliud est quam quedam (London, 1902), 1-72; S. Berger, Quam notitiam linguae hebraicae habuerint Christiani medii
inalterabilis locutionis idemptitas diversis temporibus atque locis. aevi temporibus in Gallia, (Berger Levrault, 1893); G. Dahan, Les Intellectuels. . ., 239-
39 See M. Fredborg, “Universal G ram m ar. . .,” 75. 70, especially 253-54; and above all G. Dahan, “L’enseignement.. . .”
88 IRENE ROSIER-CATAGH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 89

possess no grammar of this language, which Bacon acknowledged as Bacon proposes certain general principles on which every diachronic
not having mastered to the point of knowing how to write it (Op. tert., analysis should be grounded. It is well known that lexicographers
ch. xxv, p. 88). In various parts of his Opera Bacon gives elements of from Isidore de Seville onwards had the habit of grouping under the
his description of Greek and Hebrew (Opus maius, part three, Vol. Ill, heading of etymobgy a number of practices aimed at explicating the
ch. iii, 90—92; CSPh., ch. ix, 497ff.).43 It should be noted that accord­ meaning of a word on the basis of its form, and these practices covered
ing to his own admission the Grammatica Graeca is no more than an the morphological processes of composition-derivation, as well as
“introduction to the Greek language.” He would like to have written various kinds of relationships, e.g. between syllables (cadaver quasi caro
a more elaborate version (maior tractatus) required “for the work of data vermibus) or between letters (deus quasi dans etemam vitam suis), with
translation, and the deeper knowledge of the Greek language” (O.G.G., these relationships taking place either within the one language or
pp. 171-172). He identifies three levels in the knowledge of languages: between two languages.44 Bacon gives a description of etymology in
the lower level is reached when one knows how to read the language terms which comply more with the modem understanding, while giving
and when one has a minimum of knowledge of the grammar. The a new meaning to the traditional definition verus serrno interpretationis
middle level implies that one knows how to translate “into the Latin alicuius vocabuli (O.G.G., p. 62). Etymology is governed by five principles.
mother tongue.” The highest level demands that one knows the lan­ (1) The ordo linguarum. An earlier language is not to be explicated by
guage “like one’s mother tongue,” and it is at this level that Bacon a later language, and here the authority of Jerome is invoked:4546“Greek
himself knows English, French, and Latin. Bacon prides himself on does not come from Latin, nor Hebrew from Greek, and so a Hebrew
having acquired the highest level in Greek and Hebrew in thirty etymology can not be taken from the Greek, anymore that a Greek
years, but his level of competence which almost no one of his con­ etymology from the Latin” (Opus maius, part three, Vol. Ill, ch. vii,
temporaries could boast of having attained in his judgment, is not 105-108; CSPh., ch. vii, 448). For example, amen is not to be inter­
necessary. Only knowledge at the lower level is deemed to be preted with the two Greek morphemes, a, the privative, and mene,
indispensible and he offers to teach this level in three days to anyone “deficiency”, from which one gets the meaning “as if without fault”
motivated enough (Op. tert., ch. xx, pp. 65-66; CSPh., pp. 433-434). (quasi sine defectu) (Opus maius, part three, Vol. Ill, ch. vi, 108; CSPh.,
Additionally, Bacon seeks to help his contemporaries by giving them 452.). (2) Not all words have to be given an etymology. Certain words
lists of Greek and Hebrew words which have become Latin words, are “purely Latin,” such as ave, and one must guard against confus­
so that the latter may be identified as such (CSPh., ch. vi-vii, p. 441 ing derived with pure forms (Opus maius, part three, Vol. Ill, ch. vii,
sq.) and that their pronunciation be correcdy established (O.G.G., p. 133 108-9; CSPh., ch. vii, 451-52). (3) It is necessary that the derived
sq.). He would have liked to have done more, namely a glossary “of word and the word from which it is derived resemble one another
all the Greek words used in Latin, arranged alphabetically” (O.G.G., both in form and in meaning, this principle being clearly borrowed
p. 68), with indication of spelling, pronunciation, meaning (interpretatio) from the deliberations of Logicians on paronymy, beginning with the
and etymology (Opus maius, part three, Vol. Ill, ch. vi, 107). The first Chapter of Aristode’s Categories,^ as is attested by the parallel
criticisms which he levels at contemporary lexicographers force him with the classic example of respublica, “which does not mean the same
to take up position on this terrain, through his demonstration that thing when it is a composition as when it is a division [res + publica\.”
the knowledge of languages is above all knowledge “of vocabulary.” Thus Bacon criticises on various occasions the analysis of Israel as vir
Finally, alongside this grammatical and lexicographical knowledge, videos Deum proposed as a composition of the elements Is - vir + ra
= videos + el = Deum (Opus maius, part three, Vol. Ill, ch. vi, 102;
43 Ms Toulouse 302 contains a treatise on Greek and Hebrew, and it has often CSPh, ch. vi, 435-36). In more general terms, this principle allows
been attributed to Bacon or one of his disciples without the question ever being
settled. See S. Berger, Quam notitiam. . ., op. cit., ch. iii, who quotes numerous ex­
tracts; S.A. Hirsch, “Roger Bacon and Philology”, 140-41; See Vandewalle, Roger 44 See I. Rosier, “La grammatica practica. . . ” & Bibliography.
Bacon. . ., 104ff. for an analysis of the Grammatica graeca et its comparison with the 45 O n Bacon’s debt to St Jerome, see P. Lardet, “Un lecteur de Jerome . . .”
CSPh., 495-519. 46 Cf. especially, the Summulae dialecticae of Roger Bacon (1), 187-88, par. 15-19.
90 IRENE ROSIER-CATACH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 91

Bacon to reject derivations without semantic proximity (cf. the example was even more grave with Holy Scripture “which contains all wis­
of antiphrasis lucus [wood] as deriving from luceo [to shine]; or without dom” (Op. tert., ch. xxiv, p. 81: Tota sapientia concluditur in sacra Scriptura).
formal proximity (e.g. semel [once] from wins [one]). (4) It is important How could one, he often lamented, arrive at the “true” spiritual sense
to respect original spellings, and to be watchful of the fact that they when the letter contained so much “error and intolerable imprecision!”
have been “varied” in time (Opus maius, part three, Vol. Ill, ch. viii, (Opus minus, 349; Op. tert., ch. xxv, p. 93). Whereas in the area of
109). Infractions against this principle are legion and induce multiple philosophy Bacon confined himself to critiques of principle, he strove
confusions, for example between poly- (several) and poli(s) (city) (O.G.G., to propose corrections for the sacred texts. Thus one understands
62); or between kenon (empty) and kainon (new), wrongly conflated in how he wished to place his stringent method of textual criticism based
the spelling cenon (CSPh., ch. vii, p. 457). on the knowledge of languages at the very heart of his great project to
It is in the Compendium studii philosophiae that Bacon’s exposition on renew the state of knowledge.
languages is at its most detailed: taking his inspiration directly from
Augustine’s De doctrina Christiana, he seeks to untangle the difficulties
that Latin sets in the written texts, whether by rectifying the stress or 4. Signs
length of a vowel, or by clearing up semantic or syntactic ambigui­
ties, or by reestablishing good readings or correct pronunciation, Roger Bacon proposes an analysis of signs in the De signis, an unfin­
on the basis of the original sources (CSPh., ch. vii, p. 457). ished chapter of the Opus maius, part three which was independently
This philological research, which would have been out of place in in circulation, and also in the Compendium studii theologiae, written right
the Faculty of Arts of the Middle Ages, finds its concrete application at the end of his life. In contrast to the other sections of the Opus
in the establishing of the Corrections of the Bible and gives rise to new maius, part three, this section, on signs, inserts itself largely into the
descriptions of Greek and Hebrew. Bacon refers on numerous occa­ debates in the Faculty of Arts.50 O ur only consideration here is what
sions to this activity while establishing most notably a typology of concerns the classification and the definition of the sign.
“errors” to be corrected, such as one finds with other writers, includ­ Commentators have remarked on how original this interest in the
ing Gerard de Huy.47 His criticisms of his colleagues, Dominican or notion of the sign was. It would need to be said, more exactly, that
Franciscan, often seem excessive, considering their actual practice.48 it was indeed a mark of his originality especially if one considers the
For a man of the thirteenth century like Bacon, knowledge in tradition of the “artists” whose semantics were for the most part of
matters religious or philosophical comes from books, with these books Aristotelian inspiration. And even with this qualification, such a judg­
being translations and often bad translations. Bacon demonstrates how ment needs to be careful. For it is indeed remarkable that Roger
some central doctrinal questions which were causing a flurry at the Bacon’s contemporary Robert Kilwardby, whose influence with regard
time the Opera were being written, such as the problem of the nature to the Summa grammatica we have already noted, had already introduced
of the agent intellect, were based on bad translations of Aristotle’s the notion of the “sign” (signuni) in his commentary on the famous
text (Opus maius, part two, Vol. Ill, ch. v, 45-6; Op. tert., ch. xxiii, first chapter of Aristotle’s De interpretatione. Aristotle, he says, speaks of
78-9). One only has to compare different translations of the same “mark” (nota) for that which is in the mouth of the speaker and “sign”
treatise of Aristotle to guage the extent of a scholar’s confusion in (signum) for what is in the ear of the listener. Whereas for Boethius
this era confronted by these “authorities,” by the fluctuating letter
which it was his job to read, comment on, interpret.49 The situation
sapientia Aristotelis non esset translata, quam tali obscuritatitate et perversitate tradita,
sicut eis qui ponuntur ibi triginta vel quadraginta annos; et quanto plus laborant,
47 Opus maius, part three, Vol. Ill, ch. ix, 113ff. tanto minus sciunt, sicut ego probavi in omnibus qui libris Aristotelis adhaeserunt. . . .
48 See G. Dahan, “La critique textuelle dans les correctoires de la Bible du X III' Si haberem potestatem super libros Aristotelis ego facerem omnes cremari, quia non
siecle,” in Langages et Philosophic. Hommage a J . Jolivet, ed. A. de Libera, D. Elamrani- est nisi temporis amissio studere in illis, et causa erroris, et multiplicatio ignorantiae,
Jamal, A. Gallonier, (Paris: Vrin, 1997), pp. 365-392. ultra id quod valeat explicari. . . .
49 Cf. CSPh., ch. viii, 469: Certus igitur sum, quod melius esset Latinis, quod 50 Cf. Alain de Libera, in this volume.
92 IRENE ROSIER-CATAGH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 93

the “mark” was principally viewed in its relation to things and to the a new meaning: signification is thus subordinate to the decision of
“passions of the soul,” the notion of “sign” allows Bacon to introduce the speaker. The definition of the sign in the De doctrina Christiana had
a connection between speaker and listener. Kilwardby justifies this been the subject of commentary by the theologians in general, be­
distinction by citing a definition of the sign of Augustinian inspira­ ginning with Peter Lombard. But this more original idea of a two-
tion: “the sign is that which offers itself to the senses while present­ way relationship is to be found expressed in terms astonishingly close
ing something else to the intellect” (signum est quod se offert sensui, aliud to those of the De signis in the writings of the English Dominican
derelinquens intellectui) One comes across this definition now and again, Richard Fishacre, and likewise in Bacon’s colleague, Bonaventure.55
and the classification of signs which goes along with it, in several However, here the primacy between the two relations is reversed. In
texts on logic and grammar from the 1240’s on, most notably in the the sphere of sacramental theology it is quite impossible to envisage
Summa grammatica of our author.5152 One sees here the intervention of that the signification of the sign depends on the speaker or on the
Augustine into the domain of the Artists. With regard to sign theory, listener. Bonaventure raises precisely this question with regard to the
his presence loomed large with the theologians in their writings on matter of infant baptism. For these theologians, the relationship be­
the sacraments whereby they themselves placed Augustine alongside tween the sign and what is signified is an essential one, it depends
Aristotle. This fact shows us the way towards research on Bacon’s on its having been instituted as such and it is not subject to modi­
sources of inspiration, something we will do by examining the two fication. This difference of point of view between Bacon and the
central elements of his analysis. theologians is nicely illustrated with the example of the circulus vini,
The first element concerns the definition of the sign.53 Bacon defines which they analyse in the exactly opposite way. The circular sign
the sign as “that which offered to the senses or the intellect desig­ above the tavern, Bonaventure explains, remains a sign even if no
nates something to that intellect” {signum est illud quod oblatum sensui vel one is looking at it: the relationship of sign to signified, once insti­
intellectui aliquid designat ipsi intellectui) {D.S., par. 2).54 This definition, tuted, remains always in force {in actu) and grounds the sign as such.
Bacon says, contains a two-way relationship, that of the sign to the In contrast, Bacon maintains that a sign such as this, even if it has
intellect for whom it signifies (relationship in the dative) and that been instituted to signify some thing, is only a sign in potentia, but not
of the sign to what is signified (relationship in the accusative). For in actu, if there is no one “for whom” it signifies {D.S., par. 1).
Bacon the first relationship determines the second (D.S., par. 1). In The second element consists of the classification of signs. In the
fact, as he demonstrates time and again in the following pages, the De signis (par. 3-15) or in the CSTh (par. 26-43) Bacon proposes the
speaker is at all times free to reimpose the signs, that is to give them following typology:56
(1) natural signs: example smoke-fire
51 This commentary is in the process of being edited and I thank A. Conti for
having allowed me to use his transcription. (Passage cited in I. Rosier, La parole. ..,
(2) signs directed by the soul in order to signify
97). See below for the exact source of this definition. (2.1) signifying conventially, in the mode of the concept
52 S.G., 21:5-10: for examples in this grammatical tradition, see I. Rosier, La (2.1.1) linguistic signs
parole. . ., 98-100; for other examples, especially those in the tradition of Logic, see
C. Marmo, Semiotica e linguaggio. . ., ch. 1; I. Rosier, “Variations medievales. . .
(2.1.1.1) by way of imperfect deliberation: interjections
53 De signis, par. 1-2; see our translation, notes and bibliography in La parole. . .,
text 7; CSTh, ch. 1, with the translation, notes and references provided by Th.
Maloney; C. Marmo, Semiotica e linguaggio. . ., 20-36 and bibliog. 55 For a more complete demonstration, see I. Rosier, La parole. .., ch. 3.4. The
54 This definition is at the same time close to the one in De doctrina Christiana, II, Commentary of Richard Fishacre is being edited by Joseph Goering who has kindly
1, 1 (ed. J. Martin, Corpus christianorum, series latina, xxxii, iv, 1, Tumhout: Brepols, provided his transcription (cf. texts cited, Ibid., 113—120). For Bonaventure, see
1962): Signum est res praeter speciem quam ingerit sensibus, aliud aliquid ex se Commentarii in quattuor Libros Sententiarum Petri Lombardi, (Opera omnia, Quarracchi, IV,
faciens in cogitationem venire; and that of De dialectica, v, (ed. J. Pinborg, trs. & 1, 1, art. n., q. 11, 15).
notes B. Darrell Jackson, Dordrecht/Boston: D. Reidel, 1975): Signum est quod et 56 For a more detailed presentation, see U. Eco et al. “O n Animal Language . . .”;
se ipsum sensui et praeter se aliquid animo ostendit. One notices the addition in the T.S. Maloney, “Roger Bacon on the signification . . . ”; C. Marmo, Semiotica e hnguaggu)... ,
definition of Bacon: that which offers itself to both sense and intellect, already intro­ 36—56. See also the notes to our translation of the De signis and that of the CSTh by
duced by other authors (cf. I. Rosier, La parole .. ., 108; 114-115 and 323, nn. 8-9). Maloney, cited above.
94 IRENE ROSIER-GATAGH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 95

(2.1.1.2) by way of perfect [completed] deliberation: other Augustine, this is not the case with the internal division of the sec­
parts of speech ond category [(2.1) vs. (2.2)], which is classical in the Aristotelian
(2.1.2) non-linguistic signs (the language of gestures, signs made Latin tradition from Boethius on. The first division takes an opposi­
by monks, sign-boards, etc.) tion between signs which are such because their “reason for being a
(2.2) signifying naturally, in the mode o f affect sign” does not depend on an “intention of the soul,” (the relation­
(2.2.1) products of the sensitive soul: sounds emitted by animals ship between signifier and signified depending precisely on the things
(2.2.2) products of the rational soul: groans, exclamations, cries of signified), as illustrated by the classic example of smoke and fire (D.S.,
pain. para. 3). In contrast the signs “established by the soul in order to
signify” (ordinata, data, cf. D.S., para. 15, 164, 165) are those whose
The first distinction [(1) vs. (2)] corresponds to the De doctrina Christiana
(I. 11, I, 2-3). It is taken up by the theologians from the second half “reason for being a sign” has been conferred by the soul. Among
of the twelth century on. To make a place for the sacraments in the these latter are those called ad placitum, the result of conventional
signa data they work out classifications based on several distinguishing agreement, of choice and deliberation (2.1), whether linguistic in
character (2.1.1) or no (2.1.2), like the circulus vini, which we have
criteria [naturalia/data (or voluntaria)\; signa sacra/ non sacra; significata sacra/
already mentioned. Others are said to “signify naturally,” as for ex­
non sacra etc.57 Beginning with Peter Lombard’s outline (Sent. IV, 1, 6),
ample groans or the barking of dogs (2.2). They have their origin in
several commentators of the thirteenth century will do the same, most
notably Robert Kilwardby.58 reactive instinct, the impulses which are not controlled by reason,
whether produced by animals (2.2.1) or by human beings (2.2.2).
These parallels lead us to consider as improbable what Bacon says
Bacon thus distinguishes between natural signs (1) and signs which
in the CSTh, namely that he worked out independently in the De
signis an analysis of signs (per studium proprie inventionis) and that subse­
signify naturally (2.2). In the case of the latter, even if deliberation
quently coming across Augustine’s outline he was able to claim it as is rudimentary, the relation of the sign to the signified nevertheless
an authority (CSTh, par. 25). Why would Bacon, who quotes Augus­ activates an operation “of the soul” whether sensitive or rational. What
tine’s De doctrina Christiana in so many passages of his Opus maius when characterizes a sign as belonging to one or other of these categories
does not consist in its nature as thing but in the “reason” for which it
he wishes to legitimize his project, parallel to Augustine’s, of placing
the sciences, and the linguistic sciences in particular, in the service of is a sign. This idea can be found already in Abelard when he explains
that the barking of a dog can be seen either from the dog’s perspec­
theology and the Church, this Bacon who mentions Augustine in the
tive as a mode of expression “instituted by God” for the dog so that
resume of the Opus tertium, who draws the inspiration for this whole
section on the cognitio linguarum from the De doctrina Christiana—why he can speak his anger or, from the point of view of the listener, as
would he overlook these chapters on the sign when he was writing the a sign associated with this sentiment, and thus as a concommittance
linking the two events.59 In the first case we have what Bacon calls a
De signis? It seems to us on the contrary that Bacon’s treatment is in­
sign signifying naturally; in the second a natural sign. Already in the
deed dependent on Augustine’s, by way of theologians who had them­
selves reflected on these definitions and classifications. Bacon’s great Summulae dialectices, Bacon was making the similar opposition between
the crowing of the cock (cantus galli), emitted with intention, and the
merit is precisely to have integrated into the one analysis those ele­
fact that the cock crows (gallum cantare), which is for us the sign that
ments which were present in the theological tradition, along with other
treatments, of Aristotelian origin, which were in part present in the day is breaking.60
treatises of the Artists.
Indeed, if the first distinction [(1) vs. (2)] is in fact borrowed from 59 Abelard, Dialectica I, ed. L.M. de Rijk (Assen: Van Gorcum, 1970), 114-22-25;
Glossae super Peri Hermeneias, ed. B. Geyer, Peter Abelards Philosophische Schrifien I. Die
Logica “Ingredientibus” (Munster: Aschendorf, 1919), 335-29-32.
50 Summulae dialedice, I, 222, par. 21-23; the second example is repeated in the De
57 Cf. D. Van den Eynde, “The terms Hus positivum, et ‘signum positivum. . signis, par. 4. The example of the hen which cackles to call its young to eat is very
58 Quaestiones in librum quartum sententiarum, ed. R. Shenk, (Munchen: Verlag der close to that of the cock which, having found some food, “makes a vocal sign” to
Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1993), 225:95-226:104. the hen, cited by Augustine in the De doctrina Christiana, II, iii, 3.
96 IRENE ROSIER-CATAGH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 97

Two supplementary points deserve to be briefly noted. The first “similitude,” or “similar configuration,” including not only pictures
has to do with a particular category of signs, namely, interjections. and images but also all sorts of natural relations existing between the
These signs have in fact an intermediary status. O n the one hand, different poles of the semiotic triangle, for example the relation of
they are words in language, part of the institution of language, and sound to the concept of a thing in the mind (if I hear a word, I infer
merit as such being classified in the category (2.1) of conventional from that that a concept associated with that sound exists in the
signs, signifying “in the mode of concept.” O n the other hand, in mind of a person pronouncing the word) (.D.S., para. 16-18, 162—
contrast to other parts of speech, these words are emitted by the 169). All the relations in this triangle are signa for Bacon, whether
speaker when he is troubled and thus are close to the groans emitted conventional or natural (D.S., para. 166). Category (1.3) of D.S. is
under the assault of pain “suddenly and without deliberation” belong­ not carried over into the Opus tertium or the CSTh. It contains two
ing to the category (2.2) of signs which signify “in the mode of affect.” examples borrowed from the De doctrina Christiana—smoke as sign of
Bacon elsewhere vacillates between classifying interjections in one or fire, tracks as sign of an animal’s passage, with this latter being reclassi­
other category. It should be said that these reflections all belong in fied in the CSTh under (1.2) by reason of the relation of similitude
the important tradition of discussion instituted among grammarians existing between the sign and the signified. In the D.S., the signs in
from 1240 on. In terms close to Bacon’s, they distinguish for example this third category were characterized by the relation of cause and
three modes of expression of pain—a purely instinctive expression, effect linking the sign (smoke) to the signified (fire). Even here Bacon
by means of a cry; a completely conventional expression, by a word explains that this type of relation is not sufficient to ground a relation
or a sentence; and an expression intermediary between the two, by of signification, which would require, over and above the sign and
an interjection, which partakes at once of the “concept mode” and what it signifies, some one “for whom” it signifies (D.S., para. 6).
the “affect mode.” It is to be noted that this type of discussion is to This hesitation of Bacon’s concerning the relation of cause and effect
be found in some English writers, such as the Tractatus de grammatica can be compared once again to the exposition of Richard Fishacre.
which we will speak about below; and in some authentic works of He discusses it with regard to the relation of created things to their
Robert Kilwardby or in the later writings of anonymous authors which creator. Granting the priority of the relation of the sign to “what it
are conserved in Kilwardby’s manuscripts—all of which indicating signifies” above the relation of the sign “for whom” it signifies, Fishacre
the milieu in which Bacon developed.61* maintains that created things remain signs even if no one interprets
The last point which we mention is connected with the content them as such, a state of affairs he deplores moreover as being the
of the first category of signs (1). The signs of type (1.1) signify by case too often. One understands why Bacon, who inverses this pri­
virtue of a relationship of natural consequence. One recognizes here ority, was led to reject the relation of cause and effect as character­
everything the logic tradition calls “sign,” especially as in the Prior izing a certain type of sign. The real nature of the relation between
Analytics (70a6 sq.), the Sophistical Rejutations (167b9 sq.), and the Rhetoric the two poles of the sign, particularly cause and effect, is of little
(I, 1357a-b), where one finds the classic examples (e.g. if an animal importance. What is important is the intellect which recognizes this
has vigorous limbs it is because it is strong). One of the non-Aristotelian relation, that which is produced by means of the inferential signs
examples— “to wander often at night is a sign that one is a thief” mentioned above.
(.D.S., para. 4)—is to be found in Averroes’ paraphrase of Aristotle’s One needs to keep in mind the parts missing from this third section
Rhetoric, which, as we will see below, was probably known by Bacon. of the Opus maius, part three, whose contents are available to us thanks
The signs of the second category (1.2) are grounded in a relation of to the summary of the Opus tertium. In fact the complete section regard­
ing the application of the study of signs to theology is missing. The
61 See I. Rosier, La parole.. ., chs. 2 & 3; on the interjections, see J. Pinborg, fact that this study includes the study of the sacraments as signs only
“Inteijektionen und Naturlaute, Petrus Heliae und ein Problem der antiken und confirms the connections we mentioned with the work of theologians
mittelalterlichen Sprachphilosophie,” Classica et mediaevalia, 22 (1961), 117-138; on
the distinction between per modum affectus and per modum conceptus, see G. Nuchelmans, on this subject. But it covers other questions as well (cf. para. 2.3
“The distinction . . and I. Rosier, Ibid., ch. 5. supra). Perhaps certain theologians pondered these same questions, as
98 IRENE ROSIER-GATAGH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 99

is suggested by the interesting chapter of Henry of Ghent on divine et per viam narrationis, without demonstration but by simple description
names, which develops the Augustinian theory of the sign while intro­ of what is, true reflexive knowledge must leave this level behind to
ducing like Bacon some reflections on the relations between the differ­ reach the level of explanation per causas et rationes {Opus maius part four,
ent levels of meaning in exegesis or on the Adamic language, while Vol. 1, 100). Even if he seems to suggest sometimes that this gram­
not denying himself recourse to the reflections of the “artists.”62 The mar per rationes belongs to the study of grammar and that Priscian
analysis of Peter John Olivi on conventional signs is another indica­ furnished the relevant model, he says clearly elsewhere that this task
tion of these connections.63 The study of signs which Bacon under­ exceeds the domain of grammar and that it belongs to two other
takes in the conserved section of De signis where he tries to construct disciplines. The first is metaphysics. The grammarian should restrict
a general semantic and semiological doctrine on the basis of a tra­ himself to articulating properties substantial and general and to giv­
dition both theological and “artistic” was undoubtedly conceived ing the rules for the realization of such in the different languages
by Bacon as the theoretical section before being afterwards used {O.G.G., p. 142). The “pure grammarian” must not research the
for multiple theological ends. In the CSTh. for instance, after a very “causes” which would explain for example why there are only five
technical passage invoking Aristotle and Averroes on signification, he vowels {O.G.G., p. 58). Bacon opposes himself vigorously to the route
encourages his reader to become interested in the metaphorical locu­ taken by a certain treatise on grammar which had been attributed—
tions of the Scriptures, in the three levels of meaning operative there, without justification, as he demonstrates—to Aristotle. This treatise,
or in the signification of the sacraments and other sacred signs {CSTh, according to Bacon, begins its chapter on letters and sounds with an
para. 83). exposition of the movements of the heavenly bodies, to conclude by
showing that there are seven such movements and for that reason
seven vowels {O.G.G., pp. 57-59). The anonymous author of the Trac-
5. Conclusion tatus de grammatica does indeed set forth this concept, detailing how
the four premier vowels (a, u, i, o), which originate in the four kinds
The diversity and richness of Roger Bacon’s reflections on language is of simple celestial movements, are common to all speakers {omnes ser-
remarkable. It is somewhat difficult to gather them together in one well mocinantes), with it being otherwise in the case of the last three—e
expressed general idea. Nonetheless one can propose a few remarks being used only by the Latins, and e, v, and w by the Greeks.65 Not
in this sense, by way of a conclusion. only, says Bacon, is the conclusion false66 but above all it is not to a
We have already seen that for Bacon there were three successive treatise on grammar but to a treatise on metaphysics that he would
levels in the mastering of a language: to be able to read it and the go to study these “causes.” The Tractatus traces the diversity of
rudiments of grammar; the ability to translate; the ability to speak it vowels to the “diversity of complexions of mankind which vary as a
like one’s mother tongue. He seems to think that one cannot attain function of the climate, an idea which Bacon refers to frequently.67*
this third level by a purely grammatical method but rather by direct
contact with native speakers. He contrasts here natural “innate” knowl­ naturam, quae posterior est. Vocabula enim grammaticae et logicae discimus; sed
edge which every native speaker has of the grammar and logic of a naturaliter scimus componere orationes ex dictionibus et argumenta ex propositionibus.
Et hoc docet grammatica, et logica. . . . Quapropter de logica et grammatica non est
language with a reflective knowledge which is only attainable by the necessaria instructio humana nisi propter vocabula linguarum, quibus utimur in col-
very few.64 Going beyond elementary primers which proceed pueriliter latione facienda cum aliis, propter necessitatem scientiae. See also Quaestiones supra libros
prime Philosophiae Aristotelis, ed. Steele, 96-7; Communia mathematica, ed. Steele, 64—5.
65 Tractatus de grammatica, ed. K. Reichl, in Ibid., “Tractatus de grammatica” einejalschlich
62 Henry of Ghent, Summa quaestionum ordinarium, q. 73, ed. with study, I. Rosier, Robert Grosseteste zugeschriebene spekulatwe Grammatik (Miinchen: Schoningh, 1976), 19-21.
“Henri de Gand, le Dialectica d’Augustin, et l’imposition des noms divins,” in Documenti 66 One notices that Bacon is not always consistent, because elsewhere he clearly
e studi sulla tradizione jilosofica medievale vi (1995), 145-253. affirms that the Greek has seven vowels, which are reduced to four according to the
63 See F. Delorme, “Question de P.J. Olivi ‘Quid ponat ius vel dominium’ ou principal sound (Opus maius, part three, ed. Bridges, Vol. Ill, ch. iii, 92; CSPh., ch. ix,
encore ‘De signis voluntariis’”, Antonianum xx (1945), 309-330. 499).
64 Op. tert., ch. xxviii, 104—105: Et Avicenna dicit, in logica sua, quod rusticus 67 Tractatus de grammatica, ed. Reichl, 21:1-9: Sunt igitur in universo differencie
Arabicus scit grammaticam per naturam; quod oportet, si logicam sciamus per motus simpliciter 7 iuxta quas 7 prime differencie vocis simpliciter sumuntur, iuxta
100 IRENE ROSIER-CATACH ROGER BACON AND GRAMMAR 101

This example, with its important methodological implications, is not Cassiodorus, Bede, and above all on Augustine’s De musicaT He like­
the only reference in Bacon to the Tractatus de grammatica. In point of wise invokes the Poetics and the Rhetoric of Aristotle, along with the
fact, the Tractatus explicitly claims to be doing grammar modo metaphyske, Commentaries of Averroes,72 and also the De scientiis of Al-Farabi,73 who
thus exceeding the limits of the discipline.68 Bacon on the other hand had assigned to the speculative part of music the task of “giving the
explicitly refuses this position, arguing by contrast that an elementary reasons and the causes of everything which underlies harmony,” espe­
discipline should remain within the bounds of its proper limits (Op. cially as it is operative in metrical composition.7475Bacon views here
tert., ch. xvi, 57). In the same way Bacon finds fault with scholars discourse in all its dimensions, starting with the preliminary combi­
who introduce into a grammar these concepts belonging to disci­ nation of vowels and syllables, which is part of elementary grammar,
plines which will only be studied later in the curriculum, and this is upto semantic content, which is determined by its rhythmical and
the procedure adopted by the author of the Tractatus, who begins his prosodic qualities as well as by the gestures and the positions of the
exposition with a classification of the sciences. This connection be­ body accompanying the enunciation. These said dimensions come
tween Bacon and the Tractatus is noteworthy, all the more because one together towards the formation of what Bacon calls the poetic argu­
of the manuscripts containing the Tractatus is the celebrated Oxford ment, which he deals with in the fifth treatise of his Phibsophia moralis.15
Digby 55, which preserves the De signis. And because the Tractatus When we remember that music arises out of the science of quantities,
probably comes from the circle of Robert Grosseteste.69
But it is above all to music that he assigns the “causes and reasons”
huius scientiae; Ibid., ch. lx-lxiv, 243-268, ch. lxxv, 306-9; O.G.G., 96-7. On this
of phenomena which grammar does no more than describe—the “reduction” of grammar and logic to music, see Jeremiah M.G. Hackett, “Moral
length and accents of letters and syllables, the processes of prosody, Philosophy. . .,” 31-35 and 99-102.
71 Opus maius, part four, ed. Bridges, Vol. I, 237-238: Augustinus reducit metra et
metre and rhythm which underly compositions in sound. “The gram­ pedes et hujusmodi ad musicalia. Cf. Augustine, De musica, II, 1-2, PL 32, 1099ff.
marian is to the musician as the carpenter is to the geometer.” The The other sources are analysed by E. Massa, Ruggero Bacone. .., 167, n. 17.
“mechanical” work of the grammarian is not to be compared with 72 Phil. Mor., V, 263: Liber autem Aristotelis de argumento poetico non est
translatus, set exposicio eius per Avenrois et quedam aha reperiuntur in latino, ut
the musician’s, which is “the principal artisan.”7071It should be noted patet ex libro Alpharabii De scienciis et ex Logicis Avicenne et Algazelis; cf. also Phil,
that Bacon relies here on a number of authorities such as Isidore, mor., VI, 267. One knows that the Rhetoric of Aristotle was first translated perhaps by
Bartholomew of Messina (translatio vetus). It was little used. A second, based on the
Arabic, and accompanied by the Commentary of Averroes, was made by Hermannus
quas 7 vocales sumuntur: a, u, i, o, e, v, w. Quorum 4 primorum omnes sermocinantes Alemannus in 1246. And finally that by William of Moerbecke, based on the Greek,
utuntur que a 4 speciebus mutus simplicis sumuntur. Ceteris vero tribus, e, v, w, non in 1270. The Poetics was translated from the Greek by William of Moerbecke in
utuntur omnes, sed quidam quibusdam ut latini e in lingua latina, greci vero in 1278, and Bacon could not have known the text directly. In contrast, he knew the
lingua sua omnibus. Et hec diversitas a diversitate naturalis complexionis hominum translation of the Middle Commentary of Averroes on the Poetics, translated from
est secundum diversitates climatum. Unde greci proferendo v magis tangunt naturam the Arabic by Hermannus Alemannus in 1256, which explains the passage above.
[z] quam a, cum tamen v sit media inter a et i. He himself stated that the translator himself told him that he declined to translate
68 Ibid., 17:31-32: Excedendo igitur artis metas et sciencie terminos dicendum est the Poetics after the Rhetoric because he lacked a knowledge of logic {Phil, mor., VI,
de natura vocis et omnis soni modo metaphysico. 267-8-26), his confession of failure appearing, along with other justifications as well,
69 Ibid., 105-113. in the preface to the commentary of Hermann to his translation of the Commen­
70 Opus menus, part four, ed. Bridges, Vol. I, 237: Sed musicae est dare causas et tary of Averroes (ed. L. Minio-Paluello, A.L. 33 [Paris-Bruxelles, 1968], 51). Bacon
rationes horum, licet grammaticus doceat, quia est de his. Praeterea tota pronuntiatio points out also that this latter translation was little used in his times, especially by
scripturae consistit penes accentus, longitudines, et brevitates, et penes cola, commata, the Artists {Phil, mor., V, 251:15-18, 255:24—30). O n this topic, see E. Massa, Ruggero
periodos; et haec omnia pertinent causaliter ad musicam, quia horum omnium musicus Bacone, pp. 137-143 and the study of G. Dahan, “Notes and T e x ts .. . ”, esp. pp.
dicit propter quid, grammaticus vero quia est tantum. Sic enim auctores philosophiae 173-75, 181-2, 191-92; O n Phibsophia Moralis and rhetoric, see Hackett, “Moral
determinant, et Augustinus in musicalibus de his determinat; Op. tert., ch. lix, 231: Philosophy. . .” and Rosier-Catach, “Roger Bacon, Al-Farabi.. . .”
Ergo grammaticus, qui per viam narrationis laborat, cui dem onstrate non pertinet, 73 Opus maius, part four, ed. Bridges, Vol. I, 238; Op. tert., ch. lxiv, 266, ch. lxxv,
non dabit causas istorum, sed solum quia sic sunt, et sic habent fieri. Ergo grammati­ 305; Phil, mor., v, 263.
cus se habet ad musicum, sicut carpentator ad geometricum. Et ideo grammaticus 74 Liber Alfarabii de scientiis, ed. cit., 154, see also 139-140 on poetics. Cf. Dominicus
est mechanicus in hac parte, et musicus est artifex principalis. Quapropter sufficiens Gundisalinus, De scientiis, ed. cit., 107.
et principalis cognitio, scilicet quae est per causas et rationes, non habetur per 75 Op. tert., ch. lxiv, 266-67, Phil, mor., ch. v, 254—55, 258-61; See E. Massa,
grammaticam, sed per hanc scientiam; et hoc manifestum est ex libris antiquorum Ruggero Bacone. . ., 127ff.; 148ff.; 155ff.: see Jeremiah Hackett below.
102 IRENE ROSIER-GATACH

that is mathematics, we begin to see how substantial was Bacon’s


rearranging of the traditional framework of the trivium by placing
grammar under music. 5. RO GER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE
We see here the break that Bacon makes with the type of gram­
mar taught at the university since the first half of the thirteenth century Alain De Libera
and particularly in the years 1267—68 when he was writing his Opera.
And yet, as we said in our first section, he was still following the
speculative mode of doing grammar when he wrote, like a good “art­ Relativement abondante, l’oeuvre logique de Bacon n’est pas pour
ist,” his Summa grammatica, borrowing from various treatises of Aristotle autant comparable a celle de ses contemporains artiens ou theolo-
in order to explicate the rationes behind regular and figurative construc­ giens. Elle ne comporte aucun commentaire de VOrganon, contraire-
tions, all the while using the demonstration methods of the quaestio ment par exemple a l’oeuvre de Robert Kilwardby.1 En outre, dans
disputata. sa dimension proprement universitaire, elle est liee aux formes litte-
What connects perhaps the Summa grammatica with the three sections raires les plus anciennes pratiquees a Paris ou a Oxford: les recueils
of the third part of the Opus maius, as well as with elaborations and de distinctions et les sommes, et elle n’aborde pas le domaine des
parallel developments in other works of Roger Bacon’s is this vision questions disputees. Son importance est neanmoins considerable tant
of language apprehended in its concrete functioning, situated in time dans l’histoire de la logique en general que pour ce qui concerne sa
and space, always being seen in its intersubjective dimension, whether place et sa fonction dans l’oeuvre de Bacon lui-meme. On peut,
it is a question of the reader/interpreter before the text, sacred or grossierement, distinguer deux periodes dans la production logique
profane, of the “author”, of the priest before the faithful or of the baconienne: une premiere, qui le fait contemporain des premieres
preacher about to “persuade” the unfaithful. In these matters the grandes realisations de la Logica modemorum, c’est celle de la Summa de
Augustinian heritage, especially that of the De doctrina Christiana, is sophismatibus et distinctionibus (= SSD)2 et des Summulae dialectices {— SD);3
always present.76 This conception of language is assuredly in conformity une seconde, qui, avec le De signis {= DS)4 et son produit derive le
with his ideal of a sapientia which aims not only at speculation but Compendium studii theologm (= GST)5 s’inscrit dans un univers plus origi­
much more at action,77 a sapientia which touches not only the intellect nal, celui des projets de reforme de la societe chretienne par la reforme
but also the feelings, and which has as its goal the perfection of man du savoir chretien, ou BacQn met toute son energie et ses espoirs,
as a whole. All the elements which together give speech its value celui aussi de l’universite de la seconde moitie du XIIIe siecle, pro-
and effectiveness are viewed in the context of a hierarchy which begins fondement transformee par l’apparition de courants nouveaux—tel
with grammar to culminate in music or poetry, passing through the
stages of logic and rhetoric {Op. tert., ch. lxxv, 307-308). The analysis 1 Cf. P.O. Lewry, O.P., Robert LCilwardby’s writings on the Logica vetus, diss., Oxford,
begins with the simplest constitutive physical elements, letters, signs, 1978. Sur la semantique de Kilwardby, cf. P.O. Lewry O.P., “Robert Kilwardby on
Meaning: A Parisian Course on the Logica Vetus1’, in Sprache und Erkenntnis im Mittelalter,
sentence; proceeds to the description of the various arguments, dia­ J.P. Beckmann et al., ed., Miscellanea Medievalia 13/1, Berlin, Walter De Gruyter,
lectic and rhetorical; and culminates with the integration of the differ­ 1981, p. 376-384.
ent parameters which one might call the “enunciatives”—intonation, 2 Cf. Summa de sophismatibus et distinctionibus, ed. R. Steele, Opera Hactenus Inedita
Roigeri Baconi, XIV, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1937.
gesture, the mental disposition of the speaker and his underlying 3 Cf. Summube dialectices I—II, ed. A. de Libera, “Les Summube dialectices de Roger
intention, the state of the world and the disposition of the heavens. Bacon. I.-II. De Termino. De enuntiatione”, AHDLMA., 53 (1986), p. 139-289; Summube
dialectices III, ed. A. de Libera, “Les Summube dialectices de Roger Bacon. III. De
argumentatione”, AHDLMA., 54 (1987), p. 171-278
76 Cf. Among other references, Op. tert., 305. 4 Cf. De signis, ed. K.M. Fredborg, L. Nielsen & J. Pinborg, “An Unedited Part
77 Cf. Opus maius, part two, ed. Bridges, Vol. Ill, 76: tota philosophia speculativa of Roger Bacon’s Opus maius: De signis”, Traditw, 34 (1978), p. 75-136. Le DS etant,
ordinatur in finem suum, qui est philosophia moralis. On the relations between the comme on le sait, un fragment de YOpus maius, on peut le dater des annees 1267.
Scientia speculativa and the Scientia practica, in the Phibsophia moralis, see Jeremiah Hackett, 5 Cf. Compendium Studii Theobgbe, ed. Th. S. Maloney, (Studien und Texte zur
“Moral Philosophy . . .”, 24ff. Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters, 20), Leiden-Koln, Brill, 1988.
104 ALAIN DE LIBERA ROGER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE 105

le modisme6—et la place croissante prise par les theologiens dans annoncee par H.A.G. Braakhuis. La situation est encore plus incer-
l’elaboration des doctrines semantiques, la philosophic du langage et taine s’agissant de la seconde oeuvre attribute parfois a Roger Bacon:
la logique. le traite contenu dans le manuscrit d’Amiens, Bibl. mun. 406, connu
L’exceptionnelle longevite de la carriere intellectuelle de Bacon fait sous le titre d’Opus puerorum.10*Ce traite sur les syncategoremes, qui
que son oeuvre logique reflete a peu de chose pres l’ensemble de integre un certain nombre de regies, de distinctions, de questions et
revolution du siecle.7 II y a en elle de quoi la rapprocher de Guillaume de sophismes, est transmis par peciae (ce qui indique une diffusion
de Sherwood ou des plus modestes Text-books d’Oxford aussi bien universitaire). Comme il est contenu dans la manuscrit qui livre les
que des speculations les plus complexes d’un Henri de Gand sur la Questions parisiennes de Bacon sur la philosophic naturelle d’Aristote,
classification des signes ou des discussions d’un Duns Scot ou d’un on peut etre tente de le lui attribuer egalement. Mais rien dans le
Pierre Jean Olieu sur la reference vide. texte ni dans le manuscrit n’incite a le faire—a commencer par les
Telle qu’elle se presente aujourd’hui, l’ceuvre authentique de Bacon indications donnees a chaque changement de piece, qui font inva-
comprend, on vient de le voir, quatre litres. C ’est sur ces oeuvres riablement reference a un certain “maitre p.h.” (e.g. f. 130ra: Pnma
que nous fixerons notre attention. II faut neanmoins rappeler, pour pecia magjstri p.h). En outre, comme on va le voir, l’ouvrage ferait
memoire, que d’autres textes lui ont ete attribues par les historiens. nettement double emploi avec la SSD, qui presente la meme struc­
II y a d’abord un traite sur les syncategoremes, contenu a la fois ture et la meme fonction.
dans un des manuscrits des Summulae dialectices (le ms. Oxford, Bodleian
Library, Digby 204) et un manuscrit d ’Erfurt (Amplon. Q 328).
Toutefois, si N. Kretzmann penche pour l’attribution a Roger Bacon,8 La Summa de sophismatibus et distinctionibus
H.A.G. Braakhuis, qui a donne de nombreux extraits de l’oeuvre
dans son etude sur la litterature des Syncategoremata au XIIT siecle La SSD, dont une partie a ete editee en 1937 par R. Steele d’apres le
soutient, comme L.M. De Rijk, une autre candidature: celle du domini- manuscrit incomplet d’Oxford, Bodleian Library, Digby 67 (f. 117ra-
cain d’Oxford, Robert Bacon.9 Une attribution de ces Syncategoremata 124vb), est preservee plus extensivement dans un manuscrit d’Erfurt,
a Roger Bacon n ’est pas totalement exclue—de fait, les Summulae Amplon., F. 135 (f. 60r-85vb), lui-meme helas incomplet. Aucune
dialectices font elles-memes clairement allusion a un traite de ce genre copie integrate de cette oeuvre, qui remonte, semble-t-il, aux annees
(SD, 2.1.3, § 163-164: “In Syncategorematicis magis patebit hoc”) a propos 1240-1245, n’a ete jusqu’ici retrouvee. La SSD appartient a un genre
d’une distinction entre deux modes de disiunctio (entre termes et entre litteraire qui a connu une vogue certaine a Paris, dans la premiere
phrases), dont on retrouve effectivement la trace dans les Syncategoremata moitie du XIIIe siecle, les Distinctiones sophismatum, dont il existe beau-
attribues par Braakhuis a Robert Bacon. En outre, il existe divers coup de temoins: le Tractatus de distinctionibus communibus in sophismatibus
paralleles textuels entre les deux oeuvres, que nous avons nous-memes accidentibus attribue a Matthieu d’Orleans, les Distinctiones e(JVotandum”,n
signales (Libera 1986: 157-160). On ne saurait, cependant, tirer de qui ont peut-etre servi de base aux Abstractiones d’Hervaeus Sophista,
conclusion valable avant de disposer de l’edition critique du texte les traites De multiplicitatibus circa orationes accidentibus, De solutionibus
sophismatum et De communibus distinctionibus, tous trois edites par L.M.
De Rijk,12 ainsi que plusieurs traites anonymes egalement decrits par
6 Cf. C. Marmo, Semiotka e linguaggio nella scolastica: ParigL, Bologna, Erfurt 1270—
1330. La semiotka dei Modisti, Rome, Istituto Storico Italiano per il Medioevo, 1994.
7 Pour un panorama general, cf. S. Ebbesen, ed., Sprachtheorien in Spatantike und
Mittelalter (Geschichte der Sprachtheorie), Tubingen, Gunter Narr Verlag, 1995. 10 Sur cette oeuvre, cf. H.A.G. Braakhuis, De 13de Eeuwse Tractaten.. ., p. 411
8 Cf. N. Kretzmann, “Syncategoremata, Exponibilia, Sophismata”, in The Cambridge 412, n. 9.
History of Later Mediaeval Philosophy, ed. N. Kretzmann, A. Kenny & J. Pinborg, Cam­ 11 C f Anonyme, Distinctiones Parisienses “Notandum”, ed. A. de Libera, in Cesar et le
bridge, Cambridge University Press, 1982, p. 221-222, n. 41. Phenix, Distinctiones et sophismata parisiens du XLLLe siecle (Centro di cultura medievale,
9 Cf. H.A.G. Braakhuis, De 13 de Eeuwse Tractaten over syncategorematische termen: Lnlei- IV), Pise, Scuola Normale superiore-Florence, Opus libri, 1991.
dende studie en uitgave van Mcolaas van Parijs’ Sincategoreumata, Dissertation, Leiden, 1979, 12 C f L.M. De Rijk, Some Earlier Parisian Tracts on Distinctiones sophismatum (Artis-
p. 106-111. tarium, 7), Nijmegen, Ingenium Publishers, 1988.
106 ALAIN DE LIBERA ROGER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE 107

De Rijk et H.A.G. Braakhuis. Bien qu’il soit assez difficile de distin- dans des propositions contenant plusieurs syncategoremes ou plusieurs
guer clairement entre Distinctiones, Sophismata13 et Syncategoremata,H on quantificateurs.15 On appelle normalement inclusio la relation de subor­
peut, a titre heuristique, poser que les Distinctiones ont pour objet dination syntactico-semantique existant entre deux syncategoremes a
d’inventorier les regies utilisees dans la pratique des sophismata et de l’interieur d’une phrase. Par extension, toutefois, l’inclusion designe
dresser la carte de leur application, tandis que les Syncategoremata ont aussi toute relation de subordination existant entre termes exergant
pour fonction de decrire pour chaque categorie de syncategoremes, une certaine fonction (officium) dans une phrase—que ces dktianes officiates
definie sur la base de proprietes specifiques, l’ensemble des condi­ soient ou non des syncategoremes. Un terme “inclus” est done un
tions dans lesquelles chacun de ces termes peut exercer ces proprie­ terme pris dans le champ d’un autre terme, quels qu’ils soient.16 Face
tes et Pensemble des conditions qui font que, dans certains cas, il en aux propositions susceptibles de deux interpretations, l’une selon le
est empeche. La SSD semble occuper une position intermediaire entre sens compose, l’autre le sens divise—comme omne animal est rationale
les deux genres: comme les Distinctiones, c’est un recueil de regies vel irrationale qui peut etre interpretee soit comme une proposition de
classees d’apres les syncategoremes qui y figurent; comme dans les predicat disjoint, dans le sens (compose) de “Tout animal est dote de
Syncategoremata, les regies sont censees exprimer les proprietes syntaxi- raison ou depourvu de raison”, soit comme une disjonction de proposi­
ques et semantiques des termes syncategorematiques. tions, dans le sens (divise) de “Tout animal est dote de raison ou Tout
L’essentiel du texte actuel de la SSD est consacre aux problemes animal est depourvu de raison”17—, les logiciens du XIIIe siecle sou-
de quantification universelle, il prend done pour principal fil conduc­ tiennent en general une theorie du sens naturel, selon laquelle
t e d le syncategoreme omnis. Dans la version d’Erfurt (a partir du l’ordre d’occurrence des termes d’une phrase (leur ordre d’enoncia-
f. 73vb), Bacon passe a l’examen d’autres problemes lies au reste des tion, ordo prolationis) constitue une information semantique sur cette
syncategoremes, mais non sans remarquer que “beaucoup de choses phrase, du fait que la structure logique des phrases est representee
dites a propos d’omnis peuvent s’appliquer aux autres signes” soit dans l’ordre lineaire des constituants des enonces realises et que ce
directement soit a contrario (par exemple, omnis “exige trois objets de qui vient en premier dans l’enonciation determine (“inclut”) neces-
reference, tria appellata, de la part du terme” qu’il quantifie, mais pas sairement ce qui vient en second (ce qui, dans l’exemple precedent,
uterque, ambo, etc.). Dans la suite, il s’attache done uniquement aux present automatiquement une interpretation de sens compose).
signes qui presentent des difficultes propres (c’est le cas de infinita, de Parmi les differentes theories qui contestent la doctrine du sens
totns, puis des “signes negatifs”). naturel, celle de Bacon presente une originalite incontestable. Plutot
La SSD ne presente pas d’originalite dans les matieres abordees: que d’essayer de justifier naturellement le rapport d’inclusion existant
son genre litteraire meme l’interdit, qui consiste a mettre en question entre deux syncategoremes (ou quantificateurs) dans une phrase rea-
des regies courantes. Elle est, en revanche, souvent audacieuse dans lisee, Bacon axe sa reflexion sur le rapport entre l’intention de signifier
le traitement qu’elle leur reserve. Elle contient, notamment, des vues du locuteur, la forme linguistique ou elle s’exprime et le sens que lui
tres neuves sur la notion d’inclusio, couramment utilisee dans la logique attribue l’auditeur. L’articulation des trois est foumie par la notion
terministe pour rendre compte des phenomenes de scope intervenant
15 Cf. A. de Libera, “Suppositio et inclusio dans les theories medievales de la refe­
rence”, in La reference. Actes du Colloque de Saint-Cloud, Ecole Normale Superieure de Saint-
13 Cf. A. de Libera, “La litterature des Sophismata dans la tradition terministe Cloud, 12-13 octobre 1984, ed. par L. Danon-Boileau et A. de Libera, Paris, Ophrys,
parisienne de la seconde moitie du X IIIe siecle”, in The Editing of Theological and 1987, p. 9-34.
Philosophical Texts from the Middle Ages, Acts of the Conference Arranged by the 16 Cf., a ce sujet, A. de Libera, “La logique medievale comme logique naturelle
Department of Classical Languages, University of Stockholm, 29-31 August 1984, (Sprachlogik): vues medievales sur l’ambiguite”, in Sprachphilosophie in Antike und Mit-
ed. by M. Asztalos (Studia Latina Stockholmiensa XXX), Stockholm, Almquist & telalter, Bochumer Kolloquium, 2-4 Juni 1982, Hrsg. von B. Mojsisch (Bochumer
Wiksell, 1986, p. 213-244. Studien zur Philosophic 3), Amsterdam, Griiner, 1986, p. 403—437.
14 Cf. A. de Libera, “La litterature des Abstractions et la tradition logique d’Oxford”, 17 Sur la theorie medievale du sens compose/divise, cf. N. Kretzmann, “Sensus
in The Rise of British Logica. 6th European Symposium on Medieval Logic and Semantics, compositus, Sensus divisus, and Propositional Attitudes”, Medioevo, 1 (1981), p. 195-229.
Balliol College, Oxford 19-24 juin 1983, ed. by O. Lewry O.P. (Papers in Mediaeval Cf., egalement, M.L. Rivero, “William of Sherwood on Composition and Division”,
Studies 7, Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies), Toronto, 1985, p. 63-114. Historiographia linguistica, 3 (1976), p. 17-36.
108 ALAIN DE LIBERA ROGER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE 109

d’“engendrement du discours” (generatio sermonis)}8 La these centrale Facile a saisir dans une perspective centree sur le pole recepteur
de la SSD est double: (a) une enonciation doit normalement etre dans l’acte de communication, la theorie de Bacon presente plus
consideree comme porteuse d’un certain nombre d’indications permet- de difficultes pour qui la considere du point de vue du pole emet-
tant a l’auditeur de lui associer une interpretation correspondant a teur. Il ne fait pas de doute, pourtant, que, pour Bacon, la notion
l’intention de signifier du locuteur; (b) toutefois, ces indications ne d’engendrement du discours qui fait de toute proposition mentale
suffisent pas toujours pour retrouver ce vouloir-dire et meme, dans une interpretation vaut aussi bien pour le locuteur que pour Pauditeur.
certains cas, elles y font obstacle, dans la mesure ou la forme linguis- En posant que toute proposition mentale est une interpretation,
tique de l’enonce, specialement Pagencement des mots, ne reflete pas e’est-a-dire l’intellection d’un intellect “qui analyse (= decode) ou qui
directement la pensee du locuteur. Dans sa propre conception de engendre (= encode)”, Bacon souligne clairement que la signification
l’inclusion, fondee sur le parallelisme entre les donnees des sens et d’une phrase est toujours ou construite ou deduite par une intellec­
Interpretation semantique, Bacon soutient que ce qui vient en pre­ tion. Si la notion d’engendrement du discours n’est pas suffisamment
mier dans une phrase est normalement inclus par ce qui vient en elaboree pour permettre de formuler une theorie d’ensemble des meca-
second—puisque si Pon veut degager un sens naturel des phrases, il nismes par lesquels “l’intellect qui juge, engendre” un sens dans l’esprit
est plus naturel de considerer que ce qui est premier est determine du locuteur “a partir d’elements simples” (les syncategoremes et les
par ce qui est second (comme, dans la nature, la matiere est deter- categoremes), tandis que celui “qui analyse”, le “resout” dans l’esprit
minee par la forme). Au niveau du discours profere, en tant que tel, de Pauditeur “en distinguant ses elements”, elle place, d’une maniere
le premier syncategoreme (ou quantificateur) est done toujours inclus nouvelle, la reflexion semantique sur le terrain de l’interlocution en
par le second. Les caracteres qui determinent la proferation du dis­ attirant l’attention sur une serie de phenomenes laisses dans l’ombre
cours ne suffisent pas pour autant a determiner la signification de la par les autres theories. Surtout, elle noue de maniere originale le
phrase: ils ne livrent pas automatiquement Pintention de signification probleme de l’adequation entre forme linguistique et sens exprime,
du locuteur. Pour acceder a Yintentio proferentis il faut faire intervenir en obligeant a considerer ensemble le sens produit par Pagencement
la notion d’engendrement du discours. des constituants d’un enonce, le sens conforme a Pintention du locu­
Telle que Pexpose Bacon, la theorie de la generatio sermonis soutient teur et les actes d’interpretation (encodage, decodage) effectues par
(a) que la proferation d’une phrase etant accidentelle, formalite et deux sujets linguistiques a la fois egalement fibres, egalement raison-
materialite n’y ont qu’un sens relatif; (b) que l’ordre lineaire d’une nables et supposes egalement sinceres, dans une situation d’inter-
phrase ne contient pas, pour Pauditeur, toute Pinformation sur sa locution. S’il est vrai que e’est dans la Summa grammatica que les
forme logique; (c) que seul l’ordre dans lequel ont ete effectuees les relations entre contraintes naturelles regissant Pagencement des cons­
operations mentales du locuteur precedant la realisation acoustique tituants d’une phrase et construction des sens dependant de la liberte
de la phrase permet de distinguer entre le materiel (inclusum) et le et de la volonte des locuteurs sont le mieux theorisees {Summa, 24,
formel (includens) et ainsi d’assigner une forme logique a la proposi­ 6-15), on peut done dire que, malgre les limitations du genre litte-
tion mentale qui constitue son sens (intentio proferentis). Ainsi done la raire d’un recueil de Distinctiones sophismatum, la SSD engage une
theorie de la generatio sermonis permet de poser que toute phrase pro- reflexion logique decisive sur la triple determination de la dimension
feree est le resultat d’une serie d’operations effectuees dans l’esprit interlocutoire—liberte du locuteur et de Pauditeur, nature de la lan-
du locuteur, que Pauditeur doit conjecturer puis interpreter a partir gue, contraintes de la communication—qui prepare la theorisation
du contexte extra-linguistique ou du contexte communicationnel, pour plus aboutie du De signis et du Compendium studii theobgiae.
comprendre la phrase dans le sens voulu par le locuteur.

Les Summulae dialectices


18 Sur cette notion, cf. I. Rosier & A. de Libera, “Intention de signifier et engen-
drement du discours chez Roger Bacon”, Histoire, Epistemologie, Langage, 8 /2 (1986), Les Summulae dialectices, transmises par deux manuscrits (Oxford,
p. 63-79. Bodleian Library, Digby 204, f. 48-75v; Seville, Biblioteca Capitular
110 ALAIN DE LIBERA ROGER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE 111

Columbina 5-2-40, f. 68ra-120vb), ont ete longtemps d’attribution contemporains aux donnees de YAristoteles novus et des ecrits naturels
contestee,19 mais la patemite de Roger Bacon n ’est plus aujourd’hui arabes (il semble connaitre le De congelatione et conglutinatione lapidum
discutee. C ’est probablement d’ailleurs a elles que Bacon fait allusion d’Avicenne et le De plantis de Nicolas de Damas, auquel il emprunte
quand, dans le Compendium studii theologiae, il evoque les problemes de la description de Yambragyon, arbuste intermediaire entre l’herbe et
semantique des termes qu’il dit avoir traites “plus de quarante ans l’arbre; ailleurs il s’etend sans raison imperieuse sur la theorie aristo-
auparavant”. Bien qu’il soit difficile de les dater, on peut tenir pour telicienne de la “double exhalaison” ou introduit une distinction entre
vraisemblable qu’elles ont ete redigees dans les annees 1250, a Oxford. divers types d’etoiles filantes, reprenant le mot arabe assuhub, emprunte
Le titre de Summulae dialectices, qui a prevalu depuis R. Steele, son a la version arabo-latine des Meteorologiques). Cette erudition, un peu
premier editeur, n’est pas des plus heureux. Le contenu reel de l’oeuvre ostentatoire, montre que l’auteur des SD n’est pas un simple “dialec-
est plus exactement exprime par celui que donne le ms. de Seville: ticien”, mais un philosophe interesse par les nouveaux savoirs aristo-
Summula super totam logicam. II s’agit bien, en effet, d’un traitement teliciens. Tout en plongeant leurs racines logiciennes dans l’univers
complet de la logique, dont le plan presente une originalite incontes­ oxonien, les SD sont done aussi a la fois impregnees de la culture
table par rapport aux oeuvres concurrentes d’un Pierre d’Espagne ou des maitres es arts parisiens, comme le montre la presence insistante
d’un Guillaume de Sherwood.20 Adoptant l’agencement des matieres de themes couramment developpes dans les Introductions a la phibsophie21*
de VOrganon, selon un regroupement tripartite fonde sur l’ordre de des artistes parisiens des annees 1250 (c’est le cas, par exemple, de
composition croissant “terme”-“enonciation”-“argumentation”, Bacon la classification des arts proposee dans le ms. de Seville) et riches de
innove, en outre, en plagant l’etude des proprietes des termes (suppositio, la culture accumulee par Bacon durant ses annees d’etude des ecrits
appellatio, copulatio) a la fin de l’etude de l’enonciation, car la suppo­ naturels d’Aristote. Ce n’est pas la, cependant, que reside l’interet
sition est exclusivement, pour lui, une propriety intrapropositionnelle principal des SD, mais dans les vues semantiques originales qu’elles
des termes categorematiques—une these caracteristique de l’“approche develpppent sur les proprietes des termes.
contextuelle” regnant a Oxford. Un des axes principaux de la semantique des SD est la contro-
La pregnance de l’univers oxonien est sensible d’un bout a l’autre verse sur Yappellatio unwoca, e’est-a-dire sur la possibility pour un terme
de roeuvre. Les SD n’etant pas un simple manuel, mais une sorte de s’appliquer univoquement a un etant et a un non-etant. Ce pro-
d’adaptation d’un ou de plusieurs manuels preexistants, a quoi elles bleme que Bacon a toujours considere comme l’un des plus fonda-
ajoutent maintes digressions, commentaires et questions diverses, on mentaux de la semantique, au point, comme on le verra, d’y revenir
doit, en effet, souligner que beaucoup de lemmes repris par Bacon de maniere insistante dans toute l’oeuvre de sa maturite (du De signis
ont des paralleles dans les Text-Books d’Oxford (Logica Cum sit nostra, au Compendium studii theologiae), est aborde de maniere detaiUee dans
Logica Ut dicit) et que certains developpements plus construits sem- les SD. Contre la sententia communis affirmant la possibility d’une telle
blent empruntes a des contemporains anglais (c’est le cas par exem- reference univoque ad entia et non entia, Bacon accumule, des les SD,
ple du Commentaire sur les Sophistici Elenchi de Robert Kilwardby ou de une batterie d’arguments qu’il reprendra ensuite, en les perfection-
sa source). Scientifique, Bacon fait une part bien plus large que ses nant et les adaptant au nouveau contexte intellectuel. Le plus cons­
tant est le recours a l’autorite d’Aristote, dans la Metaphysique, I, 9,
992b 12-15, lue a la lumiere du commentaire d’Averroes (Metaph. II,
19 Cf. L.M. De Rijk, Logica Modemorum I I / 1: The Origin and Early Development of the comm. 46, f. 25vL): un terme nomme seulement des choses presen-
Theory of Supposition, Assen, 1967, Van Gorcum, p. 168, 173 et 445. tes, car rien n’est commun a l’etant et au non-etant ou bien a un
20 Cf. Pierre d’Espagne, Tractatus callaed afterwards “Summulae logicales”, ed. L.M. De present, un passe et un futur (cf. SD, § 526-527; DS, 4.1, ed. Fredborg
Rijk, Assen, Van Gorcum, 1972; Guillaume de Sherwood, Introductiones in Logicam;
ed. Ch. H. Lohr, P. Kunze & B. Mussler, in “William of Sherwood. Introductiones in
Logicam. Critical Text”, Traditio, 39 (1983), p. 222-299. Sur l’originalite du plan des
SD, cf. Th. Maloney, “The Summule dialectices of Roger Bacon and the Summulist 21 Sur cette litterature et ses themes, cf. Cl. Lafleur, Quatre introductions a la Phib­
form”, in L. Brind’Amour et E. Vance, ed., Archeologie du signe (Papers in Medieval sophie au X lIT specie. Textes critiques et etude hisbrique, Montreal-Paris, Universite de
Studies, 3), Toronto, Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1983, p. 235-249. Montreal-Vrin, 1988.
112 ALAIN DE LIBERA ROGER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE 113

§ 134—135, p. 125; CST, ed. Maloney, § 88, p. 88). Dans les SD, la une supposition intrapropositionnelle reduite d’elle-meme aux seuls
these de Bacon sur la nomination est exprimee dans le langage de presents, de par sa signification et son imposition originaire, mais
1’“appellation”. Les SD, 2.2, § 526-527 (ed. de Libera), presentent la susceptible d’etre amplifiee (ampliatio) aux passes ou aux futurs par le
controverse sous la forme d’une duplex sententia de appellatione: “Quidam temps verbal.
dicunt, quod terminus appellat de se appellata praesentia, praeterita Au couple parisien de la supposition naturelle et de la restriction,23
et futura, et est communis entibus et non entibus. Alii dicunt, quod Bacon substitue done la suppositio de se pro praesentibus intraproposi­
terminus est solum nomen praesentium, et nihil est commune end et tionnelle et l’amplification. Ce retournement complet des bases de la
non end, sive praeterito, praesenti et futuro, secundum quod dicit semantique n’est pas sans equivalent. En quelques passages, Guillaume
Anstoteles in I Metaphysicae”. C ’est seulement en analysant la these de Sherwood semble lui aussi rejeter la supposition naturelle au
des partisans de l’univocite que Bacon recourt a la notion de suppositio, benefice de la suppositio de se pro praesentibus,24256 C ’est, toutefois, chez
quand il mentionne la regie sur laquelle s’appuient ses adversaires Bacon que la these est formulee le plus nettement et qu’elle est tiree
(§ 529): “Terminus non restrictus ad non-praesentes supponens verbo jusque dans ses dernieres consequences. L’une de ces consequences
de praesenti non habenti vim ampliandi in propositione affirmativa remarquables est la these selon laquelle “la necessite d’une proposi­
supponit tantum pro praesentibus, ut ‘Homo est’, ‘Caesar est.’” On tion ne s’etend pas au-dela de l’existence du sujet” (SD, 3.1.4., § 222-
peut etre tente de distinguer entre la these un peu archaique selon 224), qui, reprenant apparemment un theoreme bien connu d’Aris-
laquelle un nom appelle (appellat) aussi bien des presents, des passes tote (De interpretation, 9, 19a23-24), implique en realite le rejet de
et des futurs et la these, plus moderne, selon laquelle un terme sup­ propositions comme Omnis homo de necessitate est animal, homine non existmk
pose naturellement pour des presents, des passes et des futurs, tandis ou Caesar est homo, Caesare mortuoP Derriere le probleme du determi-
que quand il est sujet d’un verbe au present, il suppose (normale- nisme et celui de l’interpretation statistique de la modalite, qui for-
ment) pour des presents, car il est restreint a cette supposition par le ment Je contexte explicite de la these de Bacon (avec la distinction
temps present du verbe. De fait, la premiere these evoque les formu­ entre necessarium per se et necessarium per accidens chere a la Logica Ut
lations de la fin du XIIe siecle, tandis que la seconde renvoie a la dicit et la Logica Cum sit nostra), c’est done un autre probleme que vise
theorie dite de la suppositio naturalis et a celle de la restrictio caracteris- Bacon: celui de la predication sur les classes vides in naturali materia.
tique des logiciens parisiens du XIIF siecle.22 Mais, il faut noter que C ’est, d’ailleurs, a ce niveau que la theorie des SD semble avoir ete
Bacon rejette les deux. En fait, des la SSD (Steele, 1937, p. 149), il condamnee a Oxford par Robert Kilwardby, en l’espece de la sixieme
pose qu’un terme “ne conceme de lui-meme que des appeles pre­ erreur in logicalibus du syllabus du 18 mars 1277: Quod veritas cum
sents, meme s’il peut etre contracte par la nature du predicat, [. . .] necessitate tantum est cum constantia subiectiP La position baconienne n’a
puisque les passes ou les futurs ne sont appeles par le terme que
relativement” (“terminus de se non concemit nisi appellata presentia,
23 Sur cette notion cf. A. de Libera, “O n some X llth and X lllth century Doctrines
et etiam per naturam predicati potest contrahi, ut dicitur commu- of Restriction”, Historiographia Linguistica, 7 /1 -2 (1980), 131-143.
n iter,. . . non enim sunt preterita vel futura appellata termini nisi 24 Cf. H.A.G. Braakhuis, “The Views of William of Sherwood on some Semantical
secundum quid”). Et toute 1’argumentation des SD consiste a reje- Topics and their Relation to those of Roger Bacon”, Vivarium, 15 (1977), p. 111-142.
25 Cf. M. Grabmann, Die sophismataliteratur des 12. und 13. Jahrunderts mit Textausgabe
ter la “supposition naturelle”, c’est-a-dire la supposition extrapropo- eines Sophisma des Boethius von Dacien, BeitrGphThMan 36/1 (1940), p. 77-95.
sitionnelle d’un terme pour toutes les entites presentes, passees et 26 Sur les condamnations d’Oxford, cf. P.O. Lewry O.P., “The Oxford Condem­
futures ou possibles, qui constituent son extension, en lui opposant nations in Grammar and Logic”, in English Logic and Semantics. From the End o f the
Twelfth Century to the Time o f Ockham and Burleigh. Acts of the 4th European Symposium on
Medieval Logic and Semantics, Leiden-Nijmegen, 23~27 April 1979, edited by H.A.G.
Braakhuis, C.H. Kneepkens & L.M. De Rijk (Artistarium. Supplementa 1), Nime-
22 Sur la supposition naturelle, cf. L.M. De Rijk, “The Development of Suppositio gue, Ingenium Publishers, 1981, p. 235-278. Sur le rapport Rilwardby-Bacon, cf.
Naturalis in Mediaeval Logic”, Vivarium, 9 (1971), p. 71-107 et 11 (1973), p. 43-79; H.A.G. Braakhuis, “Kilwardby versus Bacon? The Contribution to the Discussion
A. de Libera, “Supposition naturelle et appellation: Aspects de la semantique parisienne on Univocal Signification of Beings and Non-Beings Found in a Sophisma Attributed
au X IIP siecle” in Semantiques medievales: Cinq etudes sur la logique et la grammaire au to Robert Kilwardby”, in: Mediaeval Semantics and Metaphysics. Studies Dedicated to L.M.
rrwyen age, edite par A. de Libera, Histoire, Epistmologie, Langage, 3/1 (1981), p. 63-77. De Rijk, ed. E.P. Bos, Nijmegen, Ingenium Publishers, 1985, p. 111-142.
114 ALAIN DE LIBERA ROGER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE 115

pas rencontre un accueil enthousiaste a Paris. Elle doit y avoir eu, celui qui compose l’adverbe avec l’infinitif, puisque, du point de vue
cependant, des partisans, car sinon on ne pourrait s’expliquer ni la grammatical, les adverbes de negation et d’affirmation (comme /also
persistance de la controverse decrite par Boece de Dacie comme magna et vere) s’accordent en nature avec le mode indicatif, qui est celui de
controversia inter modemos, ni celle des interventions de Bacon lui-meme. la negation et de l’affirmation. Cette regie logique tiree, en fait, de
Toutefois, c’est plutot dans les formulations du De signis que l’opi- Priscien permet done de fixer automatiquement le sens naturel de “Tu
nion de Bacon est le plus souvent rapportee. C ’est le cas chez Siger non potes vere negare te non esse asinum” en distinguant le sens natu-
de Brabant quand il evoque ceux qui “pour echapper aux difficultes rellement compose: “Tu non potes vere-negare te non esse asinum”
ont soutenu que, si les choses (signifiees) sont detruites, les termes ne [= Tu ne peux faire une negation vraie en niant que tu n’es pas un
signifient pas identiquement (idem) ou que leur signification est equi­ ane] du sens divise, qui ne peut etre qu’artificiel (pour les besoins
voque”, en sorte qu’une proposition comme Homo est animal, nullo d’une disputatk): “Tu non potes-vere negare te non esse asinum” [= Tu
homine existente “n ’est ni vraie ni fausse, puisque ce qui est signifie par n’es pas vraiment capable de nier que tu n’es pas un ane].
elle n’est ni vrai ni faux ou est equivoque”—position rejetee par Siger Dans les regies suivantes, Bacon examine les cas ou la determina­
pour qui “la corruption des choses ne change rien au concept qu’on tion ne s’accorde pas en nature avec l’un des determinables. Dans
en a” (corruptio rerum non pervertit earundem conceptionem).27 ces circonstances, l’analyse doit, selon lui, porter soit sur la nature de
Un second apport majeur des SD est la complexe theorie de la la determination soit sur celle des determinables. Si la determination
determination proposee dans l’analyse des mecanismes de la composi­ est une “pure determination” (pura determinatio)—autrement dit: un
tion et de la division du sens propositionnel. Poursuivant la reflexion nom substantif—, il est naturel de la composer au determinable qui
sur le sens naturel des phrases entamee dans la SSD, les SD proposent la precede, plutot qu’a celui qui la suit, puisque, en tant que telle, “une
une theorie qui emprunte une partie de leur terminologie a la gram- determination est posterieure a ce qu’elle determine et en depend”
maire, en recourant aux notions de dependance, de determination et [= R2]. Le sens naturel d’une phrase comme: “Vidisti baculo hunc
de determinable.28 Cette theorie est articulee en 13 regies, les plus percussum” est done le sens compose “Vidisti-baculo hunc percussum”
novatrices etant les 7 premieres [= R1-R7], qui concement les cas [= Tu as vu avec un baton que Ton frappait cet homme], lequel est
ou une “determination est placee entre deux determinables”. La R1 evidemment absurde, et impose soit de reecrire la phrase sous une
pose que si, dans une phrase contenant deux determinables et une autre forme (e.g. “Vidisti hunc percussum baculo”) ou, au moins,
determination, la determination s’accorde en nature avec l’un des d’interpreter la phrase initiale en un sens divise, non “naturel”, mais
deux determinables, il est naturel de les composer. Autrement dit, acceptable: “Vidisti baculo-hunc-percussum” [= Tu as vu qu’avec
dans une phrase comme “Tu non potes vere negare te non esse un baton on frappait cet homme], Il est inutile d’exposer ici les autres
asinum”, qui contient deux determinables—le verbe potes a la deuxieme regies, foumies pour les cas ou le determinant est de nature adjectivale.
personne du present de l’indicatif et l’infinitif negare— et une determi­ Il suffit de noter que dans l’analyse de R3 et R5 Bacon s’appuie sur
nation—l’adverbe vere—, le sens compose et “naturel” de la phrase est la notion grammaticale de “dependance” (dependentia), qui connaitra
une fortune certaine dans la grammaire speculative,29 ou que dans
celle de R4, il s’appuie a nouveau sur Priscien, pour qui les adjectifs
27 Cf. Siger de Brabant, Quaestio Utrum haec sit vera: Homo est animal, nullo homine
existente, in Ecrits de logique, de morale et de physique, ed. B. Bazan (Philosophies medie-
vaux, XIV), Louvain-Paris, Publications universitaires-Beatrice-Nauwelaerts, 1974,
p. 56, 15-21.
28 Cf. A. de Libera, “Reference et champs: Genese et structure des theories 29 Cf. J. Pinborg, hogk uni Semantik im Mittelalter. Ein Ueberblick (Problemata, 10),
medievales de l’ambigulte (XIIe-X IIIe siecles)”, Medioevo, 10 (1984), p. 155-208; “De Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt, Frommann-Holzboog, 1972, p. 122-123; “Can Construc­
la logique a la grammaire: Remarques sur la theorie de la determinatio chez Roger tions be Construed? A problem in medieval syntactical theory”, Historiogaphia Lmgdstka,
Bacon et Lambert d’Auxerre (Lambert de Lagny)”, in De ortu grammaticae. A Tribute 7/1-2 (1980), p. 202; “Speculative Grammar”, in The Cambridge History of Later Medieval
to Jan Pinborg, ed. par G. Bursill-Hall, S. Ebbesen and K. Koemer, (Studies in the Phihsophy. Edited by N. Kretzman, A. Kenny and J. Pinborg, Cambridge, CUP,
History of the Language Sciences, 43), Amsterdam/Philadelphie, John Benjamins 1982, p. 259-260; R.H. Robins, “Functional Syntax in Medieval Europe”, Historio­
Publishing Company, 1990, p. 209-226. gaphia Linguistka, 7 /1 -2 (1980), p. 233.
116 ALAIN DE LIBERA ROGER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE 117

et les adverbes sont “mieux places” devant les substantifs que derriere cum non possit facere terminum stare nisi pro praesentibus, et ter­
{Inst, gramm. XV 39; Keil III 89).30* minus de sui natura hoc habet, quod sic stet”); (b) les noms n’ayant
Cette utilisation de Priscien et, plus largement, des concepts de la pas par eux-memes de relation semantique au non-etant, c’est aux
grammaire, montre que Bacon aborde les problemes du langage en verbes au passe ou au futur qu’il incombe d’amplifier leur supposi­
utilisant, autant que possible, toutes les ressources des arts du trivium. tion au-dela de leur imposition originaire (§ 561: “sed quia non habet
Sa conception de l’analyse logique fait une place non negligeable a de se, ut stet pro praeteritis et futuris, ideo verbum de praeterito vel
la construction grammaticale. C ’est meme par un recours assez inat- futuro vel habens vim ampliandi poterit facere ipsum stare pro aliis
tendu a cette notion de constructio que Bacon explique et justifie le a praesenti”). Ces deux theses soutiennent done exactement le meme
fond de sa doctrine de Yappellatio, le rejet de la supposition naturelle point de vue que celui qu’enoncera, quarante ans plus tard, le § 50
et de la “restriction verbale”, ainsi que le privilege qu’il accorde a la du DS (Fredborg: 99-100): “Un mot ne suppose pour quelque chose
suppositio de se pro praesentibus et a Yampliatio. C ’est en partant du phe- dans une phrase que s’il le signifie et lui a ete impose” (“dictio non
nomene grammatical qui voit un meme mot relever d’une certaine supponit pro aliquo in oratione, nisi illud significet et nisi sit ei
categorie morphologique au niveau de sa signification et d’une autre impositum”). La seule difference entre les deux textes est que dans le
au niveau de sa construction effective dans une phrase, qu’il pose en DS, Bacon explique l’amplification comme un cas particulier de “trans-
regie logique generate qu’un meme nom peut, dans une proposition, fert semantique” (transsumptio) impliquant un “renouvellement {renovatio)
etre semantiquement considere d’un double point de vue: celui de la de l’imposition du mot”. Comme on le voit, les SD ne sont done pas
signification et celui de la construction. Pris au niveau de la significa­ une simple oeuvre de jeunesse, sans rapport avec les oeuvres ulterieu-
tion un nom est toujours “nom de presents et d’existants” (§ 558: res. Riches de toute l’experience accumulee a l’universite de Paris
prout dictio consideratur ut est nomen significationis, sic est solum nomen praesen- ou, rappelons-le, dans les annees 1245, s’entrecroisaient terminisme
tium et existentium), ce n’est qu’au niveau de sa construction effective (en logique, d’une part, premodisme grammatical de l’autre, tradition
tant que nomen constructionis) qu’il peut, parce qu’il est construit avec d’Oxford et tradition parisienne, elles livrent au contraire l’horizon
un verbe au passe ou au futur, supposer de maniere amplifiee pour dans lequel Bacon a congu les premiers fondements de ses theories
des passes ou des futurs, c’est-a-dire pour des non-existants. Le § 559 les plus novatrices.
des SD rejoint ainsi, sur une base desormais mieux fondee, la these
esquissee dans la SSD: “Terminus de se solum concemit praesentia
et supponit pro illis de sua natura, per naturam autem verbi de Le De signis et le Compendium studii theologiae
praeterito et futuro vel habenti naturam eorum, ut verba ampliandi,
poterunt stare pro praeteritis et futuris.” Le De signis et le Compendium studii theologiae ne sont pas des traites
Le rejet de la theorie logique de la restriction au benefice de la logiques canoniques au sens ou le sont la SSD et les SD. Le DS est
distinction grammaticale entre le niveau de la signification et celui un fragment incomplet de YOpus maius, edite en 1978 par K.M.
de la construction explique ainsi les deux theses qui mettent les SD Fredborg; le CST est un traite de reforme de la science theologique
a part du reste de la production logique des premieres decennies du qui contient une version remaniee de plusieurs developpements du
X IIF siecle: (a) les verbes au present ne contribuent aucunement a la DS. La caracteristique commune aux deux traites est de plonger leurs
supposition des termes en position de sujet d’une phrase, car ils ne racines dans ce qu’on pourrait appeler la semantique des theologiens.
peuvent conferer au terme que ce qu’il a deja, i.e. une relation seman- Le langage theorique utilise n’est plus celui du terminisme de la
tique aux choses presentes auxquelles il est impose (§ 560: “verbum premiere moitie du X IIF siecle, massivement represente dans la SSD
de praesenti nihil operatur ad suppositionem termini a parte subiecti, et les SD, mais un langage plus complexe, empruntant davantage a
Augustin et aux reflexions sur le signe et la signification en theologie,
systematisees, entre autres, par Henri de Gand. Le meme changement
30 Cf. Guillaume de Sherwood, Introductiones in Logicam, ed. Lohr 1983, p. 280,
171-174. de registre conceptuel intervient au niveau des theories logiques et
118 ALAIN DE LIBERA ROGER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE 119

grammaticales employees par Bacon—c’est ainsi, par exemple, que le CST, § 130, “il ne l’a jamais exposee lui-meme synthetiquement”
le “langage analytique” (J. Murdoch) des suppositiones s’efface presque (:nunquam colligit omnes modos simul). C ’est done Bacon lui-meme qui
entierement devant celui de la signification, de l’imposition et de l’usage fait cette synthese, exposant une doctrine qui “n’offre pas de difficulte
metaphorique (transsumptio). particuliere” et presente une utilite certaine tant en theologie qu’en
Le DS et le CST ne sont pas des oeuvres d’arriere-garde, qui philosophic.
continueraient simplement sur la lancee de la SSD et des SD: ce La specificite de la theorie baconienne est d’integrer l’analogie a
sont des oeuvres de leur temps, qui transposent dans un nouveau l’analyse de l’equivocite ou homonymie.32 Sur les cinq modes d’equi-
contexte epistemologique certaines des theses defendues par Bacon vocite distingues par Bacon, l’analogie intervient quatre fois: la distinc­
au debut de sa carriere. Elies sont done, par la meme, difficiles a tion entre analogic et homonymie ne conceme done que le cas de
classer sur le plan disciplinaire. La nouvelle theorie du signe qu’elles l’homonymie pure (aequivocatio purissima), tous les autres cas d’homo-
proposent a pour point d’application la theologie, avec ses problemes nymie sont des cas d’analogie. Telle que l’expose Bacon, la theorie
specifiques. II en va de meme des elements d’ontologie—absents des de l’homonymie se laisse construire en utilisant deux outils: la notion
sommes de logique de l’epoque anterieure—, qui culminent dans la de diversitas et celle de convenientia existant entre les signifies des termes
discussion de themes a l’epoque surtout developpes dans les oeuvres consideres. II y a homonymie pure, quand il y a diversite absolue
theologiques ou dans les commentaires de la Metaphysique d’Aristote: entre les signifies d’un terme: c’est le cas, bien connu, des signifies
de la nouvelle doctrine de Yanalogia formulee aux § 100-133 du DS du mot “chien” (canis)—l’animal et la constellation celeste. Les termes
a la critique des theories de Vesse essentiae martelee dans les pages les comme sanum et ens, en tant qu'ens est attribue aux dix categories,
plus combatives du CST. relevent de l’homonymie relative, au sens ou leurs signifies respectifs
ont entre eux une convenientia de relation {in relatione). A cette homo­
nymie relative, Bacon ajoute l’homonymie du tout (aequivocatio totius),
L ’anafogie fondee sur une convenance “partielle” (celle de la matiere et du
compose de matiere et de forme, qui tous deux re^oivent homo-
La theorie baconienne de l’analogie (DS, § 100-133; CST, § 129— nymiquement le nom de “substance”); l’homonymie du genre (celle
142) ne ressemble a aucune des theories “scolastiques” forgees dans existant entre les signifies specifiques d’un terme generique qui “com-
la seconde moitie du XIIIe siecle.31 Et pour cause: ce n’est pas, contrai- muniquent tous dans une meme nature originaire”, celle du genre,
rement a celle dite “aristotelico-thomiste”, une theorie de Yanalogie de mais qui presentent cette nature, “descendue en eux”, sous des “modes
I’etre. Loin de remonter au seul Aristote, pour en assurer la provenance d’etre differents”); l’homonymie minimale (celle que determine pour
historique, Bacon met un point d’honneur a se donner un autre pat­ un meme terme non une difference entre les signifies, mais une
ronage: celui du “ Timee de Ciceron”, qui, selon lui, a introduit le difference entre les modes de signifier, comme pour le mot ens qui
terme grec analogia en latin sous le vocable de comparatio (CST, § 141). est homonymiquement nom et participe present). L’interet de cette
Certes, c’est Aristote qui a foumi l’essentiel des materiaux necessaires classification, dont aucun element pris a part n’est original, reside
a la construction d’une theorie de l’analogie, mais, precise-t-il, dans dans sa nature meme qui, d’un bout a l’autre, se veut purement
semantique— comme en temoigne la place meme que l’analyse occupe
31 Cf. E.J. Ashworth, “Signification and Modes of Signifying in Thirteenth-Century dans le CST, ou elle intervient apres l’analyse des problemes poses
Logic: A preface to Aquinas on Analogy”, Medieval Philosophy and Theology, 1 (1991), par la synonymie ou univocite.
p. 39-67; “Analogy and Equivocation in Thirteenth-Century Logic: Aquinas in Con­ Ce qui frappe done, dans la theorie de Bacon, c’est sa subordina­
text”, Mediaeval Studies, 54 (1992), p. 94-135. Sur les sources de cette doctrine, cf.
C. Luna, “Commentaire”, in Simplicius, Commentaire sur les Categories, trad, commentee tion de l’analogie a l’homonymie, qui la reinscrit dans l’horizon de
sous la dir. de I. Hadot, fasc. Ill, Preambtde aux Categories, trad. Ph. Hoffmann, comment. la distinction aristotelicienne entre synonymie et homonymie, sans
C. Luna (“Philosophia Antiqua”, LI/III), Leyde-New York-Copenhague-Cologne,
p. 84—94 et 153-159; A. de libera, “Les sources greco-arabes de la theorie medie-
vale de l’analogie de l’etre”, Les Etudes philosophiques, 3-4 (1989), p. 319-345. 32 Cf. Th. Maloney, “Roger Bacon on Equivocation”, Vivarium, 22 (1984), p. 85-112.
120 ALAIN DE LIBERA ROGER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE 121

lui conferer le statut quasi autonome d’intermediaire ou de tiers entre Il s’efforce de fournir un instrument permettant de proceder scien-
synonymie pure et homonymie pure, qu’elle avait fini par prendre tifiquement dans les deux registres. Cet instrument etant l’analyse du
dans la pensee scolastique: il n’y a analogic que sur la base d’une langage, on peut done soutenir, sans paradoxe ni anachronisme, qu’il
homonymie, et Panalogie ne consiste que dans la mise en evidence y a chez lui une orientation “analytique”, inseparable d’un projet
du type de comparatio ou proportio existant entre les signifies d’un terme intellectuel effectivement reformateur. C ’est sur ce point que nous
homonyme. Ainsi, ce qui compte ici en premier lieu, c’est l’analyse insisterons ici.
de la signification, la distinction entre signifies ou entre signifies pre­
miers et seconds. Le probleme de ens est d’abord de determiner quel
est son signifie premier: Yentitas ou la res subiecta eniitati ou de deter­ La reforme logique du discours
miner quel type d’etre designe cette entitas— en l’occurrence, pour
Bacon, 1’“existence actuelle”. Ensuite, il va de soi que le terme ens Dans le GST, consacre a l’elucidation des causes generates et specia­
“convient plus proprement a la substance qu’aux accidents”. L’ana- l s des erreurs theologiques et philosophiques, Bacon soutient que la
logie apparait alors comme un simple transfert au niveau de la pre­ principale des causes speciales d’erreur a trait a la semantique. Enon-
dication, conforme a la regie, inspiree de Porphyre, qui veut que le gant ses ressorts essentiels, il est ainsi conduit a critiquer les doctrines
genre se predique d’abord de l’espece la plus elevee. C ’est pourquoi de la reference soutenues par ses contemporains. Les deux aspects
Bacon fait de la predication analogique l’instrument specifique du majeurs de sa controverse concernent, l’un, l’ontologie, avec la criti­
metaphysicien, reservant l’homonymie au physicien et la synonymie que des doctrines de l’etre d’essence et de l’etre habituel, l’autre la
ou univocite au logicien. linguistique et la philosophic du langage, avec une reformulation de
Les problemes metaphysiques sont des problemes de predication. la notion traditionnelle de l’“imposition” ouvrant sur une approche
Le philosophe a done pour tache premiere d’elaborer une doctrine pragmatique du langage et de la signification.34 La premiere discussion
d’ensemble de la signification et de la predication. C ’est sur ce point conduit Bacon a prendre position sur Interpretation logique de pro­
que reside la grande innovation de Bacon. La philosophic n’est pas positions a sujet vide comme Cesar est un hommef5 la seconde, a deve-
la metaphysique—la metaphysique n’est qu’une partie de la philoso­ lopper a fond les consequences pragmatiques de la these de la liberte
phic. Soucieux d’adopter un point de vue encore plus englobant, du locuteur dans l’acte d’“imposition des voix”.
permettant d’assurer une double regulation de la theologie et de la L’analyse des “deux principes communs et absolument necessaires
philosophic, Bacon va done encore plus loin en affirmant que la theorie a la logique et a la metaphysique, principes de l’ignorance desquels
de la signification et de la predication doit permettre de resoudre decoulent les erreurs les plus graves en toute espece de dispute, qu’elle
toutes les fausses difficultes que la tradition a accumulees en ces deux soit theologique ou philosophique” est l’occasion d’une des plus vigou-
domaines. La singularity de la demarche de Bacon est de ne pas reuses polemiques intellectuelles du Moyen Age, nommement dirigee
opposer philosophic et theologie a partir de leurs principes propres contre le Franciscain d’Oxford Richard Rufus de Comouailles,36 accuse
ou a partir de leur mode de scientificite. Bacon est etranger a la d’avoir “dans sa maladie et sa demence sans limites” introduit en
confrontation entre theologie forte et theologie faible qui s’imposera
au XTVe siecle.33 Il ne cherche pas non plus a concilier les deux dem­ 34 Sur ce theme, cf. A. de Libera, “Roger Bacon et le probleme de Yappellatio
arches, pour resoudre sur le plan theorique un “conflit des facultes”. unxoocd', in English Logic and Semantics. From the End of the Twelfth Century to the Time of
Ockham and Burleigh., be. cit., p. 193-234.
35 Cf. A. de Libera, Cesar et le Phenix, Distinctwnes et sophismata parisiens.. ., qui
33 Cf. L. Bianchi et E. Randi, “Le theologien et la petite vieille”, in Verites dissonantes. contient une anthologie de textes anti-baconiens.
Aristote a la fin du Mayen Age, (Vestigia, 11), Paris-Fribourg, Cerf-Editions universitaires 36 Cf. J. Pinborg, “Magister Abstractionum”, CIMAGL, 18 (1976), p. 1-4, du
de Fribourg, 1993, p. 123-129. Sur la “theologie scientifique” et la “theologie faible” meme, “The English Contribution to Logic before Ockham”, Synthese 40 (1979),
au Moyen Age tardif, cf. M.-T. Fumagalli Beonio-Brocchieri, “Note sul concetto di 19-42; P.O. Lewry, O.P., “Grammar, Logic and Rhetoric 1220-1320”, in 7 he Early
teologia in Durando di S. Porziano”, in L. Bianchi, ed., Filosofia e teologia nel Trecento. Oxford Schools (The History of the University of Oxford, I), ed. J.I. Catto, Oxford,
Studi in ricordo di Eugenio Randi, (Federation Internationale des Instituts d’Etudes Medi- Clarendon Press, 1984, p. 401-433. Cf., en outre, P. Raedts, Richard Rufus of Corn­
evales, Textes et etudes du Moyen Age, 1), Louvain-La-Neuve, 1994, p. 57-63. wall and the Tradition of Oxford Theology, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1987, p. 107-113.
122 ALAIN DE LIBERA ROGER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE 123

Angleterre les deux theses qui, selon Bacon, ruinent toute metaphy­ Nous ne reviendrons pas ici sur la discussion de l’etre d’essence.
sique et toute theologie.37 A ces deux theses Bacon oppose deux Les elements du dossier sont trop connus. Il suffit de rappeler que,
principes dont il revendique plus ou moins la paternite: [1] “un son pour refuter entierement la premiere “erreur” semantique affirmant
vocal ne peut signifier quelque chose de commun, univoque a l’etre qu’un mot peut designer quelque chose d’univoque a l’etre et au
et au non-etre” et [2] “un son vocal peut perdre sa signification— neant, Bacon examine successivement trois doctrines: la premiere
principe au contraire duquel tout le monde ou presque adhere non soutient que les noms ne sont pas imposes a des particuliers existants
seulement avec obstination, mais de la maniere la plus obstinee qui et presents (directement saisis par la perception sensorielle), mais a
soit, au point de forger d’innombrables erreurs et d’execrables here­ leur essence, sans indication de temps. La deuxieme affirme que les
sies”. Selon Bacon, “c’est parce qu’elle ignore ces deux principes que noms signifient des choses (res), non des essences, mais qu’ils les
la foule tient que Cesar mort est un homme, qu’un homme mort est signifient quant a l’etre de leur essence (ou quant a leur etre d’essence),
un animal, que le Christ est reste homme durant les trois jours qu’il a non du point de vue de leur etre actuel limite au present de la
passes au tombeau— et une infinite d’autres theses, absolument faus- perception. La troisieme soutient que les noms signifient des choses,
ses et parfaitement stupides au sujet de la restriction ou de l’amplifi- mais du point de vue d’une forme appelee etre habituel, qui est
cation de la reference dans les propositions assertoriques, ou encore commune aux trois dimensions du temps et a toute chose, que cette
du statut du necessaire et du contingent dans les propositions modales”. chose ait un etre actuel ou qu’elle n’ait pas d’etre actuel. On a beau-
CEuvre de polemiste et de doctrinaire, le CST a lance nombre d’idees coup ecrit sur cette batterie de critiques: on a tente d’identifier les
que le nominalisme du XIVe siecle a popularisees: une semantique auteurs vises par Bacon;40 d’elucider sur ce point le role de Richard
rigoureusement extensionnelle, une ontologie du singulier, une doctrine de Cornouailles,41 nomme expressement par le GST; de rapprocher
des signes et de la signification naturels, une theorie de la connotation.38 la theorie de Yesse essentiae et de la theorie avicennienne de l’indifference
Le CST peut done etre en un sens considere comme le terreau de de (’essence de la modeme theorie meinongienne de l’independance
l’occamisme, mais il est plus legitime de ne pas separer les avancees du Sosein par rapport au Sein*2 On ne reviendra pas ici sur ces ele­
de Bacon dans le domaine theorique de l’intention generale— refor- ments. Il nous importe plutot de souligner le principe de la reponse
matrice et ecclesiologique—qui les a inspirees, et plus legitime en­ baconienne: la nouvelle doctrine de l’imposition des noms a signifier,
core de maintenir ces innovations dans le cadre meme ou elles ont qui lui permet de rejeter comme vaines toutes les tentatives faites
ete formulees. Car Bacon n ’innove pas sur tous les points et il se pour penser la relation des mots, des concepts et des choses en fai-
confronte a un univers de discours qu’il n’a pas cree.39 C ’est particu- sant abstraction de l’acte originaire d’imposition au benefice de la
lierement evident pour les deux secteurs de son activite les plus remar­ signification. C ’est done sur cet acte et l’analyse des conditions qui
ques par la critique modeme: la formulation d’une “nouvelle” theorie l’entourent que nous nous attarderons pour conclure.
du signe et la critique de la theorie de l’etre de l’essence (esse essentiae).

