Sei sulla pagina 1di 17

Ideas, Institutions, and Political Order: Explaining Political Change

Author(s): Robert C. Lieberman


Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 96, No. 4 (Dec., 2002), pp. 697-712
Published by: American Political Science Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3117505
Accessed: 14/11/2009 12:41

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=apsa.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
The American Political Science Review.

http://www.jstor.org
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4 December 2002

Ideas, and Political


Institutions, Order: Explaining Political Change
ROBERT C. LIEBERMAN Columbia University
nstitutionalapproachesto explainingpoliticalphenomenasufferfrom threecommon limitations:
reductionism,reliance on exogenous factors, and excessive emphasis on order and structure.
Ideationalapproachesto political explanation,while often more sensitiveto change and agency,
largelyexhibitthe same shortcomings.In particular,bothperspectivessharean emphasison discerning
and explainingpatternsof orderedregularityin politics,makingit hard to explainimportantepisodes
of politicalchange.Relaxingthisemphasison orderand viewingpoliticsas situatedin multipleand not
necessarilyequilibratedordersuggestsa wayof synthesizinginstitutionaland ideationalapproachesand
developingmore convincingaccountsof political change.In this view,changearisesout of "friction"
amongmismatchedinstitutionalandideationalpatterns.An accountof Americancivilrightspolicy in the
1960sand 1970s,whichis not amenableto eitherstraightforward institutionalor ideationalexplanation,
demonstratesthe advantagesof the approach.

As the time neared midnighton 10 June 1964, that we have arrivedat this pass. First,developments
Everett Dirksen took the floor of the United in world politics broughtideas onto center stage. The
States Senate to concludethree monthsof de- end of the Cold War,the collapse of communism,and
bate on the Civil Rights Act. "It is said that on the the convergenceof the world'seconomicand political
nighthe died,"Dirksensaid,"VictorHugo wrotein his institutionson a newneoliberalparadigm,amongother
diarysubstantiallythissentiment:'Strongerthanall the broad shifts,signaleda profoundideologicaltransfor-
armiesis an idea whose time has come.'The time has mation in much of the world.Never mind that the so-
come,"he went on, "forequalityof opportunityin shar- cial sciencesutterlyfailed to predictthese phenomena;
ing in government,in education,andin employment.It without reference to the ideological nature of these
will not be stayedor denied. It is here"(Congressional transformations,the new worldof the twenty-firstcen-
Record 1964, 13319;Whalen and Whalen 1985, 185, turyseems unfathomableandthe pathwaysby whichit
198).1Surelyequalityof opportunityfor all races was arrivedincomprehensible(see Andersonn.d.).
an idea of its time in the United Statesin 1964,well past Second, prevailinginstitutionalapproachesin po-
due accordingto many.But what made that particular litical science are limited in their capacityto account
nightthemomentwhen this idea arrived,to be entered for the substantivecourse of politics. Given the raw
finallyinto the nation'slawbooksby vote of a venerable material-assumptions about actors' beliefs, prefer-
legislativebody that had long resistedit? Manythings ences, knowledge,understandings,and expectations-
beyond the force of the idea itself conspiredto make institutionaltheoriescan effectivelyderivepredictions
this idea arriveat that place at that time: a broad and about whichoutcome from amonga rangeof contem-
vigoroussocialmovementespousingit, politicalparties plated outcomes is likely to occur. But precisely be-
increasinglydividedby it andconsumedwithit, andpo- cause material approachestend to take these things
litical institutionsthat were able to help its advocates as given, they are at something of a loss to explain
build and sustaina coalition aroundit. How did these the appearanceat any given moment of any partic-
thingscontributeto the triumphof the liberalideal of ular menu of substantivechoices. In the case of the
equal rights?As John Kingdon(1984, 1) asks, "What Civil Rights Act, for example, institutionaltheories
makes an idea's time come?" can explain why, given the emergence of civil rights
Long dormant in the systematic study of politics, as a salient issue, Congressacted as it did. They can
ideas have stageda remarkablecomebackin the social even explainwhythe Americanpoliticalsystemat mid-
sciencesin the last 15 yearsor so. Indeed,the challenge centurywas particularlysusceptibleto the appeals of
of "bringingideas back in" to political science and the civil rightsmovement.But they cannotaccountfor
political explanationis one of the central issues now the substantivecontentof civilrightsdemands,or of the
facing the discipline.There are a number of reasons beliefs and understandingsthat led actors to connect
these demandswith a particularset of policysolutions.
Robert C. Lieberman is Associate Professor of Political Science and Ideas, many analysts argue, can fill this explanatory
Public Affairs, Department of Political Science, Columbia University, gap. After all, they constitutemuch of the substantive
420 West 118th Street, New York, NY 10027 (RCL15@COLUMBIA.EDU). raw material
upon which institutionaltheory feeds-
The author thanks the Russell Sage Foundation, the German the goals and desiresthat people bringto the political
Marshall Fund of the United States, and the Lyndon Baines Johnson
Foundation for financial support and Sheri Berman, Mark Blyth, Bob world and, hence, the ways they define and express
Jervis, Ira Katznelson, Lauren Osborne, Sven Steinmo, and the editor theirinterests;the meanings,interpretations,andjudg-
and anonymous reviewers for their helpful advice. ments they attachto events and conditions;and their
1 The Hugo quotation is
actually a paraphrase of a passage from beliefs about cause-and-effectrelationshipsin the po-
his historical essay, Histoire d'un crime: Deposition d'un timoin, his
vicious account of Louis Napoleon's coup d'etat of 1851. The pas-
litical world and, hence, their expectationsabout how
sage reads, "On a l'invasion des on ne
' others will respondto their own behavior.To the ex-
r6siste arm6es; r6siste pas
l'invasion des id6es" ["The invasion of armies can be resisted; the tent that these and other thingsthat go on in people's
invasion of ideas cannot be resisted"] (Hugo 1987, 456). heads are not simply a function of somethingelse in

697
Ideas, Institutions,and Political Order December 2002

the politicalworld,institutionaland interest-basedap- true that ideationalaccountsare often more sensitive


proacheswilltell only a partof the causalstoryof many to changethan institutionalones; ideas,after all, are a
significantpoliticalphenomena(Berman1998,16-19). mediumby whichpeople can imaginea state of affairs
Withthese limitationsin mind,scholarsstudyingthe other than the status quo and such imaginingsmight
role of ideas in politics have offered a bracingchal- plausiblyspur them to act to try and make changes.
lenge to materialperspectiveson a numberof grounds. But ideas alone do not create the incentivesor oppor-
Ideational approacheschallenge the reductionismof tunitiesfor action,andnot all holdersof alternativepo-
much institutionaltheory,which often assumes away liticalideasact on them.Moreover,ideationalaccounts
anycomplexityin the substanceof politics,as in spatial of politicalchange typicallychronicleshifts from one
models of voting or legislativebehaviorthat collapse ideationalequilibriumto another.
politicaldisputestypicallyto a singledimension(Black There is no particularshame in these faults; they
1958;Downs 1957;Krehbiel1988;Poole andRosenthal are the necessary elements of theory building and
1997).Ideas in politics,by contrast,are often complex generalizationthat distinguishsocial science from the
and multidimensional.Ideationalaccountsof politics description of singular slices of human experience.
also challengethe tendencyof institutionaltheoriesto Nevertheless,this set of analyticalmoves, commonto
take the interestsand aims of politicalactorsas given, boththeoreticalschools,comesat somecost.In particu-
whetherthey are determinedby individualrationality, lar,whatKarenOrrenand StephenSkowronek(1994)
group affiliation,or culturalpatterns.Rather, actors' havecalledthe "iconographyof order,"the questto find
understandingof theirown interestsis apt to evolve as coherentsynchronouspatterns-equilibria-in politi-
the ideologicalsettingof politicschanges.More gener- cal life, often leaves politicalscientistsscratchingtheir
ally,ideationaltheories seem to challengethe institu- heads when asked to accountfor politicalchange.2
tional emphasison structure,aggregateorganizational I suggest furtherthat by substantiallyrelaxingthe
or behavioralregularities,as the principalguidingforce common focus on order that both sets of approaches
behind political behavior.A focus on ideas suggests, share,we canmakeprogressin accommodatingthe two
rather,the possibilitythat humanagencycan defy the perspectives.Thatis, an analyticperspectivethat con-
constraintsof politicaland social structuresand create siders both institutionsand ideas as integral,endoge-
new politicalpossibilities(Smith1992). nous explanatoryelements,withoutprivilegingone or
These challengeszero in on the central shortcom- the other,can go some distancein avoidingthese traps.
ings of institutionaltheoriesof politics.Althougheach In particular,analysisthat takes both ideas and insti-
brandof institutionalismhasits ownblindspots,in their tutionsseriouslywill almostof necessityshed light on
broadest outlines they share these characteristics-- pointsof friction,irregularities,anddiscontinuitiesthat
reductionism,the exogeneity of certain fundamental drive political change. These discontinuitiesbetween
elementsof politicallife, and a privilegingof structure separatelyconstitutedpatternsof institutionsandideas
over agency.Above all, institutionaltheoriesshare an can lead to a reformulationof the incentivesand op-
emphasis on finding order and stability,comprehen- portunitiesfacing political actors and produce large-
siveness and coherence,patternsand models that elu- scalepoliticalchangethatneitherinstitutionsnorideas,
cidatemoreor less generalpropositionsabouta classof consideredindependently,can explain. There are, to
politicalphenomena.Becauseof theiremphasison elic- be sure, analyticalcosts to this approach,particularly
iting ordered patternsand regularitiesfrom observa- the parsimonyand clear foundationsthat often char-
tionsaboutpolitics,institutionaltheoriesin generalrun acterizeinstitutionalmodels of politics.But there are
into troublein accountingfor politicalchange;How,af- correspondinganalyticalgains,particularlythe ability
ter all, canwe explainchangein outcomesby reference to accountfor majorpoliticalchange,that make these
to stable causes?Any searchfor the sourcesof change costs worth paying.After elaboratingthis critiqueof
in thissortof explanatoryscenarioinevitablyleadsto a both institutionaland ideationaltheories I sketch the
problemof infiniteregress:Toexplaina changein some outlinesof a synthesisandillustrateits possibilitieswith
familiarstate of affairs,we mustassumean antecedent an exampletaken fromthe developmentof civil rights
change in one or more causal factors that were pre- policyin the United States.
viously part of a stable system. But after makingthis
move we are left with the same problem:Whatcaused IDEAS AND INSTITUTIONS:
this antecedent change, if not some change farther back COMMON CHALLENGES
in the causal chain? At some point in this sequence, the
source of change must come from outside the system. A variety of institutional perspectives has come to oc-
It is one of my contentions that these same cupy, it is fair to say, the ascendant position in the theo-
dilemmas-problems of reductionism, exogeneity, and retical pantheon of political science. There is, of course,
structure envy-ironically bedevil much ideational po-
litical analysis, contrary to common presumptions and 2
By "order" I refer not to the orderliness of societies and
the self-professed aims of many ideational theorists government-what Samuel Huntington (1968, 1) defined as qualities
who define their enterprise as a counterweight to of "consensus, community, legitimacy, organization, effectiveness,
these particular sins of institutional analysis. Above all [and] stability"-but rather to the recognition of patterned regularity
in social and political life. Some major works of social science have
ideational and institutional accounts share the focus focused precisely on finding order among great moments of societal
on ordered regularity that makes problems of change disorder, such as revolutions, as in the work of Barrington Moore
particularly intractable for both camps. It is certainly (1966) and Theda Skocpol (1979).