40 Sur les positions des contemporains de Bacon, cf. S. Ebbesen, “Talking about
what is no more. Texts by Peter of Cornwall (?), Richard of Clive, Simon of
37 Sur l’arriere-plan oxonien des discussions baconiennes, cf. P.O. Lewry, O.P., Faversham, and Radulphus Brito. A Supplement to CIMAGL 3”, CIMAGL, 55 (1987),
“Oxford Logic 1250—1275: Nicholas and Peter of Cornwall on Past and Future p. 135-168. Cf., egalement, P.O. Lewry O.P., “Nicholas and Peter of Cornwall on
Realities”, in The Rise of British Logic, ed. cit., p. 19—62. Past and Future Realities”, in The Rise of British Logic. . ., p. 19-62.
38 Sur la semantique de Bacon, cf. Th. Maloney, “Roger Bacon on the Significatum 41 Cf. S. Ebbesen, “Roger Bacon and the Fools of His Times”, CIMAGL, 3 (1970),
of Words”, in L. Brind’Amour et E. Vance, ed., Archeobgie du signe, be. cit., p. 187— p. 40~44.
211; K.M. Fredborg, “Roger Bacon on Impositio vocis ad significandum”, in English Logk 42 Cf. A. de Libera, “Roger Bacon et la reference vide. Sur quelques antecedents
and Semantics. From the End of the Twelfth Century to the Time of Ockham and Burleigh, medievaux du paradoxe de Meinong”, in Lectionum varietates. Hommage a Paul Vignaux
be. cit., p. 167-191. (1904-1987), (Etudes de philosophic medievale, LXV), Edite par J. Jolivet, Z. Kaluza,
39 Cf. S. Ebbesen & J. Pinborg, “Studies in the Logical Writings Attributed to A. de Libera, Paris, Vrin, 1991, p. 85-120. Cf., en outre, La querelle des unwersaux. De
Boethius de Dacia”, CIMAGL, 3 (1970), p. 2-12. Pbton a b fin du Moyen Age (Des Travaux), Paris, Ed. du Seuil, 1996.
124 ALAIN DE LIBERA ROGER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE 125

Theorie du signe et connotation memes quelque chose d’autre en plus de ce qu’ils sont eux-memes”
c’est comme signe naturel que la fumee signale le feu (“car elle le
La semiotique de Bacon a longtemps ete consideree comme une fait sans le vouloir, mais nous savons, par experience, en observant
innovation extraordinaire, sans precedent dans le monde medieval.43 et en remarquant les choses que meme si la fumee apparait seule, il
Bacon lui-meme a contribue a la legende en soulignant qu’il avait y a du feu dessous”); au contraire, les signa data sont ceux que “tous
forge l’essentiel de sa doctrine avant meme d ’en avoir retrouve les les etres vivants se font les uns aux autres pour montrer, autant qu’ils
rudiments dans sa lecture d’Augustin. Que Bacon ait decouvert sa le peuvent, les mouvements de leur ame, c’est-a-dire tout ce qu’ils
semantique sans avoir lu une ligne d’Augustin est peu vraisemblable. sentent et tout ce qu’ils pensent”. La typologie de Bacon depasse,
Des les SD (dans le manuscrit de Seville), en effet, expliquant les toutefois la bipartition augustinienne, en ce que, sous les deux espe-
divers modes de la “supposition simple”, il renvoie au De Dialectica, ces des signa naturalia et des signa data, elle coordonne en fait deux
en tout cas a Augustin, pour plus de details (§ 421-422): “Simplex semiotiques distinctes: la semiotique des signes naturels selon Augus­
suppositio est quando terminus non stat pro persona alia sive pro tin, d’une part, la semiotique generate des signes naturels et des signes
inferiori aliquo, sed pro voce, ut ‘Homo est vox’; vel significato, ut conventionnels selon Aristote, d’autre part. La principal originalite
‘Homo est dignissima creaturarum’; vel pro voce significante, ut ‘Homo de Bacon par rapport a Augustin est done de distinguer deux types
est nomen’; vel pro aliqua proprietate vocis, ut ‘Homo est dissyllabum’, de signes naturels, elle est ensuite de lester d’emprunts a Aristote la
‘Homo est pes trochaeus’; vel quantum ad proprietates significati, ut theorie augustinienne meme des signes naturels. Presentee sous forme
‘Homo est universale’, ‘Homo est species’, et huiusmodi alia multa. de tableau, la typologie du DS distingue:
Et quod sic diversimode et multis aliis modis nomen possit accipi,
plane demonstrat Augustinus in fine suae <Dmlecticae>, et postea agetur 1. 1. qui inherent autre chose necessairement ou
de hoc.” Mais cette relation a Augustin, evidente, n ’est pas le seul probablement
probleme qui se pose a l’historien: Bacon ne construit pas sa seman­ 1. Naturalia — 1.2. en vertu de la conformite d’une chose a
tique dans un vide theorique ambiant. I. Rosier a bien montre que autre chose
la plupart des classifications semiotiques employees par Bacon se
1.3. les effets par rapport a leur cause
retrouvent dans des textes contemporains comme ceux d’Henri de
Gand.44 Laissant de cote la question de l’originalite de la grille em­ signa
ployee par Bacon, nous privilegierons certaines de ses implications
2.1. ad placitum et ex proposito cum
dans le domaine de la psychologie. deliberatione rationis et electione voluntatis
La distinction porteuse de la typologie baconienne des signes passe,
comme on le sait, entre les signa naturalia et les signa ordinata ab anima 2 . Ordinata
et ex intentione animae. Cette distinction correspond plus ou moins etroi- naturaliter, sine deliberatione rationis et sine
tement a la difference tracee par Augustin entre signa naturalia et electione voluntatis nec ad placitum nec e proposito
signa data: on sait que pour l’eveque d’Hippone, “les signes naturels quodam instinctu naturali, impetu naturae
sont ceux qui, sans intention ni desir de signifier, font connaitre d’eux-
Comme on le voit, Bacon distingue deux sortes de signes naturels:
les signes naturels1(= SN1ou Su_s) et les signes naturels2 (= SN2 ou
43 Sur la theorie baconienne du signe, cf. Th. Maloney, “The Semiotics of Roger S22). Sur les trois types de SN1distingues dans le DS, les deux pre­
Bacon”, Mediaeval Studies, 45 (1983), p. 120-154. Sur la semiotique medievale, cf.
U. Eco et C. Marmo, ed., On the medieval theories o f signs, Amsterdam, John Benja­ miers sont empruntes a Aristote, le premier type vient des Analytiques
mins, 1989. Cf., aussi, l’ouvrage fondamental d’l. Rosier, La parole comme acte. Sur la et de la Rhetorique;45 le second type est inspire de passages du De
grammaire et la semantique au X IIIesiecle (Sic et Non), Paris, Vrin, 1994.
44 Cf. I. Rosier, “Henri de Gand, la Dialectica d’Augustin, et l’imposition des noms
divins”, a paraitre dans Studi e Testi per la Storia della Filosofia Medievale. 45 Cf. l’analyse du syllogisme rhetorique (enthymeme) et la definition des notions
126 ALAIN DE LIBERA
ROGER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE 127
interpretatione et du De anima; assez paradoxalement done, dans cette
Telles que les definit Aristote dans le premier chapitre du De inter­
division tripartite placee sous le patronage d ’Augustin, seul le troi-
pretatione., les relations entre les mots, les concepts et les choses s’arti-
sieme type de SN1 est emprunte a Feveque d’Hippone: celui de la
culent autour de deux relations: la relation conventionnelle des mots
relation de cause a effet materialisee dans l’exemple du rapport fumee/
et des concepts, la relation naturelle des concepts et des choses, l’une
feu.46 Dans le DS, chaque type de SN1 est illustre de la maniere
variable, qui explique la diversite des idiomes, l’autre invariable, qui
suivante:
rend possible une grammaire universelle des affects. Dans ce dispo-
sitif, que l’on peut representer sous la forme d’un triangle ayant pour
Necessaire: habere lactis copiam
signum partus in muliere sommet les concepts,47 la relation entre les mots et les choses est
done indirecte: les mots designent des concepts qui, eux-memes, repre­
Passe \
sented des choses—plus exactement: “les sons emis par la voix”, les
'Probable: Terram esse madidam signum “mots paries”, “sont les symboles” ou “signes immediats des etats de
pluviae preteritae Fame”, tandis que les “etats de Fame sont les images des choses”. II
^Necessaire: cantum galli signum horae noctis n ’y a pas de relation directe entre les mots et les choses.48
Se preoccupant de Finstitution du langage, Bacon soutient une
Present/ theorie radicalement distincte de celle d5Aristote: Fimposition des “sons
'Probable: Esse matrem signum dilectionis. Esse emis par la voix” concerne les choses, non les etats de Fame. Le mot
errabundum multum de nocte Nicolas n’est pas impose a ma representation de Nicolas, mais a Nicolas
signum latronis. lui-meme. Contrairement a la semantique de la signification, qui selon
'Necessaire: aurora signum ortus solis

' Futur •
47 O n peut aussi penser a un rectangle ou a un carre, si Ton ajoute aux mots
Probable: Rubedo in vespere signum serenitatis
paries les mots ecrits, comme le fait Aristote quand il precise que “les mots ecrits
in crastino sont les symboles des mots emis par la voix”. C ’est d’ailleurs a ces quatre entites—
litterae, voces, animae passiones et res—et a ce dispositif carre que s’attachent evi-
Imagines, picturae
demment les exegees du “Liber Peryermenias”. Cf. e.g. Pierre d’Hibernie: “Quattuor
sunt ex quibus contingit habere causas constituentes quamlibet interpretationem, et
-Vestigium signum animalis.
sunt duo extrema et alia duo media: extrema sunt que scribuntur et res, duo media
sunt voces et intellectus” (texte cite par R.-A. Gauthier, in Thomas d’Aquin, Expositio
Libri Peryermenias, ed. Leonine, t. I* 1, Rome-Paris, 1989, p. 9 ad 21. Pratiquement,
■Fumus signum ignis. toutefois, les litterae sont laissees de cote dans la suite de l’analyse, comme le remar-
que Ammonius, “tamquam nichil necessarium habentes ad inmediatam rerum expres-
sionem” (ibid., p. 10, ad 49-55).
de “vraisemblable”, de signe et d’indice dans les Premiers analytiques, II, 27, 70a 1 sqq. 48 C ’est ce que souligne clairement Thomas d’Aquin. Les “sons vocaux ne peu-
et Rhetorique I, 2, 1357a22 sqq. et 1357b 10-24. L’exemple du lait matemel illustre vent signifier immediatement les choses memes” (“non potest esse quod significent
la premiere figure du syllogisme rhetorique (en Darii): “Toute femme qui a du lait immediate ipsas res”), comme le prouve leur maniere meme de signifier (“ut ex
(B) a enfante (A); cette femme-ci (C) a du h it (B); cette femme-ci (C) a enfante (A). modo siginficandi apparet”): en effet, le nom homme signifie la nature humaine “abstrac­
46 On sait que le rapport fumee/feu appartient a la theorie “dogmatique” (i.e. tion faite des singuliers”, il ne peut signifier immediatement un homme singulier. Le
stoi'eienne) du signe, comme le confirme le temoignage des Esquisses Pyrrhmiennes de caractere abstrait de la signification explique l’invention des Idees chez Platon. Mais,
Sextus Empiricus. La fumee y est definie comme un “signe de rappel” ou “comme- joint cette fois au rejet de l’existence reelle d’entites universelles, il explique aussi le
m oratif’, qui est signe du feu, “parce qu’elle a ete observee en meme temps que la caractere necessairement indirect de la relation semantique chez Aristote: “Unde
chose qu’elle signifie”. Le signe de rappel s’oppose au “signe d’indication” ou “reve- Platonici posuerunt quod significaret ipsam ydeam hominis separatam; set, quia hec
lateur” “qui n’a pas ete observe en meme que la chose dont il est le signe”, mais secundum suam abstractionem non subsistit realiter secundum sentenciam Aristotilis,
que “sa propre nature ou constitution indique”. Cfi, sur ce point, Sextus Empiricus, set est in solo intellectu, ideo necesse fuit Aristotili dicere quod voces significant
Esquisses Pyrrhoniennes, II, chap. X, § 97-102. O n notera que l’exemple du lait est intellectus conceptiones immediate, et eis mediantibus res.” Cf. Thomas d’Aquin,
analyse au § 106, du chap. XI: “la proposition unefemme a du lait est l’indicatrice de Expositio Libri Peryermenias, I, 2 (ad 16a3-5); ed. Gauthier, p. 11, 100-112. La these
elle a congu” dans l’inference: “Si une femme a du lait, elle a con^u.” de Thomas figure deja chez Boece lui-meme et Ammonius (textes cites par Gauthier,
loc. cit., p. 10 ad 97-112).
128 ALAIN DE LIBERA ROGER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE 129

les options philosophiques peut eventuellement faire place a une cas, un mot “qui a re^u une seule imposition sous un seul acte de
dimension intensionnelle, une semantique de l’imposition ne peut etre signifier” se rapporte quand meme a une pluralite de choses: ces choses
qu’une semantique de la reference et cette semantique de la refe­ auxquelles, precisement, se rapporte la chose a laquelle il a ete impose.
rence ne peut etre qu’extensionnelle: pour Bacon les noms ne sau- Simplement le mecanisme psycho-semiotique n’est pas le meme: “le
raient etre donnes originairement a ces fictions theoriques que sont mot signifie ad placitum pour la chose a laquelle il est impose”, “mais
les essences, les quiddites abstraites, les etres d’essence et autres etres il signifie naturellement et dans le premier mode du signe naturel les
d’habitude. Dans ces conditions, les phenomenes psycho-linguistiques, choses telles qu’elles sont comprises a travers son premier signifie”.
la ressemblance entre la chose et l’etat mental alleguee par Aristote, C ’est la, done, qu’intervient la notion non-aristotelicienne de signifi­
mais aussi la relation du son vocal et de l’etat mental, assumee par cation naturelle: le mecanisme est d’ordre inferentiel et bien deli-
les notions de “symbole” et de “signe immediat” chez Tricot, de mite, les signifies secondaires etant compris par une consequence
“rcota” chez Boece, demandent a etre etudies pour eux-memes et fixes naturelle et necessaire a travers le terme impose et, plus precisement
epistemologiquement—ce que ne font ni le De interpretatione ni meme encore, “par la raison du signifie de ce terme”. Le rapport de conse­
le De anima. quence se laisse alors ainsi formuler: le consequent naturel est com­
La nouveaute remarquable de la philosophic de Bacon est de donner pris dans l’antecedent par la raison de son signifie ou, ce qui revient
une theorie semiotique precise des phenomenes psycho-linguistiques.49 au meme, “un mot signifie de nombreuses choses auxquelles il n’est
Le fondement de cette nouvelle doctrine reside dans la coordination pas impose, puisqu’il signifie toutes les choses avec lesquelles la chose
explicite des mecanismes de la signification “institute” (type S21) et ayant regu 1’imposition possede un rapport essentiel de par la force
de la signification naturelle (type S1•'•) au sein d’une meme theorie de de son signifie”. Bref, “en meme temps que, parce que, tant que et
la signification, de l’imposition et de la reference. Cette coordination lorsque le mot homme signifie ce a quoi il fut impose, a savoir telle
est rendue possible par une mise en evidence du phenomene de la espece d’animal, il signifie aussi l’animal et ce qui est capable de rire
connotation. Le principe est simple: selon Bacon, un nom qui signifie et toutes les autres choses avec lesquelles cette chose signifiee est dans
ad placitum (= S21), signifie seulement la chose a laquelle il a ete un rapport essentiel de par la force du signifie.”
impose. II ne peut done referer (“etre mis pour”, stare pro) autre chose. Le phenomene decrit par Bacon depasse la simple “signification
“Neanmoins, il signifie aussi ses connotata en tant que signe naturel par accompagnement” analysee par Avicenne et Ghazali. Tout en se
du premier mode (= S1J ), dans la mesure ou les realties connotees recommandant de ces grands ancetres, Bacon s’efforce de depasser
sont reliees au nom qui les connote par une consequence naturelle les exemples avances par eux: “le fait qu’un toit signifie une paroi et
et necessaire.” une fondation” ou “le fait que le nom de n’importe quelle chose qui
L’ensemble du processus est bien decrit dans le DS, qui, pour la a un rapport essentiel a une autre chose signifie cette autre chose”—
premiere fois, foumit une theorie de la signification secondaire ou relations purement topiques, limitees a un stock d’exemples tradi-
connotation qui connecte explicitement la signification ad placitum et la tionnels: “le nom d’un relatif qui signifie l’autre <relatif> ou le nom
signification naturelle de type S11. Le fondement est clairement enonce du tout qui signifie les parties”. Il commence done par analyser sept
au § 102, ou l’ensemble de la reflexion est place sous le patronage modes selon lesquels un mot peut signifier une chose a laquelle il n’a
de la notion d’analogie: il y a fonctionnement analogique lorsqu’un pas ete impose. Il enumere ainsi: (1) le nom d’un non-etant, qui
mot “donne a comprendre une pluralite de choses auxquelles il n ’a “donne toujours a comprendre l’etant dont il dit la privation”, puis-
pas ete impose” ou plus exactement “plusieurs choses parmi lesquel- que le non-etre ou neant “ne peut ni etre nomme ni etre signifie si
les une seule a re$u l’imposition”. Autrement dit: dans la plupart des ce n’est par rapport a l’etre”; (2) les noms divins relatifs (par oppo­
sition au nom absolu de Dieu), qui impliquent les creatures en vertu
d’une relation “qui est dans la creature comme dans un sujet mais se
49 Cf., sur ce point, les remarques pionnieres de J. Pinborg, “Roger Bacon on
Signs: A Newly Recovered Part of the Opus Maius”, Miscellanea Mediaevalia, 13, termine seulement en Dieu comme en un objet” (e.g. “maitre”, “crea-
Berlin-New York, Walter de Gruyter, 1981, p. 403-412. teur”, “cause premiere”, “gouverneur”, “conservateur”, “recteur du
130 ALAIN DE LIBERA ROGER BACON ET LA LOGIQUE 131

monde”, etc.); (3) les noms des creatures, qui tous, relatifs ou absolus, [. . .] Un son vocal signifiant une chose ad placitum est un signe naturel
donnent a comprendre le createur; (4) les noms des creatures en tant de la forme de cette chose existant dans 1’ame, et cela dans le pre­
qu’ils “se signifient mutuellement” (e.g. le nom d’un accident, qui mier mode du signe naturel.50 [. . .] Il importe que le mot signifie la
donne a comprendre une substance, “puisqu’il ne peut ni exister sans forme et l’habitus non comme un signe donne par 1’ame [...], puis­
une substance, ni etre compris, defini ou nomme”, ou le nom d’une qu’il ne les signifie ni naturellement [au sens d’Aristote] ni ad placitum,
substance, qui donne a comprendre un accident); (5) le nom d’un uni- mais comme un signe naturel. Et il est impossible qu’il les signifie
versel qui “donne a comprendre un particulier vague” (e.g. “Phomme, selon le deuxieme ou le troisieme mode du signe naturel, puisque le
done un homme”) ou “determine, mais seulement en disjonction” mot n’est pas configure d’apres la forme de cette chose, mais d’apres
(e.g. “Phomme, done Socrate ou Platon, ou . . . etc.”); (6) le nom d’une sa propre forme, afin de pouvoir en etre le signe, et puisqu’il n’est pas
partie essentielle et principale d’un tout, qui en signifie necessaire- non plus un effet de la forme de cette chose. C ’est pourquoi il importe
ment une autre, ou, pour mieux dire, toute autre (les exemples d’Avi- qu’il en soit le signe uniquement dans le premier mode du signe
cenne et de Ghazali, auxquels s’ajoute celui du coeur “qui signifie la naturel” (DS, § 165).
tete, le foie et l’estomac et toutes les parties principales de l’animal”, Place au carrefour de la nature (mecanismes psycho-linguistiques)
chacune de ces parties “signifiant n’importe quelle autre”); (7) les et de la liberte (donation de sens), la semiotique de Bacon combine
noms des correlatifs. Toutefois, ce n’est pas dans cette typologie que de maniere originale la theorie des inferences naturelles avec celle de
Bacon pousse la fine pointe de sa theorie: e’est en appliquant sa theorie Pimpositio vocis ad significandum: le volontarisme linguistique n’est pas
de l’implied-meaning aux fonctionnements psycho-linguistiques. borne par les relations inferentielles—la sphere de l’imposition est
Pour aller a l’essentiel, on soulignera done que le franciscain fondee sur le jeu articulant les representations de mots et les repre­
d’Oxford etend la connexion de la signification S21 et de la signifi­ sentations de choses, elle ne se laisse ni reduire a lui ni contraindre
cation S1: (1) a la relation du son vocal a sa propre “forme” (species) par lui.
dans 1’ame (articulation du mot parle a son image acoustique); (2) a Cette doctrine du signe a done une multitude d’applications pos­
la relation du son vocal a la forme de son referent dans 1’ame (associa­ sibles. La plus connue est celle de la reimposition ou renovation de
tion d’une image acoustique a une image mentale du referent); (3) a l’imposition qui permet a Bacon d’expliquer comment un mot peut
la relation de l’image mentale du referent au referent lui-meme. La perdre sa signification originaire lorsqu’il perd son objet de refer­
necessite d’une combinaison de S21 avec S11 plutot qu’avec S12 (ou ence sans que, pour autant, la communication sensee entre individus
5 12 et S13 dans le DS) est expressement formulee dans le cas de (2) soit compromise. Le principe du bapteme, qui regie la conception
(DS, § 165); en revanche, S21 se combine a la fois avec S11, S12 et baconienne de l’imposition, et qui veut que donner un nom a une
5 13 dans le cas de (1). Cette discrepance entre les deux fonctionne­ chose soit obligatoirement donner un nom a une chose presente et
ments s’explique aisement; elle n’en eclipse pas pour autant le phe- existante tombant sous le sens, ne peut etre complete par le principe
nomene central, qui est que tous les mots prononces ont en commun, de reimposition, qui veut que tout emploi d’un mot, dans une situation
quel que soit leur fonctionnement, de combiner les significations S21 linguistique concrete, passe par une reimposition, il ne peut done etre
et S11. On donne ici les deux principaux passages touchant les rela­ un principe de communication effective que dans la mesure ou les
tions (1) et (2): (1) “Le mot prononce est un signe de sa propre forme divers partenaires de communication, le locuteur et l’auditeur, utilisent
dans Paine, mais seulement un signe naturel, et non pas un signe les signes de la meme maniere, selon les memes lois psychologiques
institue par 1’arne [. . .] Et il est evident qu’il en est un signe naturel et semantiques. Dire, comme le fait Bacon, que nous redonnons sens
dans le triple genre du signe naturel. En effet, il infere necessaire-
ment sa forme dans 1’ame du locuteur, il est forme et configure d’apres
50 Cf., dans le meme sens, Roger Bacon, CST, ed. Maloney, § 60: “Sed quia
elle, et il est l’effet de celle-ci” (DS, § 18). (2) “Un mot significatif ad
species rei et habitus cognitivus de re sequuntur naturali consequentia ad rem et
placitum prononce significativement infere necessairement la forme de nomen [.. .] ideo vox rei imposita comparatur ad speciem et habitum sicut vox
son referent dans 1’arne et l’habitus <cognitif qui lui correspond> significativa naturaliter, et primo modo signi naturalis [. . .].”
132 ALAIN DE LIBERA

aux mots a chaque fois que nous les employons, que nous fixons leur
reference a chaque occasion d’enonciation, ne peut apparaitre comme
une theorie raisonnable que si cette reimposition obeit a des meca- 6. ROGER BACON ON RHETORIC AND POETICS
nismes psychologiques inconscients, permettant a tout sujet parlant
d’affronter de la meme maniere les contextes d’enonciation linguisti- Jeremiah Hackett
ques et extralinguistiques des phrases. O r c’est bien ce qu’affirme
Bacon: l’activite de reimposition s’effectue de maniere inconsciente,
“dans un temps non sensible a 1’ame”, par une sorte d’adaptation Although Roger Bacon claims to have written a treatise on the compo­
spontanee, plutot que volontaire au sens de “deliberee”. Sans etre sition of rhetorical arguments, such a work has not been identified.
capable de la conceptualiser dans le detail, Bacon met en place les He does, however, offer many comments on rhetoric and poetics in
conditions d’une analyse de cette reimposition spontanee, quand il his later works, and from these we can reconstruct the outline of his
decrit la maniere dont se structurent au niveau psychologique les theory. Moreover, in his Opus maius, he gives us a practical example
phenomenes d’implied-meaning. of how such a Rhetoric should be accomplished. From the very
C ’est done autour d’une meme difficulte, celle de la generatio sermonis beginning of the opening polemic in Opus maius I, he connects the
que gravite toute la pensee logique et logico-semantique de Bacon: study of wisdom and language with the theme of moral philosophy.1
c’est elle qui est approchee dans les premieres elaborations de la In Opus maius II, he explicitly connects his doctrine of truth with the
theorie de Yinclusio foumies par la SSD, mais c’est elle aussi qu’aborde theme of moral wisdom. His treatise on Semiotics in Opus maius III
le DS en theorisant les mecanismes inferentiels existant au niveau might be seen as a contribution to the construction of a rhetorical
psycho-logique entre representations de choses et representations de argument about language. In the Communia mathematica he explicidy
mots. Deplacer la limite entre nature et convention en la faisant passer affirrps that in logicalibus he composed a treatise on rhetoric.2 Further,
a l’interieur meme des processus psychologiques, au lieu de la laisser in many texts, Opus maius, Opus tertium and especially in the Communia
au dehors, dans le face a face du signe naturel et du signe conven- mathematica, Bacon connects the rhetorical and poetic arguments to
tionnel au sens d’Aristote, telle est la grande nouveaute de l’appro- Mathematics and Music, and he argues that without some knowledge
che baconienne de la signification. II serait exagere de dire que cette of these, a person will not understand rhetoric or poetics.
approche aboutit a une theorie veritable, complete et structuree. C ’est The intention of this paper is to present the main characteristics
plutot une serie d’esquisses et de trouvailles limitees, mais qui toutes of Bacon’s views on Rhetoric and Poetics. A corollary of the paper
convergent vers un meme probleme, celui du rapport entre pensee, will be the suggestion that Bacon’s views did not die with him in
langage et communication—un probleme que Bacon ne pouvait cer-
tainement pas resoudre avec les instruments dont il disposait, mais 1 For a recent study of Bacon’s theory of language, see Irene Rosier, La parole
qu’il a, plus que beaucoup de ses contemporains, puissamment contri- comme acte: Sur la grammaire et la semantique au XIIF siecle, Paris: J. Vrin, 1994. See
p. 23: Les arts du language ou trivium se partagent, au Moyen Age, l’analyse du
bue a faire eclore. language: la grammaire s’occupe de la correction des enonces, la logique de leur
verite, la rhetorique de leur elegance. Le parent pauvre, au X IIF siecle, est sans
conteste la rhetorique, du moins a rUniversite. Les prerogatives de la grammaire et
de la logique, par contre, sont clairement hierarchisees: un enonce doit d’abord etre
construit, correct et acheve avant d’etre susceptible d’un jugement de verite.
2 Communia mathematica, ed. Steele (Opera, XVI, p. 17): Et jam composui de eo
tractatum in logicalibus, et ostendi quod ei proprium est.
Already in 1250 in his De ortu scientiarum, Robert Kilwardby presents a compari­
son of Rhetoric and Logic. As part of Logic, it is a linguistic science which deals
with enthymemes and with the construction of public speech and the goal of this
science is ethics. Already in Kilwardby one finds a distinction between the theory of
rhetoric as part of Logic, and the uses of rhetoric in civil science. Here, as in gram­
mar and logic, Bacon is indebted to Robert Kilwardby.
134 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON RHETORIC AND POETICS 135

obscurity. It will be argued that the seed which Bacon planted grew while Scholasticism reigned throughout the middle ages in Paris, and
in the 1270-80’s in the first Latin Commentary on the Rhetoric of Aristotle while Ciceronian humanism dominated the Italian City rhetoric, the
by Aegidius Romanus (Giles of Rome). combination of an interest in astrologia, scientia experimmtalis and rhetorica
Bacon differs from the common view of philosophers in the 13th did find a home in some Italian Universities.5
century concerning the neat division of the Trivium: Grammar, Logic, Bacon gives the theory of the relation of rhetoric and poetics to
Rhetoric.3 His rejection of the trivium is part of his general criticism Logic in the Communia mathematica. And he refers the reader to the
of the new curriculum at Paris, a system which he rejects due to his Moralis philosophic (= Opus maius VII), where he gives an account of
adherence to example of Robert Grosseteste and Adam Marsh. The the uses of rhetoric and poetics. In the former text, he notes that due
omission of Rhetoric and Poetics from the ordinary courses at Paris to the ignorance of mathematics, many who know the principles of
meant that in practice students were primarily introduced to gram­ this study are ignorant of its purpose. He then tells us about the
mar and formal Logic.4 O f course, at times Rhetoric, that is Ciceronian available literature on these topics circa 1267. And he remarks:
Rhetoric, could be taught as an occasional course, but it meant in
For this [the theory of rhetoric and poetics] is known from al-Farabi
effect that Grammar and Logic would be the dominant subjects. Now, in his book On the sciences and from the logic of Avicenna and al-Ghazali
and by means of Averroes book On Poetk Argument which has been
3 O n Bacon’s division and the medieval Trivium see P. Osmund Lewry O.P., translated and by means of the prologue to this work in which the
“Rhetoric at Paris and Oxford in the Mid-Thirteenth century,” Rhetorica, 1 (Spring translator Hermannus Allemanus explains that he was not able to trans­
1983; Ibid., “Grammar, Logic and Rhetoric 1220-1320,” in J.I. Catto ed. The Early late Aristotle’s text on the poetic argument, because he did not know
Oxford Schools [The History of the University of Oxford], Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, the Greek meter which Aristotle uses in this book, and we know that
401-434; see esp. 431-33: “Rhetoric was the neglected member of the Trivium. . . .”
For Bacon’s own summary of his criticism of the normal division of the Trivium,
this book was written in Greek and was translated into Arabic, although
see Opus tertium, ed. Brewer, 307-8; the following from the Communia mathematica, this text of Aristotle has not yet been translated into Latin.
p. 64 is Bacon’s view: rhetorica enim docens composicionem argumenti rhetorici est - But al-Farabi has presented to us the meaning of this argument, and
pars Logice, ut patuit in predictis. Et Rhetorica utens hoc argumento est pars Moralis Avicenna, al-Ghazali and Averroes have done likewise. Because of this,
philosophic, ut in Metaphysicis et in Moralibus demonstravi; et ideo multum errat one ought to present an account of the nature of poetic argument, and
vulgus quando ponit Rhetoricam in divisione contra Logicam et Grammaticam. Simi­ it falls to Logk to compose such a book, since the composition of the
liter Poetica, docens argumentum poeticum, est pars Logice, et ea que utitur tali
argumento est pars Moralis philosophic, ut demonstravi suis locis, et ideo solo due,
doctrine of Argumentation pertains to Logk alone. Again, I have dem­
scilicet, Grammatica et Logica computantur preter dictas scientias has duas de quibus onstrated in my Metaphyska that this kind of argument is necessary and
iam expositum est quomodo abstrahunt et quomodo non. that this science ought to be established in Logic, and that this argu­
For a seminal essay which discusses some of the problems about Aristotle’s Rhetoric ment is more useful [than others] since it leads to salvation in the soul
in the Middle Ages, see James J. Murphy, “Aristotle’s Rhetoric in the Middle Ages,” and to virtues and happiness so that vices can be avoided.
The Quarterly Journal of Speech 52 (1966), 109-115. See Paul Oskar Kristeller, The appropriate presentation of this argument is found in [my] Moralis
Renaissance Thought and its Sources, New York, 1979 . . . and ibid., “Rhetoric in philosophia, and in its use, and likewise in theological proofs and doctrines;
Medieval and Renaissance Culture,” in James J. Murphy ed. Renaissance Eloquence,
Berkeley, University of California Press, 1983, 1-19. For the authoritative study of and in such moral matters, this kind of argument moves a [person]
the effects of Arabic philosophy on medieval rhetoric, see D.L. Black, Logic and Aristotle's much more than the demonstrative argument since it has much greater
Rhetoric and Poetics in Medieval Arabic Philosophy, Leiden-New York-Koln, E.J. Brill, power. And I have already composed a treatise on this argument
1994 (Islamic Philosophy, Theology and Science: Texts and Studies, Ed. H. Daiber
and D. Pingree). See her “Traditions and Transformations in the Medieval Approach
to Rhetoric and Related Linguistic Arts,” in Claude Lafleur, ed., L'enseignement de la See the work of William J . Courtenay, Teaching Careers at the University of Paris in
philosophic au X IIP siecle: Autour du “Guide de I'etudiant" du M s Ripoll 109 (forthcoming). the Thirteenth and Fourteenth Centuries, Texts and Studies in the History of Medieval
For modem accounts of these issues which indicate the continued significance of Education, no. 18. Notre Dame, Ind.: United States Subcommission for the History
(a) the relation of rhetoric to dialectic and (b) the relation of rhetoric to ethics, see of Universities, University of Notre Dame, 1988. Ibid., Schools and Scholars in Fourteenth-
Amelie Oksenberg Rorty ed., Essays on Aristotle's Rhetoric, Berkeley-Los Angeles-London: Century England, Princeton, N.J.; Princeton University Press, 1987.
University of California Press, 1996 and David J. Furley and Alexander Nehamas, 5 See G. Federici Vescovini, Astrologia E Scienza: La crisi dell'aristotelismo sul cadre del
eds. Aristotle’s Rhetoric: Philosophical Essays, Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton Univer­ Trecento e Biagio Pelacani da Parma, Firenze: Nuovedizioni, Enrico Vallechi, 1979. Ibid.,
sity Press, 1994. “Peter of Abano and Astrology,” in Patrick Curry, ed., Astrology, Science and Society,
4 See Learning Institutionalized: Teaching in the Medieval University, ed. John Van Engen (The Boydell Press, 1987), 19-40; Ibid., “Libri e maestri dello studio ferrarese,” in
and Edward D. English, (Notre Dame, University of Notre Dame Press.) La Renascita Del Sapere, ed. Patrizia Castelli (Padova: Marsilio, 1991), 293-306.
136 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON RHETORIC AND POETICS 137

[Rhetoric-Poetic] in my works on Logic, and I have shown there what in the curriculum. He makes the point that the normal student and
is proper to this science.
Professor were ignorant of this material. If a rhetoric was used it
And according to Aristotle and to al-Farabi, this argument makes
use of beautiful and decorous speech so that the soul will be immedi­ that that of Cicero.7 And by 1270, apparently under the influence of
ately raised to the love o f virtue and happiness and to the hatred of Thomas Aquinas, the Rhetoric of Aristotle in the new William of
vice, and will scarcely ever be attracted to it. And so poetic speeches Moerbecke translation would be read.8
that are complete, beautiful and efficacious in moving the soul ought Earlier in Gundissalinus’s classification of the sciences, rhetoric as
to be dressed out in all proper forms of prosaic speech, and abide by eloquence had been omitted. And Rhetoric was seen to be part of
all the laws of meter and rhythm, just like Sacred Scripture in the
Logic, while Poetics linked with the imagination. With the influence
Hebrew Language, and Boethius in the Consolation of Philosophy, and
Alanus On the Plaint of Nature, and the hymns of the Church, and much of al-Farabi, one has the evident move toward the ethical and political
of the divine office, so that by the decor and sweetness of the lan­ uses of rhetoric. One major consequence of Bacon’s placing the con­
guage, the soul may be stongly and immediately m oved.. . .6 struction of the rhetorical and poetical argument in Logic is that the
traditional medieval treatment of Cicero as auctor in rhetoricam is rejected.
Bacon’s advocacy of the use of the extant translated materials on
He is retained but given a small place behind Aristotle. In other
Rhetoric and Poetics at Paris shows us that there was a major lacuna
words, Bacon will not agree that Rhetoric is just a side-connection
to civil science. Rather, it is deeply tied to human and ethical con­
6 Communia mathematica, ed. Steele (Opera, XVI), pp. 16-17: (Nam longe magis cerns in the broadest sense. And the Master of the ethical life is
ignorabitur finis logice quam ejus principium vel medium per ignoranciam math-
ematice si diligenter attendamus). Nam certum est per Alpharabius in libro De scientiis Aristotle, the author of the Nicomachean Ethics.9
et per Logicam Avicenne et Algazelis, et per commentum Averroys super librum de It is important to mention the Nicomachean Ethics here because Her­
argumento poetico translatum, et per prologum in quo translator Hermannus
mannus Alemannus in the conclusion of his prologue to the translation
Allemanus se excusat quod textum Aristotelis quern fecit de dicto argumento non
potuit transferre, quia ignoravit metrum Graecum quibus utitur Aristotelis in hoc of the Rhetoric explicitly makes the connection between the Rhetoric
libro, et scimus quod hie liber est in Greco compositus, et de Greco in Arabicum and the Ethics. Further, he refers to himself as continuing the kind
translatus, licet in Latinum non sit conversus Aristotelis textus. Sed Alpharabius exponit
intencionem illius argumenti, et Avicenna similiter et Algasel et Averrois, quapropter
oportet ponere genus arguendi poetice, et quod logica de hoc constituat librum,
quoniam ad solam logicam pertinet argumenti compositio et doctrina. Ceterum
demonstravi in Metaphysicis quod hoc genus arguendi est necessarium, et quod 7 For an account of the dominance of the Rhetoric of the early Cicero on the
scientia debet de eo constitui in logica, et quod argumentum hoc est utilis omni argu­ Middle Ages, see James J. Murphy, “Cicero’s Rhetoric in the Middle Ages,” in The
mento cum feratur in anime salutem et circa virtutes et felicitatem, et ut vicia decli- Quarterly Journal of Speech, 54, 4 (1967), 334—341. “Medieval culture was, of course,
nantur. Quod argumentum proprium est in textu Moralis philosphie, et in ejus usu essentially a Latin culture”, p. 338. See p. 336 for the 14th century exclusion of
et similiter in theologicis probacionibus et doctrinis, et plus potest hoc argumentum Rhetoric from the curriculum at the University of Paris and the dominance of Cicero
in illis movere sine omni comparacione quam demonstracio quantum cumque potis- in Bologna and Italian schools. However, for Cicero the 13th century Schools were
sima habeatur. Et jam composui de eo tractatum in logicalibus, et ostendi quod ei limited to the Ps. Ciceronian Rhetoricam ad Herennium and to the De Inventione.
proprium est. Et secundum Aristotilem et secundum quod exponit Alpharabius, hoc 8 See Edward Kennard Rand, Cicero in the Courtroom of St Thomas Aquinas, Mil­
argumentum utitur semonibus pulchris et in fine decoris, ut rapiatur animus subito waukee, Marquette University Press, 1944 and James J. Murphy, “Rhetoric in the
in amorem virtutis et felicitatis, et in odium vicii et pene perpetue que ei respondet. Et Middle Ages,” p. I l l : Concerning William Moerbecke’s translation of the Rhetoric:
ideo sermones poetici qui sunt completi et pulchritudine et effacacia movendi animum “Composed about 1270 at the height of the Parisian interest in Aristotelian writings,
debent esse omati omni venustate loquendi prosaice et astricti omni lege metri et it appeared to be in the main stream of endeavors to make all the works of Aristotle
rithmi, sicut Scriptura Sacra in lingua primitiva que Hebrea est, et Boecius De conso- available to the Western world. Says a chronicle for the year 1273: “William of
lacione, et Alanus De consolatione nature et Poetria Oratii, et hymni Ecclesie, et Brabant, of the Order of Preachers, translated all the books of Aristotle from Greek
multum de officio divino, ut decore et suavitate sermonis animus subito et fortiter into Latin, word for word (verbum ex verbo), which translation scholars are now
moveatur. Nam “pro-desse volunt aut delectare”, poete, et Omne tulit punctum qui using in school, at the instance of Thomas Aquinas.” One should notice how Tho­
miscuit utile dulci. mas Aquinas in his account of the Passions, especially that of Anger (ira), uses the
See also Moralis philosophia, ed. E. Massa, pp. 255-6. See William F. Boggess, Rhetoric of Aristotle as his interpretative help. See Jeremiah Hackett, “Roger Bacon
“Hermannus Alemannus’s Rhetorical Translations,” VIATOR 2 (1971), 227-50; on Magnanimity and Virtue,” in Moral and Political Philosophy in the Middle Ages, ed.
(Ansto teles Latinus, XXXI, 1-2), RH ETO RIC A-translatio anonyma et guillelmi, Bazan, Andujar, Sbrocchi, New York-Ottawa-Toronto, 1995, Vol. I, 367-77.
ed. Bemhardus Schneider, (Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1978), 337-43 for a specimen of 9 The establishment in the University Curriculum of the Nicomachean Ethics of
Hermann’s translation. William F. Bogges, “Alfarabi and Rhetoric: The Cave Revis­ Aristode by scholars such as Roger Bacon and Thomas Aquinas was, perhaps, one
ited,” Phronesis, 15 (1970), 86-90. of the most revolutionary moves in medieval education.
138 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON RHETORIC AND POETICS 139

of work which Robert Grosseteste usubtills intellectus Linkoniensis episcopus” Bacon ends this section by noting how Aristotle states that the end
did recendy in his translation and gloss on the Nicomachean Ethics.101 or goal imposes teleological necessity on the means, and thus the
Bacon continues his account of Poetic argument itself and again poetic argument imposes a necessity on the other parts of logic.
notes the need for elegant prose, good meter and rythm and states Moreover, “the end [finis) of logic cannot be known without knowl­
that all of this pertains to Music.11 He had mentioned this in Communia edge of mathematics; neither can the means or principle of logic be
mathematica and had already treated this topic in the Opus maius and known without mathematics. And so the pure logician can provide
in the Opus tertium. He remarks: “On account of which, this book of nothing of value in logic (without the aid of mathematics).”14
Logic cannot be understood nor taught without the help of music When we return to Bacon’s works for Pope Clement IV, we notice
which gives us an account of the causes and reasons concerning prose, the extent to which these works are influenced by his readings in
meter and rythm.”12 And having once more scolded Hermannus rhetoric and poetics. Not only does he use the new materials from
Alemannus, he notes that this book on Poetics is the main goal and translations from Greek and Arabic, but he also returns to the main
completion of logic (finalis bgicae). It is so because it aims at the ulti­ sources of Latin rhetoric and poetics, to Cicero, Seneca, Horace and
mate good of the human being, that is, virtue and happiness (.Felicitas), especially to the De doctrina Christiana of St Augustine. Concerning the
and it moves one strongly towards them. He then notes that other latter text, he remarks that “the whole of book IV is concerned with
truthbearing forms of argument move the human being either to the present subject matter [i.e. the uses of rhetoric and poetics in
opinion such as dialectical argument or to science such as demonstra­ moral matters], and almost everything that I have said here [in Moralis
tive argument or to belief such as the rhetorical argument, but this philosophici] is found in that book in a philosophical mode.”15 The
kind of argument, [the Poetic argument] leads one to action and influence of Augustine’s writings on language, especially the De doctrina
orders one to the complete human good. “These then are the only Christiana had a profound impact on the writings of Roger Bacon in
four kinds of truthful argument concerning which Logic treats, as the I260’s.16
the books of Aristotle and others teach, and as I have demonstrated Before proceeding to an account of how Bacon makes use of the
in my Metaphysics and in my books on Logic.”13 sources of rhetorical and poetic argument from the ancient and early
medieval world, one should note that the Opus maius itself is con­
10 Hermannus Alemannus’s Prologue to his translation of the Rhetoric, cited. structed as a rhetorical argument. It is conceived as an introductory
William F. Bogges, art. tit., 250: Quemadmodum contingit in libro Nichomachie
quem Latini Ethicam Aristotelis appelant. Nam et hunc prout potui in latinum verti Persuasio to a projected work in philosophy. And while it does con­
eloquium ex arabico. Et postmodum reverendus pater magister Robertas Grossic apitis tain specific treatises such as De signis and the Perspectwa and De scientia
sed subtilis Linkoniensis episcopus ex primo fonte unde mandaverat, greco videlicet, experimental, it is largely a vast polemic on the state of learning in
ipsum est completius interpretatus et grecorum commends proprias annectens notulas
commentatus. Sic, si totius scientie largitori placuerit, contingere poterit in his opusculis the mid-13th century. More than that, it is a profound attempt to
primordialiter a nobis, etsi debeliter, elaboratis, quod ipse patrare dignetur qui vivit
et regnat etemaliter in perfecta trinitate. Amen. The reader should note that much
of Bacon’s recommendation about the interpretation of Aristotle’s Rhetoric and Poetics poetica nella storia delVOpus Maius, (Roma: Edizioni di Storia e Litteratura, Uomini e
is taken from this Prologue. For the importance of the Mcomachean Ethics for virtue Dottrine 3, 1955).
and human friendship in the context of these discussions, see James McEvoy, 14 Ibid., p. 18: Et ideo finis logice non potest sine mathematica sciri, sicut nec
“Grosseteste’s Reflections on Aristotelian Friendship: A ‘New’ Commentary on medium nec principium. Et ideo nihil dignum potest purus logicus in logicalibus
Nicomachean Ethics VIII. 8-14,” in James McEvoy, ed., Robert Grosseteste: New Perspectives pertractare.
on His Thought and Scholarship, (Instrumenta Patristica xxvii, Brepols, 1995), 149-168. 15 Moralis philosophia, ed. E. Massa, p. 258: Set, cum philosophic utilitas non patet
11 In Communia mathematica, Bacon presents a lengthy account of the connection of nisi quando trahitur ad divina, potest hec pars philosophic pulcherimme deservire
Rhetoric and Poetics to Music and Mathematics. See the paper of Nancy Van Deusen divinis, secundum quod pulchre et magnifice docent Sancti et precipue beatus
below. Augustinus, libro quarto De doctrina Christiana. Nam totus hie fiber est de hac
12 Ibid., 18: Quapropter hie liber logice non potest intelligi nec doceri sine beneficio materia, et fere quicquid nunc dixi, philosphice invenitur in illo libro.
musice cujus est causa et raciones prose metrorum et rithmorum d are .. . . 16 Thomas S. Maloney, “Is the De doctrina Christiana the Source for Roger Bacon’s
13 Ibid., p. 18: Sunt enim hec quatuor tantum argumenta veridica de quibus est Semiotics?,” in Edward D. English, ed. Reading and Wisdom: The De doctrina Christiana
logica, ut libri Aristotelis docent et aliorum, et hoc in Metaphysicis et Logiclibus of Augustine in the Middle Ages, Notre Dame and London, University of Notre Dame
demonstravi. On Bacon and the poetics, see Eugenio Massa, Ruggero Bacone: etica e Press, 126-142.
140 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON RHETORIC AND POETICS 141

harmonize the “new” works which had been lately translated from who include Robert Grosseteste, Adam Marsh, the logician William
Greek and Arabic with the traditional Latin and Christian texts. of Sherwod, Albertus Magnus and others. In my view, there is much
I have argued elsewhere that there is a remarkable parallel be­ evidence to show that Bacon’s polemic against the vulgus philosophorum
tween the aim and goal of Averroes Kitab fasl al-Maqual (The Decisive et theologorum at Paris was in part directed against the new school of
Treatise Determining the Nature of the Connection between Religion and Philosophy) Latin Aristotelianism, which began about 1262 under leadership of
and the Opus maius of Roger Bacon.17 I noted that although Bacon Siger of Brabant and Boethius of Dacia.20 It is clear also that Richard
did not know this work by Averroes, he did make use of Averroes’ Com­ Rufus O.F.M. and Thomas Aquinas O.P. came under Bacon’s attack,
mentary on the Poetics of Aristotle as well as works by al-Farabi, al-Ghazali and one can conclude that on some issues his attack on Rufus was
and Avicenna to construct a position that is analogous to that of a veiled attack on Bonaventure.21 According to Bacon, these are “the
Averroes.18 Like Averroes, he argues that the dialectical and demon­ false authorities”— “the modem teachers of the people”, and he adds:
strative arguments are deficient concerning moral matters. In such
Although many important portions of philosophy have been translated,
matters, one needs both the rhetorical argument for the masses and [they] make no use of them, and delight in small and trivial works
the poetic argument for direction of the person towards action. while neglecting the two better works on Logic, one of which has been
Like Averroes’s Decisive Treatise in the Islamic world, Bacon’s Opus translated with a commentary of al-Farabi [i.e. the Rhetoric of Aristotle
maius is essentially a moral-persuasive defense of a position. It is a and the Didascalia of al-Farabi], and an exposition of the second made
persuasio, a work of moral philosophical persuasion in both form and by Averroes has been translated without the text of Aristotle [i.e.
Averroes exposition on the Poetics] . Far more do they neglect all the
content. And it was intended as such by Bacon on the basis of what
rest possessing still greater value such as the nine sciences o f Mathe­
he understood to be a theory of persuasion that he had learned from matics, and the six great Natural Sciences, comprehending in themselves
the above mentioned writers. The importance of secetive writing, many others, and the four very excellent divisions o f moral philosophy.
influenced by al-Farabi and others, influenced Bacon.19 He makes it And they seek their wretched solace in Gratian and the other recognized
abundantly clear that on more controversial topics such as astrology Masters who had no knowledge of the parts o f Philosophy, even as
and alchemy, he is cloaking his references and meaning from the these men have not. They take refuge also in the bald statements of
certain Sacred Writers since they do not understand the reasons stated
common teachers.
above. For the Sacred Writers after Christ did not take advantage of
In the Opus maius, Bacon launches a polemic against “the sophis­ the great value of philosophy. . . [and] the host of modern students
tical authorities of the irrational multitude, men who are authorities neglect important sciences, although they were introduced after the time
in an equivocal sense.” By this he means the common run of student of Gratian.22*
and teacher at Paris. They are set in opposition to the wise (Sapientes),
20 Jeremiah Hackett, “Practical Wisdom and Happiness in the Moral Philosophy
17 Jeremiah Hackett, “Averroes and Roger Bacon on the Harmony of Religion of Roger Bacon,” Medioevo, XII (1986), 5-109.
and Philosophy,” in Ruth Link-Salinger ed. A Straight Path: Studies in Medieval Philosophy 21 Jeremiah Hackett, “Aquinas, Roger Bacon and Latin Averroism: The problem
and Culture: Essays in Honor o f Arthur Hyman, Washington D.C., The Catholic University of the Intellective Soul (anima intellectiva) 1266-77,” in Jeremiah Hackett, ed., Aquinas on
of America Press, 1989, 98-112. Mind and Intellect: New Essays, NY: Dowling College Press, 1996, 15-43, esp. 28-30.
18 See Irene Rosier-Catach, “Roger Bacon, Al-Farabi, et Augustin Rhetorique, 22 Opus maius I, ed, Bridges, (= Vol. Ill), 33: Modemi vero Doctores vulgi licet
Logique et Philosophic Morale,” in Gilbert Dahan, Irene Rosier-Catach, eds., La multa de philosphiae magnalibus sint translata, tamen non habent eorum usum,
rhetorique d’Aristote, traditions et commentaires, de I’Atiquite au XVIP siecle, (forthcoming): cum etiam in parvis et vilibus delectati duos libros meliores negligunt, quorum unus
This work demonstrates the manner in which the Rhetoric of Aristotle with the Middle translatus est cum commentario Alpharabii super ilium et alterius expositio per
Commentary of Averroes (trs. Hermannus Alemannus) and the works of al-Farabi, Averroem facta sine extu Aristotelis est translata. Et longe magis caetera quae
especially the De scientiis and Didascalia were used by Bacon. These works he fused majorem obtinent dignitatem, sicut novem scientias Mathematicae, et sex scientias
with the De doctrina Christiana of Augustine to produce his notion of persuasive rheto­ magnas Naturales, quae multas alias sub se comprehendunt, atque Morales quattuor
ric. For al-Farabi, see J. Langhade & M. Grignaschi, Al-Farabi: Deux Ouvrages Inedits partes negligunt dignissimas; et suae ignorantiae quaerunt miserabile solatium per
Sur La Rhetorique: I. Kitab Al-Hataba II. Didascalia in Rhetoricam Aristotelis ex Glossa Alpharabi, Gratianum et caeteros Magistros authenticos, qui non habuerunt notitiam partium
(Beyrouth: Dar El-Machreq Editeurs, 1971). Philosophiae, sicut nec praesentes; et per dicta sanctorum antiquorum simplicia, non
19 Leo Straus, Persecution and the Art of Writing, Chicago, University of Chicago intelligentes causas antedictas. Nam sancti post Christum non sunt usi multa
Press, 1988. Philosophia dignitate . .. multorum studentium modemorum magnas negligit scientias,
ROGER BACON ON RHETORIC AND POETICS 143
142 JEREMIAH HACKETT

work in moral philosophy is firmly set in a theological context. This


In Bacon’s view, in explicit dependence on Averroes, the masses will
can be seen from Bacon’s own words: “Besides, this science alone
always follow principles contrary to Philosophy. And this includes
[moral philosophy] or for the most part is concerned with the same
the common teachers and students of philosophy, law and theology.
matters as theology since theology considers the five abovementioned
He puts the matter as follows:
[sciences] albeit in a different manner, namely in the faith of Christ----
For the Wise have always been divided from the multitude, and they But theology is the noblest of the sciences, therefore that science
have veiled the secrets of wisdom not only from the world at large but which is most clearly related to it is nobler than the others.”24
also from the rank and file of those devoting themselves to philosophy.23 There is a rhetoric built into the whole structure of the Moralis
Bacon is deeply indebted above all to al-Farabi for his notion of philosophia. In part one, Bacon sets out to give a rhetorical argument
Rhetoric in the service of persuasion, and this combined with Bacon’s in which he attempts to combine Ancient Greek philosophers, Neo­
interest in comparing Religions and Cultures leads Bacon to emphasise platonic authors, Islamic writers, with traditional Latin and Christian
the moral and religious uses of a rhetoric and a poetics. Bacon’s is sources to present a philosophical Anthropology. In parts two and
particularly dependent on the De scientiis of al-Farabi. And indeed, three, he is alert to the rhetorical uses of argument in Social Philoso­
he makes a very interesting synthesis of the materials from the De phy and in theory of Virtue. In part four, he presents a persuasion
doctrina Christiana of Augustine and the newly translated works on concerning comparative religion. Part five has to do with the persua­
rhetoric from the Arabic authors. And yet, lurking in the background sion of those who believe in Christianity, and the short part six has
of this synthesis is Bacon’s plan for an application of Abu M a'shar’s to do with persuasion in legal matters.
works on astronomy-astrology to the determination of the cultural
characteristics of different societies. In a very real sense, Moralis philo­ The Role of Rhetoric in Morality and Religion
sophic,, part four, presents a sketch of a sociology of cultures and reli­
gions based on a calculation of character traits based on a model of Bacon is concerned with the role of argument in morality and religion.
astrology taken from Abu Ma'shar. He notes that the human being has greater difficulty with regard to
the operabilia than he does with speculative knowledge. In issues which
relate to justice, the virtues, peace, eternal happiness and worship of
Philosophia moralis: the Uses of Rhetorical and Poetical Argumentation God, the human being has great need of rational persuasion. But
these matters, since they touch on deeply felt emotions involve much
For Bacon, Philosophia moralis is concerned with human actions, with more than bare rationality. They involve motivation, desire, inclination,
the operabilia. Further, Moral Philosophy is seen by him as the “Queen hope, and will. In a word, they belong to the domain of Practical
of the Sciences.” It is the finis or end of all other branches of philo­ Reason. Also, due to man’s fallen condition, Bacon thinks that the
sophy and science, and “. . . the conclusions of the other sciences are human being has much need of “forceful and inducive” remedies in
principles in it in accordance with the relationship of the preceding practical affairs. “Now, because of the well-known works of Aristotle,
sciences to those that follow. . . .” Thus, there is an inner coherence we are, familiar with two kinds of argument, namely the dialectical
in Bacon’s scheme: following the Stoic model, Bacon subordinates and the demonstrative.”25 But a knowledge of both the Aristotelian
the study of language and physics to morals. From the viewpoint of Rhetoric and Poetics was lacking.
Christian theology, this is a Reductio artium ad theologiam. Thus, Bacon’s
24 Moralis philosophia, ed. E. Massa, 4: Ceterum, de eisdem negociatur hec sola
scientia vel maxime, de quibus theologia; quia theologia non considerat nisi quinque
cum tamen fuerint introductae post Gratianum et alios et in usu per viros Sapientiae predicta, licet alio modo, scilicet in fide Christi. . . . Set theologia est scientia
excellentis, quos oculis nostris conspeximus, et aliqui adhuc vivunt qui in solemnibus nobilissima; ergo ilia, que maxime convenit cum ea, est nobilior inter ceteras.. . .
studiis eas sapientibus perlegerunt. 25 Ibid., 250: Duo vero sunt argumenta nota per libros Anstotelis de hiis vulgatos,
23 Ibid., 9—10: Nam semper sapientes contra vulgus divisi sunt, et arcana sapientiae scilicet dialecticum et demonstrativum.
non toti mundo solum sed plebi philosophantium velaverunt.
144 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON RHETORIC AND POETICS 145

One needs to emphasise here that Bacon has a very difficult task. his conviction that rhetoric is essentially directed towards engender­
He is presenting an account of Aristode’s ethics and his rhetoric in ing action. Teaching [doctrina) alone is a necessary but not a sufficient
a context where Cicero was the Master of forensic rhetoric. More condition for action. A person may well know that something is
importantly, Bacon is very alert to Aristode’s injunctions in the morally right, but the same person may avoid the requisite moral
Nicomachean Ethics that demonstrative or mathematical arguments may actions. In such a case, the forms of moral persuasion may be required.
not be appropriate in morals.26 He notes that it is equally erroneous Where public oratory is concerned, Bacon advocates that the speaker
for moral argument to use demonstrations as it is for mathematical should mix the plain, the moderate and the grand styles.
sciences to use rhetorical argument. Dialectical arguments are equally There is some repetition in Bacon’s text. Still, he gives a threefold
invalid in ethics. These kinds of argument are unable to sway the division of rhetoric which corresponds to his threefold division of
mind to the good. They lead only to a knowledge of the true. Moral practical moral philosophy. The first kind is that used in persuasion
reason is primarily practical (non-speculative) and is directed to the in Religion. This deals with levels of assent and proof. The second
achievement of goodness in a person’s life. Therefore, in the practi­ kind has to do with forensic oratory and is found in Cicero in his
cal sphere one has need of a different kind of argument, namely, the book on rhetoric. The third kind is concerned with things which
rhetorical argument. sway us in regard to human actions (the operabilia). The first two
Now, in Bacon’s view, “Ciceronian rhetoric does not teach this kinds, he calls “rhetoric absolutely speaking.” The third kind, he says,
kind of argumentation, except in terms of cases to be pleaded, in “is properly called poetic argument by Aristotle and other philosophers,
order that an orator might persuade a judge. But as I have pointed since truthful poets use it to sway men to the honesty of virtue. . . .”29
out there are three kinds of persuasion, and therefore the argument The difference between a Poet who has a truthful poem and one
taught by Cicero is inadequate; rather we need the complete doctrine who has a frivolous rhyme is presented by Bacon in a contrast between
found in Aristotle and his commentators.”27 For Bacon, the rhetoric the Roman poets Horace and Ovid. Whereas Horace is noble and
of Aristotle is one which has an “argument taken from a group of beneficial to the reader, Ovid is plainly frivolous, if not downright
truthful arguments, and [which] lacks fraud and sophistry.”28 Further, morally injurious to young people. However, despite this dependence
this rhetorical persuasion which is directed to belief, action, and right on Roman writers, Bacon makes it clear that Aristotle in the Rhetoric
judgment is based on principles of eloquence. That is, it aims to and Poetics is to be taken as the true norm of moral discourse.
render the hearer docile, well-disposed, and eager. And it takes care In Bacon’s account ca. 1267, the problem is that “the unlearned
to explain the truth clearly so that difficult problems can be untied. multitude” of university students are ignorant of the composition of
Thus, the element of utility must be introduced if the truth is to be such arguments. And this is so, especially since the Poetics of Aristotle
believed, acted on, and rightly judged. Oratory or Public Speech is lacking. Still, in his view, diligent students could figure it out from
demands not only teaching (doctrina), which is obligatory, and pleasure, Averroes’ Commentary, the Rhetoric, which had been translated, but is
which is voluntary; it requires persuasion, which is essential. Notwith­ not in common use, and from Horace’s Ars poetica, al-Farabi’s De
standing his acclaim for Aristotle, Bacon takes some of this material scientiis, Avicenna and al-Ghazali on Logic. Both here and again in
from Cicero and St Augustine, and uses this material to drive home part six, Bacon maintains the superiority of moral rhetoric over foren­
sic. In the remainder of part five, Bacon gives examples of the uses
of rhetoric in moral and religious truth. The following is a short
26 Ibid., 250: Unde Aristoteles primo Ethice vult quod moralis sciencia non habeat review of these exempla.
uti demonstracione, set rhetorico argumento.
27 Ibid., p. 251: Rhetorica vero tulliana non docet hoc argumentum, nisi propter
causas ventilandas, ut orator possit persuadere iudici, quatinus consenciat parti sue 29 Ibid., p. 255: Tercium vero argumentum, quod flectit ad ea, que hec quinta pars
et indignetur adverse. Sed flexus triplex est, ut dixi; et ideo hoc argumentum, ut considerat, rhetoricum quidem est, sed vocatur proprie nomine “Poeticum” ab Aris-
Tullius docet, non sufficit, sed indignemus completa doctrina Aristotilis et commen- totile et ceteris philosophis, quia poete veraces usi sunt eo in flectendo homines ad
tatorum eius. virtutum honestatem.. .. See G. Dahan, “Notes et Textes Sur La Poetique Au Moyen
28 Ibid., p. 252. Age,” in Archive d’Histoire Doctrinale et litteraire du Moyen Age, T.XLVII, 1981, 171-239.
146 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON RHETORIC AND POETICS 147

First, he advocates the view that “poetics”, his third kind of rhetori­ language as a structure and the living embodiment of teaching and
cal argument, must use “the grand style, since it always speaks of speech.
great and magnificent things and therefore requires high-sounding The conclusion of part five provides Bacon’s remarks on the rela­
language when the mind is swayed to action.”30 He goes on in general tion of rhetoric to theology, and again he finds confirmation of this
to advocate a mixture of styles, but he insists that the grand style topic in book four of Augustine’s De doctrina ckristiana. He sees Scrip­
must dominate the others. He gives as an example the speech of ture as having a great variety of rhetorical ornaments such that it needs
Cicero on his return from exile. And he notes that this kind of grand interpretation in the following manner. The word of God is con­
style is make up from “analogies drawn from the properties of things.” tained in wonderous enigmas which must be deciphered; here the
Thus, virtue is compared to light, and favorable things to whatever help of both Pseudo-Dionysius and Cicero are invoked. This view of
causes light. The happiness of the other life is compared to all that the unfolding of the senses of Scripture as an unveiling which leads
is good in this life. Now, it might be thought that Bacon’s position to greater knowledge of the truth agrees with Bacon’s earlier reflec­
commits him to a rhetorical twisting of the truth. Indeed, following tions on this topic in Opus maius, part two. For Bacon, there is no
Avicenna, he holds that this kind of argument is not concerned with automatic avenue to truth or an inner vision of truth. One has need
speculative truth. Yet, such a rhetorical proposition is true not accord­ of philosophy in all of its parts, and especially Rhetoric and Poetics
ing to nature, but “by way of analogy.”31 to gain access to that truth.
This theory of interpretation in Bacon is closely linked to his view Rhetoric and Poetics are not a kind of afterthought to formal logic,
that the spiritual sense of the text of Scripture will not be understood a kind of icing on the cake or a kind of nice style. For Bacon they
unless one understands the literal text.32 Thus, the analogies will be are not a take it or leave it subject, but an essential part of the work
worthless unless they presuppose a base of literal meaning. Rhetoric of hermeneutics. And in his view, Aristotle, “the Master of those
simply accepts the existence of such literal truth and simply draws who know” is the master of the teaching on Rhetoric and Poetics.
analogies, similarities and comparisons from things, but one is not He ends by advocating that Preachers improve their presentation by
concerned whether such things exist or not. a study of rhetoric and poetics. In part six of the Moralis philosophia,
Poetic argument, however, is not complete in simply giving analogies Bacon re-introduces forensic rhetoric and tells the reader to look to
drawn from the properties of things. To reach fulfillment, there must al-Farabi on the Rhetoric and to Cicero and Seneca.
exit over and above the flow of language a movement of the mind Corollary: Did Roger Bacon’s views have any direct influence?
and a proper gesture of the body in keeping with the words of the One thing is clear; the whole issue of the Rhetoric and Poetics became
teaching, so that the hearer will be moved “. . . we ought to learn a public issue. By 1270, Moerbecke’s translation was in use at Paris
more by the required affects and gestures than by language. . . .”33 probably due to the influence of Thomas Aquinas. But again, it was
This remark shows us that Bacon makes a sharp distinction between not taught as an ordinary course.
The one thinker who give evidence of the influence of the Aristo­
30 Ibid., p. 256: Hoc argumentum semper utitur grandi stilo, quia semper de telian Rhetoric and Poetics is Giles of Rome (.Aegidius Romanum). In
grandibus eloquitur et magnificis rebus, et ideo semper de grandibus requiritur; sed his Commentary on the Rhetoric (1280’s), he begins his discussion with a
hoc maxime est cum flectitur animus ad agendum .. . .
31 Ibid., p. 258: Et secundum quod docet Avicenna in L(og)ica sua, hoc argumentum
presentation of the position that the part of Rhetoric which deals
non curat de veritate proposocionum nec de falsitate, quia non movet intellectum with the composition of Rhetorical Arguments belongs to Logic.
speculativum, sed practicum, ut manifestum est, cum de peccatore dicitur quod est Further, he takes the view that Philosophia moralis is the locus for the
<sus lota in volutabro luti>. Propositio ista non est vera secundum proprietatem
rerum, sed secundum similitudinem. See See Bacon, De signis and Cts on analogy. uses of Rhetoric.34 The Rhetoric has survived in many manuscripts
32 See H. De Lubac, Exegese Medievale, Les quatre Sens de VEcriture (4 vols.) Paris,
1959-1964; see also Tzvetan Todorov, Synbolisme et interpretation, Paris 1978; Edward
D. English, ed. Reading and Wisdom: The De doctrina Christiana. .., ed. cit. 34 Aegidius Romanus (Colonna), Commentaria in rhetoricam Aristotelis, Venice 1515
33 Moralis philosophia, 262: . . . magis debemus afectibus et gestibus debitis exprimere (Minerva reprint, 1968), 1: Rhetorica assecutiva dialectice est.. .. See J.R. O ’Donnell,
quam sermone. . . . “The Commentary of Giles of Rome on the Rhetoric of Aristotle,” in Essays in
148 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON RHETORIC AND POETICS 149

and this despite its exclusion from the curriculum of the Universities and to the Averroes’ Commentary on the Poetics. When we bear in mind
until the late Middle Ages and early Renaissance. Giles of Rome’s that the Western World did not get the complete Poetics until William
Commentary played a major role in presenting to a Latinate culture Moerbecke’s translation in the 1280’s and did not get a first Commentary
a Rhetoric which was different in scope from the Ars poetica of Horace on the Rhetoric until Giles of Rome completed his commentary in the
and the many Ciceronian writings on Rhetoric. Further, it would 1270’s, then one grasps a true image of Bacon’s situation. He was a
appear that the strong linkage between rhetoric and Moralis philosophia transition figure who was an advocate for a deeper study of what he
which one finds in Giles of Rome led to an emphasis on this aspect held to be the “greater” works in logic by Aristotle, namely the
of the subject. This is so, because one does not find much connec­ Rhetoric and the Poetics. By holding that the domain of the true is
tion between Rhetoric and Logic during this period. Bacon may have tied to logic and a part of rhetoric and of poetics, that part dealing
sown the seed but it was Giles of Rome who developed Latin knowl­ with the formulation of rhetorical and poetical truth, is part of Logic
edge Aristotle’s rhetoric and its relationship to ethics. and that its application and use is tied to Moral Philosophy, Bacon
Translations into the vernacular of works on Rhetoric, especially was well on the way to noticing that in Aristotle’s practical philoso­
that of Aristotle, came late. In fact, it had to wait until the late phy which he admired, nous and phronesis are closely related. Bacon
Renaissance. Aristotle’s Rhetoric was not translated into English until made a criticism of the division of the Trivium because he believed
Thomas Hobbes penned his paraphrase in the 17th century. In this that such a division reduced the truth bearing capacity of rhetoric
as in the case of the doctrine of Signs, he continued the interests of and poetics. By placing rhetoric over against Grammar and Formal
his fellow-countryman, Roger Bacon.35 Logic, the medieval curriculum led to an interpretation where Rhetoric
was the non-logical (non-truthful) aspect of speech, thus in time lead­
ing to rhetoric having a purely pejorative meaning. Rhetoric had to
Conclusion be distinguished from sophistry and fraud. The latter were the oppo­
site of truthful speech. The construction of a true rhetorical argu­
Because Bacon’s study of rhetoric and poetics has such an evident ment, in Bacon’s view, was a task for “Logic”, while the applications
influence on his Opus maius, it was necessary to pick out his various and uses of such arguments was the task of Moral Philosophy. And
remarks which he uses concerning this topic. His work on rhetoric at the heart of this matter is Bacon’s recognition of unique impor­
has not come down to us. But we can see his context in outline. He tance of Aristotle’s reflections on practical reason in the Nicomachean
is dealing with a University system which placed all the emphasis on Ethics.
Grammar and Logic to the detriment of rhetoric and poetics. The Further, by placing emphasis on Aristotle’s Rhetoric and Poetics,
Aristotelian Nicomachean Ethics had only been translated completely Bacon was helping the West to see aspects of life and thought which
by Robert Grosseteste in 1249. Bacon had access to Hermannus were absent from Latin rhetoric with it overemphasis on legal-forensic
Allemanus’s translation of the Rhetoric which reached Paris by 1256, argument. In the end, language study as well as the study of nature
was to be directed to moral good.

Medieval History presented to Bertie Wilkinson, ed. T.A. Sandquist and M.R. Powicke,
Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1974, 139-156. See also G. Bruni, “The ‘De
Differentia Rhetoricae, Ethicae, et Politicae’’ of Aegidius Romanus,” in New Scholasticism, VI
(1932), 1-18. For the manner in which the Rhetoric of Aristode became detached
from logical concerns and became connected only with moral issues, see James Jerome
Murphy, “The Scholastic Condemnation of Rhetoric in the Commentary of Giles
of Rome on the Rhetoric of Aristotle,” in Artes Liberaux et Philosophie Au Moyen Age,
Montreal-Paris, 1969, 833-41.
35 For a recent study of the significance of Rhetoric in Thomas Hobbes, see
Quentin Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in The Philosophy of Thomas Hobbes, Cambridge
University Press, 1996.
7. ROGER BACON’S KNOWLEDGE OF MATHEMATICS

George Molland

I. Introduction

The cult of Roger Bacon has had many and shifting facets: he has
been lauded as magician, alchemist, experimental scientist, perspec-
tivist, ecclesiastical reformer, justified rebel, scourge of the wilfully
ignorant, and so on. But persistently there appears the image of him
as mathematician, and especially as one who would apply mathematics
to natural and other branches of philosophy for the greater good of
Christendom. At the end of the seventeenth century, the noted mathe­
matician John Wallis wrote to Leibniz that, “Those who in the present
century (following Galileo) joined mathematics to natural philosophy
have advanced physics to an enormous extent. This was also being
attempted by Roger Bacon (a great man in a dark century) four
hundred years ago (and more).” And similar encomia abound across
the ages.
In this chapter I shall discuss Bacon’s conception of the role, nature
and methods of mathematics, concentrating on arithmetic and geome­
try, which were joined in the subset of the seven liberal arts tradi­
tionally known as the quadrivium by the more applied mathematical
sciences of music and astronomy, but, as we shall see, Bacon made
modifications to this scheme. Bacon’s expressed enthusiasm for the
subject was enormous, at least from the time of the works for the
Pope around 1267 onwards. Before that time the situation is less
clear, although he obviously needed time to acquire the mathemati­
cal knowledge displayed in the Opus maius, Opus minus and Opus tertium,
and some mathematical facility is evinced in his Compotus, dating from
the earlier 1260’s.
With the exception of some geometrical argumentation in optical
contexts, the mathematical sections of the works for the Pope are
mainly concerned with persuasions as to the extreme usefulness of
the subject, and Bacon’s discussions often roam so far afield that the
actual connection with mathematics becomes tenuous, as for instance
in his arguments against the unity of matter in all bodies and his
152 GEORGE MOLLAND ROGER BACON’S KNOWLEDGE OF MATHEMATICS 153

long discussions of the length and shortness of syllables, with respect Bacon, Stewart C. Easton tentatively dated the first recension of the
to the differing relative positionings of different consonants and work to 1257, and argued that it at least preceded the Opus tertium.3
vowels. Bacon’s faith in the power of mathematics is one of his best- His principal argument for this stems from the mention of Petrus
known features, and we shall return to the theme at the end of the Peregrinus as a great mathematician in the Opus tertium compared
chapter, but one remark is in order at this point. It concerns the with his absence from the Communia mathematica. For reasons that will
need that Bacon felt to defend the subject against possible attacks on be evident later (in my consideration of Bacon’s authorities) I am
the grounds that mathematicians were magicians, or something equally unable to accept this argument, and on various counts I am inclined
as bad. This gained its plausibility from the fact that in the tradi­ to date it after 1267.
tional literature astrologers were often called mathematici and attacked
for necessitarian views. Bacon is much concerned to defend true
mathematics (including legitimate forms of astrological prediction) II. History and Authorities
against such aspersions. To this end, in both the Opus maius and the
Opus tertium, he attempted to distinguish mathesis with a short e, rep­ At least in his mature works, Roger Bacon was adamant about situ­
resenting true mathematics, from mathesis or matesis, with a long e ating mathematics in wider contexts that he loosely comprehends
representing false mathematics. Here he made a philological error, under the term metaphysical. Thus he begins the Communia Mathematica
which he corrected almost tacitly in later writings; I say almost tacitly as follows:
because he does rail against the ignorance of those who got the long
Everyone treating any special science must frequently compare it to
and the short e the wrong way round, but without mentioning that
the science common to all, which is called metaphysics, and whose
he himself had belonged to their number.1 This point can be useful property it is to give the division, difference and origin of all great
in attempting to resolve the often vexed question of the relative sciences, and what is proper to each; also to assign their order, [to
chronology of his writings. say] who discovered them and when and where they were discovered,
One of the works in which it is corrected is the Communia mathematica, and to verify their principles. Each special science supposes its prin­
ciples to be, and it cannot investigate them by its own power, as Aristotle
which, together with an annexed truncated treatise on geometry, will
teaches. And I have made this manifest in my Metaphysics.4
provide the main source for this chapter.2 O r at least it is corrected
in what is called the second recension of this work, for the Communia Unfortunately this Metaphysics (if it were ever actually written) is not
mathematica is represented in two extant manuscripts, Digby 76 of the known to be extant. It certainly cannot be identified with the work
Bodleian Library, Oxford, and Sloane 2156 of the British Library, printed by Robert Steele under that title in Fascicle I of the Opera
London. The Sloane manuscript contains only the beginning of the Hactenus Inedita, even taking into account the more complete version
work, while the Digby manuscript contains the later parts of the work of this found in two Vatican manuscripts.5 It may at one stage have
and the geometrical material. The two manuscripts overlap in the been in the library of St Augustine’s, Canterbury,6 but for the present
middle, and a comparison reveals clearly that the Sloane manuscript
contains a later, revised version of the work. In his fine biography of 3 S.C. Easton, Roger Bacon and his Search for a Universal Science: A Reconsideration of the
Life and Work of Roger Bacon in the Light of his own Stated Purposes (Oxford, 1952), 88.
4 Communia Mathematica Fratris Rogeri, ed. R. Steele [hereafter, CM], Opera Hactenus
Inedita Rogeri Baconi [hereafter, O H I], XVI (Oxford: Clarendon, 1940), 1-2.
1 Cf. my “Roger Bacon’s Appropriation of Past Mathematics”, Tradition, Transmis­ 5 Little, “Roger Bacon’s Works, 407. I have consulted photostats of the relevant
sion, Transformation: Cultural Exchange in the Premodem World, ed. S.J. Livesey & F.J. parts of the Vatican manuscripts, held in the Bodleian Library, Oxford as MS Lat.
Ragep (Leiden: Brill, forthcoming). misc. d. 37.
2 I think that the De laudibus mathematicae, on which see A.G. Little, “Roger Bacon’s 6 Steele’s item no. 3 in his list in Metaphysica Fratris Rogeri Ordinis Fratrum Minomm
Works, with References to the MSS. and Printed Editions”, Roger Bacon: Essays, ed. de Viciis Contractis in Studio Theologie, ed. Robert Steele, OHI, I (Oxford, 1905), iii,
A.G. Little (Oxford, 1914), 375-426, at 393-394, may be worthy of greater atten­ seems to me the most likely candidate. Cf. M.R. James, The Ancient Libraries of Canter­
tion than it has often been accorded. I cannot consider it here, but hope soon to bury and Dover: The Catalogues of the Libraries of Christ Church Prioy and St Augustine’s Abbey
publish a separate study of it. at Canterbury and of St Martin’s Priory at Dover (Cambridge, 1903), 286, 313.
154 GEORGE MOLLAND ROGER BACON’S KNOWLEDGE OF MATHEMATICS 155

at least we must draw evidence for Bacon’s views on contextualisation of the Communia Mathematica, we read that, “It is to be believed that
from other sources. he knew it later, because it is known in these times.”11
Let us first look at the historical dimension. It was one of Bacon’s But, reverting to our main theme, we must note that there were
most firmly held beliefs that all worthwhile philosophical and scientific traditions more special to the history of mathematics available to
knowledge had been revealed to the ancient patriarchs and prophets Bacon. In this connection he quotes from Adelard of Bath in the
near the beginning of time, and then handed down to later ages, but version of Euclid’s Elements usually known as Adelard III:
not without considerable distortion.7 Thus it had continually been in
Geometry like the other disciplines went on in use before it did in art.
need of renovation by a variety of means; three notable restorers had
Its use grew up with the Egyptians. Since the flooding Nile covered
been Solomon, Aristotle and Avicenna, and it seems clear that Bacon over the boundaries of their fields each year, they instituted certain
would have liked to see himself as a fourth. Josephus had been a procedures of measurement, by which they recovered fields of the
prime source for the earlier part of Bacon’s story, in whose accounts previous measure. Then philosophers, reviewing and approving these
of the descent of Seth, of Noah and his sons, and of Abraham, the procedures, and taking thence the occasion, applied their efforts to
mathematical sciences figure prominently, but when we approach the mensuration. But because of the difficulty of the thing, individuals
stopped short of perfecting the work; some, like Pythagoras and Archytas,
restoration theme they are less in evidence, for neither Solomon, nor instituted the rudiments, and others, like Plato, Aristotle and Alexander,
Aristotle, nor Avicenna was particularly renowned mathematically. more advanced parts, until at length Euclid by superadding confirma­
We may, however, pause on one facet of Bacon’s account of tion and order wove together the proposed art, and marked it as a
Aristotle, which also shows how sometimes in Bacon’s mind the idea monument for the memory of posterity.12
of the restoration of knowledge could be (confusedly or otherwise)
This, as Bacon notes, could appear at variance with his main tradi­
almost identified with a notion of scientific progress. In the Categories
tion, but he seems to see the two as reconciled in the preface to a
Aristotle had spoken of the quadrature of the circle as something,
work that he believed to be by Boethius.
supposing it knowable, of which knowledge did not yet exist, although
the knowable existed.8 The circle of course cannot be squared by Although many, and almost all the common authors, grant this, citing
elementary geometrical means, but this fact was unappreciated by works known to them, yet if one turns over the histories back to the
earliest times, one will find that in Book I of the Antiquities Josephus
Bacon, and in any case was not for him the main point. In the Opus
determines that this science was discovered at the beginning of the
Maius he used it as an example of Aristotle’s limitations, “for he world by the sons of Adam, before the Flood. And Varro the most
confesses that he did not know the quadrature of the circle, which in skilled of the Latins grants this. And Boethius, at the beginning of his
these days is truly known, and since he was ignorant of this, then all Practical Geometry, relates the common rationale of its discovery, as given
the more of greater things.”9 His sentiments in the De secretis operibus above, on account of the Nile, but he approves Varro’s opinion, who
artis et naturae are similar, and he appends what is ostensibly a further testifies that it had been possessed for long ages before this.13
affirmation of progress: “For sages are now ignorant of many things
which the crowd of students will know in future times.”10 But it was
uncharacteristic of Bacon to diminish Aristotle, and so in what I judge 11 CM, 120.
to be his more mature opinion, but expressed in the first recension 12 George Molland, “Roger Bacon’s Geometria Speculated', Vestigia Mathematica: Studies
in Medieval and Early Modem Mathematics in Honour of H.L.L. Busard, ed. M. Folkerts
and J.P. Hogendijk (Amsterdam, 1993), 265-303, at 296-297; cf. M. Clagett, “King
Alfred and the Elements of Euclid”, Isis, 45 (1954), 269-277, at 273-274. For the
7 On this schema see my “Roger Bacon and the Hermetic Tradition in Medieval nomenclature “Adelard III” see M. Clagett, “The Medieval Latin Translations from
Science”, Vivarium, 31 (1993), 140-160. the Arabic of the Elements of Euclid, with Special Emphasis on the Versions of Adelard
8 Categoriae 7, 7b31—33. of Bath”, Isis, 44 (1953), 16-42. Although there is substantial doubt about Adelard’s
9 The “Opus Majus” of Roger Bacon, ed. J.H . Bridges (3 vols.: I—II, Oxford, 1897; authorship of, especially, Adelard II, it seems to me fairly safe to ascribe Adelard III
III, London, 1900; repr. Frankfurt, 1964), III, 14. to him.
10 Fr. Rogeri Bacon Opera Quaedam Hactenus Inedita, Vol. 1, containing I.— Opus tertium; 13 Molland, ibid. For the reference to “Boethius” see J.P. Migne, Patrologiae Cursus
II.— Opus minus; III.— Compendium philosophiae, ed. J.S. Brewer (London, 1859), 542. Completus. .. . Series prima (Paris, 1844-93), LXIII, 1352-53.
156 GEORGE MOLLAND ROGER BACON S KNOWLEDGE OF MATHEMATICS 157

Whatever we may think of this reconciliation, it is clear that Euclid Scientiis and the De Ortu Scientiarum ascribed to him are often appealed
is a pivotal figure in Bacon’s historical picture of mathematics, as to, usually on classificatory themes, although, as we shall see, one of
Aristotle was in that of knowledge in general. However, whereas Bacon his references is seriously misleading—or at least very puzzling. He
took pains to find as little fault with Aristotle as possible, this reverence also refers unspecifically to algebraic or algorithmic works, which must
was not extended to Euclid, with whom Bacon was prepared to take derive either proximately or remotely from Arabic originals.
issue on a number of points: he clearly had not been granted the Among the Latins, Boethius is Bacon’s most respected authority,
same special divine illuminations that had assuredly favoured Aristotle. especially for arithmetic and music. On the former subject he also
But we leave this topic in abeyance for the moment, while giving often appeals to Jordanus (although unfortunately without giving any
a more general (though unexhaustive) survey of Bacon’s mathemati­ biographical indications on this enigmatic figure), but says that he
cal authorities (excluding those on astronomy).14 Among ancient authors drew from the founts of Boethius and also was liable to include too
Bacon mentions Theodosius for spherics, Vitruvius for architecture, many superfluities. Besides this, Bacon mentions Jordanus De Triangulis,
and a work De conductibus aquarum (perhaps by Philo of Byzantium), which in a more pristine form was usually known as the Philotegni,18
but there is little sign that he used any of them, at least in a stricdy but there is little sign that he actually used it, and the same applies
mathematical context, and the same applies to Euclid’s Data, which to his citations of a De isoperimetris (which in its original Latin form
Bacon mentions (under the title De quantitatibus datis), as well as the was a direct translation from the Greek), and an otherwise unknown
Elements. On the other hand he does employ Ptolemy’s Optics for work De replentibus locum, although Bacon did spend much time dis­
geometrical purposes. Bacon also refers to De Curvis Superficiebus cussing, in an Aristotelian context, problems of filling place.19
Archimenidis and Liber Piramidum Apollonii. Both these works are deriva­ I now move to two passages where Bacon, at least apparently,
tive from rather than by their cited ancient authors. The first is usually singles out certain contemporary mathematicians for special praise.
ascribed to a certain Johannes de Tinemue15 (on whom a little more The,first comes from the Opus Tertium, and reads as follows: “There
below), and the second is a fragment on conic sections16 prefaced by are only two perfect [mathematicians], namely Master John of London
Gerard of Cremona to his translation of Alhazen’s De speculis combu- and Master Peter of Maricourt (Petrus de Maharii curia), a Picard;
rentibus, which conveniently brings us to the Arabs. The mathemati­ another two are good, namely Master Campanus of Novara and
cal influence of Alhazen (Ibn al-Haytham) is of course pervasive in Master Nicholas, the teacher of the Lord Amaury de Montfort.”20
Bacon’s optical discussions, but he also often mentions the above The context is the necessity of having excellent mathematicians, but
short work on parabolic mirrors, though without himself displaying there are problems with the passage. O f five relevant manuscripts
much technical knowledge of conic sections. He makes rather more two (including what I regard as the best) present this as a marginal
use of Gerard of Cremona’s translation of the commentary on Euclid note, and of the three others two insert it in one place in the text
by Anaritius (al-Nayrizi), who also introduced him to some of Sim­ and one in another. It thus clearly originated as a gloss, and, although
plicius’s mathematical views. Although Bacon usually uses the version I am strongly inclined to attribute it to Bacon himself, we cannot be
of Euclid known as Adelard II (now more plausibly ascribed to Robert absolutely sure, and it could have been made considerably later than
of Chester),17 he does from time to time appeal to the (partial) trans­ 1267, at about which time the original composition of the Opus Tertium
lation accompanying Anaritius’s commentary. Both al-Farabi’s De is dated. The second passage is from the first recension of the Communia

14 The principal references for this part of the chapter are CM, 42-49, 157-159, 18 Clagett, Archimedes, V, 145-477.
and Molland, “Bacon’s Geometria Speculativa”, 266-267. 19 A.G. Molland, “An Examination of Bradwardine’s Geometry”, Archive for His­
15 It is edited and translated into English by M. Clagett, Archimedes in the Middle tory of Exact Sciences, 19 (1978), 113-175, at 171-172, reprinted in my Mathematics and
Ages (Vol. I, Madison, 1964; Vols. II-V , Philadelphia, 1976-84), I, 439-520. the Medieval Ancestry of Physics (Aldershot, 1995).
16 Edited in Clagett, Archimedes, IV, 3-13. 20 I work from the new edition and English translation that I am preparing of
17 See H.L.L. Busard & M. Folkerts, Robert of Chester’s (?) Redaction of Euclid’s Elements: this work. A Latin text of the passage is printed in Opera Quaedam Hactenus Inedita,
The So-Called Adelard I I Version (Basel, 1992). ed. Brewer, 34—35.
158 GEORGE MOLLAND
ROGER BACON’S KNOWLEDGE OF MATHEMATICS 159

Mathematica, in the context of how conventional mathematical education


James accordingly conjectured that this John of London should be
included the learning of an inordinate number of useless propositions.
identified with Roger’s pupil John, whom he had specially educated
Bacon continued: “Because the books and teachers of mathematics
and had sent as courier to the Pope. James drew attention to the
insist on the multiplication of conclusions and demonstrations, no
fact that early antiquarians and bibliographers referred to Bacon’s
one can arrive at knowledge of this science in the common way unless
pupil as John of London, and suggested that they may have had
he devotes 30 or 40 years, as is plain in those who have flourished
access to sources no longer extant. He was, however, understandably
in these sciences, like the lord Robert of happy memory, lately Bishop
loath to identify him with the perfect mathematician mentioned in
of the Church of Lincoln [i.e. Grosseteste], and Brother Adam Marsh,
the Opus Tertium, since at the time he would have been too young
and Master John Bandoun, and the like.” The intent is not unambigu­
for the description. But if this gloss was added at a much later date,
ously laudatory, and so {pace Easton) we should not expect the pas­
the reference is plausible, although still highly conjectural. What is
sage to include a complete listing of contemporary excellent mathe­
certain is that Bacon’s pupil cannot be identified with John Bandoun,
maticians. But let us run through the names mentioned in the two
for it was Bacon’s pride and joy that he had educated his John by
passages.
a very effective and speedy method.23
John of London and John Bandoun. I couple these names together since
Peter of Maricourt (Petrus Peregrinus). It is not surprising to see this spe­
there has been an understandable tendency to think that they may
cial hero of Bacon’s listed as a perfect mathematician, and his inclu­
well have been the same person. A recent example of this is Wilbur
sion increases one’s confidence that the gloss was the work of Bacon
Knorr, who would go further and identify them both with Johannes
himself. The only extant works ascribed to Peter are the famous letter
de Tinemue, the above-mentioned author of the geometrical work
on magnetism, and a work on the construction of the astrolabe.
De curvis superficiebus; Knorr also ascribes other geometrical works to
However, Bacon’s eulogies, even allowing for exaggeration, make clear
the composite figure, including a recension of the Adelard III ver­
that his range was far wider. He is particularly praised as a master
sion of Euclid.21 While not wishing flatly to contradict this thesis, I
of experiments [dominus experimentorum), and, associated with this, for
confess to being unconvinced. There also seem to be argumenta a silentio
his work on alchemy. But mathematics also entered his ambit, for
against it in that Bacon fails to mention John in connection with the
instance in his work on astronomical instruments (and probably more
De Curvis Superficiebus Archimenidis or the Adelard III version of Euclid,
generally in astronomy), and in his construction of a parabolic buring
which he refers to as the editio specialis of Alardus Bathoniensis. In
mirror, for which Bacon implied that he used Alhazen’s quite sophisti­
the course of his article Knorr notes an intriguing possibility raised
cated De Speculis Comburentibus.24 Bacon was certainly acquainted with
by M.R. James in his work on the ancient libraries of Canterbury
Peter and very much influenced by him, but it remains a moot point
and Dover.22 James remarked on the large number of books that
as to how much this was the case in mathematics. As we noted above,
were given to St Augustine’s Abbey at Canterbury by a certain John
S.C. Easton used the absence of Peter from Bacon’s list in the first
of London, who was at some stage a monk there. Many of the works
recension of the Communia Mathematica as evidence for an early dat­
in the manuscripts were of a mathematical or astronomical nature,
ing (he suggests 1257) of that work,25 but I think it could as easily be
and the collection also exhibited a strong Baconian connection in
explained by his not having taken 30 or 40 years to learn mathematics.
containing both works by Roger Bacon and ones (such as that by
Petrus Peregrinus on the magnet) in which he had a strong interest.
23 See especially Opus Maius, ed. Bridges, III, 23-25. On John see also F. Picavet,
Essais sur I’Histoire Generate et Comparees des Theobgies et Phibsophies Medievales (Paris,
21 W.R. Knorr, ‘John of Tynemouth alias John of London: Emerging Portrait of 1913), ch. 12.
24 Opus Maius, ed. Bridges, I, 116. cf. A.G. Molland, “Roger Bacon as Magician”,
a Singular Medieval Mathematician”, British Journalfor the History of Science, 23 (1990),
293-330. Traditb, 30 (1974), 445-460, at 454-5, reprinted in Molland, Mathematics and the
22 James, Ancient Libraries of Canterbury and Dover, lxxiv-lxxvii. Medieval Ancestry of Physics.
25 Easton, Roger Bacon, 88.
160 GEORGE MOLLAND ROGER BACON’S KNOWLEDGE OF MATHEMATICS 161

Campanus of Novara. It is less clear that Bacon knew Campanus per­ apparently only uses this part of Campanus’s Euclid, but one might
sonally,26 and on the whole I am inclined to think not, since he used suspect a codicological explanation.
his work without apparendy being conscious of the fact, although Bacon’s putative use of Campanus does not end with the Elements,
one then still has to ask how he formed his good opinion of him— for he also quotes verbatim from a work on ratios that is ascribed to
perhaps it could be from his work in astronomy rather than pure Campanus in some manuscripts, and also by H.L.L. Busard in his
mathematics. Bacon’s use of Campanus is a little complicated, but modem edition of the treatise.30 This work is one of several medieval
we may immediately dismiss Steele’s assumption that the influence tracts that typically included a set of 18 conclusions which follow
was the other way round, and that Campanus was drawing on the from the assertion that the ratio of A to B is composed of those of
first recension of Bacon’s Communia Mathematica. In this connection C to D and E to F. It then follows for example that A:C is com­
Steele made special note of Proposition V.8 from Campanus’s version posed of B:D and E:F, and that C:F is composed of A:B and D:E.
of Euclid’s Elements, but Bacon had shortly before been discussing Many of the treatises include arguments concerning the possible per­
how mathematics had been made unnecessarily hard to learn by the mutations of the six terms involved, and both Campanus (assuming
multiplication of useless conclusions and demonstrations,27 and his that he was indeed the author) and Bacon arrive at 360 possible
reason for including the demonstration of V.8 was as an example of modes of composition, most of which represent invalid inferences from
such otiosity. “I shall include the eighth demonstration for one of the original equality. There remain 36 valid modes, or alternatively
the ten causes given, namely that there may be seen the horrible 18 if one does not count those formed by simple inversion of the
cruelty of demonstrations that reigns in this book, so that such damn­ three ratios. Both Campanus and Bacon refer to these as useful modes
able consumption of time may be avoided.”28 Also, as I have argued (:modi utiles) as opposed to the multitude of useless (inutiles) ones. Bacon
elsewhere,29 Campanus’s V.8 can be seen as an important stage in partly quotes Campanus verbatim, and partly appears to develop a
his getting to understand how the famous Eudoxean criteria for the parallel argument on his own, though it could be that he is quoting
equality and inequality of ratios actually operated, for the relevant from another text, since (and this brings us to the next point) he says
definitions at the beginning of Book V had been badly garbled in that he has been gathering from each translation of Thabit’s book
the version that he received. There is little sign that Bacon understood (ex utraque tanslatione libri Tebit). This and other remarks reveal that
or had much patience with these criteria, and indeed, as we shall Bacon thought that he was drawing not on Campanus, but on a
see, his own approach to the comparison of ratios was antithetical to work by Thabit ibn Qurra called Liber de Kata. Thabit ibn Qurra did
Euclid’s. As noted above, Adelard II was Bacon’s customary version indeed write on the 18 modes in a work known in Latin as the De
of the Elements, and it seems to be only in the case of Book V that Jigura sectore. F.J. Carmody has identified three Latin translations of
he employed Campanus’s version, which became the standard one this, of which that by Gerard of Cremona has been edited by A.A.
for the later Middle Ages. However, he does not seem conscious that Bjombo.31 There is no reason to suppose that Bacon used any of
he is using a work of Campanus, but speaks as if he were quoting these, even though the word kata is a rendering of the Arabic word
Euclid himself, nor does he even mention that he is using a different that is translated into Latin as sector. The Campanus text is ascribed
version from usual. I do not know the reason for this, nor why he in at least one manuscript to Thabit, and in an Oxford manuscript
it is given the title Tractatus de proportione et proportionalitate de kata coniuncta
26 F.S. Benjamin & G.J. Toomer. Campanus of Novara and Medieval Planetary Theory: et disiuncta. Interestingly and perhaps significantly the manuscript is
Theorica planetarum (Madison, 1971), suggest that they may have met during a pos­
sible visit of Campanus to England in 1265-68, but quite probably Bacon was in
Paris for all this time. 30 CM, 129-140; H.L.L. Busard, “Die Traktate De proportionibus von Jordanus
27 On this point see further my “Roger Bacon’s Appropriation of Past Mathematics”. Nemorarius und Campanus”, Centaurus, 5 (1971), 193-227.
28 CM, 125; cf. 120. 31 Francis J. Carmody, The Astronomical Works of Thabit b. Qurra (Berkeley, 1960),
29 A.G. Molland, “Campanus and Eudoxus; or, Trouble with Texts and Q uan­ 150-164; Axel Bjombo, Thabits werk fiber den Transversalensatz (liber deJigura sectore), ed.
tifiers”, Physis, 25 (1983), 213-225, espec. p. 220, reprinted in Molland, Mathematics H. Burger & K. Kohl, Abhandlungen zur Geschichte der Naturwissenschaften und
and the Medieval Ancestry o f Physics. der Medizin, Heft 7 (Erlangen, 1924).
162 GEORGE MOLLAND ROGER BACON S KNOWLEDGE OF MATHEMATICS 163

one of those that was given to St Augustine’s Abbey at Canterbury own view of this was strongly influenced by practical considerations,
by the monk John of London.32 for in this field as in others Bacon always had an eye to the ends of
the sciences, and inter alia this meant that it was especially important
Master Nicholas. Bacon describes him as the teacher of Amaury de for a Christian not to waste his time on useless conclusions and
Montfort, who must be taken to be the son rather than the elder demonstrations. “Authors have published more [in mathematics] than
brother of Simon de Montfort.3334This Nicholas may be the same as in other sciences, and out of the curiosity of human singularity have
the Nicholaus Grecus, a member of the Grosseteste circle, who assisted digressed to many things that are not necessary, and especially to
Grosseteste in his translating activities, and himself translated the Christians. For nothing is necessary to a Christian other than on
pseudo-Aristotelian De mundoN In that case Bacon probably derived account of his soul’s salvation, and so fewer of the parts of philosophy
his assessment from personal acquaintance, and I know of no other are to be conceded to them than to infidel philosophers, who have
testimony to Nicholas’s mathematical abilities. often strayed from the truth.”36 In fact experience was often a better
guide to mathematical truth than formal demonstrations, and Bacon
Robert Grosseteste and Adam Marsh. Bacon asserts that both of these had held that mathematics was subject to his general rule that the empiri­
a laborious mathematical education before they could be said to cal dimension was essential to proper knowledge. “Argument does not
flourish in that field. It is no surprise that Bacon does mention them suffice but experience does, and this is evident in mathematics where
as having flourished, for they were special heroes of his, and prob­ there is the most powerful demonstration. But he who has a most
ably had a strong influence on his rather surprising decision to join powerful demonstration about the equilateral triangle without expe­
the Franciscan order, even if Bacon did not actually know Grosseteste rience will not in his soul adhere to the conclusion, nor care for it,
personally. Neither Grosseteste nor Marsh is known to have written but ignore it until a test (experientia) is given to him by the intersection
much on pure mathematics, but Grosseteste’s works in other fields of two circles, from either section of which two fines are drawn to
are infused with a particularly strong mathematical spirit, which made the extremities of a given fine: then the man receives the conclusion
the subject essential for his ideals of scientific explanation. In the with all contentment.”37 The reference is to the very first proposition
case of Adam Marsh we have virtually no extant writings, but, even of Euclid’s Elements, which was often cited in philosophical discussions.
allowing for some exaggeration, Bacon’s testimony should allow us The last quotation was from one of Bacon’s discussions of experi­
to assume that he was at least highly competent mathematically.35 mental science, which had for him a very high order of dignity, taking
its place just before moral philosophy. Mathematics by contrast was
comparatively lowly in his scheme of knowledge and order of learn­
III. Classification and Pedagogy ing. It was not quite innate, but did not require much sophisticated
preparation.
In addition to discussing their origins Bacon held that it was a func­
After the necessity of languages I posit mathematics to be in the second
tion of metaphysics to consider the ordering of the sciences. Bacon’s place necessary for knowing those things that are to be known. It is
not known to us by nature, but yet among all the sciences that we
know by discovery and teaching it is near to natural cognition, for its
32 On all this see Busard, “Die Traktate De proportionibus”, 198; James, Ancient theorising is easier than in all other sciences, since boys immediately
Libraries o f Canterbury and Dover, 226, 517; H.O. Coxe, Catalogue Codicum MSS. qui in grasp these sciences, as we see, and Aristotle says this in Ethics VII, but
Collegiis Aulisque Oxoniensibus Hodie Adsewantur (Oxford, 1852), II, 14—15. The manu­ this is not so for natural, metaphysical and other sciences. Moreover
script in question is Oxford, Corpus Christi College 41.
33 Cf. Knorr, “John of Tynemouth”, 304.
34 Cf. Ex Rerum Anglicarum Scriptoribus Saeculi X III, ed. F. Liebermann, Monumenta
Germaniae Historica, Scriptorum, XXVIII (Hannover, 1888; repr. Stuttgart & New 36 CM, XVI, 116-117. For further discussion of this theme see my “Roger Bacon’s
York, 1964), 575. Appropriation”.
35 For a somewhat different view see Easton, Roger Bacon, 208-209. 37 Opus maius, ed. Bridges, II, 168.
164 GEORGE MOLLAND ROGER BACON’S KNOWLEDGE OF MATHEMATICS 165

laymen easily know how to figure, number, sing and use musical instru­ they must be understood as speaking of the order of nature rather
ments, and how to dance and make gestures appropriate to singing than that of teaching. Moreover, a question of nobility is involved,
and the sound o f instruments. And these are all works of mathematics. for it is open to the practical astronomer to command the geometer
Therefore it must be an easy science and almost innate or near to
innate cognition. And on this account it follows that it is the first of
and arithmetician to produce tables and instruments for him, which
the sciences, without which the others cannot be known, because that only he is really competent to use.
is naturally first which is common to clerks and laymen, and which is
appropriate to the youthful state.38
IV. Consequences of Communality
Such passages provide an important reminder, that, although it was
epistemologically a vital servant to the other sciences, mathematics
It is Bacon’s separation of a realm of common mathematical that is
for Bacon was by no means their queen.
most original to his division of mathematics, and understandably this
Within the subject also Bacon had interesting classificatory views,
had consequences for his treatment of the subject. This often pro­
which were again pedagogically related. His first division of it was
vided opportunities for berating Euclid, for he had written a book
into things common to the whole of mathematics and those proper
that Bacon, following al-Farabi calls the Book of Elements and Roots,
to its more specialised areas. In this connection he was fond of citing
Aristotle to the effect that, “There is innate in us a way of knowing but because there are not contained there only those things that are
from the more common to the proper”, although this quotation in common to the special parts of mathematics, but there is descent to
fact came from a florikgium rather than from Aristotle himself.39 Bacon the special things of geometry and arithmetic, it does not deserve so
properly to be called Book of Elements as a treatise that only has roots
gives as his authority for the division the De scientiis of al-Farabi, but that are common to all parts of mathematics, and does not descend to
I have been unable to find a justification for this. Although there are the conclusions of any special part, on which account that common
hints of it in various earlier writings, including Aristotle and Gros­ part must deservedly be called Book of Roots and Elements with respect to
seteste, it is particularly reminiscent of Proclus’s commentary on the all the parts of mathematics.41
first book of Euclid’s Elements, but so far as is known this work was
Mathematics was the science dealing with quantity, but this could
not available in Latin in the Middle Ages, and I think it unlikely
not be rightly understood without the meanings of such terms as
that Bacon would have used the Greek text without vociferously telling
“together”, “contiguous”, “continuous”, “finite”, “infinite”, “position”,
the reader that he had done so.40 Although the division is fundamen­
“straight”, “curved”, “convex”, “concave”. Bacon complained that
tal to both recensions of the Communia Mathematica, it scarcely appears
these terms (most of which will be very familiar to a reader of Anstotle)
in the works for the Pope, which seems to me another reason for
had been omitted by Euclid, who perversely started with a definition
dating the first version of the Communia to after 1267.
of a point, an understanding of which was in any case (in Bacon’s
After the initial division, the proper parts of mathematics are divided
view) posterior to the description of a line.
into theoretical and practical, and then each of these subdivided into
Quantity was for Bacon, as for Aristotle, primarily that by which
the traditional parts of the continuum, geometry, arithmetic, astron­
things were said to be equal or unequal, but ever since the Pythagorean
omy and music. Bacon is insistent on this order, for, by his asser­
discovery of incommensurability there had been a rigid dichotomy
tion, the study of things musical is more difficult than that of things
between discrete quantities (such as numbers) and continuous quan­
astronomical, and geometry must precede arithmetic pedagogically.
tities (such as lines). The former were the concern of arithmetic (and
If Anstode and Boethius seem to place arithmetic as prior to geometry,
music), and the latter of geometry (and astronomy). Whereas, given
any two numbers, there was a certain quantity, even if only unity,
38 Opus tertmm, 105 in Brewer’s edition. that would fit into each an integral number of times, this did not
39 Jacqueline Hamesse, Les Auctoritates AristoteUs: Un Florilege Medievale: Etude Historique
et Edition Critique (Louvain & Paris, 1974), 140. Cf. Aristotle, Physica I. 1, 184a 16-18.
40 For further discussion of this problem see my “Roger Bacon’s Appropriation”. 41 Molland, “Bacon’s Geometria Speculation”, 268-269.
166 GEORGE MOLLAND ROGER BACON’S KNOWLEDGE OF MATHEMATICS 167

apply universally to lines, as for example the side and diagonal of a are not put forward, since the rationale of ratios is only evident in
square, something which in modem mathematical language we would these species, and because also there is not explained what is a certain
ratio in numbers and in continuous quantities, following the manner
be inclined to refer to as the irrationality of V2. Bacon of course
already given, in finding to the extent of our power an indivisible in
acknowledged this distinction, but in common with writers such as continuous quantities, just as there exists one by nature in discrete
Proclus before him, and innumerable later ones, from the Renais­ quantities.43
sance onwards, he insisted that there were many things that could
be said about quantity in general, and which accordingly belonged Such a policy might indeed make things easier for students, but it
to common mathematics. also had the effect of leaving irrational ratios in limbo, or at least
Not surprisingly the theory of proportion was a prime field for only to be treated by approximation.
common mathematics, and Bacon was in accord with a general In the next century ways were found of numerically denominating
medieval tendency towards seeing Book V of Euclid’s Elements as many irrational ratios, notably by Thomas Brawardine and Nicole
dealing with quantity in general, rather than just with continuous Oresme. These depended on a particular interpretation of the process
quantity, or magnitude (magnitudo) as it was usually called, and of compounding ratios.44 It was generally agreed that if the ratio A:B
Campanus had made a point of emphasising the variety of quanti­ was compounded with the ratio B:C (where A is greater than B, and
tative genera in which ratios could be found. But, if discrete and con­ B greater than C) the result was A:C. To us, who chacteristically
tinuous quantity were thus to be brought more closely together, there view ratios as fractions, it is natural to regard this as multiplication,
was a strong temptation to give a privileged position to the way in and this is the interpretation that Bacon, in common with the
which arithmetic treated ratios. Boethius’s account (deriving from Campanus De proportionibus discussed above, adopts. But another inter­
earlier Greek traditions) was extremely cumbersome, but at least its pretation was available, which flowed naturally from the musical
general intention was clear: it strove to give an expression of the size tradition, in which composition of ratios was regarded as addition.
of a ratio in numerical terms—its denomination (denominatio) as it was This gave a different meaning to the idea of multiplying and divid­
conventionally termed. On the other hand, because of the difficulties ing ratios by whole numbers, for whereas in the multiplicative inter­
associated with irrational ratios Euclid (probably following Eudoxus pretation half of 16:1 would be 8:1 in the additive interpetation it
of Cnidus) had laid down very sophisticated criteria for equating ratios, would be 4:1. And in the latter interpretation half of 2:1 would
whether rational or irrational, with each other. Unfortunately his correspond to our V2, and describe the ratio of the diagonal of a
account had been garbled by the time that it reached the Latin Middle square to its side. Ironically, if Bacon had read his hero Grosseteste
Ages, and although, as I have argued elsewhere, Campanus seems to rather more carefully, he might have come to a similar interpreta­
have acquired a good understanding of Euclid’s actual intent, his tion, for Grosseteste had said that this ratio was “a certain combina­
commentary on the relevant definitions is, to the say the least, obfus­ tion (collado) by comparison to denomination by number, for it is
cating.42 Unsurprisingly Bacon, who in this area at least was not in­ half of the double ratio.”45
clined to dwell on logical niceties, was unimpressed. He came down Bacon’s own thrust was more towards a direct assimilation of the
clearly against Euclid, and in favour of giving primacy to the arith­ continuous and the discrete rather than to a probing exploration of
metical, denominational criterion for the equality of ratios.
A great difficulty occurs to those learning Euclid’s Book V, because 43 CM, 80.
44 A.G. Molland, “The Geometrical Background to the ‘Merton School’: An
before the definition o f ratio the species of greater and lesser inequality Exploration into the Application of Mathematics to Natural Philosophy in the Four­
teenth Century”, British Journalfor the History of Science, 4 (1968-69), 108-125; Molland,
“Examination of Bradwardine’s Geometry”; E.D. Sylla, “Compounding Ratios:
42 Molland, “Campanus and Eudoxus”. Cf. J.E. Murdoch, “The Medieval Lan­ Bradwardine, Oresme and the First Edition of Newton’s Pnncipia", Transformation and
guage of Proportions: Elements of the Interaction with Greek Foundations and the Tradition in the Sciences, ed. E. Mendelsohn (Cambridge, 1984), 11-43.
Development of New Mathematical Techniques”, Scientific Change, ed. A.C. Crombie 45 Robert Grosseteste, Commentarius in Posteriorum Analyticorum Libros, ed. P. Rossi
(London, 1963), 237-271. (Florence, 1981), 119-120.
168 GEORGE MOLLAND ROGER BACON’S KNOWLEDGE OF MATHEMATICS 169

the former’s own proper mysteries. In this, as hinted above, he was In this passage from the beginning of the Communia Naturalia Bacon
continuing a common medieval tendency noted by J.E. Murdoch.46 speaks as if he had completed the mathematical volume, and hence
Murdoch points out how a definition of communicating numbers was treated all the special parts of mathematics. But, as is so often the
inserted into Book VII (one of the arithmetical books) in many versions case with him, this was proleptic. His agile mind darted hither and
of Euclid’s Elements. We should call such numbers those that are not thither, and probably he was almost always working on several themes
mutually prime, but what is interesting for our present purposes is at the same time. It is no surprise that he would have had little
that the adjectives communicantes and incommunicantes were also and more appetite for labouring patiently through systematic treatments of the
commonly used to denote continuous quantities that were mutually quadrivial sciences in both their theoretical and practical departments.
commensurable or mutually incommensurable. The common mean­ All that we have is a short, and rather unsystematic, (pure) geometrical
ing then for both numbers and magnitudes is that two of a kind are fragment following on the end of the first recension of the Communia.
communicating if they have a common measure, other than unity in the This is now available in print in Latin and English, and, as regards
case of numbers. Bacon adopts this approach wholeheartedly, and in a geometrical content, I shall confine myself to just two remarks. One
string of enunciations of propositions from Book VII he regularly is that, when he gets down to geometrical detail, he is quite capable
replaces the term numerus by quantitas and the phrase contra se primi of getting immersed in a logical quagmire, which, to all but the most
(mutually prime) by incommunicantes or incommensurabiles. In this way charitable of readers, must seem more obfuscating than enlightening.
he hoped to form by amalgamation basic principles for his common This, as I have discussed elsewhere,49 comes through forcefully in his
mathematics. Many in later ages would have been able to sympathise discussion of perpendicularity.
with his general aim, while still wishing to censure the cavalier, if The other remark is to note that, while all the Euclidean geometrical
not crude, way in which he dismissed the labyrinthine subtleties of postulates remain (although Bacon, in common with others, thinks that
the infinite, which have been such an important charm to so many some are capable of proof), the common notions are much reduced,
pure mathematicians. as a consequence of his preceding treatise on common mathematics.
Conceptions proper to geometry are few, because almost all are com­
mon to continuous and to discrete quantity, and so were placed ear­
V. Geometry and Conclusion lier, in the treatise on the common things of the whole of mathematics.
But two can be placed here: If one continuous quantity be superposed
Bacon’s Communia Mathematica was intended as part of Volume II of to another and applied to it, and neither exceed the other, they will be
mutually equal. This is Euclid’s, and on account of the superposition
his repeated attempt at a grand synthesis of knowledge, variously
and application of one to the other, it is evident that it belongs only
referred to as Compendium Phibsophiae, Scriptum Principale, Compendium to continua and not to discreta, because the conception of equality
Studii TTieologiae, etc.47 appropriate to discreta and continua was had earlier in the Communia,
and was the first definition assigned there. And Adelard of Bath in a
After I delivered up grammar according to different languages according
comment adds another, which is this: “As much as one quantity is to
as they are of value, indeed are necessary, to the study of the Latins, another, so much any third to be to some fourth. This is to be observed
and with these things made ready matters of logic, and in the second
in continuous quantities, whether the antecedents be greater or less,
volume treated the parts of mathematics, now in the third there come for magnitude decreases infinitely” by division, as he alleges, and by
up matters o f nature (naturalia), and in the fourth those of metaphysics
the geometer’s will it can also be imagined to increase infinitely so far
together with morals will be attached.48
as he wishes, as Aristotle teaches in Physics III.50

This remark, with which the fragment concludes, again gives evi­
46 J.E. Murdoch, “The Medieval Euclid: Salient Aspects of the Translations of
Euclid by Adelard of Bath and Campanus of Novara”, Revue de Synthese, 79 (1968), dence of Bacon’s strong strategic sense in mathematics. His separating
67-94, at 86-90.
47 Cf. Little, “Roger Bacon’s Works”, 402-407.
48 Liber Primus Communium Naturalium Fratris Rogeri, Partes Prima et Secunda, ed. Robert 49 Molland, “Roger Bacon’s Appropriation”.
Steele, OHI, II (Oxford, n.d.). 50 Molland, “Bacon’s Geometria Speculative”, 302-303.
170 GEORGE MOLLAND ROGER BACON’S KNOWLEDGE OF MATHEMATICS 171

out of a prior realm of common mathematicals was not an arid quantity feigned by the imagination, so that it be posited to exist by
technical affair, but an act of considerable boldness, especially for itself, for this would be false, because then the consideration would be
one who, in some respects more than his contemporaries, put such useless, for the science of quantity in mathematics is for the sake of
bodies with size, not for the sake of quantity existing outside bodies.53
an emphasis on ancient authority. For (unless he had access to Proclus
on Euclid) he had only ancient hints to go on, and his programme In Bacon’s time mathematics was applied above all in astronomy,
involved quite frequent sideswipes at Euclid, who emerges as a much but with the translation of Alhazen’s Optics, whose influence Bacon
less respected authority than Aristotle, Ptolemy, Avicenna or Alhazen. himself did so much to promote, it was also gaining a sophisticated
Also the passage just quoted shows Bacon’s consciousness that a sys­ hold on happenings in the sublunary world. And in a remarkable
tematic work on geometry would need casting in rather a different passage from the Geometria Speculative/, Bacon acknowledges this two­
mode from Euclid’s Elements, and it is interesting that he adds an fold role while commenting on geometry’s first postulate, “To draw
axiom asserting the existence of a fourth proportional in continuous a straight line from any point to any point, and to produce a finite
quantities, a course that was later to be taken by Christopher Clavius.51 line continuously and in a straight line so far as is wished.”
Given this and all his other achievements, it would be unfair to
On account of the irregularity or tortuosity or difformity of corporeal
carp that Bacon did not himself undertake what could often have
matter in these inferior things, the first [postulate] cannot be reduced by
been the tedious task of performing this recasting or of presenting a man to operation, or scarcely and with great difficulty. But it is possible
new version of the other seven mathematical sciences. And while for operative nature, as in the multiplication of virtue and species in the
acknowledging Bacon’s achievements within the bounds of mathe­ things of the world, as in the diffusion of light and rays, which is made
matics, it is appropriate to terminate this chapter in accord with multiplicatively by straight lines in a single body, and also the perpen­
his own spirit by looking once more at the purposes of the subject, diculars to the first bodies are made in a straight fashion. The geometer
therefore considers the possible paths of nature, because geometry was
and in particular of geometry. Its theological and physical uses are first and essentially constituted for the sake of certifying the works of
propagandised at length in the works for the Pope, but in some ways nature, and thereafter for human works. For the authors of perspective
the quieter style of the Communia Mathematica can given us greater show us that lines and figures declare to us the whole operation of
insight into how he saw mathematics applying to the physical world. nature, its principles and effects. And this is similarly evident by celes­
Unsurprisingly Bacon adopts an Aristotelian abstractionist view of tial things, which both natural philosophy and astronomy consider. The
geometer therefore does not attend to tortuous sensible matter, but
mathematical objects, but, just as Aristotle was ambivalent as regards
he understands regular nature as it is in celestials and as nature knows
the power of mathematics, so this view can either, as, in the case of how to find in its operations in these inferiors, and he imitates the
Albertus Magnus,52 allow mathematics a very limited role in physics, ways of nature. And thus it was not in the imagination of straight
or, as now with Bacon, magnify its physical relevance. lines, as Aristotle says in the Posterior Analytics, that the geometer does
not speak of the sensible line but of what is understood through it.54
The fourth abstraction is said to be made from matter and motion, so
that, even though the abstracted thing is in corporeal matter, yet it is Here there seems to be some modification, or at least change of
not considered as being in it, and thus do theoretical geometry, theo­ emphasis, from Bacon’s earlier abstractionist account, for now in the
retical arithmetic, theoretical music, and the first part that is about the sublunary world the focus is not on material bodies themselves but
common things o f mathematics. . . abstract and separate quantity from
all matter and motion, that is, they consider it not as it is in matter
on lines of physical action as exemplified in optics. And it is not just
but in itself, as it is something in the nature of things. Nor is this a question of optics, for in Bacon’s view the transmission of light was
just one manifestion of the general doctrine of multiplication of species,
whereby all kinds of action were propagated from one place to another,
51 The Thirteen Books of Euclid’s Elements, tr. T.L. Heath (2nd edn., Cambridge, 1926),
II, 170.
52 Cf. A.G. Molland, “Mathematics in the Thought of Albertus Magnus”, Albertus
Magnus and the Sciences: Commemorative Essays 1980, ed. J.A. Weisheipl (Toronto, 1980), 53 CM, 59.
463-478, reprinted in Molland, Mathematics and the Medieval Ancestry of Physics. 54 Molland, “Bacon’s Geometria Speculativa”, 298—301.
172 GEORGE MOLLAND ROGER BACON’S KNOWLEDGE OF MATHEMATICS 173

including, we may note, astrological and psychic action.55 And it was Fisher, N.W. & Sabetai Unguru. “Experimental Science and Mathematics
in this way that mathematics, although rather a lowly science in itself, in Roger Bacon’s Thought”, Traditio, 27 (1971), 353-378.
became for Bacon one of the chief servants of what, with little exag­ Grosseteste, Robert. Commentarius in Posteriorum Analyticorum libros, ed. P. Rossi
geration, may be called his physical science of sciences. (Florence, 1981).
Hamesse, Jacqueline. Les Auctoritates Aristotelis: Un Florilege Medievale: Etude
Historique et Edition Critique (Louvain: Publications Universitaires & Paris:
Bibliography Beatrice-Nauwelaerts, 1974).
James, Montague Rhodes. The Ancient Libraries of Canterbury and Dover: The
Bacon, Roger. Opera Quaedam Hactenus Inedita, Vol. I, containing I.— Opus tedium; Catalogues of the libraries of Christ Church Priory and St Augustine's Abbey at
II. Opus minus; III— Compendium phihsophiae, ed. J.S. Brewer (London, 1859; Canterbury and of St Martin's Priory at Dover (Cambridge: Cambridge Univer­
repr. Kraus, 1965). sity Press, 1903).
. The “Opus Majus” of Roger Bacon, ed. J.H. Bridges (3 vols.: I—II, Oxford, Knorr, Wilbur R. “John of Tynemouth alias John of London: Emerging
1897; III, London, 1900; repr. Frankfurt: Minerva, 1964). Portrait of a Singular Medieval Mathematician”, British Journalfor the History
------ . Opera Hactenus Inedita Rogeri Baconi, ed. R. Steele et al (16 fascicles, of Science, 23 (1990), 293-330.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1905-40).
Benjamin, Francis S. & G.J. Toomer. Campanus of Novara and Medieval Planetary Liebermann, F. (ed.). Ex Rerum Anglicarum Scriptoribus Saeculi XIII, Monu-
Theory: Theorica planetarum (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1971). menta Germaniae Historica, Scriptorum, XXVIII (Hannover, 1888; repr.
Bjombo, Axel. Thabits Werk iiber den Transversalensatz (liber de figura sectore), ed. Stuttgart & New York, 1964).
H. Burger & K. Kohl, Abhandlungen zur Geschichte der Naturwissen- Lindberg, David C. “On the Applicability of Mathematics to Nature: Roger
schaften und der Medizin, Heft 7 (Erlangen: Max Mencke, 1924). Bacon and his Predecessors”, British Journal for the History of Science, 15
Busard, H.L.L. “Die Traktate De proportionibus von Jordanus Nemorarius und (1982), 3-25.
Campanus”, Centaurus, 15 (1971), 193-227. ------ . “Science as Handmaiden: Roger Bacon and the Patristic Tradition”,
. “Ein mittelalterlicher Euklid-Kommentar, der Roger Bacon zugeschrie- Isis,' 78 (1987), 518-536.
ben werden kann”, Archives Internationales d’Histoire des Sciences, 24 (1974) Little, A.G. (ed.). Roger Bacon: Essays (Oxford, 1914).
199-218. ------ . “Roger Bacon’s Works, with References to the MSS. and Printed
& Menso Folkerts. Robert of Chester's (?) Redaction of Euclid's Elements: The Editions”, in Roger Bacon: Essays, ed. Little, 375—426.
So-Called Adelard II Version, Science Networks, Historical Studies, Vol. 8
Molland, A.G. “The Geometrical Background to the ‘Merton School’: An
(Basel: Birkhauser, 1992).
Exploration into the Application of Mathematics to Natural Philosophy
Carmody, Francis J. The Astronomical Works ofThabit b. Qurra (Berkeley: Univer­ in the Fourteenth Century”, British Journal for the History of Science, 4 (1968—
sity o f California Press, 1960). 69), 108-125.
Clagett, Marshall. “The Medieval Latin Translations from the Arabic of ------ . “Roger Bacon as Magician”, Traditio, 30 (1974), 445-460.
the Elements of Euclid, with Special Emphasis on the Versions of Adelard ------ . “An Examination of Bradwardine’s Geometry”, Archive for History of
o f Bath”, Isis, 44 (1953), 16-42. Exact Sciences, 19 (1978), 113-175.
. Archimedes in the Middle Ages (Vol. I, Madison: University of Wisconsin ------ . “Mathematics in the Thought of Albertus Magnus”, Albertus Magnus
Press, 1964; Vols. II-V, Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society, and the Sciences: Commemorative Essays 1980, ed. J.A. Weisheipl (Toronto:
1976-84). Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1980), 463-478.
------ . “Campanus and Eudoxus; or, Trouble with Texts and Quantifiers”,
Easton, S.C. Roger Bacon and his Search for a Universal Science: A Reconsideration
of the life and Work of Roger Bacon in the light of his own Stated Purposes Physis, 25 (1983), 213-225.
(Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1952). ------ . “Roger Bacon and the Hermetic Tradition in Medieval Science”,
Euclid. The Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements, tr. T.L. Heath (2nd edn., Cam­ Vivarium, 31 (1993), 140-160.
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1926). ------ . “Roger Bacon’s Geometria Speculative", Vestigia Mathematica: Studies in Medi­
eval and Early Modem Mathematics in Honour of H.L.L. Busard, ed. M. Folkerts
and J.P. Hogendijk (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1993), 265-303.
------ . Mathematics and the Medieval Ancestry of Physics (Aldershot: Variorum, 1995).
------ . “Roger Bacon’s Appropriation of Past Mathematics”, Tradition, Transmis­
55 On this extended role for multiplication of species see, for instance, my “Roger sion, Transformation: Cultural Exchange in the Premodem World, ed. S.J. Livesey &
Bacon and the Hermetic Tradition”. FJ. Ragep (Leiden: Brill, 1996), 347-365.
174 GEORGE MOLLAND

Murdoch, J.E. “The Medieval Language of Proportions: Elements of the


Interaction with Greek Foundations and the Development of New Mathe­
matical Techniques”, Scientific Change, ed. A.C. Crombie (London: Heine- 8. ROGER BACON ON ASTRONOMY-ASTROLOGY:
mann, 1963), 237-271.
TH E SOURCES OF TH E SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTALIS
. “The Medieval Euclid: Salient Aspects of the Translations of Euclid
by Adelard of Bath and Campanus o f Novara”. Revue de Synthase, 79 (1968),
67-94. v ' Jeremiah Hackett
Picavet, F. Essais sur I’Histoire Generate et Comparees des Theologies et Philosophies
Medievales (Paris: Felix Alcan, 1913).
Smith, D.E. “The Place of Roger Bacon in the History of Mathematics”, in
Roger Bacon wrote at length on astronomy-astrology in three works:
Roger Bacon: Essays, ed. Little, 153-183. the Opus maius, the Communia mathematka, and the Communia naturalium}
Steele, Robert. “Roger Bacon as Professor: A Student’s Notes”, Isis, 20 (1933) However, he did not set out to write a Treatise on astronomy after
53-71. '
the manner of his Perspectwa, and he should not be judged negatively
Sylla, E.D. “Compounding Ratios: Bradwardine, Oresme and the First Edi­
for not doing so.12 As can be seen from the chapter on Mathematics
tion o f Newton’s Pnncipia”, in Transformation and Tradition in the Sciences, ed.
E. Mendelsohn (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 11-43. above, Bacon was well aware of contemporary “experts” in this field,
Thijssen, J.M.M.H. “Roger Bacon (1214-1292/1297): A Neglected Source
and he drew on their work.34*This paper, primarily concerned with
in the Medieval Continuum Debate”, Archives Internationales d’Histoire des Bacon’s polemic in Opus maius, part four, on the applications of mathe­
Sciences, 34 (1984), 25-34. matics (astronomy), will be dealing with the manner in which Bacon
adapts traditional sources in astronomy-astrology to the needs of his
new scientia experimental.
Thjs paper is strictly limited to this one topic in these writings.
Thus, it will be limited to providing an account of the polemic in
the Opus maius* and related work in their actual historical context

1 Opus maius, part four, ed. Bridges, 159—269, 376—404; Communia naturalium, Liber
Secundus: De coelestibus, ed. Steele, Fasc. IV, Opera) Communia mathematica, ed. Steele,
Fasc. XVI.
2 John North, Astronomy and Cosmology, (New York & London: W.W. Northon &
Co., 1995 [The Norton History of Science]), 237: There was no one moment of
enlightenment. Roger Bacon (ca. 1219—ca. 1292) introduces a mildly empirical note
into his writings, but he was no astronomer. [While this statement is true in the
sense that Bacon does not rank with Campanus of Novara and others, we should
bear in mind that we have no information about Bacon’s years as the expert on the
Quadrivium at the University of Paris. And as we shall see below, his later years,
especially the 1260’s show us an emeritus Professor located in a difficult battle in a
theological context].
3 See De coelestibus, 395, 423, 446 for his references to older authorities: Ptolemy,
Al-Fraganus, Abu Ma'shar, al-Bategni, Thebit, Arzachel. See also the list in Opus
maius, part four, ed. cit., 235 for some of the same names but especially 242 where
he claims that the vulgus philosophantium attack them: Aristotle, Avicenna, Ptolemy,
Hali the commentator on Ptolemy (= Ahmed ibn Yusuf), Masahalla, Abu Ma'shar
and later (248) the author of the De dispositione spherae [— Geminus]. In a further
study, I will present an account of Bacon’s understanding of his first part of Astron­
omy: speculative Astronomy as found in the De coelestibus.
4 A further paper which will be a study of Bacon’s views on physical astronomy
with a critical comparison of that theory with the views of Albertus Magnus is being
176 JEREMIAH HAGKETT ROGER BACON ON ASTRONOMY-ASTROLOGY 177

and in relation to other thinkers such as Albertus Magnus, Thomas fruit of faith.”7 Because of this, Christianity rejected the sciences and
Aquinas and Bonaventure. In this way, I hope to clear the air of a philosophy due to the abusers of those subjects, and thus, it did not
number of false accusations made by some scholars against the Doctor receive a full complement of the works of science and philosophy
mirabilis. until quite recently in Bacon’s times. Bacon therefore sets out to prove
that “the holy patriarchs and prophets at the beginning of the world
received all the sciences from God . . . to the end that, when the
1. Opus maius, Part One: The Polemic faith of Christ was introduced and the fraudulence of the art of Magic
was purged away, the power of philosophy might be advantageously
Roger Bacon did not just replace Plato as the authority in Philoso­ applied to divine things.”8 And he adds: “Neither the sacred doctors
phy by installing Aristotle in that position, he also addressed the issue made use of the splendid sciences of philosophy, nor did their succes­
of the uses of the sciences in the context of the theology of the Latins.5 sors, Gratian, the Master of the Sentences (Peter Lombard), the Master
If we bear this in mind, we can see that he is no pure Astronomer of the Histories (Peter Comestor), Hugh of St Victor and Richard of
but rather a propagandist for the advancement of astronomy-astrology St Victor. For they had not been translated in their times, nor were
towards its uses in a definite Rhetorical persuasion in Moral philoso­ they in use among the Latins, and therefore these men neglected
phy and in religion. them, and did not know how to judge their dignity in regard to
Bacon had a very good historical sense of things. He knew that sacred mysteries. Rather, due to prejudice, they rejected that of which
in the Ancient world, the intellectual elite had used the combined they had no experience, and in many places speak against these
resources of astrologia and magic in the affairs of state. He would sciences, taking occasion to so all the more due to the fact that sacred
have known this from Augustine, De cwitate dei and other works.6 He doctors neglected the same sciences, doubtless because these works
acknowledges that “The art of Magic besides was increasing in strength had not been translated in their time, and because the church neglected
throughout the whole world, and seizing on people under every form to order them to be translated for the five reasons mentioned previ­
of superstition and religious fraud; and although it was hated by phi­ ously.”9 However, the “Modernes vero doctores vulgi” also neglect
losophers and fought by them all, yet the early sacred writers finding these sciences even though they have already been translated. They
the world occupied with it as well as with philosophy, reckoned delight in the works of the trivium and ignore the Rhetoric and Poetics.
both as the same art, since both in many ways were hindering the Further, they utterly neglect “the nine sciences of Mathematics and
the six great Natural Sciences . . . and the four very excellent divi­
sions of morals.” Thus, they solve their problems by mere appeals to
prepared. Thus, the present paper is going to deal strictly with the impact of Astrologia authority. In this Bacon, reflects clearly the “new” attitude to truth
on Bacon’s notion of an experimental science.
5 This theme and its justification in the 13th century theological context is the proposed by Adelard of Bath.10*Experience and reason and proper
subject-matter of part one of the Opus maius. scientific authority is the only route to knowledge in the sciences.
6 For this theme in the Ancient Classical world, see G.E.R. Lloyd, Magic, Reason
Bacon appeals to Pope Clement IV to use his power to change the
and Experience: Studies in the Origin and Development of Greek Science, (Cambridge: Cam­
bridge University Press, 1979. Until recently, studies on the issue of astrology in situation in the Universities so that sciences of experiences, based on
Augustine were incomplete. This has been rectified in some recent studies: see Bernard the latest translations, should be carefully studied.
Bruning OSA, “De L’Astrologie a la Grace,” in Collectanea augustiniana-Melanges T.J.
Van Bavel, eds. B. Bruning, M. Lamberigts, J. Van Houten, (Louvain: Institut
Historique Augustinjen), 574—643. This study will rank as one of the most clear­ 7 Opus maius, part one, ed. Bridges, Vol. Ill, 31-2: Insuper ars magica per totum
headed and useful on the topic of Augustine and Astrology; Thomas O ’Loughlin, orbem invalescens, occupans homines in omni superstitione et fraude religionis. . . .
“The libri Philosophorum and Augustine’s Conversions,” in Thomas Finan & Vincent 8 Ibid., eh. xiv, 32.
Twomey, The Relationship Between Neoplatonism and Christianity, (Dublin: Four Courts 9 Ibid., ch. xv, 33.
Press, 1992), 101-125 for the central role astrology had in the early Augustine; Ibid., 10 Ed. cit., ch. ii, 5: Nam in libro Quaestionum naturalium Adalardi quaeritur de
“Astrology and Thirteenth Century Philosophy: A New Angle on an Old Problem,” auctoritate fragili, “Quid est aliud auctoritas hujusmodi quam capistrum? See recent
in Milltown Studies (Dublin), 33 (Spring, 1994), 89-110. This work will be referenced works by Charles Burnett on Adelard of Bath: these have set out the basis for a
below as O ’Loughlin, “Astrology. . . .” scientific account of 12th century English scientists.
178 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON ASTRONOMY-ASTROLOGY 179

This opening polemic in Opus maius sets the scene for the discus­ 2. Bacon’s Definition of Astronomia-Astrologia
sion of astronomy/Astrology in Opus maius, part four. In Bacon’s view,
Aristode has replaced Plato as the auctor in philosophy and the newly We have seen above in the chapter on the classification of the sciences
translated Sciences from Greek and Arabic have replaced the weak that Bacon divides Astronomy into three parts. Parts one and two
Latin learning in these matters. But the Vulgus philosophantium et are concerned with the quantity of the heavenly bodies. Part three is
theologorum at Paris still in 1266 neglect both Aristode and these new concerned with the effects of the heavenly bodies on terrestrial events,
sciences. Here, it is important to indicate that while they did study and can be called judicial astronomy or astrology. The first part,
parts of Aristode, the history of the condemnation of the new sciences therefore, deals with the mathematical principles used in presenting
and occult sciences did continue up to 1277, where this issue plays a theory of the celestial motions such as Ptolemy gives in the Almagest.
a much greater role than the literature on this topic has admitted. This can be called “speculative astronomy.” The second part of theo­
Thus, despite the fact that the Statutes of the English Nation man­ retical Astronomy is called “practical astronomy,” and it has to do
dated the study of the works of Aristode at Paris by 1255, other with the uses of canons, astronomical tables and instruments. The
works, particularly in the sciences were not accepted by what Bacon third part of astronomy is concerned with the natural powers of the
called the vulgus philosophantium. heavenly bodies and with their influence on the earth.12 This latter
Still, a very interesting item is present here. Bacon knew quite concerned is addressed explicitly in Opus maius, part four, and in Opus
well from the De civitate dei and elsewhere that Augustine had made tertium, and related sections in Opus maius, part six, and in the intro­
a strong and spirited criticism of Astrologia and its uses in human and duction to the Secretum secretorum.13
ecclesiastical matters. He would have known that Grosseteste in his
important Hexaemeron had condemned the applications of judicial
astronomy (astrology) to human affairs.11123 Hence, his polemic and 3. Bacon’s Defence of Judicial Astronomy (Astrologia):
his attempt to get around early Christian criticism of these matters, Opus maius, Part Four
in order to broaden the scope of a science of experience, a scientia
experimentalis. Bacon’s defence of Astrologia is just one item in a complex defence of
the uses of Mathematics in religion (in divinis). He begins his defence
by providing a review of Patristic and early Medieval teaching on the
general application of mathematical knowledge in religious matters.
In this, Bacon, having listed Cassiodorus, Bede, and Isidore of Seville
11 Robert Grosseteste, Hexaemeron, ed. Richard C. Dales & Servus Gieben O.F.M.
Cap., (London: The British Academy: Oxford University Press, 1982) [Auctores as support, turns to the De doctrina Christiana of Augustine to argue
Britannici Medii Aevi, VI], V, ix, 1-2, 165-6. This passage is very important. Like that unless the literal sense of things is understood, the moral and mystical
Augustine, Grosseteste objects to mathematical prediction of personality based on
sense, as used in theology, will be mistaken. Citing Augustine in De
the moment of birth (11. 17—23); V, x, 8: Ad hoc, si stelle vel natura vel voluntate
ad malum cogunt, vel malum persuadeant, male sunt. Et si natura male sunt, conditor doctrina Christiana, book two, he argues that “We should not aspire to
eorum Deus maius esse convincitur, quod blasfemum est dicere. Si vero voluntate any of the sacred writings without a knowledge of numbers,” and
male sunt, est in celestibus peccatum et error. Item si valeret constellacio, sicut
fingunt astronomi, periret, ut supra dictum est, libertas arbitrii; similiter cassa esset
providencia et negociatio, et infructuosa pietas et religio Christiana, et ad Deum
facta omnino. 12 Communia naturalium, I, ed. Steele, 6; Thomas O ’Loughlin, “Astrology. ..,” argues
In Opus maius, part four, Bacon would seem to have V, ix, 2 in mind when he that Bacon coalesces Isidore’s division of the two parts of astronomia. He correctly
repeats that it is not possible for the astronomer to judge and make statements notes that for Albertus and Bacon “the distinction between natural and judicial
about singular fortuitous events. It should be noticed that although Grosseteste firmly Astronomy is not important in practice.” And he contrasts this position with that
follows Augustine “Contra huiusmodi inanem iudicum . . .,” he does allow for “a of Aquinas. See more on this below. Yet, as we saw above, Bacon’s division of
true kind of Astrology,” one in which one studies the effects of the heavens on Astronomy-astrology is more complex than that of Isidore.
natural events and on bodily dispositions, as for example in medicine. See Richard 13 Opus maius, part four; Opus tertium, ed. Bridges, 27ff.; Opus maius, part six, 166—
C. Dales, “Grosseteste’s Views on Astrology,” Mediaeval Studies, 29 (1967), 357-363. 222; Secretum secretorum, ed. Steele, 1-27.
180 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON ASTRONOMY-ASTROLOGY 181

“Ignorance of numbers causes many things placed in the Scriptures the former. Direct rays can compare to the action of grace on the
with a transferred and mystical meaning not to be understood.”14 just. Light is reflected away in the case of the unjust, and it is bent
Again, he appeals to Cassiodorus and Augustine on the importance or refracted in the case of the imperfect human being.16 (vi) Num­
of both music and astronomy. He turns to the latter work where bers: there is much reference to number in Scripture. Knowledge of
Augustine states that this science, astronomy, is useful in a threefold the Jewish law requires that one understand numbers. Only a math­
manner, that is, as “a demonstration of the present, a knowledge of ematician can solve textual problems. Further, calculations are re­
the past, and a reasonable conjecture of the future. The demonstra­ quired for Astronomy concerning the position of the earth and the
tion of the present consists in the assignment of the properties of heavenly bodies, (vii) Music: this covers both vocal and instrumental
celestial things. Besides a demonstration of the present, it possesses music, including recitation, pronunciation, accent, prose and poetry.
something like a Narrative of the past, because from the present knowl­ Instruments are important and have a literal and spiritual meaning.
edge and motion of the Stars we can revert regularly to their tracks Dancing can be called visible music; it too is important in religion.
in the past. It possesses also conjectures according to the rule of the Bacon then picks three areas of study to illustrate the applications
future, not full of mistrust and ominous, but definite and certain.”15 of Mathematics, in particular Astronomy/Astrology. They are: I. The
Bacon then outlines seven areas in which Mathematics can be Correction of the Calendar,17 II. Knowledge of Geography,18 III.
usefully applied in the study of religion, (i) Astronomy provides a Astrology.19
knowledge of the nature of the heavens themselves, the place of Naturally, it is the third item which was destined to raise serious
paradise and hell and the influence of the heavens on the earth, (ii) questions. Yet, before presenting a resume of a treatise on Astrology
By means of Geography, which is subalternated to Astronomy, one at the end of part four,20 Bacon launches into an apologia for judicial
can know the places found in the Scriptures. These places have both Astronomy/astrology. It is in the context of this polemic that Bacon
a spiritual and literal sense. But we need to know the latter precisely first introduces his notion of a Scientia experimentalis. O ur task now is
in order to know the former. Hence, astronomy is a key to Scriptural to outline the dimensions of this polemic.
meaning, (iii) Religion has need of a knowledge of sacred times, con­
cerning the Creation and the calculation of time, (iv) Chronology:
Jews and Christians uses different ways of reckoning time periods. 4. Roger Bacon’s Apologia for Judicial Astronomy/Astrology
Yet, there is a real need to calculate the birth of Christ, (v) Geometrical
forms: Scripture is filled with references to sacred objects: the Ark, He begins as he did in part one, with an historical review of early
the Tabernacle, the Temple. One needs to know their precise geomet­ Christian history. He notes that in later times, certain theologians,
rical form in order to know the spiritual meaning. A great example
of this is the Rainbow. It is given as a sign of the Deluge in the Book
16 Ibid., 212-217: Nam Aristoteles magis omnibus philosophantibus nos involvit
of Genesis. But we misunderstand its meaning because we do not suis obscuritatibus in tractando de iride, ut nihil per eum quod dignum sit intelligamus,
yet know the complete Geometry of the rainbow, which is produced immo multa falsa in translatione Latinorum continentur. .. . Et Avicenna dux ac
by solar rays reflected or refracted from raindrops. Direct (incident), Princeps philosphiae post Aristotelem, ut clamant omnes, seipsum ignorasse iridis
naturam humiliter confessus est. Et sic de omnibus philosophis certum est, quod
refracted and reflected rays have both literal and spiritual meaning, nullus potuit scientiam iridis obtinere. . . . Nam in bonis perfectis infusio gratiae
and a true knowledge of the latter depends on a good knowledge of comparatur luci directe incidenti. .. .
17 See Jennifer Moreton, “Robert Grosseteste and the Calendar,” in James McEvoy,
ed., Robert Grosseteste: New Perspectives on His Thought and Scholarship, ed. cit., 77-88.
14 Opus mains, part four, ed. Bridges, Vol. I, 178; See Richard Newhauser, “Der 18 See below, David Woodward and Herbert W. Howe: Roger Bacon on Geog­
Tractatus de oculo des Petrus von Limoges und seine exempla,” in Walter Haug & raphy and Cartography.
Burghart Wachinger, Exempel und Exempel-Sammlungen, (Tubingen: Max Niemeyer, 1991), 19 See Thomas O ’Loughlin, “Astrology.. .,” 94-7 on Roger Bacon.
95-136 for the importance of the literal sense and the transfer of this literal sense 20 Opus mains, part four, ed. cit., 376-403; see Thomas O ’Loughlin, art. cit., 97:
to moral and religious meaning. The Tract on Astrology in the Opus maius is so detailed that from it alone most of
15 Ibid., 180. the Astrological teachings of the period could be recovered.
182 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON ASTRONOMY-ASTROLOGY 183

“who were ignorant of the power of philosophy and the fallacies of on the earth, it does not presume to judge infallibly about all things,
Magic,” condemned astrology (judicial astronomy) in their “lectures, and especially about human destiny. Bacon’s goal then is to defend
preaching and collations, both private and public.21 This, he believed, a true mathematics, including a true Astronomy/Astrology. But here,
led to the ruin of philosophy, the failure of the Church and Common­ Bacon does face a problem. He is committed to a theoretical quanti­
wealth and the inability to convert the unbelievers. Further, in the tative astronomy, with its practical counterpart, the uses of instru­
eyes of the canon lawyers and theologians, those who practiced Astron­ ments, canons and tables and to a general, although not particular,
omy were labeled Magicians. The theologians had “no leisure for astrologia. That is, he believes that from the actions of the heavens on
the works of astronomy.” the human disposition, one can make “general” or “universal” pre­
In other texts, he returned to this theme, and argued that certain dictions about human customs such as kinds of behavior produced
theologians confused true Science and the practice of Magic. For by climatic conditions. But he eschews any prediction of singular
Bacon, “there was no falsehood in the judgments of Astrology.”22 events, certudinaliterP
The names of his contemporary experts in astrology cannot be men­ However, the distinction between (a) a quantitative astronomia/
tioned in public “because of the violence of the mob.”23 And in the astrologia and (b) a spurious superstitious astrologia is not original with
Opus tertium, he tells us that much that he wrote on these matters Bacon. Therefore, Bacon is not introducing it simply to get around
were secret and that he dissimulated in regard to astrology and al­ Augustine’s strictures against astrology. One sees it in Robert Kil-
chemy lest his work should fall into the wrong hands. wardby’s De ortu scientiarum.26 He calls this part the “teachings of the
Above all, these theologians, in Bacon’s view, confused the etymol­ professors of superstitious astrology.” For Kilwardby as for Bacon,
ogy of the word Mathematics (Mathesis). In some works, he noted there is a true astronomia/astrologia. This studies both the quantity of
that Mathematica was derived from the word Mathesis, written with the heavenly bodies and the natural effects of those bodies on bodily
the letter t aspirated with a short middle syllable. This was a true disposition (complexio), health, weather, and their in-direct affect on
scientific discipline. The word Matesis with a long middle syllable and the human mind. The false and superstitious kind of astrologia claims
written without an aspirate t, according to Bacon, derived from Mantos on the basis of the stars to be able to predict a definite and specific
or Mantia which are the same as dwinatio. Thus, for him, false mathe­ knowledge of singular events in the future, the hidden present and
matics is the second part of Magic.24* This latter is simply pure, the distant past, and also concerning affairs which depended on human
hard determinism at its worst. It holds that the stars control the free will.
human will by utter necessity, the location of one’s birth determines The crucial question, then, concerning Bacon is: Does he go beyond
everything, and that one can predict singular future events with abso­ these limits set by Robert Kilwardby? Does he accept a kind of deter­
lute infallibility. This is magical divination. True Mathematics, on ministic, all-encompassing predictive astrologia wherein, not merely
the other hand, (and here he is following Augustine and Robert “general patterns” of disposition, health and weather can be generally
Grosseteste), talks about quantity and explains the motions of the
heavens. But while it will speak about the influence of the heavens
25 See Grosseteste, Hexaemeron, ed. cit., V, x, 2: . .. manifestum est quod non est
astronomo possibile iudicare et pronunciare per constellationes de singulisfortuitis eventus,
aut nati moribus aut eciam naturalibus complexionibus. Bacon agrees in regard to singular
21 Ibid., 248: . . et ob hoc earn in lectionibus, praedicationibus et collationibus fortuituous events and predictions based on birth, but he still does wish to defend
publicis et privatis damnantes . . See Theodore Crowley, Roger Bacon. . ., 50fF. an account of charater of peoples based on natural disposition. But so too does
22 Opus minus, ed., Brewer, 320. Albertus and to some extent also Aquinas. See below.
23 Ibid., 320. 26 Robert Kilwardby, De ortu scientiarum, ed. Albert G. Judy, O.P., (London-Toronto:
24 See Opus maius, part four, ed. cit., 239; Opus tertium, ed. Brewer, 27; Secretum The British Academy & The Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1976), 41-48:
secretorum, ed. Steele, 3. But see E. Nolan & S.A. Hirsch, eds. The Greek Grammar of See p. 43 on astrologia. Even on the issue of natural astrology joined to quantative
Roger Bacon and a Fragment of His Hebrew Grammar, (Cambridge: Cambridge University astronomy, Kilwardby is negative, stating: Certe nemo circa huiusmodi novit aliquid
Press, 1902), 117-18 for his change of mind on this etymology; see also Communia dicere probando, sed coniecturas fallacs asserunt ex his quae contigerunt aliquando,
mathematica, ed. Steele, 3. Opus maius, ed. cit., 240: Nam numerantur quinque species et non accidit regulariter sicut dicunt, et ideo astrologia iudicaria fatua est et infatualwa
arris magicae, scilicet, mantice, mathematica, malelficium, praestigium, sortilegium. eorum qui sibi vacant.
184 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON ASTRONOMY-ASTROLOGY 185

predicted on the basis of good mathematics in astronomy or is he Opus maius, Secretum secretorum, Communia mathematica, Communia naturalium
committed to a kind of deterministic predictive capacity wherein “sin­ and occasional references to the topic in Opus minus and Opus tertium.
gular events” in the future, hidden human motivation and actual free Bacon admits that the criticism of Astrologia by the theologians
human action can be specifically predicted? This is a difficult ques­ involves more than just the censure about characters, sacrifices and in­
tion to answer especially given the polemical nature of Bacon’s remarks cantations. The really important point is the accusation that Astronomia-
and also his acknowledgment that he has to cloak his real intentions. Astrologia involves “infallible" claims about singular future events and
One thing is clear. Bacon, like Albertus Magnus, was engaged in the prediction with necessity of the future.
an effort to separate a true Science and Art of Nature from the In Opus maius, part four, he cites the authoritative statements from
trickery of Magicians. And this meant deciding which books were those “true” Mathematicians, namely, Aristotle, Avicenna, Ptolemy,
authentic books of science, and which were fraudulent works of magi­ Haly (Pseudo-Hali), and Abu M acshar concerning the kinds of judg­
cians.27 Since this is the case, one has to follow Bacon’s explicit inten­ ment one can make about the future and about human free will. He
tions as far as possible and attempt to understand his situation. opens with a remark ostensibly from Ptolemy to the effect that the
In a number of works, Bacon states his belief that magicians or astrological judgments are not infallible but are “between the neces­
“false mathematicians” have abused the language of the astronomers, sary and the impossible,”29* that is, they are judgments concerning
meaning by this that they used charms, terminology, titles and claims events which are midway between absolutely necessary events and
that gave the impression of legitimacy. Further, he charged that “those absolutely impossible ones, in other words, contingent possible events.
terrible Magicians (Mathematici) put laudable titles to their works such The burden of his remarks from these authoritative Astronomi is to
as Liber Ade, Liber Moysi, Liber Salomonis, and Libri Aristotelis et Hermetis. show that Astrologi do not make infallible judgments about particular
In the Opus tertium, Bacon presents another list of these magical books, future events. In Bacon’s view, the astrologer can make a general
which he states are fraudulent and are not true art or part of the judgment about individual things about to take place, but not a spe­
study of nature.28 cific one. And in most cases, he cannot give a definite judgment but
In his defence of the works of true Astrologi, Bacon set out to prove must often rely on conjecture. Thus, it does not reach the epistemo­
from the statements of the saints and the true astronomers that there logical level of a science. Now, we must notice that Bacon is arguing
is no truth in these above-mentioned magical books. Further, he states from Authority, that is, the authority of those teachers on the Heavens
that if certain theologians and canon lawyers “who are ignorant of who had been accepted by English natural philosophers for about
both the power of philosophy and of the fallacies of magic,” would one hundred years. Evidently, we have here a conflict of two authority-
read the statements of true astrologers and the books by the magi­ sources, scientific and religious. Bacon in both the Opus maius and
cians, they would easily see that Astronomia-Astrologia is no magic, but the Communia mathematica believes that the astronomers-astrologers are not
is a true Science and Art of Mature. Thus, to understand the full impact guilty as charged. Yet, Bacon does hold that the astrologer can say
of Bacon’s polemic, the following works need to be read together: something veraciter et laudabiliter about the influence of the heavenly
bodies on natural events and on human characteristics. He simply

27 See Paola Zambelli, The Speculum astronomiae and its Enigma, (Dordrecht/Boston/
London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1992) [Boston Studies in the Philosophy of 29 Pseudo-Ptolemy, Centibquium and Commentary by (Pseudo Hali = Abu J a cfar
Science, Vol. 135]; See also David Pingree, “The Diffusion of Arabic Magical Texts Ahmad ibn Yusuf ibn Ibrahim). O n this work and its commentator, see Richard
in Western Europe,” in La difjuswne delle scienza islamiche nel medio evo europeo, (Roma: Lemay, “Origin and Success of the Kitab Tham ara of Abu Ja'far Ahmad ibn Yusuf
Accademia Nazionale di Lincei, 1987), 57-102. The latter is the most careful study ibn Ibrahim from the tenth to the seventeenth century in the world of Islam and
on this topic to-date. the Latin West,” in Proceedings of The First International Symposium For The History O f
28 Opus tertium, ed. Litde, 48: Et hie omnes libri magici debent considerari et Arabic Science, April 5—12, 1976, Vol. II, ed. Ahmad Y. Al-Hassan, Ghada K am i,
diffamari; ut Liber de morete animae, et liber Fantasmatum, et liber De officiis et potestatibus Nizar Namnum, (Aleppo: University of Aleppo, Institute for the History of Arabic
spiritum et Libri sigillis salamonis, et libri De arte notoria, et omnes hujusmodi quo demones Science), 29-45. This work has not yet been critically edited. Professor Lemay informs
invocant, vel per fraudes et vanitates procedunt, non per vias Mature et Artis. See David me that his edition is proceeding. For the Latin text of the lam Scripsi version, see
Pingree, art. cit. Cambridge, MS Ii, III. 3., Verbum primum.
186 JEREMIAH HAGKETT ROGER BACON ON ASTRONOMY-ASTROLOGY 187

denies that knowledge of this influence can be infallible or that the ity of an experimental science but he also condemns geomancy,
heavens impose an absolute necessity on human free will. aeromancy, hydromancy and pyromancy as forms of that kind of
What Bacon seems to have in mind is seen from his explanation magic found in books. But in his view, other studies, using the same
of this matter in the introduction to the Secretum secretorum, where he names but not having the same intention or meaning, are parts of
sets out his distinction between a false and a true mathematics in the philosophy and experimental science. Here, indeed, one can see why
following manner: some theologians for good reasons might have objections. They could
Those mathematicians who are false state that all things happen by accuse him of bringing in the practice of geomancy, aeromancy,
necessity and through Fate, and not only in natural things but in volun­ hydromancy and pyromancy by the back door. It is one thing to
tary matters. Whence they argue that an infant bom in one constella­ claim that the heavens indirectly affect the will and the mind, and
tion or another will of necessity be of such or such a kind and through on this even Albertus Magnus and Thomas Aquinas would be in
this they presume to judge concerning all things, future, present, and agreement.32 But it is another matter to retain the above subjects
past, certitudinaliter. . . .
and claim that astrology and its applications here are legitimate. But,
But true mathematicians do not presume these three positions, because
they do not judge that anything that was, is or will be, happens by in the end, this is not the real issue. The critical issue is the one of
necessity in these contingent and voluntary matters on earth; nor do who sets the limits of what is legitimate: the theologians and the
they pass their judgments about all things, but only about some things. canon lawyers who know neither philosophy in its scientific aspects
Nor do they teach with absolute certainty one part of a contradiction, and the books on magic, or one qualified in philosophy, science and
such that this infant will be good or bad, but that this infant will be the books of magic. That is, the Experimentator. Scientia experimentalis,
good or a bishop, if God wills it. For always in their judgments, they
add: “If God wills it [Si Deus voluerit]”. Whence, when they foresee then, for Bacon is a kind of practical wisdom which scientific schol­
the possibility of anything contingent about to happen in natural or ars should use to separate a true science and art of nature from the
voluntary events, they do not say that it will happen by necessity, but fallacies of magicians. This is a work, he thinks, for the Astrologi them­
that it may happen, and that it will happen in so far as it is according selves. And here, one can see why certain theologians would not agree
to the power of its causes, and that it will happen in virtue of these with him, since they would claim that theology has the task of ulti­
causes unless God changes the Ordained Law of Nature and of the WillN
mately deciding what is true and false in knowledge. Theodore
The kinds of astrological judgment that Bacon has in mind as valid Crowley was correct in pointing to this “border-dispute” as the one
and laudable would seem to be the following: the recognition that which led to some friction between Bacon and Bonaventure.33*
people are affected by their temperaments, and that character is
affected by climate. He does, however, go one step further, and argues
that an astrologer can make “general judgments” about whole com­
munities on the basis of “manners and customs,” which are affected
by temperament and climate. But here, one only has conjecture and
not the infallible necessity of science. This positive approbation of a
kind of astrology in Bacon has important consequences for his under­
standing of a scientia experimentalis. He makes the third prerogative of
his scientia experimentalis the way to a special knowledge of the past, sexta; sed ubique relucet eius potestas et in astronomia et in omnibus. See esp.,
present and future “in a more certain manner than the ordinary Opus maius, part six, ed. Bridges, II, 213-4; Tractatus de experientia in communi, ed.
Hackett, 338.
astronomy (astrology).”31 32 Albertus Magnus, De fato; Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, see comments
In the introduction to the Secretum secretorum, he defends the valid- below.
33 Theodore Crowley, Roger Bacon, 50—64; See Jeremiah Hackett, “Anstotle, Astrologia
and Controversy at the University of Paris, 1266-74,” in Jo h n Van Engen &
30 Secretum secretorum, ed. Steele, 3-4: Mathematici igitur qui sunt falsi___ Edward D. English, eds. Learning Institutionalized: Teaching in the Medieval University,
31 Opus tertium, ed. Brewer, 45: De ista scientia (sc. exp.), multa tango in parte (forthcoming) for a critical study of Bacon and Bonaventure on this topic.
188 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON ASTRONOMY-ASTROLOGY 189

5. Bacon’s Sources for a Scientia experimentalis in Opus maius not books of Magic in the sense signalled by the important Medieval
Part Four and Related Texts: Fraudulent Astrology or a Speculum astronomiae.38 My task now is to review the arguments which
Way to a “New” Experimental Science? Bacon makes on the basis of these works.
The first reference is to the Centiloquium.39 Bacon’s text reads:
I should begin here by stating that Bacon has been accused, even “In general, therefore, in considering what is to be held by the phi­
recently, of teaching “certain suspected novelties.”34 Thus, it becomes losophers on this matter, [we should note that] Ptolemy (= Pseudo-
fundamental to identify Bacon’s actual sources for the scientia experi­ Ptolemy) makes the following statement at the beginning of the
mentalis, and then to determine whether or not he makes adjustments Centiloquium: ‘The astronomer ought not speak about things specifi­
of a kind which could “save the appearances” in regard to scientific cally but in general as one who views things from a distance,’ and
prediction, forecasting of human mores, and determination of human he adds ‘the judgments that I give you are between the necessary
behavior.
and the impossible.’”40 Bacon follows on this with material from the
The important authorities cited by Bacon are: Aristotle, Avicenna, commentary by Hali (= Ahmed ibn Yusuf) and more material from
Ptolemy (= Pseudo-Ptolemy), Hali his commentator (= Abu J a cfar the Centiloquium. The commentator states that “He made this state­
Ahmad ibn Yusuf), Ptolemy, Massahalla, Abu Ma'shar.35 The first ment, because this science does not exist except by means of proof or
thing that needs to be said is that with the exception of Abu Macshar, opinion since the subject to which the whole work of the stars per­
all the others are used with qualification by Thomas Aquinas. And tains is convertible to one and to the other.”41
all of them are used with approbation by both Albertus Magnus and Bacon follows with comment from Geminus’s Almagestum parvum
by Bacon. It is here that one sees a difference between the younger {De dispositione sphaerae) and states: “The judgments of the astronomer
and older generation of theologians. For Albertus as for Bacon, Abu concerning matters here below are not discovered from a science of
M acshar is the auctor in astronomiam. art, whose limits are necessary [i.e. formal logic], but they are dis­
Bacon then cites a series of texts from some of these authors. But covered from those things which happen for the most part,” and
it is important to notice that he integrates all of them into the sci­ “Astronomers have made that statement not according to the way of
ence of Aristotle. He sees them a complementing the science of art nor according to a determined quality {ingenium determinatum), but
Aristotle, particularly the Anstotle of the Meteorologica. The main works by means of a conjunction falling on the adjacent thing,” and “In a
used are: (i) Pseudo-Ptolemy, Centiloquium; (ii) Pseudo-Ptolemy (= Latin third passage, he states that ‘it is clear that what they affirm is affirmed
translation of Arabic version of Geminus, Introduction to the Phenomena, in the most general manner and not in an artificial way and does not
know in Latin both as De dispositione sphaerae and as the Introductorius involve necessity.’”42 This, according to Bacon is further supported by
in almagesti,36 the Quadripartitum (Tetrabiblos) of Ptolemy, and Avicenna’s Ptolemy in the Quadripartitum, who in the third chapter states that
Liber sufficientia?1 Whatever one may think of these works, they are error is always possible in this science.43 It follows then that Ptolemy,
the master in this filed, makes clear that the Astrologer “cannot give
34 Thomas O Loughlin, “Astrology . ..,” believes that Bacon so re-reads the Patristic full certitude in regard to his judgments, especially in particular
sources that he was open to Augustinian criticism. But see below for qualification.
See ch. 1 above for Bacon’s condemnation in his O rder “for certain suspected
novelties,” which means astrology and alchemy.
38 See Paola Zambelli above. The consensus of scholarship now is that Albertus
35 Opus maius, part four, ed. Bridges, I, 242. Bacon does not discuss Abu M a'shar is the author of this work. And it is clear that it had long lasting influence for Latin
in this context. But since his influence is ubiquituous in Bacon’s later works, we Christians in determining which books were books of Science and Art and which
might see this discussion as Bacon’s response to the critical comments of Aquinas in were books of Magic. The books cited here by Bacon were not regarded as books
the Summa contra gentiles. See Jeremiah Hackett, “Necessity, Fate and a Science of
of magic by Albertus or Thomas Aquinas.
Experience in Albertus Magnus, Thomas Aquinas and Roger Bacon,” in Susan J.
39 See above, Richard Lemay, art. cit.
Ridyard & Robert G. Benson, eds., Sewanee Mediaeval Studies 6 (1995), 113-23.
40 Centiloquium, Verbum primum.
36 For MSS information on Medieval Latin versions of this work, see Jeremiah 41 See Cambridge MS Univ. Lib. Ii. HI. 3, comment on Verbum primum: “.. . dixit
Hackett, “Scientia experimentalis: From Robert Grosseteste. . .,” art. cit. 111-12. quia hec scientia non est nisi secundum probationem et opinionem.”
37 Avicenna, Liber de philosophia prima sive Sciencia Divina, ed. S. Van Riet (Louvain-
42 Opus maius, part four, ed. Bridges, II, 243-4.
Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1980), 522-30 [Avicenna Latinus].
43 Ibid., 243-4.
190 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON ASTRONOMY-ASTROLOGY 191

judgments. This is clear not only from these, but from his other which is called experimental, and which still gives a more certain judgment than the
discourses, in which, although he hints at the possibility of judging common form of Astronomy.
about many things with reasonable certitude, yet he unqualifiedly Therefore, after a careful consideration of these and such like state­
ments, it is obvious that true Mathematicians and Astronomers or Astrologers,
states that such great difficulty is inherent in the art, that it is easily who are Philosophers do not assert a necessity and an infallible judgment in the
apparent that he himself places the definite limit, that the astrono­ case of Future Contingents. And so whosoever attributes these erroneous
mer ought not to boast of sufficient certitude in particular judgments.”44 views to them are clearly to be proved guilty of the ignorance of phi­
Bacon summarizes his interpretation of Ptolemy, Geminus and the losophy, and the dismissal of the truth of which they are ignorant. . . ,49
Author and Commentator on the Cenliloquium and concludes that “it
These are strong words and strong claims. And it is likely that they
is not Ptolemy’s thought that the astrologer should give in particular
are directed against the younger generations of theologians which
matters a fixed judgment and one that is sufficient for singular events,
would include, Thomas Aquinas, Bonaventure, Richard Rufus, Giles
but that this judgment should be a general one and a mean between
of Rome, Henry of Ghent and others. But Bacon does not stop there.
the necessary and the impossible, and that the astrologer cannot in all
He immediately presents his own reading of the Patristic writers, Basil,
cases give a determinate judgment.”45 In what follows, Bacon makes
Ambrose, Augustine and Gregory with the intention of proving that
explicit reference to Avicenna’s Metaphysics, book ten. This is a signifi­
his opponents misread the Patristic authors. This is high polemic
cant reference as I will show below. It reads:
and one can expect a few texts to be deconstructed in the process.
For this reason, Avicenna, who completed the works of Ptolemy, as he The crucial text here is the De doctrina Christiana which does of course
himself states in the Introduction to the Libri sufficientiae, reveals in the condemn the frauds of the astrologers. This, however, is not a simple
tenth book of the Metaphysicae that the astrologer is not able to verify citation, but rather a combination of texts from the De doctrina Christiana
in all matters nor should he do so because of the instability of the
and other works by Augustine.50 Bacon has a difficult task here, espe­
generable and corruptible matter, which does not in all things obey
the powers of the heavens, as Massahalla states, giving the example of cially since a rejection of necessarian Astrology motivated Augustine’s
the Magnet, because it does not have power over iron unless it will be departure from Manichaeism, and Augustine is very critical of the
adjusted in the required distance and under the conditions demanded forms of astrological magic.51 Further, there are echoes here of the
for attraction.46 continuing influence of ancient Stoicism.52 But Augustine, while offering
In what follows, Bacon argues that the divine Will can changed the this criticism does allow for a world in which natural and human
ordained law of nature, and the astrologers always add “This will be so, events are destined by God’s Will, and in which the stars and their
if God wills it.”47 Further, they testify that the rational soul can change effects on earth are instruments of the divine will. The real issue is
gready and impede the effects of the stars.48 Bacon comes to the whether Bacon adheres to Augustine’s distinction between a true
following conclusion: mathematics which gives reasonable conjectures about past, present
and future and a false kind which a divinatio, namely the second part
It is clear then from these statements that the philosophers do not of magic.
posit an inevitability in all things in the happenings of nature by means In the light of the above comments by Bacon, it is clear that his
of the heavens, nor do they posit infallible judgment in singular events,
but (only) according to the possibility of this Science, particularly since the
situation is quite different from that of Augustine. The latter was
also add that there is another science [in addition to Astronomy-Astrology]
49 Opus maius, part four, ed. Bridges, ed. cit., 246: Bacon coins the phrase scientia
experimentalis from a combination of these works, antonomastically.
44 Ibid., 245-6. 50 Thomas O ’Loughlin, “Astrology. . 108, n. 60.
45 Ibid., 245. 51 B. Bruning OSA, art. cite, Thomas O ’Loughlin, “The Libri philosophorum. . .,”
46 Opus maius, part four, ed. cit., 245-6; Avicenna, liber de philosophia prima, ed. cit., art. cit.
525-6. 52 Bacon takes over many Stoic themes from Augustine and other Latin writers.
47 See Secretum secretorum, ed. Steele, 3-4. See Marcia Colish, The Stoic Tradition from Antiquity to the Early Middle Ages, II, (Leiden:
48 Bacon like Albertus repeats the remark: Quod sapiens homo dominabitur astris. E.J. Brill, 1985).
192 JEREMIAH HAGKETT
ROGER BACON ON ASTRONOMY-ASTROLOGY 193

involved in a life long polemic with the necessitarian astrologers of Indeed, Bacon’s account above of scientia experimentalis did not cite
his times including the Manichaeans. Bacon had inherited the riches from Abu Ma'shar. Yet, it did not need to do so since an entire
of Greek and Arabic Astronomy-Astrology. And if he is to be believed, rhetoric of the uses of experientia, experimentum and experimentalis runs
there was a strong animus on the part of some theologians against throughout the Introductorium maius in astronomiam. In brief, Abu
this kind of learning on the grounds that it inevitably led to the bad M a'shar’s doctrine of causation, necessitation and celestial influence,
kind of necessitarianism. One notices Bonaventure, John Pecham and further developed by Avicenna, and supplemented by Averroes, was
Aquinas dealing explicitly with this problem. Bonaventure, in par­ defended by Bacon in the Paris of the 1260’s. By adding the above
ticular, links the condemnation of Astrologia with the items which references to the Pseudo-Ptolemaic works, De disposition sphaerae and
become central in the Parisian Condemnations of 1270 and 1277. the Centiloquium and its commentary, Bacon hoped to mitigate the
These include (i) the Eternity of the Word, (ii) the Unity of the Possible attack on Astronomia-astrologia by some major theologians. In this, we
Intellect, (iii) Fatalism or absolute necessity and denial of free will.53 must remember that these theologians, Grosseteste, Bonaventure and
It is easy to see how a scientist and philosopher like Bacon with Aquinas, state that there are two kinds of Astronomia: (a) Speculative
careful distinctions would become open to an accusation of magic. quantitative analysis of the movement of the heavenly bodies and
Bacon knows that Cicero and Augustine attacked the abuse of their natural effects on earth and (b) judicial astrology which predicts
astrology, and adds that the above-mentioned philosophers or as­ human motivation and action. Grosseteste and Bonaventure simply
tronomers likewise condemned the abuses of astrology.54 dismiss the “astrologia iudicaria,'>as “fatua est et infatuatwa eorum qui ibi
vacant.'''’ Thomas Aquinas is more comprehensive in his account. And
he has more in common with Roger Bacon than might appear at
6. Bacon as a Follower of Robert Grosseteste: The Paradox first light. But our concern here is Roger Bacon and the evident
difference between him and his putative hero, Robert Grosseteste on
In recent papers, I have addressed the issue of Bacon’s relation to
the issue of judicial astrology.
Grosseteste and Bonaventure on the question of astrology. The issue
is complex. It is clear that Bacon argues for a greater role of astrol­
ogy in human affairs than does Bonaventure, but it is an argument 7. The Source for Bacon’s ARISTOTLE and ASTROLOGY:
for astrology as a mathematical ars and not for a form of magic. He Ps. Ovid: De vetula
also appears to go much farther than Grosseteste, who in his own
lifetime seems to have moved from an acceptance of astrology to an From the beginning to end of Opus maius, Bacon links Aristotle with
outright condemnation based on Augustine concerning predictions Astrology.58 He does so because in the third book of the Pseudo-
about human life. Grosseteste was willing to retain the uses of astrol­ Ovidian De vetula by Richard of Foumival, he found a synthesis of
ogy for such things as the prediction of weather phenomena.55 It is Aristotle and Astrology placed in the service of a Christian Cosmol­
clear then that Roger Bacon is departing from the main theological ogy. Here one is reminded of the Liber nimrod, which Bacon cites in
line of influence from Grosseteste through Bonaventure.56 This means Opus maius, book two, and which he likewise used for apologetic pur­
that some major influence must have affected Bacon in this respect, poses.59 The modern editors of the De vetula, attributed to Richard of
since we find Bacon in the 1260’s stoutly defending Abu Ma'shar, Foumival, identify Bacon as the first commentator on this work. They
who did represent a necessitarian doctrine of astrological influence.57 demonstrate that some of Bacon’s citations have to do with the positive

53 Bonaventure, Collations on the Six Days, trs. Jose de Vink (Vol. V, The Works of
Bonaventure, (Paterson, NJ, 1970), 96-7. 58 Opus maius, part one to seven.
59 For a summary of this debate and for evidence that Roger Bacon does have
54 Opus maius, part four, ed. Bridges, I, 240; See B. Bruning OSA, art. cit.
this work in mind in Opus maius, part two, see Jeremiah Hackett, “Philosophy and
55 Richard C. Dales, “Grosseteste on Astrology,” art. cit.
Theology in Roger Bacon’s Opus maius,” in R. James Long, ed., Philosophy and the
56 Jeremiah Hackett, “Aristotle, Astrologia. . art. cit.
God of Abraham: Essays in Memory of James A. Weisheipl, O.P., (Toronto: PIMS, 1991,
57 See papers by Richard Lemay and David Pingree on Abu Ma'shar.
55-70.
194 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON ASTRONOMY-ASTROLOGY 195

use made by Bacon of Abu M acshar’s mention of the birth of Christ, analysis of human health. And in the case of Thomas Aquinas, one
and of the preparation in the stars of that event. In themselves, these finds a very judicious account.
citations are not very long or numerous and they could serve simply
as evidence that Bacon was one of the earliest readers of this work.
However, a much more important kind of borrowing was made 8. Bacon and Thomas Aquinas on astral determinism
by Bacon from the De Vetula, book three. It is my considered view
that Roger Bacon not only borrowed the positive acceptance of Abu In the Summa contra gentiles, III, chs. 72, 73, he introduces arguments
M a'shar’s account of the Virgin Birth, but that he took over from against the opinio stoicorum “for they said that all things come about by neces­
this work a whole schema in which the Artes and Aristotle were inte­ sity, according to an irrevocable order (chain) of causes, which the Greeks call
grated into an astrological universe with Monotheistic foundation. eimarmene.”62, Aquinas, like Albertus and Roger Bacon allows for an
The author of the De vetula, as does Bacon, leads the pilgrim on a indirect influence of the heavily bodies on natural events and on hu­
journey through the Artes (that is, the humanities and the sciences) to man actions. And like Albertus and Bacon, he rules out direct influ­
philosophy and theology. Aristotle is presented as Graecorum philosophorum ence of the heavenly bodies on human intellect and will. In ch. 86,
princeps et dominus verique perennis amicus.60 This is a Monotheistic Aristotle he argues that not even corporeal effects on earth result Necessarily
with trinitarian leanings who is presented in the context of the effi­ {de necessitate) from the motions of the heavenly bodies. The motions
cacy of Astrologia for theology. This is the kind of Aristotle, among of the heavens are necessary; those on earth are mutable and contin­
other kinds, which one finds in Bacon in the 1260’s. gent. Material corporeal beings do not produce their effects de necessitate.
Book III of De vetula does not just provide an account of an astro­ In ch. 86, Aquinas singles out the Introductorium maius in astronomiam
logical world which is totally dependent on the Introductorium maius in of Abu M a'shar for special criticism. Briefly, Abu Ma'shar defends a
astronomiam of Abu Ma'shar. Surprise, surprise, it also provides an kind-of causal necessity which, while it uses the word possible (in the
abbreviated and emended version of the cosmogony of light as one sense of contingent), empties the word of real meaning. He thinks
finds it in the De luce of Robert Grosseteste.61 Here, one finds a physics that the effects of the heavens must come about, and thus, still wishes
of light, an astrological cosmos, and a moral and religious cosmos in to say that possibility is not thereby removed from the lower bodies
one synthesis. The prophecy of the Virgin Birth as set out by Abu since each effect is in potency until it comes about. Thus, before it
M a'shar is inserted into a completed cosmogony which matches happens, it is called possible. But when it becomes actual, it passes
perfectly that of Roger Bacon. This is especially the case since Bacon from possibility to actuality. And it necessarily must pass from pos­
in the Moralis philosophia, drawing on al-Farabi, but in astrological sibility to actuality due to the control of the heavenly bodies under
terms on Abu Ma'shar, took over the idea of using astrology to jus­ the power of God.
tify religion. Now, such a move was not opposed by everyone in the Aquinas begins his response to this problem by stating: “But one
1260’s. Even Bonaventure and John Pecham were willing to allow cannot defend this meaning of the word possible. Such an idea would
such a use.62*But it was John of Paris in the late 13th century among imply the principle of plenitude: every genuine possibility must at some
other who took over Bacon’s proposals in his De probatione Jidei. And time become actualized. It leaves no room in nature or in human
even in the case of Grosseteste, allowing for the stark rejection of life for unactualized possibilities. Thus, in ultimate terms, the realm
judicial astrology in its abusive form, it is clear that he retains its of possibility and necessity would coincide. In fact, not only does
valid form for an understanding of human dispositions and for an Aquinas attack Abu M a'shar on this matter and re-define possible as
“the possible that is opposed to the necessary in the sense that the possible is
called that which can be and also not be. Now a thing is not called possible
60 De vetula, ed. Klopsch, 276; See Hackett, “Aristode, Astrologia. . . .”
61 Ibid.., part III.
62 For Bonaventure, see Hackett, “Aristode, Astrobgia. . for Pecham, John 63 See Vernon J. Bourke, St Thomas Aquinas: On the Truth of the Catholic Faith: Summa
Pecham, Canticum pauperis (Quarrachi, 1949), 137. contra gentiles, Book Three, part I, 246.
196 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON ASTRONOMY-ASTROLOGY 197

or contingent in this way . . . as the preceding answer [Abu M acshar] Quadripartitum of Ptolemy and from the Pseudo-Ptolemaic Centiloquium
takes it. . . . Moreover, we should note that, in order to prove that as did Bacon, to argue against an inevitability in the effects of the
the effects of the celestial bodies come about by necessity, Avicenna heavens. And he ends with “These prognostications that I give you
uses an argument like this in his Metaphysics.”64 And this latter text are midway between the Necessary and the Possible.”
was precisely the prooftext from Avicenna that Bacon used above. Thus, despite their different readings of Abu Ma'shar and Avicenna
Further, in ch. 87, Aquinas directly attacks both Abu M a'shar and (Bacon tries to interpret them benignly), they both agree that there
Avicenna, and states the following: “However, we should note that is a kind of Astronomia-Astrologia which is more than weather forecast­
Avicenna maintains that the motions of the celestial bodies are also ing, and which has to do with the prognostication of human dispo­
the causes of our acts of choice, not simply as occasions, as we said sitions and customs. We have come a long way from Grosseteste’s
above, but directly. . . . On this point he seems to return to the theory bald statements in his Hexaemeron and Bonaventure’s repetition of the
of Albumasar.”65 same message.
And yet, in chs. 84 and 85 of this same work, Aquinas, like Roger
Bacon, uses the Pseudo-Ptolemy, Centiloquium to argue to speak about
the influence of the heavenly bodies and about the role of Astrologia 9. Roger Bacon and the Condemnations of 1277
and a kind of Scientia experimentalis. He states:
Since there is some evidence that sometime in late 1277, Roger Bacon
However, we should note that, though celestial bodies cannot be directly
was condemned within the Franciscan Order on account of certain sus­
the causes of our understanding, they may do something indirecdy to
it. For although the understanding is not a corporeal power, the opera­ pected novelties, the issue naturally arises as to whether or not he was
tion o f understanding cannot be accomplished in us without the opera­ a victim, like Thomas Aquinas and Giles of Rome, of the so-called
tion of corporeal powers: that is, the imagination, the power of memory, Augu$tinian theologians on the commission set up by the Bishop
and the cogitative power. . . . And as a result, if the operations of these of Paris, Stephen Tempier? This is not the place to present a full
powers are blocked by some indisposition of the body, the operation
account of this matter. Still, certain directions can be identified.
o f the intellect is impeded. . . . Now, the condition of the human
body does come under the influence of the celestial motions. In fact,
It is not just proposition 101 of the condemnation which finds an
Augustine states in the City of God, v, that “it is not utterly absurd to echo in the Communia naturalium of Roger Bacon. Rather, all of the
say that certain influences o f the Stars (my italics) are able to produce articles 92-107, which have to do with fate and Astral Determinism,
differences in bodies only.” And Damascene says, in Book II, that have a direct relationship to the debate on Astrologia described above.
“different planets establish in us diverse temperaments, habits and dis­ If we add to this the fact that in the prologue to the Condemnation,
positions.” So, the celestial bodies work indirectly on the good condi­
the Bishop of Paris is concerned not with Aristotle but with Experimental
tion of understanding. Thus, just as physicians may judge the goodness
of an intellect from the condition of its body, as from a proximate books and with books in Magic, one can see why the works of Roger
disposition, so may An Astronomer judge from celestial motions, as the Bacon described above have to be regarded as central to the lead up
remote cause o f such dispositions. In this way, then, there is some to the condemnation of 1270 and 1277. The accurate description of
truth in what Ptolemy says in his Centiloquium: “When, at the time of this relationship is a matter for another paper.67
a man’s birth, Mercury is in condition, it gives inwardly to things the
goodness of understanding.”66

Not merely does Aquinas agree with Roger Bacon in this matter. In
fact, at the end of ch. 87, he uses the same proof-texts from the

64 Ibid., part, two, 26-7.


65 Ibid., 30-31. 67 But for the present, see Jeremiah Hackett, “Scientia experimentalis: From Robert
66 Aquinas, Ibid., 17-18. Grosseteste . . .” and “Aristode, Astrologia. . .
198 JEREMIAH HACKETT

Conclusion

I believe that I have now demonstrated the connection between 9. ROGER BACON ON GEOGRAPHY
Astronomia-Astrologia and Roger Bacon’s Scientia experimentalis. I have AND CARTOGRAPHY
placed his concerns in their proper historical context. Further, I have
shown that Bacon’s instincts in regard to the retrieval of one of David Woodward with Herbert M. Howe
the greatest works in ancient Hermeneutics, the De doctrina Christiana,
was correct: there was a legitimate application of Astronomy for an
understanding of human events, past, present and future. It was not This chapter assesses the contribution of Roger Bacon to the geo­
the second form of magic. It was, rather, an applied Astronomy, graphical study of the earth. In particular, it seeks to show that, despite
which in time would develop into a science of experience, a scientia the derivative nature of much of Bacon’s regional and ethnographical
experimentalis.
description, there is evidence of modernity in his geographical
method—particularly in his strong allusions to maps and his insistence
on the importance of longitude and latitude in compiling them. I use
the term “modernity” here to refer to a paradigm shift that occurred
in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries, during which period maps
became everyday tools of scholars, administrators, and military com­
manders, and in which the concept of world coordinates—based largely
on the instructions given in Ptolemy’s Geography—came to dominate
how maps were made and how the geography of the world was
conceived in Early Modem Europe.

The “Geographia” in the Opus Maius

Bacon’s geography is found largely in some ninety pages (in Brewer’s


edition) in the Fourth Part of the Opus Maius dealing with the utility
of mathematics in theology. A geographical section is also found in
the Opus Tertium, three fragments of which were discovered and
published by J.S. Brewer, Pierre Duhem, and A.G. Little.1 In the
fragment edited by Little, which contains Duhem fragment and the
geographical and astrological material, Bacon states that he did not
include the astrological and arcane material in the Opus Maius, not
wanting to hold up the sending of the work to Pope Clement.2

1 J.S. Brewer, ed. Fr. Rogeri Bacon, Opera quaedam hactenus inedita, Vol. I containing
I-Optis Tertium, II-Opus Minus, Ill-Compendium Pfulosophiae, The Chronicles and Memorials
of Great Britain and Ireland during the Middle Ages (Rolls Series) 15. (London: Her
Majesty’s Stationery Office, 1859); A.G. Litde, ed. Part o f the Opus Tertium of Roger
Bacon including afragment now printedfor thefirst time, (Aberdeen: University Press, 1912).
2 Little, Opus Tertium xix.
200 DAVID WOODWARD WITH HERBERT M. HOWE ROGER BACON ON GEOGRAPHY AND CARTOGRAPHY 201

All of the geographical points that Bacon makes in the Opus Tertium Jerom e’s De situ et nominibus locorum Hebraicorum and several biblical
are found in the Opus Maius. He summarizes the reasons for the commentaries, Orosius’s Historiarum adversus paganos (De ormesta mundi),
importance of geographical knowledge in spiritual affairs, and stresses Isidore’s Etymologiae and De natura rerum, the Bible and Apocrypha,
again the importance of putting this information in a map. But the al-Farghani, Avicenna, and a host of other less frequently cited works
role of astrology is again given more weight in these matters.3 from the classical, early Christian, and Islamic worlds, not always
Although it constitutes a large proportion of Bacon’s work, the uncritically. Bacon is explicit about the need for careful collation and
geographical section has not received the attention of other subjects interpretation of sources:
in Bacon’s thought. A.G. Little’s edited volume on Bacon’s writing
In assessing the consensus of learned opinion, we ought not to include
did not contain a chapter on geography or cartography, and David
anything of which we are not sure; we should, moreover, only include
Eugene Smith, the author of the chapter on Bacon’s mathematics in in our account what seems reasonably certain to the best-known
that work, claimed that it did not fall in his purview.4 philosophers.7
One explanation for the lack of attention is that his geographical
work was regarded as wholly derivative. Thus Thorndike, who is not Bacon’s closest claim to firsthand observation was in his use of
known for his support of Bacon’s originality in any arena, believed William of Rubruck’s travels to the Tartar Empire in the service of
that the treatment of geography in the Opus Maius was “simply an Louis IX (1253-55): Bacon uses him as an example of the reliability
intelligent compilation of well-known past writers, including the of the eyewitness accounts he has used:
wretched work of Ethicus, supplemented from writings of the friars For this reason, then, I shall generally go back to writers who have
who had recently visited the Tartars.”5 personally travelled in the parts of this world [they describe]. Thus in
It is true that all of Bacon’s geographical description is based on the regions to the northeast I shall chiefly refer to the friar I have
earlier sources and not on eyewitness observation, notwithstanding already mentioned, whom his Majesty King Louis of France sent to
the Tartars in A.D. 1253. He travelled through these northeastern lands
his assurance that “Again and again, therefore, I sent messengers and those between us and them, and reported to that famous ruler the
overseas, to foreign parts, to gatherings of thoughtful men, so that I facts I have mentioned. I have studied his book with great care and
might [as it were] see these natural phenomena with my own eyes discussed it with its author, as well as with many other explorers of the
and put them to the test,”6 northwest and southern Europe are left lands in that direction.8
out of the Opus Maius because he regarded them as so well known.
Bacon’s use of William of Rubruck was important because his travels
^Ethicus Ister’s Cosmographia is indeed cited often. This tract, which
were ignored by his contemporaries, such as Vincent of Beauvais,
appears as a narrative of an “exploration” by ^Ethicus translated from
whose Speculum Historiale, one of the Dominican Friar’s massive trilogy
the Greek by a priest masquerading as Jerome, a favorite traditional
of natural science, philosophy, and history, relied on the narratives of
authority on geographical thinking, is one of the longest and liveliest
John de Plano Carpini and Simon of St Quentin for his account of
early Christian geographical documents. But, in addition, Bacon cites
the regions east of the Black Sea. Through Bacon’s use of William,
many other classical and early patristic sources: Aristotle’s De Caelo
for example, he was able to confirm that the Caspian Sea was not
and Meteorologica, Sallust’s De bello Jurgurthino, Seneca’s Naturales quaes-
an arm of the circular Oceanus surrounding the world, as it had been
tiones, Pliny’s Naturalis historia, Ptolemy’s Almagest and its commentaries,
previously described in texts and mappaemundi, but was instead a huge
inland sea.
3 Litrie, Opus Tertium 14—16.
4 David Eugene Smith, “The Place of Roger Bacon in the History of Mathematics,” 7 John Henry Bridges, ed. The “Opus Majus” of Roger Bacon, (London: Williams
In Roger Bacon: Essays, ed. A.G. Little, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1914), 153-83. and Norgate, 1900), 295. References to the Latin text are to the Bridges edition.
5 Lynn Thorndike, A History o f Magic and Experimental Science During the First Thirteen All translations are by Herbert M. Howe. A new translation by Herbert M. Howe
Centuries o f Our Era, Vol. 2. (New York: Columbia University Press, 1923), 2:645. of all the geographical sections in the Opus Maius is available from http://feature.
6 F.A. Gasquet, “An Unpublished Fragment of a Work by Roger Bacon,” English geography.wisc.edu/woodward/.
Historical Review 12 (1897): 494—517, 502. 8 Opus Maius 1:305.
202 DAVID WOODWARD WITH HERBERT M. HOWE 203
ROGER BACON ON GEOGRAPHY AND CARTOGRAPHY

But it was, in part, Bacon’s use of William of Rubruck that also If, as Bacon believes, the heavens directly influence the earth, the
set his work apart from the geography of his Dominican rival, Albertus study of astronomy has direct bearing on the earth’s geography. If
Magnus. In comparing the two, it is difficult, however, to agree with the heavens are primarily made up of fire, as he says Augustine and
Kimble that “With the exception of a reference to the Rubruck expe­ others believe, then should we look for heaven-on-earth where there
dition, his regional description of the world is essentially the same as is fire (at the Equator?). If Paradise is to be found on the Equator,
Albert’s.”9 Albert’s regional description in the De natura locorum con­ where is Hell? All these questions require the Christian to under­
sists mostly of lists of places and natural features, and has much less stand the elemental makeup of the earth, its size and shape, and its
ethnographical material than Bacon’s Opus Maius. But both agree in geometrical relationship to the sun, stars, and planets.
stressing the “nature” of places if one wishes to understand the world. Furthermore, since the Bible is full of astronomical problems, such
Albert is perhaps more theoretical in his treatment of this subject, as the explanation of the length of the day when the sun stood still
Roger more explicit about the theological and political ramifications (Joshua 10.13) or such phenomena as when the sun retreated ten
of this knowledge. As Kimble says: “They wrote as clerics for clerics, degrees (II Kings 20.12),
to promote the welfare of the Church and Christianity, and their
sole motive in writing was to promote a sound and saving knowl­ a theologian must, then, have a good knowledge of the phenomena in
the heavens, not just because treatises and commentaries are concerned
edge of God.”9 The geographical studies of the thirteenth century, with such questions, but for the sake of the text itself.13
relying heavily on classical and early patristic sources, were not revo­
lutionary, but there are indications of the incorporation of secular, Second, the Christian theologian must understand mathematical geog­
contemporary travels based on firsthand observation.10 raphy because the Bible is full of allusions to places and physical
The geographical themes that Bacon discusses are clearly related geography. “If one does not understand the physical form of the
to his general aim of employing a knowledge of the world in the serv­ world/’ Bacon says, “history is apt to become a stale and tasteless
ice of the Christian call to mission. The Franciscan order, founded in crust.”14 History and geography are thus the two inseparable con­
1209, nurtured an intense curiosity about the natural world and the texts for human affairs, a theme that continued to be expressed in
interests of its friars frequently turned to cosmography and geography.11 the Renaissance, when history was described as a “dead carcass”
Bacon justifies the use of mathematics (which in the sense used in without geography, and when the two were described as “Castor
this section bears on mathematical geography) in three main ways. and Pollux” which, when joined together “crown our reading with
First, it is important because it leads to an understanding of the infinite delight and profit.”15
heavens: Since the Scriptures are set in the geographical context of “re­
gions, cities, deserts, mountains, seas, and other sorts of terrain,” the
If we are true Christians, the Apostle tells us, our attention is fixed on
theologian first needs to locate these features on the earth with the
heavenly things: we hope to gain them, and we believe that in our
bodies we will dwell in the heavens and remain there forever. It follows aid of mathematical knowledge. By this Bacon basically means we
that no knowledge is as important to us as that of the heavens, and need to know their longitude and latitude. Furthermore, in addition
that no merely human matter should be as eagerly longed for.12 to knowing the precise location of places, the reader of the Scrip­
tures needs to be able to visualize what they are like:
If, then, whoever wants to gain a vivid picture of the places and their
9 George H.T. Kimble, Geography in the Middle Ages, 2nd ed., (New York: Russell relations to each other— distance and location, longitude and latitude,
& Russell, 1968), 91.
10 Clarence J. Glacken, Traces on the Rhodian Shore: Nature and Culture in Western height and depth; who wants to understand their variations in heat
Thought from Ancient Times to the End of the Eighteenth Century, (Berkeley: University of and aridity, cold and damp, color, taste, and smell, beauty, ugliness,
California Press, 1967), 262.
11 Armando Cortesao, History o f Portuguese Cartography, (Coimbra: Ju n ta de Inves­ 13 Opus Maius 1:183.
tig a te s do Ultramar-Lisboa, 1969-71), 1:190. 14 Opus Maius 1:183.
12 Opus Maius 1:180. 15 Peter Heylyn, Cosmographie in four books, (London: 1669).
ROGER BACON ON GEOGRAPHY AND CARTOGRAPHY 205
204 DAVID WOODWARD WITH HERBERT M. HOWE

charm, fertility and barrenness— will find his climb to spiritual heights time. But we cannot understand all this without clear pictures of the
sorely hampered, and can only dimly understand what he reads.16 size and shape of the habitable earth and its divisions or climatic zones.18

He invokes the names of Jerome, Orosius, Isidore, Cassiodorus, and Bacon assumes that the world is spherical, and asks us to imagine
Eusebius as examples of authors who have stressed the need for such three straight perpendicular axes drawn through its center, one the
careful geographical knowledge. But this literal knowledge was only axis of the earth passing through the poles, and two 90° apart in the
a stepping stone to the allegorical meanings attached to sacred geog­ plane of the equator. These axes, following Aristotle, establish six
raphy. Bacon uses the example of the River Jordan. Certainly we different reference points in the heavens. He then establishes two
have to know where it is and how to visualize the regions on its great circles on the earth, the equator and the colure, whose planes
banks, but what we really need to know is what that geographical are perpendicular. The surface of the earth is now divided into four
place means in a spiritual sense. Although he paints a mental map for quarters, two in the northern hemisphere and two in the southern,
us of the River Jordan flowing north to south, with the location of and Bacon shows us a diagram to explain the “quarter part of the
Jericho, Mount Olivet, the Valley ofjosaphat, and Jerusalem, he is heavens under which we live.” (Fig. 1)
quick to point out that these places are all associated with the pit- Bacon then discusses how much of the world is habitable and how
falls and joys along the road of the Christian life; real roads in the much is covered by sea. Ptolemy, in the De dispositione sphaerae (Epitome
landscape are symbols of spiritual roads. The Jordan flows into the of the Almagest), he says, suggests that only one sixth is habitable.
Dead Sea, a symbol of the Inferno; Jericho and its plain symbolize Ptolemy’s world is thus confined to less than half of one hemisphere,
the flesh, the Mount of Olives “the loftiness of the spiritual life, because and, had Bacon had access to the Geography, which he did not, he
of its own altitude, and the sweetness of devotion, as sweet as its would have seen this graphically depicted in Ptolemy’s world map.
oil.” The Valley ofjosaphat signifies humbleness in the eyes of God, Bacon prefers to believe Aristotle, however, whom he quotes as sug­
and Jerusalem signifies “the holy soul which possesses peace of h eart. . . gesting [de Caelo 2.14.15 298a] that more than a quarter of it is in­
after a man has put down the world under his feet and has perfect habited, a statement confirmed by Averroes. Then comes the famous
lowliness, then he has entered Jerusalem (peace), in all three senses of passage that has been used (and misused) to link Bacon’s Opus Maius
the word (peace in his heart, the peace of God, and the peace of the with Columbus’s estimation of the width of the Western Ocean
Church militant).”17 between Spain and Cathay:
What sets Bacon aside from his contemporaries and forebears, Aristotle, moreover, suggests that the sea between the west of Spain
however, is his insistence on the need for a systematic, mathematical and the eastern edge of India is of no great extent. In Naturales Quaesdones
way of positioning places on the earth for the practical needs of gov­ [1, pr. 13], Seneca informs us that this sea can be crossed in a few
ernment, both to understand history and to predict from where in days if the wind is favorable. . . . This conclusion [that more than one
fourth of the earth is habitable] is also proved by the voice of one with
the world threats to Christianity are likely to come. But here too he
a very different point of view. Esdras tells us in his fourth book [the
must lay the mathematical foundations: apocryphal II Esdras 6.42] that six parts o f the earth are inhabited,
And this is the first axiom of our study: every point on the earth is the while the seventh is covered with water. Nobody should question the
apex of a pyramid which transmits the power of the heavens. To make authority of this passage by claiming that this book is apocryphal
simpler and more certain the line of the reasoning I am proposing, we and o f dubious authority; everyone knows that the saints of old used
this book constantly, to confirm the sacred truths, and even used its
must turn our attention to the diversity of the regions of the earth;
pronouncements in the divine office. For these reasons, it must be
how any region changes with the passage of time; and how different
things in the same region are subject to different influences at the same accepted as authoritative, whether Esdras wrote it or someone else. I

16 Opus Maius 1:183. 18 Opus Maius 1:288.


17
17 Opus Maius 1:185-86. 19 Opus Maius 1:289.
206 DAVID WOODWARD WITH HERBERT M. HOWE ROGER BACON ON GEOGRAPHY AND CARTOGRAPHY 207

therefore insist that, though the habitable world known to Ptolemy and tions, such as the Ptolemaic value for the size of the earth, his esti­
his followers is squeezed into a quarter of the total, far more than a mate of the width of the inhabited world, Marco Polo’s report on
quarter is, in fact, fit for habitation.20
the width of Asia and the distance of Japan (Zipangu) from the Asian
Bacon mentions Aristotle’s curious argument for the small distance mainland. Columbus was aware of these issues, with or without the
between Spain and India: he says that, since there are elephants in help of the Ymago mundi, whether in manuscript or print.
both regions, the regions must be similar and therefore close together. The discussion then moves naturally to what is in the southern
Bacon feels he must defend Aristotle from the jeers of those who hemisphere, quoting Ptolemy’s De dispositione sphaerae, (a passage almost
would interpret Aristotle’s use of the term “Further Spain” as mean­ identical appears in the De natura locorum of Albertus Magnus), in
ing western Spain, where, as everyone knows, there are no elephants. support of his view:
He points out that the term “Further Spain” at one time (before the Nature requires that there be two races of Ethiopians, one beneath
Straits of Gibraltar were formed) included not only what is now each tropic. From this some argue that habitation is to be found on
Portugal, but the west coast of Africa in the region of the Atlas the other side of the equator, just as on this.25
Mountains, where “there are plenty of elephants.”21
He concludes that the proportion of habitable land south to 66° must
If the earth is viewed from above the north pole, then the inhabit­
again be much greater than merely half of that hemisphere. Indeed,
able part of the world extends far more than half the globe’s circum­
he argues that there is a greater proportion of habitable land in the
ference, although he admits that of course its actual size has not
quarter of the earth south of the inhabited quarter, because, he claims,
been calculated in his age, “since more than half of the quarter in
due to the eccentricity of the sun’s orbit, the sun comes much closer
which we live is still quite unknown, and its towns are not familiar
even to philosophers.”22 to the earth in that quarter, there is more heat, and thus less water.
A similar conclusion can be drawn about the other quarter-earth
The relationship of this passage in Bacon to the Columbian voyages
south [i.e. southwest] of the inhabited quarter. His reasoning ignored
has been a matter for debate. Most authors have assumed that there
the fact that the earth rotates, removing any effect of this eccentricity
was a strong connection between the two. The facts of the case seem
in the earth’s distance from the sun throughout the year.
to be that Pierre d’Ailly (Cardinal Petrus Alliacus) quoted Bacon almost
Since the poles are colder, and “cold magnifies dampness,” he
verbatim on the subject in his Ymago Mundi without direct acknowl­
argues there is an abundance of water there, and that the water
edgment. Although the sixteen treatises comprising the Ymago Mundi
moves north-south from pole to pole (presumably to the north in
were compiled in 1410-14 it was not published until ca. 1483 and
winter and to the south in summer, in a kind of crude model of
Columbus owned a copy, which he annotated with almost 900 notes,
ocean currents). He provides a curious diagram, usually reproduced
but probably not before 1494.23 Columbus alluded to the passage in
as a geometricized line drawing, to illustrate the shape of the ocean
d’Ailly in a letter to Ferdinand and Isabella which he wrote from
between “the west of Spain to the east of India” and the short dis­
Hispaniola in 1498. Although Humboldt believed that this “had more
to do with the discovery of America than the Toscanelli letters,” it tance between them.26 (Fig. 2)
Bacon then goes on to explain how the inhabited world can be
is difficult to pinpoint such influence.24 For the would-be global navi­
divided into seven climata, as Ptolemy and al-Farghani have done.
gator of the 1470’s, the question of the width of the Western Ocean
The climata are latitudinal belts around the earth whose boundaries
was no doubt discussed with reference to several well-known assump­

20 Opus Maius 1:290-01. 25 Opus Maius 1:291. The De Dispositione Sphaerae is the Almagesti minoris libri VI, or
21 Opus Maius 1:292. Almagestum parvum, an introduction to the Almagest—based on Geminus’s Introduction to
22 Opus Maius 1:293. the Phenomena which had been translated into Latin by Gerard of Cremona in the
23 Tony Campbell, The Earliest Printed Maps, (London: British Library Publica­ twelfth century. The passage on the two races of Ethiopians is found in Paris,
tions, 1988). Bibliotheque Nationale MS Lat. 16198, 174v.
24 Thorndike, Magic and Experimental Science, 1:645-66. 26 Opus Maius 1:294.
ROGER BACON ON GEOGRAPHY AND CARTOGRAPHY 209
208 DAVID WOODWARD WITH HERBERT M. HOWE

straight line [a meridian], from the point corresponding to the number


are defined by the length of the longest day at that latitude. He of degrees of latitude of the place. This point is also marked on the
spends a great deal of time explaining how the relationship of the colure (the quarter of the great circle that passes from the equator to
earth to the angle of the sun causes differences among the complexions the pole of the universe), and is, in fact, an arc of the colure. This
of the world’s peoples and makes some places uninhabitable. Later procedure is both easier and better [than anything now in use], and a
in the Opus Maius, Bacon discusses how it has been observed that— map drawn in this way is quite capable of representing to the senses
the location of any point in the world.27 (Fig. 3)
even in the zones of the climata, there are conditions where no shadow
is cast, called askia. In some places, [along the Tropic of Cancer] he At great length, Bacon explains that measurements “east and west”
explains, when the sun passes directly overhead at noon at the sum­ must be measured along the equator, not along the parallel. In modem
mer solstice, no shadows are cast in any direction. Those who live parlance, we would say that Venice is west of Rome, for example,
between the Tropic of Cancer and the equator experience shadows because the meridian of Venice is west of the meridian passing through
more often to the north than to the south, because the sun is to Rome. What he is explaining is a coordinate system based on paral­
their south longer than it is to the north. Those who live on the lels and meridians:
equator have the sun to the north and south for an equal time. Then
If, now, we want to find the distance of a city [with which we are
comes a puzzle: from Pliny, Bacon says, we learn that people live
concerned] from the west as I have defined it, let us draw [on our
south of the Tropic of Capricorn who experience only southern shad­ map] a line whose length represents the distance of our city from the
ows all year round: a “part of India called Pathalis is said to have a western limit; this segment between the city and the western limit will
busy port,” and an island called Taprobane. Some men from this indicate the city’s longitude, measured from the west. Now let us draw
place came to Rome in the reign of Claudius, and were apparently a line from Arm, a city half way from extreme east to extreme west,
extending to the North Pole [a sort of prime meridian]. From this
astonished to find that their shadows fell to the north. Taprobane is
draw a latitudinal line to your city; this will show your city’s distance
identified with usually Ceylon (Sri Lanka) is of course of which are from the “middle of the world” [from the meridian o f Arm].28
far north of the Tropic of Capricorn, so it is unclear either where
these men came from or whether their account of the sun appearing Bacon’s source for the coordinates of cities were the “Toledo” or
always to the north in their homeland was correct. “Alphonsine” tables derived ultimately from the tables of al-Khwarazmi
In his description of how the various latitudinal zones of the inhab­ and Zarkala and compiled at Toledo, under the patronage of Alfonso
ited world can be described, Bacon makes what can be regarded as X of Castille (1252-84), by Islamic and Jewish astronomers.29 The
his most original geographical contribution, the allusion to a systematic Alphonsic computations, with all their defects, estimated the length
map of the inhabited world, which is therefore quoted here in full: of the Mediterranean far more truly than Ptolemy.30 Bacon expresses
his frustration that more such data have not been gathered:
Since these climata and their famous cities cannot well be described by
words alone, a map must be used to make them clear to our senses. And since the distances of longitude and latitude from Toledo of other
I shall, therefore, first present a map o f our quadrant, and on it I shall cities can only be found collected in the Alphonsine tables, in this part
label the important cities, each in its own place, with the distance from of my work I have generally followed them, although we sorely need
the equator— what we call the latitude— of the city or region. I shall more accurate ones, since the latitudes and longitudes of the Latin­
also label them according to their distance from the east or west, what speaking world and its cities have not yet been established. Indeed, they
we call the place’s longitude. In my assigning o f climata, and likewise of
latitude and longitude, I shall make use of the prestige and experience
of the wisest scholars. To locate each city in its proper place [on this 27 Opus Maius 1:295-96.
map] by its longitude and latitude, which have already been discov­ 28 Opus Maius 1:300.
ered by my authorities, I shall use a method by which their positions 29 John Kirtland Wright, The Geographical Lore of the Time of the Crusades: A Study in
the History of Medieval Science and Tradition in Western Europe, American Geographical
may be shown by their distances north and south, east and west. The Society Research Series No. 15, ed. W.L.G. Joerg. (New York: American Geographical
device is this: parallel to the equator (already drawn on a plane surface), Society, 1925), 102-04.
a straight line [i.e. a parallel of latitude] is drawn. This intersects another 30 Opus Maius 1:298-99.
210 DAVID WOODWARD WITH HERBERT M. HOWE ROGER BACON ON GEOGRAPHY AND CARTOGRAPHY 211

never will be, except under an apostolic or imperial decree, or the sup­ Glacken regards Albertus Magnus’s De nalura locorum as “the most
port of some great ruler willing to offer his backing to philosophers.31 important and the most elaborate discussion of geographical theory'
We then get a glimpse of what the map might have looked like: it with relation to human culture since the Hippocratic Airs, Waters,
was on parchment and the cities were marked in red: Places. . . Albert also perpetuated the old error of extrapolating to
entire peoples environmental influences that presumably caused mental
For all these reasons, then, I am presenting such figures in the blank or physical differences among individuals. As it was with the ancients,
part of this parchment [pellis, “sheepskin”, i.e. map], where cities are
shown by little red circles. To the rest of the parchment, a different so it was with Albert: the environmental theory became a handy
function may be assigned, that of describing in greater detail the places explanation for racial differences—especially skin color and type of
of the world. This second sort of description I have added, because of hair—and for physiological and cultural differences.”36
the great importance of the places concerned.32 Bacon’s is no blind oversimplified geographical determinism, how­
The map is of course lost to posterity, but it must have been quite ever. As Glacken points out, Bacon
large and complicated to bear all the information he suggests. It was is aware of the cultural diversity in the various climata, among the
also quite different from such contemporary maps as the Hereford Scythians, Ethiopians, Picards, French, Normans, Flemings, and the
Map (ca. 1290) which is based on the usual mappamundi model of the English, but the causes of these differences are in the heavens, not on
earth or in men. Observation, however, forces him to modify the gen­
tripartite earth, usually oriented to the east, and often centered on
eralization, because Bacon sees too the cultural influence of a great
Jerusalem.33 Bacon’s map is oriented to the north and centered on city on its environs; a province surrounding a famous city assumes its
Arin, and uses a completely different structural base that only came manners and customs because “the city serves as a refuge and a cen­
into common use in the fifteenth century. tral point for transacting the affairs of life.”37
The position of places must be known and marked on a map,
Geographical knowledge, Bacon says, has been sadly lacking in the
Bacon says, but the character of these places must also be described
philosophy of the Latins, and thus they have been unable to explain
and understood for several practical reasons. He states a core axiom
phenomena fully out of geographical context. Furthermore, a knowl­
of geography:
edge of the world’s geography is essential if we are to avoid the
As Porphyry tells us, position in space is a prerequisite for the genera­ pitfalls of extreme climates in missionary travel:
tion of things, and diversity of position means diversity of everything.34
There have been times when men in the best of health have crippled
The notion that a knowledge of place (locus) was necessary to under­ themselves—not to mention the concerns of all Christendom—by their
stand the diversity of the world’s peoples, (a theory known as geographi­ ignorance of the various climates [naturam locorum] of the world. They
cal determinism that became discredited as a vast over-simplification have [tried to] traverse regions too hot for them in the summer, or too
cold in the winter.38
in the early twentieth century), is strongly present in the thought of
Albertus Magnus: An ethnographical knowledge of the world’s peoples and religions is
also necessary to avoid diplomatic or doctrinal blunders:
For here it has been proved that a place is an active principle of genera­
tion, as some think. The reason for this is that every thing that has been Whether he is setting out to convert the heathen or to further some
located keeps itself located in its own place just as matter to form.35 other business of the Church, he must know the practices and behavior
of every region, so that he may be able to approach a fitting place to

31 Opus Mams 1:300.


32 Opus Maius 1:300. Magnus and His Contributions to Geographical Thought, Michigan Geographical Publication
33 Paul D.A. Harvey, Mappamundi: The Hereford World Map, (London: British No. 4, (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Department of Geography, 1971), 25.
Library, 1996). 36 Glacken, Traces on the Rhodian Shore, 270.
34 Opus Maius 1:301. 37 Glacken, Traces on the Rhodian Shore, 285.
35 Sister Jean Paul Tilmann O.P., An Appraisal of the Geographical Works of Albertus 38 Opus Maius 1:301.
212 DAVID WOODWARD WITH HERBERT M. HOWE ROGER BACON ON GEOGRAPHY AND CARTOGRAPHY 213

carry out his purpose, and will not fall among idolaters when he means Geography and Cartography in the Thirteenth Century
to approach pagans.. . . Men without number have failed to succeed in
the most important business of Christendom, simply because they did not It can be claimed that there was a “geographical renaissance” in the
understand the immense differences between the regions of the world.39
thirteenth century. It was not a dramatic or revolutionary change,
Bacon specifies an example in knowing the location of the ten lost but there were a number of distinct manifestations of a new interest
tribes of Israel, which he links to the legend of the tribes walled in in describing and representing the physical and cultural world. Many
by Alexander: of the materials for such an enterprise were now available, except
for the most obvious, Ptolemy’s Geography. The prime classical sources,
But since these peoples, still imprisoned in clearly-marked parts of the
particularly Aristotle and his Arabic commentators and Ptolemy’s
world, are destined to emerge and to gain the Antichrist as their leader,
it is well for Christians— and especially the Roman Church— to con­ Almagest, now existed in Latin translation. The universities of Oxford
sider carefully the geography o f those places, so that they may be able and Paris were particularly strong centers of a cosmographical and
to understand the savagery of these tribes. In this way they will be geographical culture that reached its climax in Europe in the thir­
able to foresee the day of the Antichrist’s coming, as well as the place teenth century. The Dominican and Franciscan orders founded in
whence he will appear (originem).40
that century, although primarily advancing the sacra doctrina, the sav­
Bacon then passes on to a geographical description, region by region, ing knowledge of Scripture, stimulated the intellectual life of the
following especially Pliny, but also Jerome, Orosius, Isidore, and secular thirteenth century. The result was a profusion of treatises and great
writers, as he fully acknowledges. encyclopedias, such as those by Vincent de Beauvais, Albertus Magnus,
The regional description, which starts with a discussion of the Bartholomew Anglicus, Brunetto Latini, and Roger Bacon. The geo­
sources of the rivers of Paradise, then takes a broad sweep— not graphical passages in Dante drew on much of this material and helped
entirely systematic or without repetition—to cover Asia, Africa, north­ to popularize it.41
ern Europe, and finishing with Southeast Europe. He dwells at great Moreover, as John K. Wright points out, many of the leaders of
length on the description of the Holy Land, because it is with it that this twelfth- and thirteenth-century interest in geography, from Adelard
Scripture is most concerned. The tour then extends to the southern of Bath, Alexander Neckam, Alfred of Sareshel, Daniel of Morley,
coast of India, and doubles back to Ethiopia, Egypt, and the course Robert Grosseteste, and Roger Bacon, were Englishmen.42
of the Nile and the theories (based on Anaxagoras and Aristode) Sacrobosco (d. 1256), although bom in England and possibly edu­
about its flooding, North Africa, Arabia, and the encampments of cated at Oxford, was admitted as a member of the University of
the Children of Israel, Syria (in its multiple regions), the Tigris and Paris in 1221. He is best known for his work De sphaera, which prob­
Euphrates, the Holy Land (once more), Mt. Taurus and the Caucasus, ably appeared in the 1220’s or 1230’s, almost certainly predating the
the kingdoms of the Medes, Persians, and Parthians, India which De sphaera of Robert Grosseteste. The English geographical culture in
evidently includes Indo-China, back to Asia Minor, the Black Sea, the thirteenth century is also revealed by the clustering of at least
River Don, the swamps of Maeotis, the Danube, Poland, and east­ four important thirteenth-century mappaemundi—the Vercelli (ca. 1200),
ern Hungary, Great Russia, the Steppe zone of the Tartars and the “Duchy of Cornwall,” (before 1220), Ebstorf (ca. 1235—40), and
origins of that people (based largely on William of Rubruck), and a Hereford (ca. 1290) maps—which either were made in England or
section on the Caspian Sea, fully asserting its inland character. appear to have strong English connections. In addition, important
smaller examples include the Psalter map (ca. 1250), and several maps

39 Opus Maius 1:302. 41 Wright, Geographical Lore, 107.


40 Opus Maius 1:303. 42 Wright, Geographical Lore, 408-09, fn. 97.
214 DAVID WOODWARD WITH HERBERT M. HOWE

by Matthew Paris. Records describe Henry I ll’s decorations at Win­

1 D iagram from a late thirteen th -century m an u scrip t o f th e Opus M aius, show ing th e division o f th e E q u ato r an d th e m eridian
chester Casde as including a world map (1236).43
Another significant cartographic development in the thirteenth
century was the beginning of portolan charts—nautical charts of the
Mediterranean and Black Seas known for their accuracy. Bacon does
not refer to them, and they may have become familiar only after the
appearance of the Opus Maius. The earliest reliably documented

o f Arin. British Library, Royal MS 7 F VII, 43r. By perm ission o f th e British Library.
reference to these charts dates from 1270, and the oldest surviving
chart—the so-called Carte Pisane—are thought to date from about
the same time, but many attempts have been made to justify an
older beginning. For example, Nordenskiold believes that Ramon Lull
was the guiding spirit in these charting developments.44
Much evidence points towards an association between these early
charts of the Mediterranean and the books of sailing directions, or
portolani. An early example for the Mediterranean is the mid-thirteenth-
century Lo compasso da navigare (1232 X 1258). Motzo, its modem editor
and commentator, concluded that Lo compasso da navigare and the
prototype chart (not necessarily the Carte Pisane) were derived from
the same data, and proposed the mathematical school of Leonardo
Pisano (Fibonacci) or of his pupil Campano da Novara as a possible
origin.45
Also strongly associated with these charts— and one of many pos­
sible explanations for their origin—was the mariner’s compass. The
writings of the English monk Alexander Neckam provide confirma­
tion of its existence by the last two decades of the twelfth century of
a simplified lodestone, consisting of a magnetized needle pushed
through a floating piece of wood. One commentator, Jacques de Vitry,
bishop of Acre, even wrote in 1218 of its necessity for navigation.46
Bacon’s association with the compass is much more tenuous. It was
certainly well known in his time, but it is by no means clear that he

43 David Woodward, “Medieval Mappaemundi,” In History of Cartography: Cartog­


raphy in Prehistoric, Ancient, and Medieval Europe and the Mediterranean, ed. J.B. Harley
and David Woodward, 1. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 286-370.
44 Adolf Eric Nordenskiold, Periplus. An Essay on the Early History of Charts and Sail­
ing Directions, (Stockholm: 1897).
45 Tony Campbell, “Portolan Charts from the Late Thirteenth Century to 1500,”
In History of Cartography: Cartography in Prehistoric, Ancient, and Medieval Europe and the
Mediterranean, ed. J.B. Harley and David Woodward, 1. (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1987), 371-463, 382.
46 For an excellent account of the compass in medieval Europe, see Julian A.
Smith, “Precursors to Peregrinus: The Early History of Magnetism and the Mariner’s
Compass in Europe,” Journal of Medieval History 18 (1992): 21-74.
!

O u
be 2

O <J

Pi

00 Js
ROGER BACON ON GEOGRAPHY AND CARTOGRAPHY 215

understood its workings, believing that it could be made to turn to


any other point of the compass if only it has been properly magnet­
ized.47 The apocryphal story of Brunetto Latini showing Bacon “the
secret of the magnetic needle” which Bacon was anxious not to divulge
for fear of being accused of practicing magic has been traced to a
magazine article of 1802.48

The Mathematical Method

It has often been pointed out that, although Bacon stridently called
for mathematical methods in the study of natural science and theology,
his practical grasp of mathematics was not at all strong, especially
when compared to roughly contemporary “pure” mathematicians such
as Leonardo Fibonacci. Thorndike summarized it as “expounding
his physical and astronomical theories by means of simple geometrical
diagrams,” concluding that Bacon’s glowing reputation in the appli­
cation of mathematical method in the sciences was unfounded.49
Nevertheless, Bacon’s description of a system of plotting places with
latitude and longitude was innovative because he understood that
the idea of coordinate systems could be transferred from a celestial
to a terrestrial context and construed that this might be useful in the
making of maps. There are no similar allusions to such a system
earlier in medieval Europe, and between Bacon’s time in the mid­
thirteenth century and the introduction of Ptolemy’s Geography in the
early fifteenth century we hear of no other such application in the
Latin west.50*
It should be pointed out that Bacon’s system was not a map pro­
jection, as has often been stated. A careful study shows that Bacon
nowhere mentions that a graticule of longitude and latitude lines was
added to his map. We can certainly rule out the idea that Bacon
developed equations for a projection of the inhabited world or even
that he had much theoretical knowledge of how to systematically
transform a spherical surface to a flat one. Nevertheless, his obvious
understanding of the use of meridian great circles and parallels with
4. Detail o f the seventh figure” from a m anuscript o f Pierre d ’Ailly, Imago M undi
showing his m ap o f the inhabited world. Brussels, B ibliotheque Royale, MS. 21198,
fol. 4. Copyright B ibliotheque royale A lbert Ier. 47 Brewer, Opus Minus, 383-84.
48 Thorndike, Magic and Experimental Science, 621.
49 Thorndike, Magic and Experimental Science, 645.
50 David Woodward, “Roger Bacon’s Terrestrial Coordinate System,” Annals of
the Association of American Geographers 80 (1 1990): 109-22.
216 DAVID WOODWARD WITH HERBERT M. HOWE 217
ROGER BACON ON GEOGRAPHY AND CARTOGRAPHY

reference to graduated axes indicates that a projection was latent in question of latitudes and longitudes was astronomical and astrologi­
his procedure. We may therefore conclude that Roger Bacon’s method cal, not geographical.”52 Wright went as far as to say that the influ­
involved at least some understanding of how to represent the spheri­ ence of such coordinates on the geographical cartography of the twelfth
cal earth on a flat plane (to “appeal to the sense”) even if he had and thirteenth centuries “was absolutely nil.”53 Although Wright’s
neither fitted an equation to the transformation nor drawn a grati­ statement may be true in the light of the general lack of immediate
cule of parallels and meridians on his map. acceptance of the Opus Maius, the very appearance of the description
The Islamic geographers had already been exposed to Ptolemy’s of Bacon’s map as a tool for political expansion must suggest that
idea of terrestrial coordinates. The date usually given for its arrival functions other than those associated with traditional astrology may
is during the reign of Caliph al-Ma’mun (ninth century), and the have been in Bacon’s mind. The exact knowledge of the position of
translation is attributed originally to al-Kindi and later to ibn Qurrah. places in Bacon’s writing had both practical and spiritual functions,
It is likely that the full translation of the Geography into Arabic did and the Opus Maius is carefully laid out to distinguish between the two.
not come until much later in the ninth century, certainly after the
death of al-Ma’mun.
Central in Ptolemy’s ideas was the principle that maps should be Effect o f Bacon’s Geographical Ideas
plotted from tables of latitude and longitude values. For Islamic science,
the tables seem to be of much more importance in this early period Like many other of Bacon’s writings, the advice on how to make a
than the maps themselves. Lists of both latitude and longitude, fol­ systematic map went unheeded, presumably because no driving need
lowing Ptolemy at least in method if not in detail, are exemplified by was present in the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries for such a
the sets of tables— designed for astrological use—by al-Khwarazmi, precise way of positioning places on the globe. By the time that
one of the scholars of al-Ma’mun’s court, and al-Battanl and Suhrab, European geography was ready for such precise cartography, Ptolemy’s
both of the tenth century. Geography had been translated, in the first decade of the fifteenth
The application of these tables to geographical mapmaking was century, from Byzantine Greek manuscripts into Latin. The center
quite another matter. We have only one account of how this could of geographical attention was on this work, certainly not the Opus
be done from the work of Suhrab in the tenth century. Suhrab gives Maius, as the full impact of Ptolemy’s theoretical ideas for terrestrial
an introduction to his version of al-Khwarazmi’s tables in which he mapping became apparent in the proliferation of manuscripts and
explains in detail how to draw a map of the world. His explanation printed editions during the fifteenth century.
is illuminating. First he draws a rectangle, “the larger the better,” Clearly, however, Bacon was an influence on the Tmago mundi of
and then he divides the edges into degrees and marks the equator Pierre d’Ailly (1410-14), whose map may well have been based on
and then the horizontal lines dividing the climates. To pinpoint his Bacon’s (Fig. 4). In addition to the passages on the short distance
features on the map he uses a thread stretched due north and south between Spain and India, d’Ailly lifted almost word for word the
at the longitude required, with another thread stretched due east section describing Bacon’s artificium, his system of coordinates. Com­
and west at the required latitude. The feature could then be placed pare the following short excerpts from a much larger almost identi­
at the intersection of the threads.51
cal pair of quotations:
The primary purpose of these calculations was to fix the locations
of birthplaces for astrological use. John K. Wright stated, “the whole [Bacon] Et hoc artificium consistit in concursu lineae rectae equidistantis
aequinoctiali signatae in piano; secundum formam lineae rectae ductae

51 Gerald R. Tibbetts, “The Beginnings of a Cartographic Tradition,” In The His­ 52 John Kirtland Wright, “Notes on the Knowledge of Latitude and Longitude in
tory of Cartography: Cartography in the Islamic and South Asian Societies, ed. J.B. Harley and the Middle Ages,” Isis 5 (1923): 75-98, 83.
David Woodward, 2 Book 1. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), 90-107.
53 Wright, Geographical Lore, 246.
218 DAVID WOODWARD WITH HERBERT M. HOWE ROGER BACON ON GEOGRAPHY AND CARTOGRAPHY 219

a numero graduum latitudinis regionis signato in quarta coluri ducta etry, and astronomy] redound— in this world, at least to the benefit
ab aequinoctiali ad polum mundi.54 of the Church of God, rather than to the enemies of the Faith, who,
indeed, can be more effectually destroyed by Wisdom and her works
and: than by the tools of war and soldiery.58
[D ’Ailly] hoc artificium consistit in concursu linie recte equidistatis
equinoxiali signate in piano secundum formam linee recte ducte a
numero graduum latitudinis regionis signato in quarta coluri usque ad Visualization
polum mundi.55

Furthermore, Bacon was admired by the sixteenth-century English Another element in Bacon’s geographical writing that is unusual for
pioneers of the English geographical Renaissance, Richard Eden and the thirteenth century is his emphasis on the need for pictures and
John Dee, whose prescient calls for a British Empire hark back to maps in order to visualize the geography of landscapes and places.
Bacon’s plea to Clement IV for a universal system of knowledge to We have already referred to the example of the Jordan valley. In
support a worldwide missionary effort. It has also been claimed that addition to his extensive allusions to his own map in the Opus Maius
Dee’s teaching of the importance of applied mathematics and of an and Opus Tertium, he mentions the maps of others:
experimental approach to science was strongly influenced by the Opus Eusebius of Caesarea, as Jerome tells us in his book On Places, wrote in
Maius, of which he owned several of the seven books in manuscript, his own hand about the land of Judaea and the parts inherited by
including Book IV. Richard Eden invoked Bacon when he wrote: each tribe, and at the end added a map [picturam] of Jerusalem itself
“no man knoweth further . . . than is tryed and founde by experi­ and the temple in that city, with a short commentary.59
ence.” Leonard Digges, amateur mathematician and author of the Some passages in the Opus Maius appear to have been written with
influential book on surveying and measurement, the Tectonicon (1556), a map in mind. For example, he describes the shape of the north
owned a manuscript of Bacon’s book on optics.56 coast of the Black Sea as like a Scythian bow.60
Part VI of the Opus Maius, dealing with experimental science, also Other writers in the thirteenth century had mentioned maps. Thus
contains material relating to geography and cartography. In it, Bacon Jacques de Vitry, bishop of Acre, specifically mentioned that he found
calls for a adequate instrumentation: a mappamundi to be a useful source of information. Fra Paolino Veneto,
Mathematics could perfectly well develop a spherical astrolabe, on which an early fourteenth-century Minorite friar, seems to have taken up
would be engraved everything in the heavens that people might find Bacon’s plea for their value:
useful, placed on accurately measured parallels and meridians— those
of both the geographical circles and those of the heavens.57 without [maps] I say it would be not so much difficult as impossible to
imagine or conceive in the mind the dispersal of the sons of Noah and
He continues to discuss how mathematics will benefit the broader the four great kingdoms.. . . What is needed are maps with both pic­
aim of furthering the Church: tures and words, for without the one the other will not suffice. Pictures
without words do not show provinces and kingdoms clearly, and words
Thus mathematics considers everything still unknown with an eye to without the support of pictures do not enable the eye to comprehend
the state and its citizens; it gives orders to other sciences as though the boundaries of provinces.61
they were its housemaids, so that all the powers of investigation may
properly be attributed to mathematics alone. Thus the unbelieveable
benefits of these three sciences [presumably he means arithmetic, geom­
58 Opus Maius 2 221.
59 Opus Maius 1 184.
54 Opus Maius 1:296. Opus Maius 1 366.
55 Cortesao, Portuguese Cartography, 1:197. 61 Juergen Schulz, ‘Jacopo de’ Barbari’s View of Venice: Map Making, City Views,
56 E.G.R. Taylor, Tudor Geography 1485-1583, (London: Methuen, 1930). and Moralized Geography Before the Year 1500,” Art Bulletin 60 (1978): 425-74,
57 Opus Maius 2:202. 452.
220 DAVID WOODWARD WITH HERBERT M. HOWE
ROGER BACON ON GEOGRAPHY AND CARTOGRAPHY 221

Albertus Magnus also mentions a small map to be attached to his De


major original achievement. It was this deceptively simple concept of
natura locorum, but apparently not as ambitious as Bacon’s, and com­
coordinates, with its ability to control the accuracy of positions over
ments as if this was expected of the au courant scholar:
its entire face, that was to become central to cartography, and the
In order that I may not seem to be lacking in some way to those who primary characteristic that made it “modern.” Furthermore, despite
wish to read my writings, I will attach a little map of the world to this Bacon’s careful wording that all this mathematical knowledge should
work, granted it is not skillfully made, in which I first describe our always redound to the Glory of God, the obvious contributions of
habitable world, presenting its seas, and mountains that have been
geography and cartography to secular politics are frequently made
named, its rather famous rivers, and the boundaries and limits of our
inhabited world.62 explicit. Bacon’s geographical ideas seem to represent the beginnings
of an emergence from the center/periphery frame of mind in car­
tography towards the more homogeneous and systematic structure
Conclusions for geographic space, a gndded space that was to form the backdrop
for the European colonization of the globe. Despite the attacks on
Armando Cortesao, the eminent Portuguese historian of cartography the hagiographic leanings of Bacon’s biographers, E.G.R. Taylor’s
and exploration, regarded Bacon’s contributions to geography and epithet describing him as the “Father of Modern Geography”64 still
cartography as outstanding for his time. Citing his references to the holds a grain of truth.
compass, the astrolabe, his estimate of the distance west to Asia, his
drawing of a world map “the first known to have been drawn on a
projection after the time of Ptolemy,” he concluded: Bibliography

This is enough to show the importance of the English Franciscan friar’s Bacon, Roger. Opus Maius. Translated by Robert Belle Burke. Philadelphia:
great work for the history of geography, cosmography, navigation and University of Pennsylvania Press, 1928.
cartography, among its other aspects o f exceptional significance for the Brewer, J.S., ed. Fr. Rogeri Bacon, Opera quaedam hactenus inedita, Vol. I contain­
history o f science in general.63 ing 1-Opus Tertium, 11-Opus Minus, Ill-Compendium Philosophic. The Chronicles
and Memorials of Great Britain and Ireland during the Middle Ages
In this chapter, we have seen that his references to the compass, the (Rolls Series) 15. London: Her Majesty’s Stationery Office, 1859.
spherical astrolabe, or the length of a degree of latitude were not Bridges, John Henry, ed. The “Opus Majus” of Roger Bacon. London: Williams
unique in the thirteenth century, nor did Bacon invent a “map projec­ and Norgate, 1900. Page references to the Latin are to this edition.
------ . The life and Work of Roger Bacon. An Introduction to the Opus Maius. London:
tion.” His estimate of the distance west to Asia was also a gross
Williams and Norgate, 1914.
mistake, although maybe a fortunate one, like Columbus’s, for the
Campbell, Tony. “Portolan Charts from the Late Thirteenth Century to
European discovery of America. His geographical regional compila­ 1500.” In History of Cartography: Cartography in Prehistoric, Ancient, and Medi­
tion was intelligent and extensive, but it was not particularly original. eval Europe and the Mediterranean, ed. J.B. Harley and David Woodward.
Nevertheless, Bacon’s explicit call for a systematic way of mapping 371-463. 1. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987.
the world with astronomical instruments and according to the lati­ Cortesao, Armando. History of Portuguese Cartography. [& lit] Coimbra: Junta
de Investigates do Ultramar-Lisboa, 1969-71.
tude and longitude principles of Ptolemy, well over a century before
those had otherwise been absorbed into the Christian west, was a Durand, Dana Bennett. The Vienna-Klostemeuburg Map Corpus of the Fifteenth
Century. A Study in the Transition from Medieval to Modem Science. [& lit] Leiden:
E.J. Brill, 1952.