698
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4

a varietyof "newinstitutionalisms"in politicalscience ter of causal accountsof tumultuouspoliticalchange.


(and the social sciences more generally),rooted in a Nor do they fully capturepoliticaldevelopmentsthat
varietyof methodologicalanddisciplinaryapproaches, involve basic conflictsand transformationsamongpo-
from neoclassicalmicroeconomicsand the theory of litical ideas and values. Such developmentsspan the
games to macrohistoricalsociology to the sociology spectrumof substantiveconcernsin political science:
of organizationsand culture(Campbelland Pedersen the rise of Keynesianismand its eclipse by neoliberal-
2001a;Hall and Taylor 1996;Immergut1998;Powell ism (Campbelland Pedersen2001b;Hall 1989, 1993),
and DiMaggio 1991;Thelen and Steinmo 1992). Al- the triumphof color-blindliberalintegrationismin the
though these perspectives differ in significantways, United Statesover a historyof race-consciousoppres-
they sharea commonset of concernsand assumptions, sion (King2000;Smith1997),and the emergenceof in-
particularlyan interestin the way in whichsome set of ternationalnormsof multilateralismand humanrights
regularitiesin politicallife (rulesandprocedures,orga- out of Cold War realism (Risse, Ropp, and Sikkink
nizationalstructures,norms,culturalscripts)shapesthe 1999;Sikkink1993).If institutionalismwantsto remain
expressionand aggregationof politicalpreferences,al- relevantin politicalscience,it mustproveitself able to
locates power and regulatesits exercise,and therefore account convincinglyfor these changes that manifest
affectspoliticaloutcomes (Immergut1998). themselvesnot simplyin new policiesbut in fundamen-
Another characteristicthese perspectives share is tally new ideologicalbases for politics.
a tendency to relegate ideas, however they are con- The challenge for institutionalapproaches,there-
ceived, to the sidelinesin explanatoryaccountsof po- fore, is to find a way to treat ideas as analytically
litical processes (see, e.g., Berman 1998, 14-24, and consequential in accounts of political action, policy
Hall 1997).One extremeversionof thisview holds that development, and institutionalchange, and to do so
ideas are epiphenomenal,simplyconsequencesof ma- withoutfallinginto the characteristictrapsthat I have
terial(or structuralor institutional)arrangements.This outlined-particularlythe ad hockerywithwhichinsti-
view is most clearlyassociatedwith certainversionsof tutionalaccountsusuallyappropriateideas as explana-
Marxism,but it also appearsin non-Marxistvariants. tory factors.But this must also be done in a way that
In such cases,expressionsof ideas in a politicalsetting retains the essential strengths of institutionalismin
mightbe takennot as genuinearticulationsof beliefsor all its varieties:its accounts of strategic behavior by
understandingbutas strategicmanipulationorposition purposive agents under structuralconstraints,of the
takingaimedat advancingan interestor pursuinga goal aggregationof interests, of the distributionand ex-
that is deemed to be fundamental(see, e.g., Mayhew ercise of power, and of the social construction of
1974). political rationality-and its ability to combine and
Even in cases where the analysis is not quite so recombinethese elementsandmobilizethem into con-
doggedly materialist, ideas are seen as exogenous vincing causal explanationsof a wide range of politi-
to the more fundamental explanatory framework. cal phenomena,from the presidentialveto (Cameron
Ideas often make an appearancein institutionalanal- 2000) and the political control of the bureaucracy
yses, where they serve the purpose of patching over (McCubbins,Noll, and Weingast1987) to social rev-
lacunae in the basic explanation.This move has be- olutions (Skocpol 1979), industrialpolicies (Dobbin
come somewhatcommonin rational-choiceinstitution- 1994), lawmakingunder separatedpowers (Krehbiel
alism, where ideas operate as focal points that help 1998),andwelfarestates (Pierson1994;Skocpol1992).
solve game-theoreticmodels with multiple equilibria Our synthesis should recognize,in other words, that
(Bates,de Figueiredo,and Weingast1998;Garrettand ideasarenot simplytools in the handsof power-seeking
Weingast 1993). Ideas are unquestionablyimportant strategicagents (althoughthey can be and often are)
to such analyses,but not ideas as ideas-that is, their (Campbell1998).
content,valence, and intensityare less importantthan Whileinstitutionalapproacheslaborunderthese dif-
the role they play in a causal tableau. Ideas work in ficultiesin tryingto assimilateideas, ideationalexpla-
suchinstancesmerelyas devicesto untanglethe knotty nationssharemanyof the same blinders.Again, these
problems of institutionalmodels; something else en- difficultiestakemoreandless extremeforms.At the far
tering from the wings would do just as well. More extremeare accountsthatposita single,overwhelming,
generally, as Mark Blyth (1997, 231) has observed, and, above all, stable set of ideas as the driving force
"Ideas in such treatments are ultimately secondary to in politics (see, e.g., Geertz 1964 and Hartz 1955). In
the mode of analysis in which they are employed. Their such accounts it is the substance of ideas that matters
definition, operationalization, and explanatory power above all in shaping political outcomes, whether they
are simply derivative of the wider theory in which are coherent, logical, internally consistent, and thus
they are embedded." Although they might be impor- influential; the causal mechanisms that drive this in-
tant to particular explanations, ideas when adduced in fluence inhere in the ideas themselves. While such an
this way do not fundamentally alter the institutionalist approach is admittedly rare in the rationalist world of
enterprise. the social sciences, functional explanations of politics
Such moves also ignore commonplace readings of often ascribe this role to political ideas; modernization
history, in which ideas often appear as the prime theory, which ascribes great importance to the logical,
movers of history. Prominent accounts of the American functional connections among the components of po-
(Bailyn 1967; Wood 1969) and French (Sewell 1985) litical systems, is a prominent example (Almond and
Revolutions, for example, have put ideas at the cen- Coleman 1960; Inglehart 1997).

699
Ideas, Institutions,and Political Order December 2002

More common are studies that emphasize political pendent explanatory weight and he does not assimilate
ideas as central causal factors but give short shrift to their effects systematically into his framework.
the political settings in which ideas become influential Just as ideas are not merely strategic tools, political
and to the causal mechanisms that influence the selec- ideas are not free-floating bits of knowledge and con-
tion among ideas in concrete political choices (Berman jecture, detached from considerations of structure and
2001). In his magisterial survey of the multiple political power, that rise and fall according to the functional
traditions that have challenged liberalism for ascen- logic of the marketplace (to borrow Oliver Wendell
dancy in American politics, for example, Rogers Smith Holmes Jr.'smetaphor) or of natural selection (Abrams
(1997) places his bets squarely on ideational factors, v. United States 1919, 630-31; Mill, On Liberty, chap. 2).
the interplay of three clusters of ideas about national Part of understanding political development and insti-
membership and civic identity, as the central factor in tutional change is understanding which ideas win (or,
shaping American citizenship laws and American po- in fact, which ideas are in the arena to begin with), why,
litical development more generally. Smith (1993, 1997) and with what consequences for whom. The important
brilliantly parses the ideological currents that found point is not only where ideas come from or how they
expression in American citizenship and immigration cohere or collide but also how they come to be promi-
policy and effectively challenges the view of American nent, important, and powerful, even determinative in
culture as thoroughly suffused with egalitarian liberal- shaping political behavior and defining political ratio-
ism that has held sway from Tocqueville through Louis nality. As Sheri Berman (2001, 233) writes, "Political
Hartz and beyond (see also King 1973). These ideo- scientists must be able to explain... why some of the
logical traditions do not stand alone in Smith's work; innumerable ideas in circulation achieve prominence
like a mirror image of institutional accounts that rely in the political realm at particular moments and others
on ideas as catalytic but not constitutive, his account not. Since no intellectual vacuum ever exists, what is
presents evidence about the institutional settings in really at issue here is ideational change, how individ-
which ideas are enacted as policy-courts, legislatures, uals, groups, or societies exchange old ideas for new
administrative agencies, and the like. But these settings ones." These exchange processes, it is clear, occur at
are exogenous to his theoretical framework; they ap- the intersection of ideas and institutions, and any fully
pear conveniently as stage-setters for his interpretive convincing theory of political or institutional change
enterprise but they do not fundamentally change the must incorporate both as constituent elements with rea-
theoretical approach, limiting somewhat his theory's sonably equal weights.
capacity to explain the particular sequence of outcomes
he charts (Orren 1996a, 1996b; Smith 1996, 1999). As
Smith (1999, 25) himself notes, ORDER,DISORDER,AND POLITICAL
CHANGE
Conduciveconditionsare... not enough to explain out- The most important limitation on the capacity of both
comes. To grasp how and why early Americanpolitical
actorscombinedliberal,republican,racist,andsexistideas institutional and ideational approaches to come to grips
and institutions,we must go beyond a Hartzianfocus on with processes of change is their common emphasis
their initial materialand intellectualcircumstancesand on ordered, patterned regularity. It is this emphasis,
attend to their central political tasks. Those tasks were after all, that distinguishes social science from other
not, first and foremost, the carryingon of any particu- modes of inquiry into human experience-the search
lar tradition,althoughmany early Americansidentified for general patterns of behavior and interaction.3 This
withhistoricalfigureswho defendedpersonallibertiesand emphasis on order leads, as Karen Orren and Stephen
championedrepublicangovernments.Americanleaders Skowronek (1994,1996,1999) argue, to a view of politi-
weremostimmediatelyconcernedwithusingavailabletra- cal development that consists of periods of stability and
ditionsfirstto mobilizesupportfor the Revolution,thento
build a successfulnew nation,and finallyto maintainand coherence, of "politics as usual," punctuated by mo-
extendit in variousways. ments of extraordinary, even transformative change,
after which things settle back down into a reformu-
More precisely, these broad political projects posed lated pattern of ordinariness (see Baumgartner and
particular political challenges to these actors, who had Jones 1993 and Carmines and Stimson 1989). Each
to negotiate a distinctive and shifting institutional uni- brand of institutionalism lends itself to this view: Ra-
verse to implement them. They had to pass laws, de- tional choice, with its emphasis on equilibrium and its
fend those laws against legal challenges, and administer methodology of comparative statics; historical institu-
them according to particular institutional rules and log- tionalism, with its focus on periodization and regimes;
ics that were not necessarily connected to (or in synch
with) the ideas these policies embody. These patterns 3 This minimalist definition of social science is intended to be a thor-
surely affected the sequence and substance of the out- oughly catholic one. I do not mean to endorse a vision of social
comes Smith charts by placing power in certain hands science that depends on the discovery of Hempelian covering laws
at certain moments, privileging certain interests over that govern human behavior across time and space, nor do I mean
others, and creating moments of opportunity for politi- to exclude interpretive modes of inquiry such as Geertz's (1973)
notion of "thick description," which, although it does not endorse
cians to act, whether out of strategic or ideological or
generalization across cultural milieus, nevertheless hews to an idea
some combination of motives (Kingdon 1984; Mayhew of understanding human societies by discerning regular patterns of
2000). These features of the political landscape are not interaction and signification among their members (Merton 1949;
absent from his account, but they do not carry inde- Zuckerman 1997).