62 Tilmann, Albertus Magnus, 112. A simplified map rather evocative of those


mentioned in the Opus Maius appears in the autograph ms Codex Vindobonensis
273, fol. 15 lv, but it is so simple that it cannot be the one to which Albertus refers. 64 E.G.R. Taylor, “Compendium Cosmographiae: A Text-Book of Columbus,”
63 Cortesao, Portuguese Cartography, 1:196.
Scottish Geogaphical Magazine 47 (1931): 214—19, 214.
222 DAVID WOODWARD WITH HERBERT M. HOWE

Glacken, Clarence J. Traces on the Rhodian Shore: Nature and Culture in Western
Thoughtfrom Ancient Times to the End of the Eighteenth Century. [& lit] Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1967.
10. RO GER BACON ON MUSIC
Harvey, Paul D.A. Medieval Maps. London: British Library, 1991.
------ . Mappamundi: The Hereford World Map. London: British Library, 1996. Nancy van Deusen
Kimble, George H.T. Geography in the Middle Ages. 2 ed., New York: Russell &
Russell, 1968.
Little, A.G., ed. Part of the Opus Tertium of Roger Bacon including a fragment now And this is a Wonderful Diversity in the Action of Nature
printed for the first time. Aberdeen: University Press, 1912.
------ . Roger Bacon: Essays. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1914. In the preface to his 1859 edition of Roger Bacon’s Opera tertium
Nordenskiold, Adolf Erik. Facsimile Atlas to the Early History of Cartography. et minus, and the Compendium philosophiae, J.S. Brewer wrote that the
Stockholm: 1889. Opus minus had attracted litde or no notice. This neglect was attribut­
Taylor, E.G.R. Tudor Geography 1485-1583. London: Methuen, 1930. able, perhaps, as he stated, “to an erroneous notion, which has long
Thorndike, Lynn. A History of Magic and Experimental Science During the First prevailed, as to its nature and contents.” It would appear that in an
Thirteen Centuries of Our Era. [& lit] Vol. 2. New York: Columbia Univer­ account of the work, a certain Dr. Jebb1 had both confused it with
sity Press, 1923.
other writings of Roger Bacon, and, in addition, had “formed an
Tibbetts, Gerald R. “The Beginnings of a Cartographic Tradition.” [& lit]
In The History of Cartography: Cartography in the Islamic and South Asian Soci­ imaginary notion of its contents.” This, it seems to me, is very often
eties, ed. J.B. Harley and David Woodward. 90-107. 2 Book 1. Chicago: the case; that is, that thirteenth-century writers have received what­
University of Chicago Press, 1992. ever shadowy reputation they might possess as the result of an “imagi­
Sister Jean Paul Tilmann, O.P. An Appraisal of the Geographical Works of Albertus
nary notion” of what they did and wrote. Not only is this the case
Magnus and His Contributions to Geographical Thought. [& lit] Michigan Geo­
graphical Publication No. 4, Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Depart­ for Roger Bacon, as Brewer pointed out over one hundred years
ment of Geography, 1971. ago, but it had been the case as well, until fairly recently, for the
Woodward, David. “Medieval Mappaemundi.” [& lit] In History of Cartogra­ theologian-natural philosopher, Robert Grosseteste, who both pre­
phy: Cartography in Prehistoric, Ancient, and Medieval Europe and the Mediterranean, ceded and influenced Bacon.
ed. J.B. Harley and David Woodward. 286—370. 1. Chicago: University To explore all of the theological and scientific interactions of these
o f Chicago Press, 1987.
two important thirteenth-century English academics, particularly with
---- “Roger Bacon’s Terrestrial Coordinate System.” Annals of the Associa­
tion of American Geographers 80 (1 1990): 109-22. respect to the substance and function of music within systematic intel­
Wright, John Kirtland. The Geographical Lore of the Time of the Crusades: A Study lectual activity, would exceed the limits of a short paper. Rather, the
in the History of Medieval Science and Tradition in Western Europe. [& lit] American present study will address the issue of Augustine’s influence, which
Geographical Society Research Series No. 15, ed. W.L.G. Joerg. New the two writers shared, pointing, especially, to the influence of
York: American Geographical Society, 1925.
Augustine’s treatise, De musica, specifically upon Bacon’s view of music
as a mathematical discipline. That music, as Bacon repeatedly states,
is essentially mathematical, presents an inherent problem to be rec­
onciled, since Augustine’s De musica for the most part, addresses, in
detail, the topic of accent, accentual pattern, and verse. Bacon’s rec­
onciliation of this apparent contradiction served as an introduction

1 Samuel Jebb, who died in 1772, published an edition of Bacon’s Opus maius in
1733, that omits Part VII of this work. See Fr. Roger Bacon. Opera quaedam hactenus
inedita, vol. I, ed. J.S. Brewer {Rerum Britannicarum Medii Aevi Scriptores, London, 1859
repr. Wiesbaden, 1965), ixff.
224 NANCY VAN DEUSEN ROGER BACON ON MUSIC 225

to music’s function as a quadrivial art within a coherent system of Grosseteste and Bacon were convinced that basic principles, empha­
studies, leading to the two goals of understanding basic philosophical sized by Augustine and Aristotle, could be made to harmonize and
principles, and theological effectiveness. The usefulness of learning complement one another. An indication that Bacon thought this was
was ever on Bacon’s mind. so can be found in Bacon’s writings on the subject of music as a
Roger Bacon and the theologian he admired, Robert Grosseteste, mathematical art and its function with respect to the other arts.
were profoundly influenced by Augustine, in ways that differ from Certainly Bacon had read not only Augustine’s great theological works,
their significant contemporaries, both in Paris and at Oxford.2 This such as De doctrina Christiana, De Trinitate, De civitate Dei, and De Genesi
is not so much, as has been stated, an accommodation of the new ad litteram, but he had also assimilated Augustine’s shorter works on
Aristotelian learning to what might be considered by some to be an the liberal arts, written during the earliest part of Augustine’s career,
outdated Augustinian system, but, rather, it was the discovery that namely De ordine, and De musica. Influenced, as well, by De ordine,
the newly-available—and accepted—Latin Aristotle reinforced and Grosseteste also, evidently during the earlier years of his own writing
extended the very directions Augustine had considered important, projects, wrote a treatise on the interconnections between the liberal
and that he emphasized throughout his productive life. This coales­ arts.4*As is the case for Grosseteste, it is, in some respects, crucial to
cence was due, at least partially, to the fact that both writers, Aristotle his entire perspective on what could be regarded as the natural,
and Augustine, shared a common philosophical background in count­
less subtle ways. The questions both addressed were related to the
discipline, “expounding theological truths through the potency of these sciences”
same priorities, but from different standpoints, an affinity of priority (Opus maius, 2 vols., Engl, transl. Robert Belle Burke [Philadelphia, 1928, repr. New
that both Robert Grosseteste and Roger Bacon recognized and ex­ York, 1962], I, 197), under the topic, “the praise of music.” Bacon begins: “More­
plored. The realization that Augustine’s directionality and terminol­ over, although the praise of music is now manifest in common with arithmetic,
because both take into consideration the relations that exist in numbers, yet num­
ogy, as well as principal preoccupations, were indeed reinforced by bers, as they exist in sounds, Augustine greatly praises. .. ‘What importance num­
Aristotle’s arguments—as well as granted analytical tools—informed bers have in all motions of things is more easily considered in the case of what is
uttered by the voice, and this consideration by certain graded roads presses on to
the directions Grosseteste and Bacon followed.3
the supernal paths of truth, in which wisdom joyfully discloses herself” ’ (Engl, transl.,
Opus maius, I, 198fL). Bacon, in his Opus maius, also discusses music as necessary to
theology (Engl, trans., I, 259f.). In his Opus tertium, Bacon complements and extends
2 The entries for Roger Bacon in the Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy his presentation, within the Opus maius, of the place, function, and usefulness of
(ed. Nonnan Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny, and Jan Pinborg, with Eleonore Stump music. Music is also specifically treated, especially with the focus of discrete partes,
[Cambridge, London, 1982]), give evidence for this. See especially p. 461. Robert as comparable to both litterae/fgurae and numbers, within the continuity of move­
Grosseteste provides early examples of the effort to accommodate Aristode within a ment, thus relating the discretion of number to the movement of gesture, in Bacon’s
predominandy Augustinian scheme. Communia mathematica (ed. Robert Steele, in Opera hactenus inedita Rogeri Baconi, Fasc.
3 As has been stated, these directions separated both Grosseteste and Bacon from XVI [London, 1940], 51-63). Although Bacon has been criticized for repeating
some of their contemporaries, resulting in what Richard Southern has termed Robert himself, and reincorporating what he had said before into his other works (as, for
Grosseteste’s insularity, a primary thesis in Robert Grosseteste: The Growth of an English example by A.G. Little in his introduction to the appendix following H. Rashdall’s
Mind in Medieval Europe (Oxford, 1986). It is of interest to note that both authors, edition of the Compendium studii theologiae [Aberdeen, 1911 repr. 1966, 71]), Bacon’s
Robert Grosseteste and Roger Bacon, actually quote Augustine a great deal, an presentation of music in these three treatises exemplifies medieval compositional prac­
obvious indication of Augustine’s influence. Further, Augustine’s influence on tice in general, that is, the placing together of pieces of verbal-intellectual material
Grosseteste is seen by the fact that he followed Augustine’s example in writing rela­ in order to compose a treatise. These pieces, or centones, could include the composer’s
tively short, succinct, discipline-related treatises during the earlier years of his writ­ own material as well as that of others, such as Augustine. One would identify this
ing activity. Later, with respect to larger, more comprehensive theological works, process— “an aggregate coming together”— as compilation, not composition, and
both authors, Augustine and Grosseteste, rely upon the reader to connect analogies further, would regard it as negatively derivative today. See also van Deusen, Theology
from the earlier works to the principles discussed in the later works (i.e. law, place and Music, “A Theory of Composition and its Influence,” 127-145.
and origin, figure, demonstration). For a detailed discussion of Grosseteste’s modus 4 Grosseteste, De artibus liberalibus, ed. L. Baur, Die philosophischen Werke Robert
operandi, see van Deusen, Music and Theology at the Early University: The Case of Robert Grosseteste, Bischofs von Lincoln (Muenster i. W., 1912); Die Philosophie des Robert Grosseteste
Grosseteste and Anonymous IV (Leiden, London, 1995). Bacon, on the other hand, pre­ (Muenster i. W., 1917), in which music is set forth as a ministry discipline. See van
sents circumscribed sections of discussion concerning, for example, music as a cogent Deusen, Theology and Music at the Early University, especially introduction, ix—xvi. This
mathematical discipline, within the body of his treatises. Music is both intermittently may have been written during a period of Grosseteste’s study of the liberal arts at
(with allusions to Augustine’s De musica), and extensively discussed as a mathematical the newly-organized University of Paris.
226 NANCY VAN DEUSEN ROGER BACON ON MUSIC 227

mathematical sciences, to observe what Bacon has to say on the subject a discrete section, focusing again upon a priority in Augustine’s De
of music. Bacon’s writing on this subject gives a particular insight musica. This present overview, rather than summarizing and bringing
into Augustine’s treatise De musica, as well as into sources that may to discussion all that Bacon had to say on the subject of music, forms
have influenced Augustine, particularly with respect to both the import­ an introduction to Bacon’s view of music’s importance and function.6
ance and choice of accentual schemes, as well as the examples of For both Augustine and Bacon, the essence of grammar, for
them used in that treatise. Bacon’s discussion of music also delineates example, was the variety and diversity of tones.7 This fact was evi­
the function to be carried out by the mathematical sciences, both dent to the senses, and also formed the basis of the study of gram­
separately and altogether, with respect to the understanding of theol­ mar, to be taken on authority. A study that must be completely
ogy, thus answering the important question concerning the specific received from, and taken on, authority, writes Bacon, is puerile; that
task of music within the early university curricular system. is why both grammar and its parallel mathematical discipline, num­
Both Augustine and Bacon thought that music was important since ber, are studied by children during the introductory phases of their
music was both useful and necessary, not only in understanding the education. Accordingly, grammar is appropriate to primary educa­
essential principles of other allied disciplines, but in understanding tion, since what is learned through the senses, that is, through sight
what they considered to be ultimate realities, namely, God and the and sound, can be more easily perceived. Numbers, as well, belong
human soul. This is seen in the chronology of writing projects fol­ to the initial stages of education since they can be perceived as con­
lowed by Augustine, who, as far as we know, wrote his treatise on taining certainty. Bacon writes, “Grammar furnishes children with
music during a period when he was also engaged in writing De the facts relating to speech and its properties in prosody, meter, and
immortalitate animae and De quantitate animae, two treatises on the soul rhythm, nevertheless it does so in a puerile way by means of state­
that can be viewed as framing De musica. That music was absolutely ment and not through causes or reasons. For it is the function of
necessary for the understanding of all of the arts is an underlying, as another science to give the reasons for these things, namely of that
well as overtly-expressed, point of view for Bacon. It is interesting, in science which must consider fully the nature of tones, and this alone
this regard, to observe how Bacon returns to music. Music can be is music, of which there are numerous varieties and parts.”8 Rhythm
found as a discrete section within his large-scale discussion of math­ teaches connection and relationship, and is exemplified in song; in
ematics in his encyclopedic treatment of the liberal arts in his Opus fact, cantm and accent are identical. “Therefore,” writes Bacon, “gram­
maius.5 In the Opus maim, Bacon places music within a series of topics mar depends causatively on music.”9*
including the unity of time, motion, application of mathematics to The essential rationes of grammar and logic, namely those of par­
sacred subjects, astronomy, the calendar, and number; a placement ticularity in terms of particular and diverse tones, as well as the
and function that is addressed, as well as extended, in his Opm tertium.
Further, in his Communia mathematica, Bacon again treats music within 6 A more exhaustive treatment of both the sources and influences of Bacon’s
ideas on music, as well as music’s place within thirteenth-century science is in prepa­
ration by this author.
5 See Roger Bacon, Opus maius, Engl, transl. by Robert Belle Burke, who places 7 Cf. Augustine, De ordine and De musica in Augustini opera omnia, (ed. J.-P. Migne
this treatise in the 1270’s. See also Opera hactenus inedita Fratris Rogeri Baconis, 16 fasc., [.Patrologiae cursus completus.. . series latinae, 221 vols., Paris, 1844-65], vol. 32). Both
ed. R. Steele (Oxford, 1905-1940); S.H. Thomson, “An unnoticed Treatise by Roger music and grammar use as their materials, sound; music however differs from gram­
Bacon on Time and Motion,” Isis, 27 (1937), 219-229; F. Delorme, E. Massa, Rogeri mar in that it uses a wider variety of tones, which appeal, by their diversity, to the
Baconis Moralis Philosophia (Zuerich, 1953). It is of interest that Burke, in discussing memory. See De musica, especially chapters I and II, (cols. 108Iff.).
the contents of the Opus maius, mentions its contents as comprising astronomy, optics, 8 Roger Bacon, Opus maius (Engl, transl., Burke, I, 118) under the heading, Mathematics.
theology, chronology, astrology, and the correction of the calendar, with a treatise on 9 The entire passage: For it is called “accent” since it is, as it were, song (accantus)
geography closing the work, without mentioning at all that music is also included— from accino, accinis. Hence these subjects pertain to music as Cassiodorus teaches in
indeed forms an important, if not indispensable, portion of this mathematical sec­ music, and Censorinus in his book on Accent, and so too in those on other topics.
tion. The Opus tertium forms a complement to the Opus maius (ed. J.S. Brewer, London, Authorities on music bear witness to this fact as well as do their books on that
1859, repr. 1965). It should be noted that what Bacon had to say on the subject of science. And Alpharabius agrees with them in his book on the Division of the Sci­
music was also contingent upon the nature of the treatise at hand. In other words, ences. Therefore grammar depends causatively on music (Engl, transl., 118-119).
his observations on music appear in an intellectual as well as generic context. Censorinus’ third-century summarization of accentual patterns is no longer extant.
228 NANCY VAN DEUSEN ROGER BACON ON MUSIC 229

principle of reasonable connection {copula) could be best exemplified that children learn and acquire mathematical truths better than the
in the science of music. Therefore, Bacon wrote that the end of logic, other parts of philosophy.”12
the discipline that is based upon, and exemplifies connection, depends Music, then, made simple, as well as reasonably complex, prin­
upon music as well.10 So far Augustine could have accused Roger ciples plain.13 Frequently Bacon, when actually using the concept planus,
Bacon of plagiarism, had both lived in the twentieth century. But brings up, as well, a musical allusion. Music as a topic appears repeat­
Bacon goes on to draw in Aristotle and the second book of the Physica: edly throughout his work. Since music had been established as a
“But the end of everything is its noblest part in every matter and discipline, and its role delineated many hundreds of years before Bacon
imposes necessity on what is related to it, nor have those things any wrote his Opus maius, the reader of this work could also relate, for
utility of their own which are naturally formed for the end, except example, the principles of jigurae corporales et superficial, exemplified in
when they are related to their end, as is clear in individual cases. contemporaneous music notation to Bacon’s discussion. In fact, the
And therefore, the whole utility of logic is drawn from the relation very presence—also in one’s mind—of music notational figurae, standing
of all logical arguments to arguments of this kind, and therefore since as they did for musical substance, made this point. “Spiritual and
they depend on arguments of music, necessarily logic must depend corporeal substances,” superficial and corporeal figures, surface itself,
on the power of music (which is the power of connection coupled time and motion, as well as the concept itself of “certain and plain,”
with beauty). All these facts are in accordance with the opinion of were also primary concepts for contemporaneous, thirteenth-century
Alpharabius in his book on the Sciences, and they are likewise clearly writers on music, who would have been Bacon’s peers. They can also
stated by Aristotle and Averroes, although these are not used by the be related to musical style of his time. Bacon established a cluster of
Latins.”11 Further, music exemplifies number, both in its particular­ concepts and terms for each of these subjects, as well as a summary
ity, its physicality as substance, and in its capacity to be projected by of how they could be comprehended within music. Many of the terms
the use of figure. Due, partially, to this fact, Bacon writes, mathematics used for emphasis are also used by Augustine, signaling an affinity of
is not beyond the intellectual grasp of anyone. “For the people at purpose and directionality that existed between the two authors.14*
large, and wholly illiterate, know how to draw figures and compute, Bacon, however, deliberately shows how both term and argumenta­
and sing, all of which are mathematical operations. Children begin tion have been enlarged by Aristotle’s writings on the same and related
with facts that are better known by us and that must be acquired subjects. He also incorporates contemporaneous commentaries on
first. But of this nature is mathematics, since children are first taught Aristotle into what he has to say on the subject of music and its
to sing; and in the same way they can learn the method of making relationship to both the other mathematical arts and to theology.
figures and of counting, and it would be far easier and more necessary It may be useful to follow the structure and order of Bacon’s treatise
for them to know about numbers before singing, because in the relations itself, summarizing at this point what Bacon sets forth in the opening
o f numbers in music the whole theory o f numbers is set forth by example, just chapters of the Opus maius concerning music and its relationship to
as the authors on music teach, both in ecclesiastical music and in phi­
losophy. But the theory of numbers depends on figures, since numbers 12 Opus maius, Engl, transl., I, 122-123, italics added.
relating to lines, surfaces, solids, squares, cubes, pentagons, hexagons, 13 This aspect of music as an instrument for making conceptual distinctions plain
is discussed in van Deusen, Theology and Music, chapter XI: uPlanus, cantus planus’'’
and other figures are known from lines, figures, and angles. For it
(177-187).
has been found that children learn mathematical truths better and 14 Copula is a case in point, a word that is frequently used by Augustine, in De
more quickly, as is clear in singing, and we also know by experience musica, and also with apparent emphasis in thirteenth-century writing on music.
Compare, for example, De musica with Fritz Reckow’s edition of, and index for, the
anonymous treatise on music, Der Musiktraktat des Anonymus 4, 2 vols. (Beihefte zum
10 Opus maius p. 119, an extension of the passage given above. Archiv Jim Musikwissenschafl V, Wiesbaden, 1967) as well as the discussion of common
11 Opus maius, Engl, transl., I, 119: cf. Physics, 199bl—30. The principle to which terms used with pointed musical significance in order to exemplify philosophical con­
Bacon alludes here, that of the tripartite model of incipit, middle processional phase, cepts, in van Deusen, Theology and Music', introduction, and chapter I, “Thirteenth-
with individual partes linked by necessity, and termination, is emphasized as well in Century Motion Theories and Their Musical Applications,” pp. 1-18, as well as the
the Metaphysics. index to this volume.
230 NANCY VAN DEUSEN ROGER BACON ON MUSIC 231

the mathematical sciences, in order to compare this with his chap­ What did music make plain, and what became manifest by musi­
ters on the usefulness of all of the basic principles contained within cal study? Bacon continues to point out, in much detail, the useful­
mathematics for the study of theology. First, as we have seen, it is of ness of all of the mathematical sciences for the proper understanding
interest that Bacon includes music among the mathematical disci­ of scripture and the study of theology. There are seven headings
plines, which are, as he states, absolutely necessary for understanding under which the mathematical sciences contribute indispensable capaci­
scripture, for the study of theology, and for study itself. Mathematics ties as well as specific details for the study of the Bible. These areas
as a discipline, furthermore, preserves intellectual life and institutions include: 1) celestial movements and distances, 2) places, 3) chronology
from the instability that inevitably follows from ephemeral intellec­ which relies upon an understanding of prior and posterior, beginning,
tual fashions and opinions that are constantly changing, and have points along the way or events, fruition, span, longevity—all of which
recourse to nothing except doubt expressed for what has been pre­ form the substance of chronology—and accidents, 4) figurae or litterae
viously asserted. Music is part of a two-fold mathematical system, that give physical significant form to intellectual and sound substance,
that is, numbers for themselves exclusively, and numbers within propor­ 5) number and relationships of numbers, or proportion, and 6) music.
tional relationships—the study of relationship and movement. Music, Bacon includes, in his extended discussion, many examples of how
therefore, is useful since it forms an analogical construct to two utterly each category of comprehension specifically contributes to the under­
basic factors, that is, relationship itself, and movement or gesture. standing of the biblical scriptures, making the point that the study of
This is the underlying reason for the privileging of mathematics mathematics is necessary to the study of theology. For example, a
throughout intellectual history. Josephus, for example, gives the four­ capacity for understanding movement and length contributes to a
fold division of the mathematical sciences, and this emphasis on comprehension of vastness, an abstraction. According to Ptolemy, in
mathematics is maintained throughout what is known as late antiquity the Almagest, it requires 36,000 years for a star to complete its circuit
and the early medieval period. Bacon points out that early Christian of the heavens. The earth, on the other hand, can be traversed by
writers, such as Augustine, as well as Jerome, and Cassiodorus, appear foot in three years.16
to be much more interested and devote more written discourse to With regard to place, Bacon states that the whole of scriptures is
them than to other studies. Augustine, who wrote an extended trea­ full of places. The Bible contains lengthy passages dealing with regions,
tise on music, provides a case in point. states, deserts, mountains, seas, and other places of the world, with
Ignorance, specifically, of genuine insight into number, relationship, cities, famous regions, with the conclusion that “history frequently is
movement, and the substitution of numerical figures for material reality distasteful because of the infinite number of places. Nevertheless, place
also makes the biblical scriptures inaccessible. These principles are is the basis for spiritual meaning.” Jerome, furthermore, thought that
all made clear by music. Therefore, to ignore music, is to render scrip­ one should actually visit these places for the purpose of understand­
ture itself incomprehensible. “Not a few things in the sacred books an ing scripture.17 Not only are the Biblical scriptures full of places, but
ignorance of the principles of music closes and covers up,” said Augus­ every other author of note, such as Augustine, Cassiodorus, and
tine.15 Again, according to Augustine, music “made plain,” showed, Isidore, as well as Origen, whose writing contained a multitude of
revealed, and made manifest what would otherwise be incomprehen­ places. “Do not read these names of places with disdain, or think
sible, a capacity music as a science held in common with arithmetic, Scripture is a worthless texture of many names, but be assured that
since both took into consideration the relations that exist in num­ in these are contained greater mysteries than human speech can utter,
bers. This clarity of manifestation is the principal reason for the utility or mortal ear can hear.”18 Bacon writes, “But it is the function of
of music. Finally, musical training applies to all of the acts of life.
16 Bacon, Opusmaius, Engl, transl., I, 200ff.
17 Bacon, Opusmaius, Engl, transl., I, 203f.
15 Augustine, quoted by Bacon, Opus maius, Engl, transl. I, 208; cf. De musica (PL 18 Bacon, Opusmaius, Engl, transl., I, 205, quoting Origen on the multitude and
32, cols. 1082ff.): that musical instruments, and music itself clarify matters is an diversity of places; cf. Bacon, Opus tertium, ed. Brewer, 203f.:Deinde descendo ad
underlying theme within Augustine’s entire treatise, but note especially Chapter I. radicem secundam, quae est de cognitione locorum mundi. Manifestum enim est
232 ROGER BACON ON MUSIC 233
NANCY VAN DEUSEN

astrology and astronomy to give explanations and full certitude with matters specifically pertaining to music itself.” It is not, as he states,
regard to the places in the world. . . . But he who knows the lengths, necessary for an understanding of scripture that the theologian actu­
breadths, depths, heights, variety of qualities, as heat, cold, dryness, ally be able to sing, that is, have a practical knowledge of singing,
humidity, and of those following these four, softness, hardness, thick­ and of instruments, and of other specific musical matters, yet he should
ness, thinness, harshness, smoothness, aridity, fluidity, slipperiness, and be able to grasp its “nature and properties,” as well as understanding
innumerable other qualities which are defined in the fourth book of writings specifically on this subject. This acquaintance with musical
the Meteorologies. Moreover, colors, savors, odors, beauties, ugliness, material and a comprehension of its nature was useful for understand­
pleasantness, sterility, fertility, matter infected, corruptible, and their ing the large vocabulary of musical terms in scripture, such as rejoice,
opposites, and others which have to be considered in their place— shout for joy, sing, play upon the cithara, cymbals, and many other
he who knows all these can understand clearly the literal sense and instruments. Further, there are “many kinds of meters contained in
delight himself in it, and can pass to the spiritual meanings in a the sacred Hebrew text, of which the writers in their expositions
calm and glorious manner. For by considering a few facts relating to take note in many ways. But it belongs to music to give the under­
the places named, we can express important meanings in a moral, lying reasons for these although grammarians teach the practical rules
allegorical, and analogical sense.”19 regarding them.” What follows gives ample evidence for the fact that
With respect to the usefulness of geometry for the study of figures, Bacon had read Augustine’s De rnusica, Bacon writes:
Bacon writes: “Oh, how the ineffable beauty of divine wisdom would Moreover, the whole pronunciation o f Scripture consists in accents,
shine and infinite benefit would overflow, if those matters related to longs, shorts, colons, commas, and periods: and all these belong caus­
geometry, which are contained in scripture should be placed before ally to music, because of all these matters the musician states the reason,
our eyes in physical forms,” and, further, “For the sake of all things but the grammarian merely the fact. For so the authors of philosophy
decide, also Augustine so decides regarding them in dealing with music.
in general. . . nothing can be known concerning the things of this
For one part of music deals with what is audible, the other with what
world without the power of geometry . . . because we can understand
is visible, as authorities decide.
nothing fully unless its form is presented before our eyes; and there­
fore in the Scripture of God, the whole knowledge of things to be Bacon goes on to deal with the audible, that is, the human voice
defined by geometrical forms is contained and far better than mere compared to musical instruments, melody, as in singing, meter, and
philosophy could express it.”20 Numbers, according to Bacon, are all the “nature and properties of all songs”, meters, feet, “rhythm,
always to be taken literally, that is in the literal sense, according to and varieties of relations in rhythms, as well as accents within verse,”
all their arithmetical properties, “to the end that through fitting simili­ with Censorinus as his authority for that subject. Accent (accino, accinis)
tudes the spiritual meaning may be elicited.”21 derives from “to sing,” since “every syllable has its own proper sound
Finally, with respect to music’s distinctive usefulness in accessing either raised, lowered, or composite, and all syllables of one word
the scriptures, Bacon writes that music is necessary “for the under­ are adapted or sung to one syllable on which rests the principal sound.
standing of the nature and properties of these matters, as well as Thus length and shortness and all other things required in correct
pronunciation are reduced to m usic.. . . Music, moreover, consisting
in what is visible, is necessary.”22
quod totus textus decurrit super haec loca, et per haec loca corporalia significantur
loca spiritualia, et per vias ad ea viae spirituales. . . . Et etiam res locatae non possunt Bacon’s short synopsis of the uses one might put to music skims
cognosci nisi per loca; quia complexiones earum accidunt per complexiones locorum. off several of the most general subjects of Augustine’s De rnusica, as
Cf. as well, Robert Grosseteste, Prooemium to the Hexaemeron, (ed. Richard C. Dales Bacon himself states. One of the most important of these is the fact
and Servus Gieben, OFM. Cap., London, 1982), 17-48, who fills his prologue with
a diversity of places, the etymologies of their designations, and their importance.
19 Bacon, Opus maius, Engl, transl., I, 205f. The entire passage has been quoted
to give indication of Bacon’s style. 22 Bacon, Opus maius, I, 259f. Cf. Augustine, De rnusica (PL 32, cols. 1082f.): open­
20 Bacon, Opus maius, Engl, transl., pp. 233f. ing remarks of treatise: Sonorum certas dimensiones obseruare non ad grammaticam spectat, sed
21 Bacon, Opus maius, Engl, transl., p. 242. ad musicam.
234 NANCY VAN DEUSEN ROGER BACON ON MUSIC 235

that music and grammar have sound in common, yet music searches of the substance of chronology, that is, time-concepts of prior and
out the rationality of, and sense experience within, sound, whereas, posterior, beginning, and event, as well as the accidents of chronology.
grammar is purely descriptive, and, accordingly, must be learned by Music by its very nature demonstrates movement in time, how time
rote. Augustine’s extensive classification and elucidation of the varieties changed, and how one could tell that it had changed because of its
of metrical feet do, in fact, as Bacon states, give evidence for rela­ mutated characteristics. In other words, the abstractions, “prior” and
tionship itself, and for the nature of motion. Augustine had reduced “posterior” became utterly plain, even to a child, by means of music.
meters, feet, and “matters of this kind to the subject of music.” Having Further, by means of visual aspects, the jigurae of music notation,
observed this, Bacon writes of the visible, that is, of instruments and music made clear the capacity of figures themselves to physically
their constructs, with which one might achieve some acquaintance, present meaning. Finally, music exemplified number and proportion.
so that the theologian might be able to know “how use has to be We have seen how Bacon, in each case, initiates his choice of
made of them on account of their numberless mystical meanings topic related to music by, right from the start, presenting a theme
besides their literal ones.” As we have observed, what is visible, how­ Augustine, in his De musica, also emphasizes. This is also true of his
ever, is Bacon’s priority, as he states, “Music, moreover, consisting later work, the Communia mathematica. The science that deals with
in what is visible, is necessary, and that it is such is evident from the transient, that is, non-permanent, discrete quantity is the science of
book on the Origins of the Sciences. For whatever can be conformed music, writes Bacon. These discrete parts—since music constantly
to sound in similar movements and in corresponding formations, so changes—or each part, i.e. vox, is, however, to be found within move­
that our delight may be made complete not only by hearing, but ment or passiones, a subject, that, accordingly to Bacon, had been
by seeing, belongs to music. Therefore dances and all bendings of misunderstood by many. The alliance, or conformity, of “passing,
bodies are reduced to gesture, which is a branch of music, since these discrete, quantifiable part” to connected motion composed of con­
are conformed to sound in similar movements and corresponding nected parts, presents a unified quality of connected, formated, charac­
formations, as the author of the aforesaid book maintains. Therefore teristic motion, or gesture. Gesture, then, is the “root” of music itself—
Aristotle says in the seventh book of the Metaphysics that the art of the actual place where music can be found.24 As the culmination of
dancing is not complete without another art, that is, without another what Bacon has to say concerning music, this passage—indeed the
kind of music to which the art of dancing is conformed.”23 entire portion of the treatise—exemplifies his overall treatment of
Bacon succeeds, in these short, succinct paragraphs, in bringing music. The observation that the very substance of music was related
together, without particularly calling attention to the fact, Augustine’s
De musica with Aristotle’s Metaphysica. But there is another reason why
his section on music is so short, particularly compared to the other 24 Bacon, Communia mathematica, ed. R. Steele, 51: Sciencia vero de quantitate
sections that seem, by comparison, to be full of details. Music, as he discreta non-permanente est Musica, et hec communiter sumpta ad speculativam et
practicam habet considerare quantitatis discrete non-permanentis partes et passiones
has taken care to state in more than one context, discloses basic et causas et opera et instrumenta et omnia que circa hanc habent term inari.. . .
principles themselves, that is, the natures and properties of the quint­ Sicut igitur in divisione partium quantitatis dictum est et expositum sonus, ut vox et
essential aspects that cause the other mathematical sciences to differ alii soni sunt quantitates discrete non-permanentes, sed Musica est de hujusmodi
speciebus principaliter et secundario de quibusdam aliis que sono possunt conformari
from each other, both in their approaches and in the information motibus consimilibus et figuracionibus competentibus ut omnia vadant simul in unam
they make manifest. Music by its very nature and properties makes declaracionem completam sicut in unum finem cujusmodi sunt non omnes motus
clear the principle of movement and length, necessary for discussion sed quidam determinati, ut gestus et exultacio et omnes flexus corporum et partium
eius. Et hoc determinatur in libro De O rtu Scienciarum in quo dicitur quod gestus
of what he names “celestial things,” places and surface, the components est una radix Musice, quoniam potest conformari sono motibus consimilibus et
configuracionibus competentibus, hujusmodi enim motus vadunt in unum finem cum
sono, scilicet in delectacionem completam, et habent easdem proporciones, et
23 Bacon, Opus maius, Engl, transl., I, 260, an extension of the quotation given configurantur et conformantur ei, quod patet per experienciam, quoniam tunc sonus
above. Bacon refers to Robert Kilwardby’s De ortu scimtiamm; cf. discussion of Bacon’s vocis humane vel cithare vel alterius instrument! quantum decet delectat quando
Communia mathematica below. gestus et exultaciones et flexus corporum proporcionales simul perficiuntur.
236 ROGER BACON ON MUSIC 237
NANCY VAN DEUSEN

to gesture, is Augustine’s observation.25 That movement may be in­ Bacon cites his contemporary Robert Kilwardby’s De ortu scientiarum
finitely divided, for purposes of measurement, into discrete, quantifi­ and Aristotle’s Metaphysics within the context of his discussion of music
able, segments is a topic taken up and elaborated upon in Aristotle’s and gesture,28 but the entire passage again brings together Augustine
Physics,26 Further, Bacon, in the passage that immediately follows, with Aristode in a reciprocal relationship, demonstrating how the
suggests that delectability received through the aural faculty—again topics selected as primary by Augustine are in fact reinforced by a
a preoccupation of Augustine—is enhanced by the combination of reading of Aristode. The two authors, together, had been able to
visible bodily movement with what is heard in terms of music given grasp the essence of music’s character and power. Bacon could have
forth by the voice or by an instrument, such as a stringed instru­ gone on to show by careful example, relating specific musical instance
ment. Music combines visible motion with sound.27 to each of his subjects, how all of this was indeed the case. This,
however, was not Bacon’s priority, and a treatment of that kind would
have, no doubt, been inconceivable to him, since the purpose of his
25 This is true, but not always with positive effect; see Augustine, De musica, Chapter treatise was to set forth the properties all of the mathematical sci­
II {PL 32, col. 1083) under the topic: Musica quid sit, modulari quid sit: Musica est
scientia bene m odulandi. . . sed quia video modulari a modo esse dictum, cum in ences had in common, or how they, as basically related, differed
omnibus bene factis modus servandus sit, et multa etiam in canendo ac saltando from one another.29 Specific musical examples of discrete “sound
quamvis delectent, vilissima sint; volo plenissime accipere quid prorsus sit ipsa
modulatio, quo uno pene verbo tantae disciplinae definitio continetur.
26 Continuous motion is divisible; see Aristotle, Physics, 200b 13; 17. This concept
of the divisibility of motion into discrete, measureable increments was also exten­ makes between number and sense perception is also made by Augustine. See also
sively discussed by Robert Grosseteste, both in his early treatise on the liberal arts, Augustine, De ordine {PL 32, col. 1010): Quod vero ad aures, quando rationabilem
and within his commentaries on both the Physics and the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle, concentum dicimus, cantumque numerosum rationabiliter esse compositum; suavitas
for example: Proportiones vero motuum secundum duplicem motus divisibilitatem vocatur proprio jam nomine. Sed neque in pulchris rebus cum nos color illicit,
considerantur. Est enim motus divisibilis divisibilitate temporis et secundum hanc neque in aurium suavitate cum pulsa chorda quasi liquide sonat atque pure, rationabile
divisibilitatem dicitur motus duplus ad alium . . . {De artibus liberalibus, ed. Baur, 2). illud dicere solemus. Restat ergo ut in istorum sensuum voluptate id ad rationem
Since, as far as we know, this treatise on the provinces of, and interactions between, pertinere fateamur, ubi quaedam dimensio est atque modulatio.
the liberal arts was written during the early years of Grosseteste’s academic career, 28 Bacon was, no doubt, referring to Metaphysics 1016al: The things, then, that are
and the commentary on the Posterior Analytics well on in his writing activity, the called one by accident, are called so in this way. (2) of things that are called on in
topic, obviously an important one within Aristotle’s Physics, occupied him for many virtue of their own nature some (a) are so called because they are continuous, e.g.
years. Bacon’s discussion of the topic, as well, as far as we know, occurs in his a bundle is made one by a band, and pieces of wood are made one by glue; and
mature work, that is, the Communia mathematica, a section on music that was, presum­ a line, even if it is bent, is called one if it is continuous, as each part of the body
ably, his final discussion at length of the discipline of music. For a discussion of the is, e.g. the leg or the arm. O f these themselves, the continuous by nature are more
impact of this concept on writing concerning music, see “Thirteenth-Century Motion one than the continuous by art. A thing is called continuous which has by its own
Theories” in van Deusen, Theology and Music, especially 6ff. nature one movement and cannot have any other, and the movement is one when
27 Bacon, Communia mathematica, ed. R. Steele, 52 (the complete passage included it is indivisible, and indivisible in time. Those things are continuous by their own
for context): Propter quod dicit Aristotiles septimo Methaphysice quod ars saltandi nature which are one not merely by contact; for if you put pieces of wood touching
non vadit in finem unum sine alia arte, nec alia ars sine ilia, quoniam ars sonandi one another, you will not say these are one piece of wood or one body or one
in debitis armoniis cantus et consonanciarum et in instrumentis, et ars saltandi, id continuum of any other sort. Things, then, that are continuous in any way are called
est, faciendi gestus et exultaciones et omnesJlexus corporum quando conjunguntur simul tunc vadunt one, even if they admit of being bent, and still more those which cannot be bent,
in finem mum qui est completa delectado duorum sensuum, scilicet visus et auditus, et quando e.g. the shin or the thigh is more one than the leg because the movement of the leg
separantur tunc est delectacio incompleta et neuter vadit in suum finem ut oportet; need not be one. And the straight line is more one than the bent; but that which
propter quod subjectum Musice non est solum sonus, licet sit principale subjectum, is bent and has an angle we call both one and not one, because its movement may
ymmo Musica considerabit omnia ilia que possunt similibus proporcionibus conformari be either simultaneous or not simultaneous; but that of the straight line is always
sono et vadunt in finem unum completum, et non versatur circa aha visibilia nec simultaneous, and no part of it which has magnitude rests while another moves, as
tangibilia nec quecumque aha. Unde motus pulsus qui obiiciuntur tactui, hcet habeant in the bent line (revised Oxford English translation, ed. Jonathan Barnes, 2 vols.
discrecionem quandam ut motus gestus et easdem proporciones que sunt in sono et [.Bollingen Series LXXI. 2, Princeton, New Jersey, 1984]), II, 1604.
gestibus ut medici determinant, tamen quia non possunt sono et gestui conformari 29 Bacon mentions this several times, for example: Musica sicut tota Mathema­
ut faciant delectacionem unam completam non cadunt sub consideracione Musice, tica, et ideo proporciones et armonie que hie debent esse sunt omnino aliene a
et similiter multi motus visibiles alii a gestibus faciunt secundum proporciones quas proprietatibus (aliter proporcionibus) quantitatis et Mathematice. Preterea ex predictis
habent gestus et soni, sed non proporcionantur eis in unum finem, et ideo de eis constat Musicam considerare quantitatem discretam non-permanentem, sed hujusmodi
musicus non curat. The concept of delectability—sensuous dehciousness—and expres­ proporciones et armonie que sunt in elementis et inter corpus et animam et in
sions such as suavitas, ducti bene canunt, delectari, etiam in canendo ac saltando quamvis delectentis partibus anime sunt permanentes et in rebus permanentibus et ideo nichil faciunt
frequently occur throughout Augustine’s De musica. The specific connection Bacon ad Musicam (ed. Steele, 53).
238 NANCY VAN DEUSEN ROGER BACON ON MUSIC 239

portion” or tone within motion would have required an additional, If Bacon did not appeal to his own intellectual environment of the
detailed treatise, De musica, or Musica disciplina—the sort of specific mid- to late thirteenth century—an aversion to both his writing style
treatise he actually did write in the area of optics. Bacon, it seems, and the ideas he expressed that recurred in the mid- to late nine­
was primarily interested in what could be discerned and observed teenth century—perhaps he can be more spontaneously appreciated
with the eyes.30 today, concerned as he is with usefulness, with effective education,
Bacon, it would appear, desired to communicate well what he had and, finally, with the uses of diversity. The diversity and variety of
learned, and to influence his contemporary intellectual environment, the physical world with its diversities and varieties of figures, bound­
that was, Bacon thought, composed of human beings who felt they aries, races, rivers, and phenomena, tantalized and absorbed him,
had, generally speaking, learned quite enough as it was.31 He wanted apparently, for his entire life. Music, as the science of diverse and
to interact with the intellectual culture of his own day, and also desired varied tones, demonstrated by its very nature the concept of diver­
to convince students of the usefulness, not only of the liberal arts, sity and variety itself. Music, as a science that engaged both the eyes
and especially of music, but also of philosophy-theology. So far as and the ears, for Bacon, showed the way to a deeper, more pro­
we are able to tell, he did not achieve that goal, either for his own found, understanding of these utterly basic principles.
generation, or subsequently. T.S. Brewer, in his preface to the 1859 Further, Bacon shows a genuine hunger for rapprochement between
edition of Roger Bacon’s Opus minus and the Compendium philosophise, the physical world and the word, between observable physical phe­
stated that the Opus minus— as well as most of Bacon’s other works— nomena and the communication of these phenomena. A given lan­
attracted very little notice, a state of affairs of which Bacon himself guage, with its idiomatic expressions is autonomous; if science were
complained. This neglect was attributable, Brewer thought, to erro­ also autonomous, there would be no problem, nor necessity to trans­
neous notions of its contents. It seems that an “imaginary notion” late its internal principles into another, verbal language.33
had been formed of both Bacon, the writer, and what he, in fact, Certainly this is another principle that, so far as Bacon is con­
had written.32 cerned, cannot be adequately understood without music, since it is
an inquiry that comes directiy under the category of matter. Music
30 Bacon’s obvious special interest in sight contrasts with that of Robert Grosseteste, is composed of substance with its own physical properties, namely,
who was especially interested in sound. those of sound. A portion, obviously, of the physical world, it is a
31 See Burke’s preface to his English translation of Bacon’s Opus maius.
32 Preface to Brewer’s edition, xiv-xix. Brewer further notes that “theology and substance onto itself. One has transformed it and mutated it, actu­
philosophy languished, partly from the superior rewards and attractions of the law, ally beyond recognition, when one describes music with words. The
and partly from the prejudices of the age. Indifference to science on the part of the question for Bacon is, can one actually translate musical—or scientific
vulgar assumed the shape of fixed contempt and hostility to the learned.” Bacon
ignored, or opposed, the “vulgar,” to whom he frequently refers. It is interesting to
compare Brewer’s view of Bacon’s life, as well as his assessment of the reasons for
what he considers to be the neglect of his works, with other biographies and assess­ 33 The idiomatic has its own properties, that is, a “vocabulary” is constructed
ments, such as those contained in the preface to Burke’s English translation of the from language. Latin is idiomatic in that it retains its own substance, varied accord­
Opus maius, the assessment of Allan B. Wolter, OFM, in his article on Bacon in The ing to diverse idiomata that are distinct from every other linguistic substance. Just so,
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (4 vols. ed. Paul Edwards [New York, London, 1967], I, the sciences have their own language, and conventional Latin vocabulary is not
240-242); and the short biographical summary contained in the Cambridge History of sufficient to express these terms. (Quarta causa potest esse quod vocabula infinita
Later Medical Philosophy (884-885). Brewer thought that Bacon had been neglected ponuntur in textibus theologiae et philosophiae, de alienis linguis, quae non possunt
because his colleagues were envious, and, citing Matthew Paris, his family royalist scribi, nec proferri, nec intelhgi, nisi per eos qui linguas sciunt. Et necesse fuit hoc
by persuasion, Wolter because of his irrascibility. Sten Ebbesen, in his chapter entitled, fieri propter hoc, quod scientiae fuerunt compositae in lingua propria, et translatores
The Source of Medieval Scholastic Logic,” in the Cambridge History of Later Medieval non invenerunt in lingua Latina vocabula sufficientia, cf. Opus tertium, ed. Brewer,
Philosophy, designates Bacon as idiosyncratic, who “did dig up Augustine’s Dialectica 90.) Bacon is not only advocating learning languages, but also pointing out the
and found something useful for his own inspiration” {CHIMP, 122). Further, the problem of expressing a given science by the use of language at all. The writer goes
period of Bacon’s imprisonment is placed by various writers as early as the late on to say that not only does one have to know both languages, i.e. the language
1250’s or soon before his death in 1292, and several different reasons for this incar­ from which one translating, as well as the language into which one is making the
ceration are given. In short, a thorough appraisal of Bacon, his work, and influence, translation, but one must also be intimately acquainted with the subject matter itself,
would be welcome. since all three have their own autonomous germane properties.
ROGER BACON ON MUSIC 241
240 NANCY VAN DEUSEN

substance into words? The answer is no, but music itself can make recurring finality to Bacon’s acknowledgment of this fact in all three
principles themselves manifest. Further, the physical world must some­ of Bacon’s extended treatments of music within the Opus maius, the
how be brought into a framework of language. Questions follow: Opus tertium, and the Communia mathematica. Music, by its physicality,
what is the role of language for scientific investigation? How does its comprehensibility, its delectability, and even its non permanence,
language accomplish what it can accomplish? What are, in fact, the was supremely capable of providing, in a proportional relationship,
differences between physical substances and the language that describes analogies to the profoundest mysteries of motion within time, motion
them? What does it mean that a science is composed within its own and time designated by word, and substance itself. For Bacon, with­
proper language, with the implication that it cannot go outside of its out music all things remained obscured.
own language (since there may be, literally, no words to use)? Finally,
Bacon observes that the non-negotiable qualities of language—there­
fore, in some respects the most important—are related to scientific
language, not to everyday common expressions.34 And yet, words are
powerful. Through language we gain “profound cognition, great
desire, just intent and the strength of confidence” writes Bacon.35
The work of the mind is done with words, and in words the mind
also delights. The problem of uniting and relating non-verbal physi­
cal phenomena with adequate words to describe and express them is
to be taken seriously.
In this, as in all other difficult matters, music makes plain what
would otherwise remain incomprehensible.36 There is an underlying,

34 See Bacon, Opus tertium, ed. Brewer, pp. 90-96. Bacon himself was not able to
answer, even to his own satisfaction, all of the questions he raised. More than once
he comments on the great difficulty to actually learn anything at all, since only with
great effort can one break the confines of recognizing and understanding only what
one already knows. In a sense, each person is locked into, and limited by the per­
sonal and intellectual language spoken and understood. Again, in a sense, each one
is, therefore, as is the case with each one of the sciences, onto oneself in a non-
negotiable and non-communicable isolation.
35 Bacon, Opus tertium, ed. Brewer, p. 96: Sed considerare debemus quod verba
habent maximam potestatem; et omnia miracula facta a principio mundi fere facta
sunt per verba. Et opus animae rationalis praecipuum est verbum, et in quo maxime
delectatur. Et ideo cum verba proferuntur profunda cogitatione et magno desiderio,
et recta intentione, et cum forti confidentia, habent magnam virtutem. Nam cum
haec quatuor contingunt excitatur substantia animae rationalis fortius ad faciendum
suam speciem et virtutem a se in corpus suum et res extra, et in opera sua, et
maxime in verba, quae ab intrinsecus formantur; et ideo plus de virtute animae
recipiunt.
36 There is scriptural precedent for this certitude, cf. Psalm 49, 1-4: Hear this,
all ye people; give ear, all ye inhabitants of the world: Both low and high, rich
and poor, together. My mouth shall speak of wisdom; and the meditation of my parabolam aurem meam; Aperiam in psalterio propositionem meam. All three trans­
heart shall be of understanding. I will incline mine ear to a parable: I will open my lations present the concept of obscurity “opened” by a musical instrument, with the
dark saying upon the harp (King James version), cf. Psalm 48 in the Vulgate ver­ implication that an instrument forms order in sound material. Cf. Bacon, Opus tertium,
sions: . . . Os meum loquetur sapientiam, Et meditatio cordis mei intellegentiam. ed. Brewer, 228: Post hoc tetigi utilitatem musicae in Scriptura; et sancti non possunt
Inclinabo in proverbium aurem meam, Pandam ad sonum lyrae aenigma m eum / satiari de laude musicae respectu theologiae et Scripturae Sacrae intelligendae .. .
Os meum loquetur sapientiam. Et meditatio cordis mei prudentiam. Inclinabo in (p. 233), cf. 232ff.
11. ROGER BACON ON LIGHT, VISION, AND THE
UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORCE

David C. Lindberg

Introduction

Light was one of the most important entities in the medieval cosmos,
and Roger Bacon was its most accomplished medieval student. Bacon
was well-read and well-informed on all of the new sciences presented
to Western Europeans through the translations of the twelfth and
thirteenth centuries. But the one that he knew best and that occu­
pied the most space in the writings of his mature years was the sci­
ence of light and vision—known to him and his contemporaries as
perspectiua or scientia de aspectibus. However, Bacon did not conceive
light merely as the instrument of vision; he regarded it also as the
key to an understanding of the inner workings of nature, a privileged
(because of its visibility) case of universal causal agency and, conse­
quently, an opportunity for the most intimate inspection of natural
causes at work. Bacon referred to the generic causal agent of which
light was a visible instance as species (or likeness). This chapter will
deal with light in ail of its manifestations—the propagation, reflec­
tion, and refraction of visible light; its participation in the act of
sight; and the causal role of species in nature.
What were the sources of Bacon’s knowledge? Although Bacon
had European predecessors in the investigation of light— Robert
Grosseteste (ca. 1168-1253) was undoubtedly the most important—
Bacon was the first to master the full corpus of translated Greek and
Arabic works on the subject. In the first place, he was well acquainted
(as any European scholar must be) with Plato’s Timaeus and its dis­
cussion of light and vision. He was thoroughly familiar with the
mathematical analysis of light and vision in Euclid’s Optica and
Catoptrica, translated as De visu (or De aspectibus) and De speculis, respec­
tively. He knew Ptolemy’s Optica {De aspectibus in its Latin version)
and Alkindi’s De aspectibus, both of which went well beyond the mathe­
matics of light and vision but which, nonetheless, were frequently
perceived as demonstration pieces of the mathematical program. He
244 DAVID G. LINDBERG LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORGE 245

possessed a thorough mastery of the Aristotelian corpus, including all The Multiplication of Species
of the books touching upon light and vision—most notably De anima
and De sensu, where Aristotle offered a detailed physical account of Bacon’s theory of the multiplication of species had Neoplatonic roots.3
light and the act of vision, but also the Meteorologica and works on One of the Neoplatonic authors who exercised a crucial influence on
animals. He had studied the anatomical and physiological analysis of the direction of Bacon’s thought was Alkindi (d. ca. 866). Developing
vision by Galen (as embodied in the De oculis that circulated under ideas that had originated with Plotinus (d. 270), Alkindi argued (if
the name of its translator, Constantine the African) and Averroes. we assume, as Bacon did, that his De aspectibus and De radiis are to be
He was the first western European to master the great De aspectibus read together) that “rays” emanate in all directions from every point
of Alhacen,1 where the various strands of thought on light and vision— (or small part) of everything in the cosmos, conveying the powers of
mathematical, physical, and medical—were thoroughly and brilliantly things to surrounding objects. As a result of this radiation, “every
integrated. And he developed his doctrine of the multiplication of place in the world contains rays from everything that has actual
species out of the emanationist metaphysics of Alkindi’s De radiis, existence”;4 everything acts on everything else, and the cosmos becomes
Avicebron’s Fons vitae, Avicenna’s Physics and Metaphysics, and the Liber an intricate network of forces responsible for everything from the
de causis.2 radiation of heat to astrological influence and the efficacy of prayer.
Finally, Bacon drew on a modest literature concerning light and These ideas were elaborated by the Spanish Jew Avicebron (d. ca.
vision indigenous to the Latin world. He had full command of the 1058), to whose works Bacon also had access. Avicebron describes
encyclopedic tradition of Rome and the early Middle Ages, which the emanation or procession of all things from the divine being, the
occasionally touched on phenomena of light and vision. He was influ­ “First Maker,” as a dispensing “of the abundance that he has within
enced by Augustine’s treatment of these subjects in his Literal Commentary himself,” and argues that in this regard all created things are obliged
on Genesis. The works of pseudo-Dionysius, with their metaphysics to imitate the First Maker. “Therefore, all substances must imitate
and theology of light, could hardly have escaped his notice. And he his action and follow him in imparting their forms and sharing their
drew both inspiration and content from the works of Grosseteste, a forces as long as they find suitable recipient matter.”5*Avicebron makes
distinguished Oxford scholar from the previous generation, for whom clear that what is emanated is a force (vis), ray (radius), or likeness
Bacon had deep admiration. (species) of its source.
Through his mastery and use of these sources, Bacon became a The background of Christian European thought on the subject is,
key transitional figure in the history of the science of perspectioa and of course, richer and more complicated than this brief account would
one of the leading Western authors of the doctrine of the multiplica­ suggest; but these are the essential theoretical pieces. One of the first
tion of species. It was Bacon, more than any other author in the in Latin Christendom to reveal their influence was the distinguished
Latin world, who taught Europeans how to think about light, vision, Oxford scholar and churchman Robert Grosseteste (ca. 1168—1253).
and the emanation of force. Grosseteste’s writings touch only briefly on the universal emanation
of force (what he called “universal action”), but his ideas powerfully
influenced Bacon and are therefore important to us. In his De lineis,
angulis, et fguris Grosseteste argues that every natural agent

1 It is high time historians of medieval science ceased to employ the erroneous 3 A full analysis is found in David C. Lindberg, Roger Bacon’s Philosophy of Nature: A
spelling “Alhazen” (invented in the sixteenth century). The universal spelling in Critical Edition, with English Translation, Introduction, and Notes, of “De multiplicatione specierum”
medieval Latin manuscripts was “Alhacen” or (less commonly) “Alhaycen,” “Alacen,” and “De speculis comburentibus” (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), pp. xxxv-liii.
or “Alphacen”—all of them transliterations of the Arabic “al-Hasan.” 4 M.-Th. d’Alvemy and F. Hudry, “Al-Kindi, De radiis,” Archives d’histoire doctrinale
2 For a fuller account of Bacon’s sources, see the introduction to David C. Lindberg, et litteraire du moyen age, 41 (1974), 224.
Roger Bacon and the Origins of Perspectiva in the Middle Ages (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 5 Avicebron, Fons vitae, III. 13, ed. Clemens Baeumker (Beitrage gur Geschichte der
1996). Phihsophie des Mittelalters, 1, pts. 2-4) (Munster: Aschendorff, 1895), p. 107.
246 DAVID C. LINDBERG LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORCE 247

multiplies its power from itself to the recipient, whether it acts on sense Bacon develops this theme in the first chapter of De multiplicatione
or on matter. This power is sometimes called “species,” sometimes a
specierum, commenting on the various synonyms of “species” employed
“likeness,” and it is the same thing whatever it may be called.. . . But
the effects are diversified by the diversity of the recipient, for when this in different contexts. As for his own definition, a species
power is received by the senses, it produces an effect that is somehow
is the first effect of an agent; for all judge that through species [all]
spiritual and noble; on the other hand, when it is received by matter,
other effects are produced. Thus the wise and the foolish disagree about
it produces a material effect. Thus the sun produces different effects in
many things in their knowledge of species, but they agree in this, that
different recipients by the same power, for it cakes mud and melts ice.6
the agent sends forth a species into the matter o f the recipient, so that,
If this were all Grosseteste had to say on the subject, he would have through the species first produced, it can bring forth out of the poten­
tiality of the matter [of the recipient] the complete effect that it intends.8
made only the relatively restricted claim that radiation issues from
everything and produces effects in recipients— a claim to which many That the species is a likeness of the agent from which it emanates is
European natural philosophers would have assented. But he appears apparent from the fact that agents always endeavor to make the
to go further, arguing that if the natural philosopher masters the recipients of their influence like themselves; clearly this can occur
geometrical rules governing the propagation of rays (the laws of reflec­ only if the species, the first effect of an agent and the intermediary
tion, refraction, and rectilinear propagation), he can “in this manner between it and the recipient, resembles the agent that produced it.
specify the causes of all natural effects. And he can do this in no Thus fire sends forth a species that ignites flammable bodies in its
other way, . . . since every natural action is varied in strength and vicinity—an impossibility if the species did not bear the specific nature
weakness according to variation of lines, angles, and figures.”7 It seems of fire.
to follow that all physical causation is reducible to the radiation of If, as Bacon believes, all agents send forth species, it remains to
force, governed by geometrical rules. inquire what kinds of things can be agents. One way of finding an
Bacon’s theory of the multiplication of species, developed at length answer to this question is to examine the “sensibles”—things that can
in his De multiplicatione specierum, was an attempt to articulate fully the be perceived by the senses—since Bacon held species to be the uni­
ideas of his predecessors on the radiation of force and to work out versal intermediaries between sensibles and the sense organs. But the
all of the implications of their theory. Whereas many of his prede­ case is complicated by a distinction between different kinds of sensi­
cessors had devoted but a few paragraphs or a few pages to the bles. The nine “proper sensibles” are the primary objects of the various
subject, Bacon made it the subject of a 40,000-word treatise. senses—light and color for sight, sound for hearing, flavor for taste,
It may be well to begin our analysis of Bacon’s achievement with odor for smell, and the tangible qualities (hot, cold, wet, and dry) for
a few words about the crucial term “species.” The original meaning touch. These, Bacon argues, are indeed agents from which species
of this term was simply “aspect” or “form.” Augustine employed it emanate.9 But there are also twenty “common sensibles,” so-called
to designate the incorporeal likeness or image of a thing in the senses because they are common to several of the senses. These Bacon
and the intellect, by which it is perceived—usage retained through­ identifies as remoteness, position, corporeity, shape, size, continuity,
out the Middle Ages in theories of perception. Finally, with Grosseteste distinction or separation, number, motion, rest, roughness, smooth­
and Bacon it acquired the broader meaning of physical or corporeal ness, transparency, density, shadow, darkness, beauty, ugliness, as well
likeness of an object, responsible (to be sure) for perception, but also as similarity and difference in all of the foregoing. In addition, there
conceived as the force or power or influence by which objects act on are sensibles that are subordinate to these twenty: thus curvature
other objects—in short, a name given to Alkindi’s universal force. falls under shape, and paucity under number. The common sensibles

6 Quoted, with slight modifications, from Edward Grant, ed., A Source Book in 8 De multiplicatione specierum, 1.1, lines 75-80, in Lindberg, Bacon's Philosophy of Na­
Medieval Science (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1974), pp. 385-6. ture, p. 6.
7 De natura locorum, in Die philosophischen Werke des Robert Grosseteste, ed. Ludwig Baur 9 But sound is a special case, requiring lengthy analysis. O n sound, see De
(.Beitrage z.ur Geschichte der Philosophic des Mittelalters, 9) (Munster: Aschendorff, 1912), multiplicatione specierum, 1.2, pp. 21-3; Perspectiva, 1.8.2, in Lindberg, Bacon and the Origins
pp. 65-6.
of Perspectiva.
248 DAVID C. LINDBERG LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORGE 249

and the sensibles subordinate to them, Bacon insists, do not send forth a suitable medium to a recipient, as some of the terminology employed
species, but are perceived through the species of the proper sensibles, above might suggest? (2) Are they impressions made in the recipient?
augmented by a process of ratiocination.10 Both of these theories had ancient antecedents and, if they were not
But there are other approaches to the question of agency and the to be accepted, needed to be refuted. (3) Are species created ex nihilo
sources of species. Both substance and accident send forth species. by their agents? (4) Do agents acquire species from outside them­
So do matter and form; Bacon thus denies that only form is active. selves and dispatch them to recipients?14 Finally, are there further
Universal and singulars both produce species—though just as uni­ alternatives?
versal exist only in individuals, so do the species of universals exist Bacon easily refutes the four positive theories outlined just above
only in the species of individuals. Species also emanate from both and invests his major effort in a long and elaborate defense of a fifth
terrestrial and celestial things. In an argument that is highly relevant alternative—one of the centerpieces of De multiplicatione specierum.15There
to his theory of vision, Bacon insists that the senses and the sense is only one viable alternative, Bacon believes, to the four refuted
organs are not merely the recipients of species, but also sources of theories—namely, that species are generated in recipient matter by
species. This we can infer from the facts (a) that visual rays emanat­ “a bringing forth” out of its “active potentiality.” It follows that no
ing from the sense of sight are required if we are to explain all of species passes from the agent to the recipient; rather, a species is
the phenomena of vision, and (b) that sense organs can themselves elicited in the recipient out of potentiality that already exists there.
be seen—an impossibility if species did not proceed from them to In order for this to take place, the agent and recipient must be con­
the eye of the observer.11 tiguous; once that condition has been met, “the active substance of
Two other points need to be made about the agents from which the agent, touching the substance of the recipient without intermedi­
species emanate. First, the more animate the agent is, the more active ary, can alter, by its active virtue and power, the first part of the
it is in producing species, “since animate things are nobler and there­ recipient that it touches. And this action flows into the interior of
fore more active.”12 Second Bacon formulates what we might call a that part, since the part is not a surface, but a body. . . .”16
“principle of homogeneity,” important for understanding the nature of But the requirement of contiguity restricts the applicability of this
species. According to this principle, “the species of substance is sub­ theory to a very limited range of phenomena. The interesting cases
stance, the species of accident is accident, the species of a composite are those in which the final recipient is separated by some distance
is composite, and the species of a simple is simple, just as the species from the original agent. In such cases, a medium between the origi­
of matter is matter, of a form is form, of a universal is universal, and nal agent and the final recipient is required. The original agent elic­
of a singular is singular.”13 its a species of itself in the first part of the medium, contiguous with
We have learned thus far that species are likenesses of the agents the original agent; Bacon calls this the “first effect” of the agent.
from which they issue, and we know that a species has the same This first species elicits a second species in the second part of the
specific nature as the agent it represents (so that the species of sub­ medium (contiguous with the first part of the medium); the second
stance is substance and of accident is accident). But we still know species elicits a third species in the third part of the medium (con­
little about the physical nature of species. (1) Do they actually emerge tiguous with the second part of the medium); and so forth. It is
as individuals from their agents and proceed with local motion through important to understand that it is not the original agent that elicits
species in consecutive parts of the medium, but the species in the
10 O n the proper and common sensibles, see De multiplicatione specierum, 1.2, lines immediately preceding part of the medium, for contiguity is required
220-349, pp. 32-41; Perspective 1.1.3 and 1.10.1, in Lindberg, Bacon and the Origins of at every stage of the process. Note also that the relevant parts of the
Perspectiva.
11 De multiplicatione specierum, 1.2, lines 30-196, 350-77, pp. 24-33, 40-3- I 5 lines
5-126, pp. 70-7.
14 Ibid., 1.3, lines 3-49, pp. 45-47.
12 De multiplicatione specierum, 1.2, lines 200-8, pp. 32-33.
15 Ibid., 1.3, lines 50-207, pp. 47-57
13 Ibid., lines 381-5, pp. 42-3.
16 Ibid., 1.3, lines 151-5, pp. 52-3.
250 DAVID G. LINDBERG LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORCE 251

medium are all of equal size; and they are minute—the smallest parts Now, that multiplication desires by nature to occur along straight lines
of the medium in which the agent can produce an alteration. Note, is determined by the authors of works on optics, especially Ptolemy
and Alhacen; and they show by sensible experiments how multiplica­
finally, that as this process of “multiplication” (the very apt term
tion runs along straight lines in all inanimate substances until it is turned
chosen by Bacon to describe the process of successive generation) back by an obstacle and forms an angle— or else by a second medium
continues, the species generated will become progressively weaker.17 of different rarity .. ., in which an obliquely incident multiplication
Bacon offers a nice summary of the theory in his Perspective applying passing from the first medium to the second forms an angle.20
it there specifically to the propagation of light:
Species proceed in straight lines in uniform, homogeneous media (the
But a species is not body, nor is it moved as a whole from one place only exception being animated media, to be dealt with below); and
to another; but that which is produced [by an object] in the first part they deviate from rectilinearity only when they encounter an obstacle
of the air is not separated from that part, since form cannot be sepa­
that reflects them or when they are obliquely incident on a transpar­
rated from the matter in which it is unless it should be soul; rather, it
produces its likeness in the second part of the air, and so on. There­ ent interface that refracts them.21
fore, there is no local motion, but a generation multiplied through the When a species encounters an opaque body, it can no longer
different parts o f the medium; nor is it body that is generated there, multiply itself in a straight line and, therefore, “seizing the occasion
but corporeal form that does not have dimensions of itself but is pro­ from [the presence of] the dense body, [it] returns by its own power
duced according to the dimensions of the air; and it is not produced in the direction from which it came.” Since it is unable to “multiply
by an effluence from the luminous body but by a drawing forth out of
itself in the dense body, it multiplies itself in the original medium,
the potentiality o f the matter of the air. . . ,18
forming an angle.” And, in fact, it retreats from the opaque body at
There are fine points of Bacon’s theory of the multiplication of spe­ an angle (formed by the path of the retreating multiplication and the
cies that we have not covered, but this captures the essentials.19 surface of the opaque body) equal to the angle between the incident
ray and that same surface of the opaque body. In short, the angles
of incidence and reflection are equal; and the incident and reflected
Light and its Propagation rays define a plane perpendicular to the reflecting surface. It is impor­
tant to note that Bacon does not conceive of reflection as an instance
Thus far the analysis has been exclusively physical and causal—an of mechanical rebound (as Alhacen and many others had done): the
analysis of the nature of species, their relationship to the agents that species “undergoes no violence; rather, when it is prevented from
produced them, and the physics of their multiplication through physical proceeding [straight ahead] by the density of the resisting body, the
media. But Bacon is also interested in the geometry of propagation, species generates itself in some [other] direction open to it. For it
a topic to which he devotes substantial attention in all three of his could be violently driven back, as a ball from a wall, only if it were
major perspectival treatises. In De multiplicatione specierum, it is the body.”22
propagation of species in general with which he is occupied; in the Refraction is a more complicated phenomenon. A species obliquely
Perspectiva and De speculis comburentibus, his focus is on the propagation incident on the interface between two media of different density is
of the species of light. But the geometrical rules and the physics that refracted. If the second medium is denser than the first, the species
account for the phenomena are the same in the two cases. is bent toward the perpendicular to the refracting interface (drawn at
The multiplication of species, Bacon argues, can occur along any the point of incidence), the amount of bending increasing as the density
of five kinds of line—straight or direct, reflected, refracted, twisting,
and accidental. But species prefer to proceed along straight lines:
20 De multipikatime specierum, II. 1, lines 66-73, pp. 94-95.
21 Ibid., II.2, lines 3-52, pp. 91-93. In Bacon’s vocabulary, it is a matter of in­
17 Ibid., 1.4, II. 1. difference whether one speaks of variations in transparency, variations in density, or
18 Perspectiva, 1.9.4. variations in rarity.
19 See Lindberg, Bacon’s Philosophy of Nature for more. 22 Ibid., II.2, lines 87-9, pp. 100-1; III.l, lines 102-5, pp. 184—5.
252 DAVID G. LINDBERG
LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORGE 253

of the second medium increases; if, on the other hand, the second
medium. Bacon thus implicidy applies a principle of uniform action:
medium is rarer than the first, the species is bent away from this
the species elects that path in the second medium which will most
perpendicular, the amount of bending increasing with greater rarity
nearly preserve its strength. This interpretation is confirmed by Bacon’s
of the second medium. This much of the theory is merely descriptive;
analysis of the refraction of a species passing in the opposite direc­
the hard part, yet to come, is to identify the causes of refraction.23
tion, from a denser to a rarer medium. Such a species finds that
Bacon’s starting point is the assumption that a species perpendicu­
“every path is easy for it by comparison with the difficulty it encoun­
larly incident on the interface between two transparent media of
tered in the first body. Therefore, the species is able to assume a
different densities is better able to penetrate that interface and pass
direction away from the perpendicular, and it must necessarily choose
into the second medium than is an obliquely incident species. O r as
this direction, since in so far as possible it acts uniformly and in one
Bacon expresses it, the perpendicular species is the stronger of the
mode.”26
two (other things being equal). He assumes, moreover, that the two
Before leaving the subjects of reflection and refraction, we must
media, because they differ in density, also differ in the resistance
consider the images produced by the reflection and refraction of light.
they offer to propagation of the species. It follows that a species inci­
The simplest case of image-formation by reflection is illustrated in
dent obliquely on such an interface will be bent as it passes between
figure 1. Let AB be a plane mirror, O the visible object, and E the
the two media.24
observer’s eye. The species responsible for vision is multiplied along
But why is the species bent in one direction rather than another?
line OCE (it makes no difference to the theory whether the species
And why, in particular, is the direction of bending such as to endow
emanates from the object at O or the eye at E), so constructed that
the species with a course in the denser medium closer to the perpen­
angle ECB equals angle OCA. Now the visual sense, Bacon argues,
dicular—that is, the perpendicular to the interface between the two
is unaware of the bend in the ray at C and unconsciously projects
media, erected at the point of incidence? The argument goes like
ray EC backwards (or forwards if the ray is conceived to emanate
this. Bacon has previously established (he believes) that perpendicu­
from the eye) until it intersects perpendicular OA (the cathetus)
lar incidence on a transparent interface is stronger than oblique inci­
extended from the object to the mirror. At that point of intersection
dence; he now slips (unconsciously, we must assume) from that claim
the visual power perceives image I of point O to be located. Images
to the superficially similar—but, in fact, quite different—claim that
are formed by refraction in much the same way. In figure 2, let AB
passage through a transparent substance along a line perpendicular
be a plane refracting surface, O the visible object in the denser of
to its surface is stronger than passage along any other line. Now a
the two media, and E the eye in the rarer of the two media. Let OB
species is slowed as it passes obliquely from a less dense to a more
be the cathetus, drawn from the object perpendicular to the refract­
dense medium, “because of the greater resistance offered by the coarse­
ing interface, and CD the perpendicular to the interface at the point
ness of the latter.” Therefore, “the natural virtue generating the species
of refraction. Once again, vision is unaware of the bend in ray OFE
desires the easier passage and chooses it; and this is towards the
at F and unconsciously projects ray EF backwards until it intersects
perpendicular.”25 Why exacdy does it do this? Evidently, in order to
the cathetus at I; and here the image is situated. These are the sim­
compensate for the greater resistance it encounters in the denser
plest cases of image-formation, useful for illustrating the principles
medium, the species chooses the path of greatest strength in that
involved; but Bacon is able to apply them, as well, to more difficult
problems.
23 For the description of refraction, see ibid., II.3, lines 39-80, pp. 107-11. For a
more thorough analysis of Bacon’s views on the cause of refraction, including a
comparison of his views with those of his sources and contemporaries, see David C.
Lindberg, “The Cause of Refraction in Medieval Optics,” British Journal for the His­
tory of Science 4 (1968-69), 23-38.
24 De multiplicatione specierum, II.3, lines 99-131, pp. 113-15.
25 Ibid., II.3, lines 138-41, p. 115.
26 Ibid., II.3, lines 151-4, p. 115.
254 DAVID G. LINDBERG LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORGE 255

But we need to be careful how we talk about these images. Is any­


thing really located at the points (I) where we have marked the image
in figures 1 and 2? Can an observer go around behind the mirror in
figure 1 and find some real thing corresponding to an image? Are
images real things? Or, is there perhaps something on the mirror
surface at point C? The answer to all of these questions is negative.
Bacon addresses this matter with some vehemence, aparently argu­
ing against opinions being advanced in his lifetime. What we call an
“image,” he argues, is simply the object seen outside its true place.
We destroy the error of the multitude who believe that the species of
the object [seen by reflection] is truly [behind the mirror at the inter­
section of the visual ray and the cathetus] and diffuses itself through
the mirror to appear there. But the species of the visible object is not
[in that p lace],. . . nor does it pass through the mirror. . . . Thus it is
said that the place of the image is at the intersection of the visual ray
and the cathetus, not according to the truth of its existence there but
only according to appearance.27

The existing things are objects and observers and reflecting or refract­
ing surfaces; “image” is simply a name for the object misperceived
as to.location.
The two remaining modes of propagation can be dealt with briefly.
What Bacon calls the “twisting path” (lima tortuosa) is encountered
only in animated media. Its theoretical purpose is to account for the
transmission of species through the “twisting threads of the nerves”
from the various sense organs to the appropriate seats of perception;
and Bacon’s best example is the propagation of the species of light
and color through the optic nerve to the brain. An agent, he argues,
cannot produce a species along a twisting path in an inanimate medium,
but only in a straight lin e.. . . But in a medium animated by the power
of the soul, a species is directed according to the requirements of the
soul’s operations; and since the operations of the soul with regard to
species occur in the twisting nerves, the species follows the twisting of
the nerve because of the necessity of the operations of the soul.28

Finally, accidental multiplication is a special case, since it has to do


with secondary, rather than primary, radiation. When solar light passes
through a window (without reflection or refraction), it not only cre­
ates a rectangle of light on the wall or floor opposite the window,
but also illuminates the comer of the room outside of that rectangle.
Figure 2 27 Perspectwa, III. 1.3.
28 Ibid., II.2, lines 99-104, p. 103.
LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORCE 257
256 DAVID C. LINDBERG

surrounding the crystalline and vitreous humors; but the spider’s web
How is this possible? Bacon’s answer is that every point of a primary
does not, in his judgment, qualify as a genuine tunic.
species (proceeding from the original agent along rectilinear, reflected,
These tunics contain three humors. At the back of the eye is the
or refracted lines) is also the origin of weaker, secondary species issuing
vitreous humor, so-called because it has the consistency of melted
in all directions from that point. These are the species of a species,
glass. (Bacon also refers to this humor as the interior or posterior
rather than the species of the original agent, and by means of them
glacial humor.) In front of the vitreous humor is a thin, lentil-shaped
we see not the original agent, but only its primary species.29 Acci­
humor called the crystalline or anterior glacial humor. Containing
dental multiplication will occupy an important place in Bacon’s optical
the vitreous and crystalline humors (the interior and anterior glacial
explanations, bringing intelligibility to a number of otherwise per­
humors) is the spider’s web. Finally, at the front of the eye, outside
plexing phenomena.
the spider’s web, filling the aperture of the uvea and extending from
the crystalline humor to the cornea, is the albugineous humor (our
aqueous humor), which has the consistency of the white of an egg.
Vision
Although Bacon’s conception of the structure of the eye is not iden­
tical with ours, most of its features and much of its terminology are
Bacon’s account of the geometry of the propagation of light was heavily
still recognizable. Bacon’s schematic drawing of the eye is given in
dependent on Greek and Islamic antecedents. So too was his theory
of vision—though in both cases Bacon refined, extended, and amended figure 3.
what he borrowed. And always there was the need to mediate among
competing claims and to solve unsolved problems in the literature
available to him. On the question of ocular anatomy, fundamental
to any comprehensive theory of vision, Bacon drew from the Galenic
tradition as presented in the works of Hunayn ibn Ishaq (circulating
as a work of its translator, Constantine the African), Alhacen, and
Avicenna.
The eye, Bacon argued, consists of three tunics (six if a distinction
is allowed between their anterior and posterior halves) and three
humors.30 The innermost tunic, which is continuous with the inner­
most coat of the optic nerve, is the uvea or grape-like tunic in its
anterior half (grape-like, inasmuch as the aperture at the front of the
eye, through which light enters, is like the end of a grape after the
stem has been removed), the retina in its posterior half. The second
tunic, continuous with the middle coat of the optic nerve is called
the cornea in its anterior portion, the secundina in its posterior por­
tion. And the outermost tunic, which grows out of the outermost
coat of the optic nerve, is the consolidativa or conjunctiva (the white
of the eye) in front, the sclera in back. In addition to these tunics,
Bacon identifies a capsule or web, which he calls the “spider’s web,”

29 Ibid., II.2, lines 116-41, pp. 103-5. Figure 3


30 Perspective 1.2.2—3.
258 DAVID G. LINDBERG LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORCE 259

The function of the retina, which contains veins, arteries, and fine already formulated a scheme that achieved this, and Bacon appro­
nerves, is to offer nourishment to the vitreous humor; the function of priated its essentials and incorporated them into his theory. The first
the remaining tunics is to contain, protect, and darken the humors necessity was to impose an idealized, geometrical model on the eye.
in the interior of the eye. The vitreous humor, having received nourish­ The eye, Bacon argued, “has a shape approaching that of a sphere,
ment from the retina, passes it onward to the crystalline humor. The as do its tunics and humors, because of the praiseworthy properties
albugineous humor consists of surplus substance from the crystalline of the sphere, which offers fewer impediments [to motion] than does
humor. All three humors of the eye are transparent, as is the cornea, a figure having angles, and which is the simplest figure and the most
in order to permit free multi-plication of the species of light through capacious of isoperimetric figures” (see fig. 3).33 It does not matter, in
the eye to the optic nerve. fact, whether or not the entirety of the eye and its tunics and humors
Vision begins when visual species reach the crystalline humor, the are spherical; it is required merely that the surfaces through which
seat of vision within the eye. The crystalline humor is “altered” by species pass should be portions of spheres having their centers of
these species; owing to its density, species “linger in it for a while” curvature arranged along the central axis of the eye. In Bacon’s
and become “apparent to the visual power and thus enable a judg­ scheme, the cornea and front surface of the crystalline humor share
ment to be formed. And it must be somewhat dense, so that it may the same center—and Bacon regards this as the center of the eye.
undergo a kind of pain on account of the species,. . . although this The center of the uvea is anterior to the center of the eye, the cen­
pain is not always perceptible, as .. . when the species are moderate.”31 ter of the consolidativa posterior to it.
But vision is not completed in the eye. Species do not come to With this anatomy of the eye in mind, we are now ready to trace
rest in the crystalline humor but, having “lingered” there briefly, radiation through the eye. Species emanate in all directions from
proceed into the vitreous humor, onward to the optic nerve, and every point (or small part) of the visible object. It follows that every
through the optic nerve (filled with visual spirit) to the common nerve, point .on the surface of the eye (and, for practical purposes, every
where the two optic nerves join and the species passing through them point in the interior of the eye, including the crystalline humor) receives
converge. According to Bacon, species from every point of the visible object. But if this is true, there
it should be understood . . . that sight is not completed in the eyes. For
is an obvious problem. If every point of the crystalline humor (the
two different species reach the [two different] eyes; and differences in seat of the visual power in the eye) receives species from every point
the species lead to differences of judgment. . . . It is necessary, there­ of the visible object, how can the clarity of vision experienced by
fore, that the [ultimate] sentient organ, where vision is completed, should people with good eyesight be accounted for? If species from every
be something other than the eyes; and the eyes, which pass the species point in the visual field mingle at every point of the crystalline humor,
of the visible object on to it, are its instruments. And this [ultimate
the result should be total confusion. If we are to explain clarity of
sentient organ] is the common nerve at the surface of the brain, where
the two nerves coming from the two parts of the anterior region of the vision—the fact that individual objects and individual parts of indi­
brain join together, afterwards dividing and extending themselves to vidual objects are distinguishable and that the arrangement of objects
the eyes; and this is the origin of the visual faculty.32 in our perceptual field corresponds to the arrangement of those same
objects in the external world—we need to establish a one-to-one cor­
Here, in the common nerve, the final visual judgment is rendered.
respondence between points in the eye influenced by species and the
Now it is one thing to argue in qualitative terms that visual spe­
points in the external visual field from which those species emanate.
cies pass through the eye and optic nerve to the common nerve; it
That is, it would appear that clarity of vision can be explained only
is another and much more difficult thing to add geometrical detail,
if each point in the crystalline humor is somehow the recipient of
tracing the course of radiation through the eye convincingly and with
species from only a single point in the visual field; and the points in
precision, taking full account of the rules of refraction. Alhacen had
the crystalline humor that receive these species must have the same
configuration as the external points from which those species emanate.
31 Ibid., 1.4.2.
32 Ibid., 1.5.2. 33 Ibid., 1.3.1.
260 DAVID G. LINDBERG LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORGE 261

The solution to this problem is found in the geometry of the eye. But, of course, vision does not end in the crystalline humor; conse­
Consider the infinity of rays issuing from some point of the visible quently, species need to be traced through the eye to the optic nerve
object; only one of these rays, the one directed toward the center of and the common sense. The vision-producing rays are those repre­
curvature of the cornea, falls on the cornea perpendicularly and enters sented in figure 4, one ray from each point of the visible object, all
it without refraction; because the cornea and the anterior surface of directed toward the center of the eye. But before they actually reach
the crystalline humor are concentric, any ray perpendicular to the the center of the eye, they encounter the posterior surface of the
former is also perpendicular to the latter, which it is therefore able crystalline humor; and here all are refracted away from the center,
to penetrate without refraction. All other rays are obliquely incident except the central axis, which is perpendicular to everything and
on the cornea and again on the crystalline humor; consequendy, they therefore remains unrefracted. This has the fortunate consequence of
are refracted, and in the process they are weakened (because a bent preventing intersection of the rays and the reversal and inversion of
ray is inevitably weaker than a rectilinear ray). Now the same argu­ the image that would, in the view of ancient and medieval perspec-
ment can be applied to each point of the visible object and the radia­ tivists, inevitably accompany intersection. The rays follow a rectilin­
tion issuing from it: only one ray from each point in the visual field ear path through the vitreous humor to the end of the optic nerve;
enters the eye without refraction. The collection of such rays forms they continue through the nerve, following its tortuous path (while
a pyramid of light, with the visible object as base and the center of apparently retaining their orderly configuration) to the common nerve,
curvature of the cornea as vertex (see figure 4). The rays of this where the act of vision is completed.
pyramid, Bacon argues, are the vision-producing rays; all others are But there is one problem not yet adequately discussed, the solu­
bent and weakened and, therefore, contribute only incidentally to tion to which required all of the ingenuity Bacon could muster. The
visual perception.34 sources available to Bacon were by no means agreed about the direc­
tion of the radiation responsible for vision. Euclid, Ptolemy, Tideus,
visible object
and Alkindi were all extramissionists—committed to the proposition
that the radiation responsible for vision had its origin in the eye.
Galen and Hunayn ibn Ishaq must also be regarded as extramissionists.
And among Latin writers, St Augustine (whose authority was not to
be trifled with), Adelard of Bath, and William of Conches all defended
versions of the extramission theory.
Standing against all of this extramissionist opinion were three great
intromissionists: Alhacen, Avicenna, and Averroes, none of whom could
be taken lightly, and all of whom had argued convincingly that the
radiation responsible for vision passed from the visible object to the
observer’s eye. And finally, there were writers who made room for
crystalline both intromitted and extramitted rays. Plato was an early represen­
humor
tative of this opinion, and Grosseteste a more recent one. And Anstotle,
though an uncompromising defender of the intromission theory in
his works on perception and the soul, apparently conceded in his
Meteorology and Book on Animals that extramitted rays are also involved
(a result, in the latter case, of mistranslation of the relevant passage).
Bacon’s starting point was the proposition that all of the authori­
ties mentioned had possessed at least a portion of the truth; if some
had incomplete knowledge, at least none of them had been wrong.
34 Ibid., 1.6.1. On a visual role for rays that fall obliquely on the eye, see 1.6.2. But the only way of bringing the contrary opinions of this diverse set
262 DAVID C. LINDBERG LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORCE 263

of authors into a plausible unity was through a combined intromission- states in his De animalibus “that seeing is nothing other than the visual
extramission theory of the sort that Aristode (apparendy) and Gros­ power extending to the visible object.” And Ptolemy “urges throughout
seteste (actually) had promoted. The broad oudine of Bacon’s theory, his whole book that visual rays proceed from the eye to the visible
therefore, was certainly taken from Aristode and Grosseteste; but its object.”37
details were Bacon’s original contribution. However, Bacon also has arguments of his own to offer. Natural
The intromission theory is implicit in Bacon’s Perspectiva from the objects complete their action through their own species, “as the sun
beginning; indeed, a reader of the first twenty-three of its sixty-six and other celestial bodies cause the generation and corruption of
chapters would never suspect that the extramission theory was about things through their powers dispatched into mundane things. Terres­
to put in an appearance. In these first twenty-three chapters, Bacon trial substances do likewise, as fire dries and consumes and does many
develops the theory that species emanate in all directions from every other things through its own power.” If this is so, then “the eye must
point in the visual field, reach the eye, and proceed to the crystalline perform the act of sight through its own power. But the act of sight
humor and the common nerve, where they are perceived by the is the perception of a visible object at a distance, and therefore the
visual power. He also buttresses this theory with arguments from eye [must] perceive the visible object through its own power multi­
authority and experience. As for authority, Bacon argues that “vision plied to the object.”38 Bacon also advances empirical arguments in
requires the species of a visible object; for without that species there the form of phenomena that can be explained, he believes, only by
will be no sight, according to Aristode, who says in On the Soul, book 2, the assumption that species issue from the eye. One of these is the
that sense universally receives the species of sensible things so that alleged ability of people with deep-set eyes to see farther than other
the act of perception can occur.”35 Empirical evidence leads to the people. One of several causes of this capability is
same conclusion: “When there is an obstacle between the species of
an object and the eye, sight does not occur, but when all impedi­ that the visual power is more gathered together and united when it is
more deeply buried in the eye socket, so that it follows a narrower and
ments are removed, so that the species reaches the eye, then the
straighter path to the visible object and is less dispersed and spread
object is seen.” Persistence of vision teaches the same thing: out and thus proceeds through the place occupied by the visual pyra­
mid. For this reason a man who wants to look at something carefully
That colors act on sight is evident from the fact that when somebody
from a distance places the hollow o f his hand to the socket of his eye,
has looked at a garden thickly planted with vegetation, on which the
so that the visual power will be more concentrated and less dispersed.39
light of the sun shines, and continues to gaze at it, if he then shifts his
vision to a dark place, he will discover in that dark place the form of Additional proof is found in the (legendary) phenomenon of the
the light colored by the green of the vegetation.36
“observation well,” according to which the stars are visible by day to
And there are more arguments. a person situated at the bottom of a deep well. “One reason for
But having developed a convincing theory of vision around the this,” Bacon argues, “is the narrowness of the pathway, which con­
intromission idea, Bacon raises the surprising question, whether “the stricts the visual power over a considerable distance, so that it pro­
species of the eye is [also] required for the act of sight,” and answers ceeds more directly to the region of the stars above the well; and
it in the affirmative. If this is not an abrupt change of direction, it this occurs because the eye is buried in the depth of the well.”40
is at least the introduction of a theoretical element for which Bacon Bacon has other arguments, including appeal to the light that can be
did nothing to prepare his reader. Again Bacon employs the argument seen emanating from the eye of a cat.41
from authority, invoking the extramissionist opinions of Aristode,
Euclid, Ptolemy, Tideus, Alkindi, and Augustine. Aristode, for example,
37 Ibid., 1.7.2.
38 Ibid., 1.7.4.
35 Ibid., 1.5.1. 39 Ibid., II. 1.1.
36 Ibid. 40 Ibid.
41 Ibid., 1.5.1.
264 LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORCE 265
DAVID G. LINDBERG

If the evidence for extramission is as persuasive as Bacon appar­ What are we to make of Bacon’s theory of vision? Much of its
ently believes it to be, what does he make of the opposition of Alhacen, content, of course, was borrowed from Alhacen and other predeces­
Avicenna, and Averroes? Bacon replies that these authors were not sors; but all of it passed through Bacon’s mind, where it was judged,
opposed to the claim that extramitted species exist, but only to the corrected, elaborated, and synthesized. And it was introduced by Bacon
much more ambitious claim that “a visual species. . . extends from into the western optical tradition, where it became the standard
the eye to the visible object, that by means of it the eye perceives account of visual theory until Johannes Kepler replaced it with the
the very object, and that it seizes the species of the visible object and theory of the retinal image early in the seventeenth century. The
returns this species to the eye.”42 If, on occasion, these authors appear persuasive power of the theory came not only from its ingenious and
to condemn extramission outright, we must understand that they were plausible scheme for establishing a one-to-one correspondence between
merely expressing popular opinion in the course of an argument, points in the external visual field and points in the eye, but also
without meaning to endorse it. In short, they were not opposed to from its successful unification of mathematical, physical, anatomical,
the existence of visual species, but only to attempts to endow them physiological, and perceptual approaches to the phenomena of sight.
with inappropriate functions.43 Following the lead of Alhacen, Bacon took the whole corpus of authori­
What, then, is their appropriate function? Bacon assigns them an tative opinions on the subject of vision (whatever their methodology),
ancillary role, arguing that resolved difficulties, and worked out compromises, thereby blending
the achievements of the mathematicians, the physicists, and the phy­
the species o f mundane things are not immediately suited o f them­ sicians into a workable, convincing, and (for a considerable period)
selves to bring to completion an action on the eye, owing to the nobility
of the latter. Therefore, they must be assisted and excited by the spe­ enduring synthesis.
cies [of the eye], which proceeds through the region occupied by the
visual pyramid, altering and ennobling the medium and rendering it
commensurate with sight. Thus the species of the eye prepares for the The Methodology of Perspectiva
approach of the species o f the visible object and, moreover, ennobles
the latter so that it is wholly conformable to and commensurate with
Were the optical achievements discussed above made possible by the
the nobility o f the animated body, the eye.44
application of a new (and perhaps modern) scientific methodology?
This argument is an extension of a basic Platonic and Augustinian This possibility is suggested by the praise heaped on Bacon by nine­
theme, which maintains that the soul is superior to the body and teenth- and twentieth-century mythologizers, eager to view him as a
therefore, in sensation, cannot be the passive recipient of sensory champion of modem scientific methodology.45 And the magnitude of
impressions; rather, the soul is the causal agent in sensory acts. In this praise has been sufficient to call for a reasoned response. O f
Bacon’s adaptation of this theory, the extramitted species of the eye course, Bacon himself made dramatic methodological claims, issuing
(nobler than the medium and the inanimate objects in the external appeals for the cultivation of both mathematics and experimental
world because of the close connection between the sense organs and science, as instruments vital for the reform of learning and the pres­
the soul) prepares the way for sensation, ennobling both the material ervation of Latin Christendom. O f mathematics, Bacon wrote:
medium and the incoming species, making them “commensurate”
. .. knowledge of this science prepares the mind and elevates it to sure
with the eye, and rendering the species capable of “completing its knowledge of all things, so that if one grasps the basics of wisdom
action” on the eye. concerning this science and applies them correctly to knowledge of

42 Ibid., 1.7.3. 45 For example, A.C. Crombie argued in his Robert Grosseteste and the Origins o f
43 This paragraph is borrowed, with only minor changes, from the introduction Experimental Science, 1100-1700 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1953), p. 140, that “Roger
to my forthcoming Bacon and the Origins of Perspectiva. Bacon . . . first postulated a theory of science as a means of discovering reality and
44 1.7.4, 12. truth, and then used this methodological theory in detailed researches.”
266 DAVID G. LINDBERG LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORGE 267

other sciences, one will be able to know all things that follow, without light, for example, was heavily geometrical and went some way toward
error or doubt, easily and powerfully.46 identifying mathematical causes of observational phenomena. Thus
As for experiment, Bacon began his Tractatus in quo Jit de experientia in Bacon could offer a geometrical account, based on the geometrical
communi (devoted to “experimental science,” the science of experi­ laws of refraction, to explain why images formed in a plane mirror
ence) by assuring his reader that “without experience nothing can be are located as far behind the mirror as the object is before it, or
sufficiently known, nor will the soul ever rest in the light of truth how it is that we are able to secure clear vision of the external world.
unless it discovers the cause by means of experience.”47 But to what But when Bacon took the next step, endeavoring to identify the causes
degree did perspectiva, in Bacon’s hands, fulfill the promise of these that lie behind and explain the laws of reflection and refraction, he
methodological prescriptions? Let us look for an answer, beginning found it necessary to appeal to mechanical analogies and metaphysi­
with the question of mathematization. cal principles: direct blows are more powerful than oblique ones,
It is beyond question that Bacon (following Euclid, Ptolemy, Alhacen refracted light selects that direction of passage in the second medium
and other predecessors) gave perspectiva a strong mathematical orien­ that will most nearly maintain uniformity of strength, and so forth.
tation. His perspectival treatises [Perspectiva, De multiplicatione specierum, Bacon’s fullest account of visual perception, given in his Perspectiva,
and De speculis comburentibus) contain an abundance of serious geo­ begins with an (entirely nonmathematical) analysis of the soul, sensa­
metrical arguments, supported by a multitude of geometrical dia­ tion, and cognition; and these provide the setting and foundation for
grams. It goes without saying that Bacon’s analysis of the rectilinear the entire work. Even Bacon’s analysis of the propagation of light
propagation of light was geometrical (for otherwise we could not specify or species, to which he devoted De multiplicatione specierum, was funda­
its propagation as “rectilinear”). It is also no surprise to those of us mentally a study of the nature of species and the physics of their
with a modern education to find that reflection and refraction were propagation through transparent media. It appears that the ultimate
the objects of careful geometrical analysis. But Bacon also employed explanatory principles in Bacon’s optical writings were not geometri­
geometry to elucidate the act of vision, tracing the path of radiation cal at all, but physical, metaphysical, and perceptual.49
from the object of vision to the eye and through the eye to the References to experience and experiment are scattered through
common nerve. As we have seen, he even geometrized the anatomy Bacon’s Perspectiva, De multiplicatione specierum, and De speculis comburentibus.
of the eye. And he was able to provide geometrical explanations of The term experior (with its inflected forms) appears thirteen times in
a variety of other visual phenomena, such as double vision, the bent the Perspectiva; experientia appears ten times, experimentum or experimmtalis
appearance of a rod partially submerged in water, and the apparent ten times, and experimmtator twice. Roughly similar statistics would
enlargement of the sun and moon when near the horizon. hold for the other two treatises. But before we can make anything
But it does not follow that, in Bacon’s hands, geometrical analysis out of Bacon’s use of these terms, we must understand what he meant
extended to the furthest reaches, the most fundamental principles of by them. The Latin term experimentum and its synonym, experientia,
perspectiva. Although he argued in his Opus tertium that “the causes of denoted, in their root meanings, a “test” or “trial,” and Bacon was
natural things cannot be given except by means of geometry,” Bacon prepared to accept many kinds of tests as “experiments,” including
was unable even to come close to fulfilling this implied mandate in contrived or artificial experiments, casual everyday experience avail­
his optical studies.48 His analysis of the reflection and refraction of able to everybody, reports of the experiences of other observers, what
I call “geometrical experiments,” even the spiritual experience of divine
illumination. “Experimental science,” as he employed the phrase,
46 Opus maius, ed. J.H. Bridges, 3 vols. (London: Williams & Norgate, 1900), IV. 1.1,
vol. 1, pp. 97-98. covered all of these “experimental” practices, as well as various bodies
47 For the Latin text, see Jeremiah M.G. Hackett, “The Meaning of Experimen­ of practical knowledge or lore allegedly acquired by empirical means.
tal Science (scientia experimmtalis) in the Philosophy of Roger Bacon,” Ph.D. disserta­
tion (University of Toronto, 1983), p. 271.
48 Opus tertium, in J.S. Brewer, ed., Fr. Rogeri Bacon Opera quaedam hactenus in edita 49 For a fuller analysis of Bacon’s attempt to mathematize perspectiva, see the intro­
(London: H er Majesty’s Stationery Office, 1859), p. 111. duction to Lindberg, Bacon and the Origins of Perspectiva.
LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORCE 269
268 DAVID G. LINDBERG

From this it is evident, as we learn by experience, that there are as


Because another chapter in this volume is devoted explicitly to Bacon’s many rainbows as observers. For if two people stand observing the
experimental science, I will not delve further into the larger issue of rainbow in the north and one moves westward, the rainbow will move
Bacon’s empiricism here; the question to which I will confine my parallel to him; if the other observer moves eastward, the rainbow will
attention is the degree to which and the ways in which experiment move parallel to him; and if he stands still, the rainbow will remain
or experience entered into Bacon’s investigations of the science of stationary. It is evident, therefore, that there are as many rainbows as
observers, from which it follows that no two observers can see the
perspective50
same rainbow, although an inexperienced person does not comprehend
I wish to present and to offer a brief defense of four conclusions. this fact. For the shadow of each observer divides the arc of the rain­
First, Bacon’s perspectival theories were not primarily the product of bow in half; therefore, since the shadows are sensibly parallel, they do
his own empirical activity. I wish I could convince myself that this not meet at the middle of the same rainbow, and each observer must
point is too obvious to require restatement, but there has been enough see his own rainbow.52
fatuous literature on the history of early science, castigating those Bacon’s theory of radiation through small apertures offers additional
who formulated scientific knowledge by appeal to any resource other examples. Bacon maintains that solar light projected through a small
than personal experimental or experiential activity, to suggest other­ triangular aperture appears to contract immediately beyond the aper­
wise. Let us be clear, then, that Bacon proceeded as natural philoso­ ture, before beginning to dilate. This observation is certainly not called
phers and scientists have always proceeded, by constructing an edifice for by the geometrical theory that Bacon is in the process of construct­
largely out of inherited materials. His primary source of perspectival ing; on the contrary, it throws a monkey-wrench into his theoretical
knowledge was the written word—the scholarly tradition going back efforts, and we therefore have solid grounds for assuming that the
to Alhacen, Alkindi, Ptolemy, Aristode, and Euclid.51 Bacon’s origi­ observation is a genuine one. Here is Bacon’s account of the matter:
nal contribution was to take the radically diverse materials available
to him in this scholarly tradition and, through a combination of AH these arguments show that the incident radiation should in no way
be narrowed beyond the aperture if the last-mentioned mode of multi­
judicious selection and intelligent compromise, to produce a work­
plication were true. And since the narrowing of light beyond the aper­
able and convincing synthesis. This was a significant achievement; ture is manifestly evident to the eyes, it seems possible to conclude, by
but it was theoretical, rather than empirical, in nature. turning the foregoing arguments around, that light is not multiplied as
Second, it does not follow that first-hand experiments or experience described and established above. I am therefore at a total loss to know
played no role in the formation of Bacon’s perspectival theories. A what to say, since I cannot deny what I see with my eyes.53
certain amount of simple optical observation is inescapable: in the Finally, consider the observation described in Bacon’s analysis of the
simplest acts of seeing, we experience many of the phenomena that maximum angle covered by the visual field. Bacon argues that
a theory of vision must explain. Moreover, we all encounter rain­
bows, double images, after-images, and instances of reflection and it is certain from experience that an eye at the surface of the earth
refraction, whether we seek them or not; this was true for Bacon no cannot see a quarter of the heaven. For a person looking at some star
directly overhead while standing on flat terrain will not be able to see
less than for the rest of us. However, Bacon’s works evince knowl­
the earth, however hard he tries. . . . And therefore he does not see a
edge of perspectival phenomena going well beyond what can be quarter, but a little less, since if the person thus observing inclines his
learned from such simple, everyday observation. Consider the follow­ head slightly, he will see the earth and not the star.54
ing account of the phenomena of the rainbow, taken from part VI of
Bacon’s Opus maius: Not only is the detail convincing; but this experiment is so easily
performed that, in my opinion, the burden of proof shifts to the
person who wishes to deny that Bacon actually performed it.
50 For more on empiricism in Bacon’s optics, see my introduction to Roger Bacon
and the Origins of Perspectiva in the Middle Ages, from which some of the phraseology
52 Opus maius, vol. 2, p. 187.
employed above has been borrowed.
53 De speculis comburentibus, VI, in Lindberg, Bacon’s Philosophy of Nature, pp. 315-17.
51 A similar claim can be made for modem scientists, who obtain most of their
54 Perspectiva, 1.8.3.
scientific knowledge from scholarly texts and papers.
270 DAVID G. LINDBERG LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORCE 271

Third, a few of Bacon’s observations can be identified as contrived Despite the impressive level of detail, there is no assurance that Bacon
experiments employing instruments. The clearest piece of evidence is ever built this apparatus or performed experiments with it. For one
undoubtedly his measured value of 42° for the maximum elevation thing, his description of the instrument comes, with little change,
of the rainbow, a correct value not given by any author (so far as we from Alhacen’s De aspectibus?1 Furthermore, the demonstration that
know) prior to Bacon. We may appropriately infer, therefore, that Bacon constructs by reference to this apparatus does not depend for
this figure was obtained by Bacon through the use of an astrolabe. its persuasive power on the actual performance of a physical experi­
In this connection, we need to keep in mind Bacon’s claim to have ment, but rather on the geometry of the device and of the experi­
spent more than 2,000 pounds on books, experimental apparatus, mental set-up. In short, this is a case in which a thought experiment
and other necessities of his research.55 There can be little doubt that based on a geometrical analysis of the apparatus is as persuasive as
Bacon also made use of mirrors for investigating reflection, crystals any actual observations that one could make. This is certainly a test,
for investigating refraction, and small apertures for investigating the and therefore (in Bacon’s terms) an experiment; but it is a geometri­
phenomena of pinhole images. cal test.
We do, however, need to be cautious in our attempts to identify That Bacon draws no hard distinction between such geometrical
genuine experiments and genuine experimental apparatus. Bacon’s thought “experiments” and other kinds of “experiments” is nicely
most elaborate description of a piece of experimental apparatus— revealed by his analysis of the shadow cast when a small, opaque,
apparatus designed for the investigation of double vision—is found spherical body is bathed in the light of a larger, luminous sphere.
in the Perspective According to Bacon, “it is evident to sense that as the shadow retreats
continuously from the opaque body, it is continuously spread out.”
An investigator can prove [the phenomena of double vision] by taking
a board of a palm’s width, four or five or six palms in length, and However, in the course of the argument, Bacon remarks that all of
with a smooth surface [fig. 5]; and he should take three separate vis­ this “is visibly evident in the figure”5758—revealing, thereby, that the
ible objects formed of wax or wood, the size of the last joint of the spreading of the shadow is “evident to sense” not in the material
little finger, shaped like pyramids; and they should be of different col­ world but in a geometrical diagram.
ors for greater clarity. These objects should be arranged [longitudinally
Fourth, observations and experiments (real or imaginary) served
on the board at points M, A, and N ], with a sensible distance between
them; and the middle one should be in the middle of the board, one theoretically significant functions in Bacon’s science of perspective The
o f the others at the far end, and the third halfway between the middle simplest such function was to supply observational data requiring
object and the eye. The end of the board nearest the eye should have explanation within the framework of existing theory. Thus the apparent
a cut-out, so that it can be easily applied to the eyes above the bridge enlargement of the disks of the sun and moon when near the hori­
of the nose. If the axes of the eyes are then fixed on the middle object, zon called forth from Bacon an explanation in terms of the already-
which will [thus] appear single, both o f the others will appear double.56
established rules of refraction. The principles of refraction were also
P B
employed to explain the rod that appears bent when partially sub­
merged in water and the coin in the bottom of a cup, which becomes
visible when the cup is filled with water.59
D But the more usual and more important function of experience
and experiment in Bacon’s optical writings was to confirm, refute, or
challenge theoretical claims. For example, to confirm that deep-set
K C L F

Figure 5 57 Alhacen, De aspectibus, in Opticae thesaurus Alhazeni Arabis libri septem, ed. Friedrich
Risner (Basel: Per Episcopios, 1572), III.2.12, pp. 81-83.
55 Opus tertium, p. 59. 58 De speculis comburentibus, III, p. 293.
56 Perspective II.2.2; cf. II.2.3. 59 Perspectiva, III.2.4.
272 DAVID C. LINDBERG LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORGE 273

eyes see better at a distance because their deep positioning prevents best, spotty. Optical investigations remained, for Bacon as for his con­
dispersion of the visual power, Bacon reports the observation that an temporaries and immediate predecessors, primarily a matter of intellec­
observer at the bottom of a well is able to see the stars during the tual effort expended in the mastery of a scholarly tradition, mediation
daytime: “And an experiment confirms [this]; for a man situated in between its divergent tendencies, and reconciliation of its competing
a deep place, as [at the bottom of] a well, will be able to see the theories. Observations were not totally absent, but neither were they
stars by day that he cannot see when he is at the surface of the well, particularly prominent. But is this cause for disapproval? What addi­
as Pliny states . . . and as experience teaches.”60 That the observation tional observations do we wish Bacon had made, and how would
in question was apparently somebody else’s (and a legendary one, at they have been relevant to his theoretical concerns? Wasn’t the kind
that) in no way alters the logic of the relationship between observa­ of intellectual effort made by Bacon precisely what was required,
tional datum and theoretical claim. given Bacon’s aims, the existing state of optical theory, and the condi­
Another example, and one that may well involve genuine observa­ tions under which the investigator of perspectival matters necessarily
tion on Bacon’s part, appears in his attempt to put to an experimental worked in the thirteenth century? Bacon’s purpose was basically
test the theoretical claim that refracted rays are visually efficacious. pedagogical, and the appropriate way of instructing interested scholars
He proposes to place a straw or needle between the eye and a visi­ of the thirteenth century on the mysteries of perspediva was to produce
ble object. If all parts of the object are visible, it follows that some a synthesis of the diverse, authoritative sources then available.
parts are seen through radiation obliquely incident on the eye and, Bacon was more successful in fulfilling the mathematical portion
therefore, refracted. The needle or straw of his methodological program. It is true that he failed to live up to
the implied promise made in his Opus tertium, to discover geometrical
will impede the direct passage of the species of some part of [the object].
But oblique rays will fall from that object onto the cornea, since, be­
causes of all natural things.62 All too frequently, in his perspectival
sides the one perpendicular that would come if there were no obstacle, studies, he found it necessary to fall back on explanatory principles
there comes an infinity o f oblique rays, as we have seen. Therefore, it of a physical, metaphysical, or perceptual sort. Nonetheless, Bacon
will be seen only by refracted rays, and not by direct rays. This is (inspired by the achievements of Euclid, Ptolemy, and Alhacen) car­
evident by experience if you hold a straw or needle between your eye ried the mathematization of optics as far as it was to go during the
and some visible thing; and you can easily experience this with a candle
[as visible object].61
European Middle Ages. Perspediva, as it emerged from his pen, had
both the appearance and the reality of a mathematical science. Bacon
Observational consequences of the theory are empirically verified, was a transitional figure of great importance, who played a critical
thus confirming the relevant theoretical claims. role in the transmission of Greek and Islamic learning to medieval
Europe. It was he, more than any other, who introduced Latin
Christendom to the mathematical optics of Euclid, Ptolemy, Alkindi,
Bacon’s Achievement and Alhacen; who synthesized their works, clarifying and exhibiting
their methodological achievement; and who, consequently, stood at
How are we to judge Bacon’s achievement? In particular, must he the head of the European tradition in geometrical optics.
be condemned to insignificance by his failure to complete the mathe-
matization of perspediva and by his limited application of experimental
methodology to perspectival matters? There is no doubt that Bacon Bibliography
failed to live up to his own methodological prescriptions. His applica­
tion of an experimental methodology to perspectival problems was, at Alhacen, Opticae thesaurus AUiazeni Arabis libri septem . . ., ed. Friedrich Risner.
Basel 1572. Reprint New York: Johnson Reprint Corporation, 1972.