700
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4

and sociological institutionalism, with its account of (1) to (2). What we do not have is an account of how and
taken-for-granted cultural meanings and scripts that why the world changed; there is nothing in the stable
underlie action. Although ideational theories are often patterns of variation in model (1) that can provide a
more attuned to change, they too tend to emphasize causal story about the emergence of model (2). Any
order and regularity. Ideas do not appear willy-nilly explanation we might be able to mount for this change
in ideational accounts; rather, they appear in settled, would have to be exogenous to model (1), based on
ordered configurations that serve to organize some rea- something that was simply relegated to the error term,
sonably broad aspect of political life over some span since model (1)'s parameters (Pi and 82) are constant.5
of time, whether as all-encompassing ideologies or as What all of this abstract symbolism is meant to sug-
what Berman (1998, 21-22) calls "programmatic be- gest is that the only source of explanatory power to ac-
liefs" (see also Eckstein 1988). count for significant political change-change that goes
Both institutional and ideational approaches thus beyond the bounds of ordinary variation-is the error
exhibit something of a bias toward finding and ex- term, the detritus of the normal model of political af-
plaining stability in political arrangements. Each set fairs. These are the things that, as noted above, are con-
of approaches has developed sophisticated tools for sidered irrelevant or unnecessary to a model of political
making causal inferences about the effects of stable, re- order or else too wispy or ethereal to be the focus of sys-
curring patterns on political outcomes. This bias, how- tematic explanation. This is true, in general, of both in-
ever, poses a problem when we are confronted with stitutional and ideational models that focus on ordered
significant political change. From a perspective that em- patterns in the political world. To explain the move
phasizes stability and relegates things that do not fit the from one set of institutions to another, we need refer-
pattern to the background, the sources of important ence to something exogenous to an institutional model
change almost necessarily appear to be exogenous, the of the initial state of affairs; likewise for a shift from
result of some sort of shock of unknown origin that one ideational pattern to another. The question is how
may or may not be assimilable by the prevailing order. to develop models of politics that can account for such
What we are after is an explanation not of ordinary substantial episodes without recourse to such ad hoc
predictable variation in outcomes but of extraordinary exogenous factors-in other words, how, if possible, to
change, where relationships among explanatory factors endogenize multiple ordered patterns, whether based
themselves change. on institutions or ideas, in a single type of explanatory
To put the matter in more analytical terms, consider framework that can help explain how apparently stable
a simple model of some political phenomenon: institutional and ideological patterns can change quite
Y= Po + Pl X1 +2•X2 + 8. dramatically. There are limits, of course. Not every-
(1)
thing that happens in the political world is predictable
Although the explanatory factors, X1 and X2, vary, the and consequential things happen that are quite simply
model describes a stable pattern of relationships be- beyond the reach of any reasonable model-singular
tween these factors and the outcome, Y; when X1 or events such as assassinations, for example. Thus we
X2 varies by a certain amount, Y changes by a pre- cannot hope to endogenize everything. Nevertheless,
dictable amount, as described by the parameters, Pd there does not seem to be any a priori reason why both
and ,2. Anything we do not observe or cannot mea- ideas and institutions, neither of which has such singular
sure or consider unnecessary to explain the outcome character, cannot both be incorporated into reasonable,
is bundled in the error term, e. This model describes a tractable models of politics.
stable pattern, and we can test its explanatory power by One way out of this bind is to relax the emphasis
observing variation on the independent variables and on order and regularity in modeling politics. The al-
comparing the model's predictions with actual states of ternative need not be chaos. Rather, we can consider
the world under a variety of conditions. But consider that any political moment or episode or outcome is
that, for some reason, the pattern changes, requiring a situated within a variety of ordered institutional and
new model to describe the same phenomenon: ideological patterns, each with its own origins and his-
tory and each with its own logic and pace (Orren
Y = P3 + + P5sX2+, F (2) and Skowronek 1994, 1996). These patterns, it is often
-4X-
This model describes a new set of stable regularities, in metaphorically said, "take on lives of their own"; that
which the variables are the same but the relationships is, they come to structure and delimit political interests,
among them are different-we have new parameters, understandings, and behavior independently of other
64 and fs, in place of the original ones. Now we have factors that might also be important. It is common in
useful models of two situations, before and after some
transformative change that has altered not just the con- (1) to (2). This eventuality, however, would not change the funda-
ditions that produce some outcome (what I describe mental point and would in fact deepen the conundrum that I am
above as ordinary variation) but the very causal pro- illustrating.
cess at work in producing the outcome (extraordinary 5 I offer this stylized example not to suggest, as some have (King,
Keohane, and Verba 1994), that the statistical reasoning represented
change).4 We might even have a description of what- therein is any kind of gold standard for social scientific inference but
ever happened at the moment of transformation from rather to demonstrate the distinction I am making between explain-
ing stability and explaining change and to point to the need for more
4 For simplicity's sake, I have not considered the possibility that some configurative models of politics that embrace a multiplicity of causal
new variable, X3, may have entered the mix in the transition from elements (Katznelson 1997).

701
Ideas, Institutions,and Political Order December 2002

both institutional and ideational analysis to conceive of resolution, presenting actors with contradictory and
political order in holistic terms. A political "order," in multidirectional imperatives and opportunities.
this mode, is a regular, predictable, and interconnected These considerations immediately shift attention
pattern of institutional and ideological arrangements away from any particular regularity and onto the ten-
that structures political life in a given place at a given sion or complementarity among patterns that might
time-"a durable mode of organizing and exercising more plausibly drive the dynamics of political devel-
political power.., .with distinct institutions, policies, opment. If we picture politics as occurring in mul-
and discourses,"as David Plotke (1996,1) defines it (see tiple concurrent orders, it is in the friction between
also Skowronek 1993). Such an order might have mul- orders that we may more readily find the seeds of
tiple institutional and ideological components, which change within the politics of any given moment. Samuel
shape and constrain political action by providing in- Huntington (1981) identifies just such friction, between
centives, opportunities, and grounds for legitimation political ideals and the performance of political insti-
to political actors. An important presumption behind tutions, as the motive force behind American polit-
this approach is that a political "order" is internally ical development; when the gap between ideals and
coherent. This definition implies that the effects of the institutions grows large enough, he argues, periods of
component parts are cumulative and mutually reinforc- "creedal passion" occur in which institutional practices
ing, that they generally point most actors in the same are reformed to align more closely with the ideals.
(or at least complementary) directions most of the time. Huntington's approach suggests the importance of the
(This is not to say there is no conflict, only that conflicts lack of fit among multiple ideological and institutional
are fundamentally stable and predictable and tend to orders as an important motor of political change (al-
be contained and resolved within the normal political though it is unclear what the causal mechanism is).
processes that constitute the order in question accord- But his view of these orders, particularly of ideas, is
ing to generally agreed upon or conventionally under- a relatively static one, in which a constant set of po-
stood rules and expectations.) As an analytical strategy litical ideas-the American Creed-serves as a fixed
for explaining political outcomes, this approach pre- point to which political institutions and practices are
sumes that other factors are not consequential enough tethered so that, like a pendulum, they return with a
to create sufficiently strong incentives for actors to de- certain mechanical regularity and periodicity toward
viate from what appear to be the "normal"workings of a central location. Political ideas and institutions are
politics. not fixed, however. Certain ideological constructions,
There is no reason to presume, however, that the at the level of Huntington's Creed (or culture, or ide-
ideological and institutional currents that prevail at any ology, or tradition)-the ideals of liberty and equality,
given time or place are necessarily connected with each for example-have a very long life span and can de-
other in any coherent or functional way. This is true for fine enduring boundaries that a nation's politics will
a number of reasons. First, political arrangements are rarely, if ever, cross (Greenstone 1993). But ideas at
rarely, if ever, the products of a coherent, total vision this level do not offer a concrete guide to understand-
of politics that informs institutions and ideas and knits ing the more precise pathways a country's political de-
them together into a unified whole (and even in times velopment might take. Many particular programmatic
and places that approach this extreme-revolutionary beliefs might be consistent with these broad bound-
France, the Soviet Union, Nazi Germany-politics re- ary conditions, and these ideas might change more
mains subject to multiple, discordant forces). Rather, quickly. Moreover, the interpretation and framing even
they are inevitably the products of compromise, partial of deeply rooted ideas might change over time, so that
and circumscribed, incoherent and jury-rigged, rarely concepts such as "liberty" or "equality" might be in-
if ever sweeping away the detritus of a previous or- voked to support very different practices in different
der to construct a new one. New policies, institutional contexts by people who all the while believe themselves
arrangements, or ideological paradigms thus do not to be upholding a timeless and unchanging political tra-
replace the old but are layered atop prior patterns, dition. Similarly, some institutional features of politics
creating what Jeffrey Tulis (1987, 17-18) has called a are relatively stable over long stretches of time, while
"layered text." Second, such arrangements are often others are less fixed and more variable. If we unmoor
the products of some past event, so that while insti- both sets of factors from overly general assumptions
tutions, policies, or sets of ideas might have arisen in about their fixity and stability, new patterns of order
response to particular historical circumstances, they of- and change may well emerge into view.
ten outlast the conditions that led to their creation and As an example of this analytical dilemma, consider
may persist despite being dysfunctional (North 1990). pluralism and consensus historiography, which dom-
Consequently the ideological and institutional orders inated American social science in the aftermath of
that prevail at any given time or place are unlikely to be World War II. This approach, exemplified by such
connected with each other in any coherent or functional scholars as Louis Hartz (1955), Richard Hofstadter
way. There may be instances in which ideological and (1948), and David Truman (1971), offered a view of
institutional patterns "fit" together and cumulate into American politics in which ideology, institutions, and
something that looks like an equilibrium (on the notion behavior were fundamentally aligned with one an-
of "fit" see Skocpol 1992). At other times, however, other. Liberal individualism, skepticism toward the
they will collide and chafe, creating an ungainly con- state, the separation of powers, and a commitment to
figuration of political circumstances that has no clear a set of "rules of the game" all went together to create

702
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4

a unified and ordered whole, in which ideas, institu- about the central causes of change, the key contextual
tions, and interests reinforced one another to produce factors and political patterns that are likely to generate
a frictionless politics of incremental adjustment and friction in the political environment will be well known
group accommodation, devoid of intense, polarizing, and this is unlikely to be a source of bias in the analysis
and destabilizing institutional or ideological confronta- (see Lustick 1996). Second, the characteristics of the
tions (Bell 1960). But this school of thought lacked the major sources of political order are also well known,
capacity to explain the convulsive changes in American through the extensive literatures on ideas and institu-
politics in the 1960s, such as the civil rights revolution, tions and their effects that I have already discussed. It
which mounted a profound challenge to the pluralist is important to note that the approach I outline here is
picture of order, consensus, and functionality-the type not a substitute for work that theorizes about order or
of untidy change that Truman (1971, xliv, 524) called discerns and explains ordered patterns in the political
(with more than a little horror) "the whirlwind." Even world, whether institutional or ideational. In fact, this
writers in this school who recognized the civil rights synthesis can only build on the advances that have been
challenge, such as Gunnar Myrdal (1944), could not made in the last generation by both institutional and
conceive of racism and segregation as anything other ideational theorists and depends on the continuation
than mistakes, deviations, somehow external to the and expansion of these research programs (see Fiorina
American political tradition (Smith 1993, 1997). But 1996).
an alternative perspective understands the civil rights Thus finding the multiple political orders that com-
transformations of the 1950s and 1960s not as alien to bine and potentially clash to produce change is no great
the American political tradition but as outgrowths of mystery. In general, there will be a finite number of
many of the very ideological and institutional struc- components that will constitute the field of inquiry,
tures that are constitutive of it: an ideology of equal what we might call the dimensions of disorder (or order,
rights;political mobilization and organization; pressure as the case might be). These can be described in three
on policymakers through the courts, electoral politics, clusters, each of which is a familiar presence in political
and other institutional venues, and so forth (Klinkner analysis. The first cluster comprises governing institu-
and Smith 1999; McAdam 1982). In this view, the civil tions, whether the conventional institutions of states
rights revolution arose from a clash among elements (legislatures, executives, courts, bureaucracies), inter-
of the American political system rather than an unex- national organizations, or other governance arrange-
plainable exogenous shock. ments. The second cluster comprises the organizational
The central hypothesis that emerges from this dis- environment, such as political parties and party sys-
cussion is that where friction among multiple political tems, the organization of interests, nongovernmental
orders is more prevalent, the likelihood of significant, organizations, and the like. The third cluster comprises
extraordinary political change (as opposed to normal the ideological and cultural repertoires that organize
variation) will increase. Note that this formulation is and legitimate political discourse.
not necessarily about friction between ideas and in- Each of these sets of factors generates incentives
stitutions, although it may take this form, but about and opportunities and defines repertoires of legitimate
friction among ordered political patterns however con- moves for political actors. Measuring friction, then, is a
stituted,whether institutional or ideational. Institutions matter of deriving, from the historical record, accounts
can clash with each other, as can ideas. The essential of these incentives, opportunities, and repertoires that
point is to decompose the notion of a single, encompass- arise from multiple sources of political order and im-
ing political "order"into its component parts, whatever pinge simultaneously on the same set of actors. What
form they happen to take, to judge the extent to which is important is the "directionality" of these incentives.
they overlap or conflict, and, finally, to assess whether Where they point mostly or predominantly in one direc-
the disjunction among them plausibly generates im- tion, at least for most actors most of the time, the result
portant political change. It is an important advantage will likely be political stability. Friction, on the other
of this approach that it can consider both institutions hand, occurs when they point in substantially differ-
and ideas as building blocks of an explanation for po- ent directions, especially where they subject the same
litical change, but it need not do so if the important sets of actors to conflicting pressures that pose acute
motors of change in a given case fall on one side or dilemmas and make conventional moves untenable. In
other of the ideas-institutions divide. such circumstances, significant political change is more
The challenge of identifying and measuring friction likely to result.
among orders is a serious one. As the pluralism exam- The structure of the multiple-orders argument draws
ple demonstrates, different analysts can find order and significantly on parallels with Paul Pierson's (1993,
disorder in the same material. Most important to the 2000a) work on policy feedback and path dependence.
enterprise is simply the careful historical reconstruction Pierson has called attention to processes by which polit-
of the relevant elements of the political setting of the ical decisions made at particular moments can become
moment under consideration-a policy debate, an era self-reinforcing, making change difficult and costly
in political history, whatever the unit of analysis might even when the policies or institutions become dysfunc-
be. This is not as biased and ad hoc an approach as it tional (North 1990). The causal process in Pierson's
sounds at first blush. First, most episodes of important framework involves the "locking-in" of policies or
political change have already been the subject of vo- other political arrangements through processes of
luminous historical analysis; even if analysts disagree learning, the coordination and organization of political

703
Ideas, Institutions,and Political Order December 2002

activity, and the adaptation of expectations. Political ac- normal order of politics is unsettled rather than change
tors, whose interests and understandings of the political per se. Such friction, it is important to note, need not
world are increasingly likely to be aligned with these actually produce substantial change. The Clinton ad-
arrangements, act to protect them. This approach, with ministration's health policy effort of 1993-94, for exam-
its emphasis on order and regularity,is thus particularly ple, was a moment when a variety of institutional and
successful at explaining the status quo bias of many po- ideological currents-electoral politics, interest-group
litical arrangements, as in Pierson's (1994) own analysis configurations, policy legacies, and ideas flowing from
of the surprising resilience of welfare policies in the the health policy community, among other things-
face of strong political and ideological pressures for combined to make the status quo seem untenable and
retrenchment (Wood 2001). to make dramatic policy innovation seem possible, if
Although the path-dependence framework is espe- not probable (Hacker 1997; Peterson 1998; Skocpol
cially well suited to explaining continuity, its focus on 1996). That Clinton's effort failed does not diminish the
the unfolding of political processes over time draws importance of understanding politics in terms of over-
attention to the particular mechanisms by which polit- lapping orders; rather, it underscores the importance
ical processes reinforce themselves and consequently of identifying such moments of prospective choice and
provide an important opening to the study of politi- opportunity when new directions seem genuinely avail-
cal change (Pierson 2000b; Thelen 1999; Wood 2001). able and tracing the choices actors make under these
In particular, its causal approach-its attention to the circumstances.
incentives, opportunities, and repertoires that prevail- This perspective presents politics as a process that
ing structures construct for political actors-provides may have stable elements but contains within itself
a useful guide to the causal mechanisms that underlie the seeds of change, much like Joseph Schumpeter's
the multiple-orders approach. The causal sequence, in (1950, 83) notion of "creative destruction," which he
which actors adapt to existing political arrangements called "the essential fact about capitalism." In this pic-
and behave in response to them, is parallel, but with ture, Schumpeter argues, "analysis of what happens in
the recognition that at any given moment, politics is any particular part of [the economy]-say, in an in-
situated on multiple "paths,"each of which contributes dividual concern or industry-may clarify details of
to the array of the choices available to actors. When mechanism but is inconclusive beyond that." Similarly,
these paths are consonant with one another, when they the multiple-orders approach suggests that political life
point actors in complementary directions, the result thus rarely settles into stable patterns that persist un-
may be stability and incrementalism; when they are changing for long periods; rather, it may be more fruit-
not, rather than self-reinforcing patterns of "lock-in," ful to regard politics in terms of systems, as Robert
the result will more likely be instability and uncertainty Jervis (1997) argues, in which multiple sets of intercon-
among actors about how to formulate and pursue their nected relational patterns interact. Analytically, this
political aims. turn suggests a move toward a more configurative and
Thus the causal mechanism linking structural fric- relational approach to political change, which focuses
tion and political change is the reformulation of the "less on the causal importance of this or that vari-
incentives and opportunities for individual political able contrasted with others but more on how variables
action that friction produces-the discontinuities be- are joined together in specific historical circumstances"
tween the expectations generated by the "orders" con- (Katznelson 1997, 99).
sidered individually and new opportunities presented Much path-breaking work on political change takes
by the "system" (conceived as a complex of individual something like this approach. In his important account
"orders"). When stable patterns of politics clash, pur- of changing institutional rules in the U.S. Congress,
posive political actors will often find themselves at an Eric Schickler (2001) develops a model of "disjointed
impasse, unable to proceed according to the "normal" pluralism," in which different interests drive the
patterns and processes that had hitherto governed their process of building coalitions for congressional reform
behavior. Political ideas and interests that had formerly at different times, and various reforms adopted to serve
prevailed might no longer find outlets in the same in- different purposes are layered atop one another. "By
stitutional settings, or institutions might no longer be disjointed," he writes, "I mean that the dynamics of
able to resolve (or even paper over) clashes of ideas as institutional development derive from the interactions
before. Political actors in such circumstances will often and tensions among competing coalitions promoting
be induced to find new ways to define and advance their several different interests. These interactions and
aims, whether by finding a new institutional forum that tensions are played out when members of Congress
is more receptive to their ideas or by adapting ideas to adopt a single institutional change, and over time
take advantage of new institutional opportunities. The as legislative organization develops through the
result of these moves is not that old orders are jetti- accumulation of innovations, each sought by a different
soned but that elements of them are recombined and coalition promoting a different interest" (Schickler
reconfigured into a new set of political patterns that is 2001, 4; original emphasis). The result is a dynamic
recognizably new and yet retains some continuity with process of reform and development, in which members
the old ones (much as Tocqueville [1955] described the of Congress continually find themselves dissatisfied
aftermath of the French Revolution). with their institutional setting, but for shifting reasons
One key to this explanatory strategy is the open- as both interests and institutions evolve. No reform
ness and unpredictability of these moments when the is ever complete in that it does not sweep away old