60 Ibid., II. 1.1.


61 Ibid., III.2.1. 62 See above, n. 48.
274 DAVID G. LINDBERG LIGHT, VISION, AND THE UNIVERSAL EMANATION OF FORCE 275

Bacon, Roger, De speculis comburentibus, ed. and trans. David C. Lindberg, ------ , ed. and trans., Roger Bacon’s Philosophy of Nature: A Critical Edition, with
Roger Bacon’s Philosophy of Nature: A Critical Edition, with English Translation, English Translation, Introduction, and Notes, of De multiplicatione specierum and De
Introduction, and Notes. . . . Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983. speculis comburentibus [& lit]. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983.
------ , De multiplicatione specierum, ed. and trans. David C. Lindberg, Roger ----- , “Roger Bacon’s Theory of the Rainbow: Progress or Regress?,” Isis,
Bacon’s Philosophy of Nature: A Critical Edition, with English Translation, Intro­ 57 (1966), 235-48.
duction, and Notes. . . . Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983. ------ , Studies in the History of Medieval Optics. London: Variorum, 1983.
------ , Perspectiva, ed. and trans. David C. Lindberg, Roger Bacon and the Ori­ ------ , Theories of Vision from al-Kindi to Kepler [& lit]. Chicago: University of
gins of Perspectiva in the Middle Ages. . . . Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996. Chicago Press, 1976.
Bjombo, A.A., and Vogl, Sebastian, “Alkindi, Tideus und Pseudo-Euklid: ------ , “The Theory of Pinhole Images from Antiquity to the Thirteenth
Drei optische Werke,” Abhandlungen zur Geschichte der mathematischen Wissen- Century,” Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 5 (1968): 154—76.
schaften, 26, pt. 3 (1912), 1-176. Rosen, Edward, “Did Roger Bacon Invent Eyeglasses?,” Archives intemationales
Crombie, A.C., Robert Grosseteste and the Origins of Experimental Science 1100- d’histoire des sciences, 1 (1954), 3-15.
1700. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1953. ------ , “The Invention of Eyeglasses,” Journal of the History of Medicine and
Fisher, N.W., and Unguru, Sabetai, “Experimental Science and Mathemat­
Allied Sciences, 11 (1956), 13-46, 183-218.
ics in Roger Bacon’s Thought,” Traditio, 27 (1971), 353-78. Smith, A. Mark, “Getting the Big Picture in Perspectivist Optics,” Isis, 72
(1981), 568-89.
Hackett, Jeremiah M.G., “The Meaning of Experimental Science (Scientia
Experimentalis) in the Philosophy of Roger Bacon,” Ph.D. dissertation (Uni­ Vogl, Sebastian, “Roger Bacons Lehre von der sinnlichen Spezies und vom
versity of Toronto, 1983). Sehvorgange,” in Roger Bacon Essays, ed. A.G. Little, pp. 205-27. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1914.
Lejeune, Albert, Euclide et Ptolemee: Deux stades de I’optique geometrique grecque.
Louvain: Bibliotheque de l’Universite, 1948. Wiedemann, Eilhard, “Roger Bacon und seine Verdienste um die Optik,”
----- , Recherches sur la catroptrique grecque, d’apres les sources antiques et medievales. in Roger Bacon Essays, ed. A.G. Little, pp. 185-203. Oxford: Oxford
Brussels: Palais des Academies, 1957. University Press, 1914.
Lindberg, David C., “The Cause of Refraction in Medieval Optics,” British Wiirschmidt, J., “Roger Bacons Art des wissenschaftlichen Arbeitens, darge-
Journal for the History of Science, 4 (1968), 23-38. stellt nach seiner Schrift De speculis,” in Roger Bacon Essays, ed. A.G. Little,
------ , “The Genesis o f Kepler’s Theory o f Light: Light Metaphysics from pp. 229-39. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1914.
Plotinus to Kepler,” Osiris, n.s. 2 (1986), 5-42.
------ , “Laying the Foundations of Geometrical Optics: Maurolico, Kepler,
and the Medieval Tradition,” in David C. Lindberg and Geoffrey Cantor,
The Discourse of Lightfrom the Middle Ages to the Enlightenment, pp. 1-65. Los
Angeles: William Andrews Clark Memorial Library, 1985.
------ , “Lenses and Eyeglasses,” Dictionary of the Middle Ages, VII, 538-41.
------ , “Lines of Influence in Thirteenth-Century Optics: Bacon, Witelo, and
Pecham,” Speculum, 46 (1971), 66-83.
------ , “Medieval Latin Theories of the Speed of Light,” in Roemer et la vitesse
de la lumiere, pp. 45-72. (CNRS, Collection d’histoire des sciences, 3.)
Paris: J. Vrin, 1978.
------ , “On the Applicability of Mathematics to Nature: Roger Bacon and
His Predecessors,” British Journal for the History of Science, 15 (1982), 3-25.
------ , “A Reconsideration o f Roger Bacon’s Theory of Pinhole Images,”
Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 6 (1970), 214-23.
----- , Roger Bacon and the Origins of Perspectiva in the Middle Ages: A Critical
Edition and English Translation of Bacon’s Perspectiva, with Introduction and Notes
[& lit]. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996.
------ , “Roger Bacon and the Origins of Perspectiva in the West,” in Math­
ematics and Its Applications to Science and Natural Philosophy in the Middle Ages:
Essays in Honor ofMarshall Clagett, ed. Edward Grant and John E. Murdoch,
pp. 249-68. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987.
I

12. ROGER BACON ON SCIENT1A E X P E R IM E N TA L

Jeremiah Hackett

Roger Bacon and his Scientia experimentalis has been a matter of debate
ever since the Renaissance philosophers and writers designated him
as a Magus. The mainly negative assessment of medieval philosophy
and science by Francis Bacon ensured that the teaching of any
medieval scientist would be treated as secondary.1 And the return to
Greek and Roman sources which one associates with the Renaissance
and Early Modem times ensured that even 19th century authors would
be ignorant of the actual achievements of Medieval philosophers and
scientists. It is only with the recovery of Medieval texts in a system­
atic manner since the nineteenth century that it is possible to pro­
vide a just estimate of the role and achievement of Roger Bacon and
his contemporaries. Hence, a study of Scientia experimentalis in Roger

' While Francis Bacon is generally negative about Medieval philosophers, he does
make an exception for Roger Bacon in one example concerning alchemy and medi­
cine: See Francis Bacon, in Spedding, Ellis, Heath, The Works of Francis Bacon (Lon­
don: Longmans, 1870; Reprint, Garrett Press, Inc., New York, N.Y., 1968), [Temporis
Partus Masculus], III, 534: Siquidem utile genus eorum est, qui de theoriis non
admodum solliciti, mechanica quadam subtilitate rerum inventarum extensiones
prehendunt; qualis est Bacon (my italics). See the comment of Francis Bacon in Historia
vitae et mortis, 158 for a clear use by Francis Bacon of the experimental works of
Roger Bacon. This section on the prohngatw vitae is taken from the De mirabilis potestate
artis et naturae (pub. Paris 1542) otherwise cited below as Epistola de secretis operibus artis
• et naturae. This citation from Roger Bacon has to do with the English woman who
lived for 300 years, and it is here also that Francis Bacon gets his information on
the infamous Artephius.
Since this is solid proof that Francis Bacon knew one of the central treatises,
then, we shall have to claim that this reference in Francis Bacon may have influ­
enced 19th century comment on Roger Bacon. More importantly, it raises the issue
of just how much of Roger Bacon was read by the Philosophical Chancellor. Did
he know about the great amount of Roger Bacon works in John Dee’s Library? Did
he use them? I will try to answer these questions elsewhere. There is a need to do
J this since this topic has not been well-served by recent study. Joseph Kupfer, “The
Father of Empiricism: Roger not Francis,” Vivarium 12 (1974), 52H52 recognises that
Roger Bacon has a good claim to being the Origin of Empiricism in Latin philoso­
phy, but the comparison with Francis Bacon needs much development. His main
claim that the account of the Causa erroris is the same in both Bacon’s cannot be
sustained. Yet, it is not impossible that Baron Verulam got the idea of a Causa erroris
from Roger Bacon.
278 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON SCIENTTA EXPER1MENTAUS 279

Bacon must begin with a proper framing of the issue of “experi­ teenth century research scientist. Our task then is to understand his
ment” and with an account of the modem scholarship. place in medieval science and to understand the relation of that science
A very modem attitude has been put in the form of a question: to the early modern science of the late Renaissance.
“Did Roger Bacon developed the experimental procedures of mod­
ern research science?”2 This question hides a number of pertinent
issues. First, did the Greeks, the discoverers of this kind of thinking, 1. Modem Interpretations of Bacon’s Scientia experimentalis
use “experiments” in their science? Second, allowing for the “new”
developments of method in modem research science, is not the above The 19th century romantic image of Roger Bacon as a medieval
question anachronistic in the first place? That is, whatever the com­ predecessor of modern science has its origin in William Whewell’s
plex relation of medieval to early modern science, the issue to be highly influential three volume History of the Inductive Sciences from the
settled is whether or not “experiment” is a factor in Greek, Arabic, Earliest to the Present Time. For Whewell, the first awakening of science
Medieval Latin and Early Modern Science. was among the Greeks, the foremost of whom, as far as experimen­
This issue has already arisen in the study of Ancient Greek Science. tal science was concerned, was Aristotle and Ptolemy. Between this
And it is the well-considered position of G.E.R. Lloyd that we need Greek past, which was carried on by the Islamic scientists, and the
to look to three areas of study in order to address the issue: astronomy, modem period lay the “midday slumber” of western science. In the
optics and meteorology. Observation and not experiment in a strict account by Whewell, a solitary figure stands out in this “stationary
sense is relevant to ancient astronomy. But in both optics and in period” of science, namely, Roger Bacon, who in Whewell’s interpre­
meteorology, ancient authors did not just rely on doctrines or book tation championed the cause of experimentation to such an extent
knowledge. They did attempt complex experiments. And this is espe­ that he resembles the acknowledged founder of modern experimen­
cially the case in Ptolemy.3 The issue which must be answered here tal science, Francis Bacon. For Whewell, the correspondence between
is whether or not Roger Bacon developed this “experimental” meth­ Roger Bacon and Aristotle was more a matter of sympathy of spirit
odology handed on from the Greeks and developed by the Arabic than a direct doctrinal dependence. But the resemblance between
scientists? Roger Bacon was a Medieval scientist and not a nine­ Roger and the Philosophical Chancellor of England so astounded
Whewell that he wrote:
2 A good example of this approach is found in Martin Heidegger, “Die Zeit des Roger Bacon’s works are not only far beyond his age, in the knowl­
Weltbildes,” in his Holzwege and also in his Beitrage zur Philosophie. In the former, he
edge which they contain, but so different from the temper of the times,
states: The more exacdy the ground plan of nature is projected, the more exact
becomes the possibility of experiment. Hence the much cited medieval Schoolman in his assertion of the supremacy of experiment, and in his contempla­
Roger Bacon can never be the forerunner of the modem experimental research tion that it is difficult to conceive how such a character could then exist.4*
scientist; rather he remains the successor of Aristotle.. . . Therefore, the discussion
of the words and doctrinal opinions of the various authorities takes precedence in This view of Roger Bacon as an experimentalist in the sense of Francis
the acquiring of knowledge in the Middle Ages. The componere scripta et sermones, the Bacon, a kind of precursor born out of his time, became standard
argumentum ex verbo, is decisive and at the same time is the reason why the accepted
Platonic and Aristotelian philosophy that had been taken over had to be trans­ fare in the nineteenth century and in the early part of the twentieth.
formed into Scholastic dialectic. If, now, Roger Bacon demands the experimentum— Those works of Bacon, which were published in the 19th century
and he does demand it—he does not mean the experiment of science as research; did tend to provide some evidence for this point of view since they
rather he wants the argumentum ex re instead of the argumentum ex verbo, the careful
observing of the things themselves, i.e. Aristotelian empeiria, instead of the discussion dealt with the more experimental side of Bacon’s thought. Further,
of doctrines. (In Martin Heidegger, The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, there was some evidence in the works of Roger Bacon which could
trs. William Lovitt, New York: Harper and Row, 1977, 122.)
3 See G.E.R. Lloyd, Methods and Problems in Greek Science: Selected Papers, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1991, 70-99. See pp. 79-81 on experiments relating to
refraction in optics. And see 81-99 in regard to acoustics and to medical experi­ 4 William Whewell, History of the Inductive Sciences from the Earliest Times to the Present
ments. As will become apparent belong, these issues arise again in the case of Roger Times, Vol. I, New York, 1859, 245. See also Robert Adamson, Roger Bacon: The
Bacon. Philosophy of Science in the Middle Ages, Manchester, 1876.
280 JEREMIAH HACKETT 281
ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTALIS

suggest parallels with some aspects of Francis Bacon’s thought. But duplicate and confirm “the medieval status of experimental method
there were certainly other aspects which did not. which we have already obtained from other earlier sources.”8 Fur­
The picture of Bacon’s Scientia experimentalis by some 19th century ther, he argues that Bacon’s experimenta were not dissimilar to the
scholars as the parent of modem experimental science was shattered experiments found in the works of Robert Grosseteste, William of
by the scholarship of Lynn Thorndike and Pierre Duhem in the second Auvergne, Peter of Spain and Albertus Magnus. He found Bacon’s
decade of this century. The romantic image gave way to a more works to be lacking in an account of the laboratory equipment, instru­
realistic portrait. Pierre Duhem devoted much attention to two areas ments and the exact measurements of modem science.
of Bacon’s interest, his physics and astronomy. His comments on However, Thorndike himself tended to see an incipient “inductive
Bacon’s Scientia experimentalis are, however, very brief. Duhem con­ method” in Bacon’s account of experimental science. He argues that
cluded that Bacon’s experimental science did not constitute a distinct Bacon “approaches” the notion of “an inductive method through
special science. In his view, it was simply a means of replacing the regulated and purposive observation and experience to the discovery
notion of reason with that of experience. The function of experience of tru th .. . .”9 Thorndike’s caution in stating that Bacon “approaches”
was to test the truth of all rational statements about nature. Duhem the modern inductive method was due to the fact that, in his view,
saw Bacon’s praise of verification as a praise of observation alone, Bacon’s experimental method
and he concluded that Bacon did not know experimental method in
the Modem sense of that term.5 is not, like modem experimentation, the source but “the goal of all
speculation”. It is not so much an inductive method of discovering
Raoul Carton accepted Duhem’s interpretation and presented a scientific truth, as it is applied science, the putting the results of the
synthesis of all the passages by Bacon on Scientia experimentalis. Verifi­ “speculative” sciences to the test of practical utility.10
cation (<certificate) in his view was an intuition (intuitio) of the truth of
a statement by means of an experienced effect, that is, what hap­ In his analysis of the medical, alchemical, and astrological examples
pened to be the case experientially. Thus, the central role of practi­ of experimental science in Opus maius, part six, Thorndike maintained
cal experience was its utility in confirming or falsifying any given that the experimental “science” of Bacon was especially connected
statement. For Carton, Bacon was very definitely a utilitarian or per­ with alchemy and astrology. In this he saw himself as one who exposed
haps a pragmatist in the sense of one who sought to prove truths by “the faults of Bacon’s learning, his superstition and credulity, his
the way in which they worked out in practice.6 belief in alchemy and astrology.”11 Further, he argued that “Bacon
Lynn Thorndike wrote a number of studies on the Scientia expe­ fails in his attempt to draw the fine between science and magic.”12
rimentalis of Roger Bacon between 1914 and 1929. Thorndike stated In his view, then, Bacon placed occult science at the center of his
that “it is admitted by many that Bacon did not anticipate modern experimental method and in the end his Scientia experimentalis was little
inventions by actual discoveries” and that “Bacon’s outspoken criti­ more than the recognition of experience as a criterion of truth and
cism of the learning of his age is no longer unquestioningly accepted.”7
In Thorndike’s view, Roger Bacon’s experiments did little more than 8 Lynn Thorndike, A History of Magic and Experimental Science, II, New York, 1929, 650.
9 Ibid., 650.
10 Ibid., 650-51. On the manifold meaning of Induction and its uses in Medieval
philosophy, see Julius R. Weinberg, “Historical Remarks on Some Medieval Views
5 Pierre Duhem, Le systeme du Monde: Histoire des Doctrines Cosmologiques de Platon a of Induction,” in his Abstraction, Relation and Induction: Three Essays in the History of
Copemic, T. Ill, Paris, 1915, 442. Thought, (Madison & Milwaukee: The University of Wisconsin Press, 1965), 121-53.
6 Raoul Carton, L ’Experience Physique chez Roger Bacon, Paris, 1924, 60: . . . et cette Here one finds evidence that Medieval authors use different forms of inductive
idee inspiratrice, c’est L’Utilitarisme; la notion Baconienne de la certitude et de la argument based on the forms of argument inherited from Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics,
certification en derive comme une consequence necessaire. C ’est un principe including some that seem to be like Mill’s Method of Agreement. Yet, notwithstand­
categorique chez Roger Bacon qu’en toutes choses il faut considerer avant tout l’utilite ing the subtlety of formal argument in both Scotus and Ockham, it should not be
{ante omnia utilitas cujuslibet rei consideranda est). thought that these thinkers, including Roger Bacon, have the version of inductive
7 Lynn Thorndike, “Roger Bacon and Experimental Method in the Middle Ages,” argument as formulated by Francis Bacon. See Weinberg, p. 153. There are antici­
Philosophical Review, 23 (1914), 271—298. See ibid., “The True Roger Bacon I,” and pations of this in medieval authors but not this precise formulation.
“The True Roger Bacon II,” in The American Historical Review, 21 (1916), 237-57; 11 Lynn Thorndike, “Roger Bacon and Experimental M ethod. . 275.
468-80. 12 Ibid.., A History of Magic and Experimental Science, 666.
282 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTAUS 283

“a promulgation of the phrase ‘experimental science.’ ”13 George Sarton most thoroughly grasped, and who most elaborately developed
followed Thorndike in arguing that Bacon did not suceed in separat­ Grosseteste’s attitude to the nature and theory of science was Roger
ing Science and Magic. Neveretheless, he accepted what he called Bacon. . . .”18 Crombie looked to Bacon’s theory of the Rainbow in
“the essential soundness of his (Bacon’s) experimental point of view,” Opus maius, part six, as the crucial illustration of a theory of experi­
and claimed that Bacon’s greatest claim to fame was “his vindication ment which had been formulated by Grosseteste in his Commentary on
of the experimental spirit.” He added: the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle. He was certainly correct in his view
He was not himself an experimenter any more than he was a mathema­
that Bacon in both Opus maius, parts five and six, had Grosseteste’s
tician, but he clearly saw— better than anybody else in his time— that commentary in mind. Thus, he did show that there is a definite kind
without experimentation and without mathematics, natural philosophy of Scientific Method involved in Bacon’s works. This forced scholars
is very soon reduced to verbiage.14 to reconsider Duhem’s thesis of a pure empiricism in Bacon.
Crombie’s account, however, raised two issues. First, despite his
In the post-World War II period, Stewart C. Easton in his Roger
care in the use of such terms as “induction” and “falsification”, the
Bacon and the Search for a Universal Science drew attention to the Secretum
secretorum as a catalyst for Bacon’s experimental ideas.15 impression was given that Bacon was really a Popperian. And sec­
ond, by an omission of the “occult” aspects of Bacon’s thought, one
In his study Robert Grosseteste and the Origins of Experimental Science,
got the impression that Bacon was more modern than he is. Paolo
1200-1700, A.C. Crombie opened up a new chapter in the study of
Rossi commented that “. . . one cannot ignore, on the other hand
both medieval science in general and of the experimental method of
Roger Bacon. He challenged the common approach of scholars such certain basic opinions by which Bacon showed himself to be a man
as Duhem, Carton, and Thorndike. In Crombie’s view, Bacon based of his time, heir to the hermetic tradition.”19
More recent research has focused on Bacon’s account of the rain­
his idea of an experimental science on an explicit notion of a true
scientific method. This more rational scientific method was based on bow.2.0 And there have been some studies of the general nature of
his experimental method.21 In the present volume, studies of Bacon’s
the applications by Bacon of Robert Grosseteste’s commentary on
the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle. Crombie went a step further stating: alchemy and medicine assist in gaining a more secure knowledge of
Bacon’s contributions in these fields.22 And the study of the Secretum
The thesis of this book is that the modem, systematic understanding of secretorum allows one to see the uses of Scientia experimentalis in Roger
at least the qualitative aspects of this method was created by the philoso­ Bacon.23*
phers of the West in the thirteenth century. It was they who trans­
formed the Greek geometrical Method into the experimental science
odology, see Em an McMullen, The Inference that Makes Science, Marquette University
of the modem world.16
Press, 1992 (Aquinas lecture 1992).
18 Ibid., 139.
According to Crombie, both Grosseteste and Bacon believed that 19 Paolo Rossi, Francis Bacon: From Magic to Science, Chicago (Midway reprint), 1978,
“Scientific knowledge, properly speaking, was thus, demonstrative 28. See 239, n. 99.
knowledge of things through causes, and its instmment was the demon­ 20 Carl B. Boyer, The Rainbow: From Myth to Mathematics, New York: Thomas Yoseloff,
1959, 111-124; William A. Wallace, O.P., The Scientific Methodology of Theodoric of
strative syllogism.”17 In Crombie’s considered view, “the writer who Freiberg, Freibourg, Switzerland: University Press, 1959, 174-226; David C. Lindberg,
“Roger Bacon’s Theory of the Rainbow: Progress or Regress,” Isis 57 (1966), 236-
49. See David C. Lindberg, Studies in the History of Medieval Optics (London: Variorum
Reprints), 1983 for a selection of papers on Bacon’s science.
13 Ibid., “Roger Bacon and Experimental Method .. 283. 21 N.W. Fisher and Sabetai Unguru, “Experimental Science and Mathematics,”
14 George Sarton, Introduction to the History o f Science, II, pt. 2, Baltimore, 1931, Traditio 27 (1971), 353-78; Malgorzata Frankowska, Scientia wujeciu Rogera Bacona,
953. See also 959. Warsaw: I.H.S.T. of the Polish Academy of Sciences and Technology, Monographs,
15 Stewart C. Easton, Roger Bacon and his Search for a Universal Science, New York, Vol. 55, 1969; English trs. Science as Interpreted by Roger Bacon, trs. Ziemislaw Zienkiewicz,
1952. See 75-77, 176. (Warsaw: Central Institute for Scientific Technical and Economic Information, 1971).
16 A.C. Crombie, Robert Grosseteste and the Origins o f Experimental Science, 1200-1700, 22 See papers by Faye Getz and William Newman in present volume.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1953, 1. 23 See Steven J. Williams, “Roger Bacon and His Edition of the Pseudo-Aristotelian
17 Ibid., 155-6. For a new consideration of demonstration in Grosseteste’s meth- Secretum secretorum, Speculum 69 (1994), 57-73.
284 JEREMIAH HAGKETT ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTALIS 285

In this account I will attempt to interpret Bacon’s Scientia experimentalis Aristotle’s Meteorologica and Seneca’s Maturates quaestiones. These sources
on the basis of his texts and in the light of our current knowledge are qualified by material from ibn al-Haytham and from Robert
of Bacon and his contemporaries. I will look at the following issues: Grosseteste.
(1) What were his Sources? (2) the relation of the Scientia experimentalis The second prerogative of experimental science, knowledge gained
{Opus maius, part six) to the Perspectiva {Opus maius, part five) (3) the by experience with instruments and with medicine draws on Ptolemy’s
source for a “new” use of Scientia experimentalis (4) the distinction Almagest, Al-Betrugi, Aristotle, Galen, Haly Abbas, the Secretum secretorum,
between Argumentum and Experimentum (5) The definition of Experi­ Pliny, Avicenna. The third prerogative on the Prognostication of the
ence and the need for an Experimental Science (6) The Three Pre­ future draws on Ptolemy, Almagestum pawum {Be dispositione spherae).26
rogatives of this science in detail (7) The uses of this science (8) Bacon The section on applied science draws on the Secretum secretorum as
and Experiment. well as on Pliny.

2. Bacon’s Scientia experimentalis: a Reconsideration (2) The status of a science o f the rainbow and a Scientia experimentalis
Already in the work of Aristotle, there is considerable difficulty con­
(1) The sources o f Bacon’s science cerning the name of that science to which the science of the rainbow
It would be no exaggeration to state that Bacon had access to all the is subordinated. Is it part of Physical Does it involve going beyond a
available knowledge from Greek and Arabic sources which a Medi­ pure demonstrative science in the sense of having to deal with opin­
eval author after 1260 could use. Here, a comparison with Robert ion, conjecture and with a semiotics?27* And in the case of strict
Grosseteste is instructive. Whereas the latter had access to some ancient demonstration, is there a demonstrative science of the “fact” {quia) as
work on perspectiva and on the rainbow {Be iride), Roger Bacon had there* is for the “reason for the fact” {Propter quid)? How does the
access to most of the Greek material on optics, especially Ptolemy study of the experimental topics in Opus maius, part six relate to
and Pseudo-Ptolemy, and he had mastered the Be aspectibus of Ibn
al-Haytham (Alhacen). In my view, this latter work enabled Bacon Bacon’s account this is grounded in the notion of a history of truth and an Augus-
tinian doctrine of illumination. That moral character and scientific insight was related
to extend an understanding of the optics of the rainbow which he in the educational process, see Therese-Anne Druart, “Al-Kindi’s Ethics,” Review of
had inherited from Anstotle. And it allowed him to make some adjust­ Metaphysics 47 (December 1993), 329-357. This is instructive since Bacon drew heavily
ments to the material which he had found in Seneca. The primary on Al-Kindi’s De radiis, De aspectibus, and knew his Theorica artium Magicarum.
26 Almagestum pawum (De dispositione spherae) or Almagesti minoris libri VI is the Intro­
sources for the introduction to Opus maius, part six are Aristotle and duction to the Almagest which is based on Geminus’ Introduction to the Phenomena. For
Euclid. For his account of experience, he relies on Pseudo-Ptolemy, the medieval Latin MSS, see Lynn Thorndike and Pearl Kibre, A Catalogue of Incipits
Centiloquium?4 His account of a phenomenology of moral and reli­ of Mediaeval Scientific Writings in Latin, Cambridge, Mass., 1963, 442. Latin translation
from Arabic by Gerard of Cremona. See Germaine Aujac, ed. and trs., Geminos.
gious experience is based on traditional Jewish, Arabic and Christain Introduction aux Phenomenes, Paris, 1975.
sources.2425*The two basic texts for the doctrine of the Rainbow were 27 Jacques Brunschwig, “Aristote et le statut epistemologique de le theorie de l’arc-
en-ciel,” in Lloyd P. Gerson, ed. Graceful Reason: Essays in Ancient and Medieval Philosophy
Presented to Joseph Owens, CSSR. Papers in Medieval Studies 4, Toronto: Pontifical
Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1983, 115-34; On the need to examine endoxa in
24 On the whole issue of the Pseudo-Ptolemaic Centiloquium, see above. For the Aristotle’s account of Meteorological phenomena, see Cynthia A. Freeland, “Scientific
idea of Bacon’s experimental science, this text must be read in the context of other Explanation and Empirical Data in Aristotle’s Meteorology,” Oxford Studies in Ancient
related works on experience and experimentum. See the works of Raoul Carton for a Philosophy, ed. Julia Annas, Vol. VIII, 1990, 67-102. This latter need has much
complete list of all references to experience in Bacon. implication for Roger Bacon’s treatment of meteorological phenomena. That is, it is
25 On the issue of moral and religious experience, Bacon is drawing on traditonal in Opus maius, part three that he provides a theory of signs and in parts four and
Neoplatonic ideas as mediated in Jewish, Christian and Islamic traditions. See espe­ six, an application of a theory of signs to issues in science. Thus, in Bacon’s science,
cially the influence of al-Ghazali here and of the main elements of the mystical path one is not dealing with a pure deductive demonstrative science alone. As will be
of knowledge. It is important to note that Bacon holds the view that moral wareness apparent from the texts, the latter is much qualified by a concern for Endoxa and
and religious devotion are not unconnected with the scientific search for truth. In for signs.
286 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTALIS 287

Perspectiva in Opus maius, part five. Grosseteste had addressed the topic goes one step beyond these sciences and demands a more intensive
in his Commentary on the Posterior Analytics,28 investigation of the phenomena.
In the subaltemation of the sciences in Aristotle, the middle sciences Nevertheless, the treatment of the rainbow and related phenom­
(scientiae media) such as optics, harmonics and astronomy were neither ena in Opus maius, part six, are properly located as phenomena which
purely mathematical nor purely physical. In the case of optics, geom­ can be studied by means of perspectiva, the science of radiant lines,
etry is the proper mode of demonstration. Thus, knowledge of “the angles and figures, and consequently come after the treatment of
reason for the fact” (propter quid) was provided by Geometry, while Perspectiva.
knowledge of “the fact” was given by the subalternated science. In
this case, optics as the science of radiant lines, angles and figures (3) The sources for the term Scientia experimentalis
provided a knowledge of the “fact”. In Bacon’s view as in that of
Grosseteste, geometry provided the mathematical reason for the fact. Already in Grosseteste’s Commentary on the Posterior Analytics, one finds
But luminous agency as well as physio-psychological activity had to a clear analysis of the notion of experimentum.30 Posterior Analytics II, 19
be accounted for. and related Aristotelian texts are important here. “From sense comes
The higher science, geometry, therefore accounted for one aspect memory, and from the repetition of many memories an experimentum
of the whole phenomenon. One still had need of physical and psy­ and from the experience (ex experiment) the universal which is apart
chological sciences. from the particular. Yet the universal is not separate from the par­
Roger Bacon inherited this position from Grosseteste. However, in ticular, but is the same as them, of art that is and the science of
Opus maius, part six, concerning the rainbow, he notes: principles.”31 For Grosseteste, there is no problem for incomplex truths,
but in the case of “experimental universals which are complex
The Natural Philosopher (Aristotle) discusses these phenomena, and the
(universalia complexa experimentalia), verification is needed.” The actual
writer on Perspective (Ibn al-Haytham) has much to add pertaining to
the moder of vision that is necessary in this case. But neither Aristotle grasp of the experimental universal is twofold. First, one has to formu­
nor Avicenna in their Natural Histories has given us a knowledge of phe­ late a hypothesis and a possible cause. This induction from experi­
nomena of this kind, nor has Seneca, who composed a special book on ence brings the mind to the formulation of a true proposition whose
them. But Experimental Science gives an account of these phenomena.29 truth must be tested. The testing comes through or by means of
Bacon it would seem not merely subordinates the science of radiant experience or more properly an experimentum. This involves a collatio,
lines (perspectwa) to Geometry; he also emphasises that traditional Natu­ a gathering together which is the work of reasonable intelligence and
ral Philosophy and Perspectiva do not go far enough in investigating not just of instinct alone.
The central issue then concerns the extent to which Experimentum
the physical phenomena themselves. Thus, the Scientia experimentalis
in Grosseteste does or does not differ from the Aristotelian empeiria,
and in what manner Grosseteste does anticipate modern views.
28 Robert Grosseteste, Commentarium in Posteriorum Analyticomm Libros, ed. Pietro Rossi,
Crombie’s thesis is simply that the qualitative model of a science is
Firenze: Leo S. Olshki, 1981 (Corpus Philosophorum Medii Aevi, II); De iride, ed. set out by Grosseteste. He does not argue that Grosseteste uses the
Ludwig Baur, Die Philosophischen Werke des Robert Grosseteste, Munster: Aschendorff, quantitative methods of post-Cartesian science.32
1912. See William A. Wallace, Causality and Scientific Explanation, Vol. I: Mediaeval and
Early Modem Science (Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 1972), 27-47;
James A. Weisheipl, The Development of Physical Theory in the Middle Ages (Ann Arbor:
The University of Michigan Press, 1971), 61; W.R. Laird, The Scientiae Mediae in 30 Ed. cit., 403-8.
Commentaries on Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics (University of Toronto Ph.D., 1983) and 31 Ibid., 404—5.
Ibid., “Robert Grosseteste and the subaltemate sciences,” Traditio, xliii (1987), 147- 32 See E. Serene, “Robert Grosseteste on Induction and Demonstrative Science,”
69 for an account of the subordination of the sciences and for the idea of a scientia Synthese 40 (1979), 97-115; Steven P. Marrone, William of Auvergne and Robert Grosseteste:
media (middle science), which is intermediate between mathematics and the science New Ideas of Truth in the Early Thirteenth Century (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University
of nature. Press, 1983); Ibid., “Robert Grosseteste on the Certitude of Induction,” in L ’Homme
29 Opus maius, part six, ed. Bridges, 173. I am preparing a critical edition of this text. et son Unvvers au Moyen Age, ed. Christian Wenin, Louvain-la-Neuve, 1986, Vol. II,
288 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTALIS 289

Perhaps, at this point, it would be useful to note the re-currence Bacon take over a whole “rhetoric” of experientia-experimentum from
in Roger Bacon of sources found in Grosseteste for experimenta which the Introductorium maius of Abu Ma'shar.36
are non-Aristotelian. This will indicate the extent to which both As we noted in the chapter on Astronomy and Astrology, Roger
Grosseteste and Bacon are in debt to “books” on ancient science Bacon takes over and uses many of these same sources for the termi­
and not only to some experimentation on their own part. nology of Scientia experimentalis. There is, however, one new element
Already in Grosseteste one notices a strong connection between in Roger Bacon which gives a greater scientific precision to his use
astronomy, optics and experientia. In De iride, he states “The visual of the term.
rays penetrating through several transparent substances of diverse
natures is refracted at their junctions. . . .” This is revealed by that Bacon’s debt to Ibn al-Haytham: Experientia, experimentum (ictibar)
experiment in the book De speculis. This leads Grosseteste to a consid­
It is the considered view of A.I. Sabra that Ibn al-Haytham intro­
eration of the Law of Refraction: that the angle of refraction equals
duced a “new” concept of experiment into the medieval debates.
half of the angle of incidence. Bruce C. Eastwood has seriously ques­
That is, he introduced a concept of experiment was different in kind
tioned the “experimental” nature of this proof.33 And he is correct in
from the notion of experience (empeiria) found in Aristotle. The Arabic
this. Grosseteste and Bacon in turn simply took the geometry from
word itibar is translated in Latin by experimentatio and its cognates.
Ancient Authors, especially Ptolemy and Ibn al-Haytham. The same
Due to the influence of Ptolemy’s Almagest the notion of a practical
is the case with references to other experimenta. For example, in De
test in Astronomy brought about an ideal of the experimental test.
sphera, De cometis and elsewhere. In De natura locorum, he criticises Ps.
This was due naturally to the need for accurate comparisons with
Aristotle and Averroes on the basis of “the experiments and reasons
Tables and with correct observations. A.I. Sabra notes that a change
of Aristotle, Ptolemy and other authors.”3435In De cometis, he uses the
in the meaning of the Term was bound to happen when ictibar was
Ps. Ptolemy, Centiloquium. He takes his theory of the tides from Abu
transferred to an experimental discipline like Optics. He states:
Ma'shar. And a reference to heat in the tropics is taken from the
Ps. Ptolemy, De dispositione spherae?b In general, both Grosseteste and Testing remains as a form of proof, but a proof in which physical
properties were directly investigated, sometimes with the aid of an
experimental apparatus especially designed for the purpose. And the
481-488. In the former work, Marrone argues “It is important to remember that aim of the proof was to bring certainty or exactness and precision to
Grosseteste held that the principles of science are verified by experiment, but not the an observation by subjecting it to an artificial situation in which con­
conclusions (my italics). Scientific reasoning per se was deductive, concerned with formal, ditions could be varied. To operate explicitly with such a distinct concept
logical inference of conclusions from certain principles.” (p. 276, n. 158). See p. 273: of experimental proof while regularly attaching it to a definite set of
W hat is more he meant by “experiment” what we mean by it today, a controlled terms (i'tibar and its cognates), and thus dissociating it from the idea of
procedure intended to verily a scientific hypothesis. Such a notion is not found in
Aristotle, and Grosseteste probably came upon the idea in the works of Arabic
accumulated experience or empeiria, was a significant conceptual develop­
science, etc. ment in the history o f experimental science. It remains true, however,
33 Bruce C. Eastwood, “Grosseteste’s ‘Quantitative’ Law of Refraction: A Chap­ that the confirmatory experiments in I.H.’s Optics differ in at least one
ter in the History of Experimental Science,” Journal of the History of Ideas, 28 (1967), respect from the discovery experiments o f seventeenth-century optics: they
403-415; see also Ibid., Astronomy and Optics from Pliny to Descartes: Texts, Diagrams and do not reveal new properties, such as diffraction, double refraction or
Conceptual Structures, Aldershot: Variorum reprints, 1989. dispersion of light; and although some of them are supported in a
34 Robert Grosseteste, Die Philosophische Werke, ed. cit., 66.
remarkable way by geometrical arguments (e.g. I, 3 [48-67]), they lack
35 See Jeremiah Hackett, “Scientia experimentalis: From Robert Grosseteste to
Roger Bacon,” in James McEvoy, ed., Robert Grosseteste: Mew Perspectives on His Thought measurement.37
and Scholarship, Dordrecht, 1995 (Instrumenta Patristica, XXVII), 89-120; See for
Grosseteste on experientia and experimentalis, 109-113. One should note Grosseteste’s
remark to the effect that not only did he and his contemporaries find experimenta Grosseteste: Roger of Hereford and Calendar Reform in 11th and 12th Century
in books, but they sought their own experimenta: “Et hoc plus consonat ei quod England,” Isis, 86, 4 (Dec. 1995), 562-86.
invenimus per experimentum nostri temporis de antecessione solsticii.” (Steele, Computus 36 Abu Ma'shar, Introductorium maius. Introduction. A critical edition of this work
correctorius, 215) [For Grosseteste’s Computus, see Jennifer Moreton “Robert Grosseteste by Richard Lemay has been published from the Oriental Institute, Naples, for 1997.
and the Calendar,” in James McEvoy ed. cit:, See also Jennifer Moreton, “Before 37 A.I. Sabra, The Optics of Ibn al-Haytham: Books I—III On Direct Vision, Vol. II,
290 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTALIS 291

It is clear then from both Opus maius, part five and six, that Roger what can be known, yet because they lack experience they neglect
Bacon has pushed the notion of an experimental science beyond the the arguments and neither avoid what is harmful nor follow what is
empeiria of Aristode. He is actively seeking the kind of experimental good.”40 Bacon then gives the example of a person who has never
test which Ibn al-Haytham outlines in his Optics. In this respect, it is seen a fire. Such a person may have a notion of a fire but will not
well to note that in a recent study, A.C. Crombie indicates that Bacon avoid one. He then turns to Mathematics and provides an example
in his Questions On the First Philosophy of Aristotle (ca. 1240’s) was already from Euclid to which he then attaches some important texts from
grappling with this problem.*38 In Crombie’s interpretation, Bacon has Aristotle. It is important to look at these texts.
already moved the issue of experiment away from the treatment of Bacon’s use of Euclid, I, prop, i: that an equilateral triangle can be
the experimental universal in Grosseteste and onto the issue of a constructed with any given line segment as a base, is intended as
practical test.39 One can state then that quite a significant advance evidence for his thesis that in certain kinds of knowledge experience is
occurs in Bacon’s appropriation of the Optics of Ibn al-Haytham and an absolute requirement. While this example will suggest the case of
its application to issues concerning the secondary stars, that is, to the the Meno as outlined in Posterior Analytics I, Bacon seems to be stating
rainbow, halo and related phenomena. One will notice too that Bacon that in Geometry, a person will not have certainty unless there is an
sees the need for much more “particular” experiments in order to actual intuition of the spatial lines.41 Is he simply stating that one
discover the structure of these phenomena in greater detail. needs a drawing as a visual aid? O r is something more significant
being implied? He seems to be stating that in the case of mathemat­
ics, his great example of certified proof, logic alone is not sufficient.
(4) Argumentum and Experimentum: Opus maius, six, Ch. 1
Without the combination of the two ways of knowledge, argumentum
Bacon presents this distinction as follows: “For there are two modes and experimentum, verified knowledge is not to be had. Here, Bacon
of acquiring knowledge, namely, by reasoning and by experience. Rea­ seems, to be stating that geometrical reasoning cannot proceed “ana­
soning draws a conclusion, but does not make the conclusion cer­ lytically” according to logical concepts alone. The pure analysis of
tain, nor does it remove doubt so that the mind may rest in the the concept of the properties of lines and angles will not yield new
intuition of the truth (in intuitu veritatis), unless the mind discovers it knowledge. Rather the seeing or intuition of the triangle will lead to
by the path of Experience. Since many have arguments concerning clear inferential knowledge guided by an experiential intuition.
When one looks at the Aristotelian references, one notices certain
oddities. He seems to be not merely repeating Aristotle’s words, but
London: The Warburg Institute, University of London, 1989, 18-19. See G. Federici
Vescovini, Studi sulla perspectiva medievale, (Turin, 1965); Ibid., art. cit. below; David C.
Iindberg, Theories of Visionfrom Al-Kindi to Kepler, (Chicago & London: The University 40 Opus maius, part six, Bridges, ed. 167.
of Chicago Press, 1976). Professor Sabra is correct in stating that the medieval 41 Bacon’s discussion here is clearly based on Aristotole’s Posterior Analytics, book
experiments did not reveal “new” properties such as diffraction etc., but does this one. The issue at stake: whether geometrical lines and angles are to be understood
not beg another question? In the middle ages, in both Arabic and Latin science, the in a purely analytical manner or whether some form of intuition is involved in the
stage was reached where experimental a device— Ibn al-Haytham’s refraction construction of the proofs does go back to Aristotle. Thus, Bacon must not be inter­
instrument was used to gain “new” knowledge of the basics of Refraction. That had preted here as though he is following Plato in the Meno. In Aristode, one must intuit
to come first. But in its day, that was experiment in the service of discovery of new the existence and nature of those straight lines that are presupposed by geometrical
knowledge. This applies too to Witelo’s use of such an instrument. See S. Unguru proof. See Thomas V. Upton, “Aristode on Hypothesis and the Unhypothesized First
below. Further, more knowledge of Medieval Calculation and Mathematics will extend Principle,” Review of Metaphysics 39 (Dec. 1985), 283-301. See p. 285, n. 5: What
our awareness of just how much measurement was used by these experiments. must be stressed is that the upward movement of thought in geometrical analysis is
38 A.C. Crombie, Styles of Scientific Thinking in the European Tradition: The History intuitive and not (always) through necessary inference, etc. See also p. 294.
o f Argument and Explanation especially in the Mathematical and Biomedical Sciences and Arts, This Euclidian example and related ones play a major role in the philosophy of
Vol. I, London: Duckworth, 1994, 335-7. See also Jeremiah Hackett, “Scientia geometry and epistemology. For a discussion of this issue with K ant’s use of the
experimentalis: From Robert Grosseteste to Roger Bacon,” 107-109. same examples as Bacon, see Michael Friedman, Kant and the Exact Sciences, Cam­
39 A.C. Crombie, Styles of Scientific Thinking, Vol. I, 337: Here Bacon subdy moved bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1992, 55-93. I am not claiming that Bacon’s
the meaning of experimentum from the context of Aristotle’s psychology of knowledge position and that of Kant are the same, but I do wish to argue that both offer a
acquired through the senses to that of the experimental practical test. criticism of a pure analytic theory of geometrical knowledge.
292 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTALIS 293

rather to be changing their meaning. First, to the remark in Posterior mous Ptolemaic sources, Abu M a'shar and other writers on Astron-
Analytics 7 lb 16-20: “By demonstration I mean a syllogism produc­ omy/Astrology, Ptolemy himself, and especially from Ibn al-Haytham.
tive of syllogistic knowledge . . he adds: “This is to be understood
as if the demonstration were accompanied by the appropriate expe­
(5) The definition of Experimental Science
rience, and not of bare demonstrative proof.”42 The difficulty here
is that in strict Aristotelian scientific inference, one does not need a Bacon defines experience as follows:
further “looking at” the phenomenon. The syllogism itself yields a
Experience is two-fold. One kind is gained through our external senses,
necessary conclusion.
and in this manner we gain experiences of things in the heavens by
Second, in Metaphysica 981a23-981b9 concerning the superiority means of instruments in astronomy. We experience things on earth prima­
of art to experience, and the superiority of the artist and wise person rily by means o f vision, and by the testimony of scientists who have had
to the person of experience. The latter only know the singular fact; authentic experiences of nature. . . . This experience is human and philosophical as
the former know the reason for the fact. Bacon adds: “But I am far as man can act according to the grace given him. But this experience
speaking about the man who knows the reason and the cause through is not sufficient because it does not give full testimony about corporeal
things due to its difficulty, and it does not touch on spiritual matters.
experience [Per experientiam).”434While Aristode does allow for knowl­ It is necessary, therefore, that the intellect of man be helped in another
edge via experience in the case of productive effects, this is not the manner, and for this reason, the holy patriarchs and prophets, who
case with pure scientific knowledge. Bacon develops this argument at first gave the sciences to the world, received illumination within and
length in the Communia mathematical Third, he cites the example of were not dependent on the senses alone . . . as Ptolemy (sic! Pseudo-
the person of intuition and gives a reference to Kicomachean Ethics, Ptolemy) states in the Centiloquium that there are two roads by which
we arrive at knowledge of facts: one through the experience of Phi­
Book Six.4546
losophy (and science) and the other through divine inspiration, which
It is clear from the Communia mathematica that Bacon is making a is- far better, as he states.47
critique of pure Syllogistic reasoning. He is stating that in the case of
mathematical demonstration, the mind will not find the truth unless We see here that Bacon is not just indebted to Ibn al-Haytham. In
the examples in geometry are generated. And he adds: “Again, Knowl­ this passage, he clearly distinguishes philosophical/scientific knowl­
edge per experientiam is better than per argumentum” and he cites Ibn edge gained by both instruments and by human vision from a kind
al-Haytham as a model for this cognitio per experientiam.^ of inspired knowledge. Here he is dependent on the Augustinian Doc­
Therefore, Roger Bacon is not simply repeating Aristotelian empeiria. trine of Divine Illumination which he supplements with the Ps.
He is supplementing Aristotle’s account of scientific knowledge with Ptolemy, Centiloquiumf8 This is the “illuminism” which scholars have
accounts of science taken from many sources, including the Pseudony­ found difficult in Bacon’s science. However, it does fit in with his
overall theory of truth in Opus maius, part two, and it does lead to a
greater emphasis on personal experiential insight over mere “book”
42 Analytka posteriora, liber primus, 71al-73a25, [A.L., IV, 1-4], ed. L. Minio-Paluello
and Bernard G. Dod, 1968; Opus maius, ed. cit., 168; See also Roger Bacon, Tractatus
knowledge.49
de experientia in communi, ed. Jeremiah Hackett, in The Meaning o f Experimental Science In what follows, Bacon presents a Medieval account of the structure
(Scientia Experimental) in the Philosophy of Roger Bacon, 273-4 (Toronto Ph.D., 1983)
43 Metaphysica 981a23-981b9: Opus maius, part six, ed. Bridges, 168: Q uod etiam
dicit primo Metaphysicae, quod habentes rationem et causam sunt superiores expertis, 47 Opus maius, part six, ed. cit. 169-70. See Jeremiah Hackett, Tractatus de experientia,
loquitur de expertis qui solum noscunt nudam veritatem sine causa. Sed hie loquor ed. cit., 281-282.
de experto, qui rationem et causam novit per experientiam. 48 Pseudo-Ptolemy, Centiloquium, Verbum I, commentary.
44 Communia mathematica, ed. Steele, 121-4 (Capitulum quintum de demonstratione 49 James A. Weisheipl, “Science in the Thirteenth Century,” in J.I. Catto, The
per experientiam). Early Oxford Schools, ed. cit., suggested that “The first difficulty seems to lie in such
45 Ethica nicomachea 41al0-41a20: While Aristotle explicitly refers to intuitive Reason Latin terms as experimentum, experimentator, experientia and the like as used by Grosseteste,
as the means of recognizing Principles, Bacon extends the notion of intuition to all Roger Bacon, Albert the Great, Bartholomaeus Anglicus and others in the thir­
kinds of intuitive experience. teenth century.” M odem readers sometimes take these words to refer to controlled
46 Communia mathematica, ed. cit., 124. laboratory procedures, thus misunderstanding the main distinction intended by these
294 JEREMIAH HACKETT 295
ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTALIS

of internal knowledge especially in terms of the moral virtues and in This one paragraph has much significance for Bacon’s project of a
terms of religious experience. This version follows a standard Fran­ Scientia experimentalis. First, one notes that it is his goal to devise a
ciscan account.50 And it indicates a concern with an internal Phenome­ method in the practical and speculative sciences, which in a manner,
nology of moral experience. Further, Bacon is stating that there are analogous to Logic will distinguish between the fraud of Magicians
experiences which are quite real but which cannot be “reduced” to and the Truth of Art and Science. The case of the Rainbow and
natural science. This latter account becomes even more important related phenomena is presented as an example of how to achieve
when Bacon presents his account of Science in chapter 2. this real scientific knowledge. It is also clear that Bacon has the
He states: polemical goal of convincing the Pope that a new scientific method
Since this E xperim ental Science is wholly unknown to the rank and file of is needed in the Universities of the Latin West. Lynn Thorndike was
university Students, I am therefore unable to convince people o f its utility correct in recognizing that the origins of Experimental Science in
unless a t the sam e tim e I disclose its excellence an d its p ro p e r m e an ­ the West was tied to the issue of Magic. Perhaps, he was too severe
ing. This science alone, therefore, Knows how to test perfectly what can be done on Bacon in regard to Magic. Bacon is quite clear that if one is to
by Nature, what by the effort of Art, what by Trickery, what the Incantations,
distinguish between Science and Magic, the scientist must know both
Conjurations, Invocations, Deprecations, and Sacrifices that belong to Mafic mean
and dream of, and what is in them, so that all falsity may be removed and the areas. When this section of the Opus maius is read with the Epistola de
Truth alone of Art and Nature may be retained. T h is science alone teaches us secretis operibus et de militate Magiae and related works, one sees that
how to view the m ad acts o f m agicians, th a t they m ay n o t be accepted Bacon set out a comprehensive task for scientific knowledge and for
b u t rejected, ju s t as Logic considers sophistical reasoning.51 the philosopher-scientist.5253*

authors. To avoid error it is best to translate experimentum and its cognates as (6) Bacon presents three prerogatives or tasks for this Scientific Method
“personal experience” and its cognates. The point is that there is a big difference
between knowing a truth solely from books (authority) and knowing the same truth (1) It investigates by experiment the notable conclusions of all the other
by personal experience, as between reading about Rainbows in Aristotle’s Meteorologica
and seeing a rainbow in the sky. The contrast is between book-learning alone and speculative sciences. “For the other sciences know how to discover their
books complemented by personal experience. The emphasis was neither a call to principles by reasoning drawn from Principles discovered (by experi­
controlled experimentation nor a rejection of reason and book-learning. Roger Bacon
singled out the “Method” of Grosseteste, who he said, “took no notice at all of
ence). But if they should have a Particular and Complete Experience of
Aristotle’s books and their methods (vim eorum) but from his own experience (per their own Conclusions, thy must have it with the aid of this noble Science.”33
experientiam propriam) and from other writers and from other sciences he found out
and wrote more than a hundred thousand times as many things as are discussed in
Aristotle’s books or as could be taken from the perverse translations of the same.” etc.
See comment on the above passage in Graziella Federici Vescovini, “La Fortune 52 Epistola de secretis operibus. .., Brewer ed. dt. This means that Bacon sees a task
De L’Optique D ’Ibn Al-Haitham”, art. cit., 227: Neanmoins, Bacon est tres influence of the experimenter to be one of separating those books and works which are true
par la doctrine d’Alhazen de l’experience comme observation, vision sensible: c’est- SCIENCE and ART from those which are pure MAGIC. This was the task under­
a-dire que Bacon developpe sa theorie de la perspective comme science experimentale, taken by the author of the Speculum astronomiae. Pierre Mandonnet had a strong belief
scientia experimentalis, sur le fondement de la doctrine de la vision optique d’Alhazen; that Bacon was the author of this work, but the consensus of the Scholarship holds
mais il est spiritualiste et dualiste et pour cela il subordonne la science experimentale that Albertus Magnus is the author. See Paola Zambelli, The Speculum Astronomiae and
exterieure, c’est-a-dire sa perspective, a la vision spirituelle, divine, interieure. En its Enigma: Astrohgy, Theology and Science in Albertus Magnus and his Contemporaries, Dordrecht-
d’autres mots, la connaissance sensible de la perspective, la scientia experimentalis exte­ Boston-London, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1992 (Boston Studies in the Philoso­
rior, est inferieure a la science de la vision interieure.. . . As she correctly notes, phy of Science, Volume 135). Unlike the Speculum astronomiae, which looks to one to
Bacon interprets Ibn al-Haytham’s account of experiential knowledge in the light of determine this issue, Bacon leaves it up to the personal judgment of each qualified
Avicenna’s philosophy. One might add here that the dominating text behind this experimenter. O n new work on Magic in the Middle Ages, see Richard Kieckhefer,
interpretation is the De Anima of Aristotle. Thus, Bacon is not a physicalist. He Mafic in the Middle Ages, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989, reprint 1992).
should be seen as one attempts to interpret sensible knowledge in the light of Augus­ 53 Opus maius, part six, ed. cit., 172-3. The Discovery of the principles of a science
tine, Avicenna and Aristode.
is of course discussed by Aristotle in Posterior Analytics, II, 19. This kind of discovery
50 See Ewart C. Cousins, Bonaxienture and the Coincidence of Opposites, (Chicago: The of the Principles of a science is to be carefully distinguished from the notion of
Franciscan Herald Press, 1978) for this topic in Bonaventure. discovery in the experimental sciences. Indeed, the word “induction” is so over-determined
51 Opus maius, ed. cit., 172
as to be misleading.
296 ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTALIS 297
JEREMIAH HACKETT

(2) Theoretical knowledge in science is not the only way. Independ- Roger Bacon on the Rainbow
endy, experience can yield new Instruments and new data. He gives We should begin by asking “why did Bacon concern himself with
the following as examples: experiments with Magnetism, the Armillary the questions of the Rainbow in 1266?” At this time, the Meteorologica
sphere, Cures in Medicine, development in Alchemy. It should be of Aristotle and the Commentary by Alexander of Aphrodisias were
noted that in the Communia mathematica, Bacon talks about instruments. being discussed in the Faculty of Arts.56 It is unfortunate that commen­
He states that Practical Geometry is concerned with the building of tary by both Siger of Brabant and Thomas Aquinas are not extant
instruments. These instruments of Experimental Science include the for the section on the rainbow in Meteorologica, Book III.57 But it is
Astrolabe, Mirrors and Instruments of War.54 clear that Bacon was led to this discussion due to his disagreement
(3) Experimental science is concerned with knowledge of the future. with the translation of this work by William of Moerbecke.58 Before
Here, Bacon touches on the relation of Astronomy/astrology to the dealing with Bacon’s account, it is important to note that it is intended
scientia experimentalis. He refers to the Almagestum parvum and notes that as an exemplum of an experimental science. It was never designed as
“this is the pathway of experiment, which follows the course of nature, a full Treatise. He did not have the leisure or circumstances to pro­
to which many philosophers who are believers are turning. . . .”55 duce one. But he did point the way.59*
This whole matter is difficult. Bacon’s comments are short. He seems While Bacon’s concern with the Rainbow is rooted in his reading
to think that there is a short cut around the normal practice of of both Aristotle and Seneca, it is worth noting here that his scien­
Astronomy/Astrology. That is, astronomical instruments, verified tables tific instincts were correct. He would not be the last philosopher to
and good computations are hard to find, and the use of instruments
is difficult. But this science (experimental science) can give an account
of the influence of the heavenly bodies (judicial astrology) without 56 Aristotle, Meteorologica, III; Alexander D ’Aphrodisias, Commentaire sur les Meteores
D ’Aristote, ed. A.J. Smet, c.p., Louvain, 1968 (Corpus Latinorum Commentariorum
the help of the ordinary Astronomy/Astrology. Bacon may have been in Aristotelem Graecorum, IV).
thinking of instant intuition or inspiration. This is, perhaps, the most 57 See Kevin White, “Three Previously Unpublished Chapters from St Thomas
unsatisfactory aspect of Opus maius, part six. And it must be read in Aquinas’s Commentary on Aristotle’s METEORA: SENTENTTA SUPER METEORA
2.13-15,” Mediaeval Studies 54 (1992), 49-93. Omar Argerami informs me that Siger
the light of the polemic on the deterministic consequences of astrology of Brabant’s Questions on the Meteorology book three are not extant.
in Opus maius, part four. 58 It is very clear that Bacon undertook the treatise on the Rainbow as a response
to contemporary discussions of William of Moerbecke’s novo translatio which reached
Paris in 1266. See Opus maius, part six, ed. cit., 179: considerandum est tamen hie
The remaining part of Opus maius, part six has to do with the appli­ quod secundum Aristotelem, praecipue in nova translatione. See J. Brams, “Guillaume
cations of science in statecraft and we will treat it at the end of this de Moerbeke et Aristote,” in Jacqueline Hamesse & M arta Fattori, eds., Recontres De
Cultures Dans La Phibsophie Medievab: Traductions E t Traducteurs De UAntiquite Tardive Au
paper. In what follows, I will simply give a presentation of the status X IV e Siecle, (Louvain-La-Neuve-Cassino, 1990), 317-336. See n. 1: Bien que Pinvective
of Bacon’s presentation of the Rainbow as a model of a Scientia de Bacon ne puisse etre prise a la lettre, son affirmation concemant l’intention de
experimentalis, and give a brief treatment of the second prerogative on Moerbecke peut tres bien contenir un noyau de verite; etc.
59 Opus maius, part six, ed. cit., 201: Et ideo nullus sermo in his potest certificare;
experience as a source of scientific knowledge. I will then present the totum enim dependet ex experientia. Et propter hoc non reputo me attigisse hie
conclusion on the applications of science, and end with some remarks plenam veritatem; quia nondum expertum sum omnia quae sunt hie necessaria, et
on Bacon’s science in relation to early modern experimental science. quia in hoc opere procedo via persuasionis, et ostensionis quae oporteat requiri in
studio sapientiae, et non per viam componendi SCRIPTA (my emphasis) de ea. Et
ideo non pertinet ad me hec hora dare certificationem impossibilem, sed sub forma
persuadendi de studio sapientiae pertransire.
We should note that Bacon’s circumstance as a retired Professor and active
Franciscan friar did not give him either the leisure or the means to do much Scien­
tific work after 1256. He complains of a ten year exile from active studies. Thus,
the works on the rainbow, halo and related pieces must be seen as polemical efforts
54 Ibid., 202-22; Communia mathematica, 44-47. to get the leading “legal” authority in European education to exercise Influence on
55 Ibid., 215-6; See Tractatus de experientia, ed. cit., 336-41. the Universities to encourage scientific experimentation.
298 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTAUS 299

point to the study of the rainbow as the great example or indeed sun above the horizon, and keeping the instrument immovable let him
experimentum cruris for an experimental science. One needs just to look turn in the opposite direction and look through the openings of the
instrument until he see the summit o f the bow, and let him note the
at Theodoric of Freiberg, Descartes, Spinoza and Newton among the altitude of the rainbow above the horizon; and he will find that
others.60 the higher the sun’s altitude is, the lower is that of the bow and con­
Bacon’s approach to the study of the rainbow is quite traditional versely . . . the Trained Experimenter can test until he discovers the
in that he attempts like Aristode to give a causal-scientific account.61 opposed altitude of the rainbow and of the sun, namely that beyond
(1) he isolates and describes the phenomenon; (2) He examines the which there can be not appearance of the rainbow. He must then give
his attention to the calculation of the altitude of the circles.. . .
Shape of the Colors; (3) He attempts the Measurement of the Alti­
The experimenter, therefore, taking the altitude of the Sun and of
tude of the Rainbow; (4) He studies the Size and Shape of the bow; the Rainbow above the horizon will find that the final altitude at which
(5) He examines the Time and Place of the rainbow; (6) He seeks the rainbow can appear above the horizon is 42 degrees, and this is the
the Cause of the rainbow in the sense of the material and efficient maximum elevation of the Rainbow.63
causes; (7) He examines the nature of the Appearance of the Colors in
This is the only calculation which we find in this treatise. And the
the cloud; (8) He studies the nature of the colors in the rainbow.
question naturally arises as to whether or not Bacon himself made
this observation and calculation. However, he does develop a related
Bacon recommends an examination of the rainbow using crystals,
issue, the observation and calculation of the Halo in Opus tertium,
an observation of the bow in drops of water, and of the colors in
and in that text he does provide evidence that he was accomplished
a corona around a candle. In other words, following Aristotle, he
in the uses of the Astrolabe.64
recommends that the experimenter examine the phenomenon very
Fourth, Bacon’s description of the size and shape of the rainbow
careful in all of its occurrences. And second, using these stones, one
is quite traditional and chapter five is dependent on Aristotle. Fifth,
should work out the shape of the colors. Bacon would also have
the account of the Time and Place of the bow is also traditional, and
found these remarks in both Aristotle and in Avicenna’s Treatise on
presupposes a knowledge of the De sphera of Sacrobosco.65
the Rainbow and Halo, and in Averroes.62 However, it is clear that
Sixth, perhaps the most interesting epistemological aspect of the
he was disappointed with Avicenna’s account, and believed that he
whole treatise is found in chapters seven and eight. Bacon sets out to
could offer a better analysis than the one found in Averroes.
discover “whether the bow is caused by incident, reflected or refracted
Third, Bacon seeks an accurate Measurement of the altiltude of
rays. And whether it is an image of the sun, as was assumed in the
the rainbow, and he sets out the ideal of strict measurement by means of
statements made on Perspectiva, and whether there are real colors in
instruments:
the cloud itself. He must also inquire concerning the variety and
Further, let the experimenter take the required instrument and look cause of the shape of the bow, since a statement was made above
through the openings o f the instrument and find the altitude of the just in regard to the size of its figure, namely, that sometimes it is a
complete circle, and sometimes a larger portion, and sometimes the
smaller. But to understand these matters we must use experiments
60 See references in A.C. Crombie, Robert Grosseteste and the Origins. . . , op. cit.
61 See William A. Wallace, Causality and Scientific Explanation, Vol. I: Medieval and certis”66
Early Modem Science, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press, 1972.
62 Most editions of Roger Bacon’s Opus maius, part six, omit any reference to
Avicenna and Averroes. In Opus maius, Bacon is critical of Avicenna on the Rain­ 63 Opus maius, part six, ed. Bridges, 175.
bow, and he does use the text of Averroes on Meteorologies, Book III. In fact, when 64 Opus tertium, ed. Pierre Duhem, 137-148; see ed. A.G. Little for same text. It
the section on the rainbow is taken in conjunction with Bacon’s treatment of the should be pointed out that Bacon studies both the Rainbow and Halo as one theme.
Halo in Opus tertium, it will be seen that he is both influenced by and responds to Most scholars isolate the issue of the Rainbow. I am preparing a study on the Halo
Avicenna. But in this section of Opus maius, part six, on the description of rainbow in these works of Bacon.
phenomena, Bacon draws on Aristotle, Avicenna and Averroes. For Avicenna on 65 Lynn Thorndike, The Sphere o f Sacrobosco and its Commentabrs, Chicago: The
the Rainbow, see MS Urb. Lat. 186, 159v-l 73v. I am grateful to Klaus Braun for University of Chicago Press, 1949.
this reference. 66 Opus maius, part six, ed. cit., 185.
300 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPER1MENTALIS 301

This section of the account on the rainbow has caused much diffi­ and one reflection (at the backside of the drop) before transmission
culty. For a variety of reasons based on a good knowledge of perspectwa to the eye of the observer. Descartes and Newton would advance
and on the motion of a person toward and away from a rainbow, this explanation.
Bacon concludes that the cause of the Rainbow is neither the inci­ In chapter eight, Bacon examined the issue of the objectivity of
dent rays nor the refracted rays but rather the reflected rays. Reflec­ the colors in the cloud. This matter may seem secondary, but in
tion, therefore, alone accounts for the rainbow. It was this account epistemological terms it was to play a major role during the next
which led Charles B. Boyer to offer a strong criticism of Bacon.67 two centuries and into the future. Naturally, vision alone cannot
However, he did not notice that Bacon was in fact making a strong produce color. Since for Bacon, however, color is a result of reflexion
argument against a peculiar Refraction theory set out by Robert Gros­ alone, a problem arises. He argues that in the case of the rainbow,
seteste. The latter had proposed an explanation by means of a series there is only an Appearance of Color in the cloud and not real color.69
of refractions in the interior of the Cloud. More recently, David C. Lindberg The colors in the rainbow, then, unlike fixed colors in objects are
pointed out that Bacon was quite correct to notice some of the incon­ the result of vision, and therefore can have no reality but are merely an
gruities of Grosseteste’s theory, and he corrected it. Further, he argued appearance.
that Bacon advanced the study of the rainbow by placing emphasis
on the reflection in small drops of water, and not on the whole cloud 69 Opus maius, part six, ed. cit., 190-91. But then it is the case that there will be
as a reflecting totality as Grosseteste had done.68 Theodoric of Freiberg, nothing in the place of the bow except an appearance of color, and it will only
happen when the bow appears. For it was stated that the rainbow changes accord­
who knew Bacon’s treatise, would correctly demonstrate in 1307 that ing to the different perspective of the viewer. But vision does not produce the colors
the primary rainbow is caused when sunlight falls on individual drops in cloud, as is clear. Hence, there will be nothing there except an appearance.
Again, reflected vision has a visible object at the terminus of the reflected visual ray,
of moisture the rays undergo two refractions (upon ingress and egress) as was shown above, and not at the point of reflexion or elsewhere. And because
the object seen is the terminus of reflexion and of the reflected line, it follows that
nothing is seen by reflexion in the cloud.
67 Carl B. Boyer, The Rainbow, 100-101: The reader may have noted that Bacon Yet if it is stated that vision is sensibly and vividly excited by the rainbow, and
spoke of the bow as generated by multiple reflections and refractions and a question quite lively colors appear in the rainbow, and therefore it is not possible that there
arises here, as it did with Albertus. Did the author intend to use the word refraction is merely an appearance of colors, it ought to be stated that just as there is only an
in the modem sense? appearance of colors so there is only a sensible appearance and a lively change of
Boyer answers negatively. However, he notes correctly that Bacon does criticise vision. For such change is due to nothing else than a defect of vision, as we see in
the “triple-refraction” theory of Grosseteste. the examples. For in the summer morning, when a person lowers their head to the
68 David C. Lindberg, “Roger Bacon’s Theory of the Rainbow .. art. cit. 236: ground in order to see drops of dew on the ends of the grass, and if he looks at
It is quite true that Bacon drew attention away from refraction, but was this neces­ them in a careless or easygoing manner with half closed eyes, he sees in appear­
sarily a regressive step? It is my thesis that although Bacon denied any role to ance all the colors of the rainbow. And similarly in the colored circle around the
refraction, he advanced the theory of the rainbow in two crucial respects. First, he candle. . . . Therefore, it ought to be the case that this is due to a defect in vision,
rejected refraction for good reasons, by advancing sound criticisms against some of and because of this there is an appearance (of colors) and not true color. Indeed,
the more absurd aspects of Grosseteste’s refraction theory. True, refraction was this appearance is strengthened as though it existed in the place of the rainbow.
required for the eventual solution of the rainbow problem, but not all in the form And this is due to the fact that the visual ray quickly intersects the cathetus because
suggested by Grosseteste; therefore before refraction could be properly exploited for of the smallness of the drops of rain. And so in this manner there is an appearance
understanding the rainbow, criticism such as Bacon’s was required. Second, although of color near the point of reflexion, and for this reason in this matter and in the
Bacon did not promote the cause of refraction, he did develop and refine other location of the rainbow.
constituents essential to any satisfactory explanation of the rainbow. Refraction is Yet, it if is stated that the rays of the sun passing through a crystal produce true
only one essential; it is necessary also to see that reflection is involved and above all and real colors, which make a species and are in the definition of the object, it
that reflection and refraction occur in the individual drop. Bacon made a significant should be stated that the real situation is different. The observer alone produces the
contribution then, when he called attention to the function fulfilled by individual Rainbow, and there is nothing out there (in reality) except a reflexion. In the case
drops, arguing that the rainbow appears in a different set of drops for each observer. of the crystal, there is a natural cause, that is the ray and the layered stone, which
In dismissing Bacon for his exclusive use of reflection, therefore, we are ignoring has a great diversity of surface, so that according to the angle at which the light
some of his important contributions to the development of the theory of the rain­ falls a diversity of colors will results. And looking at them does not cause the colors
bow. Briefly stated, it is instructive to see why Bacon insisted that the rainbow is to be present here, for there is color before it is seen here, and it is seen by different
caused by reflection alone. (See below for an account of the practical goals involved people in the same place. But in the case of the Rainbow, there is an appearance
in Bacon’s various accounts of mirror-phenomena, and for the nature of his experi­ due to Vision, and therefore there cannot be true color but only an appearance of
mental concerns.) color. And this is evident by what was said above concerning the visual pyram id.. . .
302 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTALIS 303

Naturally, this whole issue is concerned with the nature of Species, quid verum et quid fabum sit in eb. Having discussed the mirror phe­
Intentional being, and Objective or Apparent Being, and it would lead to nomenon in small drops of water, he states; “It generally appears
some of the most vexed issues concerning Species as mediatingfactors in absurd when they state that there is no true color in the rainbow.
human knowledge in the next few centuries.70 Here, we locate Bacon’s For since the light of all color is a hypostasis and a substantial form
discussion of the epistemological status of the rainbow at the start of and constitutes depicted colors by its rays in a dense perspicuous
this debate. It would be instructive here to indicate the similarities object, it follows that there is true color. . . . Therefore, the position
and differences between this account by Bacon and the account given of the Pythagoreans has no basis. . . . This error is due to a failure
by Albertus Magnus in his treatment of the same section of the to distinguish between (I) the material being of the color and (II) the
Meteorobgica of Aristotle.71 formal being of the color. The material being of the bow has Being
In tractatus four of Book III of his comments on the Meteorologba, in the qualities of the subject in which it is found. . . . The formal
Albertus Magnus like Bacon, maintains that these issues cannot be being of the color is due to the light. . . ,74*
solved without the aid of perspectiva. And like Bacon he sets out to
give an interpretation of both Aristotle and Seneca. Again, like Bacon, The importance of this comparison is to demonstrate the actual con­
he criticises those books which make claims which go against the text of Bacon’s remarks. Like Albertus Magnus, he was a Medieval
facts of experience.72 Having noted that the ancients held that the Scientist dealing with a Medieval problem. Further, one notices the
rainbow was the result of many confused Images, Albertus notes that continuity of influence from Ancient philosophy, in particular from
Possidonius like Artemidorus believed that the rainbow is a Mirror Greek and Roman sources. And in the end, what separates Bacon
in a concave cloud and that there are no real colors in the bow. (Sed from Albertus is his adherence to a Stoic analysis of the problem of
dicit colorem nullum esse in iride) In his view, there was no real color but the rainbow as distinct from an Aristotelian answer. Naturally, Bacon’s
a mere appearance of color. This, he states, is also the view of examination of the locus imagims and his work on perspectiva helped
Seneca.73 In Ch. 9, Albertus addresses these positions seeking out confirm him in this view. But when we see Bacon’s remarks in con­
text, we will notice that in themselves they are part of a medieval
70 See Katherine M. Tachau, Visum and Certitude in the Age of Ockham: Optics, Epistemol­ debate about human knowledge, and that those who were part of
ogy and the Foundations o f Semantics, 1250-1345, Leiden-New York-Kobenhavn-Koln: this debate were very intelligent, indeed.
E.J. Brill, 1988; See forthcoming paper on Petrus Aureol “In the Ambit of Another
Faculty: Parisian Theologians and the (Meta) physical Universe,” in John Van Engen
and Edward J. English, eds., foaming Institutionalized: Teaching in the Medieval University Roger Bacon on color
(Papers of the 1992 NEH Colloquium, University of Notre Dame). This paper
demonstrates how these ideas of Bacon are at the root of much of the debate on Did Bacon mark any advance on the traditional Aristotelian analysis
whether or not knowledge needs a “real object” to ensure the proper Objectivity of of color? It would seem that he did. Further, the analysis presented
knowledge. See also Andre de Muralt, L ’Enjeu de la Philosophic Medievale: Etudes thomistes,
scotistes, occamiennes et gregoriennes (Leiden-New York-Kovenhavn-Koln, 1991). in Bacon seems to have had some influence on the practice of Paint­
71 Albertus Magnus, Tractatus IV, Meteorobgica III (Borgnet edition), Ch. XI, 679. ing in the early Renaissance. Charles Parkhurst argues that “With
72 P. HoBfeld, “Der Gebrauch Der Aristotelischen Ubersetzung in Den Meteora Des
respect to color, Bacon draws our interest not only because he pro­
Albertus Magnus,” Medieval Studies XLII (1980), 395-406. It should be noted that
Albertus and Bacon share a common attitude to Aristotle. Where the text of Aristotle duced a synthesis of many historical sources on color, but also,
or any other ancient philosopher differs from their common or contrived experi­ especially, because he made contributions to color theory from a
ence, they subjet the views of the ancients to critical scrutiny. For an overview of
Albert as a scientist and natural philosoher, see Paul HoBfeld, Albertus Magnus als viewpoint entirely his own, and in doing so opened new vistas on
Naturphilosoph und Naturwissenschaftler (Bonn: Albertus-Magnus-Institut, 1983).
73 It is clear that both Albertus and Bacon are taking the issue of the appearance
of the colors of the rainbow from Seneca, Naturaks questiones. Whereas Bacon very reality of color in objects where the same color and pattern is seen by different
deliberately uses the resources of perspectiva to expand and defend the position of observers. For Bacon, each observer of a rainbow has a distinct sense-datum. See
Seneca, Albertus is more hesitant about the scope of perspectiva. Moreover, he holds HoBfeld, art. cit., 404; See also his “Senecas Naturabs quaestiones als Quelle der Meteora
a strong view of the objectivity of the colors in the rainbow, whereas Bacon distin­ des Albertus Magnus,” Archivum Fratrum Praedicabrum 50 (1980), 63-84.
guishes sharply between color as due mainly to a reflexion phenomenon and the 74 Albertus Magnus, ed. cit.
304 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON SCIENTLA EXPER1MENTAUS 305

the future.”75 In the commentary on De sensu et sensato (1240’s/ 1250’s), are painters’ primaries (cf. Meteorologica, 3.1) where Aristotle wrote of
Bacon interprets Aristotle’s color theory in the light of Ibn al-Haytham’s “the only colors (i.e. phoinikoun, prasinon and alourgon) which paint­
ers cannot manufacture: for there are (other) colors which they create
De aspectibus and Avicenna. Bacon takes up the discussion of Aristotle’s by mixing” (372a6); this represents a confusion of two mixing prin­
systematic scale of colors between the extremes of white and black, ciples nowadays called “addative” and “subtractive,” which spawned a
and notes in passing the numerical discrepancy in Aristotle.76 He theory either accepted or argued against, until laid to rest in the mid­
displays his acquaintance with the phenomenon of refraction of light nineteenth century by Helmholtz.78
in “ice, clear glass, water and a crystal,” and proceeds to give an
Parkhurst adds the following concerning Bacon:
account of the distinction of Lux (Light) and Lumen (the first natural
effect of light). He then presents a systematic classification of the Bacon has little to say on general color theory, but what he says is
colors. In ch. 16, after a discussion of Aristotle, he proposes a radical important and very succinct, as it confirms what we have deduced
from his first work on color, De sensu. If I read him correctly (the passage
revision of Aristotle’s color system. Bacon in Ch. 17 takes over his
is garbled, perhaps through copyists’ errors), his is saying that his basic
account from the De colore of Grosseteste. At most, Bacon makes or minimal system o f color genera between whiteness and blackness
emendations to Grosseteste’s text in the account of how remission consists of three principal colors, yellowness, redness and greyblueness.
and intension work to generate color. And yet, Bacon, while retaining This is in line with the presentation we found in his De sensu, for he
the number of seven colors from Aristode, and much material from states in this passage that there are in truth five “colores principales,”
clearly identified with his genera, albedo, glaucitas, rubedo, viriditas, and
Grosseteste, argues that while their general account is good, it is lacking
nigredo.
in detail, (“but in particular it touches nothing, as is evident”) Bacon pauses to justify numerologically his five-color system, with its
Bacon’s theory of color in his later works presupposes the account three middle colors. The five are “per naturam distincti” (his universal
of light and vision in De multiplicatione specierum and in the Perspective and immutable genera). Five, he says, is a good number, but three is
Parkhurst provides a good summary of the relation of light and color better, as in the Trinity. He is clearly aware that this flies in the face
in the former work, touching on such topics as the effect of strong of classical theory and Aristotle’s dictum that there are seven colors,
no more no less.79
light, the multiplication of color, the role of species, how light and
its species find the way to the eye as the species of color, on the On the whole, it is Parkhurst’s judgment that “Bacon’s innova­
mixing of black and white, on the optical mixture in the eye and on tive doctrines with respect to color were quietly revolutionary . . . for
the weakening of color, and a diagrammatical outline of a color rela­ Bacon’s thinking on color, though sometimes nebulous but often
tionship.77 Again in the Perspectiva, Bacon presentation covers similar focussed, as if by prescience, anticipates later systems and configura­
ground. In ch. 5, he takes up the discussion of the difference between tions.”80 This influence is, perhaps, best seen in both Leonardo Da
real and apparent color in the peacock’s tail and in rainbows, where Vinci and in Marsilio Ficino.
according to him, they exist only in appearance. Parkhurst expresses In his summary, Parkhurst claims that “Modem clorimetry is the
the following judgment: direct descendant of Bacon’s work though he could scarcely have
At no point that I can discover does Bacon question the Aristotelian
foreseen this. Nevertheless, the study of color variables began imme­
identification o f the three principal rainbow colors with those which diately after his death. Theodoric of Freiberg firmly established the
binary mixing of color species for the production of mixed colors in
the early fourteenth century. Later in the trecento, Cennino Cennini,
75 Charles Parkhurst, “Roger Bacon on Color: Sources, Theories and Influence,” following Giotto, instructs artists in the particularities of modelling
in The Verbal and The Visual: Essays in Honor of William Sebastian Heckscher, ed. Karl-
Ludwig Selig and Elizabeth Sears, New York, Italica Press, 1990, 151-202. See up with ever lighter tints of a pure color. In 1435, Alberti brings
151-2.
76 Roger Bacon, Liber de sensu et sensato, ed. R. Steele, (Chs. 11-15), 36-63.
77 Parkhurst, art. cit., 176: Bacon at this point (2.3.96) [De multliplicatione specierum] 78 Parkhurst, art. cit., 182.
interpolates a diagram (fig. 2), which is, so far as I can ascertain, the earliest extant 79 Parkhurst, art. cit., 182-3.
geometrical figure for a color relationship. . . . 80 Parkhurst, art. cit., 184.
306 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTALIS 307

Grosseteste into the studio, as it were, and views white and black Bacon sees the experimenter as one who can gain access to cures
paint as altematores of the principal colors. . . . Many of Bacon’s inno­ which have been there since the time of Adam. In what follows, he
vations are apparent in his collocation, which device he may have gives a list of all kinds of cures from ancient sources and contempo­
resorted to after a complete geometrical demonstration eluded him. .. . rary accounts.
Bacon’s efforts at systematics are manifest chiefly in his arrange­ The third example is taken from alchemy. Here, he argues that
ment of color names. . . .”81 In conclusion, Parkhurst points to Giotto “experiment” will lead to greater development in alchemy. And he
as the one who, a decade after the death of Roger Bacon “revolu­ adds: “But experimental science by means of Aristotle’s Secretum secre-
tionized painting in Europe, and in so doing created an epitome of torum knows how to produce gold only of twenty-four degrees but of
Bacon’s color doctrines on the walls of the Arena Chapel at Padua, thirty and forty degrees and of as many degrees as we desire.”84
ca. 1303-05.”82
The third prerogative of Scientia experimentalis
The second prerogative of Scientia experimentalis: experience as a source
of both instruments and knowledge Perhaps, it is best to cite Bacon’s remarks in full. It would appear
that Opus maius, part six, lacks a full development of this account.
Two other chapters of this volume deal with the two topics from the And the reader should refer back to Opus maius, part four on the
second prerogative, namely, medicine and alchemy. My task here is limits of judicial astrology. He states:
simply to review the context in Opus maius, part six, and to note
But there is a third prerogative of this science. It arises from those
connections with other parts of the Opus maius.
properties through which it has no connection with the other sciences,
The first example of an experimental devise which he gives here but by its own power investigates the Secrets of Nature. This consists
is that of the Celestial armillary sphere. The second example is that in two things; namely, in the knowledge of the future, past and present,
of medicine. He begins by expressing some skepticism of astrologer’s and in the wonderful works by which it excels the ordinary astronomy
claim that the shortening of life is due to a change in the arrange­ (judicial astrology) in the power of forming judgments. For Ptolemy
ment of the heavens. Rather, in his view, it is due to a failure of (tid: Pseudo-Ptolemy) [= Geminus] states in the The Introductory Book to
the Almagest that there is a more certain road to truth than that of the
people to follow a good regimen of health. Bacon sees the Experimen­ ordinary astronomy (judicial astrology), and this is the path of experience/
talist as one who supplements the normal medical regime’s of exer­ experiment, which follows the course of nature, to which many of the
cise and health with new cures. In this way, the normal course of a philosophers who are believers are now turning, just like Anstode and
life can be prolonged beyond customary medieval “forty five or fifty a host of the authors of judgments formed from the stars, as he himself
years.” In this Bacon is critical of the academic medical teachers: states, and as we know by proper practice, which cannot be contradicted.
This science was discovered as a complete remedy for human igno­
But the medical art does not furnish remedies against this corruption rance and inadvertance; for it is difficult to get accurate astronomical
that comes from lack of control and failure in regimen, just as all instruments, and it is more difficult to get verified tables, especially
physicians expert in their own art know, although medical authors confess those in which the motions of the planets is equalized. The use, more­
that remedies are possible, but they do not teach them. For these reme­ over, of these tables is difficult, but still more difficult is the use of the
dies have always been hidden from the whole rank and file of scien­ instruments. But this science (Scientia experimentalis) has discovered the
tists, and have been revealed only to the most noted, whom Aristotle definitions and means by which it can answer easily every question, in
mentions in the division of the probable.83 so far as the power of a single branch of philosophy can do so, and by
which it can show us the forms of the Celestial Forces, and the influ­
ences o f the heavenly bodies on this world without the difficulty of
ordinary astronomy (judicial astrology). This part of the science relat­
81 Parkhurst, art. cit., 190.
ing to judgments has four principal divisions or secret sciences.85
82 Parkhurst, art. cit., 192; For Bacon and Giotto, see Klaus Bergdolt, “Bacon und
Giotto. Ein Einfluss der franziskanischen Naturphilosophie auf die bildende Kunst
am Ende des 13. Jahrhunderts,” Medizinhistorisches Journal 24 (1989), 25-41. 84 Ed. cit., 215.
83 Opus maius, part six, ed. cit., 206-7. 85 Ed. cit., 215-16. See also “Roger Bacon on Astronomy and Astrology” above.
308 ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTALIS 309
JEREMIAH HACKETT

This leaves the reader with a certain disappointment. It is clear that Finally, Bacon refers to the uses of the Magnet with iron. This
Bacon is looking for a means to qualify the evident deterministic example is instructive. He notes that the phenomenon of attraction
tendencies of the regular judicial astrology. But his dependence on in things, as in plant life, ought not to be treated as Magic. He notes:
Geminus, and his subsequent claim that he can find a way around “This is a very wonderful thing. For this reason, Magicians perform
the skilled use of astronomical instruments, verified tables and calcu­ this experiment, repeating many incantations, and they believe that
lations, leaves the reader to wonder. However, the remark that many the phenomenon is caused by virtue of the incantations. I have disre­
contemporaries are turning to the way of experiment, and to an garded the incantations and have discovered the wonderful action of
examination of the Secrets of Nature in the tight of Aristotle and the nature, which is similar to that of the magnet on iron. For just as the
authors on judicial astrology illustrate the extent to which Bacon is one attracts the other because of the similar nature of the iron and
a child of his times, and of the extent to which Aristotle was being the magnet, so do the parts in this case. Hence, the Natural Force
interpreted in an Astrological context. One also notes in this and in which is similar in both parts of the twig, causes them to unite.”89
what follows, the strong influence of the pseudo-Aristotelian Secretum
secretorum on Bacon’s thinking. (7) The uses of Scientia experimentatis for the Church and
This introduces the conclusion of Opus maius, part six, which I am the Commonwealth
going to call the Applications of Science and the Ruler as Philosophical
Chancellor. Bacon concludes his account of this science by reviewing its uses in
Following on the third prerogative, Bacon notes that a military Statecraft. Next to Moral Philosophy, it is the most useful, and it is
leader may not always want to engage in Warfare. If the customs of so in the first place to theology since it helps people to know the
a people can be changed by altering the environment so much the literal meanings of things. “For I have shown above that the literal
better. It is clear that Bacon has in mind the natural alterations to meaning consists in expressing the truth in regard to created things
the human complexio due to climate and geography. In this way, the by means of their definitions and descriptions, and I likewise showed
“complexions of their bodies can be changed, and then their minds
influenced by their complexions would choose good morals in accord­ Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991), 163-181. [Boston Studies in the Philosophy of
Science, Vol. 126] Starting from Francis Bacon’s definition of Experiment as experience
ance with the freedom of the will. This is one of the Secrets (of
quaesita, that is, not mere experience but a “sought after” experience, S. Unguru
nature).”86 In this, Bacon is of course thinking of Aristotle as advisor comments: “Various groupings toward this recognition include Peter Maricourt’s ‘idus-
to Alexander. He then turns from the issue of how to influence the tria mmurri (It was Petrus Peregrinus whom Roger Bacon referred to in the Opus tertium
as ‘dominus experimentonmi), Roger Bacon’s own ‘scientia experimentalis,’ Thomas
“internal” behavior of people, and addresses the issue of the uses of Aquinas’ ‘scientia experimentalis’ or its identical twin ‘scientia experimentalis,’ Nicolas
Military technologies. of Cusa’s ‘experimenti statici,’ etc.” See 165-6 for his judicious account of Roger
He is clearly thinking of technologies whose use in War “without Bacon’s notion of experience. (See n. 13 re. Induction: This shows that Bacon like
Ibn al-Haytham saw the Science of Optics as confirmatory o f theory rather than as a
a sword or any weapon requiring physical contact could destroy all technique of discovery). But while Roger Bacon lacks a formulation of the Francis
who offer resistance.”87 These inventions include: (a) poison gas, (b) Baconian Induction, he did think that experience itself when studied carefully and
malta, a kind of bitumen, (c) yellow petroleum, (d) noise-makers and methodically could yield new scientific information and technologies. See below.
89 Ed. tit., 219. O n the Magnet, see the Epistola de magnete of Petrus Peregrinus,
explosive devices used to disorientate people. “And thus, there are dated 1269; See below for the relationship of Bacon and Petrus Peregrinus. See
innumerable things that have strange virtues, whose powers we are Unguru, pp. 166-72 on “Witelo’s ‘hands-on,’ pragmatic, matter of fact approach-----
This is also, perhaps, the place to point out that Witelo uses this very ‘organum
ignorant of only because of our neglect of the need to experiment.”88 refractionis’ in Book X to prove experimentally, as he puts it, his various conclusions
about refraction.” From the present paper, it will be clear why Roger Bacon was no
less “experimentally” involved in such matter than Witelo; his problem was the refusal
86 Ed. tit., 216. See Secretum secretorum, ed. Steele, introduction. of his Franciscan superiors to allow him to be involved. Thus, he became the “scientific”
87 Ed. tit., 217. advocate for the Parisian scientific movement in the mid-13th century, a movement
88 Ed. tit., 218. See S. Unguru, “Experiment in Medieval Optics,” in Sabetai which existed outside of the Arts Faculty with its concentration on the philosophic
Unguru, Physics, Cosmology and Astronomy, 1300-1700 (Dordrecht/Boston/London: communis, that is, Grammar-Logic and Aristotelian texts.
310 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON SCIENTTA EXPERIMENTAUS 311

that reasoning does not arrive at this truth, but experiment does. yet all things of such wonderful utility in the State belong to this science.
Wherefore, this science next to Moral Philosophy will present the For this science has the same relation as the Science of Navigation to
literal truth of Scripture most effectively, so that through suitable the Carpenter’s Art and that of Military Art to that of the engineer.
For this science teaches how wonderful instruments may be made, and
adaptations and similitudes the spiritual sense may be derived, owing
uses them when made, and also considers all Secret things owing to
to the peculiar nature of the sacred Scripture and in accordance the advantages they may possess for the State and for individuals. And
with the methods employed by the sacred writers and by all sages.”90 it directs other sciences as its handmaids, and therefore the whole power
This science is useful then for Church and State since it provides of speculative science is attributed especially to this science. And now
a special knowledge of the future, present and past so that all useful the wonderful advantages o f these three sciences in this world on behalf
pursuits can be encouraged and evil activities be avoided. o f the Church of God against the enemies of the faith is manifest, who
should be destroyed rather by the discoveries of science than by the
Above all, this science will provide a way forward: it will help to warlike arms of combatants. The Antichrist will use these means freely
distinguish between a Science and Art of Mature and the Practices of and effectively, in order that he may crush and confound the power of
Magicians. Bacon states: this world, and by these means tyrants in times past brought the world
under their sway.92
But there is still another very useful way; since the formation of judg­
ments, as I have said, is a function of this science, in regard to what
can happen by Mature or can be effected in Art, and what does not (8) Roger Bacon and experiment: Petrus Peregrinus de Maricourt
happen in these. This science, moreover, knows how to separate the
illusions of Magic and how to detect all their errors in incantations, One answer to the vexed issue of “experiments” in Roger Bacon is
invocations, conjurations, sacrifices and cults. But unbelievers busy to return to the very significant remarks by Bacon in Ch. XIII of the
themselves in these mad acts and trust in them, and believed that the Opus tertium.93 Here he devotes an encomium to one whom he regards
Christians used such means in working their miracles.91
as the leading experimentalist in Paris. This person declined honors
Bacon, further, thinks that this science will be of use for the persuasion and offices so that he could devote himself to his experimental work.
of Christian belief. He ends this section by arguing that this science Bacon begins this chapter by noting its connection with Opus maius,
can work to the advantage of Christianity, and he cites the example part six. Again, he notes that the argumentative approach by the
of Alexander the Great once more, and states that it is in the inter­ Natural Philosophers in discussions of the Meteorologica of Aristotle
est of Princes and Prelates to encourage this kind of study. Just prior and the Perspectivists by means of bare geometrical proof try to con­
to this conclusion, he sets out his vision of this science as follows: cern themselves with “experimental” matters but do so in vain, “since
experience alone verifies this area and not bare argument.” He adds:
We must consider, however, that although other sciences do many
wonders, as in the case of practical geometry, which produces mirrors
“And so I present the roots of the experiences concerning these
that bum up every opposing object, and so too in the other sciences, matters, which only one person among the Latins can understand,
namely, Magister Petrus”.94* Bacon returns to many of the sources
90 Ed. cit., 219-20. For Grosseteste on this issue, see James McEvoy, “The Sun which we have seen above, and draws the connection again between
as res and signum: Grosseteste’s Commentary on Ecclesiasticus ch. 43, w . 1-5,” in
Resch. Theol. one. med., 41 (1974), 38-91. Bacon in Opus maius, parts four and six, is
dependent on this text for the present issue. See also Klaus Bergdolt, “Der Sehvorgang
als theologisches Analogen Augenanatomie und -physiologie bei Roger Bacon,” in
Sudhqffs Archixi 1 (1991), 1-20.
92 Ibid., 221.
91 Ed. cit., 221. On the need for the experimentalist to know both science and 93 Opus tertium, ed. Brewer, 43-47; 107-120.
magic, see Bacon’s remarks below concerning Petrus Peregrinus in the Opus tertium. 94 Ibid., 43: Et ostendi ibi maximam potestatem, quam habet haec scientia super
O n the role of Magic in relation to science in classical antiquity, see G.E.R. Lloyd, alias certificandas. Naturales quidem in libro Metheororum Aristotelis, et perspectivi,
Magic, Reason and Experience: Studies in the Origin and Development o f Greek Science, negotiantur circa hoc certificanda, sed in vanum; quia sola experientia certificat hie,
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979). In the light of this study, it is clear et non argumentum. Et ideo pono radices experientiarum circa ista, quas nullus
that Roger Bacon manages to hand on a unique synthesis of ancient views on these Latinorum potest intelligere, nisi unus; scilicet, Magister Petrus. Et sic est de aliis
topics.
rebus naturalibus.
312 JEREMIAH HAGKETT
ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTALIS 313

the scientia experimentalis and astronomia. And again, he returns to the through the grace of God this MIRROR has already been constructed by the
subaltemation of the making of burning mirrors and other instru­
wisest of the Latins.”*98*
ments to practical geometry and adds:
And so (with) this is the great instrument (product of art) which only We can now see the end result of all of the Theory of Vision, the
the faithful experimenter knows how to think out, but however he orders Theory of Force (Species) and the Theory of Burning Mirrors. All of
the geometer to prepare and configure a mirror. And so the use of this it was directed at the improvement of the Military strength of the
instrument is a task for the experimenter; the preparation of it a task
Latin West in the context of their new awareness, due to William of
for the geometer.95
Roebruck and other Travellers, of their fragile place in a bigger World.
In what follows, Bacon as in Opus maius, part six, points to the uses This would not be the first or last time that the demands of military
of technologies, especially their uses in warfare against the Tartars necessity would lead to a concern with the construction of new experi­
and the Sarascens. And it is here that he then offers the encomium mental instruments. But it does prove that Bacon was very much in
of Magister Petrus in detail: he is the one who avoids the verbalisms tune with the main experimental concerns of the few at the Univer­
and arguments of the common teachers; he knows natural things by sity of Paris who did this kind of work. And although he refers to
experience, medicine, alchemy and the secrets of nature; he exam­ himself in the late 1260’s as a Senex, he did, by means of his writings,
ines all sources of knowledge, and from rustic matters to military do much to keep the experimented vision alive for future generations
matters, he is a practical expert; not only that, but he also knows the in the Latin West.
frauds and trickery of the Magicians. And indeed without his assis­ We can now claim in the light of the above, that Roger Bacon
tance, the whole of philosophy is not able to be completed. But he, was very much involved in the first truly experimental work at the
who could receive many honors, ignores them so that he can get on University of Paris in the 13th century. We can claim that he wrote
with his experimental work. Most of all, he has worked for three the basic treatises on the geometry of this work, and that he was
years on the construction of a Burning Mirror, an object whose indeed involved in some Experiments with the Dominus experimentorum,
construction most Latins do not understand, and even though they Magister Petrus Peregrinus. Further, in the light of the above, we
have books on this matter, they never attempted the experimental will have to claim that they did in fact operate as a team: the one
construction of this kind of mirror.96 Further, Bacon informs us that was the actual Experimenter, the other was the “theorist” who wrote
he sent a “crystallinum sphericum ad experiendum” with the Opus maius, De both the hard scientific Treatises and the propaganda for the ad­
multiplkatione specierum, and other works to the Pope through the agency vancement of Science. This is what the Opus maius is: a combination
of his pupil, John, and that he had instructed his pupil Iohannes in of scientific treatise and a rhetorical persuasion for the advancement
“the demonstration and configuration of this mysterious thing”91 He adds: “And

experiendum; et instruxi eum in demonstratione et figuratione hujus rei occultae.


95 Op. tert., ed. Brewer, 45. Nec est aliquis in tota Italia, sicut nec Parisius duo, qui possunt dare causam
suflicientem in hac parte; et multa exposui circa hac fractiones.
96 Ibid., 47; see also 111-13. O n Petrus Peregrinus, see E. Schlund, “Petrus
98 Ibid., 113: Et iam per Dei Gratiam factum est hoc speculum per sapientissimum
Peregrinus von Maricourt: sein Leben und seine Schriften,” Archivum Franciscanum
Latinorum. See also pp. 116-7. First, note the reference to the auctor libri de speculis
Historicum, 4 (1911), 436-55; 633-43; 5 (1912), 22-40; Edward Grant, “Peter
comburentibus. Bacon is, of course, the author of the Latin De speculis comburentibus, but
Peregrinus, Pierre de Maricourt (fl. ca. 1269),” in Dictionary of Scientific Biography, xiv
(1976), 532-40. this seems to be a clear reference to Bacon’s use of Gerard of Cremona’s Latin
translation of Ibn al-Haytham’s O n parabolic burning Mirrors. (See A.I. Sabra,
97 Op. tert., ed. Brewer, 111: Note the point Bacon is making here. The Natural
op. cit., II, xliii-iv. Second, note what Bacon states: the great experimenter, Petrus
Philosophers are not able to account for Refraction by means of arguing to the
Peregrinus, constructed such a mirror at Paris [“Sed cum magnis expensis et laboribus
Cause from the Effect (Method of Synthesis/Analysis), but with the help of Geome­
factum est; nam artifex damnificatus est in centum libri Parisiensibus, et pluribus
try, combustion due to mirror reflection can be explained. The same is the case for
annis laboravit, dimittens studium et alias occupationibus necessarias . . .”]. Further,
all other works of nature. Their causes can only be accounted for by means of
Bacon points out that prior to his work on the Multiplication o f Species, no such work
geometry, and thus the appeal to Occult causes by the Natural Philosophers is
existed among the Latin Westerners. But, he says, all of this experimental and geo­
futile. And then he adds: Puer vero Johannes portavit crystallum sphaericum ad
metrical work is ignored by the Vulgus philosophantium at Paris.
314 JEREMIAH HACKETT ROGER BACON ON SCIENTIA EXPERIMENTALIS 315

of science. And further, it does provide strong evidence that actual Recently, A. Mark Smith has demonstrated the profound continu­
experimental work with Instruments was carried out by these experi­ ity between Medieval perspectival theory on the optics of Renee
menters. They did this, of course, as did their 17th century Counter­ Descartes.102 A similar line of influence can be demonstrated for the
parts, on the margins of University life, and often in the face the continuity in Scientia experimentalis.103
verbosity of Arts and Theology faculties who had not time for that We began this chapter with a review of modern research. But
kind of study. immediately, in the first note we drew attention to a small but real
influence by Roger Bacon on Francis Bacon. The influence definitely
What then became of Roger Bacon’s fame and reputation in the proves that Francis Bacon read at least one of the texts closely con­
Later Middle Ages and the Renaissance? Some three hundred years nected to Opus maius, part six, de scientia experimentali. Thus, an influence,
or so later, it was his fate to become known as a Magician, indeed however small, by Roger Bacon on Francis Bacon in the direction of
someone whom a modern age could honor but ignore. experimentalism can no longer be ruled out.
Further, we can say that each of the modern commentators saw
We have now seen the wide-ranging dimensions of Roger Bacon’s some side of the man and his work. Certainly, he was a Medieval
Scientia experimentalis. The first thing to be noted is that it is a Medi­ scientist, heir to the hermetic tradition. But more importantly, he
eval experimental science, and not the science of the 19th and 20th was heir to the great Translation movement (1120-1280), and only
centuries." Albertus Magnus and possibly Richard of Fournival matches Bacon’s
Within that context, one can see that decisions made by Roger range in sources. That he was well placed by his training in England
Bacon and his contemporaries would in time bring about in the to absorb the new Arabic learning is clear. Thus, he was in a good
Renaissance a greater sense of autonomy in the science and art of position as a Professor and later as a Friar to contribute to its devel­
Nature. The search for the Secrets of Nature, would, as we know opment. That he was interested in and did attempt some experimen­
form recent scholarship, play a significant role in the discovery of tation has been demonstrated. However, it has also been shown that
early modern science. There are echoes of Roger Bacon’s project in in the 1260’s he was a senex, that is, one who is over-forty years of
the English Renaissance. One need but look at the works of John age, and quite old by medieval reckoning. His inability to do experi­
Dee to notice the great continuity of influence.100 And there are hints mental work in the 1260’s in a formal manner was due to his situ­
of influence in Francis Bacon. Further, there is some evidence of ation in life: he was no longer a Professor. As a friar in the Franciscan
Bacon and his contemporaries in William Gilbert.101 And yet, an­ Order, he had other duties. Yet, his cooperation with Magister Petrus
other index of the continuity of Roger Bacon’s project is to be found in doing some experimental work led to his writing the “theory” of
in an unlikely place, that is, in the “new” science of Renee Descartes. experimental work with Burning Mirrors, “the most incisive and
original piece of geometrical optics produced in the West during the
entire Middle Ages”104 and to the writing of a work on the Multipli­
99 In this context, it is important to refer to Professor Lindberg’s remarks on
Experimentation in Bacon’s perspectiva in the previous chapter. Yes, he did do some
cation of Species and a work on Perspectiva. And in the end, even the
experimentation. Yes, much is taken from ancient and medieval books. T hat he and semiotics in the De signis is put to use to justify the Scientia experimentalis.
his contemporaries did attempt to build instruments to measure the angles of reflection And here again, the De docta Christiana had to be re-interpreted and
is attested in the case of Witelo. (See S. Ungura art. cit.) But in the light of Bacon’s
apobgia, it is easy to see that he is a spokesperson for those like Petrus de Marancuria, extended to cope with the rhetoric and semiotic of science.
Dominus experimentorum at the University of Paris. And in that role, we must see him
as a retired Professor who acts as an advocate for science in what was a strongly
verbal and bookish culture. 102 A. Mark Smith, “Descartes” Theory of Light, op. cit.
100 See John Dee’s Diary and Library Catalogue for the strong influence of Roger 103 Jeremiah Hackett, “Experientia, experimentum and the Perception of Objects in
Bacon, and also see his works, some of which draw heavily on Bacon’s geometrical Space,” 30th Kolner Medievistentagung, 1996, Raum und Raumvorstellungen im Mittelalter,
treatises. I would be surprised if Francis Bacon did not see the dependence on Miscellanea Medievalia (forthcoming). Descartes in the Paris of the 1600’s found him­
Roger Bacon by John Dee. self in an analogous position to Bacon and Magister Petrus: the Arts and Theology
101 See William Gilbert, De magnete for the influence of the De magnete of Magister faculties were not amused.
Petrus and by implication of Roger Bacon. 104 David C. Lindberg, Roger Bacon’s Philosophy of Nature, ed. cit. Lxxi.
13. AN OVERVIEW OF RO GER BACON’S ALCHEMY

William R. Newman1

Roger Bacon’s interest in alchemy was well-known to medieval and


early modern scholars, if one may judge by the numerous alchemical
pseudepigrapha that travel under his name.2 But few modern schol­
ars realize just how high Bacon’s hopes were for alchemy, or how
central a position it occupied in his reform of the sciences. Nor is it
common knowledge that Bacon’s alchemical theories were of a highly
idiosyncratic nature, and in some respects quite original.3 Bacon was
certainly enamoured of geometry and optics, as every historian of
medieval science knows. But in his Opus tertium (written 1267-8) Bacon

1 I would like to thank Dr. George Molland for allowing me to use his partial
transcript (ff. 124v~132r) of MS. Vaticanus reginensis latinus 1317, an important
unpublished fragment of Bacon’s Opus minus. Dr. Molland is preparing a new edi­
tion of the Opus tertium for publication. I have compared Dr. Molland’s transcript to
a microfilm of the MS. and have at some points made tacit changes: Dr. Molland
should not therefore be held responsible for the quotations of Vat. reg. 1317 as
printed here.
2 Newman, William R., “The Alchemy of Roger Bacon and the Tres epistolae
Attributed to Him,” in Comprendre et mmtriser la nature au moyen age (Geneva: Librairie
Droz, 1994), pp. 461-479; cf. pp. 461, 471; and Newman, The “Summa perfectwnis”
of pseudo-Geber (Leiden: Brill, 1991), pp. 46-47, n. 88.
3 The following entries are devoted to Bacon’s alchemy, but a definitive treat­
ment is lacking: Newman, William R., “The Philosophers’ Egg: Theory and Prac­
tice in the Alchemy of Roger Bacon,” Micrologus, 3 (1995), pp. 75-101; Michela
Pereira, L ’oro dei filosofi: saggio sulle idee di un akhimista del trecento (Spoleto: Centro
Italiano di studi sull’alto medioevo, 1992), pp. 43-83. Faye Marie Getz, “To Prolong
Life and Promote Health: Baconian Alchemy and Pharmacy in the English Learned
Tradition,” in Sheila Campbell, et al., Health, Disease and Healing in Medieval Culture
(London: Macmillan, 1992). Stanton J. Linden, “Roger Bacon in the Age of Francis:
The mirror o f akhimy and the mirror of nature,” in Cauda Pcwonis, 10 (1991), pp. 10-
13. Agostino Paravicini Bagliani, “Storia della scienza e storia della mentalita: Ruggero
Bacone, Bonifacio VIII e la teoria della ‘prolongatio vitae,” ’ in Aspetti della ktteratura
latina nel secob X III (Firenze: La Nuova Italia, 1986), pp. 243-280. Edmund Brehm,
“Roger Bacon’s Place in the History of Alchemy,” Ambix, 23 (1976), pp. 53-57.
Guy-H. Allard, “Reactions de trois penseurs du XIIT siecle vis-a-vis de l’alchimie,”
in La science de b nature: theories et pratiques. Cahiers d'etudes medievaks, II (Paris, 1974),
pp. 97-106. For the older literature, see Dorothea Waley Singer, “Alchemical Writ­
ings Attributed to Roger Bacon,” Speculum, 7 (1932), pp. 80-86, M.M. Pattison
Muir, “Roger Bacon: His Relations to Alchemy and Chemistry,” and H.W.L. Hime,
“Roger Bacon and Gunpowder,” in A.G. Little, Roger Bacon Essays (Oxford, 1914),
pp. 285-335.
318 WILLIAM R. NEWMAN AN OVERVIEW OF ROGER BACON S ALCHEMY 319

passes from those sciences to alchemy with a virtual manifesto on making a knowledge of it essential to the operational needs of the
the powers of alchemical science.4 commonwealth. Practical alchemy is useful in another way as well; it
First Bacon argues that the science that deals most properly with is by means of this art that man can arrive at the prolongation of
the generation of things from the elements is “theoretical alchemy” human life up to its final and absolute limit.
[alkimia speculativei), a discipline that is currentiy ignored by his con­ Bacon’s alchemical manifesto in the Opus tertium will provide a rough
temporaries in the universities. He then argues that it is theoretical outline for the remainder of this paper. First I shall detail his idea
alchemy that teaches how “simple and compounded humors” arise that alchemical theory provides the basis for studying the generation
from the elements, along with all the other things that descend from of all natural things, then I shall pass to his goals for practical alchemy
elemental origins, such as precious stones, metals, pigments, and items in medicine and chemical technology. The purpose will be that of
of chemical commerce and the technology of warfare, such as salts, giving an overview, and so the essay will conclude with a brief treat­
sulfurs, oils, and burning pitches. In addition, vegetables, animals, ment of Bacon’s place among the alchemical writers of his time. Let
and men derive from the humors, so that an ignorance of theoretical us therefore proceed to a consideration of theoretical alchemy.
alchemy necessarily entails ignorance in theoretical medicine, and thus
failure in practical medicine. But in addition to this critical science
of theoretical alchemy there is also a “practical alchemy,” {alkimia Alchemy and the Generation of Things from the Elements
operativa et practica) which teaches the manufacture of precious metals,
pigments, and other items of chemical technology. Practical alchemy, Bacon begins his praise of alchemy in the Opus tertium with the state­
moreover, can even surpass nature in the perfection of its products, ment that this science can teach us about things generated from the
elements, such as “simple and compounded humors.” Before proceed­
ing into the depths of Bacon’s alchemical theory one must first get a
4 Roger Bacon, Opus tertium, in J.S. Brewer, ed., Fr. Rogeri Bacon, Opera quaedam grip on this concept of two types of humors. Drawing on an alchemical
hactenus inedita (London: Longman, Green, Longman, and Roberts, 1859), pp. 39- work spuriously attributed to Abu Bakr Muhammad ibn Zakariyya
40: “Sed alia est scientia, quae est de rerum generatione ex dementis, et de omni­
bus rebus inanimatis: ut de dementis, et de humoribus simplicibus et compositis; de ar-Razi, Bacon asserts that the most fundamental level of fully formed
lapidibus communibus, gemmis, marmoribus; de auro et caeteris metallis; de sul- terrestrial matter is provided by the four canonic elements, fire, air,
phuribus, et salibus, et atramentis; de azurio, et minio et caeteris coloribus; de oleis water, and earth, from which are composed in turn the four simple
et bituminibus ardentibus, et aliis infinitis, de quibus nihil habemus in libris Aristotelis;
nec naturales philosophantes sciunt de his, nec totum vulgus Latinorum. Et quia humors—blood, phlegm, choler, and melancholy, or as he likes to
haec scientia ignoratur a vulgo studentium, necesse est ut ignorent omnia, quae call them, humor aereus, aqua vite, virtus ignea, and calx.5*Each of these
sequuntur, de rebus naturalibus; scilicet de generatione animatorum, ut vegetabilium,
et animalium, et hominum: quia ignoratis prioribus, necesse est ignorari quae
simple humors is composed of all four elements, but one element
posteriora sunt. Generatio enim hominum, et brutorum, et vegetabilium est ex
dementis et humoribus, et communicat cum generatione rerum inanimatarum. Unde,
propter ignorantiam istius scientiae, non potest sciri naturalis philosophia vulgata, 5 The notion that the four elements “proceed up to twelve” is openly derived
nec speculativa medicina, nec per consequens practica; non solum quia naturalis from pseudo-Razfs Lumen luminum. See Bacon’s De erroribus medicorum, in A.G. Little
philosophia et speculativa medicina necessariae sunt ad practicam ejus, sed quia and E. Withington, Opera hactenus inedita Rogeri Baconi (Oxford, 1928), vol. 9, p. 159:
omnes simplices medicinae de rebus inanimatis accipiuntur de hac scientia, quam “Nam cum in libro qui Lumen luminum dicitur, quern multi Aristoteli ascribunt,
tetigi, sicut manifestum est in secundo libro Avicennae Medicinalis, qui simplices asserantur corpora 12 esse materialia ad species rerum generatas per naturam, ut
medicinas enumerat; et ex aliis auctoribus manifestum est: quarum medicinarum 4or elementa et 8 alia, non potest naturalis in philosophia vulgata hec scire. . . . ” I
nec nomina sciri possunt, nec significata, nisi per hanc scientiam; et haec scientia have verified that Bacon’s attribution to the Lumen luminum is correct by reference to
est alkimia speculativa, quae speculatur de omnibus inanimatis et tota generatione that text in Manchester, John Rylands MS. lat. 65, 13r: “Amplius omnis generatio
rerum ab dementis. Est autem alkimia operativa et practica, quae docet facere metalla ex iiii dementis consistit. unde calor et frigus set et humor et siccitas opponuntur.
nobiha, et colores, et aha multa melius et copiosus per artificium, quam per naturam Omne etiam compositum ex simplicibus esse constat, sunt autem hec a iiii usque ad
fiant. Et hujusmodi scientia est major omnibus praecedentibus, quia majores utihtates xii quorum iiii simplicia sunt, viii vero composita. Omnia tamen hec inferior mundus
producit. Nam non solum expensas et aha inhnita reipubheae potest dare, sed docet comprehendit.” The incipit of this Lumen luminum is “Cum de sublimiori atque
invenire taha, quae vitam humanam possunt prolongare in multa tempora, ad quae precipue. . . .” (TK 290). The text is described in a fundamental article by Julius
per naturam produci potest.” Ruska, “Pseudepigraphe Rasis-Schriften,” in Osiris, 7 (1939), pp. 31-94.
320 AN OVERVIEW OF ROGER BACON’S ALCHEMY 321
WILLIAM R. NEWMAN

will dominate therein, in accordance with traditional medical theory. Bacon clearly associated Avicenna’s experiment with the common
These simple humors in turn give birth to four compound humors alchemical practice of “separating the elements” of various substances
(<humores compositi) which are also called blood, phlegm, choler, and by means of stratification and fractional distillation. One of the main
melancholy: the compound humors each contain all four of the simple, conduits of this practice was an Arabic forgery attributed to Avicenna
but each is “denominated by the dominant one,” that is, each com­ which came to be called the Liber de anima, a work with which Bacon
pound humor receives its name from the simple humor that predom­ was intimately acquainted (not to be confused with the genuine De
inates in it.6 Thus the humors as evacuated from a patient are actually anima or Liber sextus de naturalibus, Avicenna’s work on the soul).9 Pseudo-
compounds, each containing a primary constituent. Avicenna’s De anima provides extensive recipes for separating the four
Bacon has experimental evidence for the compound nature of the elements from such diverse products as apples, milk, and cheese. In
humors as evacuated, provided by a well-known passage in Avicenna’s the case of milk, for example, the author says that upon its distilla­
Canon, where the Persian philosopher says that the physician should tion a clear, tear-like substance passes over first: this is the element
put some blood into a vessel in order to observe its separation into of water. When the distillation continues, a yellow water follows, and
a spuma, a fex, a part like egg-white, and a watery substance. Although a black, burnt substance is left in the flask. The yellow water corre­
the blood that issues forth during phlebotomy is itself a humor, sponds to air, the black residue to earth, and the smoky vapors that
Avicenna states that there are actually four further humors contained appear during the process to fire. Hence all four elements have been
within blood which correspond to the strata within the flask—these separated from the initial milk.10 Now Bacon was immensely impressed
“humors” are colera rubea, melancolia, flegma, and aquositas.1 Bacon of by such examples of alchemy’s analytical prowess, but in the Opus
course equates these four with his simple humors, and as we shall tertium he does not mean to say merely that alchemy teaches one
see, Bacon’s use of alchemical sources allowed him to put a pre­ how to separate the elements from one another. Instead, he argues
mium on these simple humors that was certainly not shared by the that the books of alchemists teach things about the different orders
medical authors upon whom he drew. To Bacon, in fact, this genu­ of humors that have gone unnoticed both by the physicians and the
ine Avicennian passage would serve to confirm that medicine ought natural philosophers.
to be dependant on alchemy, for here Avicenna “sends the physi­ In an unpublished section of the Opus minus, Bacon states that there
cians to alchemy.”8 are not in fact two orders of humors, but three, and that the humors
are found in all sublunary things.11 In order to grasp his meaning, it
will be necessary to consider this important unedited passage in extenso.
Bacon begins by saying that the humors “are in all things, although
6 Bacon, De erroribus, p. 157: “Et hii humores sunt primo 4or simplices, quorum
quilibet est ex elementis 4or sed ex uno per dominium; et deinde sunt 4or humores
compositi, quorum quilibet est ex 40r humoribus simplicibus, sed ex uno eorum per
dominium, ut in homine colerico, vel a membro colerico, exit humor compositus argumenta confirmat quod dicit per experientiam alkimie, dicens: Ipsum quoque
qui vocatur colera, et tamen componitur ex omnibus simplicibus sed denominatur a sanguinem aliis invenimus commixtum humoribus qui ab eo separantur.”
dominante. . . 9 Ruska, Julius, “Die Alchemie des Avicenna,” Isis, 21 (1934), pp. 14—51.
7 Avicenna, Liber canonis Avicenne revisus et ab omni errore mendaque purgatus summaque 10 ARTIS CHEM ICAE PRINCIPES, AVICENNA A TQU E GEBER, H O C
cum dihgentia Impressus (Hildesheim: Olms, 1964. Reprint of Venice, 1507), f. 6r: “Ipsum Volumine Continentur. Quorum alter nunquam hactenus in lucem prodijt: alter vero vestutis
quoque sanguinem aliis invenimus admixtum humoribus que ab eo separantur. Cum exmplaribus coUatus, atque elegantioribus & pluribus pguris quam antehac ilhistratus, doctrinae
enim extrahitur et ordinatim ponitur in catin visu discemitur quod separatur in hums professoribus, hoc nostra editwne turn iucundior turn utilior evasit Adiecto Indice rerum
partem que est sicut spuma. et est colera rubea: et partem que est sicut fex et res & verborum copioso. Cum gratia & privilegio. Basileae per petrum pemam M.D. LXXII.,
turbida. et est melancolia: et partem que est sicut albumen ovorum et est flegma: ut pp. 14—15: the first product is “clarius lacryma: & illud est aqua, post destillabis
partem aquosam que est aquositas. . . . ” inde alia non tam clara, & vertitur in colore citrino, & illud est aer, postea remanebit
8 Bacon, De erroribus medicorum, in Litde and Withington, De retardatione accidentium terra combusta in fundo nigra, modo habes aquam, aerem & terram: ignis evanuit
senectutis, pp. 156-157: “Medicus autem, licet tangat, tamen non explicat sed transmittit in vaporibus & efficitur fumus, & fumus versus est in aquam. Et intellectum est,
medicos ad alkimiam. sicut patet per Avicennam in primo canone, ubi disputat quia omnia quae sunt in mundo de vitali & herbali sunt composita de istis quatuor
contra Galienum dicentem quod solus sanguis currat per nutriendas partes corporis. elementis, & ad ilia se solvunt.”
Ostendit autem quod alii humores sunt necessarii propter multas causas, et post 11 MS. Vaticanus reginensis latinus 1317, f. 129r-v.
322 WILLIAM R. NEWMAN AN OVERVIEW OF ROGER BACON S ALCHEMY 323

they do not retain their own names in them. . . Supporting this In this summarizing passage, Bacon equates his notion of the four
universality of the four humors with references to pseudo-Avicenna simple humors with Aristotle’s theory that terrestrial things such as
and pseudo-RazI, Bacon continues to say that the humors are usually metals are generated from two sublunar exhalations—one hot and
called blood, choler, melancholy, and phlegm only when found in dry, the other cold and moist—mentioned at Meteors 378a. One can
animals. Nonetheless, Bacon says, the simple humors exist in beings therefore see precisely what Bacon means when he says that all
other than the animals, though they are not normally called such. minerals and metals are composed of humors. He is referring to his
Indeed, “in no science other than alchemy are they named such in four simple humors, and according to him it is only the alchemical
things other than animals. . . . ” Alchemical writers, especially pseudo- writers, especially pseudo-RazI, who have dared to assert that these
RazI, state that there are twelve elements or humors from which the are components of the world as a whole.14*Bacon’s claim then that
whole world is composed. These are what Bacon customarily calls theoretical alchemy provided a theory of generation not found in
the four elements, the four simple humors, and the four compound other sources refers, in sum, to the derivation of the world from the
humors. He points out, however, that the alchemists are in the habit simple humors blood, phlegm, choler, and melancholy, or, to use his
of substituting one name for another, in order to maintain secrecy. peculiar terms, humor aereus, aqua vite, virtus ignea, and calx. This was
Thus a given humor can be referred to by the predominant element the primary contribution that theoretical alchemy made to his con­
in it, and a given element can be named after the humor in which cept of terrestrial coming-to-be. At the same time, alchemy provided
it predominates.12 At any rate, the composition from twelve elements a powerful tool of material analysis in its techniques for the separa­
or humors, Bacon tells us, is especially true for man, the microcosm. tion of the elements, and this technology of stratification and distil­
In the case of inanimate things, on the other hand, one cannot argue lation confirmed the very elemental theory that Bacon derived from
for the presence of all four composite humors (blood, phlegm, choler, alchemical sources.
and melancholy), though wherever four simple humors are present,
one can of course say that one composite humor is there. Conclud­
ing this passage, Bacon summarizes as follows: Medical Alchemy
But all things, both animate and inanimate, are generated from the
four humors, for the humors are resolved from earth and water by It was precisely the alchemist’s ability to analyze and purify material
means of vapor, as Aristotle teaches in Book IV of the Meteors, in the substances that led Bacon to an application of alchemy to medicine.
beginning, from which [humors] stones, salts, sulfurs, atraments, bitu­
mens, oils, colors, metals and all minerals come into being.. . ,13

compositi ex simplicibus et maxime in homine qui est totus mundus scilicet minor
nam minor mundus occultatur et nichilus invenitur hec 12 in omnibus rebus animatis
12 MS. Vaticanus reginensis latinus 1317, f. 129r. scilicet quatuor ultima non inveniuntur nisi in rebus animatis scilicet plantis et
13 From the unpublished section of the Opus minus transcribed by Dr. George animalibus et hominibus in qualibet tamen re mixta ex humoribus simplicibus invenitur
Molland from Vaticanus reginensis latinus 1317, f. 129r: “Sed in aliis rebus omni­ unus de compositis quia simplices sunt in composito unde alkimistice locutus est
bus sunt, non tamen nomina retinent in eis. . . . Quod enim hii humores sint in Rasi cum dicit hominem et totum mundum componi ex illis 12 nam cum dicit
omnibus dicit Avicenna maiori libro et Rasi in libro qui lumen luminum vocatur. . . . quod homo componitur et totus mundus intelligitur homo qui est minor mundus
[129v] Corpora hec quatuor in animalibus habent nomina specialia et vulgata ut nam in eo maxime apparent hec 12 corpora.. . . Ex his vero humoribus omnia
dixi sed in aliis rebus non dicimus quod sit sanguis nec est colera nec melancolia generantur tarn animata quam inanimata nam humores resolvuntur a terra et aqua
nec flemma si proprie loquamur. Sed concedimus bene quod sunt humores simplices per modum vaporis ut vult Aristoteles 4 Metheororum in principio ex quibus hunt
similes illis qui sunt in animalibus et idem secundum speciem licet non sic nominentur lapides et sales et sulphures et attramenta et bitumina et olea et colores [130v] et
quantum ad usitatem et propriam nominationem nec in aliqua scientia nominentur metalla et omnia mineralia. . . .” The manuscript was identified by Auguste Pelzer,
in rebus aliis ab animalibus nisi in alkimia. . . . [130r] Et ideo dicit Rasi in libro qui “Une source inconnue de Roger Bacon,” Archivum Jranciscanum historicum, Annus XII,
lumen luminum vocatur quod sunt quatuor elementa demum alia usque 12 ex quibus Fasc. I—II, pp. 44-67.
hoc et totus mundus componitur ex quo habetur quod 12 sunt corpora naturalia ad 14 Bacon, De enoribus, p. 156: “. . . hec sola scientiarum, scilicet alkimia, ausa est
species rerum generabilium et corruptibilium consistentium in hoc mundo scilicet diffinire quod primo sunt 4or elementa, deinde aha 4or, et 3° 4or usque ad duodecim,
animatarum scilicet quatuor elementa et quatuor humores simplices et quatuor ex quibus homo et totus mundus inferior componitur.”
324 WILLIAM R. NEWMAN AN OVERVIEW OF ROGER BACON’S ALCHEMY 325