704
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4

rules to create a new, self-contained,coherent order, the act's passage, the United States had adopted just
and it is the constant friction among procedural this approach, having developed an extensive set of
rules, organizationalstructure,and members' goals race-conscious, group-based policies and practices that
that drivesthe developmentalprocessforward. offer compensatory advantages to members of histor-
Severalrecentworksin the ideationalcampalsotake ically or currently disadvantaged groups-known col-
this approach(although rather less self-consciously). lectively as affirmative action.
In his accountof the transitionfrom Keynesianismto This transition, from a convergence on color-
monetarismin Britain, Peter Hall (1993) shows how blindness to an embrace of race-conscious remedies
a process of social learning created friction not just for discrimination (ambivalent and controversial, to be
withinthe Keynesianparadigmthat dominatedpolicy sure), poses a sharp challenge for both ideational and
but between the shiftingideologicalmilieu and the in- institutional explanatory approaches. Color-blindness,
stitutionalstructureof Britisheconomicpolicymaking. as John Skrentny (1996) has pointed out, is part of
What made the ideological drift from Keynesianism the taken-for-granted ideological and cultural fabric of
toward monetarismparticularlyinfluentialin funda- American political life: the principle that individuals
mentallyremakingpolicy was not just the ideological should be judged and afforded opportunity without
triumph of a new paradigmbut the difficultiesthat reference to their race (or any other irrelevant char-
ideational change posed for institutionalactors-the acteristic). How, then, did American policy effectively
Treasury,the Bank of England,the Cabinet.Similarly, turn away from this powerful idea and embrace its op-
KathleenMcNamara(1998) locates the causes for the posite, even after major legislation effectively affirmed
success of monetaryunion in Europe at the intersec- and institutionalized the notion of color-blindness in
tion of shiftingpolicyideas and the increasinglybrittle national policy (Burstein 1985)? At the same time, the
structureof internationaleconomicinstitutions.These agency created to enforce the Civil Rights Act's vision
worksshowhow the disjunctionamongdifferentlycon- of color-blind policy-the Equal Employment Oppor-
stituted political orders, both ideational and institu- tunity Commission (EEOC)-was given no effective
tional, can driveprocessesof politicaldevelopment. enforcement power and was relegated to a sideline role
as conciliator and investigator. It could neither order
remedies for discrimination nor file lawsuits. Moreover,
IDEASAND INSTITUTIONS
INAMERICAN the EEOC was embedded in a fragmented and decen-
RACEPOLICY tralized state that frustrated the aims of civil rights ad-
vocates who sought vigorous enforcement. And yet the
As an illustrationof how the overlayof ideologicaland "weak" American state not only proved surprisingly
institutionalpatterns can generate dramaticand un- effective at devising means of enforcing antidiscrimina-
expected political change, I sketch an example from tion law, but also managed to challenge the color-blind
American political development, the history of race presumptions of its own law and to forge an extensive
policy in the United Statesin the 1960sand 1970s.The network of race-conscious policies and practices that
trajectoryof racepolicyprovidesampledemonstration have proven strikingly resilient in the face of political
of the potential of a multiple-ordersapproachto ex- and legal challenges.
plain outcomes that seem to defy analysisin terms of Analytically, then, the puzzle is that neither ideas
stability and order. In this section, I begin by outlin- (the apparent triumph of color-blindness in 1964) nor
ing the puzzle that civil rightspolicy presents,namely, institutions (the apparent weakness of the civil rights
the surprisingemergenceof affirmativeaction. I then enforcement apparatus) predict the emergence of af-
sketch the institutionaland ideological contexts that firmative action in any kind of way that makes sense.
seemed to make this developmentunlikely.Finally,I Neither approach even comes close; both would lead us
show how affirmativeaction arose out of the tension to expect anemic enforcement, color-blindness because
createdby this particularconfigurationof elementsby it rules out collective, compensatory hiring policies and
inducingactorsto behavein waysthatdefiedthe expec- institutional weakness because it leaves the state with
tationsof more linearmodels of policy development. little or no coercive power to enforce the law. In statis-
The Civil Rights Act of 1964 adopted an explicitly tical parlance, the signs on the parameters are wrong.
color-blind approach to prohibiting racial discrimina- Answering this puzzle thus demands a perspective
tion in employment: Title VII of the act outlawed de- that can account for the development of rather dra-
liberate, individual acts of discrimination such as the matic change out of political elements that seem to
refusal to hire or promote individuals because of their point toward stability. The development of civil rights
race. In doing so, the act appeared explicitly to rule out policy was situated in several ideational and institu-
an alternative, race- and group-conscious approach to tional orders simultaneously. Ideologically, the debates
recognizing and remedying discrimination in the work- over civil rights represented the culmination of a long-
place. It refused to recognize so-called "statistical dis- standing debate in American political and intellectual
crimination" (the inference of discrimination from the life between color-blind and race-conscious visions of
mismatch between an employers' proportion of minor- American society. On one hand, the American liberal
ity employees and the proportion of minorities in the tradition demanded color-blindness-the idea that race
local labor force) and refused to sanction group-based is irrelevant to citizenship and that the law, the state,
remedies for discrimination, such as targets or quotas and public policy should make no distinctions between
for the hiring of minorities. And yet within 10 years of persons on account of skin color. The color-blind vision

705
Ideas, Institutions,and Political Order December 2002

of civil rights policy invoked the deeply rooted tradi- pivotal position in the policymaking process (Carmines
tions of individual rights and equality before the law and Stimson 1989; Katznelson, Geiger, and Kryder
(Skrentny 1996, 7). This idea has a long intellectual lin- 1993). These characteristics of congressional and par-
eage in civil rights policy, dating at least to 1896, when tisan politics underscored a deep sectional split that
Justice John Marshall Harlan wrote in his dissent in had long been a central structural feature of American
Plessy v. Ferguson (1896, 559) that "our Constitution politics and prevented Congress from passing any civil
is color-blind, and neither knows nor tolerates classes rights legislation from 1875 until 1957 (Bensel 1984;
among citizens. In respect of civil rights, all citizens are Key 1949). Third, civil rights policy was made in the
equal before the law." But Harlan wrote as the lone context of a chronically weak and fragmented state,
voice against a decision that, in fact, validated an alter- in which civil rights authority, such as it was, was
native vision of civil rights policy, an ascriptive tradi- already divided among a number of different adminis-
tion of racism that had long challenged liberalism for trative agencies, most of whom lacked coercive author-
ascendancy in American politics (Smith 1997). In this ity. Moreover, the federal civil rights establishment was
view, race was not only a legitimate but an essential steeped in the color-blind model of antidiscrimination
political category, and in Plessy's wake racial distinc- policy (Skrentny 1996, 34). These institutional factors
tions could be (and were frequently) invoked to protect did not augur well for significant change in civil rights
white supremacy and state-sponsored segregation. policy; rather, they tended to pull policy toward the
Not surprisingly, the race-conscious ideological tra- status quo or, at least, to foreclose all but incremental
dition was not popular among civil rights advocates for moves toward color-blindness.
much of the twentieth century. But in debates over Two other elements of the institutional context, how-
how to prevent racial discrimination in such spheres ever, looked more promising. The first was the cycli-
as education, commerce, and employment, it became cal pattern of American presidential elections. Both
increasingly clear that a straightforward color-blind Kennedy and then Lyndon Johnson needed to balance
approach would not suffice, because in any context, the electoral demands of Southern whites and North-
simply treating race as irrelevant would not outweigh ern blacks, each of whom was an essential piece of the
the effects of past discrimination that left many, if not Democratic coalition. Consequently, civil rights leg-
most, African-Americans ill equipped to take advan- islation posed both challenges and opportunities for
tage of the opportunities that color-blindness might building a reelection coalition in 1964 (Miroff 1981).
offer. Beginning in the 1940s with the Fair Employ- Civil rights posed similar challenges and opportunities
ment Practices Commission and continuing through the for Richard Nixon in his own presidential bids, as he
1950s, civil rights advocates and public officials con- sought to pry the South loose from the Democrats'
cerned with racial equality began to debate whether grip while also competing for minority votes (Frymer
race-conscious means were necessary to achieve man- and Skrentny 1998). For all of these presidents, civil
ifestly color-blind ends (Burstein 1985; King 1995, rights offered an opportunity for distinctive and bold
208-9; Kryder 2000, 88-132; Skrentny 1996, 114-17). action, although one that had to be handled gingerly
This dilemma found felicitous expression in the phrase (Skowronek 1993). The second such factor, and what
"affirmative action," which was included almost casu- made civil rights an irresistible political force for these
ally in an executive order issued by President John presidents, was the civil rights movement, which em-
E Kennedy in March 1961. The phrase was intended braced race-consciousness in a double sense, both em-
not to supplant the order's fundamentally color-blind bodying it in its embrace of race as a collective political
purpose (to ensure nondiscrimination by federal gov- identity and championing it as a policy paradigm.
ernment contractors) but to supplement it, indicating The conflict and ambivalence among these contend-
vaguely that employers ought to take extra steps to ing institutional and ideological forces, particularly
ensure that hiring was not biased but not indicating between color-blind and race-conscious visions of an-
how they were to go about this (Graham 1990, 40-43; tidiscrimination policy, were played out first in con-
Kennedy 1961; Skrentny 1996, 114). Thus the debate gressional deliberations over the Civil Rights Act of
surrounding the Civil Rights Act occurred on ideolog- 1964. Civil rights advocates embraced a policy vision
ical terrain defined by two competing paradigms, each that coupled a race-conscious approach with strong
of which had a deep intellectual legacy as well as insti- regulatory enforcement by the federal government by
tutionally powerful proponents. creating a new agency with the power to uncover and
These debates took place in several nested institu- prohibit broad patterns of discrimination by employ-
tional settings. They were played out, first, in a Congress ers. This approach was opposed not only by Southern
still dominated, as it had been for much of the twenti- Democrats, who were almost-unanimous in their unal-
eth century, by Southern Democrats, who wielded dis- terable opposition to any federal action on civil rights,
proportionate power through a variety of procedural but also by Republicans, who mistrusted the expansion
and organizational mechanisms (such as the filibuster of state power it entailed, and the Kennedy adminis-
in the Senate) and who were by and large committed tration, which could ill afford to alienate the South.
to protecting their region's autonomy in racial matters A somewhat stripped-down bill passed the House in
(Key 1949). Second, they were shaped by a party sys- February 1964, only to run into a three-month fili-
tem in which race was playing an ever-growing role. buster in the Senate. The act's final form was the prod-
In particular, the Democratic party was increasingly uct of a compromise between Senate Republicans and
divided over civil rights, leaving Republicans in the Northern Democrats, with the blessing of the Johnson

706
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4

administration. The compromise, brokered by Senate among others. The model of enforcement implied by
minority leader Everett Dirksen, resolved both the the law's color-blind ideological approach was one of
ideological and the institutional questions that were retrospective judgment, in which deliberate individual
at the center of the debate. Ideologically, the Dirksen acts of discrimination could be adjudicated and pun-
compromise fell squarely in the color-blind camp, defin- ished after the fact. But-and here is the critical source
ing discrimination as a deliberate individual act and ap- of friction in the civil rights enforcement regime-the
parently explicitly ruling out collective, race-conscious law did not throw the state's institutional weight be-
remedies. Institutionally, the compromise substantially hind this enforcement model: The EEOC could in-
hollowed out the enforcement authority of the new vestigate and conciliate in individual cases; the Justice
EEOC (Graham 1990). Department could bring lawsuits, but only in "pattern-
Although the Civil Rights Act certainly counts as or-practice" cases where it could document systematic,
dramatic political change, it was in many ways conso- rather than simply individual, discrimination; and, after
nant with much that had come before, both in its em- Johnson's Executive Order 11246 in 1965, the Labor
brace of color-blindness and in its withholding of strong Department could threaten to rescind federal contracts
coercive enforcement power from the state. Moreover, when it could document discrimination (Graham 1990,
by establishing an apparently consistent and coherent 180-87; Johnson 1965; Skrentny 1996, 133-34). No arm
set of ideological and institutional parameters for civil of the federal government possessed the power to en-
rights policy, it seemed poised to lock antidiscrimina- force the central employment discrimination aim of the
tion enforcement into a pattern of weak enforcement. Civil Rights Act. Color-blind antidiscrimination policy,
Looking at the situation prospectively from the vantage focused on punishing particular individual instances of
point of 1964, there are several compelling institutional discrimination by employers, failed to take hold not pri-
and ideational reasons to expect this outcome. First was marily because of a lack of consensus on color-blindness
the lack of state power. The EEOC could neither order as a goal but because the institutional setting of civil
employers not to discriminate nor sue them. The sec- rights enforcement efforts provided weak support for
ond was the fragmentation of state power. The EEOC this model.
was only one among a veritable alphabet soup of civil More particularly,this mismatch between the ideol-
rights agencies in the federal government, each with ogy embedded in the Civil Rights Act and the institu-
its own turf and resources. It was, like all federal agen- tional capacity that it created affected the incentives
cies, subject to the oversight of both the president and and opportunities of political actors in the civil rights
Congress, which remained subject to the same electoral field. For presidents, first Johnson and then Richard
and partisan forces that had produced the compromise Nixon, it posed a political dilemma. Vigorous enforce-
in the first place. A result of ineffectual bureaucratic ment would please the act's supporters and assuage
enforcement subject to contending interests and politi- the still vigorous forces of the civil rights movement
cal interference would not have been at all inconsistent but would displease Johnson's fellow Southerners and
with other regulatory initiatives in this period, as insti- other skeptics of strong state civil rights authority. On
tutional theory has frequently confirmed (Fiorina 1977; the other hand, a White House task force in June
Moe 1987, 1989). Finally, the Civil Rights Act insti- 1964 doubted "that the bill will make for sufficient
tutionalized color-blindness, writing its presumptions or sufficiently rapid progress as far as the Negro and
quite explicitly into the law. Both the institutional and a good part of the white community is concerned
the ideational settlements of 1964 seemed to create a to placate the forces that have gathered over the
new status quo, a new equilibrium, that would carry for- past years."6 The Johnson administration responded
ward, and analytical perspectives that emphasize either by temporizing--first by delaying appointing EEOC
institutions or ideas as constraints on political behav- commissioners, then by only half-heartedly supporting
ior or on ordered patterns in political life would expect moves in Congress to expand the EEOC's power, and,
this equilibrium to endure. None of these factors points finally, by developing and then shelving a plan to re-
toward the emergence of a strong, race-conscious an- quire minority hiring targets of federal contractors (the
tidiscrimination enforcement mechanism. "Philadelphia Plan") (Graham 1990, 177-79, 278-97).7
And yet emerge it did. The momentary resolution Nixon faced a similar dilemma. On one hand,
embodied by the Dirksen compromise generated fric- he hoped to pursue a "Southern strategy," winning
tion among its ideological and institutional elements traditionally Democratic white Southern votes. On
that deflected antidiscrimination policy from the path the other hand, he had to do something; he could
it seemed most likely to take. In particular, the Dirksen not ignore the prevailing (if precarious) civil rights
compromise produced a critical mismatch between the
ideological underpinnings of antidiscrimination policy 6 Task Force Issue
and the institutional capacity created to enforce it. In Paper, Civil Rights, 17 June 1964, Office Files of
Lee C. White, Box 3, Lyndon B. Johnson Library (hereafter cited as
general, this friction arose because, despite the com- LBJL).
promise, the Civil Rights Act established strong ex- 7 Memorandum, Lee C. White to Johnson, 28 September 1964, LE,
pectations that the federal government would act to White House Central File, Box 167, LBJL; Memorandum, Lee C.
combat employment discrimination, expectations that White to Johnson, 5 October 1965, Civil Rights during the Johnson
Administration, 1963-1969: A Collection from the Holdings of the
shaped the outlooks and interests of presidents and Lyndon Baines Johnson Library, part 1, reel 5; Memorandum,
members of Congress, bureaucrats in the EEOC and Ramsey Clark to Joseph Califano, 1966 Task Force Report, Legisla-
elsewhere, and advocates in the civil rights movement, tive Background, Civil Rights Act of 1964, LBJL.

707
Ideas, Institutions,and Political Order December 2002

consensus in the rest of the country by burying the of affirmative action in the form of the same kind of
problems of employment discrimination enforcement hiring targets imposed by the Philadelphia Plan. In
(see Skowronek 1993). Although given the party's right particular, these groups were equipped to undertake
turn on civil rights in the early 1960s a Republican the fight for affirmative action on the local level. De-
administration was perhaps an unlikely champion of spite the mass national mobilization that characterized
strong federal enforcement, Nixon had in fact long wor- the civil rights era, the attempts to bypass the perva-
ried that the United States's record on race relations sive localism of African-American politics-in the civil
weakened its international position in the Cold War rights movement, the War on Poverty, and the courts-
(Dudziak 2000). He opposed expanding the EEOC's did not ultimately forge firm political links between
power and eventually engineered and signed compro- African-Americans and the national state. Despite (or
mise legislation in 1972 that gave it the power to file law- perhaps because of) overwhelming electoral support
suits (although not to issue regulatory cease-and-desist for Democratic candidates, African-Americans found
orders). Most important, however, Nixon resurrected themselves political captives of an increasingly in-
the Philadelphia Plan, throwing the weight of the exec- different party at the national level (Frymer 1999).
utive branch behind race-conscious antidiscrimination Instead, African-American political organization flour-
policy with the power of coercive sanctions behind it ished at the local level in the late 1960s and early
(Skrentny 1996, 137-39, 193-211). This move-a form 1970s, continuing the traditional pattern of linkages be-
of affirmative action as we know it today-allowed tween African-Americans and the state. But whereas
Nixon to support enforcement efforts in the North these historical patterns of diffusion, decentralization,
while soft-pedaling the issue in the South (where he was and local attachment had long been sources of weak-
simultaneously winning credit with his vigorous oppo- ness for the political fortunes of African-Americans,
sition to school busing) and to drive a wedge between in the present context they were, ironically, sources of
African-Americans and labor unions, two pillars of the strength. In particular, federated organizations such as
Democratic party's constituency. It thus proved an apt the NAACP and its Legal Defense Fund could col-
vehicle for Nixon to negotiate his complex partisan, laborate with the EEOC in pursuing race-conscious
sectional, and electoral situation. remedies for employment discrimination in a variety
For other actors as well, the ideological-institutional of local-level forums (Greenstone and Peterson 1973;
mismatch of the new civil rights regime presented op- Lieberman 1998;Morone 1990, chap. 6; Skocpol, Ganz,
portunities as well as constraints. The unfortunate exec- and Munson 2000).
utives and bureaucrats of the EEOC found themselves The principal institutional arenas for these activi-
in a nearly impossible position. Expected to enforce the ties were collective bargaining between union locals
law but left essentially powerless to do so, the EEOC and employers and lawsuits in the federal courts; both
had to find other outlets to fulfill its enforcement mis- of these arenas allowed the EEOC to get around its
sion. These institutional limitations, however, proved a lack of coercive authority. In particular, the EEOC's
double-edged sword. On one hand, the EEOC's rela- relationship with the federal courts (especially after
tive weakness and political vulnerability reflected the the 1972 amendments) proved empowering, because
general limits on administrative power in American it gave the commission access to a politically and or-
government. On the other hand, these very same in- ganizationally independent means of deciding discrim-
stitutional constraints created a great deal of slack in ination cases and enforcing remedies. It was by these
the commission's political and administrative environ- alternative routes that the EEOC became a key player
ment. Limits on its power forced it to seek other means in subverting the very color-blind model of race policy
of influence, particularly by collaborating with other that it had been created to enforce. It held hearings to
institutions, both inside and outside the state. This im- publicize egregious cases of discrimination, pressuring
perative drove the problem of antidiscrimination en- employers to change their personnel practices. It par-
forcement into the same fragmented and decentralized ticipated with the NAACP and other civil rights organi-
political arena that had produced the EEOC's incapac- zations in precedent-setting antidiscrimination actions
ity in the first place. The struggle for enforcement would in labor negotiations and the federal courts that shaped
be fought out not in terms of administrative power antidiscrimination practices in a wide swath of Ameri-
emanating from Washington but in multiple arenas can industry. The EEOC, for example, played a central
and jurisdictions around the country. In this context, role in Griggs v. Duke Power Company (1971), the case
the EEOC sought to play what role and forge what in which the Supreme Court ruled that employers could
alliances it could as it sought pragmatic rather than ide- not use even ostensibly race-neutral tests or other oc-
ological or coercive solutions to the problem of fulfill- cupational qualifications that tend disproportionately
ing its mandate in constrained environment (Skrentny to bar minority applicants, unless the employer could
1996, chap. 5). show that they were a bona fide qualification for the
In moving away from its prescribed institutional job in question (Graham 1990, 383-90; Stein 1998).
role, the EEOC was also led to move away from the Like the presidential initiatives designed to cut through
color-blind model of antidiscrimination enforcement. the ideological and institutional confusion engendered
Among the EEOC's key partners in this endeavor were by the Civil Rights Act, these moves contributed
African-Americans themselves, especially groups such to the unraveling of the color-blind consensus and
as the NAACP that were important proponents of race- the consolidation of a race-conscious policy approach
conscious approaches to civil rights policy, particularly backed powerfully by the state by the early 1970s, an