Since it is in this area that Bacon is at his most original, it will however, when compared to his use for that discipline in the prolon­
behoove us to consider his medical alchemy in some detail. In brief, gation of human life. Perhaps the most comprehensive treatment of
Bacon envisages two roles for alchemy in medicine, both related to Bacon’s macrobiotic project can be found in a little studied work of
the technology contained in alchemical texts, especially the distillation- his, the fragmentary text printed as In libro sex scientiarum in 3° gradu
technology of pseudo-Avicenna’s De anima. The first role consists in sapientie, which contains a comprehensive description of Bacon’s
purifying ordinary pharmaceuticals, which Bacon views as having been macrobiotic project. The Liber sex scientiarum, as I shall call it in accord­
abused by apothecaries. The second concerns a veritable idee fixe in ance with Agostino Paravicini Bagliani, attempts to show the inter­
Bacon’s work, namely the prolongation of human life to its utmost, connectedness of Bacon’s scienlia experimentalis, alchemy, optics (including
by means of substances that have been “reduced to equality” with catoptrics) “operative astronomy,” medicine, and geometry, in achiev­
the aid of alchemy. I shall dispense briefly with the more modest of ing Bacon’s program for the prolongation of human life.18 Bacon
the two plans, for it belongs more to the treatment of Bacon’s medi­ begins the treatise by asserting that even postlapsarian man should
cine than to that of his alchemy. Bacon’s plan to purify drugs by naturally attain to a vastly longer life span than obtains currently,
means of alchemy receives a partial treatment in one of his best but that bad regimen transmitted from father to son has curtailed it
known medical works, the De erroribus medicomm. In this text, Bacon progressively over the centuries.19 As a result of this cumulative folly
is concerned inter alia with the removal of poison (<momentum) from and willfulness in neglecting proper regimen, the complexion of man
otherwise beneficial medicines, such as laxatives. He describes several has been woefully corrupted. Yet, since this corruption arises from
methods of doing this that are explicitly alchemical, as the following: natural causes, it should be capable of a natural correction. Indeed,
. . . resolutions and separations o f one thing from another, which can­ Bacon tells us exactly how he hopes to arrive at a medicine free
not occur without the aid o f alchemy, which teaches how to resolve from corruption that will pass on its salutary benefit to man:
one thing from another.15
. ! . corruption arises in things on account of this— that the form can­
What Bacon wants to separate in the above passage is “gross earthy, not satisfy the total appetite of the matter, and therefore it always desires
another form. And celestial agents are sufficient for leading its appetite
poisonous substances,” which can be isolated from the active ingre­
to a new form up until a form of equal complexion is induced, which
dient (the virtus) of a drug. Moreover, some substances, such as “quick­ is the final good of nature, and this suffices for consummating the
silver, and many others,” must be sublimed, in order to remove their appetite of matter in corruptible things and for taking away their cor­
poisonous qualities.16 In addition, Bacon says that alchemical meth­ ruption and excluding it forever.20
ods must be applied to all metals that are to be ingested; calcination
The “appetite of matter” refers to the insatiable desire, as it were, of
and dissolution “into water” must especially be employed so that the
the inchoate prime matter infused with the forms of corporeality and
metals do not merely pass inertly through the body.17
The type of purificational technology promoted by Bacon’s De
erroribus medkorum has little to do with the separation of the four humors 18 A.G. Little and E. Withington, eds., Fratris Rogeri Bacon De retardahone accidentium
or elements that we described earlier. In the De erroribus Bacon is not senectutis cum aliis opusculis de rebus medicinalibus (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1928), pp.
181-186. For Paravicini Bagliani’s treatment of the text, see “Storia della scienza,”
primarily concerned with purification at the profound level; rather pp. 257-261.
he wants to separate useless or poisonous by-products from a medically 19 Cf. George Molland, “Roger Bacon and the Hermetic Tradition in Medieval
Science,” Vwarium 31 (1993), pp. 140-160, especially pp. 147-148.
desirable active ingredient. This role for alchemy is rather minor, 20 Bacon, In libro sex scientiarum in 3° gradu sapienck, in Little and Withington, Opera
hactenus inedita Rogeri Baconi (Oxford: Clarendon, 1928), vol. 9, pp. 183-4: “corruptio
accidit in rebus propter hoc quod forma non potest complere totum appetitum materie,
15 Bacon, De erroribus medkorum, p. 155: “.. . resolutiones et separationes unius ab et ideo semper appetit alteram formam et agenda celestia sufficiunt ad promovendum
alio, quod norl potest fieri sine potestate alkymie, que docet resolvere quodlibet ex eius appetitum semper in novam formam usque quo inducatur forma equalis
quolibet.” complexionis, que est ultimum bonum nature, et hoc sufficit ad perficiendum in
16 Bacon, De erroribus, p. 165. rebus corruptibilibus appetitum materie et tollere corruptionem et excludere in
17 Ibid. etemum.”
326 WILLIAM R. NEWMAN AN OVERVIEW OF ROGER BACON’S ALCHEMY 327

substance (Bacon’s materia naturalis) to be delim ited and form ed.21 As with this body once acquired? B acon argues that the sapientes have
B acon points out, corruption will continue to occur until the matter invented “optical instrum ents,” w hich they use to gather the celestial
in question receives a form o f equal com plexion; w hen such a form rays, then projecting these onto food, drink, and drugs. A t the end
has been provided, the substance in question will be incorrupt. W hat o f the Liber Sex scientiarum, he makes it clear that these “optical instru­
Bacon has in mind by “equal com plexion” is a state where the qualities m ents” are burning mirrors, w ith w hich he intends to concentrate
o f the four elem ents exist in a condition o f perfect harm ony. This the starlight com ing from beneficent celestial bodies:
does not m ean that the substance in question m ust have equal quanti­
ties o f fire, air, water, and earth. T o the contrary, if that were the Therefore when the excellent experimentor has prepared this body of
equal complexion, he commands the astronomer to consider the rising
case, the substance w ould disintegrate rapidly, for fire, being m uch
of the beneficent stars above the horizon at a future time and the
m ore active than earth, w ould quickly overpow er the latter if the setting of the maleficent stars at that time, and he commands to the
tw o w ere present in equal am ounts. Incorruptibility can only be perspectivist that instruments be made with the aid of geometry that
attained w hen the elem ental qualities in a substance are equal “accord­ congregate the rays in which the equal body is put, so that, after it has
in g to virtue and active pow er,” n ot according to w eight.22 Such a received the wonderworking powers of the stars, it may wonderfully
remove the defect of a [bad] regimen of life contracted from youth,
form o f equal com plexion can be produced in at least three ways:
and restore all that was lost, and retard the effects of old-age, and
first, the bodies o f the resurrected will exhibit perfect tem peram ent, when they do come, mitigate them happily, so that life be prolonged
having had all their impurities purged aw ay by the conflagration.23 marvellously.26
Second, this form already exists within a created substance— gold.
N ot only does Bacon claim that this panacea can slow dow n old-age
N onetheless, B acon insists that the gold must undergo an alchem ical
remarkably, but that it will also rem ove the defects already accum u­
treatm ent in order to m ake it capable o f being digested.24 Finally,
lated by the body. T h e “equal body,” once it has absorbed a suffi­
nature, with the help o f art, can m ake this “equal body,”25 w hich is
cient am ount o f “celestial virtue,” will “contain and m ultiply”27 the
the principle o f incorruptibility within gold, from any body o f unequal
stellar rays; it will then be able to propagate species autonom ously,
com plexion— once the dom inating elem ent in that substance has been
corrupted. reproducing the action o f the beneficent celestial bodies w hen these
are not actually in advantageous positions. By this means:
N o t surprisingly, the m eans o f acquiring such a body o f equal
com plexion will be supplied by alchem y. But w hat should be done . . . opportune remedies will be found against illnesses, pestilences, fam­
ines, and all evils both of the republic and of individuals. . . ,28

21 Theodore Crowley, Roger Bacon: The Problem of the Soul in His Philosophical
Commentaries (Louvain, 1950), p. 104.
22 Bacon, Opus minus, in Brewer, op. cit., p. 369: “Hoc igitur modo bene potest 26 Bacon, Sex scientiarum, pp. 184-5: “Cum igitur experimentator magnificus
esse aequalitas pura secundum virtutem et potestatem activam, licet non secundum preparaverit hoc corpus equalis complexionis, iubet astronomo ut ortum stellarum
quantitatem earum quam medici vocant pondus, sicut erit in corporibus post virtuosarum super orizonta de futuro consideret et occasum stellarum prave actionis
resurrectionem. Et ideo non erit aliqua alteratio mixto tali. Nam ubi aequalitas ad illud tempus, et iubet perspective ut cum adiutorio geometrie fiant instrumenta
potentiarum activarum est non potest esse corruptio, secundum Aristotelem secundo congregantia radios in quibus ponatur corpus equale, ut, postquam receperit virtutes
Metaphysicorum. Et secundum Averoym super Decimum. Under Averoys arguit ibi mirificas stellarum, possit miro modo tollere defectum regiminis vite contractum a
contra Galienum, qui posuit in homine aliquo complexionem aequalem. Nam tunc iuventute et restaurare totum deperditum et retardare passiones senectutis et cum
arguit Averoys quod ille esset immortalis, quia non esset actio, nec passio, nec alteratio venerint, eas mitigare feliciter, ut vita mirabiliter prolongetur.”
talis mixti propter aequalitatem. Et ideo nec corruptio. Causa vero praecisa hujusmodi 27 Bacon, Sex scientiarum, p. 185: “Nam cum omnia fiant per virtutem celorum,
rei est quod aequalitas qualitatum elementarium est ultimum quod materia desiderat, congregabimus virtutem stellarum quorumcumque volumus, et res componemus in
et nobilissimum in mixto unum mixtum est. Et ideo habita aequalitate quiescit loco congregationis que recipiant virtutem celestem quam continebunt et multiplicabunt
appetitus materiae.” a se per actionem naturalem, ut faciant operationes debitas constellationi in absentia
23 Bacon, Sex scientiarum, p. 184. The same theme is covered also in the Opus stellarum. . . . ”
minus, ed. Brewer, pp. 370-375, and in the Opus maius, vol. 2, p. 212. 28 Ibid., “. . . et sic contra infirmitates et pestilencias et fames et omnia mala
24 Bacon, Sex scientiarum, p. 183. personarum et rei publice inveniantur remedia oportuna, et sic accidit prolongatio
25 Bacon, Sex scientiarum, p. 184. vite sublimius quam per aliquas vias.”
AN OVERVIEW OF ROGER BACON’S ALCHEMY 329
328 WILLIAM R. NEWMAN

Bacon goes on to say that the “philosopher” Artephius managed to famous Secret of Secrets of pseudo-Aristotle, a work that Bacon held in
live for 1,025 years by using this method, and that by sitting directly the highest regard and even glossed. The Secret of Secrets contains the
in the beam of concentrated starlight, one can become wise as well following riddle for producing the philosophers’ egg, which is evi­
as healthy; the sapience procured thereby will even allow one to know dently meant to be the “philosophers’ stone,” the agent of metallic
all future and past events.29 transmutation:
Despite the fact that Bacon did not think man capable of effecting Therefore take the animal, vegetable, and mineral stone, which is not
a state of such perfect elemental equality as that to be expected after a stone, and does not have the nature of a stone. This stone is in a
the resurrection, he did believe that art could attain both the perfect certain way compared to the stones of mountains of minerals, plants,
and animals: it is found in every place, in every time, and in every
body of gold and the “equal body” derived from other substances.
man: [it is] changeable into every color: it contains within itself all
In both cases he viewed alchemy as occupying an instrumental role. elements: and it is called the lesser world. And I will name it by its
Indeed, Bacon’s concern with alchemy was such that he devised actual own name, by which the crowd names it, that is, the end of the egg,
recipes for the elixir, and gave explicit instructions for its acquisition. that is to say, the egg of the philosophers. Therefore divide it into four
Although Bacon has been portrayed as an “armchair alchemist,” parts: each part has one nature. Then unite it equally and proportion­
concerned with theory alone, the detail and consistency of his recipes ally, so that there be neither division nor repugnance in it, and you
will have the goal, God willing.34
suggests that this view may be mistaken.30
Pseudo-Aristotle’s alchemical riddle enjoins that the alchemist should
begin his quest with a stone that contains all the elements, is found
Bacon’s Alchemical Practice in every man, and is called the lesser world. This stone is to be
divided into four parts, and then reassembled in a proper proportion.
Bacon’s reputation as an alchemist hinges largely on his famous Epistola As I shall now show, Bacon used his knowledge of alchemical theory
de secretis operibus artis et naturae which ends with three alchemical to solve this riddle in a way that could lead directly to practice.
chapters that describe, in veiled terms, the making of the “philosophical First, as he informs the reader in his commentary to the Secret of
egg.”31 Although it has been argued by a number of scholars that Secrets, the word “stone,” in alchemy, means “anything upon which
these chapters are spurious, they are, as I have shown elsewhere, an alchemical operation begins.”35 In interpreting the riddle, then,
quite similar to a partially unprinted section of the Opus minus.32 Indeed, Bacon felt no need to limit himself to actual stones, but could employ
the chapters take up motifs that are treated throughout Bacon’s work, anything with which an alchemical process can begin. At this point
and they may well be genuine, or contain genuine scraps reassembled Bacon called upon his knowledge of both the genuine and the pseudo-
from Bacon’s work.33 The term “philosophers’ egg” occurs in the Avicenna to help him solve the riddle. As we mentioned above,
Avicenna’s Canon teaches the separation of four humors out of blood,

29 Ibid. Nicholas Clulee brings attention to two late French Artephius manu­
34 Bacon, Secretum secretorum, Robert Steele, ed., Opera hactenus inedita Rogeri Baconis
scripts held in the Bibiotheque de PArsenal (MSS. 2344 and 3009) in his “At the
(Oxford, 1920), vol. 5, pp. 114—115: “Accipe ergo lapidem animalem, vegetabilem,
Crossroads of Magic and Science: John Dee’s Archemastrie,” in Brian Vickers, ed.,
et mineralem, qui non est lapis, nec habet naturam lapidis. Et iste lapis assimilatur
Occult and Scientific Mentalities in the Renaissance (Cambridge, 1986), p. 70, n. 38. I am
quodammodo lapidibus moncium minerarum, et plantarum, et animalium: Et reperitur
not convinced that the Artephius to whom Bacon refers is the author of the Clovis
in quolibet loco et in quolibet tempore et in quolibet homine: Et convertabilis est in
sapientiae majoris published in J J . Manget, Bibliotheca chemica curiosa (Geneva, 1702), I,
pp. 503-9. quemlibet colorem: Et in se continet omnia elementa: Et dicitur minor mundus. Et
ego nominabo ipsum nomine suo quo nominat vulgus, scilicet, terminus ovi, hoc est
30 Singer, “Alchemical Writings,” p. 80, and Muir, pp. 301-302.
dicere, ovum philosophorum. Divide ergo ipsum in quatuor partes: quelibet pars
31 Bacon, Epistola de secretis operibus artis et naturae, in Opera quaedam inedita, vol. 1, habet unam naturam. Deinde compone ipsum equaliter et proporcionaliter, ita quod
pp. 545-551.
non sit in eo divisio nec repugnancia, et habebis propositum, Domino concedente.”
32 MS. Vaticanus reginensis ff. 109v-110v.
35 Ibid., p. 117, n. 1: “Lapis igitur sumitur primo metaphorice pro omni eo super
33 Newman, “The Philosophers’ Egg: Theory and Practice in the Alchemy of
Roger Bacon,” Micrologus, 3 (1995), pp. 75-101. quo incipit operacio alkimie.”
330 WILLIAM R. NEWMAN AN OVERVIEW OF ROGER BACON’S ALCHEMY 331

and each of these humors can be named after the element that pre­ employing these divided parts of the philosophers’ egg. The alche­
dominates in it. Therefore blood would certainly be an obvious candi­ mist should begin with human blood:
date for something that contains all four elements. Blood, moreover,
in which the four humors, namely phlegm, choler, blood, and melan­
is surely found “in every man,” and if we are talking about human
choly, are distinguished by the eye. The alchemist seeks to separate
blood, then it would certainly make sense to refer to the philoso­ these humors from one another and to purge each from the other.
phers’ egg as “the lesser world,” since as Bacon admitted in a pas­ When they have been led back to their pure simplicities by means of
sage cited above, man is a microcosm. Bacon was helped along in difficult works, then they should be mixed in a secret and most sure
this interpretation of the philosophers’ egg by a passage from pseudo- proportion. Quicksilver is added to them after it has been mortified
Avicenna’s De anima, which explicitly identifies the subject of this riddle and sublimed multiply. Likewise the calx or powder of the baser metal
from which the nobler will be made. Likewise [calx of] the nobler.
with human blood:
Then they should be incorporated together until they make one body.
Take the stone which is not a stone, and is not of the nature of stones: This is then projected onto the liquefied baser metal, and it thus becomes
divide it into four parts— air, fire, earth, and water, and we find no nobler.37
other way that this can be done except in the following mode: man
This blueprint for an alchemical elixir is repeated in various forms
lives dies, and subsists on account of [his] blood. Thus the stone: there­
fore they say that this stone is the animal stone, and therefore, because at other points in Bacon’s works.38 One must begin with stratified
there is no higher soul than [that in] man, they take the stone of blood, whose phlegm, choler, blood, and melancholy are then sepa­
man. . . . The blood necessary in this work is [that] of man: because rated and purified. These must then be recombined in a secret pro­
the soul of man is better than that of all other [animals], and because portion, mixed with purified mercury, the calx of a base metal, and
the body of sol and luna is better than all others, we therefore take the the calx of a noble metal. The resulting elixir can then be used as
blood of man, which is a soul, because the soul of man is blood, and
the blood is soul, and therefore the stone is called “animal.”36
a means of transmuting base metals. It is evident that Bacon has
combined the practice of pseudo-Avicenna with his own belief that
Pseudo-Avicenna openly equates the “stone which is not a stone,” the alchemist must operate on a corpus equate: this is the significance
the philosophical egg of the Secret of Secrets, with human blood. This of the secret proportion alluded to above. And it would appear that
must be divided into parts, just as in pseudo-Aristotle. In pseudo- Bacon believed his mercurial medicine to be applicable not only to
Avicenna’s De anima this division is then openly equated with the the imperfect metals, but to ailing humans as well. In the short treat­
separation of the elements that the text prescribed for apples, milk, ment of alchemy that Bacon gives in his Opus maius, he claims that
and other substances by means of stratification and distillation. Bacon the Secret of Secrets’ riddle about the philosophical egg reveals both
therefore could invoke the authority of both the genuine and the the secret of metallic transmutation and the means of prolonging
pseudonymous Avicenna in support of his view that the philosophers’ human life to its utmost:
egg referred to human blood, which had to be divided into its four
parts, the simple humors. Bacon’s commentary on the Secret of Secrets 37 Bacon, Secretum secretorum, p. 117, n. 1: “Lapis igitur sumitur primo metaphorice
then proceeds to detail a recipe for the philosophers’ stone or elixir, pro omni eo super quo incipit operacio alkimie. Et hoc potest esse res mineralis, ut
sulphur et arsenicum, set melior est res vegetabilis ut fructus et partes arborum et
herbarum, optime vero sunt res animales ut sanguis ovum et capilli, et maxime
partes hominis, et inter illas sanguis, in quo ad oculum distinguntur quatuor humores,
36 Pseudo-Avicenna, De anima, pp. 275-276: “Accipe de petra quae non est petra, & scilicet, fleuma, colera, sanguis, et melancolia. Alkimista igitur querit separare hos
non est de naturis petrae, divide per 4. partes, per aerem & ignem, & terram, humores abinvicem et purgare quemhbet a quolibet. Et cum per difficilia opera
& aquam, & nos non possumus invenire quod aliter fieri possit, nisi in hunc modum: & fuerint redacta ad puras simplicitates suas, tunc commiscentur secreta proporcione
de sanguine vivit homo, & moritur & stat. Ita de lapide: ideo dicunt, quod iste lapis et certissima, quibus additur argentum vivum postquam mortificatum fuerit et
est lapis animalis: & ideo, quia non est anima altior homine: ideo accipiunt lapidem sublimatum pluries. Similiter calx sive pulvis metalli vihoris de quo fiet nobilius. Et
hominis. . . . [p. 397:] Sanguis necessarius in magisterio est hominis: & quia hominis similiter nobilioris. Et post hec incorporentur adinvicem donee fiant unum corpus.
anima est melior omnibus, & quia corpus solis & lunae est omnibus melius, ideo Et tunc proicitur in metallum vilius liquatum et fit nobilius.”
mittimus sanguinem hominis, qui est anima, quia hominis anima est sanguis, & 38 Roger Bacon, Part of the Opus tertium of Roger Bacon, ed. A.G. Little (Aberdeen:
sanguis est anima: & ideo vocatur lapis animalis.” The University Press, 1912) p. 88.
AN OVERVIEW OF ROGER BACON’S ALCHEMY 333
332 WILLIAM R. NEWMAN

De mineralibus is not an alchemical text proper, in that it does not


Aristotle said to Alexander—“I wish to show you the greatest secret;”
and indeed it is the greatest secret, for not only would it procure the have alchemical praxis as its goal. Indeed, Albert wrote the work as
good of the republic and something desired by all by providing enough a mineralogical supplement to the corpus of Aristotle, which he found
gold, but what is infinitely greater, it would prolong human life. For deficient in that area. All the same, Albert does defend alchemical
that medicine which would take away all dirtiness and corruptions of a transmutation, arguing that good alchemists act towards metals just
base metal, so that it become very pure silver and gold, is considered by as physicians do toward their patients.41 The alchemists first clean
the wise to be able to take away the corruptions of the human body
to the degree that life would be prolonged through many centuries.39 and purify the old metal, just as doctors employ emetics and dia­
phoretics as purges. Then they strengthen the “elemental and celes­
One can see then that Bacon’s theory of the corpus equale allowed tial powers” in the metal’s substance, primarily by adding drug-like
him to link the metallurgical transmutation of such texts as the De components and heat. In all this the alchemist must copy nature’s
anima of pseudo-Avicenna and the alchemy of pseudo-Razf with his methods very closely, using fire to achieve the effects of the stars,
macrobiotic program. In either case the same subject was required— and even modelling his vessels on the presumed shape of the subter­
a body that was perfecdy tempered in regard to its elemental quali­ ranean caverns in which metals and ores are generated. By this means,
ties. Such a subject had the power to impart its own incorruptibility Albert argues, the alchemist can make art act as an instrument of
to other matter—be it metal or flesh—and to end the incessant warfare nature, so that the gold or silver produced will be a true natural
among the unequally powerful elemental qualities hitherto resident product, not a mere human artifact.
therein. As we know from the Liber sex scientiarum, this power could Albert’s alchemical theory, which is closely based on the Aristote­
be heightened even further by subjecting the corpus equale to celestial lian idea that art can perfect what nature has left incomplete (.Physics
influences that had been magnified by means of burning mirrors. In ii.8.199a) is radically different from that of Bacon. First, although
the final section of this essay we shall consider the place of Bacon’s Albert draws a parallel between medicinal cures and the perfection
remarkable theory within the context of contemporary alchemy. of base metals, this is for him only a linguistic commonality. There
is never any question in the De mineralibus of alchemical “medicines”
actually being used to cure ailing humans: his medicines are for metals
Bacon’s Alchemy in Context alone. Hence the medical and macrobiotic aspect of Bacon’s alchemy
is completely absent from Albert’s work. Second, Roger’s belief that
It is instructive to compare Bacon’s alchemical program with those alchemy should operate by producing a corpus equale from the sepa­
of other writers on the same subject who were also active in the rated and purified humors derived from human blood finds no par­
second half of the thirteenth century. O f these the two most influential allel in the De mineralibus. Indeed, Albert’s insistence on following the
were surely Albertus Magnus, whose De mineralibus was written between generative methods of nature would seem a priori to exclude such
1250 and 1254, and the author of the Summa perfectionis, who called operations from his canon of accepted techniques. Nature does not
himself “Geber,” and wrote around the end of the century.40 Albert’s make the precious metals by separating human blood, so why should
the alchemist?
39 John Henry Bridges, ed., The “Opus mains” o f Roger Bacon (Oxford: Clarendon The same emphasis on following the methods of nature can be
Press, 1897): vol. 2, p. 215 “.. . Aristoteles dixit ad Alexandrum ‘volo ostendere found in the Summa perfectionis of “Geber,” and it is quite likely, as I
secretum maximum’; et vere est secretum maximum, nam non solum procuraret
bonum reipublicae et omnibus desideratum propter auri sufficientiam, sed quod plus
est in infinitum, daret prolongationem vitae. Nam ilia medicina, quae tolleret omnes intemationales d’histoire des sciences, 35 (1985), pp. 240-302. For Albert, see Robert Halleux,
immunditias et corruptiones metalli vilioris, ut fieret argentum et aurum purum, “Albert le grand et ralchimie,” in Revue des sciences phibsophiques et theologiques 66 (1982),
aestimatur a sapientibus posse tollere corruptiones corporis humani in tantum, ut pp. 57-80. See also Newman, The Summa perfectionis of pseudo-Geber (Leiden: E.J. Brill,
vitam per multa secula prolongaret. Et hoc est corpus ex elementis temperatum, de 1991), pp. 17-20.
quo prius dictum est.”
41 Albertus Magnus, Liber mineralium, in Auguste Borgnet, ed., B. Alberti M agni. . .
40 William Newman, “New Light on the Identity of Geber,” in Sudhoffs Archiv, 69 Opera Omnia (Paris, 1890), vol. 5 pp. 70-71.
(1985), pp. 76-90; Newman, “The Genesis of the Summa perfectionis,” in Archives
334 WILLIAM R. NEWMAN AN OVERVIEW OF ROGER BACON S ALCHEMY 335

have argued elsewhere, that its author was influenced by Albert.42 is not to say that Bacon was without influence, of course, for Thorndike
But the Summa goes even further than the De mineralibus, for it pro­ and Kibre list some thirty alchemical incipits associated with Bacon’s
scribes all “organic” reagents such as blood, hair, and urine, and name, many of these surely by his followers. But among such
restricts the ingredients of the philosophers’ stone to mercury, sulfur, “Baconian” works there are few that betray a genuine knowledge of
and “arsenic,” the presumed components out of which nature fashions Roger’s alchemy.47 It seems, rather, that his was a name to conjure
the metals. This again is an attempt to model alchemical techniques with, at least in alchemical circles, and that this conjuration was based
on the generative methods of nature, using the same ingredients as on hearsay rather than close analysis of his genuine views. But it
does she. And like Albert, “Geber” avoids the pharmaceutical appli­ remains to be said that Roger Bacon’s bold synthesis of alchemy and
cation of his elixirs, although he too calls them “medicines.” Finally, medicine, in which both are subordinate to scientia experimental, was
the Summa avoids all attempts to arrive at a proper tempering of a significant novelty for its time, and if it did not have a major impact,
elemental qualities: the very discussion of such qualities is largely it did at least foreshadow the development of a medical alchemy in
absent from the work. Instead, the theory behind “Geber’s” proc­ the following century.
esses is driven by a corpuscular view. The author believes that the
metals are made up of minute corpuscles which diminish in size with
the perfection of the metal. Hence his major goal is the acquisition Bibliography
of an exceedingly subtle medicine whose particles can penetrate to
the profundity of a base metal and bond therewith. Needless to say, Albertus Magnus, Liber mineralium, in Auguste Borgnet, ed., B. Alberti Magni. . .
this is utterly distinct from the alchemical theory of Roger Bacon. Opera Omnia (Paris, 1890), vol. 5.
Allard, Guy-H., “Reactions de trois penseurs du XIIIe siecle vis-a-vis de
As Lynn Thorndike remarked in his History of Magic and Experimen­ l’alchimie,” in La science de la nature: theories et pratiques. Cahiers d'etudes medievales,
tal Science, the dominant alchemical theory of the fourteenth century II (Paris, 1974), pp. 97-106.
maintained that transmutation should proceed by means of “mer­ Anawati, Georges C., “Avicenne et l’alchimie,” Oriente e occidente nel medioevo:
cury alone.”43 The “mercury alone” theory informs the works of Filosofia e scienze (Rome, 1971), pp. 285-341.
Avicenna, Liber canonis Avicenne revisus et ab omni errore mendaque purgatus summaque
Amald of Villanova, John Dastin, Bernard of Trier, and others. An
cum diligentia Lmpressus (Hildesheim: Olms, 1964. Reprint of Venice, 1507).
analysis of these authors and their sources has allowed me to deter­ ------ , pseudo, ARTIS CHEMICAE PRINCIPES, AVICENNA ATQUE
mine elsewhere that they are all heavily dependant on the Summa GEBER, HOC Volumine Continentur. Quorum alter nunquam hactenus in
perfectionis of “Geber.”44 It was “Geber,” not Roger Bacon, who pro­ lucem prodijt: alter vero vestutis exemplaribus collatus, atque elegantioribus & pluribus
vided the dominant alchemical theory of the late Middle Ages. On fguris quam antehac illustratus, doctrinae huius professoribus, hac nostra editione turn
iucundior turn utilior evasit Adiecto Indice rerum & verborum copioso. Cum
the other hand, it is true that the fourteenth century witnessed the gratia & prwilegio. Basileae per petrum pemam M.D. LXXII.
wide dispersion of a genuine medical alchemy in the form of the
Bacon, Roger, Opera hactenus inedita Rogeri Baconi, Robert Steele, ed., (Oxford:
Liber de consideratione quinte essentie omnium rerum of the well-known Clarendon, 1905-).
Franciscan prophet John of Rupescissa.45 But Rupescissa’s medical ------ , Opera quaedam hactenus inedita, J.S. Brewer, ed., (London: Longman,
agenda is significantly different from Bacon’s, and he seems to have Green, Longman, and Roberts, 1859).
developed his alchemical medicine quite independently.46 All of this ------ , pseudo-, Sanioris medicinae D. Rogeri Baconis Angli. . . Francojurti, Typis
Johannis Saurii, Sumptibus Loannis Theobaldi Schonvvetteri, Anno M.DCLLL.
Bignami-Odier, “Jean de Roquetaillade,” in Histoire litteraire de la France (Paris:
Imprimerie nationale, 1981), vol. 41, pp. 75-240.
42 Newman, The Summa perfectionis o f pseudo-Geber, pp. 215-223.
43 Lynn Thorndike, A History of Magee and Experimental Science (New York: Colum­
bia University Press, 1934), vol. 3, p. 58.
44 Newman, The Summa perfectionis of pseudo-Geber, pp. 193-208. 47 One obvious exception to this ignorance is found in the Tres epistolae attrib­
45 Robert Halleux, “Les ouvrages alchimiques de Jean de Rupescissa,” in Histoire uted to Bacon. But as I have argued elsewhere, that too is probably a forgery. See
litteraire de la France (Paris: Imprimerie nationale, 1981), vol. 41, pp. 241-284. Newman, “The Alchemy of Roger Bacon and the Tres epistolae Attributed to Him,”
46 Ibid., pp. 250, 253, 256, 266-267. pp. 471-479.
336 WILLIAM R. NEWMAN

Brehm, Edmund, “Roger Bacon’s Place in the History of Alchemy,” Ambix,


23 (1976), pp. 53-57.
Bridges, John Henry, ed., The “Opus maius” of Roger Bacon (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1897). 14. ROGER BACON AND MEDICINE: THE
Getz, Faye Marie, “To Prolong Life and Promote Health: Baconian Alchemy PARADOX OF TH E FORBIDDEN FRUIT AND THE
and Pharmacy in the English Learned Tradition,” in Sheila Campbell, SECRETS OF LONG LIFE
et al., Health, Disease and Healing in Medieval Culture (London: Macmillan,
1992).
Faye Getz
Halleux, Robert, “Les ouvrages alchimiques de Jean de Rupescissa,” in Histoire
litteraire de la France (Paris: Imprimerie nationale, 1981), vol. 41, pp. 241—
284.
Hime, H.W.L., “Roger Bacon and Gunpowder,” in A.G. Little, Roger Bacon
Roger Bacon was not a physician, but in his own opinion, and in
Essays (Oxford, 1914), pp. 321-335. the opinion of men who took him seriously, he was something better:
Linden, Stanton J., “Roger Bacon in the Age of Francis: The mirror ofalchimy
an interpreter of nature’s signs, a fierce advocate of simplicity over
and the mirror o f nature,” in Cauda Pavonis, 10 (1991), pp. 10-13. complexity, of openness over obscurity, and most of all, of proper
Newman, William R., “The Philosophers’ Egg: Theory and Practice in the
medicine—a return to a pristine state of long life and pure language,
Alchemy of Roger Bacon,” Micrologus, 3 (1995), pp. 75-101. once known to the patriarchs but now lost in a Babel of decayed
-, “The Alchemy of Roger Bacon and the Tres epistolae Attributed to tongues and Original Sin. If Bacon appeared to patriotic alchemists
Him,” in Comprendre et maxtriser la nature au moyen age (Geneva: Librairie an English Hermes Trismegestus, then he seems also to have been
Droz, 1994), pp. 461-479.
------ , The Summa perfectionis of pseudo-Geber (Leiden: EJ. Brill, 1991).
England’s very own Pliny, with an encyclopedic knowledge of the
secrets of nature and a cranky old man’s nostalgia for better times.
Paravicini Bagliani, Agostino, “Storia della scienza e storia della mentalita:
What the Roman Republic was for Pliny, just so the glory days of
Ruggero Bacone, Bonifacio VIII e la teoria della prolongatio vitae,” in
Aspetti della letteratura latina nel secolo XIII (Firenze: La Nuova Italia, the Old Testament were for Bacon. Similarly, as the paterfamilias super­
1986), pp. 243-280. vised the physical and spiritual needs of his family and his slaves,
Pattison Muir, M.M., “Roger Bacon: His Relations to Alchemy and Chem­ so the Old Testament patriarch looked out for the members of his
istry,” in A.G. Little, Roger Bacon Essays (Oxford, 1914), pp. 285-320.
household, a task requiring several species of potency bitterly lamented
Pelzer, Auguste, “Une source inconnue de Roger Bacon,” Archwumfranascanum
historicum, Annus XII, Fasc. I—II, pp. 44-67. in Bacon’s own less-virile times. Bacon like Pliny held “professional”
Pereira, Michela, I’oro dei filosojv saggio sulle idee di un alchimista del trecento (Spoleto: physicians in similar contempt to John of Salisbury for lawyers
Centro Italiano di studi sull’alto medioevo, 1992), pp. 43-83. physicians were money-grubbing, dependent, and ignorant. A properly-
Ruska, Julius, “Die Alchemie des Avicenna,” Isis, 21 (1934), pp. 14-51. educated patrician knew how to run his household without asking
------ , “Pseudepigraphe Rasis-Schriften, ” in Osiris, 1 (1939), pp. 31-94. any “experts,” save his fellow patriarchs, and it was medicine as part
Singer, Dorothea Waley, “Alchemical Writings Attributed to Roger Bacon,” of a general knowledge of the natural world, not medicine as an
Speculum, 1 (1932), pp. 80-86. intellectual speciality, that Bacon advocated so strenuously. The scope
Stapleton, H.E., et al, “Two Alchemical Treatises Attributed to Avicenna,” of Bacon’s medical writings is narrow—confined by and large to
Ambix, 10 (1962), pp. 41-82.
restoring the vitality of old men—and his knowledge of his subject
very limited, especially as compared to the titans of medical scholas­
ticism writing in Italy at the same time. But Bacon, or rather the
image of Bacon, was dear to the hearts of the English, who magni­
fied his work almost beyond reason, and followed his interest in
medical restoration into the fifteenth century and beyond.1

1 See George Molland, “Roger Bacon and the Hermetic Tradition in Medieval
ROGER BACON AND MEDICINE 339
338 FAYE GETZ

Encyclopedic or Natural Historical Medicine The disregard Romans like Cato and Pliny had for what they felt
to be excessive bodily concerns, the respect for communal life, their
Long before the Norman Conquest, Christian missionaries and their nostalgia for better times, and the reverence they held for the aged
followers brought the Latin encyclopedic tradition to England. Roman man ran against Greek notions of progress5 and Greek idealization
patricians like the elder Cato and Pliny the elder wrote about medi­ of the young male athlete, the latter an obsession Pliny thought would
cine as part of the sort of knowledge the paterfamilias (patriarch of a lead to degeneracy of the worst sort. Indeed, it is remarkable that,
country estate, of his family, his servants, animals, and slaves) ought while Greek thinkers included gymnastics among the liberal arts, the
to have. For these men, simple remedies were part of traditional activities proper to a gentleman, the Romans typically left gymnas­
learning about estate management. These writers were aware of the tics out.6
accomplishments of Greek philosophical physicians, but found their During the social and cultural disorganization that accompanied
concern with the body excessive, even effeminate. In Pliny’s encyclo­ the decline of Roman authority in the west, much of the Roman
pedic Historia Naturalis, the writer denounced the repellent foreign encyclopedic tradition perished. Celsus and Varro, who included a
ways of Greek medicine and their malign effects on once-great Rome: large amount of medical material in their encyclopedias, were lost,
“It is certainly true that our degeneracy, due to medicine more than or nearly so.7 But Pliny, Latin compilations of late antiquity like the
to anything else, proves daily that Cato was a genuine prophet and works of Boethius, Martianus Capella, and Macrobius, and a host of
oracle when he stated that it is enough to dip into the works of anonymous texts attributed to various ancients, survived, especially in
Greek brains without making a close study of them.”2 Pliny’s own monastic communities,8*where Roman ideas about simple medicines,
remedies were above all things simple, based on nature lore and Stoic retirement, communal living under a male leader, and disinterest
Roman tradition. We would call them folk medicine, old wives’ tales,
or even magic,3 and yet they are some of the most respected records
of written medicine that survive in western Europe.4
see Volker Zimmermann, Rezeption und Rolle der Heilkunde in landessprachigen handschrifilichen
Kompendien des Spatmittelalters (Stuttgart, 1986), esp. “Die Rezeption der Heilkunde aus
den Kompendien in die ‘Hausvaterliteratur,’” 120-6.
Science,” Vivarium 31 (1993) 140-60 and The Mirror o f Alchimy: Composed by the Tkrice- 5 T hat physicians of the past knew less than their successors was stressed by the
Famous and Learned Fryer, Roger Bachon, ed. Stanton J. Linden, (New York, 1992). Hippocratic text “The Science of Medicine,” in Hippocratic Writings, ed. G.E.R. Lloyd
(New York, 1978), 139-47. On the complexities of medieval ideas of medical progress,
2 Pliny, Natural History, with an English Translation in Ten Volumes, vol. 8: libri xxviii-
xxxii, trans. W.H.S. Jones, Loeb Classical Library, (Cambridge, 1975), 201 (Latin see Chiara Crisciani, “History, Novelty, and Progress in Scholastic Medicine,” Osiris
on p. 200); Faye Marie Getz, “To Prolong Life and Promote Health: Baconian 6 (1990) 118-39. On Bacon’s own ideas of scientific progress, see David C. Lindberg,
“Science as Handmaiden: Roger Bacon and the Patristic Tradition,” Isis 78 (1987)
Alchemy and Pharmacy in the English Learned Tradition,” in Health, Disease and
Healing in Medieval Culture, ed. Sheila Campbell, Bert Hall and David Klausner (New 518-36.
York, 1992) 143. On Pliny’s encyclopedia, and on his views of Greek physicians, see 6 Paul Abelson, The Seven Liberal Arts: A Study in Mediaeval Culture (New York, 1906,
Roger French, Ancient Natural History: Histories of Nature (London, 1994), 223-5. reissued 1965), 1-10. A more thorough study with citations from primary sources is
3 Pliny’s ideas about the differences between natural and supernatural phenom­ Friedmar Kuhnert, Allgemeinbildung und Fachbildung in der Antike (Berlin, 1961); also
ena are not our own. He cautioned against the use of “portentous magic” (magica M.L. Clarke, Higher Education in the Ancient World (London, 1971), esp. 109-18.
portenta) in remedies but assigned to peony the property of preventing “the mocking 7 On the medicine of Varro and Celsus as “part of the general knowledge that
delusions that the Fauns bring on us in our sleep”: Pliny, Natural History, With an every true paterfamilias was supposed to possess,” see H.I. Marrou, History of Education
English Translation in Ten Volumes, vol. vii: libri xxiv-xxvii, trans. W.H.S. Jones, Loeb in Antiquity, trans. George Lamb (New York, 1956), 254.
Classical Library (Cambridge, 1966), 154—7. 8 C.H. Talbot, Medicine in Medieval England (London, 1967), 9-23; Nancy G. Siraisi,
4 On medieval encyclopedias in general and the survival of Pliny’s in particular, Medieval and Early Renaissance Medicine: An Introduction to Knowledge and Practice (Chicago,
see Maijorie Chibnall, “Pliny’s Natural History and the Middle Ages,” in Empire and 1990), 6-11; in England, Brian Lawn, The Salernitan Questions (Oxford, 1963); M.L.
Aftermath: Silver Latin II, ed. T.A. Dorey (London, 1975), 57-78; and Texts and, Trans­ Cameron, “The Sources of Medical Knowledge in Anglo-Saxon England,” Anglo-
mission: A Survey o f the Latin Classics, ed. L.D. Reynolds (Oxford, 1983), 307-16. O n Saxon England 11 (1983) 135-55. Cameron called attention to a number of writings
the humanistic aspects of this reverence for Pliny and the Latin language, see Jerome that could have been known in English monastic libraries by the middle of the
L. Bylebyl, “Medicine, Philosophy, and Humanism in Renaissance Italy,” in Science eighth century, including Latin epitomes of Dioscorides, Oribasius, and Alexander
and the Arts in the Renaissance, ed. John W. Shirley and F. David Hoeniger (Washington, of Tralles, as well as the Latin writers Marcellus of Bordeaux, Cassius Felix, Caelius
D.C., 1985), 27-49, esp. 35. O n the medieval tradition of paterfamiliar literature, Aurelianus, Pliny, and Isidore of Seville: pp. 137-42.
340 FAYE GETZ 341
ROGER BACON AND MEDICINE

in material wealth found a happy home. Most notable of these monas­ pendia in their vernacular, Old English, as well as in Latin.13 Alexander
tic retreats were on the Benedictine model at Vivarium near Rome, Nequam (d. 1217), a teacher and later an Austin Canon, wrote an
where the senator Cassiodorus, who flourished under the barbarian encyclopedia De naturis rerum, with medical material taken from
emperor Theodoric, retired from public life in 540. Cassiodorus Salernitan sources.14 More popular than any of these was the De
ordered his monks to learn about medicinal herbs, and he had a proprietatibus rerum (On the properties of things) of Bacon’s older
number of medical texts copied, including works attributed (perhaps Franciscan brother Bartholomaeus Anglicus. Bartholomew’s encyclo­
wrongly) to Galen, Hippocrates, and the pharmacist Dioscorides.9 pedia was an aid to the study of the Bible, and it explored such
Monastic medicine, which predated the growth of scholastic medi­ diverse topics the creation of angels, the properties of the soul, the
cine at the universities and continued alongside it, is usually referred names of plants and animals, the duties of each member of a house­
to by historians as “Methodist,” because it concentrated not on the hold, and medicine.
causes or etiology of disease but on therapeutic methods, or “pre- Bartholomew’s original Latin has not been well studied, but a
Salemitan,” because it was the only form of learned medicine known Middle English translation of his encyclopedia, made by John Trevisa
in the west before the introduction of Arabic learning to the west at at the end of the fourteenth century, was the subject of a critical edi­
Salerno in the late eleventh century.10 To these useful descriptive tion.15 The editors have demonstrated in a volume on Bartholomew’s
terms might be added “Stoic,” because the “theory” of this type of sources published subsequently to the edition that the author was
medicine was that God had offered pharmaceutical remedies from bom in England before 1200 and studied first at Oxford, then at
nature, thus giving nature itself a type of divinity; or “natural histori­ Paris. He wrote his encyclopedia probably about 1245 while a teacher
cal” and “encyclopedic,” because the job of the learned man was to of his fellow friars at Magdeburg in Saxony.16
collect and research these remedies from any number of sources.11 Bartholomew’s medical sources were those commonly known both
The encyclopedia had an especially strong tradition in England. at Oxford and at Paris. The most important were the translations/
The Venerable Bede wrote his De natura rerum in the opening years adaptations made by Constantine the African of writings in Arabic
of the eighth century based on Pliny and Isidore of Seville. It was by tenth-century authors, including the Pantegni (by al-Majusi, called
created as a teaching text, presenting knowledge of the natural world in Latin Haly Abbas) and the Viaticum (by Ibn al-Jazzar).17*The medical
as part of an exegesis of the Hexaemeron (six days of Creation).12 material in the encyclopedia is concentrated in Books IV through
Bede’s fellow missionizing Anglo-Saxons assembled medical com­ VII, although other books also contain information on the human
body and on medicinal substances (Book III on the senses, Books

9 Cassiodori Senatoris Institutiones, ed. R.A.B. Mynors (Oxford, 1937), pp. 78-9 (Book
I, chapter xxxi), relevant parts translated in Talbot, Medicine, pp. 13-4; also Anne F. 13 See above Cameron, “Sources of Medical Knowledge,” for the Latin tradition;
Dawtry, “The Modus Medendi and the Benedictine Order in Anglo-Norman England,” Linda E. Voigts, “Anglo-Saxon Plant Remedies and the Anglo-Saxons,” Isis 70 (1979)
Studies in Church History 19 (1982) 25-38. 250-68 is the best source for the Old English tradition.
10 For example, Danielle Jacquart, “The Introduction of Arabic Medicine into 14 “The Scientist,” in The Schools and the Cloister: The Life and Writings of Alexander
the West: The Question of Etiology,” in Campbell, Hall, and Klausner, Health, Dis­ Nequam (1157-1217), R.W. Hunt, ed. and rev. Margaret Gibson (Oxford, 1984),
ease and Healing, pp. 186-95. On Salerno, see H. Bloch, Monte Cassino in the Middle 67-83; manuscripts and printed excerpts 134-6.
Ages (Cambridge, 1980), 1:98-110, 127-36. 15 On the Properties of Things: John Treviso’s Translation of Bartholomaeus Anglicus De
11 On the divinity of nature in Hippocrates and Galen, see Owsei Temltin, Hippoc­ Proprietatibus Rerum, A Critical Text, 3 vols., ed. M.C. Seymour et al. (Oxford, 1975
rates in a World of Pagans and Christians (Baltimore: 1991), 189-96; on natural and 1988). These editors use the Frankfurt 1601 printed edition of De Proprietatibus Return
supernatural causes of disease, see G.E.R. Lloyd, Magic, Reason and Experience: Studies (Frankfurt a.M., 1964).
in the Origin and Development of Greek Science (Cambridge, 1979), esp. 49-57. On Pliny’s 16 M.C. Seymour and Colleagues, Bartholomaeus Anglicus and his Encyclopedia (Aldershot,
Stoicism and the divinity of nature, French, Ancient Natural History, pp. 198-206. 1992) 10. This book provides further endnotes to those supplied in vol. iii of On the
12 Bedae Venerabilis Opera: Pars VI, Opera Didascalica, 1, ed. Charles W. Jones (Cor­ Properties of Things.
pus Christianorum Series Latina, vol. 123A, 1975), 174, 187, xi. Bede did not treat 17 M.C. Seymour, Bartholomaeus Anglicus and his Encyclopedia, pp. 23-5; F.M. Getz,
medicine per se, only plague, which he considered among meteorological phenom­ “The Faculty of Medicine before 1500,” in The History of the University of Oxford, vol. 2:
ena: p. 233 (chapter 37). Late Medieval Oxford, ed. J.I. Catto and Ralph Evans (Oxford, 1992), 376.
342 FAYE GETZ ROGER BACON AND MEDICINE 343

X VI-XVIII on stones, animals and plants, and Book XIX on foods pharmaceutical works, but chose to promulgate the idea that this
and tastes). Bacon, then, had Roman, late antique, Anglo-Saxon, was only a part of learned philosophical advice about the nature of
Norman, and early Franciscan English examples of an encyclopedic the good life. Whereas physicians at the University of Paris, an insti­
or natural historical approaches to the organization of medical knowl­ tution whose teachings Bacon of course knew, were anxious that their
edge, and added to that new medical material emerging from trans­ discipline have its own graduate faculty like the laws and theology,23
lations of Arabic sources. Bacon threw in his lot with Paris’s critics, like Bernard of Clairvaux
over a century before him. The monk Bernard had warned the reli­
gious against medical specialization and resort to medical doctors
Medical Scholasticism and its Critics because such vanities divorced godly learning from its spiritual roots.24
Bacon’s views on medicine seem more like those of Peter of Blois,
Pliny drew his medical knowledge from books18 and so did Bacon. student of John of Salisbury, who saw the growth of the professions
Bacon’s medical template, as it were, is well-known—the Sectretum and their perceived divorce from the improving influence of the
Secretorum—which he believed along with his contemporaries to be undergraduate liberal arts as a threat to moral and philosophical order,
the genuine advice of Aristotle to the then-ruler of the known world, and wanted, with Hugh of St Victor, to keep medicine filed under
Alexander the Great.19 Bacon’s swoonings over this fascinating piece the mechanical arts where they asserted it belonged.25
of Arabic pseudographia are widely attested and will not be repeated In the Secretum, Bacon thought he saw Aristotle the philosopher
here.20 The Secretum’s significance for Bacon’s medicine is the role directing his aristocratic patron’s regimen or daily routine—the so-
model for proper practice he saw in what he thought was the work called non-naturals: sleep and wakefulness, evacuation and retention,
of the Philosopher ipsissimus. food and drink, motion and rest, condition of the air, and state of
How different learned medicine might have been if Aristotle— the emotions, the regulation of which would prolong man’s life to its
himself the son of a court physician—actually had written a work natural extent.26 Aristotle was Alexander’s own countryman and not
precisely on that subject; but that did not happen, and the medi­ a foreigner, acting as his moderate, moral, and educated advisor,
cally-minded were sore taxed to make do.21 Bacon fell to this task just as the faithful had read in Deuteronomy 17 and 18 and as John
with enthusiasm, but instead of embracing Hippocrates and Galen of Salisbury had noted in his Policraticus.27 If the Secretum did not answer
and applying Aristode’s methodology to them as the Schoolmen were
doing under the spell of Ibn Sina,22 Bacon followed another, older
tradition. He did not reject new translations of Arabic medical and Anglicus, Compendium medicine (Lyons, 1510); Healing and Society in Medieval England: A
Middle English Translation of the Pharmaceutical Writings of Gilbertus Anglicus, ed. Faye
Marie Getz (Madison, 1991).
23 In general, Pearl Kibre, “The Faculty of Medicine at Paris, Charlatanism, and
18 For an exploration of Pliny’s methodology of “text criticizing text,” see G.E.R. Unlicensed Medical Practices in the Later Middle Ages,” in Legacies in Law and Medicine,
Lloyd, Science, Folklore and Ideology (Cambridge, 1983), 149. ed. Chester R. Bums (New York, 1977), 52-71.
19 The work, author Islamic but otherwise unknown, dates in all likelihood from 24 Siraisi, Medieval and Early Renaissance Medicine, p. 14.
the middle of the tenth century: Pseudo-Aristotle, The Secret of Secrets, ed W.F. Ryan 25 For Bernard, Peter and Hugh on the university and on the professions, see
and Charles B. Schmitt (London, 1982), 1; also the extremely useful Middle English Stephen C. Ferruolo, The Origins o f the University: The Schools o f Paris and their Critics
edition, Secretum Secretorum: Nine English Versions, ed. M.A. Manzalaoui, Early English (Stanford, 1985), 34, 47-8, especially “The Humanists,” 131-83.
Text Society 276 (1977) ix. 26 “Ars medicinalis remedium non habet nisi regimen sanitatis. Est autem ulterior longae vitae
20 Bacon’s glossing of the Secretum is in Opera hactenus inedita Rogeri Baconi, ed. extensio possibilis .. . regimen sanitatis debeat esse in cibo et potu, somno et vigilia, motu et quiete,
R. Steele et al. (16 vols Oxford [1905/9]-1940) 5. evacuatione et retentione, aeris dispositione, et passionibus animi”: The Opus majus o f Roger Bacon,
21 For a study of what little he did write, see Diego Gracia, “The Structure of Medi­ ed. John Henry Bridges (2 vols. Oxford, 1897, suppl vol. London, Oxford, and
cal Knowledge in Aristotle’s Philosophy,” Sudhoffs Archio 62 (1978) 1-36. Also, C.B. Edinburgh, 1900) 2:204; L.J. Rather, ‘“ The Six Things Non-Natural’: A Note on
Schmitt, “Aristotle among the Physicians,” in The Medical Renaissance of the Sixteenth the Origins and Fate of a Doctrine and a Phrase,” Clio Medica 3 (1968) 337-47;
Century, ed. A. Wear, R.K. French, and I.M. Lonie (Cambridge, 1985), 1-15. Shulamith Shahar, “The Old Body in Medieval Culture,” in Framing Medieval Bodies,
22 For example, Bacon’s near-contemporary, Gilbertus Anglicus, whose Compen­ ed. Sarah Kay and Miri Rubin (Manchester, 1994), 160-86.
dium medicinae was among the first major medical texts to use Ibn Sina: Gilbertus 27 For numerous citations from the Policraticus about the good ruler and the nature
344 FAYE GETZ ROGER BACON AND MEDICINE 345

the question of what Athens had to do with Jerusalem, it came close. “philosophical agriculture” (agricultura philosophica) and alchemy, a dis­
John of Salisbury wanted to demonstrate among the writings of the cipline he believed Aristotle had written of in the SecretumT Bacon’s
patriarchs natural justice; Bacon looked there for natural health. overarching pedagogical agenda, of course, was derived from the great­
Scripture, the Greeks, and the Romans all seemed to point in one est teacher of English Franciscans, Robert Grosseteste. Bacon wanted
direction—that godly medicine was a part of a general philosophical to find a place for medicine in a program of Christian education.3132
learning, learning known to the ancients and found in books, books In order to express his ideas on Christian medicine, Bacon em­
obscured by the bad translations Bacon longed to redact. Just as ployed a powerful metaphorical language common both to Holy Scrip­
philology could return corrupt, Babel-decayed texts to an uncorrupt ture and to pagan learning—redemption or renewal. Textual criticism
state, so medicine could return man’s body to its prelapsarian state would “redeem” corrupt texts and restore them to their original state
before Eve yielded to the false teaching of the Father of Lies. Man before Babel; alchemy would return base metals to their pure state
once knew how this restoration could be accomplished,28 but this was of gold; and, of course, proper medicine would restore the body to
forgotten, and only could be recovered through the proper “decod­ its prelapsarian state (the redemption of the fallen soul was of course
ing” of texts.29 another related matter). All three of these subjects—textual criticism
or philology, alchemy, and medicine—are woven together in Bacon’s
most revealing medical works, a substantial section of the Opus majus
The Nature and Scope of Bacon’s Medical Writings already cited and De erroribus medicorum (On the errors of the physicians).33
Exemplum II of the Opus majus, part six, comes under the heading
Bacon’s medical writings are tightly focussed.30 He confined his advice “scientia experimentalist’ of which Bacon made medicine a part. It is
to adult men, not surprisingly, since he was a friar, and limited his the most detailed and carefully-crafted of Bacon’s medical writings.34*
medical purview to the undergraduate subjects of mathematics, astrol­ He began by noting that some say the lengthening or shortening of
ogy, philosophy, and the mechanical arts, which for him included life is dictated by the position of the stars, which have shifted little
by little from their ideal places at the moment of Creation as the
of his advisors, see Hans Liebeschiitz, Medieval Humanism in the Life and Writings of world grew older. Bacon didn’t know whether or not this were true,
John of Salisbury (London, 1950), 23-74. The Book of Deuteronomy warned against but he suggested instead another reason why man’s life has been
imitating the “abominable customs of those other nations” (18:10), and in general
oudined an ideal of a moderate ruler, surrounded by advisor priests, who “shall
growing shorter (the reader is assumed to know the legendary ages
have no holding or patrimony in Israel. . . the Lord is their patrimony” (18:1-2). of the Old Testament patriarchs), a reason suggested by the “magni-
28 “Et praecipue haec sapientia mundo concessa est per primos, scilicet per Adam etflios ejus, ficentia Scientiae Experimentalis” and written of covertly by Aristotle: a
qui receperunt ab ipso Deo specialem congnitionem in hoc parte, quatenus vitam suam longius
protenderent. Sic videndum est per Aristotelem in libro Secretorum, ubi dicit quod Deus excelsus et
gbriosus ordinavit modum et remedium ad temperantiam humorum et conservationem sanitatis, et
ad plura adquirenda scilicet ad obviandum passimibus senectutis et ad retardandum eas, et mitigandum 31 Michela Pereira, “Un tesoro inestimabile: Elixir e ‘Prolongatio Vitae’ nell’alchi-
hujusmodi; et revalavit ea sanctis et prophetis suis, et quibusdam aliis, sicut patriarchis”: Bridges mia de 300,” Micrologus: I discorsi dei corpi 1 (1993) 164—5.
2:208. 32 O n Grosseteste’s ideas of the importance of the study of ancient languages to
29 Bacon’s disgust for translation of any sort permeates his work. See S.A. Hirsch, science, and on Bacon’s understanding of Grosseteste’s ideas of Christian scholar­
“Roger Bacon and Philology,” in Roger Bacon Essays, ed. A.G. Litde (Oxford, 1914), ship, see J.A. Weisheipl, “Science in the Thirteenth Century,” in The History of the
101-51. University of Oxford, vol. 1: The Early Oxford Schools, ed. LI. Catto and T.A.R. Evans
30 This essay supplies no comprehensive coverage of Bacon’s medical works, but (Oxford, 1984), 435-69.
limits itself to an examination of major writings whose authenticity is reasonably 33 In Latin in Little and E. Withington, pp. 150-79. For an English translation,
established in internal evidence. This is also not a study of Bacon’s sources, most of see Welbom “The Errors of the Doctors.” Dating to 1260-1270 is suggested by
which are noted in E. Withington’s useful “Roger Bacon and Medicine,” in Roger Michael R. McVaugh in his edition of Amald of Villanova, Opera medica omnia ii
Bacon Essays, 337-58, in the relevant Latin texts found in Roger Bacon, De retardatione Aphorismi de gradibus (Granada and Barcelona, 1975), 32, n. 1.
accidentium senectutis cum aliis opusculis de rebus medicinalibus, ed. A.G. Little and 34 The Opus majus was sent to the papal court in late 1267 or early 1268: David
E. Withington (British Soc. Franciscan Studies 14 Oxford 1928), and in Mary Lindberg, Roger Bacon’s Philosophy of Nature: A Critical Edition with English Translation,
Catherine Welbom, “The Errors of the Doctors according to Friar Roger Bacon of Introduction, and Notes of Tie multiplicatione specierum and De speculis comburentibus
the Minor O rder,” Isis 18 (1932) 26-62. (Oxford, 1983), xxv.
346 FAYE GETZ
ROGER BACON AND MEDICINE 347

regimen of health. The non-naturals are arranged in a man’s tem­ but medical authors Dioscorides, Haly (al-Majusi), and Avicenna (ibn
perament from infancy, and almost no physicians (medici) nowadays Sina) all say there is a medicine that will prolong life to its natural
can adjust this. Fathers are corrupted and generate corrupt sons with extent. They won’t let on what it is, though.39
the tendency to die young. This is not the only reason man’s life is Bacon continued, Adam and his sons knew what to do because
shorter than its natural extent. Sins weaken the powers of the soul, God told them; Aristotle hinted in the Secretum that God had a rem­
which in turn debilitate the body and hurry it along toward death. edy to temper the humors, conserve health, and obviate the sufferings
This too is passed along from father to son.35 . of old age and put it off. Saints, prophets, and patriarchs knew about
The implications of what Bacon has argued here are important: this—Pliny especially—but it was hidden from common philosophers.40
The body was naturally healthy, and lack of learned attention to its Bacon had read about this secret medicine in many places, espe­
regimen by people nowadays was the cause of physical deteriora­ cially in the book De accidentibus senectutis, a work believed by many
tion. Nowhere did Bacon suggest that disease “attacks” the body and even in the medieval period to be Bacon’s own.41 He also read about
makes it ill. Physical deterioration was, instead, the absence of health, it in De regimine senum of the Experimentator (al-Razi), who declared
in the same way that Augustine had argued that evil was not an that the substance was bom underwater and found in the viscera of
ontological entity, but the absence of good: “evil is removed, not by long-lived animals. It was temperate in the fourth degree.42 What­
removing any nature, or part of a nature, which had been intro­ ever it was, made by alchemy (ars alkimiae) or by nature (Bacon noted
duced by the evil, but by healing and correcting that which had that gold was temperate in the fourth degree, fourth being the maxi­
been vitiated and depraved. The will, therefore, is then truly free, mum), his conviction was that the remedy would act somehow to
when it is not the slave of vices and sins.”36 Bacon continued that restore the balance of the body’s complexion. The remedy must have
men used to know what to do about premature physical deteriora­ its elements mixed in perfect balance, because this will be the state
tion: “per experientias secretas” it had been discovered and written that of the- (saints’) bodies at the Resurrection—“for the equality of the
this rapid aging is accidental (having avoidable side-effects) and there­ elements in those bodies excludes corruption into eternity.”43*
fore can be treated. The medical art cannot achieve this but the Unlike bodies after the Resurrection, which will want nothing
experimental art can.37 because their elements are perfectly in balance, Adam’s body had
The accidents of old age include grey hair, pallor, wrinkled skin, the elements almost perfectly in balance. Because these elements lacked
lots of mucus, stinking stool, sticky bleariness of the eyes, low blood perfect balance, they strove with each other, and Adam needed
and spirits, insomnia, crabbiness, absentmindedness, and a host of
other unpleasant ills. O ur days are numbered, as Scripture says,38
39 Bridges 2: 206-7.
40 Bridges 2: 208-9.
35 Bridges 2:204—5.
41 Printed in Little and Withington, pp. 1-83; but in the Opus majus, Bacon re­
36 City of God 16:11: Basic Writings of Saint Augustine, vol. 2, ed. Whitney J. Oates ferred to “auctor istius libri,” which would indicate he did not write the work himself
(New York, 1948) 255. What follows is an explanation of how man’s fall was both (p. 210). For a thorough investigation of the correct authorship of the treatise, see
spiritual and physical (p. 256). For more on the “systemic” nature of physical ills, Agostino Paravicini Bagliani “D mito della ‘prolongatio vitae’ e la corte pontificia
see Peter H. Neibyl, “Sennert, Van Helmont, and Medical Ontology,” Bulletin of the del Duecento il ‘De retardatione accidentium senectutis,’” in Medicina e scienze della
History of Medicine 45 (1971) 115-37.
natura alia corte dei papi nel duecento (Spoleto, 1991), 283-326.
37 Bridges 2:205.
42 Bridges 2:210.
38 Here and in other passages, Bacon appears to have in mind the Book of 43 Bridges 2:211-2; citation: “Aequalitas enim elementorum in corporibus illis excludit
Ecclesiasticus, one of the few parts of (apocryphal) scripture dealing with medicine corruptionem in aetemum” (p. 212). Augustine, in the City of God, also discussed the
directly. Moderation in food, drink and emotions are recommended throughout, “incorruptible body which is promised to the saints in the resurrection”: Oates,
while chapter 37 states that “A man’s life lasts a number of days” (25/28). The p. 153. Bede’s Historia Ecclesiastica is full of examples of saints whose sanctity was
following chapter, verses 1-15, honors the doctor and advises the faithful to use known by the fact that their bodies remained uncorrupt. For example, Queen
both him and the medicines of the earth, because the Lord has made them both. Ethelthryth, a “perpetual virgin, whose body could not either be putrified in her
Petrus Hispanus (Pope John XXI) cited passages from Ecclesiasticus to begin his tomb” (pp. 102/103) and Cuthbert, who “after eleven years” burial, was found free
popular medical text, Thesaurus Pauperum, which was written perhaps ten years later of corruption” (pp. 184/185): Baedae Opera Historica, with an English Translation by J.E.
than Bacon’s medical works.
King, vol. 2: Ecclesiastical History of the English Nation (Cambridge, 1963).
348 FAYE GETZ ROGER BACON AND MEDICINE 349

nourishment.44 In his body as a consequence of this slight imbalance was combined with images of sin and resurrection to suggest that it
was a tiny bit of corruption, and that is why he wanted the immor­ was research into food and drink that would alleviate the accidents
tality that would follow if he ate the Forbidden Fruit; for this fruit of old age and extend man’s life to its greatest possible length.49
was deemed to have the elements almost in perfect balance, and for In his second major medical treatise, De erroribus medicorum,50 Bacon
that reason it could carry over its incorruption into Adam. Sages attacked improper medicine from the standpoint of medical human­
wrote about foods or drinks that were perfectly temperate or nearly ism. It is difficult to tell exactly what he used for a model in this
so, but the work and expense of finding out more about them by work, but it has its closest counterpart in the first few chapters of
experience put people off.45 Bacon implied, then, that Original Sin Book 29 of Pliny’s Historia Naturalis. Nearly a century after Bacon’s
resulted as much from the promptings of Adam’s stomach as of text, the humanist poet Petrarch wrote his Invectiva contra medicum, at
his wife. greater length but along similar lines, urging the exiled pope in
Bacon’s implications for proper, dietetic medicine are clear. Per­ Avignon to send away his many doctors and, for the sake of his
fect health lay in a balanced complexion, which will only be achieved health, choose only one.51 Both the Invective and De erroribus, then,
in the resurrected body.46 Perfection wants nothing, but the almost- would seem to belong to a tradition of humanistic anti-physician
perfect body, like Adam’s, needs food and drink. The best food and invective, put forth by fierce defenders of textual scholarship.
drink Bacon wrote of in terms of its purity, simplicity, balance, and Bacon began his bombastic diatribe in typical style, promising much
lack of corruption. It was temperate in the fourth degree—as balanced but delivering considerably less. The physicians of today are guilty of
as possible.47 Bacon offered many suggestions from his readings about thirty-six major errors and countless subsidiary ones, he began, but
what this perfecting food (or remedy) might be: gold, pearls, amber­ later on decided that naming all thirty-six errors would take too long.52
gris, rosemary flowers, something a peasant found in a jar buried in The major errors Bacon did attack fall into two related categories:
the ground, or the Forbidden Fruit. The ancients, and Pliny is the errors-of dependency and errors of ignorance. Good physicians should
last authority named,48 wrote of it, but more experience was needed know for themselves about the quality, use, price, and efficacy of
to know for sure. drugs. Otherwise, they are at the mercy of rustic apothecaries, “who
In this section from the Opus majus, Bacon attacked the question of have no intention if not to deceive them.”53 This leads to the second
proper medicine from the standpoints of natural science and Holy
Scripture. His alchemical imagery of secrecy, perfection, nobility, the
49 The equation of the duties of the good physician with those of the good priest
removal of impurities, and decoding the covert writings of ancients was a medieval commonplace Bacon and others played upon often. See Gerhard
Fichtner, “Christus als Arzt. Urspriinge und Wirkungen eines Motivs,” Fruhmittelalterliche
Studien 16 (1982) 1-18 (excellent bibliography); Ralph Arbesman, “The Concept of
‘Christus Medicus’ in St Augustine,” Traditio it) (1954) 1-28; Jole Agrimi and Chiara
44 The ability to fast over long periods, or not to eat at all was, of course, a sign Crisciani, “Medicina del corpo e medicina delTanima: Note sul sapere del medico
of sanctity. In general, see Caroline Walker Bynum, Holy Feast and Holy Fast: The fino all’inizio del sec. XIII,” Episteme 10 (1976) 5-102.
Religious Significance of Food to Medieval Women (Berkeley, 1987) and Rudolph Bell, Holy 50 A Catalogue of Incipts of Mediaeval Scientific Writings In Latin, ed. Lynn Thorndike
Anorexia (Chicago, 1985). and Pearl Kibre, rev. ed. (London, 1963), cols. 463, 893.
45 Bridges 2:212. 51 The Invectiva is by and large a defence of poetry against the false rhetoric of
46 On the history of Christian obsession with bodily integrity and resurrection, the clamoring physicians, who were after all only practitioners of the mechanical
see Caroline Walker Bynum, The Resurrection o f the Body in Western Christianity, 2 0 0 - arts. Part of the Invectiva is translated into English in Petrarch, A Humanist among Princes:
1336 (New York, 1995), esp. “Fragmentation and Ecstasy: The Thirteenth-Century An Anthology, ed. David Thompson (New York, 1971), 128-30; also, Francesco Petrarca,
Context,” 318—43, which explores some implications of bodily resurrection and con­ Invectiva contra medicum: Testo latino e volgarizzomenta di Ser Domenico Sibestri, ed. Pier
troversies over the Beatific Vision. For pontifical interest in prolongation of life, see Giorgio Ricci and Bortolo Martinelli, new ed. (Rome, 1978); Siraisi, Medieval and
Agostino Paravicini Bagliani, “Ruggero Bacone, Bonifacio VIII, e la teoria della Early Renaissance Medicine, pp. 46-7.
‘Prolongatio Vitae’”, in Paravicini Bagliani, Medicina e scienze della natura, pp. 327-61. 52 “Sed bngum esset prosequi albs defectus vsque ad 36, et bngius eorum ramos protendere,
47 On recipes for food and drink that were intended to restore the temperate nec sufficio”: Little and Withington, p. 153.
complexion, see Terence Scully, “The Sickdish in Early French Recipe Collections,” 53 “Vulgus medicorum non congnoscit suam simplkem medidnam, sed committit se rusticis
in Health, Disease and Healing, pp. 132-40. apothecariis, de quibus constat ipsis medicis, quod non intendunt nisi ipsos decipere”: Little and
48 Bridges 2:211. Withington, p. 150.
350 FAYE GETZ ROGER BACON AND MEDICINE 351

sort of error: ignorance—of mathematical compounding of drugs, of fermentation and distillation: “The seventh defect [among physicians]
astrology, of alchemy, of philosophical agriculture, natural philoso­ is in the fermentation of medicines, because a compound, as Avicenna
phy, and especially of language, which prevents them from under­ says, without fermentation will not work”: The compound drug must
standing medicine and what they ought to do.54 be reduced by proper fermentation into one nature (mam naturam) to
Summarizing Bacon’s text is difficult, largely because it is very dis­ be effective; “this is the secret of secrets that the common among
organized, wandering and doubling back on itself. But it does con­ physicians mistake entirely.”59
tain some important and revealing themes: first of all, that medical For distillation Bacon also made claims. For instance, he asserted
writers disagree with each other all the time when they should be that healing oils and waters ought to be prepared by alchemical means
speaking with one voice: “Authors say the same simple medicine purges [per vias alkimie), through distillations (per distillationes). Many medici­
contraries, i.e. contrary humors, as when Haly says that senna purges nal substances are poisonous, like quicksilver, and need to be miti­
red choler, and Avicenna in his chapter on fumitory says that it gated. Some, like precious stones, gold and silver, pass through the
purges burnt humors, and the Latin authors say that it purges mel­ body too quickly unless they are dissolved. But if they are prepared
ancholy.”55 Discordance of language, then, is a serious barrier to proper through the secret ways of alchemy, with the aid of the scientia
understanding of the meanings of words and thus of the things the experimentalis, they can in small quantity help the human body be­
words are meant to signify.56 Similarly, physicians today spend all yond every expectation. Indeed Aristotle affirmed, that substances
their time arguing about an infinite number of trivial matters, instead can be reduced to their prime matter (ad materiam primam), in the
of learning from experience, to the point that they are always seek­ Metaphysics and at the end of the Meteorology.60
ing but never finding the truth.57 Distillation and fermentation, when properly performed, were use­
Another related topic is Bacon’s preference for simplicity over com­ ful, indeed vital, ways to reduce a medicinal substance to its essential
plexity, a theme he artfully interwove into the language of alchemy. and most powerful nature. What is more, these processes allowed for
Just as astrology and astronomy were the same for him, so were the virtues of compound drugs to be united into one by ridding each
chemistry and alchemy. Bacon, like many writers on pharmacy in of its extraneous dross. Even a substance as forbidding as viper’s flesh,
his time, wanted to purify and reduce medicinal substances to their Bacon argued, could not only be rendered harmless, but useful.61
simple essence. The commonest way of doing this was by infusion— A similar desire for simplicity permeates Bacon’s ideas about the
the way we make tea. This process yielded a very weak form of healing powers of plants and animals. On this point Bacon contrasts
medicine.58 But the Arabs wrote about other ways, most notably the defects of natural philosophy, which deals with argumentation
and universals and not with alchemy, which argues from particular
to the primordial generation of things from elements and humors,
54 “Libri enim authentici sunt pleni vocabulis Arabicis, Greets et Caldeis et Hebreis, ita quod
non potest homo scire quid auctores velint dicere, ut patet in locis irfnitis, et quia ignorant linguam even up to the inanimate parts of animals and plants. “Practical”
Grecam et Arabicam et Hebream, a quibus injinita vocabula tracta sunt in libris Latinorum, alchemy derives the secret of secrets—how to transmute base metals
propter quorum ignorantiam non possunt intelligere medidnam nec operariLittle and Withington,
PP- 153-4; further, “ignoratur naturalis philosophia propter translationis peruersitatem: si vnus
into gold—of which Aristotle spoke to Alexander, from the parts of
dicit Aristotelem sentire hoc, alius dicit ipsum sentire contrarium”: p. 159. animals and plants. Similarly, philosophical agriculture (which covered
55 “Auctores eandem medidnam simplicem dicunt purgare contraria, i.e. contrarios humores, ut
Haly didt quod sene purgat coleram rubeam, et Auicenna capitulo de fim o terre quod purgat
humores adustos, Latini quod m elancoliam Litde and Withington, p. 151; cf. Augustine,
City of God (in writing about the Trinity): “Neither are there many wisdoms, but 59 “7us defectus est in fermentatione medidnarum, quia compodtum, ut didt Auicenna, sine
one, in which are untold and infinite treasures of things intellectual”: Oates, p. 153. fermentatione non valebit.. . hoc est secretum secretorum quod vulgus medicorum omnino ignorat”:
56 On the religious motivation of Bacon’s concern with the meaning of words, see Little and Withington, pp. 152-3; further, p. 167. Bacon no doubt had in mind the
R.W. Southern, Robert Grosseteste: The Growth of an English Mind in Medieval Europe various fermentations described in the fourth book of Anstode’s Meteorology.
(Oxford, 1986), 15-9. 60 Litde and Withington, p. 165.
57 Little and Withington, p. 154. 61 Litde and Withington, pp. 151-2; further, p. 163. Cf. Pliny, Natural History,
58 For practical descriptions of how medieval medical practitioners made drugs, vol. 8, pp. 228/229 (Book 29, chapter 20), in which Pliny wrote of how treacle was
see “Preparation of Medicines,” in Healing and Society, ed. Getz, pp. xxxviii-xli. made of vipers’ flesh.
352 FAYE GETZ ROGER BACON AND MEDICINE 353

Aristotelian ideas of both botany and zoology) determines through opium, deer musk, gold, and Indian rhubarb, with which Bacon had
understanding the particulars of plants and animals the nature of the experimented with success on himself against phlegm.69 All these
whole and not merely the parts. Unfortunately, alchemy and philo­ substances are rare, and their true nature known only to the most
sophical agriculture are neglected by students today.62 learned philosophers, like Bacon, for instance, who described their
Bacon was anxious to excuse physicians for one fault at least— physical properties and administration at the end of his treatise.
that they could not practice on their subjects until they got it right Difficulty arose for the physicians, he asserted, when they tried to
because of the “nobility” (propter nobilitate) of the subject matter. For compound drugs without the proper knowledge. Latin physicians did
this reason experience is difficult in medicine.63 Truth cannot be cer­ not understand the rules of degrees and proportion, which involved
tified without experience; for that reason, physicians ought to be ex­ many questions Bacon himself found difficult.70 Alkyndi (Al-Kindi)
cused for their huge deficiencies, more than others.64 Having excused understood what to do, but physicians today are entirely ignorant.
physicians in a rather backhanded way, in the very next paragraph Anybody who wants to compound drugs has to be familiar with the
Bacon renewed his attack on them for their discord, and for the agreed principles of mathematics {communia mathematice), due to the
sluggishness and death that often follows their procedures.65 Then he proportions, and uleges Jractionum difjiciles” written about by Alkyndi.
recommended the simplest medicine of all—none. Those who do What is more, since the skies change every hundred years or so, and
not use medicines are stronger, more beautiful, and live longer than therefore their effect on terrestrial beings is different, new calcula­
those who surrender to them,66 and this is exceedingly plain among tions need to be made for compound drugs to be effective. But who
northern peoples (nationibus septentrionalibus), who seldom use medicines. nowadays knows how to do this? Certainly not a mere physician
If physicians understood every medicine and all the non-naturals (omnes (purus medicus), unless he knows astronomy.71
res non naturales), and the disposition of the heavens (dispositionem cell), Bacon’s general point is perhaps less than obvious to modern
then medicines would prolong life and health.67 audiences. Medicine is not independent of other disciplines; in fact,
Bacon’s last major thematic concern is mathematics, another under­ many other things must be mastered before it: There can be no
graduate subject he thought crucial to medicine. Throughout his medicine without knowledge of languages; there can be no medicine
medical works, Bacon was wary of compound medicines, deeming without proper methods of argumentation; there can be no medicine
them overpriced, adulterated, ineffective or even dangerous. Most of without alchemy, astrology, philosophical agriculture, and mathematics.
the medicines he recommended were simples he associated in the Most of all, there can be no medicine without knowledge of natural
Opus majus with the secret of long life: rosemary flowers, the bone in philosophy: “For Aristotle says that where natural philosophy ends
a stag’s heart,68 viper’s flesh, lignum aloes (aloe wood: Aquilaria agalbcha), there medicine begins, and the natural philosopher has to supply the
first principles of health and infirmity.”72 In other words, a liberal
arts education must be propaedeutic to a medical one, or the physi­
62 little and Withington, p. 160.
63 “Difficilis est experientia in medicina”: Litde and Withington, p. 161. Bacon’s allu­
cian is useless, even dangerous.
sion is probably to the first aphorism of Hippocrates.
64 Litde and Withington, p. 161.
65 After noting the folly of slavish attention to medical treatises written only in
Greek, Pliny noted that “there is no law to punish criminal ignorance, no instance 69 Welbom lists the drugs mentioned in De erroribus on pp. 54-61. Bacon listed
of retribution. Physicians acquire their knowledge from our dangers, making experi­ among his favorite remedies “singing, the sight of human beauty, the touch of young
ments at the cost of our lives. Only a physician can commit homicide with complete girls, warm aromatic waters” and other soothing restoratives (Little and Withington,
impunity”: Natural History, vol. 8 (Book 29, chapter 8), p. 195. p. 178), reminding the reader of King David and Abishag (I Kings 1:1-4).
66 Cf. Pliny, Natural History, vol. 8, pp. 190/191 (Book 29, chapter 8), in which 70 Little and Withington, p. 166.
the writer noted that Romans had lived for over six hundred years without physi­ 71 Little and Withington, pp. 166-7.
cians, but not without medicine (L. sine medicina). 72 “Aristoteles enim dicit quod vbi terminatur philosophia naturalis, ibi incipit medicina, et
67 Litde and Withington, p. 163. naturalis philosophus habet dare principia vltima sanitatis et inftrmitatis”'. little and Withington,
68 The stag was thought to live over a thousand years; see “Theoretical Justifica­ p. 158; the passage of Aristotle cited is De sensu, book I, 436a. See Gracia, “The
tions for Pharmaceutical Practices,” in Healing and Society, ed. Getz, pp. xviii-xxii. Structure of Medical Knowledge,” p. 23.
354 FAYE GETZ ROGER BACON AND MEDICINE 355

Bacon would seem to be expanding on the arguments of St Isidore future king Henry V in 1411.77 The monk John Lydgate, patronized
(d. 636), the encyclopedic writer and bishop of Seville, who asserted by Humfrey, Duke of Gloucester, wrote a dietary in bad English
in his hugely popular encyclopedia Etymologies (IV, 13) that medicine verse.78 Numerous translations of the Secretum into French and En­
embraced all other subjects, including grammar, rhetoric, dialectic, glish were made in England during the later middle ages and survive
arithmetic, geometry, music, and astrology.73 Isidore also remarked into the early printed tradition.79
in the same passage that medicine was a “second philosophy,” an Priest, humanist and Oxford chancellor Gilbert Kymer, who held
advancement on the natural philosophy that would later be a part of doctorates in medicine and theology, also worked in the regimen
the undergraduate curriculum.74 tradition. He compiled a personal Dietary in Latin, for the would-be
By insinuating medicine into learning about Aristotle’s natural humanist Humfrey, Duke of Gloucester, youngest son of Henry IV,
philosophy and Arabic authorities on mathematical pharmacy Bacon who made generous gifts of books to Oxford University with Kymer’s
was of course declaring the moral value of a liberal arts education help in 1439, 1441, and 1443.80 The explicit (conclusion) of the text
for the physician. The influence of this idea is difficult to judge in says it was written on March 6, 1424 in Hainaut, Flanders, where
England; however, many elite medical patrons employed university- his patron waged a successful military campaign to win those lands
educated physicians without medical degrees. Among many possible on behalf of his new wife, Jacqueline of Hainaut.81 The regimen
examples, Geoffrey Melton, priest and Oxford arts master, attended contains advice on what and when to eat and drink much like that
Mary Bohun, Countess of Richmond, Henry IV, Isabella of France, Aristotle was thought to have given Alexander, with the notable
and her husband, Richard II (murdered 1400). Richard II was also addition of a virtual sermon on the evils of excessive and improper
advised by priest and arts master John Wyke.75 coitus, including lovesickness, jealousy, forgetfulness and a shortened
Equally widely-shared was Bacon’s idea, taken from the Secretum life.82*All these dire warnings were to no avail, for like many patients,
Secretorum, that the regulation of the non-naturals through a regimen
of health was the proper subject of medical learning. Humanistically-
minded vernacular poets like Geoffrey Chaucer denounced the fancy 77 Derek Pearsall, “Hoccleve’s Regement o f Princes: The Poetics o f Royal Self-
Representation,” Speculum 69 (1994) 386-410.
potions of the humoral physicians as vanity in Chaucer’s “Nun’s Priest’s 78 The poem advised moderation in diet, emotion, and exercise over the use of
Tale,” contrasting the temperate regimen of the widow: “Attempree medical practitioners: The Minor Poems ofJohn Lydgate, ed. Henry Noble MacCracken,
diete was al hir phisik,/And exercies, and hertes suffisaunce,” with part 2: Secular Poems, Early English Text Society o.s. 192 (1934, ipt 1961) 703-707.
The poem is printed with matching verses from the Regimen sanitatis Salemitanum in
the gaudy excesses of Chanticleer and his meddling medicine-dosing Latin that is its source: Max Forster, “John Lydgate’s Dietary,” Anglia 42 (1918)
wife Pertelote.76 Later on, the poet Thomas Hoccleve wrote a Regement 176-91.
of Princes in English based in part on the Secretum Secretorum for the 79 Manzalaoui, Secretum, pp. xxii—xlviii.
80 The collection included medical books: Getz, “Oxford,” p. 403. See also A.C.
De La Mare, “Manuscripts Given to the University of Oxford by Humfrey, Duke
of Gloucester,” Bodleian Library Record 13, 1 (1988) 30-51; 13, 2 (1989) 112-21. For
the medical books, see Vem L. Bullough, “Duke Humphrey and His Medical Col­
73 William D. Sharpe, “Isidore of Seville: The Medical Writings: An English Trans­ lections,” Renaissance News 14 (1961) 87-91.
lation with an Introduction and Commentary,” Transactions of the American Philosophi­ 81 The text survives in British Library, Sloane MS 4, fols 63-104, from the later
cal Society, new series, vol. 54, pt. 2 (1964) 64; also John A. Alford, “Medicine in the 15th century. The witness is badly copied, with text missing, and is exceptionally
Middle Ages: The Theory of a Profession,” Centennial Review 23 (1979) 381. difficult to read. It is not Kymer’s autograph. The table of contents and two chap­
74 “Hinc est quod Medicina secunda Philosophia dicitur. Vtraque enim disciplina totum hominem ters are printed in Thomas Hearn, Liber Niger Scaccarii, vol. 2 (London, 1774) 550-9.
sibi vindicat. Nam sicut per illam anima, ita per hanc corpus cu ra tu rSan Isidore de Sevilla, The table of contents is also printed in Early English Meals and Manners, ed. Frederick
Etimologias: Edicion Bilingiie, vol. 1 (libros i-x), ed. and trans. Jose Oroz Reta and J. Fumivall, Early English Text Society o.s. 32 (1868, rpt 1904) lxxxii-lxxxiii.
Manuel-A. Marcos Casquero (Madrid, 1982), 506. The reference is probably to 82 “Digestionem impedit, esuriem defalcat, siciem general, humores corrumpit, spiritus depauperat,
Metaphysics (1037al5): Gracia, “The Structure of Medical Knowledge,” p. 23. calorem naturalem infrigidat, virtutes defeccat, operaciones prostemit, humidum radicale consumit,
75 Faye Getz, “Medical Education in Later Medieval England,” in The History of membra liquefacit, morbos nepharios procreat, virum effeminat, amorem hereos et zdotipiam producit,
Medical Education in Britain, ed. Vivian Nutton and Roy Porter (Amsterdam, 1995), 86. oblivionem, pigriciem, negligenciam, et vercordiam parit, vitamque abbreviat”: Sloane 4, Chap­
76 The Works of Geoffrey Chaucer, ed. F.N. Robinson, 2nd ed. (Boston, 1957), 198— ter 19; Hearn, p. 557. Hearn noted dryly that such excesses were typical of the
205 (VII 2821-3446). Lancastrians: p. 551.
356 ROGER BACON AND MEDICINE 357
FAYE GETZ

Duke Humfrey defied his doctor, had his first marriage annulled, and and medical bachelor (d. ca. 1475), who spent his life teaching and
married his notorious mistress. practicing medicine in Oxford, apparently with the help of surgeon
Kymer also led a successful adventure along with other university John Barbour.86 Cokkys was the author of several medical treatises,
physicians in 1456 to gain protection from Henry VI to practice including a commentary on Hunayn (Johannitius) entided Notule M.
alchemy. Henry’s letter patent affirmed as did Bacon the reality of Johannis de Gallicantu super Johannisium, found in Bodley MS Ashmole
occult qualities. It noted that ancient wise men and exceedingly famous 1475, pp. 1-75. He also took an interest in Bacon’s alchemical
philosophers had written secretly about how many glorious medi­ medicine. Bodley MS e musaeo 155 is written in his own hand (save
cines could be made from precious stones, oils, plants and animals, several sections that are corrected by him) and contains the Opus
especially the best of all, the Philosopher’s Stone, which could cure tertium, part of Opus majus, pseudo-Bacon De retardatione senectutis (be­
curable infirmities and prolong human life to its natural extent. It lieved by Cokkys to be Bacon’s own), De erroribus medicorum, and a
would also transmute metals to gold.83 The outcome of Kymer’s number of experimenta. Most of the extracts concern the medicinal
adventure into medical alchemy failed, according to Thomas Norton’s use of alchemical preparations.87
Ordinal o f Alchemy (ca. 1490), but Norton claimed the physician wrote Bacon’s last major medical work, Antidotarium,88 mentioned De erroribus
a book on the subject.84 and was probably intended as a fulfillment of sorts of the program
A direct chain of “influences” is impossible to outline here, either its author advanced there.89 An antidotary is a work about compound
between Bacon and the vernacular poets or between Bacon and medicines, those having more than one ingredient (as opposed to a
Oxford’s first humanist physician, Gilbert Kymer. The most that can book of simples, about medicines having only one component), and
be stated is that Bacon was a very early importer of medical human­ Bacon explored the ways in which simples could be combined use­
ism from the European continent, whose popularity as an alchemical fully. As with Bacon’s other medical works, one cannot help but sense
healer is better-documented in the early modem period than during Trinitarian philosophical concerns about how various parts can be
the middle ages.85 Surer indication of the popularity of Bacon’s medical made into one substance successfully. Fermentation was once again
works appears in the writings of John Cokkys, Oxford arts master offered as most useful,90*but what this process was exactly remained
for Bacon a mystery. At least he did not describe it to his readers in
helpful detail.
83 “Cum antiqui sapientes et famossissimi philosophi in stris scriptis et libris sub figuris et Instead, Bacon wrote an often conventional treatise on quantifi­
integumentis docuerint et reliquerint ex vino, ex lapidibus preciosis, ex oleis, ex vegetabilibus, ex
animalibus, ex metallis et ex medijs mineralibus multas medicinas gloriosas et notabiles confici cation, reflecting the understanding of Arabic pharmacy as taught at
posse, et presertim quondam preciosissimam medicinam quam aliqui pkilosophorum matrem et
imperatricem medicinarum dixerunt, Alij gloriam inestimabilem eandem nominarunt, Alij vero quintam
essentiam, lapidem pkilosophorum et elixir vite nuncupaverunt eandem, cuius medicine virtus tarn for eradication of disease and the prolongation of life by alchemical means”: 302.
fficax et admirabilis existeret quod per earn quecunque infirmitates curabiles curarentur faciliter, For a Continental parallel to Bacon’s medical alchemical thinking, see Pearl Kibre,
vita humana ad suum naturalem prorogaretur terminum, et homo in sanitate et viribus naturalibus “Albertus Magnus on Alchemy,” in Albertus Magnus and the Sciences: Commemorative Essays,
tarn corporis quam anime, fortitudine membrorum, memorie claritate et ingenij viuacitate ad eundem ed. J.A. Weisheipl (Toronto, 1980), 187-202.
terminum mirabiliter preservaretur, quecunque eciam vulnera curabilia sine difficultate sanarentur 86 The Medical Practitioners in Medieval England: A Biographical Register, ed. C.H. Talbot
que insuper contra omne genus venenorum Joret summa et optima medicina. Sed et plura alia and E.A. Hammond (London, 1965), 134-6; Faye Getz, “Medical Practitioners in
comoda nobis et rei publke regni nostri utilissima per eandem fieri possent velud metallorum trans- Medieval England,” Social History of Medicine 3 (1990) 265.
mutationes in verissimum aurum. . . . ” In Latin with English translation in D. Geohegan, 87 Little and Withington, pp. xi-xiii; Getz, “Oxford,” pp. 378 n. 17, 395.
“A Licence of Henry VI to Practise Alchemy,” Ambix 6 (1957) 10-17; also Getz, 88 Little and Withington, pp. 103-19.
“Baconian Alchemy,” pp. 146-7. 89 “Sed hie est vnus de 36 defectibus qui sunt apud nos, et hoc est propter defectum librorm, vel
84 Thomas Norton’s Ordinal o f Alchemy, ed. J. Reidy, Early English Text Society quia sapientes occultauerunt hanc partem doctrine vel nescierunt; teamen ego scripsi nomina istorum
272 (1975) 50. Kymer’s treatise has not been identified. On prohibitions against defectuum alibi et partem huius doctrine, secundum quod didici a sapientibus diuersarum linguarum
alchemy, see Edgar H. Duncan, “The Literature of Alchemy and Chaucer’s Canon’s et literature”: Little and Withington, p. 110. The two treatises overlap considerably.
Yeoman’s Tale: Framework, Theme, and Characters,” Speculum 43 (1970) 633-56. 90 “Oportet igitur medicinam quamlibet compositam fermentari, quia compositum absque
85 Charles Webster, in “Alchemical and Paracelsian Medicine,” in Health, Medi­ fermentatione non valebit, ut dicit Auicenna in .v.to. Nam propterfermentationem ex pluribus rebus
cine, and Healing in the Sixteenth Century, ed. C. Webster (Cambridge, 1979) noted that simplicibus fit vna medicina, et ex pluribus qualitatibus fit vna qualitas, starts, operans, adquirens
“Roger Bacon was the major authority cited by Englishmen as sanctioning the quest aliam virtutem quam in suis simplicibus existat”: Little and Withington, p. 116.
358 FAYE GETZ ROGER BACON AND MEDICINE 359

the University of Paris around the middle of the thirteenth century.91 from its roots, so a compound by its root or roots.”97 This root was
Following his principal Arabic sources ibn Sina and al-Majusi (Avi­ a single substance, “like viper’s flesh in treacle or aloes in iera pigra,”98
cenna and Haly Abbas), Bacon wrote about the relationship between which sometimes needed to be combined with others to mitigate its
a medicine’s weight and its humoral effect. His own system, never effect, to treat multiple afflictions, or to help carry it to a remote
clearly worked out, suggested that additional substances be added to part of the body.99
the main ingredient of a compound in proportion to its quantity.92 Laxatives and opiates especially caught the author’s attention. These
Bacon, like Pliny, shrank from what he thought was the ignorant were two drugs of great interest to medieval physicians because of
compounding of drugs willy-nilly as irrational and dangerous.93 Rea­ their undoubted pharmaceutical effect. But beyond that, laxatives and
son and experience should be the guides, and for his rational system opiates satisfied their expectations because of these drugs’ perceived
Bacon turned to the Greek system of four qualities—hot, cold, moist, humoral properties. Bacon believed, like most medieval medical think­
and dry—which in a medicine acted against their opposites in the ers, that illness was a kind of poisoning, and that the job of medical
body: “And if a disease against which we are compounding is cold, treatment was to purge the body of this poison.100 This interest in
then a medicine ought to be compounded in quality hot according poison appears throughout Bacon’s medical writings.101 Viper’s flesh—
to the contrary degree of the cold disease.”94 These qualities, accord­ like many of the best medicines both poisonous and helpful—and
ing to Galen and other ancient authorities, were divided into four the celebrated treacle (L. tyriaca)—a universal antidote for poisoning—
“degrees,” with the fourth being the most extreme form. There was come up repeatedly in his works.102
also a “temperate” quality, which represented a kind of zero, having Opiates are a different story. One might think Bacon’s interest in
no pharmaceutical effect.95 opiates stem from an interest in their soporific quality, and indeed
Bacon accepted this mathematical system as axiomatic, and tried, there is some evidence that opium derivatives were used for surgery.103
in a rather half-hearted and ill-tempered way, to show how it might Surgery was one of the many medical topics Bacon neglected entirely,
apply to the successful compounding of medicines. He began with however; his interest was in the fact that opium, being extremely
one of his favorite metaphors, the plant, its roots, and its branches,96
to suggest that each compound has at least one, and often more
than one simple “root” (L. radix): “For just as a plant is sustained 97 “Nam sicut planta ex suis radicibus, ita compositum ex sua radice vel radicibus sustentatur”:
Litde and Withington, p. 106; also McVaugh, pp. 39-45.
98 For a iera pigra recipe written by an Englishman contemporary with Bacon,
see Gilbertus Anglicus, Compendium medicine (Lyons, 1510), fol. 237 or Healing and
91 The pharmaceutical system Bacon expounded, and its intellectual context, are Society, ed. Getz, p. 222.
explained thoroughly and masterfully by McVaugh in Amaldi de Villanova Aphorismi 99 Litde and Withington, p. 107.
de Gradibus, pp. 31-51. 100 Purgation of peccant humors was discussed frequendy in De erroribus, for ex­
92 “Nam ex vera proportione prouenit veritas, virtus, vel proprietas in composito, que in simplicibus ample, Little and Withington, p. 150.
non habetur, sed precipue in proportione radicis et rerum sequentium eius operationem. Nam in hiis 101 Litde and Withington, p. 105: “Nam virtutibus confortatis inimicum expellit per sensibilem
duobus consistit proprietas et operatio totius compositi”: Litde and Withington, p. 113; in vel per occultam expulsionem, sicut composita facit medicina que est de genere venenorum. ”
more detail, McVaugh, p. 39. 102 For viper’s flesh, see especially Litde and Withington, p. 110; for treacle,
93 “Caueant igitur arrogantes et proterui in vanitate studentes ex industria eorum componere p. 119; for both together, p. 108; for scriptural, medical, and natural historical con­
tnedicinam, nisi sciant scientiam componendi, quod est impossible eos noscere propter defectum texts, see Jerry Stannard, “Natural History,” in Science in the Middle Ages, ed. David
illius partis scientie que docet cognoscere res que ad inuicem se expoliant, et hec consideratio est C. Lindberg (Chicago, 1978), p. 442. Cf. Pliny, Natural History, vol. 8 (Book 29,
gratia compositi to tiu s Little and Withington, p. 113. chapter 8): “Theriace vocatur excogitata compositio. fit ex rebus sexcentis, cum tot remedia dederit
94 “Et si egritudo, contra quam componimus, est jrigida, tunc componenda est medicina in natura quae singula sujficerent. Mithridatium antidotum ex rebus L IIII componitur, inter nullas
qualitate calida secundum contrarium gradum frigiditatis egritudinisLitde and Withington, pondere aequali et quarundam rerum sexagesima denarii unius imperata, quo deorum, per Fidem,
p. 112. ista monstrante!” (p. 198). Pliny continued that the physicians, ignorant of the correct
95 “Et quandocunque medicina composita excedit in aliqua qualitate: ideo consideranda est eius names of drugs, had promoted practices that “ruined the morals of the Empire”
qualitas, vtrum debeat esse calida vel jrigida vel temperata vel sicca vel humida, vtrum secundum (p. 199).
Plinium illud quod soluit debet esse c a lid u m Litde and Withington, pp. 111-2; for the 103 Linda E. Voigts and Robert P. Hudson, ‘“A drynke that men callen dwale to
Galenic system, McVaugh, pp. 4—8. make a man to slepe whyle men kerven him’: A Surgical Anesthetic from Late
96 Cf. De erroribus, Litde and Withington, p. 150. Medieval England,” in Health, Disease and Healing, pp. 34—56.
360 FAYE GETZ ROGER BACON AND MEDICINE 361

cold,104 was able to be compounded with other medicines and pre­ Moreover, his knowledge of learned medicine is neither deep nor
vent them from dissolving before they reached the affected part.105 wide, and the length of his medical writings would scarcely exceed
At several turns in the treatise, Bacon repeated his worry that the the length of this essay. What is remarkable about Bacon’s medical
modemi were not getting things right, but his concern that time had work is the synthetic meaning he drew as much from Scripture as
changed the world in important ways went deeper than the somewhat from encyclopedias and scholastic medical texts. His weaving together
Ciceronian pose the writer chose to strike. Just as the stars were said of the fruit of the Tree of Life from the Old Testament, simple regi­
to have moved from the time of Creation, making new astrological men from Pliny, the Philosopher’s Stone from pseudo-Aristotle, and
calculations necessary for the physician,106 so the human body had of precious drugs from Islamic philosophers into a reasonably coher­
changed from ancient times, making dosage based on old texts danger­ ent set of medical theories is an achievement of almost poetic inge­
ous.107 Bacon seems to be suggesting that the medicinal substances nuity, filled with intriguing paradoxes.
he dealt with, nearly all of them exceedingly rare,108 remained like the Irritating, pompous, and self-important at times, Bacon also man­
stars immutable in their essential properties throughout the centuries. aged to convey a sense of wonder and reverence for Nature and the
Only the microcosm of humanity changed, requiring constant mathe­ works of God no English medical writer would ever surpass. He was
matical recalculations. able to do this for many reasons, but perhaps more than any because
he, like Pliny, conceived a medical system firmly connected to a
knowledge of the natural world gained through marvellous books, to
Conclusion which he added his own unshaking conviction of the moral value of
the liberal arts. Bacon the encyclopedic medical thinker was a collector
Bacon’s attempts to separate what was eternal and perfect from what and assembler of what he thought was the best medical information,
was mutable and imperfect are of course not confined to his medical from a variety of sources. As such, his writings represent continuity
writings; nor are such concerns limited to Bacon alone. His interest with the Latin and patristic past, as well as an acceptance of the
in physicality, food, and the body are striking, but certainly not unique. authority of alien thinkers. What is more, Bacon subordinated medi­
cine to philosophy, making it part of a general knowledge of the
nature of the good life. Like Pliny, he embraced the medicines, but
rejected the physicians. Historians of our time who would look to
104 Known to medical writers as a “stupefacative”: Gilbertus Anglicus, Compen­ Bacon’s remedies for pharmacological effectiveness are missing his
dium, fol. 131 v; Healing and Society, ed. Getz, p. 38. point. Bacon’s was a medicine of books—of meanings, symbols, lan­
105 “Et quandocunque intentio nostra est ut medicina quam componimus agat in membro longinquo,
et timemus ne digestio prima et secunda jrangat virtutem eius, tunc associamus ei medicinam que guage, and hidden truths. As precursors of modem ideas of scientific
earn conseruet; et non timemus audaciam duarum digestionum, ymmo ducit earn sanam ad membrum truth, Bacon’s medical thoughts are a dead end. As a set of insights
ad quod intendimus, sicut ponimus opium in medidnis tyriace, ut dicit Auicenna in 5° canone
into thirteenth-century understanding of the natural world, Bacon’s
Little and Withington, p. 111. Gf. Gilbertus Anglicus, Compendium, fol. 266, (Healing
and Society, ed. Getz, p. 247) in which opium was recommended to bring medicine medical writings hold compelling attractions.
to the kidneys.
106 Opus majus, p. 204.
107 “Tamm in hiis duobus modemi peccant, in dosi narcoticorum et laxatiuorum, quia quanta
est differentia inter calorem naturalem et corpora antiquorum et modemomm, tanta est differentia in Bibliography
dosi scripta in libris antiquis codicis et in ilia que debet hodie hominibus exhiberi”: Little and
Withington, p. 108.
108 Medieval medical texts are full of “rich man, poor man” suggestions for treat­ Agrimi, Jole and Chiara Crisciani. “Medicina del corpo e medicina dell’anima:
ment, suiting the drug to the social station of the patient: Gilbertus Anglicus, Compen­ Note sul sapere del medico fino all’inizio del sec. XIII.” Episteme 10 (1976)
dium medicine, fol. 236v; Healing and Society, ed. Getz, pp. 219-20. Likewise, various 5-102.
organs had “social status,” the heart being the noblest and requiring the most expensive *Bridges, John Henry, ed. The Opus majus of Roger Bacon. Volume II. Lon­
medicines. Bacon advised compounding medicines that “comforted” the principal
members of the body, especially the heart: Little and Withington, p. 109. don, Edinburgh, and Oxford: Williams and Norgate, 1900.
362 ROGER BACON AND MEDICINE 363
FAYE GETZ

Bylebyl, Jerome L. “Medicine, Philosophy, and Humanism in Renaissance King, J.E. Baedae Opera Hisbrica, with an English Transbtion, vol. ii: Eccksiastical
Italy.” In Science and the Arts in the Renaissance. Edited by John W. Shirley Hisbry of the English Nation. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1963.
and F. David Hoeniger. Washington, D.C.: The Folger Shakespeare Kuhnert, Friedmar. Allgemeinbildung und Fachbildung in der Antike. Berlin:
Library, 1985, pp. 27-49. Akademie-Verlag, 1961.
♦Bynum, Caroline Walker. The Resurrection of the Body in Western Christianity, Lindberg, David C. “Science as Handmaiden: Roger Bacon and the Patristic
200-1336. New York: Columbia University Press, 1995. Tradition.” Isis 78 (1987) 518-36.
Cameron, M.L. “The Sources o f Medical Knowledge in Anglo-Saxon Linden, Stanton J. ed. The Mirror of Akhimy: Composed by the Thrice-Famous and
England.” Angb-Saxon England 11 (1983) 135-55. Learned Fryer, Roger Bachon. New York: Garland, 1992.
Campbell, Sheila, Bert Hall, and David Klausner eds. Health, Disease and ♦Little, A.G. and E. Withington eds. Roger Bacon, De retardatione accidentium
Healing in Medieval Culture. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1992. senectutis cum aliis opusculis de rebus medicinalibus. British Soc. Franciscan Studies
Chibnall, Marjorie. “Pliny’s Natural Hisbry and the Middle Ages.” In Empire 14 Oxford 1928.
and Aftermath: Silver Latin II. Edited by T.A. Dorey. London: Routledge & Lloyd, G.E.R. Science, Folklore and Ideology: Studies in the Life Sciences in Ancient
Kegan Paul, 1975, pp. 57-78. Greece. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1983.
Crisciani, Chiara. “History, Novelty, and Progress in Scholastic Medicine.” Manzalaoui, M.A. ed. Secretum Secrebrum: Nine English Versions. Early English
Osiris 6 (1990) 118-39. Text Society 276 (1977).
Duncan, Edgar H. “The Literature of Alchemy and Chaucer’s Canon’s Marrou, H.I. History of Education in Antiquity. George Lamb trans. New York:
Yeoman’s Tale: Framework, Theme, and Characters.” Speculum 43 (1970) Sheed and Ward, 1956.
633-56. ♦McVaugh, Michael R. Amaldi de Villanova Opera Medica Omnia II: Aphorismi
de Gradibus. Granada-Barcelona: Seminariuum Historia Medicae Grana-
♦Ferruolo, Stephen C. The Origins of the University: The Schools of Paris and their tensis, 1975.
Critics. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1985. Molland, George. “Roger Bacon and the Hermetic Tradition in Medieval
Fichtner, Gerhard. “Christus als Arzt. Urspriinge und Wirkungen eines Science.” Vivarium 31 (1993) 140-60.
Motivs.” FruhmitteMterliche Studien 16 (1982) 1-18.
Forster, Max. “John Lydgate’s Dietary.” Anglia 42 (1918) 176-91. ♦Paravicini Bagliani, Agostino. Medicina e scienze della natura alia cork dei papi
French, Roger. Ancient Natural History: Histories of Nature. London: Routledge, nel duecento. Spoleto: Centro Italiano di Studi Sull’Alto Medioevo, 1991.
1994. ♦Pereira, Michela. “Un tesoro inestimabile: Elixir e ‘Prolongatio Vitae’
nell’alchimia de ’300.” Micrologus: I discorsi dei corpi 1 (1993) 161-87.
Geohegan, D. “A Licence of Henry VI to Practise Alchemy.” Ambix 6 (1957)
10-17. Rather, LJ. “The Six Things Non-Natural: A Note on the Origins and
Getz, Faye Marie ed. Healing and Society in Medieval England: A Middle English Fate of a Doctrine and a Phrase.” Clio Medica 3 (1968) 337-47.
Translation of the Pharmaceutical Writings of Cilbertus Anglicus. Madison: Uni­ Reidy, J. ed. Thomas Norton’s Ordinal of Abhemy. Early English Text Soci­
versity o f Wisconsin Press, 1991. ety 272 (1975).
*Getz, F.M. “The Faculty o f Medicine before 1500.” In The History of the Robinson, F.N. ed. The Works of Geoffrey Chaucer. 2nd edition. Boston:
Unwersity of Oxford, vol. ii: Late Medieval Oxford. Edited by J.I. Catto and Houghton Mifflin Company, 1957.
Ralph Evans. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, pp. 373-405. Ryan, W.F. and Charles B. Schmitt eds. Pseudo-Arisbtle, The Secret of Secrets.
Gilbertus Anglicus. Compendium medicine. Lyons: J. Saccon for V. de Portonariis, London: The Warburg Institute, 1982.
1510. Seymour, M.C. et al. eds. On the Properties of Things: John Treviso’s Translation
Gracia, Diego. “The Structure of Medical Knowledge in Aristotle’s Philoso­ of Bartholomaeus Anglicus De Proprietatibus Rerum, A Critical Text.
phy.” Sudhoffs Archiv 62 (1978) 1-36. 3 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975-1988.
Hunt, R.W. The Schools and the Cbister: The life and Writings of Alexander Nequam Shahar, Shulamith. “The Old Body in Medieval Culture.” In Framing Medi­
(1157-1217). Edited and revised by Margaret Gibson. Oxford: Clarendon eval Bodies. Edited by Sarah Kay and Miri Rubin. Manchester: Manchester
Press, 1984. University Press, 1994, pp. 160-86.
Siraisi, Nancy G. Medieval and Early Renaissance Medicine: An Introduction b
*Jones, W.H.S. trans. Pliny, Natural Hisbry, with an English Translation in Ten Knowledge and Practice. Chicago: University o f Chicago Press, 1990.
Volumes. Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, ♦Stannard, Jerry. “Natural History.” In Science in the Middb Ages. Edited by
1975. David C. Lindberg. Chicago: University o f Chicago Press, 1978, pp.
Kibre, Pearl. “Albertus Magnus on Alchemy.” In Albertus Magnus and the 429-60.
Sciences: Commemorative Essays. Edited by J.A. Weisheipl. Toronto: Pontifical ♦Steele, R. et al. eds. Opera hactenus inedib Rogeri Baconi. 16 vols. Oxford [1905/
Institute, 1980, pp. 187-202. 9]-1940.
364 FAYE GETZ

Talbot, C.H. Medicine in Medieval England. London: Oldboume, 1967.