708
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4

outcome that had seemed most improbable only a ideological and institutional orders and thus push for-
decade earlier. ward the dynamic processes of political change.
The civil rights story underscores the fundamental
point-that neither ideas nor institutions can rightly
CONCLUSIONS claim priority in an account that purports to explain
significant political change (or even to describe it in
This history suggests that the answer to the problem of a richly complex enough way to make a convincing,
understanding puzzling change in American race policy theoretically grounded explanation possible). What has
lies at the intersection of ideas and institutions and in changed, after all, in the civil rights story is not simply
the tension between ideological traditions and institu- the values of a group of right-hand-side independent
tional capacities. In the case of American race policy, variables-public opinion about segregation, say, or the
the Civil Rights Act seemed to embody a particularide- strength of the civil rights movement, or the level of
ological approach to racial inequality, but the institu- interracial economic competition-resulting in a pre-
tional incentives and opportunities in which key actors dictable change (within standard tolerances) of the
were embedded allowed them to mount a challenge to left-hand-side dependent variable-antidiscrimination
this approach even while claiming to maintain it (and policy.
possibly even believing they were doing so). In fact, had Rather, what has changed is the very relationships
the EEOC been given greater coercive powers at the among factors that and the processes by which a set
outset to enforce the color-blind vision of antidiscrim- of underlying conditions generates outcomes. The evo-
ination law, it is likely that the impulse for affirmative lution of race-conscious affirmative action out of the
action would have been weaker, because the EEOC color-blind premises of the Civil Rights Act resulted
would have turned its attention to an apparently more not simply from the marginal adjustment of a set of
fruitful set of tasks. independent variables producing linear policy effects,
More generally, this analysis suggests that public but from an entirely new configuration of mostly famil-
policies are most fruitfully understood as the results iar elements-the same elements, in fact, that helped to
of political conflicts in which particular elements of shape the Civil Rights Act itself: ambivalence and con-
national cultural and ideological repertoires are mo- tention over color-blindness and race-consciousness as
bilized and enacted into policy. These political strug- ideological models for race policy, and fragmented and
gles take place within historical and institutional con- decentralized political institutions. Neither ideas nor
texts that define the allocation and exercise of political institutions alone are sufficient to explain the trajectory
power and so shape policymaking, especially by con- of American race policy in the 1960s and 1970s. But
straining political behavior through the operation of the configuration of these two elements together en-
rules, norms, and organizational settings (Thelen and abled pragmatic but principled politicians, bureaucrats,
Steinmo 1992). At the same time, institutions also cre- lawyers, civil rights leaders, union leaders, corporate
ate strategic opportunities for purposive political actors executives, and others to grope toward a set of prac-
to further their interests, and they shape political oppor- tices that amounted to a fundamental transformation
tunities for the mobilization of social interests (Tarrow in race policy in a decade or so, one that embraced
1994). Similarly,political ideas and cultural traditions-- race-conscious employment practices and strong state
institutionalized, taken-for-granted understandings of action and one that deeply penetrated the state and
political and social arrangements-also constrain and civil society (Dobbin and Sutton 1998; Farhang 2001;
enable policymaking, both by limiting the range of poli- Graham 1990; Skrentny 1996; Stein 1998).
cies that are considered rational and by giving poli- So when does an idea's time come? The answer lies in
cymakers a repertoire of legitimating tactics for their the match between idea and moment. An idea's time
favored policies (Campbell 1998; Dobbin 1994; Hall arrives not simply because the idea is compelling on
and Taylor 1996; Powell and DiMaggio 1991). its own terms, but because opportune political circum-
National political structures thus shape policy out- stances favor it. At those moments when a political
comes not simply by organizing power but also by idea finds persuasive expression among actors whose
acting as gatekeepers for political ideas and cultural institutional position gives them both the motive and
dispositions. Policymaking in democratic government the opportunity to translate it into policy-then, and
is not simply a process of optimizing the choice of only then, can we say that an idea has found a time.
policy instruments to solve readily identifiable social This is not a story of variables but of configura-
problems (Kingdon 1984; Lindblom 1959; Stone 1997). tion, not of ordered patterns of ideas or institutions
Rather, it entails the formation of coalitions among ac- in equilibrium, but of disjunction, friction, and overlap
tors who represent both interests vying for power and among ideational and institutional elements, none of
diverse policy ideas. Because this coalition-building which is sufficient but each of which is necessary for
process combines what Hugh Heclo (1974, 305-6) has a more comprehensive explanation of an important
called "powering" and "puzzling"-clashes of both episode of political change. It suggests the potential
power and culture among social interests-the results power, even the necessity, of an approach that consid-
it produces are not necessarily coherent and orderly ers both institutions and ideas as integral to political
but rather tend to build on prior policies without clear- explanation and it underscores the importance of un-
ing away or dismantling them. The very process of derstanding the ways in which they interact to produce
policymaking can perpetuate the system of clashing outcomes that, from either partial perspective, seem

709
Ideas, Institutions,and Political Order December 2002

unpredictable. Above all, it shows off the advantages Fiorina, Morris P. 1977. Congress, Keystone of the Washington Estab-
of an approach that relaxes considerably the traditional lishment. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
social-scientific emphasis on order and embraces what Fiorina, Morris P. 1996. "Looking for Disagreement in All the Wrong
Places." In Nomos XXXVIII: Political Order, ed. Ian Shapiro and
Lionel Trilling (1950, 10), perhaps one of the more Russell Hardin. New York: New York University Press.
unexpected prophets of American social science but Frymer, Paul. 1999. Uneasy Alliances: Race and Party Competition in
a shrewd commentator on the American liberal tra- America. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
dition, called "variousness, possibility, complexity, and Frymer, Paul, and John David Skrentny. 1998. "Coalition-Building
and the Politics of Electoral Capture during the Nixon Adminis-
difficulty." tration: African Americans, Labor, Latinos." Studies in American
Political Development 12 (Spring): 131-61.
Garrett, Geoffrey, and Barry R. Weingast. 1993. "Ideas, Interests,
REFERENCES and Institutions: Constructing the European Community's Inter-
nal Market." In Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions, and
Abrams v. United States. 1919. 250 U.S. 616. Political Change, ed. Judith Goldstein and Robert O. Keohane.
Almond, Gabriel A., and James S. Coleman. 1960. The Politics of the Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Developing Areas. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Geertz, Clifford. 1964. "Ideology As a Cultural System." In Ide-
Anderson, Lisa. N.d. The Scholar and the Practitioner:Perspectiveson ology and Discontent, ed. David Apter. Glencoe, IL: Free
Social Science and Public Policy. New York: Columbia University Press.
Press. Forthcoming. Geertz, Clifford. 1973. "Thick Description: Toward an Interpretive
Bailyn, Bernard. 1967. The Ideological Origins of the American Rev- Theory of Culture." In The Interpretation of Cultures. New York:
olution. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Basic Books.
Bates, Robert H., Rui J. P. de Figueiredo Jr., and Barry R. Graham, Hugh Davis. 1990. The Civil Rights Era: Origins and Devel-
Weingast. 1998. "The Politics of Interpretation: Rationality, Cul- opment of National Policy, 1960-1972. New York: Oxford Univer-
ture, and Transition."Politics and Society 26 (June): 221-56. sity Press.
Baumgartner, Frank R., and Bryan D. Jones. 1993. Agendas and In- Greenstone, J. David. 1993. The Lincoln Persuasion: Remak-
stability in American Politics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ing American Liberalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Bell, Daniel. 1960. The End of Ideology: On the Exhaustion of Polit- Press.
ical Ideas in the Fifties. Glencoe, IL: Free Press. Greenstone, J. David, and Paul E. Peterson. 1973. Race and Authority
Bensel, Richard Franklin. 1984. Sectionalism and American Political in Urban Politics: Community Participationand the Waron Poverty.
Development: 1880-1980. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.
Berman, Sheri. 1998. The Social Democratic Moment: Ideas and Pol- Griggs v. Duke Power Company. 1971. 401 U.S. 424.
itics in the Making of Interwar Europe. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Hacker, Jacob S. 1997. The Road to Nowhere: The Genesis of Pres-
University Press. ident Clinton's Plan for Health Security. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
Berman, Sheri. 2001. "Ideas, Norms, and Culture in Political Analy- University Press.
sis." Comparative Politics 33 (January): 231-50. Hall, Peter A., ed. 1989. The Political Power of Economic Ideas:
Black, Duncan. 1958. The Theory of Committees and Elections. Keynesianism across Nations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Press.
Blyth, Mark M. 1997. "'Any More Bright Ideas?': The Ideational Hall, Peter A. 1993. "Policy Paradigms, Social Learning and the State:
Turn of Comparative Political Economy." Comparative Politics 29 The Case of Economic Policymaking in Britain." Comparative Pol-
(January):229-50. itics 25 (April): 275-96.
Burstein, Paul. 1985. Discrimination, Jobs, and Politics: The Struggle Hall, Peter A. 1997. "The Role of Interests, Institutions, and
for Equal Employment Opportunity in the United States since the Ideas in the Comparative Political Economy of the Industrialized
New Deal. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Nations." In Comparative Politics: Rationality, Culture, and
Cameron, Charles M. 2000. Veto Bargaining: Presidents and the Pol- Structure, ed. Mark Irving Lichbach and Alan S. Zuckerman.
itics of Negative Power. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Campbell, John L. 1998. "Institutional Analysis and the Role of Ideas Hall, Peter A., and Rosemary C. R. Taylor. 1996. "Political
in Political Economy." Theory and Society 27 (June): 377-409. Science and the Three New Institutionalisms." Political Studies 44
Campbell, John L., and Ove K. Pedersen. 2001a. "The Rise of Ne- (December): 936-57.
oliberalism and Institutional Analysis." In The Rise of Neoliberal- Hartz, Louis. 1955. The Liberal Tradition in America: An Interpre-
ism and Institutional Analysis, ed. John. L. Campbell and Ove K. tation of American Political Thought Since the Revolution. New
Pedersen. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. York: Harcourt, Brace.
Campbell, John L., and Ove K. Pedersen, eds. 2001b. The Rise of Heclo, Hugh. 1974. Modern Social Politics in Britain and Sweden.
Neoliberalism and Institutional Analysis. Princeton, NJ: Princeton New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
University Press. Hofstadter, Richard. 1948. The American Political Traditionand the
Carmines, Edward G., and James A. Stimson. 1989. Issue Evolution: Men Who Made It. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Race and the Transformation of American Politics. Princeton, NJ: Hugo, Victor. 1987. (Euvres completes: Histoires. Paris: Robert
Princeton University Press. Laffont.
Congressional Record. 1964. 88th Cong., 2d sess, Vol. 110, pt. 10. Huntington, Samuel P. 1968. Political Order in Changing Societies.
Dobbin, Frank. 1994. Forging Industrial Policy: The United States, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Britain, and France in the Railway Age. Cambridge: Cambridge Huntington, Samuel P 1981. American Politics: The Promise of
University Press. Disharmony. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Dobbin, Frank, and John R. Sutton. 1998. "The Strength of a Immergut, Ellen M. 1998. "The Theoretical Core of the New Insti-
Weak State: The Rights Revolution and the Rise of Human Re- tutionalism." Politics and Society 26 (March): 5-34.
sources Management Divisions." American Journal of Sociology Inglehart, Ronald. 1997. Modernization and Postmodernization: Cul-
104 (September): 441-76. tural, Economic, and Political Change in 43 Societies. Princeton, NJ:
Downs, Anthony. 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New Princeton University Press.
York: Harper & Row. Jervis,Robert. 1997. System Effects: Complexity in Political and Social
Dudziak, Mary L. 2000. Cold WarCivil Rights: Race and the Image of Life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
American Democracy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Johnson, Lyndon B. 1965. Executive Order 11246. Federal Register
Eckstein, Harry. 1988. "A Culturalist Theory of Political Change." 30: 12319.
American Political Science Review 82 (September): 789-804. Katznelson, Ira. 1997. "Structure and Configuration in Compara-
Farhang, Sean. 2001. "The Private Enforcement of Public Laws: The tive Politics." In Comparative Politics: Rationality, Culture, and
Effects of Private Equal Opportunity Litigation." Presented to the Structure, ed. Mark Irving Lichbach and Alan S. Zuckerman.
American Political Science Association, San Francisco. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