Temkin, Owsei. Hippocrates in a World of Pagans and Christians. Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1991.
15. ROGER BACON AND TH E SECRET OF SECRETS
Webster, Charles ed. Health, Medicine, and Healing in the Sixteenth Century. Cam­
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979.
♦Weisheipl, J.A. “Science in the Thirteenth Century.” In The History of the Steven J. Williams
University of Oxford, vol. 1: The Early Oxford Schools. Edited by J.I. Catto
and T.A.R. Evans. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, pp. 435-69.
*Welbom, Mary Catherine. “The Errors o f the Doctors according to Friar Roger Bacon was influenced by many books, so the present reader
Roger Bacon of the Minor Order.” Isis 18 (1932) 26-62.
may well wonder why the pseudo-Aristotelian Secret of Secrets (Secretum
secretorum, henceforth Secretum) is here being singled out for attention.
First, as will be explained below, this book was quite important to
him: in a number of writings during the 1260’s and 70’s, he cited
the Secretum with a frequency not seen by any other schoolman; what
is more, he took the time to prepare an edition of the Secretum complete
with introduction, diagrams, and notes—something he did with no
other book. Clearly, Bacon had an exceptionally high regard for the
Secretum. But there is a second reason that Bacon’s relationship to the
Secretum merits our consideration. Because it meant so much to him
and was so much a part of his intellectual life, it provides the opportu­
nity to .explore some of his characteristic ideas as well as to reexam­
ine some crucial aspects of his biography. In other words, the Secretum
provides a convenient vantage point from which to view Bacon’s phi­
losophy and career—the primary task of this volume of essays.
An extended missive supposedly sent by Aristotle to his former
pupil Alexander the Great while the latter was on campaign in Per­
sia, the Secretum contains substantial portions of pragmatic advice on
politics and morals, and as such belongs to that literary genre known
as “mirrors for princes.” But the Secretum is something more besides:
a miscellany of information useful to a ruler on the subjects of health,
physiognomy, and occult science. Initially translated from Arabic into
Latin in a partial version by John of Seville ca. 1130, the complete
Secretum appeared around one hundred years later through the efforts
of a cleric named Philip of Tripoli. Soon circulating at the papal
and imperial courts, Philip’s work was certainly known in Paris by
the mid-1240’s.1
Roger Bacon was then in Paris, teaching courses in Aristotelian phi­
losophy at the university’s Faculty of Arts (the customary dates given

1 O n the genesis of the Secretum secretorum in the Arab world and its fortuna in the
Latin West, see the bibliography at the conclusion of this article.
366 STEVEN J. WILLIAMS ROGER BACON AND THE SECRET OF SECRETS 367

by historians for his stint as regent master are ca. 1240-ca. 1247). have dated to the early 1250’s, almost certainly belongs to the fol­
Bacon probably encountered the Secretum at this time, though we have lowing decade.6 While a number of Bacon’s class lectures survive
no indubitable proof for it. In 1267 Bacon talks about having pur­ from this early period, nowhere does the Secretum appear even impli­
chased “secret books” for some twenty years, but such a category citly in them. And Bacon’s glosses on the Secretum were not com­
would have to include the whole array of books on occult science posed anywhere near the time of Bacon’s regency in Arts—contrary
plus “compilations of recipes, formulas, and ‘experiments’,” so this to what most scholars have said, following Robert Steele, the editor
statement cannot help us here.2 The medical treatise De retardatione of Bacon’s Secretum project.7
accidentium senectutis, which was begun at the suggestion of Philip the Steele places the Secretum glosses “early in [Bacon’s] career,” “at
Chancellor (d. 1236) and which quotes the Secretum repeatedly, is not, some date before 1257,” and connects them with his activities as an
we now know, Bacon’s work.3 Some other medical writings included Arts professor; the introduction is put ca. 1270.8 This early dating of
in OHI IX occasionally cite the Secretum too, but attempts to locate the glosses makes little sense on its own terms: it seems unnecessarily
them to the 1250’s are flawed by mistaken attributions and insuffi­ complicated to have Bacon comparing manuscripts of the Secretum
cient argument.4 Both the Baconian tract De secretis operibus naturae and commenting the resulting text ca. 1250, then letting his work sit
and the Metaphysica refer to the Secretum: however, the dating of the for some two decades until writing an introduction. But what under­
former to 1248 cannot be taken seriously—its contents definitely come cuts Steele’s hypothesis completely are the glosses themselves. Both
from a later time in Bacon’s life;5 the latter, which a few scholars in style and in content they are very different from the Parisian
commentaries of the 1240’s. Whole pages of the Secretum go by with
2 See p. 369 below. I take this quotation from William Eamon, Science and the Bacon saying hardly a word. Many of the comments are hortatory
Secrets ofNature. Books of Secrets in Medieval and Early Modem Culture (Princeton, 1994), 16. or philological in nature, something that was not standard fare in a
3 See the devastating objections to Bacon’s authorship made in Crowley, 23-5.
The coup de grace to this long-standing misattribution was delivered by Agostino scholastic commentary. Furthermore, there is no firm supporting evi­
Paravicini Bagliani, “II mito della prolongatio vitae e la corte pontificia del Duecento: dence that Bacon had at this time the extensive knowledge of medi­
il De retardatione accidentium senectutis,” in his Medicina e scienze della natura alia corte dei
papi nel Duecento (Spoleto, 1991), 281-326. For yet another argument contra, see Jeremiah
cal and alchemical matters that he displays in the notes.9 In fact,
M.G. Hackett, “The Meaning of Experimental Science (scientia experimentalis) in the
Philosophy of Roger Bacon” (Ph.D. diss., University of Toronto, 1983), 88-9. Accord­
ing to the testimony of two early witnesses, the author was a certain Dominus Castri (New York, 1992), xxv. Most modem students of Bacon take this work as coming
Gret or Goet. from his “mature” period, viz., from the 1260’s on.
4 Besides the editors of O H I IX, only Easton and Alessio make something of an 6 Alessio, 278-9, 281, has Bacon starting the Metaphysica ca. 1250; Malgorzata
effort to date Bacon’s medical opera: Easton, 91, 94, 101, 108, 111; Alessio, 273-5, Frankowska, Scientia as Interpreted by Roger Bacon (Warsaw, 1971), 13, 47—50, admits
281, 283-4, 288, 305. Four of the tracts that regularly accompany De retardatione in this as a possibility, and also argues for an early date on the basis of form and
the manuscripts are not Bacon’s either: see Paravicini Bagliani, “D mito della prolongatio content. The primary reason for an early dating of this work is Bacon’s statement,
vitae,” esp. 286-9, 319. “Quartum signum et pessimum est ignorancie in humanis sapienciis nunc tempori-
5 Lynn Thorndike, History o f Magic and Experimental Science (New York, 1923), vol. 2, bus, quia scimus quod veritas divina sit complete revelata jam a mille ducentis et
689, suggests that this tract was compiled from Bacon’s writings by a hand different quinquaginta annis que omnino perficit philosophiam, et dilucidat, et certificat” (OHI
than Bacon’s own; see also the doubts about the authenticity of portions of the I, 6). However, if this is indeed the correct reading of the number, it is not so clear
work expressed by Dorothea Waley Singer, “Alchemical Writings Attributed to Roger that we might take it to mean that it has been 1250 years since the birth of Jesus.
Bacon,” Speculum 7 (1932), 80-1. However, the fact that it seems to be included as Perhaps Bacon had in mind the start of Jesus’ teaching career, or perhaps he was
part of Bacon’s Secretum project in Tanner 116 (s. xiii ex., perhaps even before Bacon’s just speaking loosely (cf. Duhem, 34-5). This last possibility is most likely. There is
death) tells in its being Bacon’s own work: see n. 89 below. Also relevant are the a wealth of evidence to suggest that the Metaphysica was written in the years around
observations of Irene Rosier, La parole comme acte. Sur la grammaire et la semantique au the papal opera: see O H I I, iii-v, 53-6; Little, xxviii-xx; Little, in Roger Bacon Essays,
X IIIe siecle (Paris, 1994), 221 n. 56, and William R. Newman, “The Philosophers’ 9-10, 405 n. 1, 406-7.
Egg: Theory and Practice in the Alchemy of Roger Bacon,” Micrologus 3 (1995), 7 A slightly different argument against Steele appears in my “Roger Bacon and
93-4. Some historians have placed De secretis operibus naturae early in Bacon’s career His Edition of the Pseudo-Aristotelian Secretum secretomm,” Speculum 69 (1994), 57-73.
because of an explicit saying that the work was “ad Gulielmum Parisiensum [i.e., 8 O H I V, vii-viii.
William of Auvergne, bishop of Paris, d. 1248] conscripta”. Found only in a manu­ 9 His Parisian commentaries of the 1240’s show little familiarity with medical
script of unknown date that belonged to John Dee, this information is obviously learning or medical texts. In one of them {De plantis), Bacon specifically argues that
quite untrustworthy: see A.G. Little, in Roger Bacon Essays, 395; The Mirror of Alchimy the alchemical transmutation of metals is impossible: see William R. Newman, The
Composed by the Thrice-Famous and Learned Fryer, Roger Bachon, ed. Stanton J. Linden Summa perfectionis of Pseudo-Geber (Leiden, 1991), 22-5.
ROGER BACON AND THE SECRET OF SECRETS 369
368 STEVEN J. WILLIAMS

many of them echo the practical scientific interests found only in influenced [Bacon] during the next quarter century.”16 Stuart Easton
what is taken to be the work of the certifiably “mature” Bacon of has best argued the case in his now classic biographical study of
the 1260’s and after.10 It is also hard to imagine that Bacon would be Bacon. According to Easton, it was a formative encounter with the
willing to share some of the alchemical secrets he reveals in his glosses Secretum ca. 1247 that prompted Bacon to alter the direction of his
to the hoi polloi of students and masters.11 Add to this the fact that life in a fundamental way. Reading this book, hypothesized Easton,
one note mentions a translation of “Aristotle’s” Physiognomia—executed “awakened [Bacon’s] dormant sense of wonder” and provided him
by Bartholomew of Messina 1258-66;12 another seems to indicate with a revelation of the power, beauty, and utility of science. From
that a significant amount of time had elapsed between a cure effected the Secretum, too, Bacon learned that the entire fund of philosophic
by the Secretion's panacea ca. 1252 and Bacon’s memory of the event;13 wisdom, including great scientific secrets, was originally given by God
yet six more discuss Greek words with their Latin equivalents, and it to the patriarchs and prophets, passed on through the Chaldeans
is commonly assumed that Bacon did not develop his intense con­ and Egyptians to the Greeks and Arabs, and thence to the Latins;
cern about the quality of translations or solid competence in Greek and that it was necessary to keep these secrets out of the hands of
until some time after his professorship in Arts.14 Finally, Bacon not the multitude. In Easton’s spirited formulation, “[Bacon’s] whole later
only makes reference to the notes in the introduction but he also life and the emotional intensity with which he pursued it can be
makes reference to the introduction in the notes, which suggests that traced to the impact of this book.”17 The strength of Easton’s ac­
Bacon saw all the parts of his project functioning together as a unit, count lies as much in its dramatic sense and psychological verisimili­
and thus had probably been conceived that way.15 Unless, therefore, tude as in its factual dexterity; together they make a convincing
we are willing to acknowledge Bacon’s precocious adumbration ca. combination. In the wake of Easton’s book, it has become routine
1250 of ideas characteristic of his maturity and to say that only some for Bacon scholars to assert that the Secretum was instrumental in
of the glosses were done at this date, the conclusion is inescapable bringing about Bacon’s conversion from a text-based scholastic phi­
that all of Bacon’s work on the Secretum, including the notes, was losophy to a practically-oriented scientia experimentalis.
done around the same time. Determining that time will be our task Historians have speculated that some sort of change in Bacon’s
below. intellectual course took place just around 1247. As Bacon described
Helped along, no doubt, by Steele’s early dating of these glosses, it later in his Opus tertium (1267-68), “during the twenty years in
many scholars have given their assent to the view that the Secretum which I have labored specially in the study of wisdom, disregarding
was—in Steele’s words— “ [the] book which more than any other the common way, I have spent more than two thousand pounds on
secret books, various experiments, languages, instruments, tables, and
other things. . . .”18 Nevertheless, there is no passage to be adduced
10 See pp. 384ff. below.
11 Several times in his writings Bacon insists on keeping the great secrets of
from Bacon’s writings proving that this change was due to the sin­
alchemy away from the vulgus: O H I V, 116-7; Brewer, 42-3, 360; Little, 77, 80-3; gular effect of the Secretum, and there is no clear evidence that Bacon
Duhem, 181-4. And see nn. 76 and 137 below. was profoundly influenced by the Secretum at or near this time.19
12 O H I V, 165.
13 See p. 386 below.
14 O H I V, 60, 70, 85, 98, 140, 165. One of these notes even castigates as glomerelli
16 Robert Steele, “Roger Bacon,” Quarterly Review 221 (1914), 255-6 (with Steele’s
those who are ignorant of Greek and mispell xenium (ibid., 60); the word is also
discussion continuing onto the following page); also O H I V, viii.
discussed in the Greek Grammar (Greek Grammar, 71) and Compendium studii philosophise
17 Easton, 24, 30-1, 73, 77-82, 85-6, 103, 108.
(Brewer, 443). This concern about Greek, and a similar dismissal of glomerelli nescientes
18 Brewer, 59. Two other comments by Bacon are relevant in this connection: in
Grecum, is found in the introduction too: O H I V, 1,3, 7, 12, 14. If the commentary
the Opus minus, Bacon says that twenty years previously he had learned about tides
De sensu et sertsato is indeed Bacon’s, the knowledge of Greek signalled therein by
from a certain man (ibid., 359), and in the Opus tertium, he says that it has been
Easton (Easton, 25, n. 5) is of the most rudimentary kind.
almost twenty years since he has attended the inceptions of new Arts masters deal­
15 Williams, “Roger Bacon,” 59-61. The superscription to the introduction, which
ing with geometry (ibid., 139).
is almost certainly Bacon’s work, talks about the reader being expected to put the
19 With admirable honesty, Easton (Easton, 86) admits that there is no “corrobo­
notes and the introduction together so as to better understand the Secretum itself:
rative evidence” for his hypothesis.
O H I V, 1; also Williams, “Roger Bacon,” 64 n. 31.
370 STEVEN J. WILLIAMS ROGER BACON AND THE SECRET OF SECRETS 371

As for Bacon’s belief in a divine revelation of scientific knowledge Albumasar, Alkindi, Alhazen, Avicenna, Marbode, Hugh of St Victor,
to the Hebrews, this might have come from several sources; as fre­ Gundisalvi, the author of De retardatione accidentium senenctutis—we could
quently as Bacon cites the Secretum in this regard, he also mentions go on; the authors who might have prompted Bacon’s supposed
Josephus.20 Similarly, there was a venerable tradition of knowledge “breakthrough” insight would make a sizable library indeed.25 Simi­
only for the initiated, “secrets” and secret writings, in various trades larly, the agency responsible for this insight might have been a scien­
and disciplines; and again, Bacon’s repeated mention of this idea in tific demonstration involving a lodestone or a lens; a scientist such
his work includes references to other books besides the Secretum.21 as Peter of Maricourt; a chance event like the “pop” of a child’s
That the Secretum was the principal inspiration for Bacon’s idea of firecracker; or some combination of these factors. We will never know
scientia experimentalis will not bear close scrutiny either. In the Secretum, what prompted this revolution in his thinking—or even if it was a
Bacon refers the very phrase to Ptolemy.22 To be sure, the Secretum revolution but rather a return to a path on which he had started as
shows up often when Bacon treats this topic, and the Secretum pro­ a youth and a slow development of views that ultimately grew from
vides Bacon with several key examples of the great wonders that it the English scholarly tradition.26 Bacon tells us in the Opus tertium
could produce. But Bacon cites other authors besides Aristotle in his that he received early training “in sciences and languages.”27 He was
discussions of scientia experimentalis, and he is excited by other mirabilia not the first Englishman to spurn the speculative gymnastics of Paris
besides those described in the Secretum. or to remark the utility of scientific knowledge.28
Curiously, Steele himself offers as an explanation for Bacon’s change We are forced to conclude, therefore, that the claim for the pre­
in career path ca. 1247 the “public disgrace” that resulted from dominant role of the Secretum in Bacon’s life is an unsubstantiated
bungling the interpretation of a Spanish word that he had taken to speculation, provocative but fanciful; it oversimplifies when the facts
be Arabic in an undergraduate lecture on Aristotle’s De plantis; it was are not there to warrant it.29 With this said, it remains that Bacon’s
this, Steele surmised, that pushed him to Oxford and “the aban­
donment of traditional methods.”23 Such a scenario seems farfetched.24
Nevertheless, the example is instructive. A little imagination can come 25 O n the practical mindset developing in the High Middle Ages, see A.C. Crombie,
Augustine to Galileo (Cambridge, Mass., 1952), vol. 1, 69, 183-96; Alexander Murray,
up with lots of reasons to explain Bacon’s change of residence (if Reason and Society in the Middle Ages (Oxford, 1978), 110-6; Lynn White, Jr., Medieval
indeed he made one ca. 1247) and change in intellectual direction. Religion and Technology. Collected Essays (Berkeley, 1978); William Newman, “Technology
and Alchemical Debate in the Late Middle Ages,” Isis 80 (1989), 423-45; Guy Beau-
That nature is full of occult forces, that Man can discover these forces, jouan, “L’interdependence entre la science scolastique et les techniques utilitaires (XIIe,
that these forces are potentially useful, are ideas found in many of XIIT et XLVe siecles),” in his Par raison de nombres. L ’art du calcul et les savoirs scientfques
the books that Bacon read; the same holds for the notion that knowl­ medievaux (Aldershot, 1991), no. XIV; Eamon, Secrets of Nature, 38-58, 66-79.
26 Cf. Maurice De Wulf, Histoire de la philosophie medievale, vol. 2 (Paris, 1936), 271:
edge can be practical. Pliny the Elder, Ptolemy, Artephius, Solinus, “[Bacon] recueille et accentue les traditions d’Oxford, ou, des les debuts de l’universite,
la methode experimentale et ^interpretation des phenomenes de la nature en termes
quantitatifs etaient en honneur”; D.E. Sharp, Franciscan Philosophy at Oxford (New
20 This importance of Josephus is even noted by Easton (Easton, 73 n. 3). A num­ York, 1964), 119: “T hat Bacon simply took up the Oxford tradition is borne out by
ber of other authors were cited by Bacon in support of this idea: see the extended the late appearance of his scientific and philological interests. . . . ”
treatment in Opus maius I, 44ff. And see n. 139 below. 27 “Jam a juventute laboravi in scientiis et Unguis” (Brewer, 58; cf. 65). Cf. his
21 Opus maius I, 9—10, Brewer, 416; Little, 81; Duhem, 182. Easton himself rec­ statement in the Opus maius that he was the “auditor a iuventute” of the “maximus
ognized that the demand for secrecy in alchemy “was a long established custom” naturahs et perspectiuvus quern vidi” (Hackett, “Experimental Science,” 293. See
(Easton, 82 n. 1). the helpful discussion provided by Hackett in “Experimental Science,” chapter 1
22 O H I V, 9; cf. Opus maius II, 215-6; Brewer, 44, Gasquet, 510; O H I II, 9. passim; idem, “Scientia experimentalis: From Robert Grosseteste to Roger Bacon,” in
23 Steele, “Roger Bacon,” 255; see also idem, “Roger Bacon and the State of Robert Grosseteste: New Perspectives on his Thought and Scholarship, ed. James McEvoy
Science in the Thirteenth Century,” in Studies in the History and Method of Science, ed. (Dordrecht, 1995), 93-8.
C. Singer, vol. 2 (Oxford, 1921), 130-1. 28 R.W. Southern, Robert Grosseteste. The Growth of an English Mind in Medieval Europe
24 It is difficult to see how this was a “public disgrace” given that Bacon had long (Oxford, 1986), 85-92, 104-5.
been seeking the meaning of belenum on both sides of the Channel and that “all the 29 Cf. similar criticism by Christopher Dawson, “The Significance of Roger Bacon,”
learned men (doctores)” believed that the word was Arabic. Bacon also informs us The Month, n.s., 9 (1953), 47-52. In discussing aspects of Easton’s book that do not
that he went on to learn about many vernacular words used in translations from his concern us here, Dawson notes Easton’s “forcing of the evidence in the interests of
Spanish students. See Opus maius I, 67; Brewer 91, 467-8. a psychological hypothesis” (51).
372 STEVEN J. WILLIAMS 373
ROGER BACON AND THE SECRET OF SECRETS

new or renewed-—scholarly interests, if not specifically sparked by correct Greek root of mathematica, i.e., disciplina or true science, as
the Secretum, at least were supported and possibly pushed forward by opposed to dimnialio or the pseudoscience of magic which has a nearly
it. By the mid-1260’s, when Bacon was productive again after an identical root, thus implicidy rejecting his own position as found in
apparent hiatus in his writing career of some ten years, we see the the papal opera.35 On the other hand, it seems likely that Bacon’s
Secretum occupying a respectable, and sometimes important place, in Secretum was done not that much later. The many similarities in ideas,
his thinking. In the works that Bacon composed for the pope, the phraseology, tone, and form between the papal opera and the Secretum
Secretum often appears in connection with some of his favorite themes, project suggest that the latter followed upon the former within ten
in particular scientia experimentalist This importance of the Secretum is years or so;36 indeed, the Secretum is of a piece not only with these
likewise signalled by the fact that he had several manuscripts of the works, but also with the Communia naturalium, apparently started in
Secretum in his possession at this time.3031 It is even possible that he had the mid-1260’s, set aside, then finished in the following decade, as
started preparations for his Secretum project while in Paris.323 well as the Compendium studii philosophise (ca. 1272).37
But it was at Oxford, probably some time between ca. 1275 and That a number of Bacon’s remarks in his Secretum constitute responses
ca. 1280, that Bacon finished his Secretum. Certainly this was after to contemporary controversies and debates may also suggest a date
the works for Clement IV (written in Paris 1266-68), because Bacon around 1277, the year of the famous Parisian condemnation issued
refers in the Secretum to his own Opus m aiust He also mentions the by Bishop Etienne Tempier. By 1265, the Parisian scholarly world
Antidotarius, which was apparently written around the same time if was starting to be disturbed in a serious way by the propagation of
not later.34 He takes the opportunity to change his mind about the an eclectic, heterodox Aristotelianism. The Condemnation of 1277
was only the most dramatic of a number of complaints that had
30 See pp. 388-90 below. In the Opus maius, Bacon discusses three examples of been voiced by worried theologians for years. Repeatedly challenged
experimental science’s “third prerogative,” and the Secretum is cited first for numbers and .provoked, the authorities became increasingly touchy, and the
2 and 3; immediately following this, Bacon talks about several other mirabilia from resulting Condemnation was a kind of scattershot attack on thinking
the Secretum. Note, however, that Bacon’s very first example of scientia experimentalis is
the spherical astrolabe, and after the flurry of citations from the Secretum he goes on considered in any way threatening. Books dealing with necromancy,
to discuss marvelous works from yet other sources. See Opus maius II, 202-19. fortunetelling, and the supplication of demons were anathematized.
31 “Exemplaria quatuor que nunc inveni Oxonie non habuerunt ilia, nec similiter
multa alia, set Parisius habui exemplaria perfecta” (OHI V, 39). By the 1260’s, it
Among the “execrable errors” castigated was Aristotle’s apparent denial
would appear, Franciscan practice had caught up with the Dominicans, and scholar­ of a temporal creation, which had bothered some schoolmen since
ship had won out over poverty: see K.W. Humphreys, The Book Provisions of the the turn of the century; astrological determinism, necessitarian ema-
Mediaeval Friars 1215-1400 (Amsterdam, 1964), 46-66; Chartularium Universitatis Parisiensis,
eds. H. Denifle and A. Chatelain, vol. 2 (Paris, 1891), no. 580, 56-9. Probably Bacon nationism, and monopsychism were also impugned. But this was
had access to the Secretum in the library of Cordeliers ca. 1265; if it were organized
like the most advanced libraries of the time, perhaps he was even able to borrow a 35 Opus maius I, 239-40; Brewer, 27, 261, 269-70. The view expressed in the
copy or two from the collection’s parva libraria (see Steven J. Williams, “The Schol­ Secretum on this issue (OHI V, 2-3) is the same as in the Greek Grammar (Greek Gram­
arly Career of the Pseudo-Aristotelian Secretum secretorum in the Thirteenth and Early mar, 117-8, 137) and the Communia mathematica (OHI XVI, 2-3). See the discussion
Fourteenth Centuries” [Ph.D. diss., Northwestern University, 1991], 91-2). And friends in Williams, “Roger Bacon,” 61. Note also that one of the lectures edited by Robert
could have lent him copies. But we might take him to mean that he really owned Steele, “Roger Bacon as Professor. A student’s notes,” Isis 20 (1933), 61, contains
several manuscripts of the Secretum. After all, Bacon did spend money as a friar, and this later view, suggesting that it was composed after 1268, not before, as Steele
he did own scientific instruments.
implies {ibid., 54).
32 Bacon explains in his Secretum that the four exemplars used in the correction of 36 A number of scholars have remarked Bacon’s habit of reusing the same mate­
his work do not have the material on talismans (OHI V, 39, 172; cf. what Bacon rial for different writings and the similarity in content between the Secretum’s intro­
says here with the superscription in ibid., 157); nevertheless, it appears in his edition duction and the papal opera. Examples of the similarity in content between the
with notice o f some textual variants. This suggests the possibility that Bacon had entire Secretum project and the papal opera can be found in these notes passim. Also
already prepared a preliminary redaction of the Secretum when he was in Paris. cf. the hortatory and polemical tone taken in the one and the other; the figurae
33 O H I V, viii, 24; see also Williams, “Roger Bacon,” 61 n. 14. included in both; the glossing of the Secretum and the glossing of the selections from
34 O H I V, 23. The Antidotarius seems to refer to Bacon’s De erroribus medicorum Seneca in Part 7 of the Opus maius (for the latter, see Rogeri Baconis Moralis philosophia,
(OHI IX, 110, 214), and the latter certainly postdates ca. 1260 (Williams, “Roger ed. Eugenio Massa [Zurich, 1953], passim).
Bacon,” 72-3, nn. 88-9).
37 I would add the Greek Grammar and the Metaphysica to this group.
374 STEVEN J. WILLIAMS ROGER BACON AND THE SECRET OF SECRETS 375

no mere warning: those who did not hand over the above-mentioned called magicians.44 Aspects of occult science were singled out for
books, and those who maintained, defended, or even listened to any criticism in Bonaventure’s Collationes in Hexaemeron (1273) and Giles of
of the censured practices or propositions, were threatened with ex- Rome’s Errores philosophorum (ca. 1270), for example. It is possible that
communication and “other penalties, just as the law shall have dic­ Bonaventure’s sermons were partly inspired by and directed against
tated, according to the gravity of the offence.”38 his fellow brother Roger Bacon; John Pecham, also for a time a
While no specific mention is made of the Secretum or its contents housemate in Paris, may have been another vocal opponent.45 As
in the Condemnation, it remains that this book made its own modest George Molland has described the situation: “Bacon was adamant
contribution to the chorus of heterodoxy that so agitated conservatives that he was not advocating magic, but his repetitive vehemence shows
like Etienne Tempier. He would certainly have regarded some of the that he was conscious that he could be suspected of it”46—and, we
Secretum?s contents as dangerous. The Secretum is full of praise for astrol­ might add, probably was. Bacon was an outspoken advocate of astrol­
ogy, including a story about a king’s son inexorably drawn by the ogy and natural magic. He ridiculed those who reproved judicial
stars to become a smith.39 It has three chapters dealing with magi­ astrology as asini, and he accused them of “infinite stupidity.”47 He
cal talismans.40 The fact that the “amulet of Hermogenes” described was also an ardent defender of fascination, in spite of the fact that,
by Aristotle includes the inscription of words (in this case, the names as he recognized, the very word was “suspect.”48 Indeed, in 1277 the
of the planets) invites the charge that demons were to be summoned Condemnation would set itself explicity against this species of magic,
for aid in the amulet’s functioning.41 And the book’s recipe for the rejecting the proposition that “superior intelligences impress inferiors,
panacea includes suffiimigations, similarly redolent of the necromantic just as one soul impresses another, even a sensitive soul, and through
invocation of spirits (even Albertus Magnus, the open-minded author such an impression someone can throw a camel into a pit by sight
of the Speculum astronomiae [ca. 1265-1270?], had castigated their use alone.”49
in connection with the fabrication of talismans).42 In an apparent attempt to palliate the conservative reaction, Bacon
It is obvious from Bacon’s remarks in his Secretum that he feels goes out of his way in his introduction to condemn “wicked books”
defensive about Aristotle’s and defensive about his own scientific views. written by “wicked men” that deal with magic; he even lists some
He is convinced that scribes, shocked by what they saw as “magic”, titles.50 At the same time, it seems that Bacon is doing his best to ensure
have cut the chapters dealing with astral images.43 Presumably there that the Secretum not be counted among them. He lambasts Philip of
were other attacks; the intellectual climate of the time, and the tenor Tripoli for using words associated with magic in his translation.51
of his introduction, suggest as much. In the Opus maius, Bacon ob­
serves that scarcely anyone has dared to speak in public about talis­ 44 Opus maius I, 393-4. Also ibid., 248, 396; Brewer, 270.
mans such as Aristotle describes in the Secretum, for fear of being 45 Bonaventure: Camille Berube, “Le ‘dialogue’ de S. Bonvaventure et de Roger
Bacon,” Collectanea jranciscana 39 (1969), 61-3; Crowley, 55-61; Hackett, “Experi­
mental Science,” 145-154, 156; La scienza sperimentale. Lettera a Clemente IV, La Scineza
sperimentale, I Segreti deWarte e della natura, ed. Francesco Bottin (Milan, 1990), 52.
Pecham: Hackett, “Experimental Science,” 142-5.
38 Chartularium Universitatis Parisiensis, vol. 1, (Paris, 1889), no. 473, 543-58. O n the 46 George Molland, “Roger Bacon and the Hermetic Tradition in Medieval Sci­
Condemnation of 1277, see Aufklarung im Mittelalter? Die Verurteilung von 1277, ed. ence,” Vivarium 31 (1993), 150-1.
K urt Flasch (Mainz, 1989), which includes a thorough bibliography. 47 Brewer, 270. In the latitude that he gives to astrology, Bacon seems opposed to
39 O H I V, 136-7. Cf. condemned proposition no. 207 of 1277: Chartularium the views of his hero Robert Grosseteste: see Hackett, “Scientia experimentalist 114-5,
Universitatis Parisiensis, vol. 1, p. 555. 117.
40 O H I V, 157-63. Cf. the criticism of talismans in Giles of Rome’s Errores 48 Opus maius I, 143, 398-403; also Brewer, 96-9, 528-32. O n Bacon’s view of
philosophorum, ed. Josef Koch (Milwaukee, 1944), p. 53. fascination, see the helpful discussion in Rosier, La parole, chapter 6 passim.
41 Aquinas made just such a general argument: see Theodore Otto Wedel, The 49 Chartularium Universitatis Parisiensis, vol. 1, 549. Bacon’s being at odds with the
Mediaeval Attitude Toward Astrology (New Haven, 1920), 69; Brian B. Copenhaver, Condemnation on this issue was brought to my attention by Murray, Reason and
“Astrology and Magic,” in The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy, ed. Charles B. Society, 110, 443. See also Rosier, La parole, 227.
Schmitt and Quentin Skinner (Cambridge, 1988), 282 and n. 39. 50 O H I V, 6. See Brewer, 526, 531-2, and Little, 48, for similar lists of books.
42 Paola Zambelli, The Speculum astronomiae and its Enigma. Astrology, Theology and 51 OHI V, 2, 12, 39. In other works Bacon remarks the inadequacy of the scientific
Science in Albertus Magnus and his Contemporaries (Dordrecht, 1992), 240-1, 246-7. vocabulary used by the major Latin translators of the period: Opus maius I, 67;
43 O H I V, 39, 172; cf. what Bacon says here with the superscription in ibid., 157. Brewer, 90, 467.
376 STEVEN J. WILLIAMS ROGER BACON AND THE SECRET OF SECRETS 377

And while agreeing with those detractors who castigated magicians Bacon is even willing to acknowledge the possibility that pagan sages
for making use of demons and for asserting that their wonders hap­ like Aristotle might be saved.58
pen of necessity, Bacon argues that there are men who are wise and Bacon’s remarks in his Secretum thus seem to reflect the feelings of
good able to do great things by means of ingenuity and natural forces suspicion and tension that were especially prevalent in the years just
alone.52 This basic distinction between an evil and a good (or “natu­ prior to the great Condemnation.59 Like Albertus Magnus in the
ral”) magic was a scholastic commonplace by Bacon’s time. Bacon Speculum astronomiae, Bacon was concerned to defend books and dis­
likewise categorically rejects the idea that human actions are the ciplines that he believed were valuable. And notwithstanding his
necessary result of the movements of the heavenly bodies, again tak­ irascible forthrightness, he, like Albert, does not mention the Con­
ing the standard, orthodox line that they can incline a person to do demnation in his work, nor does he ever “suggest any modification
something, but they cannot affect free will; that they indicate, but do or withdrawal of the episcopal decree”—perhaps because his defense,
not cause future behavior.53 like Albert’s, was written before it.60 There is yet another reason that
Bacon makes an effort to deflect criticism of the Secretum's prob­ such a defense would be harder to imagine in the years immediately
lematic philosophical contents as well. He tries to steer the text clear after the Condemnation. Though Bacon was not in Paris when pre­
of the doctrines of creation by intermediaries and the unity of the paring his Secretum (so technically he was not bound by the Condem­
intellect.54 He also defends Aristotle against those who would charge nation), and though he was speaking privately for a prince’s ears
him with heresy. With firmness, Bacon implicitly opposes the stance only, it would still have been impolitic, if not audacious, for Bacon
of his esteemed mentor Robert Grosseteste who had said that Aristotle to speak so after 1277 in the face of the Condemnation’s offensive,
was a heretic because of his denial of creation and who had warned especially as it was John Pecham, a formidable, active opponent of
that those who argued otherwise were in danger of becoming here­ the “liberal” Aristotelian thinkers, who was provincial general of the
tics themselves.55 Like some other schoolmen, Bacon holds that English Franciscans (1275-1279) and then Archbishop of Canterbury
Aristotle believed in creation.56 More than that, Bacon claims that (1279-1292).
Aristotle worshipped God and had some knowledge of the Trinity; However, Bacon’s remark in his introduction about the “false doc­
that he read the Old Testament and accepted the authority of Isaiah.57 trine in philosophy begun fifteen years ago” could push the completion
date of the Secretum project to the years just after the Condemnation.61
52 O H I V, 6-8. Bacon discussed magic elsewhere in terms similar to his Secretum:
Opus maius I, 238-42, 394—403; Opus maius II, 216-7; Brewer, 96-9, 523-32; Little,
16-8, 53; Duhem, 153; Molland, “Hermetic Tradition,” 154—5. Also n. 50 above. 58 O H I V, 37 n. Bacon’s opinion found supporters among some contemporaries:
53 O H I V, 3-6. Bacon argued this frequendy in his later work: Opus maius I, 240- see Williams, “Scholarly Career,” 98-9.
50; Brewer, 26-7; Litde, 4; Gasquet, 514. See also several recent articles by Jeremiah 59 This was first suggested by Mahmoud Manzalaoui, “The Pseudo-Aristotelian
Hackett that place Bacon’s astrological views within the context of the Condemnation Sin al-asrar and Three Oxford Thinkers of the Middle Ages,” in Arabic and Islamic
of 1277 and the intellectual crisis that preceded it: “Scientia experimentalist 114—8; Studies in Honor o f Hamilton Gibb, ed. G. Makdisi (Leiden, 1965), 487, and Jeremiah
idem., “Necessity, Fate and a Science of Experience in Albertus Magnus, Thomas Hackett, “Practical Wisdom and Happiness in the Moral Philosophy of Roger Bacon,”
Aquinas and Roger Bacon,” in Man and Nature in the Middle Ages, ed. Susan J. Ridyard Medwevo 12 (1986), 91-2; see also idem, “Experimental Science,” 124—40. O n Bacon’s
and Robert G. Benson, Sewanee Mediaeval Studies 6 (1995), 113-23; idem., “Aristode, opposition to the Latin Averroists, see P. Hadrianus a Krizovljan, “Controversia
Astrologia and Controversy at the University of Paris (1266-74),” in Learning Institu­ doctrinalis inter magistros franciscanos et Sigerum de Brabant,” Collectanea franciscana
tionalized: Teaching in the Medieval University, ed. Edward English and John Van Engen 27 (1957), 121-65; Jeremiah Hackett, “Averroes and Roger Bacon on the Harmony
(forthcoming). This last item is a wide-ranging study that touches on a number of of Religion and Philosophy,” in A Straight Path. Studies in Medieval Phihsophy and Cul­
the particular points raised here. ture. Essays in Honor of Arthur Hyman, ed. Jeremiah Hackett, et al. (Washington D.C.,
54 See pp. 382—3 below. 1988), 98-112; idem, “Philosophy and Theology in Roger Bacon’s Opus maius,” in
55 Robert Grosseteste, Hexaemeron, ed. Richard C. Dales and Servus Gieben (London, Phibsophy and the God of Abraham: Essays in Memory of James A. Weisheipl, O.P., ed.
1982), 58-61. R. James Long (Toronto, 1991), 57; idem, “Practical Wisdom,” 55-109.
56 O H I V, 127 n. 4. Bacon defended Aristode on this issue for all of his life: see 60 The quotation comes from Zambelli, Speculum astronomiae, 7. I have modeled
O H I XIII, xxxv-xxxvii; Easton, 56-8; Theodore Crowley, “Roger Bacon and what I say here on one of Zambelli’s arguments for locating the Speculum astronomiae
Avicenna,” Phibsophwal Studies 2 (1952), 86-7. And see n. 140 below. before 1277: see ibid., 6-8, 52-3.
57 OHI V, 8, 37 n. 56, n. 1. Bacon spoke of Aristode’s trinitarianism elsewhere: 61 O H I V, p. 7. For earlier attempts to use this comment to date Bacon’s Secretum,
O H I I, 7-8; Opus maius II, 197, 230-1; Brewer, 423. see ibid., 267; Williams, “Roger Bacon,” 62-3.
378 STEVEN J. WILLIAMS ROGER BACON AND THE SECRET OF SECRETS 379

Bacon links the purveyors of this doctrine with the “many abomi­ and this is piquantly expressed in his Secretum.®* Repeatedly Bacon
nable men who dispose many to the worst errors of Antichrist.”62 complains about the quality of the manuscripts at his disposal;70 repeat­
Clearly he must have judged this a heinous doctrine to excoriate it edly he expresses his frustration at textual corruptions and Arabic
so. His Communia naturalium might provide a key for understanding words;71 repeatedly he mentions the need to look in other copies of
what it was. In this work, Bacon discusses three “abominable errors” the Secretum and to consult apothecaries and doctors about particular
in philosophy that were then being espoused by leading Arts profes­ medicinal ingredients.72
sors in Paris.63 It is the second of the three that especially exercises Equally important, Bacon was playing Aristotle to some princely
Bacon, viz., the unity of the intellect, defended by the doctrine of Alexander, a mentoring role he had already taken on in his work for
the “double truth”: Bacon decries monopsychism as “insane and the pope.73 Frustrated, perhaps, at not having received financial sup­
against reason, against faith . . . [and destroying] the laws of moral port from the papacy for his ideas, Bacon decided to try his luck
philosophy”; he decries its proponents as vilissimi heretici.64 The many somewhere else.74 His intention was to send his Secretum privately to
pages Bacon spends on his discussion also shows how greatly this some contemporary king or prince. The edition is personalized, with
teaching and its teachers disturbed him.656If we can link the Communia
naturalium to the Secretum on this issue, then the current historical
consensus for the start of heterodox Aristotelianism— 1263-65—yields 69 O H I V, 2. See the discussions of Bacon’s dissatisfaction with the Latin Aristo­
a terminus ante quern of ca. 1280 for Bacon’s Secretum. While this goes telian corpus by John Edwin Sandys, “Roger Bacon,” Proceedings of the British Academy
against the argument presented in the preceding paragraph, it accords 6 (1914), 382-3; Charles Borromee Vandewalle, Roger Bacon dans Thisbire de k phibbgie
(Paris, 1929), 66-9.
roughly with the general hypothesis locating Bacon’s work close to
70 O H I V, 23, 39, 172.
the Condemnation of 1277, and gives it independent support. 71 Corruptions: ibid., 23, 82, 84. Arabic words: ibid., 69, 70, 84, 87, 94, 97, 99,
Bacon’s reasons for undertaking his work were twofold. First of 100, 102, 105.
72 Ibid., 84, 97, 101, 105, 172.
all, there was the goal of preservation. Bacon thought that the Secretum 73 An apparent identification with the Aristotle of the Secretum is seen in Bacon’s
was under attack and that its best parts were being censored. For mature work: just as Aristotle served as Alexander’s preceptor and counselor, so
Bacon, Aristotle was the summus philosophorum.® Not only had Aristotle Bacon took on a tutorial role with the pope and the Secretum’s intended recipient;
just as Aristotle sent out 2,000 men on Alexander’s authority “for knowing the truth
composed exoteric works of philosophy, Bacon believed, but also spe­ of things,” so Bacon claimed that he too “sent across the sea and to other diverse
cial books not intended for the common herd.67 Among the latter regions” for experimental knowledge (Bacon himself draws the analogy in Gasquet,
502; cf. Brewer, 24; see also Easton, 114); just as Aristotle advocated secrecy and
was the Secretum, written in Aristotle’s old age, and containing awe­ spoke cryptically when treating certain secrets, so did Bacon, especially in connection
some secrets revealed nowhere else in his writings.68*Obviously, then, with alchemy (see Easton, 79, 82 n. 1); just as Aristotle promised that study of the
it was necessary to have the complete text of Aristotle’s letter as it Secretum’s enigmas would yield all that Alexander desired to know (OHI V, 26-7,
40-2), so Bacon claimed that close reading of some of his own writings would lead
came from his own hand. Bacon frequently gave vent to dissatisfac­ to understanding (Little, 89; O H I V, 1). On Bacon’s more general desire to play a
tion concerning the quality of the available translations of Aristotle, heroic role in the story of the transmission of knowledge, see George Molland,
“Addressing Ancient Authority: Thomas Bradwardine and Prisca Sapientia,” Annals of
Science 53 (1996), 214; idem, “The Role of Aristotle in the Epistemological Schemata
of Roger Bacon and Thomas Bradwardine,” in Arisbtk in Britain During the Middle
62 O H I V, 7.
Ages. Proceedings of the International Conference at Cambridge, 8~11 April 1994 (Tumhout,
63 O H I III, 284-94.
1996), 290.
64 Ibid., 286-7. Cf. Bacon’s comment in Compendium studii theobgbae, 82: “Sic igitur 74 Cf. Bacon’s remarks in the papal opera: “Et nullus sufficeret ad hoc [i.e., an
patet insania Averrois et multiplex eius fatuitas, quae stultos cogit multipliciter in encyclopedic treatise on the sciences], nisi dominus papa, vel imperator, aut aliquis
errorem.”
rex magnificus . . .” (Brewer, 24); “Et ideo patet quod scripta principalia de sapientia
65 O H I III, 286-91.
philosophiae non possunt fieri ab uno homine nec a pluribus, nisi manus prealatorum
66 Similar expressions of praise can be found in O H I I, 11; Opus mams I, 55, 392; et principum juvent sapientes cum magna virtute” (Brewer, 56); “futura pericula in
Opus maius II, 244; Brewer, 6, 81. temporibus Antichristi, quibus cum Dei gratia facile esset obviare, si praelati et
67 O H I II, 7; O H I III, 249. principes studium promoverent et secreta naturae et artis indagarent” (Opus maius II,
68 That Aristode had written the Secretum in his old age: O H I V, 1, 26; Opus 222). The doublet “princes and prelates” that we see in two of the sentences here
maius I, 393.
is often used by Bacon; for two examples in the Secretum, see O H I V, 88, 105.
380 STEVEN J. WILLIAMS ROGER BACON AND THE SECRET OF SECRETS 381

Bacon directly addressing his reader numerous times as “you.”75 It is Bacon’s patience and searching yielded impressive results: he was able
clear here that he is speaking to a particular individual and not a to produce a very good version of the text, and the edition’s complete­
group of students or colleagues: his attitude regarding the disclosure ness sets it apart from the majority of extant manuscripts.83 While it
of nature’s secrets certainly precluded letting what he termed the would be an exaggeration to describe his work as a “critical” edition
vulgus see all of his notes; only the sapientes would be worthy of this.76 in the strict sense, that appelation is deserved if it is qualified with
That Bacon was not addressing a reader with university training is the word “provisional”; though a partial achievement, nothing better
also evident from the modest intellectual level of some of the notes, has been done since.84 We have seen that Bacon recognized some of
e.g., informing the reader that a quarter of an hour equals fifteen its shortcomings. But he added to these himself. It is unsettling to
minutes and a third of one hour is twenty minutes.77 Given that realize that Bacon makes a number of silent alterations in his text,
Bacon was in England when he completed his project and that he though he had castigated just such behavior in his discussions about
talks as if his reader were English, the most obvious dedicatees are the Vulgate in the papal opera.85 Perhaps Bacon felt that the deficien­
Henry III or his son Edward I.78 What appears to be the exclusively cies of the translation and the corruptions in the manuscripts gave
English provenance of the extant manuscripts of his Secretion supports him a degree of scholarly licence, that his emendations simply had
the hypothesis that Bacon’s prospective benefactor was English.79 to be correct, and that the specific nature of the project as a speculum
Bacon’s project involved a significant investment in time and labor. principis warranted the other changes. However explain it, it consti­
Though Bacon did not go to the lengths with the Secretum edition that tutes a betrayal of his own excellent principles of textual scholarship.
he had recommended in connection with the Bible—indeed it is doubt­ Bacon tried to make his Secretum “user friendly.” The Latin Secretum,
ful that he could have, given his circumstances and lack of Arabic— just like its Arabic model, was divided into ten books whose lengths
he did go part way.80 Bacon looked at a number of manuscripts in vary significantly from one to the next; several comprise one para­
order to find the best readings and to find missing sections of the graph only, while others include many chapters. O n his own initia­
Secretum that had fallen away over the course of some five decades of tive, Bacon reorganized the uneven ten-book format into four large
frequent copying or that had been deliberately excised.81 When fina­ sections: on rulership; on the maintenance of health; on the marvels
lizing his recension in Oxford, he collated four copies of the Secretum.82 of science; on physiognomy.86 He wrote a substantive introduction
primarily intended to aid the reader in understanding the Secretum’’s
astronomical references, especially in the chapters on phlebotomy and
75 See my discussion in “Roger Bacon,” 66-7.
76 The distinction between the vulgus and the sapientes is typical of Bacon’s mature talismans.87 He composed detailed chapter headings and put all of
work: Opus maxus I, 9-11; Brewer, 42, 416; Little, 81; Duhem, 182; cf. n. 137 below. them together in a table of contents.88 He added numerous utilia to
In the Secretum, Bacon talks several times about “the wise” or “the wisest”: O H I V, the work—seven diagrams, a chart, plus notes both in the margins
1, 23, 25, 117, 166.
77 O H I V, 76 n. 2, 77 n. 5. Steele {ibid., xxx) is harsher, saying that “ [Bacon’s] and between the lines.89 Often he alerted the reader to look in other
explanations.. . seem in most cases to be pretty obvious, and show that he did not
expect much intelligence in the reader.”
78 See also Williams, “Roger Bacon,” 67. Note also the mention of cinque porte— 83 See Friedrich Wurms, Studien zu den deutschen und den lateinischen Ptosqfassungen des
the Cinque Ports?— at the end of Aristotle’s discussion of the virtues of the num­ pseudo-aristotelischen Secretum secretorum (Hamburg, 1970), 125.
ber 5 (OHI V, lvi, 135). I have examined many of the early Secretum manuscripts, 84 See n. 160 below.
and I can second Steele’s claim as to never having found these words in them. 85 Steele signals a number of changes in O H I V, passim. However, some of these
Possibly it is Bacon’s addition. are open to question, as they might have been included in one or more of Bacon’s
79 Manuscripts: O H I V, vii. Witnesses: ibid., vii; Manzalaoui, “Oxford Thinkers,” exemplars. For Bacon’s complaint, see Brewer, 93, 333.
493; idem, Secretum secretorum. Mne English Versions (Oxford, 1977), xxi. 86 O H I V, 28.
80 On Bacon and the Vulgate, see Cardinal (F.A.) Gasquet, “Roger Bacon and 87 The tractatus brevis et utilis is in O H I V, 1-24. For the introduction’s rationale,
the Latin Vulgate,” in Roger Bacon Essays, 89-99; G. Delorme, “Roger Bacon,” in see ibid., 12, 17. Elementary lessons in astronomy/astrology were also given to the
Dictionnaire de theologjx catholique, vol. 2 (Paris, 1932), cols. 23-7. On Bacon and Arabic, pope: Opus maius I, 254—62; Little, 5-9.
see n. 92 below. 88 O H I V, 28-35.
81 O H I V, 39, 80. 89 Bacon uses the word utilia to describe the astrological material that he has added
82 O H I V, 39, 172. to the text (OHI V, 23), but it has an obvious wider meaning. For the diagrams
382 STEVEN J. WILLIAMS ROGER BACON AND THE SECRET OF SECRETS 383

parts of his edition.90 Bacon, apparendy, took great care to produce the former to “what is universally called soul” (que vocatur universaliter
a book worthy of a prince. anima) and glosses exivit—a word that takes the book perilously close
Bacon’s notes take a variety of forms. There are over three score to a theory of cosmogonic necessitation—with “made by God through
emendations or variant readings—an impressive number showing creation” (per creacionem a Deo factam).95 Next comes hyle (prime mat­
Bacon’s concern for his text and the attentiveness with which he ter), which Bacon defines in a long note,96 and from that the celestial
examined his exemplars.91 He also notifies the reader when he believes spheres: silently changing their number from nine to ten (thus bring­
that a word is a transliteration.92 Sometimes he provides a brief expli­ ing it into line with what he takes to be Aristotle’s position as well
cation to clear up any possible uncertainty about the meaning of a as with other authorities), Bacon explains something of the difference
particular term or statement. And then there are the more substan­ of opinion that exists on this issue and then refers his reader back to
tive notes, where Bacon proffers advice or talks about the issues that his introduction.97 The next chapter discusses the development of soul
most interest him. Some have the nature of conversational asides; in Man from infancy to adulthood. Bacon changes the division of
others are learned disquisitions on technical subjects; yet others pulse the soul from the Secretum's two to the standard Aristotelian triad of
with the passion typical of Bacon the polemicist. vegetative, sensitive, and intellective.98 He also twice finesses the text
In spite of sometimes strident criticism of scholastic philosophy, with his explanations so as to pull it away from any implication of
Bacon never turned his back on it, and this is obvious in his Secretum, the Averroist doctrine of the unity of the intellect.99
where he occasionally talks like an Arts professor on the job. The True to the nature of the Secretum as a speculum principis, Bacon
stricdy philosophical portions of Anstode’s Secretum are limited in scope, gives political and ethical advice to his princely reader. In the chap­
but Bacon garnishes them with a goodly number of notes. Two chap­ ter where Aristotle admonishes Alexander to support education and
ters are especially interesting in this regard. The first one presents an subvent schools, Bacon observes that ancient kings did this because
emanationist, Neoplatonic cosmogony, which Bacon tries to make they were instructed in philosophy; he then quotes a remark attrib­
orthodox and to conform to his own philosophy.93 When the text uted to Henry I that “an illiterate king is a crowned ass.”100 The
has God beginning creation with “simple spiritual substance” or (First) chapter heading “On the choice of worthy ambassadors” has Bacon
“Intelligence,” Bacon interprets this to be the angels.94 When the urging his reader to “note this chapter just as all the others,”101 and
original Latin has “universal soul” (que vocatur anima universalis) “going a gloss to the heading of the succeeding chapter finds Bacon reminding
out from” (exivit) the “simple spiritual substance,” Bacon silendy changes

95 O H I V, liv, 127.
and chart, see ibid., 13, 15, 18, 21, 22, 111—2. Note that the selection of glossed 96 Ibid., 127 n. 5.
passages from the Opus tertium and the De secretis operibus naturae found between the 97 Ibid., liv, 128 and n. 1; also 13-4. A belief in ten orbs is characteristic of
introduction and text in Tanner 116, the oldest manuscript of Bacon’s Secretum, is Bacon’s mature work in his Parisian commentaries he apparently held that there
possibly due to Bacon’s initiative as well: see Williams, “Roger Bacon,” 64. were eight and then nine celestial spheres: see Pierre Duhem, Le systeme du monde.
90 Besides those references from introduction to text or vice versa (Williams, “Roger Histoire des doctrines cosmologiques de Platon a Copemic, vol. 3, pt. 2 (Paris, 1915), 269—
Bacon,” 59-61), see O H I V, 51, 70, 83, 94, 95, 100, 101. 70, 275-6, 413-4; Sharp, Franciscan Philosophy, 152-3.
91 O H I V, passim. They are introduced by the words vel or aliter. 98 O H I V, lv, 130.
92 Ibid., 69, 70, 84, 87, 94, 97, 99, 100, 102. Though Bacon implies in the Com­ 99 When the text has the anima sensibilis coming to the body from outside, de illo
pendium studii philosophiae that he will treat Arabic grammar some time in the future loco, Bacon’s gloss says misleadingly scilicet, de utero. And when the text has the per­
(Brewer, 495), based on the Secretum it seems that late in his life Bacon had not made fected human soul being taken up to the firmament of the Intelligence “by means
much progress at all in mastering this language: see O H I V, xxx; Manzalaoui, “Oxford of the universal soul” (a virtute anime universalis), Bacon omits the word anima (OHI V,
Thinkers,” 481-2; also relevant is Maurice Bouyges, “Roger Bacon, a-t-il lu des lv, 131). See also Easton, 84; Manzalaoui, “Oxford Thinkers,” 487.
livres arabes?” Archives d’histoire doctrinale et litteraire du moyen age 5 (1930), 311-5. 100 O H I V, 58. The fine that ends the chapter might be Bacon’s as well: “Quam
93 See the helpful comments by Manzalaoui, “Oxford Thinkers,” 486-7. vile igitur est quod famosi et senes in studio ignorant hec que puelle solebant scire”
94 O H I V, 127 n. 2, 132 n. 1. Mahmoud Manzalaoui, in Pseudo-Aristotle, The Secret (ibid., 59). I have examined many of the Secretum manuscripts dating from the early
o f Secrets: Sources and Influences, ed. W.F. Ryan and Charles B. Schmitt (London, 1982), fourteenth century and before, and I have yet to find these words. Steele is more
60, mistakenly attributes the “universaliter” to the translator. For a similar change, definite in his conclusion than I: ibid., 59 n., 271.
see O H I V, lv, 131 line 19. 101 Ibid., 147.
384 STEVEN J. WILLIAMS ROGER BACON AND THE SECRET OF SECRETS 385

that no one in a state be without duties and that everyone be “use­ astrology at his disposal, that ruler’s own possibly negative complex­
fully” employed.102 When Aristotle counsels that a king have riches, ions or tendencies can be counteracted and even turned toward the
Bacon cautions that immoderate concern for such could lead not to good through the application of the appropriate remedies.109
happiness but its opposite.103 But such comments are found only here A serious interest in medicine is evident in many of the comments
and there in the text. What one would have to characterize as a that Bacon adds to the text. Bacon speaks in his Secretum as an authority
certain lack of interest in the Secretum as a “mirror for princes” is on medical matters, and when Aristode is giving advice on the subject,
even manifest in the section of the book dealing specifically with Bacon is often there to correct, to explain, to elaborate, to advocate.
rulership. While it is true that its elaborate chapter titles have been The confection of medicines depends on both “study and personal
carefully done, the glossing is infrequent and perfunctory; Bacon makes experience [experientia] ,” Bacon says.110 He expatiates about an anti­
some little emendations and occasional explanations, but he says dote for poisons compounded of nuts, figs, and rue (even including
virtually nothing of consequence. Similarly, in the chapter entitled a recipe and specifying the dosage) that is utilissima for kings and
“On the marvels of Justice and the goods that come from it” found others of high station who must worry about such things.111 In an
in Section 3, Bacon makes only one rather trite political observation extended note, he seconds Aristode’s recommendation of rhubarb for
(“people remote from just kings and emperors become their friends its various salutary effects: nothing is worth more for the human
and subjects because [the rulers] are just, as history teaches”); the body, claims Bacon; he then gives detailed directions for its use.112
remainder of his comments are more properly described as philo­ When Aristode describes the “necessary” methods for relieving stom­
sophical.104 While it would be incorrect to say that Bacon did not ach pain—including “embracing a warm and beautiful girl”—Bacon
value the Secretion's edificatory dimension—his other work, especially, glosses the aforesaid word with utilis.113 Exercise is “necessary and
contradicts this—it remains that something else interested him more. useful,” Bacon observes; old wine is “useful” in the fall.114 To Aristode’s
That “something more,” of course, is science. statement that Alexander rub his teeth and gums with aromatic herbs,
In his Secretum Bacon stresses the utility of physiognomy and astrol­ Bacon appends a list of appropriate plants.115 To Aristode’s warning
ogy for the prince. Like his scholastic confreres, Bacon considered about drinking too much during meals, Bacon presents Avicenna’s
physiognomy an important discipline. In a long gloss near the start opinion, and then in a nice touch, concludes by observing that socia­
of Section 4, Bacon describes physiognomy as “a great and beautiful bility requires a bit of drinking at table which, done moderately, will
science and wisdom”; twice in this same note he describes it as not result in any serious harm .116 Bacon clarifies Aristode’s directions
utilissima.105 According to Bacon, physiognomy is useful “for avoiding for sleeping after a meal first on the left side and then on the right:
bad people and associating with good ones”; specifically, the king this is fine for those of sound disposition, but those who are weak
familiar with its rules can choose his friends, ministers, and prelates ought to begin on the left.117 Bacon also emphasizes the importance
wisely.106 A knowledge of astronomy is indispensable in this regard, of astrology for medicine, recommending, for example, that medicines
too. Knowing nativities can help a ruler in selecting an able counse­
lor.107 It can tell him the appropriate time to do things and when 109 Ibid., 5. One such remedy is the panacea Gloria inestxmabilis\ see pp. 386-7, 390
not to; it can help him in “procuring innumerable useful things and below. Cf. Opus maius I, 252-3 for a similar discussion of astrology’s value to the
avoiding bad things.”108 And if a ruler has a physician learned in prince.
110 O H I V, 120.
111 O H I V, 88.
112 “Nichil plus valet corpori humano . . . ” (ibid., 70). Practicing what he preached,
102 Ibid., 148. Bacon ate rhubarb regularly on Aristode’s authority to take care of a problem with
103 Ibid., 95.
phlegm: O H I IX, 151, 155.
104 Ibid., 123-6.
113 Ibid., 73.
105 Ibid., 165-6.
1,4 Ibid., 71, 83.
106 Ibid., 166.
115 Ibid., 69.
107 Ibid., 136.
116 Ibid., 72-3.
108 Ibid., 6. See also ibid., 55, 112-3. 117 Ibid., 73.
386 STEVEN J. WILLIAMS ROGER BACON AND THE SECRET OF SECRETS 387

be exposed to the beneficial rays of the stars; the same ought to be residing in Paris at this time, serving as co-regent of France while his
done with the sick and insane.118 Extensive notes, a diagram, and a elder brother Louis IX remained in the East after the failed Seventh
lunar chart, plus a reference to the astrological figures in his intro­ Crusade. Bacon, too, was in France for at least part of Alphonse’s
duction, follow the chapter on phlebotomy.119 tenure in office, because he tells us that he had seen the leader of
But what really excites Bacon in the Secretum are those “greatest the Pastoureaux with his own eyes (this would have been in 1251).128
secrets”—as it says in the opening superscription to his introduction— Another secret lies hidden in the Secretum!s chapter on alchemy.
“to which Man or human invention can arrive at in this life.”120 “Oh Alexander,” Aristotle intones, “I wish to give to you the great­
One of them is a panacea known as Gloria inestimabilis, whose com­ est secret of secrets . . . ”; he then provides a rapid overview of alchem­
position was perhaps revealed to Adam himself. As described by ical doctrine that concludes with the famous Emerald Table of
Aristotle, this wonder drug includes eight separate medicines—each Hermes.129 Again, Bacon does not fail to mention the utility of the
with its own wonderful benefits—that are mixed with a special “honey” subject under discussion.130 Again, he mentions that the task is expen­
plus pulverized precious substances in a golden vase, then left for sive.131 His notes here are frequent, though he says several times that
eight days exposed to celestial influences.121 Bacon makes observa­ his exposition must be brief because it is forbidden to divulge too
tions all along the way, and at the end of both this chapter and his much of this magnificent wisdom. But for those who can figure out
introduction Bacon extols the panacea’s effects. This drug, he says, what it all means, there is the promise of purifying elements to their
“extends life to the natural limits that God constituted”; it confers very essence.132 With such an ability, a person could make nobler
health “as much to the soul as the body.”122 It is expensive to make, metals from base ones—in particular gold, which Bacon describes as
however, and the ingredients are difficult to find.123 Unfortunately, “the father of miracles, that is, through it marvels are done in human
few physicians use it, “which brings infinite harm to the world” be­ affairs.”133 What these marvels are Bacon leaves unsaid here. That
cause prelates and princes are not thereby made better through its success is possible, however, he leaves no doubt.
marvelous properties.124 In an extraordinary passage, Bacon testifies A similar degree of mystery hangs over another maximum secretum,
to witnessing its transformative power. He saw, he claims, a learned viz., that of “pacifying regions so that they obey [a king] freely with­
physician use this drug to cure “the greatest prince in France after out coercion,” as Bacon’s chapter heading describes it.134 Early on in
the king” of maladies both physical and moral.125 The doctor, Bacon the Secretum, we read a query of Alexander to his teacher asking what
goes on, added to the mix “bone of a stag’s heart” (in fact, an ossifi­ he ought to do with the Persians he has just conquered: he describes
cation), rosemary, and— “if I well recall”—some pills of viper’s flesh.126 them as an intelligent people who like to dominate others, but because
As Clement C J. Webb has pointed out, the person described by Bacon these qualities would make them difficult to rule, he proposes to kill
could be none other than Alphonse of Poitiers.127 Lending Bacon’s them all. To this, Aristotle responds: “If you are not able to change
tale credibility is the fact that Alphonse was indeed seriously ill in the air and water of the land and the disposition of the states, carry
1252 and about a year or so later had recovered fully; Alphonse was out your proposal. If you can govern them with goodness, you will
listen to them with kindness.”135 Though Philip of Tripoli’s rendering

118 Ibid., 8-9.


119 Ibid., 108-13. 128 Opus maius I, 401-2.
120 Ibid., 1. 129 O H I V, 114—7.
121 Ibid., 98-105. 130 “. . .propter bonum reipublice procurandum” {ibid., 117). See also the incipit
122 Ibid., 105. to Section 3 {ibid., 114).
123 Ibid., 24, 105. Cf. Opus maius II, 212. 131 Ibid., 117. Cf. Brewer, 40-1, 46.
124 O H I V, 105. 132 O H I V, 117. Cf. Opus maius II, 214—5; Little, 13; O H I IX, 160.
125 Ibid., 105. 133 O H I V, 116.
126 Ibid., 106. 134 O H I V, 157.
127 Clement C.J. Webb, “Roger Bacon on Alphonse of Poitiers,” in Essays in His­ 135 “Si non potes illius terre mutare aerem et aquam insuper et disposicionem
tory Presented to Reginald Lane Poole, ed. H.W.C. Davis (Oxford, 1927), 290-300. civitatum, imple tuum propositum. Si potes dominari super eos cum bonitate, exaudies
388 ROGER BACON AND THE SECRET OF SECRETS 389
STEVEN J. WILLIAMS

of this passage somewhat garbles the Arabic, it remains clear that ness of the number 5.142 He cites the Secretum as an ethical text143 and
Aristotle’s first option is a rhetorical possibility only and is not to be as an authority in practical medicine.144 But it is the Secretum!s scien­
taken seriously; rather, Aristotle wants Alexander to spare the Persians tific secrets to which Bacon returns over and over again.
and to rule them well. But in a significant misunderstanding of the According to Bacon, it was through Aristotle’s help that Alexander
text, Bacon takes Aristotle to mean that it is possible to change the conquered the world.145 No doubt Bacon believed that Aristotle, who
bad qualities of the land and the air of a region into good ones so had accompanied Alexander on some of his campaigns, served as
that bad mores will be similarly changed to the good.136 According court astrologer and decided the propitiousness of the stars for the
to Bacon, such an alteration can be effected by means of a powerful army’s actions.146 And when a city that Alexander was besieging placed
amulet whose fabrication Aristotle describes. Unlike with the two other a basilisk on its walls in order to kill the attackers, Aristotle designed
great secrets, however, Bacon says comparatively little in this part of the polished surfaces that deflected the creature’s poisonous gaze back
the Secretum—perhaps because Bacon believed that such potent knowl­ upon itself.147 But much of what Aristotle had taught Alexander to
edge was just too dangerous to communicate, and it might fall into this purpose was contained in the Secretum.148 There is the instrumentum
the wrong hands.137 As Bacon says repeatedly in his later work, terribile, the Horn of Themistius, a powerful organ whose tremendous
citing Aristotle’s admonition of secrecy to Alexander at the begin­ blast of sound could be used to call the troops or to frighten the
ning of the Secretum, the person who reveals secrets to the unworthy enemy.149 There is the plant that engenders the obedience of those
breaks the heavenly seal and many evils will befall him.138 who ingest it.150 There is the stone that makes an army flee the field
The Secretum shows up with some frequency in Bacon’s mature of battle.151 And there is the amulet that allows the bearer to change
writings. It is employed in support of the idea that God had first the atmosphere of a region and thereby change the moral qualities
revealed all the secrets of philosophy to the Hebrew patriarchs and of its people.152 So excited was Bacon about this maximum secretum
prophets139 and that Aristotle believed in creation.140 Bacon refers to that once in the Opus maius, after quoting the above-mentioned
Aristotle of the Secretum on the number of fixed stars141 and the great­ response of Aristotle to Alexander’s proposal of genocide, Bacon
exclaims, “Oh how occult is the reply, but how full of the power of
wisdom!”153 However, in another work for the pope, Bacon also hints

eos cum benignitate” {ibid., 38). Most early copies of the Secretum omit the “non” in
the first sentence, which improves the sense; however, only a study of the manu­
scripts can determine if the “non” appeared in Philip’s autograph. The Arabic passage
reads this way: “If you are bent upon killing all of them, and you are able to do so 142 Opm maim II, 197, 402; O H I IV, 338-9.
by reason of your power over them, you cannot change their climate and their 143 O H I I, 20 (lines 32-4; cf. O H I V, 143), 21, 22, 33-4, 35; Opm maim I, 16;
country. Therefore conquer them by kindness and benevolence . . .” {ibid., 177). Opm maim II, 247, 261, 271, 273.
136 Ibid., 38-9. Bacon’s (mis)understanding of this passage was first pointed out 144 Opm maim I, 390; Opm maim II, 204, 211; Brewer, 374; O H I IX, 150-79
in Manzalaoui, “Oxford Thinkers,” 491; see also Mario Grignaschi, in Sources and passim.
Influences, 11. 145 Opm maim I, 392-3; Opm maim II, 221-2; Brewer 117, 395-6; Little, 53; Duhem,
137 Cf. Bacon’s words to the pope in the Opus tertium: “Sed in Opere Minore ubi 156; Gasquet, 516. Cf. O H I V, 37-8.
de coelestibus tractavi, exposui magis ista [i.e., “philosophical” magic, including tal­ 146 In Opm maim I, 390, Bacon cites Aristotle’s reminder to Alexander in the
ismans], ubi maxima secreta naturae tetigi, quae non sunt cuilibet exponenda, sed Secretum that he should do nothing without the advice of an astronomer. Also, Bacon
solis sapientissimis viris” (Brewer, 99). believes that the Secretum provides validation for the science of astrology: Opm maim I,
138 O H I V, 9; cf. 41. See also Opus maius I, 10-12, 45-6; Opus Tnaius II, 204, 246, 390.
214-5; Brewer, 543; Little, 80; Duhem, 182. 147 Opm maim I, 143; Brewer, 535.
139 O H I V, 62-3; O H I I, 45; Opm maim I, 41, 45-6, 65; Brewer, 81, 423, 544; 148 Opm maim I, 392.
Compendium studii theologiae, 44—5. 149 O H I V, 151.
140 Opm maim II, 235. Bacon was not alone in doing this. The fourteenth-century 150 Ibid., 122. Cf. Opm maim II, 216; Litde, 12, 50-1; Duhem, 154.
theology master Peter of Candia informs us that some schoolmen had also cited the 151 O H I V, 118. Cf. Opm maim II, 216-7; Little, 51; Duhem, 154.
Secretum to support this opinion: see Williams, “Scholarly Career,” 100. 152 Opm maim I, 393; Opm maim II, 216, 217; Litde, 15, 53-4; Duhem, 156-7;
141 O H I IV, 395. Cf. Opm maim I, 235, where other authors are cited in support Brewer, 538.
of this number. 153 Opm maim I, 393.
390 STEVEN J. WILLIAMS 391
ROGER BACON AND THE SECRET OF SECRETS

at danger: the Antichrist will use such talismans, too, but “far more experience/experiment. Similarly, his textual and philological con­
powerfully than Aristode.”154 cerns were shared by a number o f others: we need only call to mind
Bacon was equally excited about the Secretum"s chapter on alchemy. the work done on the Bible by a team of Dominicans led by Hugh
Against those who rejected the possibility of alchemical transmutation of St Cher during the 1230’s or the improved version of the Aristo­
because of Aristotle’s statements at the end of Meteorology Book IV, telian corpus prepared by Bacon’s contemporary William of Moerbeke.
Bacon not only disputed the authenticity of these words but also But Bacon’s relationship to the Secretum also reveals to us a man
cited Aristode’s Secretum as proof that Aristode did believe in the science who stands out from his age—idiosyncratic, independent, and inno­
of alchemy.155 According to Bacon, the Emerald Table offered the vative. Developing ideas already found among his fellow schoolmen,
prospect of virtually unlimited production of gold from other metals— Bacon sometimes pushed up to and beyond the limits reached by his
an obvious boon for the state.156 Bacon also tied it to one of his colleagues. With his Secretum, Bacon acted on his frequent remarks
favorite themes, viz., the prolongation of life. That it is possible to concerning textual criticism and produced a semi-critical edition of
extend the life of M an beyond his usual seventy years was suggested this work that is unique for the Middle Ages and that still stands as
to Bacon from several sources, among them the Secretum with its an impressive achievement.160 Bacon also made his Secretum into a
panacea. Bacon referred to this amazing concoction several times in speculum principis like no other. The conventional practicality of this
his writings.157 The Emerald Table provided a key to its composi­ literary genre is subsumed within a synthesizing vision that is origi­
tion, describing how to make an incredibly pure form of gold far nal, indeed modern.161 Reconceiving the Secretum in terms of his own
beyond nature’s limit of twenty-four degrees— “of thirty and forty philosophy, Bacon animated it with the seminal concept of scientia
degrees and of as many degrees as we desire,” Bacon enthuses.158 experimental and made it speak the doctrine of utility.162 As Bacon
The panacea’s essential ingredient, such a super-gold would ensure expressed it in his Opus tertium, “utility must be considered before
the removal of the corruptions of the body and allow it to live to its anything else.”163 No medieval thinker had ever argued the case of
natural end.159 utility so forcefully or hammered it home so often. In his repeated
Roger Bacon’s Secretum project, and his use of the Secretum in his insistance on the practical application of scientific knowledge, on its
other work, reveals to us a man who was very much of his age. beneficiality for the individual and the state, Bacon is the advocate
Bacon was not alone in considering the Secretum authentic and citing for a program that has become our own.
the Secretum as an authority: well-known schoolmen like Albertus
Magnus, Guibert of Tournai, and John of Wales all did the same.
Moreover, Bacon’s Secretum was one of several editions of this work
and one of a great many “mirrors for princes” produced in the thir­
160 For students of the Latin Secretum, Bacon’s redaction as presented by Robert
teenth and early fourteenth centuries. Typical of his day are his belief Steele in O H I V is not only an invaluable witness to the thirteenth-century text but
in physiognomy and astrology; his fascination with nature’s secrets also remains the best edition available, though it must be used with caution because
of Bacon’s interpolations and alterations. Willy Hermenau and Reinhold Moller have
and natural magic; his acknowledgment of practicality/utility and also published editions of the Latin Secretum: see the bibliography at the end of this
chapter.
161 Cf. Crombie, Augustine to Galileo, vol. 1, 69-70: “[with Bacon we see] perhaps
the earliest explicit statement of the practical conception of the aims of science. .. .
154 Little, 54; Duhem, 157. in his conception of the immediate use of science he had almost the outlook of the
155 O H I II, 6-7.
19th century.”
156 Ibid., 7; Little, 13, 80-1; Brewer, 544. 162 The phrase scientia experimentalis appears in OHI V, 2, 9, 24. Bacon uses the
157 Opus maius I, 48-9; Opus maius II, 204-13 passim; Brewer, 374; Little, 13; O H I word utilis or its relatives in ibid., 1, 6, 8, 9, 23, 28-31, 40, 55, 71, 83, 88, 98, 105
IX, 163.
(utuntur), 113, 114, 148, 155 (propter usum), 163, 165-6. But even where such words
158 Opus maius II, 215. do no appear, their spirit is often present. Cf. the observation of A.G. Little, “Roger
159 Ibid., 215; Brewer 374; Little, 13, 46; O H I IX, 160. In an unpublished por­ Bacon,” in his Franciscan Papers, Lists, and Documents (Manchester, 1943), 80: “The
tion of the Opus minus being edited by Dr. George Molland, Bacon also cites the utility of knowledge is the constant theme of the works addressed to the pope.”
Secretum in connection with alchemy.
163 Brewer, 19.
392 STEVEN J. WILLIAMS ROGER BACON AND THE SECRET OF SECRETS 393

Abbreviations and Bibliography . “T h e Secreta Secretorum• T h e M ediaeval E u ro p ean V ersion o f Kitab Sirr-
ul-Asrar.” Bulletin of the Faculty of Arts (University o f A lexandria) 15 (1961):
Alessio F ranco Alessio, Mito e scienza in Ruggero Bacone (M ilan, 8 3 -1 0 5 .
1957) . “T h e Pseudo-A ristotelian Sin al-asrar an d T h re e O x fo rd T hinkers o f
B rew er Fr. Rogeri Bacon: Opera quaedam hactenus inedita, ed. J.S . th e M iddle Ages.” In Arabic and Islamic Studies in Honor of Hamilton Gibb,
B rew er (London, 1859) ed. G . M akdisi, 4 8 0 -5 0 0 . Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1965.
Compendium studii Roger Bacon, Compendium of the Study of Theology: Edition and . “T h e Pseudo-A ristotelian Kitab Sin al-asrar: Facts a n d Problem s.” Oriens
theologiae Translation with Introduction and Notes, ed. T h o m a s S. 2 3 -4 (1974): 147-257.
M aloney (Leiden, 1988) . Secretum Secretorum. Nine English Versions. O xford: O xford U niversity Press,
C row ley T h eo d o re Crow ley, Roger Bacon: The Problem of the Soul in 1977.
his Philosophical Commentaries (Louvain, 1950) M oller, R einhold. Hiltgart von Hiimheim, Mittelhochdeutsche Prosaiibersetzung des
D uhem Pierre D u h em , Un fragment inedit de I’Opus tertium de Roger Secretum Secretorum. Berlin: A kadem ie V erlag, 1963.
Bacon precede d’une etude sur ce fragment (Q uaracchi, 1909) Paravicini Bagliani, A gostino. Medicina e scienze della natura alia corte dei papi
E aston S tew art C. Easton, Roger Bacon and His Search for a Uni­ nel Duecento Spoleto: C en tro Italiano di Studi sull’A lto M edioevo, 1991.
versal Science: A Reconsideration of the Life and Work of Roger
Bacon in the Light of His Own Stated Purposes (New York, R y an , W .F., an d C harles B. Schm itt, ed. Pseudo-Aristotle, The Secret of Secrets:
1952) Sources and Influences. L ondon: T h e W a rb u rg Institute, 1982.
G asquet F.A. G asquet, “A n U npublished F rag m en t o f a W ork W illiams, Steven J . “T h e Scholarly C a reer o f the Pseudo-A ristotelian Secretum
by R oger B acon,” English Historical Review 12 (1897), 494— Secretorum in the T h irte e n th a n d E arly F o u rteen th C en tu ries.” P h.D . diss.
517 unpublished, N orthw estern University, 1991. [a revised an d expanded ver­
Greek Grammar The Greek Grammar of Roger Bacon and a Fragment of his sion o f this w ork is forthcom ing]
Hebrew Grammar, ed. E d m o n d N o lan an d S.A. H irsch . “T h e E arly C irculation o f the Pseudo-A ristotelian Secret of Secrets in
(C am bridge, 1902) the W est: T h e P apal a n d Im perial C o u rts.” Micrologus 2 (1994): 127-44.
Little Part of the Opus tertium of Roger Bacon, ed. A .G . L itde \ “R o g er B acon a n d H is E dition o f the Pseudo-A ristotelian Secretum
(A berdeen, 1912) Secretorum.” Speculum 69 (1994): 5 7 -7 3 .
OHI Opera hactenus inedita Jratris Rogeri Baconi, fascs. I -X V I W urm s, Friedrich. Studien zu den deutschen und den lateinischen Prosafassungen des
(O xford, 1905 [?]-1941) pseudo-aristotelischen Secretum secretorum. Ph.D . diss., Universitat H am burg, 1970.
Opus maius The ‘Opus Majlis’ of Roger Bacon, vols. I—II, ed. J o h n H en ry
Bridges (O xford, 1897)
Roger Bacon Essays Roger Bacon: Essays Contributed by Various Writers on the Occa­
sion of the Commemoration of the Seventh Centenary of His Birth,
ed. A .G . Little (O xford, 1914)

Bacon, R oger. Opera hactenus inedita Rogeri Baconi. Fasc. V , Secretum secretorum
cum glossis et notulis. Ed. R o b e rt Steele. O xford: C laren d o n Press, 1920.
G rignaschi, M ario. “L ’origine e t les m etam orphoses d u Sin al’asrar.” Archives
d’histoire doctrinale et litteraire du moyen age 43 (1976): 9 -1 1 2 .
. “L a diffusion d u Secretum secretorum (Sirr-al-’asrar) dans l’E u ro p e occi-
dentale.” Archives d’histoire doctrinale et litteraire du moyen age 47 (1980): 7 -6 9 .
H erm enau, Willy. Franzosische Bearbeitungen des Secretum Secretorum und ihr Verhaltnis
zu der lateinischen Ubersetzung des Philippus Tripolitanus. P h.D . diss., U niversitat
G ottingen, 1922.
M anzalaoui, M ahm oud. “T h e Secreta Secretorum in English T h o u g h t an d Litera­
ture from the F ourteenth to the S eventeenth C en tu ry w ith a P relim inary
Survey o f the O rigins o f the Secreta.” Ph.D . diss. unpublished, O xford
University, 1954.
16. A ROGER BACON BIBLIOGRAPHY (1985-1995)

Thomas S. Maloney

In 1959 Franco Alessio published an annotated bibliography of works


by and about Roger Bacon under the title “Un secolo di studi su
Ruggero Bacone (1848-1957)” covering the years indicated in the
tide.1 In 1987 a second bibliography picked up where Alessio left off
and was published (without annotation) under the tide “A Roger Bacon
Bibliography (1957-1985).”2 What is presented here represents a survey
of the major bibliographical works on medieval philosophy covering
publications from 1986 to 1995. A few of the entries reflect works
from an earlier period omitted from the preceding lists, and a few
others announce work in progress. As a general rule, only those works
have been selected in which Bacon is given significant attention.

Works by Bacon

Bottin, Francesco, tr. La scienza sperimentale: Lettera a Clemente IV. La


scienza sperimentale: I segreti delVarte e della natura. I classici dei pensiero,
Sezione II: Medioevo e Renascimento. Milan: Rusconi, 1990.
Lindberg, David C., ed. and tr. Roger Bacon and the Origins of Perspectiva
in the Middle Ages: A Critical Edition of the “Perspectiva,” with English
Translation, Introduction, and Notes. Oxford University Press. Forth­
coming, 1995.
Linden, Stanton J., ed. The Mirror of Akhimy. English Renaissance
Hermeticism, 4. New York: Garland, 1992.
Maloney, Thomas S., tr. (English) Roger Bacon’s Summulae diakctices.
Forthcoming, 1997.
Molland, George, ed. and tr. (English) “Roger Bacon’s Geometria
speculativa.” In Vestigia Mathematica: Studies in Medieval and Early Mod­
em Mathematics in Honour of H.H.L. Busard, pp. 265-303. Edited by

1 Revista critica de storia della Jilosofia 14 (1959): 81-102.


2 Jeremiah M.G. Hackett and Thomas S. Maloney, New Scholasticism 61 (1987):
184-207.
396 THOMAS S. MALONEY A ROGER BACON BIBLIOGRAPHY ( 1 9 8 5 - 1 9 9 5 ) 397

M. Folkerts and J.P. Hogendijk. Amsterdam, Adanta, GA: Editions ------ . “Der Sehvorgang als Theologisches Analogon Augenanatomie
Rodopi, 1993. und Physiologie bei Roger Bacon.” Sudhoffs Archiv 1 (1991): 1-20.
. ed. and tr. (English) Roger Bacon’s Opus tertium. In progress. Biard, Joel. “Prodromes d’une nouvelle theorie du signe, Roger Bacon.
In Logique et theorie du signe au XIVe siecle,” pp. 25-42. Paris:
Vrin, 1989.
Works about Bacon Bottin, Francesco. “L’esperienza medievale del tempo tra modelli divini
ed umana finitudine.” Doctor Seraphicus 39 (1992): 109-25.
Aisa Moreu, Diego. “Rogerio Bacon, eslabon revelante en la tradition Bourgain, Pascale. “Le sens de la langue et des langues chez Roger
cientifica que va de los Griegos a la Revolution cientifica de los Bacon.” In Traduction et traducteurs au Moyen Age, pp. 317-31. Edited
siglos xvi-xvii.” In Adas del I Congreso Nacional de Filosojia Medieval. by Genevieve Contamine. Actes du colloque internationale du
Zaragoza 12-14 December 1990, pp. 165-80. Zaragoza: Ibercaja, C.N.R.S. organise a Paris, Institut de Recherche et d’Histoire des
1992. textes, 26-28 mai 1986. Paris: Centre National de la Recherche
Agrimi, Jole, and Crisciani, Chiara. “Per una ricerca su Experimentum- Scientifique, 1989.
experimenta: riflessione epistemologica e tradizione medica (secoli xiii- Braakhuis, H.A.G. “The Contribution to the Discussion on Univocal
xv).” In Presenza del lessico greco e latino nelle lingue contemporanee, pp. Signification of Beings and Non-Beings in a Sophism Attributed to
9-49. Edited by Pietro Janni and Innocenzo Mazzini. Macerata: Robert Kilwardby.” In Medieval Semantics and Metaphysics, Studies
Pubblicazioni della Facolta di Lettere e Filosofia, 1991. Dedicated to L.M. de Rijk, pp. 111-42. Edited by E.P. Bos. Artistarium
Alessio, Franco. Introduzione a Ruggero Bacone. I filosofi, 44. Bari: Laterza, Supplementa 2. Nijmegen: Ingenium, 1985.
1985. Brown, E.A.R. “Authority, the Family, and the Dead in Late Medi­
------ . “Ruggero Bacone fra filologie e grammatiche” in Aspetti della eval France.” French Historical Studies (Columbus, Ohio) 16 (1990):
letteratura latina nel secolo X III, pp. 281-317. Edited by C. Leonardi 803-32.
and G. Orlandi. Atti del primo convegno intemazionale di studi Clark, John R. “Roger Bacon and the Composition of Marsilio Ficino’s
delTAssociazione per il Medioevo e 1’Umanesimo latini (AAMUL), De Vita Longa (De Vita, Book II).” J. Warburg Courtauld Inst. (1986):
Perugia, 3-5 ottobre 1983. Perugia, Firenze: Regione dell’Umbria, 230-3.
La Nuova Italia, 1986. Colnort-Boldet, Suzanne. Le code alchimique devoile: distillateurs, alchimistes
------ . “Simplicitas e paupertas da Ruggero Bacone a Guglielmo di et symbolistes. Paris: Champion, 1989.
Occam”. Ricerche storiche 13 (1983): 659-95. Dahan, Gilbert, Rosier, Irene, Valente, Luisa. “L’arabe, le grec, l’hebreu
Anawati, G.C. “La recontre de deux cultures, en Occident, au Moyen et les vemaculaires.” In Sprachtheorien in Spatantike und Mittelalter, pp.
Age: Dialogue Islamo-Chretien et activite missionaire.” Elul 29 265-321. Edited by Sten Ebbesen. Tubingen: Gunter Narr Verlag,
(1989): 155-78. 1995.
Ancona, Cristina D ’. “Philosophies in libro De Causis: La recezione del Demaitre, L. “The Care and Extension of Old Age in Medieval
1liber de causis5 come opera aristotelica nei commend di Ruggero Medicine.” In Aging and the Aged in Medieval Europe, pp. 3-22. Edited
Bacone, dello ps. Enrico di Gand e dello ps. Adama di Bocfeld”. by M.M. Sheehan. Papers in Medieval Studies 11. Toronto:
Documenti e studi sulla tradizione Jilosofica medievale 2 (1991): 611-49. Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1990.
Ashworth, E. Jennifer. “Analogy and Equivocation in Thirteenth- Eco, Umberto, Lambertini, R., Marmo, C., and Tabarroni, A. “On
Century Logic: Aquinas in Context.” Mediaeval Studies 54 (1992): Animal Language in the Medieval Classification of Signs.” In On
511-8. the Medieval Theories of Signs, pp. 3-41. Edited by Umberto Eco and
Bergdolt, Klaus. “Bacon und Giotto. Zum Einfluss der franziskanischen C. Marmo. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 1989.
Naturphilosophie auf die bildende Kunst am Ende des 13. Jahrhun- Getz, Faye Marie. “To Prolong Life and Promote Health: Baconian
derts”. Medizinhistorisches Journal 24 (1989): 25-41. Alchemy and Pharmacy in the English Learned Tradition.” In
398 THOMAS S. MALONEY A ROGER BACON BIBLIOGRAPHY ( I 9 8 5 - I 9 9 5 ) 399

Health, Disease, and Healing in Medieval Culture, pp. 140-51. Edited Kraml, Hans. “Roger Bacon’s Theory of the Rainbow as a Turning
by Sheila Campbell, Bert Hall, and Daniel Klausner. Basingstoke: Point.” In Analyomen, vol. 1. Edited by Georg Meggle. Hawthorne:
Macmillan, 1992. de Gruyter, 1994.
Hackett, Jeremiah. “Averroes and Roger Bacon on the Harmony of Lardet, Pierre. “Un lecteur de Jerome au XIIIe siecle: Langues et
Religion and Philosophy.” In A Straight Path: Studies in Medieval traduction chez Roger Bacon.” In Jerome entre VOccident et l’Orient,
Philosophy and Culture: Essays in Honor of Arthur Hyman, pp. 98-112. pp. 445-63. XVLe centennaire du depart de saint Jerome de Rome
Edited by Ruth Link-Salinger. Washington D.C.: Catholic Uni­ et son installation a Bethleem. Actes du Colloque de Chantilly,
versity of America, 1988. septembre 1986. Edited by Yves-Marie Duval. Paris: Etudes augus-
. “Necessity, Fate, and a Science of Experience in Albertus tiennes, 1988.
Magnus, Thomas Aquinas, and Roger Bacon.” In Man and Nature Lertora Mendoza, Celina A. “El fundamento de la etica segun Roger
in the Middle Ages, pp. 113—23. Edited by Susan J. Ridyard and Bacon.” In Primeras jomadas nacionales de etica. Buenas Aires: Univer-
Robert G. Benson. Sewanee Mediaeval Studies, 6. Sewanee: Uni­ sidad de Buenas Aires, Faculdad de Filosofia y Letras, 1984—5,
versity of the South, 1995. pp. 183-7.
------ . “Philosophy and Theology in Roger Bacon’s Opus MaiusP In ------ . “Infinito absoluto e infinitos relativos segun Roger Bacon.”
Philosophy and the God ofAbraham: Essays in Memory ofJames A. Weisheipl, Naturaleza y gracia (Salamanca) 34 (1987): 411-23.
pp. 55—69. Edited by R. James Long. Papers in Medieval Studies. ------ . “Una propuesta linguistica para la exegesis en la Escuela de
Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1991. Oxford: Grosseteste y Bacon.” Revista biblica (Buenas Aires) 30-1
------ . “Practical Wisdom and Happiness in the Moral Philosophy of (1989): 97-124.
Roger Bacon.” Medioevo 12 (1986): 55-109. ------. “Roger Bacon, sus ideas exegeticas.” Naturaleza y gracia (Sala­
------ . “Roger Bacon (b. ca. 1214-20; d. 1292).” In Individuation in manca) 30-1 (1988): 97-392.
Scholasticism: The Later Middle Ages and the Counter-Reformation 1150 Lewry, Osmund P. “Grammar, Logic, and Rhetoric.” In The History
1650, pp. 117-39. Edited by J.E. Gracia. Albany: SUNY Press, of the University of Oxford. Edited by T.H. Aston. Vol. I. The Early
1994. Oxford Schools, pp. 401-33. Edited by J.I. Catto. Oxford: Clarendon
, and Maloney, Thomas S. “A Roger Bacon Bibliography (1957— Press, 1984.
1985). New Scholasticism 61 (1987): 184-207. Libera, Alain de. “Ars liberaux et theologie au Moyen Age.” Annuaire
Hovdhaugen, Even. “‘Una et eademK. Some observations on Roger de lEcole practique des Hautes Etudes. V Section. 94 (1985—6): 511-8.
Bacon’s Greek Grammar.” In De ortu grammaticae: Studies in Medieval ------. “De la logique a la grammaire: remarques sur la theorie de la
Grammar and Linguistic Theory in Memory of Jan Pinborg, pp. 117-31. determinatio chez Roger Bacon et Lambert d’Auxerre (Lambert de
Edited by G.L. Bursill-Hall, Sten Ebbesen, and Konrad Koerner. l’Agny).” In De ortu grammaticae: Studies in Medieval Grammar and Lin­
Studies in the History of Language Sciences, 43. Amsterdam: John guistic Theory in Memory of Jan Pinborg, pp. 209-26. Edited by G.L.
Benjamins, 1990. Bursill-Hall, Sten Ebbesen, and Konrad Koerner. Studies in the
Huber-Legnani, M. Roger Bacon. Lehrer der Anschaulichkeit. Der franziska- History of Language Sciences, 43. Amsterdam: John Benjamins,
nische Gedenke und die Philosophic des Eizelnen. Freiburg: Hochschul- 1990.
Verlag, 1984. ------ . “Histoire des theologies chretiennes dans l’Occident medieval.”
Hughes, Barnabas. “Franciscans and Mathematics.” Archivum Francis- Annuaire de I’Ecole pratique des hautes etudes, Ve section 95 (1986-7):
canum Historicum 11 (1984): 3-66. 359-68.
Jourdain, Charles. Excursions historiques et philosophiques a trovers le moyen ------. “Les mots, les concepts, les choses: Theorie du signe et seman-
age. Chapter Five: “Discussion de quelques points de la biographie tique des propositions chez Roger Bacon.” In Le pouvoir de diviser
de Roger Bacon,” pp. 31-45. Paris, 1888; reprinted Frankfurt am les mots et les choses. Fayard, forthcoming.
Main: Minerva, 1966. ------ . “Reference et champ: Genese et structure des theories medi-
A ROGER BACON BIBLIOGRAPHY ( I 9 8 5 - I 9 9 5 ) 401
400 THOMAS S. MALONEY

evales de l’ambiguite (X IP-X IIP siecles).” Medioevo 10 (1984): 155— Mariani, A. “Celestino V nell’attesa escatalogica del secolo XIII.” In
208. Celestino Vpapa angelico, pp. 33-94. Edited by W. Capezzali. L’Aquila:
. “Roger Bacon et la reference vide: Sur quelques antecedents Centro Celestiniano, Sezione storica, 1988.
medievaux du paradoxe de Meinong.” In Lexionum Varietates: Hom- Marmo, Costantino. Semiotica e linguaggio nella scolastica: Parigi, Bologna,
Erfurt 1270-1330. La semiotica dei Modisti. Roma: Nella Sede
mage a Paul Vignaux (1904-1987), pp. 85-120. Edited b y j . Jolivet,
Z. Kaluza and A. de Libera. Etudes de philosophic medievale, dell’Istituto Palazzo Borromini, 1994.
65. Paris: Libraire philosophique J. Vrin, 1991. Mensching, Gunther. “Metaphysik und Naturbeherrschung im Denken
, and Rosier, Irene. “Intention de signifier et engendrement du Roger Bacons.” In Mensch und Natur im Mittelalter, pp. 129-42. Edited
by Albert Zimmermann and Andreas Speer. Miscellanea Medievalia,
discours chez Roger Bacon.” Histoire, epistemologie, langage 8 (1986):
63-79. 21. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1991.
Molland, George. “Roger Bacon and the Hermetic Tradition in
------, and Rosier, Irene. “La pensee linguistique medievale.” In Histoire
des idees linguistiques, vol. 2, pp. 115-58. Edited by Sylvain Auroux. Medieval Science.” Vivarium 31 (1993): 140-60.
Liege: Mardaga, 1993. Muller, Paola. “La dottrina delle fallaciae in dictione’ in Ruggero
Bacone.” Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale 3 (1992):
Lindberg, Daniel. “Roger Bacon and the Origins of perspectiva in the
West.” In Mathematics and Its Applications to Science and Natural Phi­ 91-128.
Nascimento, Carlos Arthur Ribeiro do. “L’Arbre de la philosophic”
losophy in the Middle Ages: Essays in Honor of Marshall Clagett, pp. 249-
in Knowledge and the Sciences in Medieval Philosophy, vol. 2, pp. 1Ob-
68. Edited by Edward Grant and John E. Murdoch. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1987. 12. Proceedings of the Eighth International Congress of Medieval
Philosophy (S.I.E.P.M.). Helsinki, 24-29 August 1987. Vol. 2, Edited
------ . “Science as Handmaiden: Roger Bacon and the Patristic Tra­
dition.” Isis 78 (1987): 518-36. by Simo Knuuttila, Reijo Tyorinoja, Sten Ebbesen. Publications
of Luther-Agricola Society, B19. Helsinki: Yliopistopaino, 1990.
Linden, Stanton S. “Roger Bacon in the Age of Francis: The Mirror
------ . “Conhecer para dominar: Rogerio Bacon.” In Uma historia da
of Alchimy and the Mirror of Nature.” Cauda Pavonis 10 (1991): 10-3.
Lorcin, Marie-Therese. “Gerontologie et geriatrie au Moyen Age.” In filosofia verdade, conhecimento e poder, vol. 2, pp. 115-47. Rio de Janeiro:
Universidade Aberta: Universidade Federal do Rio de Janeiro, 1988.
Vieillesse et vieillissement au Moyen Age, pp. 199-213. Communications
(A translation of “Une theorie des operations . . .”) (1981), q.v.
presentees au XLe colloque du C.U.E.R.M.A., Aix-en-Provence,
------ . “As fontes de Rogerio Bacon no De Multiplication Specierum.”
1986. Aix-en-Provence: Universite d’Aix-Marseille I, Centre univer-
sitaire d’etudes et de recherches medievales Aixois, 1987. Leopoldianum (Santos) 13, no. 38 (1986): 49-63.
------. “A metodologia do De multiplication specierum.” Anais da Associagao
------ . “Rides et cheveux gris dans les ouvrages de Roger Bacon.” In
Nacional de Pos-Graduagao em Filosofia (Campinas) 1, no. 1 (1986):
Les Soins de beaute: Moyen Age—debut de temps modemes, pp. 253—9.
Actes du IIP Colloque International, Grasse, 26-28 avril 1985. 13-8.
------. “Revisitando ‘Tres tradigoes explicativas na lei da queda dos cor-
Edited by Denis Menjot. Nice: Centre d’etudes medievales, 1987.
pos.’” Revista da Sociedade Brasileira de Historia da Ciencia 5 (1991): 49-52.
Macdonald, Michael-Albion, ed. and tr. De nigromancia. Attributed
------ . “Une theorie des operations naturelles fondee sur l’optique: le
to Roger Bacon. Sloane MS. 3885 and additional MS. 36674.
De multiplication specierum de Roger Bacon.” Manuscrito (Campinas)
Berkeley Heights, NJ: Heptangle Books, 1988.
Manselli, R. “II ‘Pastor Angelicus’: una speranza, una delusione ed il 5, no. 5 (1981): 32-5.
------ . “Tres tradi^oes explicativas na lei da queda dos corpos.” Trans/
loro significato storico.” In Indulgenza net Medioevo e perdonanza di
papa Celestino V, pp. 9-16. Edited by A. Clementi. L’Aquila: Centro Form/Agao (Manrilia) 6 (1983): 5-12.
Celestiniano, sezione storico, 1987. Newman, W. “Technology and Alchemical Debate in the Late Middle
Maranesi, Pietro. “ ‘Revelatio’ e conoscenza ‘per lumen inditum’: La Ages.” Isis 80 (1989): 423-45.
Paravicini Bagliani, Agostino. “Ruggero Bacone autore del De retardation
posizione media di Bonaventura tra Bacone e Tommaso nel prob-
accidentium senctutis. Studi medievali 28 (1987): 707—28.
lema gnoseologico.” Collectanea Francescana 61 (1991): 491-511.
402 THOMAS S. MALONEY
A ROGER BACON BIBLIOGRAPHY ( 1 9 8 5 - 1 9 9 5 ) 403

------. “Ruggero Bacone, Bonafacio VIII, e la teoria della prolongatio Thijssen, J.M.M.H. “Roger Bacon (1214-1292/1297): A Neglected
vitae” In Medicina e scienza della natura, alia corte dei papi nel Duecento, Source in the Medieval Continuum Debate”: Archives Internationale
pp. 327-62. Spoleto: Centro Italiano di Studi sull’Alto Medioevo, d’Histoire des Sciences 34 (1984): 25—34.
1991. Tonna, Ivo. “La concezione del sapere in Ruggero Bacone (1214—
------. “Storia della scienza e storia della mentalita: Ruggero Bacone, 1292).” Antonianum 67 (1992): 461-71.
Bonafacio VIII e la teoria della ‘prolongatio vitae’.” In Aspetti della Urban, William. “Roger Bacon and the Teutonic Knights.” Journal
letteratura latina nel secoh XIII, pp. 243-80. Edited by Claudio Leonardi of Baltic Studies 19 (1988): 363-70.
and Giovanni Orlandi. Perugia, Firenze: Regione dell’U m bria/La Vier, Raimundo. “Rogerio Bacon: Sua carreira academico-cientifica
Nuova Italia, 1986. e seu contributo a recep9ao de Anstoteles.” Presenfa Filosofica (Rio
Parkhurst, Charles. “Roger Bacon on Color.” In The Verbal and Visual: de Janeiro) 10 (1984): 230—40.
Essays in Honor of William Sebastian Heckscher, pp. 151-201. Edited Williams, Steven J. “Roger Bacon and His Edition of the Pseudo-
by Karl-Ludwig Selig and Elizabeth Sears. N.Y.: Italica, 1990. Aristotelian Secretum secretorum.” Speculum 69 (1994): 57-73.
Poro, P. “Enrico di Gand ed il problema dell’unicita delTaevum.” Woodward, David. “Roger Bacon’s Terrestrial Coordinate System.”
Medioevo 13 (1987): 123-93. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 80 (1990): 109-22.
Ribeiro do Nascimento, Arthur Carlos. See Nascimento.
Rosier, Irene. “Grammaire, logique, semantique: Deux positions
opposees au XIIIe siecle, Roger Bacon et les Modistes.” Histoire,
epistemologie, langage 6 (1984): 21-34.
------. “La grammatica practica du mss. British Museum V A IV: Roger
Bacon, les lexicographes et l’etymologie.” In Lexique. Actes de la
table-ronde: “L’etymologie au Moyen Age,” Strasbourg, mai, 1992.
Edited by C. Buridant. Forthcoming.
. “Roger Bacon, al-Farabi, et Augustin. Rhetorique, logique et
philosophic morale,” dans Gilbert Dahan, Irene Rosier-Catach
(eds.), La rhetorique d’Aristote, traditions et commentaires, de VAntiquite au
XVIT siecle, Paris, Vrin, 1997.
------. See also Libera (7) and (8).
Servus, Gieben. Robert Grosseteste, Roger Bacon, Peter Olivi, and Duns Scotus:
A Bibliography. Subsidia Scientifica Francescalia, 6. Roma: Istituto
Storico dei Cappucini, 1977.
Sirridge, Mary. “Can lest’ Be Used Impersonally: A Clue to the
Understanding of the Verbum Substcuitivum.” Histoire, epistemologie, langage
12 (1990): 121-38.
Stabile, G. “La torre di Babele: confuzione dei linguaggi e impotenza
tecnica.” In Ars et Ratio. Delle torre di Babele al ponte di Rialto, pp.
245-77. Edited byJ.-C. Marie Vigueur and A. Paravicini Bagliani.
Palermo: Sellerio, 1990.
Tachau, Katherine H. Vision and Certitude in the Age of Ockham: Optics,
Epistemology, and the Foundations of Semantics, 1250-1345. New York,
Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1988.
17. EPILOGUE: ROGER BACON’S MORAL SCIENCE

Jeremiah Hackett

The reader of the Opus maius cannot but notice the constant series of
references forward to the seventh part of that work, the Moralis
philosophia. Bacon sees the whole work as a task of moral persuasion.
He had set out to persuade Pope Clement IV of the need to reform
the study of Languages and of Nature in the Universities of the Latin
West. Bacon saw the study of these Languages and Sciences as a
moral task. They were not just value-neutral activities. In the end,
they would help the human being to find salvation, but in themselves
they were human pursuits which were absolutely necessary for a better
human life.
Through the Opus maius, Bacon constantly reminds the reader that
his discussions of language, truth, mathematics and perspective are
guided by and toward moral reflection. The truths which are estab­
lished in these domains become principles for use in scientia experimentalis
and in moralis phibsophia. Scientia experimentalis, which must be taken as
a model for a natural science and as a phenomenology of experi­
ence, is the penultimate science, while moral science is the queen of
the sciences. Bacon, therefore, subordinates all the sciences of lan­
guage and nature and till parts of philosophy to moral science. This
reductio artium ad moralem has close parallels with Bonaventure’s Reductio
artium ad theologiam, so much so that Bacon admits that in his view
theology simply thinks about the above sciences in the light of the
teaching of Christ.1

Bacon on the Structure of Moral Philosophy

What in Bacon’s view, is the object of moral thought? With what


does moral philosophy deal? The answer to these questions is stated
clearly by Bacon. “This science is preeminently active, that is, operative,

Moralis philosophia, ed. Massa, 4.


406 JEREMIAH HACKETT EPILOGUE! ROGER BACON’S MORAL SCIENCE 407

and deals with our actions in this life and the other life.”2 Thus, who know about medicine but who cannot practice it, there are those
moral science is concerned with human actions. But a human being who know about the works of human action (operabilia) but who are
performs many different kinds of action, and many of the linguistic unable to practice them. Part One deals with the object and method
and natural sciences are concerned with human actions. Bacon qualifies of Moral science, the outline of a philosophical anthropology based
this and states that although certain sciences are active and opera­ on texts from the Platonists, Aristotelians and Stoics to argue for a
tive, they are concerned “. . . with artificial and natural works which basically Augustinian view of human being. Part two is an oudine of
refer to the speculative intellect, and they are not concerned with social order taken from Avicenna. It is very brief.
those things which refer to the practical intellect, which latter is called Part three, the largest section in the book is concerned with Virtue
practical because it exercises the operation of good and evil.”3 Human and Vice and it is written deliberately as a moral handbook for the
actions in the morally strict sense of the word have to do with good Prince and the Prelate. For the most part this section is taken verba­
and evil, and in this sense they are moral or immoral. Thus the tim from the letters and works of Seneca, which has recently come
term “practical” must be taken in a restricted sense as having to do to Bacon’s attention (i.e. ca. 1266). In this case, advising the Pope in
with actions of conduct which are good or evil. If the term “practical” Italy about the existence of Seneca’s Dialogues was like taking coals to
is taken is a broad sense, it can mean any of the practical sciences. Newcastle. While the Dialogues had remained unknown north of the
But in moral science the term “practical” is used autonomastically Alps until 1266, the had been well known in the Italy for some time.6
on account of the principal actions or operations of man which are This moral handbook with Bacon’s glosses are very important in that
concerned with virtues and vices, and with felicity and misery in the it accentuates stoic themes in Bacon’s moral philosophy. When one
other life. compares Aquinas and Bacon on the passions, one notices the differ­
Later in the Moralis philosophia, Bacon notes that the operabilia are ence. The former for the most part uses Aristotle’s Rhetoric in his analy­
“. .. more difficult to know than the objects of speculative knowl­ sis of the passions; the latter uses Seneca’s De ira and related works.7
edge.” Further, the corruption of the human will and our irascible Parts four to six have to do with moral persuasion. We have treated
nature makes it difficult to perform the works of human action this topic above in the chapter on Rhetoric and Poetics. Yet an issue
(operabilia). What then are the main operabilia for Bacon? They are arises in regard to Part IV (Persuasion and Proof about authentic
“. . . the highest truths concerning God and divine worship, eternal Religion) which has very close connections with Opus maius part IV,
life, the laws of justice, the glory of peace and the sublimity of the and which raises serious issues for Bacon’s whole program of a moral
virtues.”4 In Bacon’s view, the human being suffers a blindness in science. Further, this matter is tied in closely with his scientia experi­
moral matters. This list of topics roughly covers the first three parts mental, third prerogative and with Bacon’s advice for the Prince in
of the Moralis philosophia. his Secretum secretorum. Early in Moralis philosophia, Bacon remarks:
Moral Science for Bacon falls into two parts. The first dealing
A nd so if I cite authorities from places o th er th a n those w hich are
with the speculative side of moral issues has to do with speculative
co n tain ed in books o f m orals, it should be considered th a t these ought
truth about life and morality. The second part deals with the prac­ to be placed ap p ro p riately in this science. N o r can we d en y th a t those
tical side of moral life, that is with the process of moral persuasion.
“The practical half [of moral philosophy] is related to the first half
6 See L.D. Reynolds, “The Medieval Tradition of Seneca’s Dialogues," The Classical
as the curing of the sick and the conserving of health, which are Quarterly (New Series), Vol. XVIII, 2, (1968), 355—72. See p. 363, John of Garland
treated in practical medicine, are related to that part of medicine knew about the Dialogues yet the manuscript of this work is associated with three
which teaches what health is___ ”5 And just as there are doctors Franciscans in Paris in the 1260—70’s, Roger Bacon, Guibert of Toumai and John
of Wales. Bacon’s discovery of this work was significant for north of the Alps.
7 Jeremiah Hackett, “Roger Bacon on Magnanimity and Virtue,” in B. Carlos
2 Ibid., 3. Bazan, Eduardo Andujar and Leonard G. Sbrocchi, eds. Moral and Political Philoso­
3 Ibid., 3 phies in the Middle Ages, Vol. I, Ottawa, 1995, 367-77; see also Danielle Crivelli,
4 Ibid., 3. “Iiberta et interiorita: Seneca, una fonte per la Filosofia Morale di Ruggero Bacone,”
5 Ibid., 248. Ibid., Vol. II, 837-843.
408 JEREMIAH HACKETT EPILOGUE.' ROGER BACON’S MORAL SCIENCE 409

things are w ritten in the books o f this science, since in L atin we only other tradition of “applied science” which flourished in Court Life
have the philosophy o f A ristotle, A vicenna a n d A verroes in parts, an d and in the Italian Universities and which spread from there.
they are the principle authorities in m atters o f this kind.8

What is Bacon attempting to do? Since Part IV of Moralis philosophia Elsewhere I have argued that much of the difference between Bona-
is an astrological theory of the rise and fall of human civilizations venture and Bacon had to do with Bacon’s application of mathematics
or as he calls them “Sectae”. This part draws heavily on al-Farabi, {astrobgia) to the prediction of human behavioral trends. Further, Bacon
but also on Abu Ma'shar. One can see that Bacon is making appli­ develops his own doctrine of magnanimity which in its main aspects
cation here of his theory of Astrological influence which he develops are orientated toward the Prince and Prelate. As I have noted else­
in Opus maius, part four and which he offers the Prince in his edition where, Bacon’s doctrine of magnanimity owes more to Aristotle than
of the Secretum secretorum. And here again, one notices the great influence to St Bernard. Further, his decided preference of Seneca over Aristotle
of Abu Ma'shar in his Introductorium maius and in his De magnis coni- on the issue of Anger {De ira) put him in opposition to Aquinas in
unctionibus. This may not be a problem for either Albertus Magnus this matter.
or Roger Bacon who viewed Abu M a'shar as the auctor in astronomiam
but it certainly was not acceptable to the younger theologians in Here, I wish to argue that with Bacon we get a presentiment of
Paris. I wish to suggest that Bacon’s strong commitment to Seneca’s Machiavelli before his time. As we saw above concerning the appli­
theory of the emotions {De ira) and his reliance on Abu Ma'shar cation of the scientia experimentalis, the governor or the general must
seemed to push him, in the eyes of his critics, in the direction of a be willing to use either persuasion or force. In other words, an ethics
universal determinism, even if that was not his own explicit intention. of Virtue sits uncomfortly side by side with an ethic of Virtu in Bacon’s
This issue did not die with Roger Bacon. These very texts of Bacon moral writings. Further, this Machiavellian ethic is too closely tied to
on the application of judicial astrology to human destiny are found a necessitarian world to sit comfortably with a doctrine of free-will
again at the beginning of the 14th century in John of Paris’ De and an explicit Christian doctrine of the love of God and Neighbor.
probationeJidei.9 And the invocation of the name “Machiavelli” is no accident. Any
careful reading of The Prince will have to acknowledge that the great
More importantly, for medieval moral theory, we see here the emer­ Italian student of politics draws heavily on the textbook for Princes,
gence of a trend which will manifest itself in French, and Italian the Secretum secretorum, whose first Editor in the Latin West was Roger
Court life and culture in the early 14th century and later. That is, Bacon.11
in the context of court life, the Astrologos plays the role of psycholo­ In conclusion, one should note that throughout the Opus maius and
gist, sociologist and moralist.10 And this kind o f moral prediction is in the Moralis phibsophia in particular Bacon relates language and
very different from the moral science of the university Arts faculty. physics to morals in a teleological manner. And in all of the work he
In the latter, the text of Aristotle’s Mcomachean Ethics is primary, al­ presents his synthesis of Platonic, Aristotelian and Stoic teaching. It
though it will be supplemented by Seneca, Cicero and St Augustine. is not that of Thomas Aquinas or Bonaventure nor is it that of the
Thus, we can speak of two separate traditions of moral inquiry in young Arts Masters at the University of Paris, but it is closely related
the Late Middle Ages. There is the concern with the theory of Ethics to their concerns and must be understood in that context. And in its
in the Commentaries on the Nicomachean Ethics and there is the emphasis on Platonic and Stoic themes, it shows that the latter tra­
ditions were not forgotten in the philosophy of the 13th century.

8 Moralis philosophia, 5.
9 I am preparing a critical edition of this text.
10 See Graziella Federici Vescovini and Francesco Barocelli, eds., Filosofia, scienza
e astrologia nel Trecento europeo: Biagio Pelacani Parmense, (II Poligrfo: Centro Studi di 11 Jeremiah Hackett, “Machiavellianism before Machiavelli,” paper, University of
Civilta Del Medioevo E Del Rinascimento “Biagio Pelacani Parmense”), 1992. South Carolina, Renaissance Colloquium, 1994.
INDICES
INDEX MANUSCRIPTORUM

Amiens, Bibl. Mun. 406: 21, 105


Barcelona, Archivo di Corona de
Aragon, Ripoll 109: 69, 134
Cambridge, Univ. Lib. Ii III.3, 185n,
189
Erfurt,
London, British Library, Sloane
2156: 152
Manchester, John Rylands Library,
Lat. 65: 319n
Bibl. Amplon. F 135: 105
Bibl. Amplon. Q, 328: 104
Oxford, Bodleian Library,
Digby 55: 100
Digby 67: 105
Digby 76: 152
Digby 204: 104, 109
Corpus Christi Coll. 41: 162n
Laud. Misc. d. 37: 153n
Tanner 116: 366n, 382
Paris,
Bibliotheque de l’Arsenal, 2344: 328n
3009: 328n
Bibhotheque National: 16198: 207n
Vatican, Biblioteca Apostolica
Vaticana,
Vat. Lat. 2227: 153n
Vat. Lat. 5004: 153n
Vat. Reg. Lat. 1317: 317n, 321n,
322n, 328
Vat. Urb. Lat. 186: 298n
INDEX NOMINUM (I) 415

362, 365, 368, 370, 373-74, 376, Bernard of Trier: 334


376n, 377-80, 382-90, 403, 407-08 Biagio Pelacani da Parma: 135n, 408
Amald of Villanova: 334, 345n, 358n, Boethius: 47, 53n, 54n, 55n, 91-92,
INDEX NOM INUM (I) 363 95, 127n, 136, 136n, 155, 155n,
Artemidorus: 302 157, 164, 339
(Ancient, Medieval and Early Modern) Boethius of Dacia (Boece de Dacie):
Artephius: 377n, 328, 328n, 370
Arzachel: 175n 114, 122n, 155
Augustine: 81, 89, 91, 92, 94, 95n, Bohun, Mary, Countess of Richmond:
98n, 101, lOln, 117, 124, 124n, 354
Abelard: 95, 95n Alexander of Hales: 16, 27, 27n, 28,
125, 126, 139, 139n, 140n, 14 In, Bonaventure: 17, 40, 40n, 47, 93, 93n,
Abishag: 353n 32, 35, 49, 51, 52, 52n
142, 143n, 144, 144n, 145n, 147, 94, 141, 176, 187, 187n, 191-94,
Abraham: 154, 193n, 377n Alexander of Tralles: 339n
176, 176n, 178n, 179-80, 182-83, 197, 294n, 375, 375n, 400, 405,
Abugafarus: 46n Alexander the Great: 155, 308, 310,
191-92, 196, 203, 223-31, 233-38, 409
Abu J a ’far Ahmad ibn Yusuf (See 342-43, 351, 355, 365, 379, 379n, Bonaventure de Iseo: 36, 40n, 41
Pseudo-Hali and Pseudo-Ptolemy) 261-62, 293, 294n, 346, 347n,
383, 387-89 Bradwardine, Thomas: 157n, 167,
Abu Ma'shar (Albumazar): be, 30, 32, 349n, 350n, 371, 391, 408
Alfonso X (See King Alfonso X) 167n, 173-4
38, 44, 47, 142, 175n, 185, 188, Averroes (Ibn Roschd): 18, 30, 42, 47,
Alfred of Sareshel (Alvredus Anglicus): 55n, 60, 60n, 70, 70n, 96, 101, Brito, William: 87
188n, 192-7, 288-89, 293, 371, 408 44n, 84n, 213
lOln, 111, 135, 136n, 140, 140n, Brunetto Latini: 213, 215
Adam: 80, 155, 184, 347-48, 386 Alhacen; Al-Hasan; Al-Hazen (See Ibn
141, 141n, 142, 145, 193, 228, 244, Bulaeus (Boulay): 3 In
Adam of Buckfield: 396 al-Haytham)
264, 288, 298, 298n, 326n, 377n, Bungay, Friar: ix
Adelard of Bath: 38, 44, 155, 155n, Alphonse of Poitiers: 386 Burleigh (Walter): 12In, 122n
156, 158, 168n, 169, 172, 174, 177, 378n
Alphonsine (Tables): 209
177n, 213, 261 Avicebron (Solomon Ibn Gebirol):
Alvredus Anglicus (See Alfred of Caelius Aurelaianus: 339n
Aethicus Ister (Ethicus): 200 244-45
Sareshel) Caesarius of Hesterbach: 27n
Al-Battani (Al-bategni): 38n, 175, 216 Avicenna (Ibn Sina): 7, 18, 32, 44, 47,
Ammonius: 127n Caliph Al-Ma5mun: 216
Al-Betrugi: 285 60, 72, 78, 80n, 82, lOln, 111, 129,
Anaritius (al-Nayrizi): 156 Cassiodorus: 54, 101, 179, 180, 204,
Al-Farabi: 56, 79, 79n, 80n, 101, 135, 136, 136n, 140, 145,146n,
Anonymous (Dist. Par. “Not.”): 105n 154, 170, 175n, 181n, 185, 188, 227n, 230-31, 340
lOln, 135, 136n, 137, 140, 140n, Appolonius: 156
188n, 190, 193, 196-7, 201, 244, Cassius Felix: 339n
141, 141n, 142, 145, 147, 156, 164, Aquila: 50n
256, 264, 294n, 298, 298n, 304-5, Cato: 338-39
194, 227n, 228, 341, 408 Aquinas, Thomas: 18n, 22n, 46,
318n, 320-22, 329, 335-36, 342, Celsus: 339, 339n
Al-Fraganus: 175n, 201, 207 118n, 127n, 137, 137n, 141, 176,
342n, 347, 350-51, 357n, 358, 371, Cennini, Cennino: 305
Al-Ghazalf (Algazel): 80n, lOln, 129, 179n, 183n, 187, 187n, 188n, 189n,
385, 386, 407 Censorinus: 227n, 233
135, 136n, 140, 145, 284n 191-93, 195, 195n, 196, 196n, 197, Chalcidius: 47
Al-Khwarazmi: 209, 216, 261 297, 297n, 309, 396, 398, 400, 409 Bacon, Francis (Baron Verulam): 277, Chaldeans: 75
Al-Kindl: 59, 78, 216, 243-46, Archimides: 156, 156n, 172
277n, 279, 28In, 309n, 314, 314n, Chanticleer: 354
261-62, 268, 273-74, 285n, 290n, Archytas: 155 Chaucer, Geoffrey: 354, 362, 363
353, 371 315, 336, 400
Aristotle: 14, 25, 26, 28, 28n, 31, 32, Christ (Christus): 141, 143n, 349n,
Al-Majusi (see Haly Abbas): 285, 341, Bacon, Nicholas: 15n
33, 36, 38, 39, 39n, 43, 43n, 45, 362, 405
347, 358 Bacon, Peter: 15n
45n, 46, 47, 50n, 55n, 57, 58, 59, Cicero: 118, 137, 137n, 139, 144,
Al-Razi (see Pseudo-Razi) Bacon, Robert (OP): 104
60, 60n, 61, 69, 81, 83, 84n, 89, 144n, 145, 146, 147, 192, 408
Alanus de Insulis: 32, 46n, 136, 136n Bacon, Roger: 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7,
90, 90n, 91, 92, 96, 99, 99n, 101, Claudius: 208
Alberti: 305 8, 9-23, 25-47, 49-65, 67-102,
lOln, 102, 105, 111-113, 118, 125, 103-132, 133-49, 151-74, 175-98, Clavius, Christopher: 170
Albertus Magnus (Albert the Great): 127, 128, 131, 134, 134n, 135,
199-222, 223-241, 243-275, Cokkys, John (see Johannis de
12, 13, 30n, 36, 38, 40, 40n, 41, 136n, 137, 137n, 138, 138n, 139,
277-315, 317-336, 337-364, Gallicantu): 356-57
41n, 45, 46, 47, 49, 51, 52, 80n, 140, 140n, 144, 144n, 147, 147n, Columbus, Christopher: 6, 205-7, 220
141, 170, 170n, 173, 175n, 176, 365-93, 395-403, 405-409
148, 148n, 149, 153-56, 163-65, Constantine the African: 244, 256, 341
179n, 184, 187, 187n, 188n, 189n, Bacon, Thomas: 15n
169, 170, 173, 175n, 176, 176n, Cuthbert: 347n
190n, 195, 202, 210-11, 213, 220, Barbour, John: 357
178, 181n, 184, 185, 188, 193-4,
220n, 222, 281, 293n, 295n, 302-3, Bartholomaeus Anglicus: 213, 293n,
200, 205-6, 213, 224-5, 228-9, Da Vinci, Leonardo: 305
315, 332-35, 357n, 362, 374, 374n, 341, 341n
234, 236-7, 244, 261-62, 268, 279, Bartholomew of Messina: lOln, 368 Damascene (John): 196
376n, 377, 390, 398 282-86, 288, 290-92, 294n, 295n, Bede (Venerable): 47, 101, 179, 340, Daniel of Morley: 44, 213
Alcabitius: 30, 47 297, 297n, 298, 298n, 299, 302,
340n, 347n, 363 Dante: 82, 86, 213
Alexander Nequam (Neckham): 213, 302n, 304, 308, 311, 31 In, 318n, De C oupon, Robert (Cardinal): 28,
214, 341, 34In, 362 Bernard of Clairvaux: 343, 343n,
319n, 323, 323n, 326n, 342-43, 30, 31
Alexander of Aphrodisias: 297, 297n 409
345, 350, 350n, 353, 353n, 354-55,
416 INDICES INDEX NOMINUM (I) 417

De Foulques, Guy le Gros (Cardinal) Giles of Rome (Aegidius Romanus): 256, 258, 261, 264-66, 268, 271, King Henry IV: 354
= (Pope Clement IV: 1265-69): 17, 78n, 82n, 134, 147n, 148, 148n, 27In, 273, 284-86, 288-90, 293, King Henry V: 355
21, 41 191, 197, 374n, 375 294n, 304, 309n, 313 King Henry VI: 356
De Huy, Gerard: 81-82, 90 Giotto: 305-6, 396 Ibn al-Jazzar: 341 King James I: 240
De Longchamp, Raoul: 46n Gratian: 141, 141n, 142n, 177 Ibn Q urrah (See Thabit ibn Qurrah) King Louis IX: 201, 387
De Lounoy: 3 In Grosseteste, Robert (Bishop of Lincoln; Isaac: 45 King Richard II: 354
De Montfort, Aumury: 157, 162 Lincolniensis): 10, 11, 12, 13, Isabella (Queen): 206 Kymer, Gilbert: 355, 355n, 356, 356n
De Nemore, Jordanus: 60n 15, 16, 38, 39, 39n, 40, 44, 49, Isabella of France: 354
De Novara, Master Campanus: 157 55, 64, 65, 75, 87, 100, lOOn, 134, Isidore: 100, 212, 339n, 349 Lambert of Auxerre (de Lagny): 114n,
De Penafort, Raymond: 76 138, 138n, 141, 158, 162, 167, Isidore of Seville: 54, 88, 179, 179n, 399
De Plano Caprini, John: 201 167n, 173, 178, 178n, 181n, 182, 201, 204, 231, 340, 354, 354n Leibniz: 151
De Romans, Humbert: 76 183n, 188n, 193-4, 197, 197n, Leonardo Pisano (Fibonacci): 214
De Vitry, Jacques (Bishop of Acre): 213, 223-25, 232n, 236n, 238n, Jacopo de’ Barbari: 219n Lull, Raymond (See Raymond Lull;
214, 219 243-46, 262, 265n, 274, 281-90, Jacqueline of Hainaut: 355 Ramon Lull)
Dee, John: 218, 314, 314n, 328n, 293n, 294n, 298n, 300, 300n, 304, James of Venice: 55n Lydgate, John: 355, 355n, 362
366n 306, 31 On, 345, 345n, 350n, 375n, Jebb, Samuel: 44, 223, 223n
Descartes, Rene: 20n, 298, 301, 376, 376n, 402 Jerome: 89, 89n, 200-1, 204, 230-31, Machiavelli: 409
314-15, 315n Guibert of Toumai: 390, 407n 399 Macrobius: 47, 339
Digges, Leonard: 218 Gundisallinus (Gundisalvi): 32, 56, 80n, Jerome of Ascoli: 19, 19n Manfred (Translator): 84n
Dioscorides: 339n, 340 lOln, 137 Jesus: 367n Marbode: 371
Dominus Castri Gret or Goet: 366n Joachim: 50n Marcellus of Bordeaux: 339n
Duns Scotus, John: 104, 281, 402 Haly Abbas (see Al-Majusi): 285, 341, Iohannes (Bacon’s pupil): 312, 312n Marco Polo: 207
Durandus de St Porsain: 120n 350 350n Johannis de Gallicantu: 357 Marsh, Robert: 12, 49,
Haly al-Imrani: 47 Johannitius (See Hunayn) Marsh, Adam: 10, 11, 12, 14, 15, 49,
Eden, Richard: 218 Hearn, Thomas, 355n John Dastin: 334 50n, 134, 141, 158, 162
Emperor Frederick II: 33, 33n, 34, 34n Henri d’Andeli: 46n John of Basingstoke: 87 Martianus Capella: 47, 339
Emperor Manfred: 33 Henricus Aristippus: 45 John of Garland: 33n, 35n, 36, 407n Masha’allah (Massahalla): 30, 175,
Esdras: 205 Henry of Ghent (Henri de Gand): 98, John of Paris: 194, 408 188
Ethicus (Aethicus Ister): 200 98n, 104, 117, 124, 124n, 191, 396, John of Rupella: 16 Master Campanus of Novara
Euclid: 55n, 155, 155n, 156, 156n, 402 John of Rupescissa (Jean de (Compana da Novara): 157, 160-1,
158, 160, 163-6, 168-70, 172, 174, Hermann of Carinthia: 32, 33, 38, 38n Roquetaillade): 334, 334n, 335-36 166n, 167, 168n, 172-4, 175n, 214
243, 261-62, 266, 268, 273-74, 284, Hermannus Alemannus: 4, 12, 38, John of Salisbury: 337, 343-44, 344n Master John Bandoun: 158
291 84n, lOln, 135, 136n, 138, 138n, John of Seville: 30, 32, 38, 365 Master John of London: 157-9
Eudoxus of Cnidus: 160, 160n, 166, 140n, 148 John of Tinemue (Johannes de Master Nicholas: 157, 162
166n, 173 Hermes: 184 Tinemue): 156, 158 Master Peter of Maricourt (see Petrus
Eusebius: 219 Hermes Trismegistus: 337 John Trevisa: 341, 363 Peregrinus de Maharii curia): 157-9
Hermogenes: 374 John of Tynemouth (See Master John Matthew of Orleans: 105
Ferdinand (King): 206 Hervaeus Sophista: 105 of London): 158n, 162n, 173 Matthew Paris: 13, 13n, 214, 238
Fibonacci, Leonardo: 214—15 Heylyn, Peter: 203n John of Wales: 390, 407n Maurolico: 20n, 274
Ficino, Marsilio: 305, 397 Hilgart von Humheim: 393 Jordanus (de Nemore): 157, 161n, 172 Meinong, Alexius: 400
Fishacre, Richard: 93, 93n, 97 Hippocrates: 340, 342, 352n, 363 Josaphat: 204 Melton, Geoffrey: 354
Fra Paolino Veneto: 219 Hobbes, Thomas: 148n Josephus: 154—55, 230, 370, 370n Merlin: 50n
Hoccleve, Thomas: 354, 355n Moerbecke, William of: 4
Galen: 244, 261, 320n, 326n, 340, Horace: 136n, 139, 145, 148 Kant, I.: 29In Moses: 50n
340n, 342, 358 Hugh of Sanctalla: 46n Kepler, Johannes: 20n, 59, 265, 274,
Galileo: 151, 371n, 391n Hugh of St Cher (Cardinal): 391 290n Newton, Isaac: 167n, 174, 298, 301
Geminus: 175n, 190, 207n, 307-8 Hugh of St Victor: 54n, 343, 343n, 371 Kilwardby, Robert: 4, 56, 57, 62, 63, Nicholas Graecus (See Master Nicholas):
Gerard de Huy: 81-82, 90 Hugutio: 86 65, 68-70, 69n, 73, 91, 92, 94, 96, 162
Gerard of Abbeville: 16, 19n Humboldt: 206 103, 103n, 110, 113, 113n, 133n, Nicholas of Cornwall: 122n
Gerard of Cremona: 38, 45-46, 46n, Humphrey (Humfrey), Duke of 183, 183n, 234n, 237, 397 Nicholas of Cusa: 309n
84n, 156, 161, 313n Gloucester: 355, 355n King Alfonso X of Castille: 209 Nicholas of Damascus (Nicole de
Gerber (See Pseudo-Gerber) Hunayn ibn Ishaq: 256, 261, 357 King Charles: 84n Damas): 111
Gilbert, William: 314, 314n King David: 353n Nicholas of Paris: 104n
Gilbertus Anglicus: 342n, 343n, 359n, Ibn al-Haytham (Alhacen): 20n, 60, King Edward I: 380 Noah: 154, 219
360n, 362 62, 156, 170-71, 244, 244n, 251, King Henry III: 214, 380 Norton, Thomas: 356, 356n, 363
418 INDICES INDEX NOMINUM (I) 419

Ockham (See William of Ockham) Pope Gregory X: 41n Roebruck, William (See William of Theodoric of Freiberg: 298, 300
Oresme, Nicholas: 167, 167n, 174 Pope Innocent IV: 33, 34, 35, 36, 36n Roebruck) Theodosius: 156
Oribasius: 339n Pope John XXI (see Peter of Spain) Roger of Herford: 44 Thomas of Wales: 12, 49
Origen: 231, 23In Pope Nicholas III: 19n Tideus: 261-62, 274
Orosius: 201, 204 Porphyry: 120, 210 Sacrobosco: 213, 299 Toscanelli: 206
Ovid: 145 Possidonius: 302 Sallust: 200
Priscian: 68, 86, 87, 99, 116 Scot, Michael: 28, 28n, 33, 34, 36, 84n Van Helmont: 346n
Papias: 86 Proclus: 164-5 Scotus (See Duns Scotus, John) Varro: 339n
Paris, Matthew: 87 Pseudo-Aristode (De mundo): 162 Seneca: 7, 47, 139, 205, 285, 297, Vincent of Beauvais: 201
Pecham, John: 6, 20n, 192, 194, 194n, Pseudo-Aristode (De veg.): 43 302, 302n, 303n, 406-09 Vitruvius: 156
274, 243-75, 375 Pseudo-Aristode (Sec. sec.): 44, 285, 308, Sennert: 346n
Pertelote: 354 329-31, 361, 363, 365-393, 403 Seth: 154 Wallis, John: 151
Peter Camestor: 52, 177 Pseudo-Avicenna: (De anima): 321—22, Sextus Empiricus: 126n William Bonecour: 17
Peter Helias (Petrus Helias): 96n 324, 330, 330n, 331-32 Sibyl: 50n William Brito: 31
Peter Lombard: 52, 93, 94, 177 Pseudo-Dionysius: 147, 244 Siger of Brabant (Siger de Brabant): William of Auvergne: 15, 32, 36, 281,
Peter of Blois: 343, 343n Pseudo-Euclid: 274 114, 114n, 141, 297, 297n, 377n 366
Peter of Candia: 388n Pseudo-Gerber: 317n, 332, 332n, Siger of Courtrai: 70n William of Auxerre: 35
Peter of Cornwall: 122n, 123n 333-36 Silvestri, Ser Dominico: 349n William of Beauvais: 35
Peter of Ireland (Pierre d ’Hibemie): 127n Pseudo-Ovid (De vet.): 44, 193-4 Simon de Montfort: 17 William of Conches: 86, 261
Peter of Limoges: 180 Pseudo-Ptolemy (Centiloquium): see next Simon of Authie (de Aletis): 35 William Lupus: 12, 49
Peter of Spain; Petrus Hispanus (Pope entry Simon of Faversham: 123n William of Moerbecke: 38, 10In,
John XXI): 14, 110, 11 On, 281 Pseudo-Ptolemy (De disp. Sph.): 193, Simon of St Quentin: 201 137, 137n, 149, 297, 297n, 313,
Peter John Olivi (Pierre Jean Olieu): 205, 285, 285n, 288, 292-3, 307 Simplicius: 118n, 156 391
98, 98n, 104, 402 Pseudo-Ptolemy (=Pseudo-Hali) Socrates: 130 William of Ockham: 23, 12In, 28In,
Petrarch: 349 -A b u J a ’far Ahmad ibn Yusuf Solinus: 370 302n, 396, 402
Petrus Auerol (Peter Aureol): 302n (Comm, on Centiloquium): ix, 42, 44, Solomon: 154, 184, 184n William of Rubruck (Roebruck): 201-2
Petrus Heliae: 96n 46, 47, 175n, 185, 185n, 188-89, Spinoza: 298 William of Sherwood (Guillaume de
Petrus Peregrinus de Maricourt (Master 190, 196-7, 284, 288, 292-3, 293n Stephen of Provins: 35, 36 Sherwood): 12, 49, 81, 104, 110,
Peter of Maricourt): 157-9, 309n, Pseudo-Razi (Al-Razi): 319, 319n, 322, Suhr-ab: 216 1lOn, 113, 113n, 116n, 141
31 On, 311, 31 In, 311-13, 314n, 322n, 323, 332, 336, 347 Witelo: 6, 20n, 274, 290, 309n
315n, 371 Ptolemy: 55n, 60, 156, 175n, 179, Tempier, Etienne, (Bishop of Paris): Wyke, John: 354
Philip the Chancellor: 4 In, 366 185, 188-90, 196-7, 199, 200, 43, 46, 197n, 373
Philip of Greve: 35 205-7, 209, 215-17, 220, 231, 243, Thabit ben Qurra: 161, 161n, 172, 216 Zael (Sahl ben Bishar): 30
Philip of Tripoli: 7, 365, 375, 388n 261-63, 266, 268, 273-74, 278, Themestius: 389 Zarkala: 209
Philo of Byzantium: 156 284—5, 288-89, 293, 370
Pierre d’Ailly (Cardinal Petrus Pythagoras: 155
Alliacus): 206, 217-18
Pierre d ’Hibemie (see Peter of Ireland) Queen Ethelthryth: 34 7n
Plato: 127n, 130, 176, 178, 243, 261,
291n Radulphus Brito: 123
Plato of Trivoli: 38, 38n Raymond Lull (Ramon Lull): 77, 214
Pliny: 47, 200, 208, 272, 285, 337-40, Raymond of Laon: 17
342, 342n, 347, 349, 35In, 352n, Richard Fishacre: 93, 93n, 97
358, 358n, 359n, 361-62, 370 Richard of Clive: 123n
Plotinus: 245, 274 Richard of Foumival: 16, 44, 315
Pope Boniface VIII: 348n, 401 Richard of St Victor: 177
Pope Celestine V: 400-01 Richard Rufus of Cornwall: 15n, 49,
Pope Clement IV (See also De 121, 121n, 123, 141, 191
Foulques, Guy-Card.): 17, 19, 21, Rigord: 27n, 31
42, 45, 46, 177, 199, 218, 372, Risner, Fredrich: 27In, 273
375n, 405 Robert of Chester: 38, 44, 156, 156n,
Pope Gregory IV: 33 172
Pope Gregory IX: 33, 34, 35, 36, 36n Robert Greene: 1
INDEX NOMINUM (II) 421

Carton, Roul, 2, 280, 280n, 282, 284 De Stefano, Antonio, 33n-34n


Castelli, Patrizia, 135n De Wulf, Maurice, 37In
Catto, J.I., 134n, 345n, 362, 399 Delorme, Ferdinand M. OFM, 2, 19,
INDEX NOMINUM (II) Charles, Emile, 1 98n, 226n, 380n
(Modem) Chatelain, A., 29, 372 Demaitre, L., 397
Chibnall, Maijorie, 338n, 362 Denifle, H., 29n, 372n
Clagett, Marshall, 2, 156n, 157n, 172, Dod, Bernard G., 292n
274 Dorey, T.A., 338n
Ableson, Paul, 339n Bogges, Wilham F., 136 Clark, John R., 397 Druart, Therese-Anne, 285n
Agrimi, Jole, 349n, 361, 396 Borgnet, Auguste, 333 Clarke, M.L., 339n Duhem, Pierre, 2, 20, 199, 280, 280n,
Al-Amrani, D., 90n Bos, E.P., 113n, 397 Clementi, A., 400 282, 283, 299n, 367n, 368n, 370n,
Al-Hassan, Ahmad Y., 185n Bottin, Francesco, 375n, 395, 397 Colish, Marcia, 19In 376n, 380n, 383n, 388n, 389n, 390n
Alessio, F., 3, 8, 20, 366n, 367n, 395, Bourgain, P., 8 In, 397 Colnort-Boldet, Suzanne, 397 Duncan, Edgar H., 356n, 362
396 Bourke, Vernon J., 195n Contamine, Genevieve, 397 Durand, Dana Bennett, 221
Alford, John A., 354n Bouyges, Maurice, 382n Conti, A., 9 In Durant, 33n
Allard, Guy-H., 317n, 335 Boyer, Charles B., 283n, 300, 300n Copenhaver, Brian B., 374n Duval, Yves-Marie, 399
Alonso Alonso, Manuel, 80n Braakhuis, H.A.G., 104, 104n, 113n, Cortesao, Armando, 202n, 218n, 220,
Anawati, Georges C., 335, 396 397 220n, 221 Eamon, William, 3, 366n, 37In
Ancona, Christina D ’, 396 Bradwardine, Thomas, 167 Corwin, Elna, x Easton, Stewart C., 3, 20, 159, 159n,
Andujar, Eduardo, 137n Brams, J., 297n Courtenay, Wilham J., 135n 162n, 172, 282, 282n, 366n, 368n,
Annas, Julia, 285n Braun, Klaus, 298n Cousin, Victor, 1 369, 369n, 370n, 379n, 383n
Arbesman, Ralph, 349n Brehm, Edmund, 317n, 336 Cousins, Ewart C., 294n Eastwood, Bmce C., 288, 288n
Ashton, T.H., 20n, 345n, 362, 399 Brewer, J.S., passim, 1, 37, 52n, 199n, Coxe, H.O., 162n Ebbesen, S., 104n, 122n, 238n, 397,
Ashworth, E. Jennifer, 118, 396 215n, 223, 238, 266n, 335, 368n, Cracken, Henry Noble, 355n 401
Asia Moreu, Diego, 396 369n, 370n, 375n, 376n, 378, 379n, Crisciani, Chiara, 339n, 349n, 362, 397 Eco, Umberto, 93n, 397
Aujac, Germaine, 285n 380n, 388n, 389n, 390n Crivelli, Danielle, 407 Edwards, Paul, 238n
Asztlos, M., 106n Bridges, John H., passim (see Opus Crombie, A.C., vi, ix, 2, 173, 274, Elhs, 277n
maius) 265n, 282, 282n, 283, 290, 290n, Emden, A.B., 15n
Bacon, Francis, 277, 279, 315 Brind’Amour, L., 11On 298n, 371n, 391n Enghsh, Edward D., 187n, 302n,
Baeumker, C., 79n, 245n Brown, E.A.R., 397 Crowley, Theodore, 3, 9, 9n, 10, 14, 376n
Baird, Professor Davis Whitney, x Bruni, G., 148 19, 182n, 187, 187n, 326n, 366n, Evans, T.A.R., 20n, 345n, 362, 399
Barbour, John, 357 Brunning, B., OSA, 176n, 19In 376n
Barnes, Jonathan, 237 Brunschwig, Jacques, 285n Curry, Patrick, 135n Fattori, J.M ., 297n
Barocelh, Francesco, 408 Bullough, Vem L., 355n Federici-Vescovini, G., 135n, 294n,
Baur, Ludwig, 1, 225n, 245n Burger, H., 16In D ’Alvemy, M.T., 78n, 245n 408
Bazan, B. Carlos, 114, 137n Buridant, C., 402 Da Vinci, Leonardo, 305 Feirulo, Stephen C., 343n, 362
Beaujean, Guy, 37In Burke, Robert Belle, 225n, 227n, Dahan, G., 77n, 90n, 145n, 397 Fichtner, Gerhard, 349n, 362
Beckman, J.P., 102n 238n Daiber, H., 134n Finan, Thomas, 176n
Bell, Rudolph, 348n Burnett, Charles B., 20n, 177n Dales, Richard C., 18n, 178n, 192n, Fisher, N.W., 59, 173, 274, 283n
Benjamin, F.S., 160n, 172 Bums, Chester R., 343n 232n, 376n Flasch, Kurt, 374n
Benson, Robert G., 376n Bursill-Hall, G.L., 399 Daniel, E. Randolph, 76n Folkerts, M., 156n, 172-3, 396
Bergdolt, Klaus, 306n, 31 On, 396 Busard, H.L.L., 156n, 161, 16In, Danon-Boileau, L., 107n Forster, Max, 355n, 362
Berger, S., 88n 162n, 172-3, 395 Darrell Jackson, B., 92n Frankowska, Malgorzata, 283n, 367n
Berube, Camille, 375n Bylebyl, Jerom e L., 338n, 362 Davis, H.W.C., 386n Fredborg, K.M., 3, 85n, 86n, 103n,
Bethel, Dennis, ix Bynum, Caroline Walker, 348n, 362 Dawson, Christopher, 37In 117
Bettoni, E., 3, 20 Dawtry, Anne, 340n Freeland, Cynthia, 285n
Biard, Joel, 397 Cameron, M.L., 339n, 362 De La Mare, A.C., 355n French, Roger, 342n, 362
Bieler, Professor (Ludwig), ix Campbell, Sheila, 317n, 336, 338n, De Libera, Alain, 5, 9 In, 103-32, Friedman, Michael, 29In
Bigali, Davide, 50n 340, 362 106n, 107n, 108n, 113n, 114n, Furley, David J., 134
Bignami-Odier, 335 Campbell, Tony, 206n, 214n, 221 120n, 123n, 399-401, 441 Furnivall, Fredrick J., 355n
Bishoff, B., 82n Cantor, Geoffrey, 274 De Lubac, H., 146n
Bjombo, A.A., 161, 172, 274 Capezzali, W., 401 De Muralt, Andre, 302n Gahonier, A., 90n
Black, D.L., 134n Carmody, F J., 161, 161n, 172 De Rijk, L.M., 95n, 105n, 106, llOn, Gasquet, F.A. (Cardinal), 19, 50, 53n,
Bloch, H., 340n Carrier, Joanne, 69n 112n 60n, 200n, 379n, 380n, 389n
422 INDICES INDEX NOMINUM (II) 423

Geohegan, D., 356n, 362 Hudson, Robert P., 359n Mazzini, Innocenzo, 396
Letora Mendoza, Cehna A., 399
Gerson, Lloyd P., 285n Hughes, Barnabas, 398 McCracken, Henry Noble, 355n
Lewry, P.O., 103n, 113n, 122n, 134n,
Getz, Faye, 6, 6 In, 317n, 336-64, Huillard-Breholles, 33n McEvoy, James, 138n, 288n, 31 On,
399
338n, 34In, 354n, 355n, 356n, Humphreys, K.W., 372n 358n, 37In
Liebermann, F., 173
357n, 362, 397, 441 Hunt, R.W., 341n, 362 McVaugh, Michael R., 358n, 359n,
Liebeschutz, Hans, 344n
Geyer, B., 95n Hyman, Professor A., x 345n, 363
Lindberg, David C., ix, 2, 3, 6, 9, 9n,
Gibbs, Hamilton, 393 Meggle, Georg, 399
10, 13, 13n, 54n, 59, 59n, 173,
Gibson, Margaret, 34In, 362 Jacquart, Danielle, 340n Meier, Annalise, 2
243-76, 244n, 245n, 247n, 248n,
Gieben, Servus, OFM. cap., 232n, James, M.R., 158, 159, 173 250n, 252n, 267n, 269n, 283n, Mendelsohn, E., 167
376n, 402 Janni, Pietro, 396 Menjot, D., 400
290n, 300, 300n, 314n, 315n, 319,
Glacken, Clarence J., 202n, 211, 21 In, Jebb, Samuel, 223, 223n 339n, 359n, 363, 395, 400, 441 Mensching, Gunther, 401
222 Joerg, W.L.G., 209n Migne, J.P., 227n
Linden, Stanton J., 3, 317n, 336, 395,
Goering, J., 92n Jolivet, J., 123, 400 Miller, D.C., M.F.A., x, 67n
400
Gonzalez Palencia, A., 80n Jones, Charles W., 340n Minio-Paluello, L., lOOn, 292n
Link-Salinger, Ruth, 140n, 398n
Grabmann, M., 3 In, 35n Jones, W.H.S., 338n, 362 Mobeley, Berry, x
Little, A.G., ix, 2, 6, 10, lOn, 19, 20,
Gracia, Diego, 342n, 353n, 354n, 362 Jourdain, Charles, 10, lOn, 398 Mojsisch, B., 107n
37, 199, 199n, 200, 200n, 222,
Gracia, J.E., 398 Judy, Albert G. O.P., 183n Molland, George, 5, 22, 77n, 151-74,
299n, 33In, 344n, 345n, 347n,
Grant, Edward, 2, 245n, 246n, 274, 349n, 357n-60n, 363, 366n-7n, 156n, 157n, 159n, 160n, 165n,
312n, 400 Kaluza, Z., 123, 400 166n, 167n, 169n, 170n, 17 In,
368n, 370n, 380n, 388n, 389n,
Grignaschi, Mario, 140n, 388n, 392 Karmi, Ghada, 185 390n, 39In, 395 317n, 322n, 325n, 337n, 363, 375,
Kay, Sarah, 343n Livesey, S.J., 173 375n, 376n, 379n, 395, 401, 441
Hackett, Jeremiah, 1-9, 49-66, Kenny, Anthony, 224n Lloyd, G.E.R., 176n, 278, 278n, 310n, Moller, Reinhold, 39In, 393
133-50; 175-98, 277-315, 405-9, Kibre, Pearl, 285n, 335, 343n, 349n, 339n, 340n, 342n, 363 Moreton, Jennifer, 18In, 288n
14n, 16n, 18n, 22n, 4 In, 42n, 64n, 357n, 362 Muller, Paola, 401
Lohr, C.H., 80n, 11 On
67n, 102n, 137n, 140n, 141n, 192n, Kieckhofer, Richard, 295n Mundy, John H., 49, 50, 50n
Long, R. James, 193n
193n, 194n, 197n, 266n, 274, 288n, Kimble, George H.T., 202, 202n, 222 Murdoch, John E., 2, 166n, 168,
Lonie, I.M., 342n
290n, 315n, 366n, 375n, 376n, King, J.E., 347n, 363 168n, 173, 274, 400
Lorcin, Marie-Therese, 400
377n, 395n, 398, 407n, 409n, 441 Klausner, David, 338n, 340 Murphy, James J., 134n, 137n, 148n
Lovitt, William, 278n
Hackett, Margaret T.R., vi Kneepkens, C.H., 68n Murray, Alexander, 37In, 375n
Lusignan, S., 82n, 83n, 85n
Hackett, Thomas J.R ., vi Knorr, Wilbur, 158, 158n, 162n, 173 Mussler, B., 11 On
Hadrianus a Krizovljan, P., 377n Knuttila, Simo, 401 MacDonald, Michael-Albion, 400 Mynors, R.A.B., 340
Hall, Bert, 338n, 340 Koch, Joseph, 78n, 374n Macray, G.D., 81n
Halleux, Robert, 333n, 334n, 336 Kohl, K., 161n Maddicot, John, 17n Namnum, Nizar, 185n
Hamesse, Jacqueline, 164n, 173, 297n Koemer, K., 114n, 399 Makdisi, G., 377n, 393 Nascimento, Carlos Arthur Ribeiro do,
Hammond, E.A., 357n Kraml, Hans, 399 401
Maloney, Thomas S., 3, 7, 10, lOn,
Harley, J.B., 214n, 216n, 221-2 Kretzmann, N., 104, 104n, 107n, 224n 13, 13n, 93n, 11 On, 119n, 122n, Neibyl, Peter H., 346n
Harvey, Paul D.A., 21 On, 222 Kristeller, Professor Paul Oscar, ix, 139n, 395-404, 395n, 441 Nehemias, Alexander, 134n
Haug, Walter, 180 134 Newhauser, Richard, 180n
Manget, J J ., 328n
Hearn, Thomas, 355n Kuhnert, Friedmar, 339n, 363 Newman, William, 7, 317-36, 317n,
Manselh, R., 400
Heath, 277n Kunze, P., 11 On 328n, 332n, 334n, 335n, 336, 366n,
Maranesi, Pietro, 400
Heath, T.L., 172 Kupfer, Joseph, 277n 367n, 37In, 401, 441
Mariani, A., 401
Heidegger, Martin, 278n Manzalaoui, M., 342n, 355n, 363, 380n, Nielsen, L., 3, 103n
Helmholtz, 305 Lafleur, C., 69n, 70n, 79n, 111 Nolan, E., 8 In
382n, 383n, 388n, 392-3, 395-403
Hermenau, Willy, 39In, 392 Laird, W.R., 286n Marcos Casquero, Manuel A., 354n Nordenskiold, Adolf Eric, 214, 214n,
Herren, M.W., 87n Lamb, George, 339n 222
Marietti, 85n
Hime, H.W.L., 317n, 336 Lamberigts, M., 176n North, John, 9, 20, 20n, 175n
Marmo, C., 93n, 104n, 397, 401
Hirsch, S.A., 8 In, 87n, 88n, 344n Lambertini, R., 397 Nuchelmans, G., 96
Marrone, Steven P., 288n
Hoeniger, F. David, 338n Langhade, J., 140n Nutton, Vivian, 354n
Marrou, H.I., 339n, 363
Hogendijk, J.P., 173, 396 Lardet, P., 89n, 399 Marshall, William, x
Hofifeld, Paul, 302n, 303n Lawn, Brian, 339n O ’Donnell, J.R ., 147n
Martene, 33n
Hovdhaugen, E., 85, 398 Leibnitz, 155 O ’Loughlin, Thomas, 176n, 178n,
Martin, J., 92n
Howe, Herbert M., 6, 18In, 199-222, Lejeune, Albert, 274 Martin OSA, Professor F.X., ix 181n, 188n, 191n
441 Lemay, Richard, ix, 4, 25-48, 32n, O ’Meara, Professor (John J.), ix
Martinelli, Bortolo, 349
Huber-Legnani, M., 398 185n, 192n, 289n, 441 Oates, Whitney J., 346n, 347n, 350n
Massa, E., passim, 3, 77n, 10In, 138n,
Hudry, F., 78n, 245n Leonardi, Claudio, 402 Olshki, Leo S., 286n
139n, 143n, 405
424 INDICES INDEX NOMINUM (II) 425

Orlandi, Giovanni, 402 Sarton, George, 282, 282n 200n, 206n, 215, 215n, 280, 280n, Webster, Charles, 356n, 364
Oroz Reta, Jose, 354n Sbrocchi, Leonardo G., 137n 281, 28In, 282, 285n, 295, 299n, Wedel, Theodore Otto, 374n
Owens, Joseph, CSSR, 285n Schlund, E., 312n 334, 334n, 335, 349n, 366n Weinberg, Julius R., 28In
Schmitt, Charles B., 342n, 374n, 382n, Tibbets, Gerard R., 216n, 222 Weisheipl, James A., ix, 2, 13, 14,
Paravicini-Bagliani, A., 22, 22n, 317n, 393 Tilmann, Sister Jean Paul, 210n, 220n, 14n, 17n, 54n, 55, 55n, 56, 173,
336, 347n, 348n, 363, 366n, 393, Schneider, Bemhardus, 136n 222 286n, 293n, 345n, 357n, 364
401-2 Schultz, Juergen, 219n Tonna, Ivo, 403 Weiss, R., 82n, 87n
Parkhurst, Charles, 303, 304, 304n, Scully, Terence, 348n Toomer, G.J., 160n, 172 Welborn, Mary Catherine, 344n, 345n,
305, 305n, 306, 306n, 402 Sears, Elizabeth, 304n, 403 Twomey, Vincent, 176n 353n, 364
Pattison Muir, M.M., 77n, 317n, 336 Selig, Karl-Ludwig, 304n, 402 Tyorinoja, Reijo, 401 Wenin, Christian, 287n
Pearsal, Derek, 355n Serene, E., 287n Whewell, William, 279, 279n
Pelzer, Auguste, 323, 336 Seymour, M.C., 341n, 363 Unguru, Sabetai, 59, 173, 283n, 290n, White, Kevin, 297n
Pereira, Michela, 317n, 345n, 336, 363 Shahar, Shulamith, 343n, 363 308n, 309n, 314n White, Jr., Lynn, 37 In
Picavet, F., 159n, 173, Sharp, D.E., 37In, 383n Upton, Thomas V., 29In Wiedemann, Eilhard, 1, 275
Pinborg, Jan, 3, 70n, 103n, 115n, Sharpe, William D., 354n Urban, William, 403 Wilkinson, Bertie, 148n
12In, 122n, 128n, 224n Sheehan, M.M., 397 Wilhams, Steven J., 7, 20n, 283n,
Pingree, D., 134n, 192n Shenk, R., 93n Valente, L., 77n, 397 365-94, 368n, 372n, 373n, 377n,
Poro, P., 402 Shirley, John W., 338n, 362 Van Bavel, T.J., 176n 380n, 382n, 388n, 403, 441
Porter, Roy, 354n Shorten, William O., ix Van den Eynde, D., 93n Wingate, S.D., 25, 25n, 26, 29, 34,
Powicke, M.R., 148n Singer, C., 370n Van Deussen, Nancy, 5, 223-42, 229n, 34n, 35, 35n, 36, 39, 40n, 47
Singer, Dorothea Waley, 317n, 328n, 236n, 441 Withington, E., 2, 6, 19, 319n, 320n,
Raedts, P., 121 336, 366 Van Engen, John, 187n, 302n, 376n 325n, 344n, 345n, 347n, 349n,
Ragep, F J., 173 Siraisi, Nancy G., 349n, 363, 339n Van Houten, J., 176n 350n-353n
Rand, Edward Kennard, 137n Sirridge, M., 69n, 402 Vance, E., llOn Wolter, Allan B. OFM, 2 In, 232n
Rashdall, H., 3, 225n Skinner, Quentin, 148n, 374n Vandewalle, Charles B., 81n, 379n Woodward, David, 6, 18In, 199-222,
Rather, L J., 343n, 363 Smet, A.J., 297n Veneto, Fra Paolino, 219 214n, 215n, 222, 403, 441
Reckow, Fritz, 229n Smith, David Eugene, 173, 200, 200n Vickers, Brian, 328n Woodward, Ms. Joanna, x
Reichl, K., 99n Smith, A. Mark, 275, 315, 315n Vier, Raimundo, 403 Wright, John K., 209n, 213, 213n,
Reidy, J., 356n, 363 Southern, Sir Richard, 4, lOn, 39n, Vignaux, Paul, 123n 216, 217, 217n, 222
Reta, Jose Oroz, 354n 224n, 350n, 37In Vigueur, J.-C. Marie, 402 Wurms, Friedrich, 38In
Reynolds, L.D., 338n, 407n Speer, Andreas, 401 Vogl, Sebastian, 1, 274—5 Wurschmidt, J., 275
Ricci, Pierre Giorgio, 349n Spedding, Francis, 277n Voigts, Linda E., 34In, 359n
Richter, Dr. Michael, ix Spencer-Amado, Ms. Joan, x Zambelli, Paola, 184n, 189n, 295n,
Ridyard, Susan J., 376n Stabile, G., 402 Wachinger, Burchart, 180n 374n, 377n
Risner, Friedrich, 27In, 273 Stannard, Jerry, 359n, 363 Wallace, Wilham A., 2, 283n, 286n, 298n Zienkiewicz, Ziemislaw, 283n
Rivero, M.L., 107 Stapleton, H.E., 336 Wear A 342 Zimmerman, Albert, 401
Robins, R.H., 115 Steedley Jr., Homer R., x Webb, Clement C.J., 386 Zimmerman, Volker, 339n
Robinson, F.N., 354n, 363 Steele, Robert, Passim, 1, 2, 3, 19, 20,
Rorty, Amelie Oxenberg, 134n 37, 105, 160, 173, 335, 342n, 363,
Rosen, Edward, 2, 275 367n, 368, 369n, 370n, 373n, 38In,
Rosier-Catach, Irene, 5, 67-102, 68n, 391n
72n, 77n, 89n, 92n, 96n, 108n, 124, Stump, Eleanor, 224n
124n, 133n, 140n, 366n, 397, 402, Sylla, Edith, 2, 167n, 173, 174
441
Rossi, Paolo, 283, 283n Tabarroni, A., 397
Rossi, Pietro, 55n Tachau, Katherine M., 302n, 402
Rubin, Miri, 343n Talbot, C.H., 339n, 357n, 363
Ruska, Julius, 319n, 32In, 336 Taylor, E.G.R., 218n, 221, 22In, 222
Ryan, W.F., 342n, 363, 382n, 393 Temkin, Owsei, 340n, 364
Thijssen, J.M .M .H., 173, 402
Sabra, A.I., 289, 289n, 290n, 313n Thompson, David, 349n
Saltet, L., 36n Thomson, S.H., 226n
Sandquiat, T.A., 148n Thorndike, Lynn, 2, 20, 25, 25n, 26,
Sandys, John Edwin, 379n 28, 28n, 29, 29n, 34, 34n, 39, 200,
INDEX RERUM 427

De communibus distinctionibus: 105 De plantis: 370


De conductibus aquarum (Philo of De proprietatibus rerum (Bartholomaeus
Byzantium ?): 156 Anglicus): 341
INDEX RERUM De congelations et conglutinatione lapidum: De quantitate animae (Augustine): 226
111 De quantitatibus datis: 156
De curvis superflciebus Archimedis: 156, De radiis: 245ff
158 De reganin senum (Ps Razi): 347
Abstractions (Hervaeus Sophista): 105 Commentaire sur les Sophistici Elenchi De dialectica (Augustine): 124ff De replentibus locorum: 157
Agriculture: 61, 345 (Kilwardby): 110 De disposition sperae (Introductorius in De retardation accidentium senctutis
Albertus Magnus - auctor: 40-1 Commentary on Centiloquium: 42, 45-7, almagesti; Epitome of Almagest; (= Pseudo-Bacon): 325n, 347n
Alchemy: 62—3; See Roger Bacon - 185, 188-90, 284, 288, 293 Almagestum parvum): 188ff, 205, 207, De scientiis (al-Farabi): 56, 100, 142,
alchemy Commentary on Ecclesiasticus, ch. 43 207n, 285, 285n, 288, 296, 307 145, 156-7, 164
Alexander of Hales (education): 32 (Grosseteste): 31 On De divinis nominibus. 87 De seminibus scripturarum: 76
Almagest: 32, 200 Commentary on Posterior Analytics De division philosophiae: 46 De sensu (Aristode): 244ff
Antidotarium (Bacon): 357 (Grosseteste): 283, 285-7 De doctrina Christiana: 89, 94, 96ff, 101, De sensu et sensato (Bacon): 304—5, 368n
Antiquities (Josephus): 155 Commentary on the Poetics of Aristotle 139, 139n, 142, 147, 179, 191, 198, De signis (Bacon): 80ff, 91, 109, 114,
Amaldi de Villanova Aphorismi de gradibus: (Averroes): 140, 145 225, 315 118ff, 315
358n Commentary on the Rhetoric of Aristotle De erroribus medicorum: 319n ff, 345ff, De situ et nominibus locorum Hebraicorum:
Apocrypha: 201 (Commentaria in rhetoricam Aristotelis) - 349, 357 201
Arab authors: 44 Giles of Rome (Aegidius Romanus), Defato (Albertus Magnus): 187n De solutionbus sophismatum: 105
Arab Science: 33 134, 147-9 De febribus: 45 De speculis (Euclid): 243ff
Arabian Astrology: 32, 37, 47 Communia mathematical 59, 133, 134n, De genesi ad litteram: 225 De speculis comburentibus (Bacon): 250ff,
Arin: 209-10 135-6, 151-73, 175ff, 292 De immortalitate animae (Augustine): 226 313n
Aristotelianism: 26, 30 Compendium medicine (Gilbertus Anglicus): De impressionibus caelestibus: 45 De speculis comburentibus (Ibn
Aristotelian Natural Science: 30, 40, 47 360n De interpretation: 91, 113, 128, 125-6, al-Haytham): 156, 159
Aristotelian Studies: 34 Communia naturalia: 57-61, 63, 175 127n De sphaera (Sacrobosco): 213, 299
Aristotelian works: 30 Communia naturalium: 53, 58-60, 378 De invention'. 137n De sphera (Grosseteste): 288
Aristode’s Philosophy: 25 Compendium studii philosophise: 38, 42, De ira: 407 De substantia orbis: 42
Ars poetica (Horace): 145, 148 74ff, 168, 368n De iride (Grosseteste): 284 De triangulis [Philotegni] (Jordanus): 157
Artis chemicae princeps...: 32In Compendium studii theologiae: 51, 80, 97, De isoperimetris: 157 De tiinitate (Augustine): 225
Arts Curriculum: 29, 36 103-32, 168, 378n, 388n De laudibus mathematicis (Bacon): 152n De vegetabilibus: 43
Astrological Works: 32; See Roger Condemnations of 1210: 29 De lineis, angulis et flguris (Grosseteste): De vetula (Pseudo Ovid): 193-5
Bacon - Astrology-Astronomy Condemnation of books'. 29, 35 235-6 De vulgare eloqtientia: 82
Astrology: 33, 40, 60, 62-5 Conflict at University of Paris'. 25-47 De magnte (William Gilbert): 314 determinism: 47
Astronomy: 60, 62-4 Consolation of Philosophy: 136 De modis signiflcandis: 68 Dialogues (Seneca): 407
Auctores: 40-41 Corrections of the Bible: 90 De multiplication specierum: passim, 247ff Didascalia (al-Farabi): 141
Averroes’ Commentaries: 30, 32 Cosmographia (Aethicus Ister): 200 De multiplicationibus circa orations Dietary (Gilbert Kymer): 355
accidentibus: 105 Discovery of America: 206ff
Bible: 52, 201 Data (Euclid): 156 De mundo (Ps. Aristode): 162 Distinctions notandum: 105
Boethian division of the sciences: 53 De accidentibus senectutis: 347 De musica (Augustine): 223-41 Distinctions sophismatum: 105
Book of roots and elements: 165 De anima (Aristode): 126, 244ff, 294 De natura locorum (Albertus Magnus):
De anima (Pseudo-Avicenna): see Liber de 207, 211 Ecclesiastical commission: 35
Cassiodorean division of the sciences: anima De natura locorum: (Grosseteste): 246n, Ecclesiastical council (Paris): 25-47
54 De anima/Liber sextus de naturalibus 288 Elections: 47
Categories (Aristode): 89 (Avicenna): 188n, 32 Iff De natura rerum (Bede): 340 Elements (Euclid) [Adelard]: 155ff, 160ff,
Catoptrica/De visu/De aspectibus (Euclid): De animalibtis (Avicenna): 78 De natura rerum (Nequam): 341 291
243ff De animalibus (book on Animals): 261 De oculis (Galen/Constantine the Elements (Euclid) [Campanus]: 161-2
Celebrated “secular” teacher: 27 De artibus liberalibus: 64 African): 244 Emperor vs. Papacy: 34
Centiloquium (Liber fructus): 42, 45-7, De aspectibus (Al-Kindi): 243ff De ordin (Augustine): 225ff Encyclopaedic knowledge (13th c.):
185, 188-90, 284, 288, 293 De bello jurgurthino: 200 De ortu scientiarum (Al-Farabi): 56, 79, 213
Ceylon (Sri Lanka): 208 De caelo et mundo: 61, 200 156-7; see Bacon - Classification of the English Franciscan Tradition: 49
Chaucer: works-. 354, 354n De civitate dei (City of God): 176, 225, Scienes Epistola de magnte (Petrus Peregrinus):
Collationes in Hexaemeron (Bonaventure): 346n, 347n De ortu scientiarum (Kilwardby): 56ff, 309n, 314
375 De cometis (Grosseteste): 288 133n, 183, 237 Epistola de secretis operibus artis et naturae
428 INDICES INDEX RERUM 429

et de militate magiae: (De mirabilibus liber de anima (Ps. Avicenna): 32Iff, Mcomachean Ethics: 29, 35, 137n, 137ff, - theoretical-practical alchemy,
potestate artis et mturae): 77, 277n, 324, 330-1 292, 408 318
295, 295n, 328ff, 365ff, 382n Liber de hiis que superius accidunt: 46n Notule M. Johannis de Gallicantu super - Bacon’s Alchemy in Context
Equisses pyrrhonienne: 126n Liber de kata: 161 Johannisium (John Cokkys): 357 - Albertus Magnus, De mineralibus,
Errores philosophorum (Giles of Rome): Liber de morte animae: 184 332-5
78n, 375 Liber de officiis et potestatibus spiritum: Older form of study: 49 - Bibliography, 335-6
Etymologies (Isidore of Seville): 354 184 On the rainbow and halo (Avicenna): 298n - “mercury alone” theory of
Europe in the High Middle Ages Liber de operibus altis: 46n Optica (Euclid): 243ff Amald of Villanova, John
(Mundy): 49-50 Liber de superioribus signis: 46n Optics/De aspecdbus (Ibn al-Haytham): Dastin, Bernard of Trier, 334
European scholars: 29 Liber fantasmatum: 184 171, 244—75, 284, 289-93 - the Summa perfectionis of
Experiential See Roger Bacon Liber mineralium (Albertus Magnus): Optics/Optica/De aspectibus (Ptolemy): “Gerber”, 332-5
Experimental Science: prerogatives - 333 156, 243ff - Alchemy and Generation from
See Roger Bacon Liber moysi: 184 Opus maius: 42, 50, 74ff, 151, 175ff, Elements
Liber novem iudicum: 63 20 Iff, 223ff, 243ff, 277ff, 317ff, - Avicenna’s experiment and
Faculty of Arts: 27, 36 Liber piramidum Apolloni: 156 337ff, 365ff stratification/distillation, 321
Eons vitae (Avicebron): 245 Liber plurimum judicum: 63 Opus minus: 51, 53ff, 15 Iff, 317ff, - dependence on Razi, 319
Frederick II: 33 Liber sex scientiarum (Bacon): 325, 325n 365ff - Pseudo-Avicenna’s Liber de
Friar-scholars, younger generation: 46 Liber sigillis salamonis: 184n (see Liber Opus puerorum: 105 anima, 321
salamonis, 184) Opus tertium: 51, 74ff, 151, 20Iff, 223ff, - “simple and compound
Geography (Ptolemy): 213, 215-7, Liber sufficientia: 188, 190 243ff, 277ff, 317ff, 337ff, 365ff humors”, 319-20
Geometria speculativa (Bacon): 156n, 171, Liber triglossos: 81 Ordinal of Alchemy (Thomas Norton): - Inanimate things, 322
173 Libri Aristotelis et Hermetis: 184 356, 356n - primary contribution on
Greek Grammar (Bacon): 8 Iff, 368n Libri nataturales: 26-47, Oxford: 46 generation, 323
Grosseteste’s Commentary on the Lo composso da navigare: 214 - Razi’s 12 elements, 322
Posterior Analytics (see Commentary . ..) Logic (Al-Ghazali): 145; See Didascalia Pantegni: 341 - three orders of humor,
~ other ways in science: 40; Lumen luminum (Ps. Razi): 319nff Parisian Decrees of 1210/1215: 26, 321-22
Grosseteste’s translations: 39; 28-33 - Medical Alchemy
works in Natural Science, 40 mathematicians, fake: 78; see Roger Perspectiva (= Opus maius, V): passim, - “celestial virtue”, 327
Bacon Classification of the Sciences; 247ff, 286ff - “equal body”, 328, 331
Hebrew Grammar (Bacon): 86 Astronomy-Astrology Philosophia communis: 51 - “equal complexion”, 326-7
Hereford Map: 210 Mendicants and Seculars: 51-2 Philosophia disciplim: 79 - Bacon’s macrobiotic project, 325
Hexaemeron (Grosseteste): 183, 376n Machiavelli: 409 Philosophy and Theology: 53 - medical alchemy, Bacon’s
High Scholasticism: 37 Metaphysical 26-47, 58, 111-2, 118, Philosophy of Aristotle: 52 original contribution, 323-4
Historia ecclesiastica (Bede): 347n 234, 237, '292, 351 Physical 69—70, 169, 285, - “philosopher Artephius”, 328
Historia scholastica: 52 metaphysical basis of light: 59 Physiognomia (Bartholomew of Messina): - Bacon’s Alchemical Practice
Historiarum adversus paganos (De ormesta Meteora (Albertus Magnus): 302-3 368 - Avicenna’s Canon, 329
mundi) [Orosius], 201 Meteora: sententia super (Aquinas): 29 7n Policraticus: 343, 343n - based on the Epistola de secretis
Histories: 52 Meteorologica (Aristotle): 45-6, 111, 188, Posterior analytics: 52, 292, 295n operibus artis et naturae, - making
Holy Land (Bacon’s description): 212 244ff, 285, 297, 311, 322-3, 351, Practical Geometry (Boethius): 155 “The Philosopher’s Egg/
35In, 390 Prior Analytics: 96, 127 Philosopher’s Stone”, 328-330
Introduction: 1-8 Meteorologies (Averroes on): 298n - metallic transmutation and
Introductions a la philosophic: 111 Metaphysics (Bacon): 153, 366, 367n Quadrivium: 62 macrobiotic program, 331-2
Introductorium mavus (Abu M acshar): 44, Michael Scot, Astrologer: 28, 28n, 33, Questions on the First Philosophy of Aristotle - Pseudo-Avicenna and the Secret
193-7, 289 34, 36, 38, 84n (Bacon): 290 of Secrets, 330-1
Invective contra medicorum: 349 Moral Philosophy: 51, 405-9 Questiones Parisiennes de Bacon: 105 - Quicksilver/alchemical elixir, 331
Moralis philosophia (= Opus maius, VII):
Kilwardby’s Commentary: 69 Reform of Education and Society: 49 Roger Bacon - Astronomy-Astrology
9, 20n, lOln, 102, 139, 129n,
Kitab al-athar al-‘ubuviyya: 46n 140n, 143-6, 194, 405-9 (See also Reform of Studies: 49 in relation to scientia experimental,
Kitab fasl al-Maqual (Averroes): 140 Opus maius) Rhetoric: 96, 125, 136n 175-198
Knowledge of Greek and Hebrew: 52 Music’s transcendental role: 64 Rhetoricam ad Herennium: 137n - the applications of mathematics,
Knowledge of Latin: 52 Roger Bacon - Alchemy: 317-336 175
Naturales questiones (Seneca): 200, 205 - Baconian alchemical - Roger Bacon’s Apologia for Judicial
Latin Crusaders: 31 Naturalis historia (Pliny): 200, 338ff, 349, pseudepigrapha, 317 Astronomy/Astrology, 181-87
liber ade: 184 35In, 352n - idiosyncratic nature of Bacon’s - accusation of “infallible”
liber canonis Avicennae: 320ff Navigation: 214 alchemical theories, 317 prediction, 185
INDEX RERUM 431
INDICES

- Authoritative and “True” necessary vs. possible, 190; - demand for adequate Roger Bacon - Grammar: 67-102
mathematicians: Aristode, “true mathematicians who are instrumentation, 218-19 - Aquinas on different locutiones,
Avicenna, Ptolemy, Pseudo- philosophers”, 191; crucial role - influence on Renaissance 85
Ptolemy, Abu Ma'shar, 185 of Augustine, De doctrina savants, John Dee, Richard - Arabic, Hebrew, Greek, 87—8;
- defence against the theologians/ Christiana, 191-2 Eden, Leonard Digges, 218 - causes/rationes of language,
the etymology of the word - Astronomy/astrology and 1277, - influence on Tmago mundi of 68-71
“mathematics”, 182 192 Pierre d’Ailly, 217-18 - comparatist analysis, 85;
- fate, free will and “ordained - Pseudo-Ovid: Source for Bacon’s Geography and Cartography - dependence of Word on the
law of nature and will”, 186 “Aristotle and Astrology”, 193-95 in the Thirteenth Century, “will”, 78
- general or individual predictions - Abu Ma'shar and Grosseteste, 194 213-15 - dependencia, 71
- universal Determinism, - important English geographers - dependency of Latin Wisdom
183-86 Roger Bacon - Bibliography, Update (12th century scholars), 213 on the Wisdom languages, 75
- science/art of nature vs. magic, of “A Roger Bacon Bibliography, - magnetized needle, 214 - Different Types of Languages,
184 1987,” Thomas S. Maloney, - Portolan charts, 214 81-3
- Task of Experimentalist, 187 395-404 - Sacrobosco, 213 - Etymologies, 88-89
- valid and invalid forms of The “Geographia” in the Opus - Augustine and the Artists,
Roger Bacon - Classification of the maius, 199-212 92
experimental science, 187
Sciences, 49-66 - Bacon and Albertus Magnus - Bacon’s implicit dependence
Aquinas and Bacon: response to
- Bacon and the Reform of Studies, on geographical knowledge, on the De doctrina Christiana,
both Abu M a'shar and the
49-53 94
Pseudo-Ptolemaic texts, 195-197 202
- Six errors of theology, 51-3 - basis in earlier writers, 200—01 - categories of sign
Roger Bacon and the
- Spokesman for older - climates and inhabited world, (intermediate status) i.e.
Condemnations of 1277, 197
“Grosseteste Model” of studies, 207-9 interjections, 96
- Augustine, De doctrina Christiana,
49-50 - dependence on William of - Conclusion, 98-102
198
- Bacon and Traditional Rubruck, 201 - Corrections of the Bible, 90
Bacon’s Defence of Judicial
Classification of the Sciences - geographical description, 212 - Faculty of Arts, 90
Astrology, 179-81
- Augustine’s De doctrina Christiana, - geographical “determinism”, - Grammar in relation to
- Numbers and the Patristic
65 Rhetoric, Poetics and Moralis
writers, 179-80 211-12
- Bacon’s advocacy of additional - geographical knowledge in the phihsophia, 100-102
- Utility of Mathematics in
sciences (Communia naturalia), service of Christian Mission, - import of De doctrina Christiana,
Religion, 180-1
57-65 202-04 90
Bacon’s Definition of
- Bacon’s schema, 63 - habitation of world, dimension - Ordo linguarum, 89-90
Astronomia-Astrologia, 179
- the Boethian, Cassiodorean and of ocean, 205-6 - Signs, De signis, Cst, De
Bacon as a follower of
Isidorean division, 53-4 - lack of previous study, 200 interpretations, De doctrina
Grosseteste: 192-3; Use of
- fusion of Boethian and Stoic - mappamundi, 209-211 Christiana, 91-7
Pseudo-Ptolemaic works, 193
divisions, 54—5 - Opus tertium, 200 - Signs and natural
Opus maius, Part I: The Polemic:
- Grosseteste’s De artibus liberalibus, - section of Bacon’s geography consequence, 96-7
176
64-5 known to Christopher - sign in 13th c. Theologians,
- Astrologia and Magic in ancient
- Impact of the Posterior analytics, Columbus through Tmago mundi 92-3
world, 176
54-5 of Pierre d’Ailly, 206-7 - Signs and 13th c. theology
- neglect of both scientific
- Kilwardby’s De ortu scientiarum, - southern hemisphere and De i.e. Henry of Ghent and
astrology and knowledge of
56-7, 62-3 dispositions spherae, 207 Peter John Olivi, 98
Magic by 13th c. theologians,
- New works on the sciences: The Mathematical Model, - the classification of signs, 94
177
Al-Farabi and Gundisallinus, 56 215-17 - the definition of Sign, and De
- Aristotle, astrologia and
- 12th century classifications, - advocacy of “longitude and doctrina Christiana, 92
Augustine, 178, 179-81
54-5 latitude” before Renaissance - the definition of Sign, 13th
Opus maius, Part four: sources for
a Scientia experimentalis, 188-92 Roger Bacon - Geography and discovery of Ptolemy’s Geography, c., 92-93
- Abu Ma'shar, Introductorium 215-16 - the Tractatus de grammatica,
Cartography, 199-222
maius, Ptolemy, Quadripartitum, - aim of chapter, 199 - Tables: Alphonsine “Toledo”, 100
188-9; Pseudo-Ptolemy, 209; Al-Khwarazmi, 216 - exposition of “syntax” using
- Concluding judgment on
Centiloquium, 188-90; - location of birthplaces for Sophisms, 68-9, 73
significance of Roger Bacon’s
Pseudo-Ptolemy (= Geminus) astrological use, 216-17 - figurative constructions, 69
geographical knowledge, 220-21
De dispositions spherae, 188-9; Visualization, 219-220 - grammatical category, 70
- Effects of Bacon’s Geographical
Avicenna, Liber sufficentia, 188-9; Ideas, 217-19 - maps, 219 - grammar and logic, 72
432 INDICES INDEX RERUM 433

- grammar and physical - Utility of language for religious - “commenta” and “summa”, not Roger Bacon - Life, Career and
principles, 71—2 conversion, 76-77 classical (Greek) commentaries, Works: 9—24
- in arte, 71 - Words and multiplication of 30 - Life and Career, 9-21
- Influence of Avicenna and species, 77 - confusion about Metaphysics/ - A Roger Bacon, Clericus de curia
Al-Kindi, 78 Theology/Astrology, 32-33 Regis in Oxford, 1233, 13
- Instruments and methods in Roger Bacon - Latin Translators and - 1229-31: “Parens - Bacon’s edition of the Secretum
Analysis of Languages, 87-90 Translations of the Twelfth and scientiarum”, 33 secretorum, begun in Paris,
- intentionalist analysis of Thirteenth Centuries, 25-48 - expurgation commission of completed at Oxford, c. 1280,
grammarians, 72-4 - issue: condemnation of books 1231, 35-7 20
- Kilwardby’s Commentary, on Aristotelian natural - mediating role of astrological - Bacon’s influence in History of
69-74 philosophy and metaphysics, 26 works, 32 Science, 20-1
- knowledge of languages, 67-8 - Thorndike and Wingate on - Michael Scot, Frederick II, and - Bacon - not a “student in the
- Knowledge of languages useful Bacon’s attitude to Translations, Aristotelian science at the arts” under Grosseteste, 11-12
for Church and Commonwealth, 25 Universities of Bologna and - Bacon in Paris, 1247, 1251,
75-77 - Bacon on Arrival of Aristotelian Paris, 33-35 1256, 15
- Language, substantial unity, Science in Paris - not the commentaries of - Bacon possibly a disciple of
accidental diversity, 83-6 - limitations of Bacon’s account, Avicenna and Averroes; 30-1 Grosseteste a iuventute, 12-13
- Languages of the cross, 81 28 - place and significance of the - Bacon’s “research proposal” to
- Languages of the Laity (vulgar), - the case of Alexander of Hales, Speculum astrorwmiae, 36-7 Pope Clement IV, 10—11
82-3 27-9 - prescriptions of 1210 in effect - Condemnation of Bacon by
- Latin, language of the clergy, - Thorndike and Wingate on the up to 1254, 36 Master General of Franciscan
83 inadequacies of Bacon’s - testimony of William Brito, 31 Order, 19
- literal-spiritual sense; typology, account, 26-9 - the numerous Arabian - contact with Cardinal Guy de
80 - Bacon’s Critique of Translations “introductions” to the science of Foulques (Pope Clement IV),
- many meanings of Grammar 77 and Translators the stars, 30 17
- Missing third section of Opus - Bacon’s plan to rival Albertus - Translations favored by Bacon, - De multiplicatione specierum,
maius, see Opus tertium, 78-9 Magnus as an authority, 41-2 43-7 Compendium studii philosophiae and
- Modists, 86 - Bacon’s scientific method is - “arabic” orientation of Oxford related works, 19
- part three of Opus maius, Cst “Illuminism,” and tied to Aristotelianism, 46 - entrance to Franciscan Order,
and De signis, 80-81 Averroism, 42-3 - Bacon’s “conservative” defence 17
- the “Power” of Words, 77-8 - his neglect of large quantity of of experimental books, 47 - 40 years of experience in study,
- practical goals of language, 68 works translated since early - Bacon and Grosseteste as 11
- practical justification for study 12th Century, 38 continuing English 12th c. - he did “See” the prominent
of languages, 76 - impartiality about Grosseteste’s scholarship, 44 Oxford and Lincoln scholars
- principles of intentionalist translating competence, 39-40 - growth of influence of Avicenna mentioned, 11-12
analysis, 73 - negative attitude, 37-8 and Averroes over Abu - Inception in Arts at University
- proprietas (inch Rythmic, - negative attitude to Albertus Ma'shar and other astrological of Paris, 13-14
Musical), 84 Magnus, 40-41 writers, 47 - influence of De vetula of Ps.
- science o f languages and idioms, 79 - no mention of Grosseteste’s trs. - Isaac De febribus and the De Ovid (Richard of Foumival), 16
- “science of Wisdom languages”, of Mcomachean Ethics, 39-40 impressionibus caelestibus attributed - no agreement on chronology,
74 - role of Speculum astrorwmiae in to Aristotle, 45-6 9-10
- Speculative Grammar, 68-9 lifting ban of 1210, 41 - Parisian aversion to “arabic” - Oxford as first University to
- Student’s Guide, Ms. Ripoll - strictures against Hermann the Aristotelianism, 46 teach Perspectiva, 12-13
109, 69 German and William of - perversitas translations, 43 - personal acquaintance with
- Summa grammatica, 68-74 Moerbecke, misplaced, 38-9 - predominant “astrological” and Adam Marsh, 14
- syllogism, 71 - Parisian Decrees of 1210/1215 “deterministic” character of the - possible meeting with Grosseteste
- The Knowledge of Languages, and the libri naturales, 29-37 Aristotelian science in first wave and Adam Marsh in 1245,
81-90 - Abu M a'shar as the new of translations, 47 15-16
- The Latin’s fantasy auctoritas in scientific astrology, - role of Abu M a'shar’s - possible travel to Oxford and
“etymologies”, 86-7 32 Introductorium maius, Pseudo- Lincoln, 15
- Third Part of the Opus maius, - Bacon correct in view that Ptolemy, Centibquium, Pseudo- - purpose of Papal mandatum and
74-81 Aristotle’s libri naturales texts and Aristotle, Secret of Secrets, the nature of the Opus maius,
- Uses of language in philosophy/ commentaries by Avicenna and Avicenna’s oriental philosophy, the connection with Latin
theology, 78-9 Averroes not available, 32-31 44-5 Averroism, 17-18
434 INDICES INDEX RERUM 435

- teaching at Paris, 1237-47 (?), geometrical analysis to the basic - lois psychologiques et semantiques, - ancient and Latin authors,
14 principles of perspective 266-7 131-2 156-7
- strong mathematical - l’ouvre logique de Bacon, 103 - historican dimension, 154
Bacon’s Works: Brief Introduction, orientation, 266 - magna controversial inter modemos, 114 - mathematicians of Bacon’s
21-3 - The Multiplication of Species, - parallels in Text-books d’Oxford; times
- example of inauthentic 245-50; Robert Kilwardby, 110-111 - John of London/John
medical-alchemical works, 22; - Agents, matter, form, potency, - problemes de predication, 120 Bandoun, 158-9; Peter of
- need for new critical editions of 250-51 - quantification universelle, 106 Maricourt {Petrus Peregrinus),
all the works, 22 - Bacon on radiation of force, - relation to the Parisian Introductions 159; Campanus of Novara,
- requirement of new edition to and Al-Kindi’s universal force, a la philosophic, 111 160—62; Master Nicholas,
match that of William of 246 - scope is that of a Summula super 162; Robert Grosseteste and
Ockham, 23 - First Christian European scholar totam logicam, 110 Adam Marsh, 162
in field: Robert Grosseteste, - scope of work, 106 - restoration of knowledge, 154
Roger Bacon - Light, Vision and the - Introduction, cult of Roger Bacon,
245-6 - Signification, 129—32
Universal Emanation of Force, 151
- medium and contiguity, 249-50 - “Signification par
243-276 - John Wallis letter to Leibniz, on
- Neoplatonic roots, 245 accompagnement” - Avicenna et
- Introduction, Bacon’s significance Roger Bacon, 151
- Plotinus, Al-Kindi, Avicebron, Ghazali, 129
in the history of Perspective - magicians, mathematics
245 - signification/construction, 116
Bacon’s Sources, 243-4 (Mathesis/matesis), 152
- species elicited from potency in - 13th c. Genre of Distinctions
- Light and its propagation
matter (no species passes from sophismatum, 105
- Bacon’s sources, 261 Roger Bacon - Medicine, 337-364
one agent to another), 249 - suppositio, restrictio, 112-13
- Bacon’s use of metaphysical - Bacon and “a properly educated
- the doctrine of Species, 247-50 - Text-books d’Oxford, 104
assumptions (principle of Patriarch” {paterfamilias), 337
- theorie de la determination {composed
uniform action), 257 - Bibliography, 361-3
and divided sense o f proposition),
- extramission/intromission Roger Bacon - logique: 103-132 - Encyclopedic/Natural Historical
114—15
theories, 261-4 - appelatio univoca/reference, Medicine, 338-342
- Theorie du sign et connotation, 124-32
- geometry of the eye, 260 111-112 - Bacon’s sources, 342
- Thomas Aquinas, 127n
- historical significance of Bacon’s - Augustin, De dialectice 124-26 - Bartholomew’s medical sources:
- transumptio/“transfert semantique”, 117
theory and its relationship to - Bacon and Richard Rufus of the Pantegni and the Viaticum,
- une orientation “analytique,” 121
Johannes Kepler, 265 Cornwall, 121-23 341
- un theorie du sens naturel,
- mirrors, images, 253-5 - Bacon’s Summa de sophismatibus et - De natura rerum of Alexander
109-110
- Platonic-Augustinian themes, distinctionibus, 105-09 Nequam; De proprietatibus rerum
- un traite sur les syncategoremes-
264 - Bacon’s Summulae dialectices, of Bartholomaeus Anglicus,
attribution a Roger Bacon, 104—5;
- Reflection/Refracton, 251-56 109-117 341
- Uses of Priscian and grammarians,
- schematic drawing of eye, 257 - contexte extra-linguistique, 108 - De natura rerum of Bede, 340
116
- structure of eye, 256-9 - De interpretation 9, 19a23-24, - folk-medicine, magic, 338
- the geometry of propagation, 113 Roger Bacon - Mathematics, Knowledge - Greek idealization of the young
250-51 - De signis/ Compendium studii theologiae, of, 151-174 Male athlete and Roman
- vision and the eye, 256-65 117-132 - Bacon’s Aristotelian abstractionist attitudes, 339
- The Methodology of Perspective - deux periodes dans la production view of mathematical objects, 170 - knowledge needed by
265-72 logique baconnienne, 103-4 - Bibliography, 172-74 paterfamilias, 338
- a new and (perhaps) modem - inclusio, 106-107 - Clarification and Pedagogy: - Monastic medicine, 340
methodology?, 265-6 - influence of Aristoteles novus on - division of mathematics, 164 - Roman and Late Roman
- Bacon’s achievement, 272-73 Bacon, 111 - mathematics and experience, writers (Pliny, Martianus
- Bibliography on Bacon’s theory - influence of Aristotle, 127-8 162-3 Capella, Macrobius,
of Light and Perspective 273-5 - influence of Stoic theory, 126n - Communia mathematica, 152ff Cassiodorus, 339-40
- experience and Experiment, - intention de signifier du locuteur, - Conclusion: Geometry and common - Medical Scholasticism and its
266-8 107-8 Mathematicals, 169-71 Critics
- Four conclusions on experience - I’analogie, 118-121 - Consequences of Communality - Adam and resurrected body,
and Experiment, 268-72 - P“approche contextuelle” regnant - Communicating numbers, 168 347-9
- function of experience and d’Oxford, 110 - mathematics: the science of - Bacon’s argument for
Experiment: to confirm, refute - La reform bgique du discours, 121-23 quantity, 165-68 “simplicity” in fermentation/
or challenge theoretical claims, - la signification d’une phrase, 109 - proportions and ratios, 166-8 distillation, 350-51
271-2 - la typologie Baconienne des - History and Authorities, 153-62 - Bacon’s Antidotarium, 357
- limits of his extension of the signes, 124-28 - Adelard of Bath on Euclid, 155 - Bacon’s criticism, akin to
436 INDICES INDEX RERUM 437

Bernard of Clairvaux and Peter Language study, Mathematics as over Cicero as auctor in rhetoricam, - threefold division of rhetoric, 145
of Blois John of Salisbury, applied to Natural Science and 137 - true vs. frivolous poetry (Horace
342-3 Moral Science, 405 - Bacon’s debt to Latin tradition, vs. Ovid), 145
- Bacon’s diatribe against the - major influence of Seneca, 407 139 Roger Bacon - Sciences, introduction,
“academic/scholastic” doctors, - Opus mams as a whole: a work in - Bacon’s fusion of Augustine, 1-9
349-50 Moralis philosophia, 405 Al-Farabi and Abu Ma'shar, 142 - brief review of new Bacon
- Bacon’s model: Aristotle as - Two conflicting ethical systems: - Bacon and Giles of Rome, 134, research, 2-4
advisor to Alexander: Secretum Aristotle and the Machiavellian 147-49 - brief review of 19th/20th c.
secretorum, 343-4 Virtu, 408-9 - Bacon’s Opus maius as a rhetorical accounts of Bacon as scientist,
- Bacon’s treatise on persuasio, 139-41
Roger Bacon - Music, 223-242 1-2
quantification in medicine, - Bacon’s rejection of the Trivium, 134
- Aristotle, Kilwardby on music and - presentation of contents of
357-8 - Bacon’s treatise on rhetoric in
gesture, 237 volume, 4—8
- compounding Drugs, 353 logicalibus, 133
- Augustine’s De musica and Roger Bacon - Scientia experimentalis,
- Gilbert Kymer, 355-56 - Bacon’s theory of the relation of
Aristotle’s Metaphysica, 234—5 277-315
- his criticism of ignorance in rhetoric and poetics to Logic,
- Bacon on meter, 234 - Bacon and the issue of an
compounding of mathematics in 135-6;
- Bacon’s presentation of Music in experimental science, 277-9
compounding of drugs, 358-9 - Bacon on the uses of rhetoric and
his Opera as examples of Medieval - Roger Bacon and Francis
- ideas for a Christian medicine, poetics in Moralis philosophia,
Compositional style, 225n Bacon, 277n
345 135-6
- Bacon’s writings as witness to - Argumentum and Experirnentum: Opus
- John Cokkys, 356-7 - Ciceronian rhetoric-Italian City
influence of Augustine’s De musica maius, part six, ch. 1, 290-3
- Influence in Late Medieval Rhetoric, 134—5
(and other works: De immortalitate - Analysis of Aristotelian texts,
England, 354—60 - doctrine of Signs, 148
animae; De quantitate animae), 226 ibid.
- mathematics and medicine, - Hermannus Alemannus translation
- grammar, logic and music, 227-8 - Bacon’s use of Euclid, Prop. 1:
352-3 of the Aristotelian rhetoric, 135,
- Grosseteste and Bacon, 224 A critique of a pure Analytic
- medicine a part of “Scientia 148
- imaginary notions of Bacon’s account of human learning ?,
experimentalis,” 345-7 - Gundissalinus and Al-Farabi,
Teaching, 223
- medicine and philosophical 137 290-1
- importance of Augustine’s De - cognitio per experientiam (Ibn
argument-natural philosophy, - Kinds of argument: Demonstrative,
musica, 223-4 al-Haytham), and priority of
353 Dialectical, rhetorical, 144
- Influence of Augustine’s De ordine, this kind of knowledge over
- medicine as a “second - lateness of translations into
De doctrina Christiana, De trinitate, De argumentum, 292
philosophy,” 354 vernacular, Thomas Hobbes, 148
civitate dei, De genesi ad litteram, 225 - intuition (intuitio) and
- on laxatives and opiates, 359 - Operabilia, 143-4
- Latin Aristotle reinforces and knowledge, 290-1
- regime of health/non-naturals, - persuasion and doctrina, 144—5
extends Augustine, 234ff - Bacon’s Scientia experimentalis: a
354-57 - Philosophia moralis - uses of rhetoric
- mathematics and music, 226, 228, Reconsideration
- “simplicity” concerning “healing and Poetic argument, 142-47
230-32 - epistemological status of both a
power of Plants and Animals,” - Poetics as finis logkae, 138
- mistaken views of Aristotle contra science of the rainbow and a
351-2 - Poetics and Music, 138
Augustine, 224ff Scientia experimentalis in
- astrology and medicine, - rhetoric, poetics and analogical
- music, chronology and time, 235 Grosseteste and Bacon, 285-7
360 predication, 146
- music and language, 239-41 - Sources of Bacon’s science,
- synthesis and sense of wonder - rhetoric, poetics and interpretation
- music and philosophy/theology, 284-5
for Nature, 360-1 of Scripture, 146
238 - Modem interpretations
- the De regimine senum of Razi, - rhetoric and theology:
- music and the Physica of Aristotle, - Whewell, 279; Duhem/Carton,
347 Augustine’s De doctrina Christiana,
236 280; Lynn Thorndike, 280-82;
- The Nature and Scope of Pseudo-Dionysius, Cicero, 147
- music and the Scriptures, 232-3 George Sarton, 282; Easton,
Bacon’s Medical Writings, - rhetoric and utility, 144;
- the utility of geometry, 232 Crombie, more recent authors,
344-60 - Situation at the University of
- ubiquity of music reference in 282-3
- Thomas Norton, 356 Paris c. 1266 - ignorance of new
Bacon, 229 - Roger Bacon and Experiment:
translations of rhetoric and
Roger Bacon - Moral Science, 405-9 - word and physical world, 239 Petrus Peregrinus de Maricourt
poetics, 145
- Bacon on the Structure of Moral Roger Bacon - Rhetoric and Poetics, - the importance of the Mcomachean - Bacon and Petrus Peregrinus
Science, 405-9 133-150 Ethics, 137-8, 144, 148 as a team: Bacon wrote the
- his program for a predictive - Averroes Commentary on the Poetics, - Thomas Aquinas, William of scientific treatise and
sociology of Religions, 408 135, 140, 149 Moerbecke, Giles of Rome and propaganda; Petrus did the
- interrelation and cross-reference of - Bacon’s argument for Aristotle the Rhetoric at Paris, 1270, 147-9 experimental construction of
438 INDICES INDEX RERUM 439

the Burning Mirror, 312-3 - example: color of rainbow, - Secretum secretorum, not the main Summa perfectionis (Ps. Gerber): 332ff,
- Bacon’s praise of a great 303-6 inspiration for the Scientia 367n
experimenter, 311-2 - example of an experimentum experimentalis, 370—1 Summae: 30
- Bacon sent a “cystallinum cruris. Rainbow, 297-303 Summulae dialectices: 95, 103-4, 109-17
sphericum” to the Pope with his - second prerogative, 306-7 Papacy (Vacancy): 51 Syncategoremata (attrib. to Roger Bacon
Opus maius and instructed his - third prerogative, 307-9 Perspectiva (originally taught at Oxford): 12 and Robert Bacon): 104
student, Iohannes, to demonstrate Physica: 69
it, 312-3 Roger Bacon - Secret o f Secrets,
365-394 Poetics and Rhetoric: 177 Tartars: 200ff
- influences of Bacon in the Priscian, Commentaries on: 68ff Text-Books d’Oxford: 104, 110
Renaissance and early Modem - Abbreviations/Bibliography,
392-3 Priscain minor: 68ff The Prince (N. Machiavelli): 409
times, 314—5 Pyrrhonian sceptic influence: 124n Timaeus (Cicero): 118
- limits of Bacon’s personal - a good vantagepoint for Bacon’s
career, 365 Timaeus (Plato): 243
experimenting due to his Sacred Scripture: 51-2 Tractatus de distinctionibus communibus in
circumstances, 313 - Alphonse of Poitiers’s illness
observed by Bacon in 1252, Science of Weights (scientia de sophismatibus accidentibus: 105
- significance of Bacon’s ponderibus): 62 Tractatus de grammatica: 99
experimental work, 315 386-7
- Aristode’s advice to Alexander, Science in the Middle Ages: 54 Tractatus in qua fit de experiencia in
- Sources for the term Scientia Science at Paris: 27 communi (Bacon): 266
experimentalis, 287-90 388-9
- astrology and medicine, 384—6 scientia de impressionibus: 60 Tractatus de grammatica: 99
- Bacon’s debt to Ibn al-Haytham Secretum secretorum: 179, 186-7, 283, Translations: 25-47
for term expenmentatio (i'tibar), - Bacon as A Man of his Age,
390-1 285, 307, 308n, 328ff, 343, 355, Translations from Arabic: 40
289 365ff, 407 Translators: 25-47; see 44
- experimentum in Grosseteste, - Bacon as Aristotle to a Princely
Alexander: role of his edition of Sentences: 51-2
287 Sophistical Refutations: 96 University of Bologna: 33
- importance of “BOOKS in the Secretum, 379ff
- Bacon’s defence of Aristotle and Speculum astronomiae: 30n, 36, 38, 41, University of Paris: 26, 34, 46
Science” for Grosseteste and 184n University of Tolouse: 35
Bacon, 288-9 Astrology, 375-6;
- Bacon’s praise of Aristotle, Speculum historiale (Vincent of Beauvais): Utopian world: 49
- indications of departure from 201
empeiria of Aristotle in early 78-9
- Bacon’s remarks in his edition Stoic influence on Bacon: 7, 124ff, Viaticum: 341
Bacon, 290 302-3, 405-9 Vivarium: 8
- The Definition of Scientia of this text: connection with
Parisian Condemnations of Summa contra gentiles: 195 Vulgus studentium: 49
experimentalis Summa de sophismatibus et distinctionibus:
1277, 373-6
- Function of Scientia experimentalis: 103, 105-9 Tmago mundi (Pierre d’Ailly): 206,
Adjudication of an Art and - Bacon’s scholastic methods, 382
- Bacon and the Speculum Summa grammatica (Bacon): 68ff, 91 217-8
Science of Nature and its
separation from Magic: the astronomiae, 377
need for a Practical Logic, - change in life c. 1247 not due
294-5 to the Secretum secretorum, 369-70
- fusion of these works with - date of Bacon’s Edition of this
Augustine’s doctrine of work, 366-9
illumination, 293 - embarrassment about Spanish
- the importance of Pseudo- word in De plantis, not reason
Ptolemy, Centiloquium and for this change c. 1247, 370
Commentary, 293 - importance of Secretum secretorum
- Two kinds of experience: for Bacon, 372-3
physical and moralis, 293-4 - making the Secretum user
friendly, 381
- The Uses of Scientia experimentalis
for Church and Commonwealth, - the maximum secretum, 387
309-11 - “Mirror for Princes”, 384
- Three Prerogatives for this - nature of the Secretum secretorum,
Scientific Method: 365-6
(1) confirmation, (2) new - Overview of Secretum secretorum
experimental knowledge with with Bacon’s interpretations,
instruments, (3) Knowledge of 379-91
future, 295-309 - Recension completed at Oxford,
380
LIST OF AUTHORS

Alain De Libera, Professor, Directeur d’etudes a l’Ecole Pratique des


Hautes Etudes, Paris.
Faye Getz, Associate Professor, Department of History of Medicine,
University of Wisconsin-Madison.
Jeremiah Hackett, Associate Professor and Director of Graduate
Studies, Department of Philosophy, University of South Carolina-
Columbia.
Herbert M. Howe, Professor Emeritus, Classics, University of Wis­
consin-Madison.
Richard Lemay, Professor Emeritus, Graduate School, City University
of New York.
David C. Lindberg, Hilldale Professor, Department of the History of
Science, University of Wisconsin-Madison.
Thomas S. Maloney, Professor, Department of Philosophy, University
of Louisville, Louisville-Ky.
A. George Molland, Professor Emeritus, Department of History and
Economics, University of Aberdeen.
William R. Newman, Associate Professor, Department of the History
of Science, Harvard University.
Irene Rosier-Catach, Professor, Departement de Recherches Linguisti-
ques, Universite Paris VII; Directeur de Recherches au C.N.R.S.;
Chargee de Conferences a 1’Ecole Pratique des Hautes Etudes.
Nancy van Deusen, Professor and Chair, Faculty of Music, The
Claremont Graduate School, Claremont, California.
Steven J. Williams, Assistant Professor, Department of History, New
Mexico Highlands University, Las Vegas, NM.
David Woodward, Arthur H. Robinson Professor, Department of Geo­
graphy, University of Wisconsin-Madison.
STUDIEN UND TEXTE
ZUR GEISTESGESCHICHTE
DES MITTELALTERS

3. K och, J. (Hrsg.). Humanismus, Mystik und Kunst in der Welt des Mittelalters. 2nd. impr.
1959. reprint under consideration
4. T homas Aquinas, Expositio super librum Boethii De Trinitate. Ad fidem codicis auto-
graphi nec non ceterorum codicum manuscriptorum recensuit B. Decker. Repr.
1965. ISBN 90 04 02173 6
5. K och, J. (Hrsg.). Artes liberates. Von der antiken Bildung zur Wissenschaft des
Mittelalters. Repr. 1976. ISBN 90 04 04738 7
6. M euthen, E. Ktrche und Heilsgeschichte bei Gerhoh von Reichersberg. 1959. ISBN 90 04 02174 4
7. N othdurft, K.-D. Studien zum Einfluss Senecas auf die Philosophie und Theologie des
12. Jahrhunderts. 1963. ISBN 90 04 02175 2
9. Zimmermann, A. (Hrsg.). Verzeichnis ungedruckter Kommentare zur Metaphysik und Physik
des Aristoteles aus der fe it von etwa 1250-1350. Band I. 1971. ISBN 90 04 02177 9
10. M cCarthy, J. M. Humanistic Emphases in the Educational Thought o f Vincent ofBeauvais.
1976. ISBN 90 04 04375 6
11. W illiam of D oncaster. Explicatio Aphorismatum Philosophicorum. Edited with Annota­
tions by O. Weijers. 1976. ISBN 90 04 94403 5
12. Pseudo-Boece. De Disciplina Scolarium. Edition critique, introduction et notes par
O. Weijers. 1976. ISBN 90 04 04768 9
13. J acobi, K. Die Modalbegriffe in den logischen Schriften des Wilhelm von Shyreswood und in
anderen Kompendien des 12. und 13. Jahrhunderts. Funktionsbestimmung und Gebrauch
in der logischen Analyse. 1980. ISBN 90 04 06048 0
14. Weijers, O. (Ed.). Les questions de Craton et leurs commentates. Edition critique. 1981.
ISBN 90 04 06340 4
15. H ermann of Carinthia. De Essentiis. A Critical Edition with Translation and
Commentary by C h. Burnett. 1982. ISBN 90 04 06534 2
17. J ohn of Salisbury. Entheticus Maior and Minor. Edited by J. van Laarhoven.
1987. 3 vols. 1. Introduction, Texts, Translations; 2. Commentaries and Notes;
3. Bibliography, Dutch Translations, Indexes. 1987. ISBN 90 04 07811 8
18. Richard Brinkley. Theory of Sentential Reference. Edited and Translated with Intro­
duction and Notes by M. J. Fitzgerald. 1987. ISBN 90 04 08430 4
19. Alfred of Sareshel. Commentary on the Metheora of Aristotle. Critical Edition,
Introduction and Notes by J. K. O tte . 1988. ISBN 90 04 08453 3
20. Roger Bacon. Compendium of the Study of Theology. Edition and Translation with
Introduction and Notes by T. S. M aloney. 1988. ISBN 90 04 08510 6
21. Aertsen, J. A. Nature and Creature. Thomas Aquinas’s Way of Thought. 1988.
ISBN 90 04 08451 7
22. T achau, K. H. Vision and Certitude in the Age of Ockham. Optics, Epistemology and
the Foundations of Semantics, 1250-1345. 1988. ISBN 90 04 08552 1
23. Frakes, J. C. The Fate of Fortune in the Early Middle Ages. The Boethian Tradition.
1988. ISBN 90 04 08544 0
24. M uralt, A. de. L ’Enjeu de la Philosophie Medievale. Etudes thomistes, scotistes,
occamiennes et gregoriennes. Repr. 1993. ISBN 90 04 09254 4
25. L ivesey, S. J. Theology and Science in the Fourteenth Century. Three Questions on the 50. Etzkorn, G. J. Iter Vaticanum Franciscanum. A Description of Some One Hundrec
Unity and Subaltemation of the Sciences from John of Reading’s Commentary on Manuscripts of the Vaticanus Latinus Collection. 1996. ISBN 90 04 10561 1
the Sentences. Introduction and Critical Edition. 1989. ISBN 90 04 09023 1 51. Sylwanowicz, M. Contingent Causality and the Foundations of Duns Scotus’ Metaphysics
>6. Elders, L. J. The Philosophical Theology of St Thomas Aquinas. 1990. ISBN 90 04 09156 4 1996. ISBN 90 04 10535 2
-7. W issink, J. B. (Ed.). The Eternity of the World in the Thought of Thomas Aquinas and his 52. A ertsen, J. A. Medieval Philosophy and the Transcendental[s. The Case of Thoma:
Contemporaries. 1990. ISBN 90 04 09183 1 Aquinas. 1996. ISBN 90 04 10585 9
28. Schneider, N. Die Kosmologie des Franciscos de Marchia. Texte, Quellen und Unter- 53. H onnefelder, L., R. Wood, M. Dreyer (Eds.). John Duns Scotus. Metaphysics anc
suchungen zur Naturphilosophie des 14. Jahrhunderts. 1991. ISBN 90 04 09280 3 Ethics. 1996. ISBN 90 04 10357 0
29. L angholm, O. Economics in the Medieval Schools. Wealth, Exchange, Value, Money 54. H olopainen, T. J. Dialectic and Theology in the Eleventh Century. 1996.
and Usury according to the Paris Theological Tradition, 1200-1350. 1992. ISBN 90 04 10577 8
ISBN 90 04 09422 9 55. Synan, E.A. (Ed.). Questions on the De Anima of Aristotle by Magister Adam Burley ana
30. R ijk, L. M. de. Peter o f Spain (Petrus Hispanus Portugalensis): Syncategoreumata. First Donunus Walter Burley 1997. ISBN 90 04 10655 3
Critical Edition with an Introduction and Indexes. With an English Translation by 56. Schupp, F. (Hrsg.). Abbo von Fleury: De syllogismis hypotheticis. Textkritisch
J oke Spruyt. 1992. ISBN 90 04 09434 2 herausgegeben, iibersetzt, eingeleitet und kommentiert. 1997. ISBN 90 04 10748 7
31. Resnick, I. M. Divine Power and Possibility in St. Peter Damian’s De Divina Omni- 57. H ackett, J. (Ed.). Roger Bacon and the Sciences. Commemorative Essays. 1997.
potentia. 1992. ISBN 90 04 09572 1 ISBN 90 04 10015 6
32. O ’Rourke, F. Pseudo-Dionysius and the Metaphysics ofAquinas. 1992. ISBN 90 04 09466 0 58. H oenen, M.J.F.M. and N auta, L. (Eds.). Boethius in the Middle Ages. Latin anc
33. H all, D. C. The Trinity. An Analysis of St. Thomas Aquinas’ Expositio of the De Vernacular Traditions of the Consolatio philosophicte. 1997. ISBN 90 04 10831 9
Trinitate of Boethius. 1992. ISBN 90 04 09631 0 59. G oris, W. Einheit als Prinzip und 2Jel. Versuch iiber die Einheitsmetaphysik des OpiL
34. Elders, L. J. The Metaphysics of Being of St. Thomas Aquinas in a Historical Perspective. tripartitum Meister Eckharts. 1997. ISBN 90 04 10905 6
1992. ISBN 90 04 09645 0 60. R ijk, L.M. de (Ed.). Giraldus Odonis O.F.M.: Opera Philosophica. Vol. 1.: Logica
35. Westra, H. J. (Ed.). From Athens to Chartres. Neoplatonism and Medieval Thought. Critical Edition from the Manuscripts. 1997. ISBN 90 04 10950 1
Studies in Honour of Edouard Jeauneau. 1992. ISBN 90 04 09649 3
36. Schulz, G. Veritas est adrequatio intellectus et rei. Untersuchungen zur Wahrheitslehre
des Thomas von Aquin und zur Kritik Kants an einem iiberlieferten Wahrheits-
begriff. 1993. ISBN 90 04 09655 8
37. K ann, C h . Die Eigenschqften der Termini. Eine Untersuchung zur Perutilis logica Alberts
von Sachsen. 1994. ISBN 90 04 09619 1
38. J acobi, K. (Hrsg.). Argumentationstheorie. Scholastische Forschungen zu den logischen
und semantischen Regeln korrekten Folgems. 1993. ISBN 90 04 09822 4
39. Butterworth, C. E., and B. A. K essel (Eds.). The Introduction o f Arabic Philosophy
into Europe. 1994. ISBN 90 04 09842 9
40. K aufmann, M. Begrijfe, Sdtze, Dinge. Referenz und Wahrheit bei Wilhelm von
Ockham. 1994. ISBN 90 04 09889 5
41. H ulsen, C. R. Zjir Semantik anaphorischer Pronomina. Untersuchungen scholastischer
und modemer Theorien. 1994. ISBN 90 04 09832 1
42. Rijk, L. M. de (Ed. & Tr.). Nicholas of Autrecourt. His Correspondence with Master
Giles and Bernard of Arezzo. A Critical Edition from the Two Parisian M anu­
scripts with an Introduction, English Translation, Explanatory Notes and Indexes.
1994. ISBN 90 04 09988 3
43. Schonberger, R. Relation als Vergleich. Die Relationstheorie des Johannes Buridan
im Kontext seines Denkens und der Scholastik. 1994. ISBN 90 04 09854 2
44. Saarinen, R. Weakness of the Will in Medieval Thought. From Augustine to Buridan.
1994. ISBN 90 04 09994 8
45. Speer, A. Die entdeckte Natur. Untersuchungen zu Begriindungsversuchen einer
„scientia naturalis“ im 12. Jahrhundert. 1995. ISBN 90 04 10345 7
46. T e V elde, R. A. Participation and Substantiality in Thomas Aquinas. 1995.
ISBN 90 04 10381 3
47. T uninetti, L. F. „Per Se Notum“. Die logische Beschaffenheit des Selbstverstand-
lichen im Denken des Thomas von Aquin. 1996. ISBN 90 04 10368 6
48. H oenen, M.J.F.M. und De L ibera, A. (Hrsg.). Albertus Magnus und der Albertismus.
Deutsche philosophische Kultur des Mittelalters. 1995. ISBN 90 04 10439 9
49. Back, A. On Reduplication. Logical Theories of Qualification. 1996. ISBN 90 04 10539 5

Potrebbero piacerti anche