710
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4

Katznelson, Ira, Kim Geiger, and Daniel Kryder. 1993. "Limiting Orren, Karen. 1996b. "Reply to Rogers Smith." Journal of Policy
Liberalism: The Southern Veto in Congress, 1933-1950." Political History 8 (4): 491-94.
Science Quarterly 108 (Summer): 283-306. Orren, Karen, and Stephen Skowronek. 1994. "Beyond the Iconog-
Kennedy, John F 1961. Executive Order 10925. Federal Register 26: raphy of Order: Notes for a 'New Institutionalism."' In The Dy-
1977. namics of American Politics: Approaches and Interpretations, ed.
Key, V. O., Jr. 1949. Southern Politics in State and Nation. New York: Lawrence C. Dodd and Calvin Jillson. Boulder, CO: Westview
Alfred A. Knopf. Press.
King, Anthony. 1973. "Ideas, Institutions, and the Policies of Orren, Karen, and Stephen Skowronek. 1996. "Institutions and In-
Governments: A Comparative Analysis." British Journal of Po- tercurrence: Theory Building in the Fullness of Time." In Nomos
litical Science 3 (July and October): 291-313, 409-23. XXXVIII: Political Order, ed. Ian Shapiro and Russell Hardin.
King, Desmond. 1995. Separate and Unequal: Black Americans and New York: New York University Press.
the US Federal Government. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Orren, Karen, and Stephen Skowronek. 1999. "In Search of Political
King, Desmond. 2000. Making Americans: Immigration, Race, and Development." In The Liberal Tradition in American Politics: Re-
the Origins of the Diverse Democracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard assessing the Legacy of American Liberalism, ed. David E Ericson
University Press. and Louisa Bertch Green. New York: Routledge.
King, Gary, Robert O. Keohane, and Sidney Verba. 1994. Design- Peterson, Mark A. 1998. "The Politics of Health Care Policy: Over-
ing Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative Research. reaching in an Age of Polarization." In The Social Divide: Political
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Parties and the Future of Activist Government, ed. Margaret Weir.
Kingdon, John W. 1984. Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
Glenview, IL: Scott, Foresman. Pierson, Paul. 1993. "When Effect Becomes Cause: Policy Feedback
Klinkner, Philip A., with Rogers M. Smith. 1999. The Unsteady and Political Change." World Politics 45 (July): 595-628.
March: The Rise and Decline of Racial Equality in America. Pierson, Paul. 1994. Dismantling the Welfare State?: Reagan,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Thatcher,and the Politics of Retrenchment.Cambridge: Cambridge
Krehbiel, Keith. 1988. "Spatial Models of Legislative Choice." Leg- University Press.
islative Studies Quarterly 13 (August): 259-319. Pierson, Paul. 2000a. "Increasing Returns, Path Dependence, and the
Krehbiel, Keith. 1998. Pivotal Politics: A Theory of U.S. Lawmaking. Study of Politics." American Political Science Review 94 (June):
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 251-67.
Kryder, Daniel. 2000. Divided Arsenal: Race and the American State Pierson, Paul. 2000b. "Not Just What, but When: Timing and
during World WarII. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sequence in Political Processes." Studies in American Political
Lieberman, Robert C. 1998. Shifting the Color Line: Race and the Development 14 (Spring): 72-92.
American Welfare State. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Plessy v. Ferguson. 1896. 163 U.S. 537.
Press. Plotke, David. 1996. Building a Democratic Political Order: Re-
Lindblom, Charles E. 1959. "The Science of 'Muddling Through."' shaping American Liberalism in the 1930s and 1940s. Cambridge:
Public Administration Review 19 (Spring): 79-88. Cambridge University Press.
Lustick, Ian S. 1996. "History, Historiography, and Political Science: Poole, Keith T., and Howard Rosenthal. 1997. Congress: A Political-
Multiple Historical Records and the Problem of Selection Bias." Economic History of Roll Call Voting. New York: Oxford Univer-
American Political Science Review 90 (September): 605-18. sity Press.
McAdam, Doug. 1982. Political Process and the Development of Powell, Walter W., and Paul J. DiMaggio, eds. 1991. The New In-
Black Insurgency, 1830-1970. Chicago: University of Chicago stitutionalism in Organizational Analysis. Chicago: University of
Press. Chicago Press.
McCubbins, Mathew D., Roger G. Noll, and Barry R. Weingast. Risse, Thomas, Stephen C. Ropp, and Kathryn Sikkink, eds. 1999.
1987. "Administrative Procedures as Instruments of Political The Power of Human Rights: International Norms and Domestic
Control." Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization 3 (Fall): Change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
243-77. Schickler, Eric. 2001. Disjointed Pluralism: Institutional Innovation
McNamara, Kathleen R. 1998. The Currency of Ideas: Monetary Pol- and the Development of the U.S. Congress. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
itics in the European Union. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. University Press.
Mayhew, David R. 1974. Congress: The Electoral Connection. New Schumpeter, Joseph A. 1950. Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy.
Haven, CT: Yale University Press. New York: Harper & Row.
Mayhew, David R. 2000. America's Congress: Actions in the Public Sewell, William H., Jr. 1985. "Ideologies and Social Revolutions:
Sphere, James Madison through Newt Gingrich. New Haven, CT: Reflections on the French Case." Journal of Modern History 57
Yale University Press. (March): 57-85.
Merton, Robert K. 1949. Social Theory and Social Structure.Glencoe, Sikkink, Kathryn. 1993. "The Power of Principled Ideas: Human
IL: Free Press. Rights Policies in the United States and Western Europe." In Ideas
Mill, John Stuart. On Liberty. and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions, and Political Change, ed.
Miroff, Bruce. 1981. "Presidential Leverage over Social Movements: Judith Goldstein and Robert O. Keohane. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
The Johnson White House and Civil Rights." Journal of Politics 43 University Press.
(February): 2-23. Skocpol, Theda. 1979. States and Social Revolutions: A Compara-
Moe, Terry M. 1987. "Interests, Institutions, and Positive Theory: The tive Analysis of France, Russia, and China. Cambridge: Cambridge
Politics of the NLRB." Studies in American Political Development University Press.
2: 236-99. Skocpol, Theda. 1992. Protecting Soldiers and Mothers: The Politi-
Moe, Terry M. 1989. "The Politics of Bureaucratic Structure."In Can cal Origins of Social Policy in the United States. Cambridge, MA:
the Government Govern? ed. John E. Chubb and Paul E. Peterson. Harvard University Press.
Washington, DC: Brookings Institution. Skocpol, Theda. 1996. Boomerang: Clinton's Health Security Effort
Moore, Barrington, Jr. 1966. Social Origins of Dictatorship and and the Turnagainst Government in US. Politics. New York: W.W.
Democracy: Lord and Peasant in the Making of the Modern World. Norton.
Boston: Beacon Press. Skocpol, Theda, Marshall Ganz, and Ziad Munson. 2000. "A Nation
Morone, James A. 1990. The Democratic Wish:Popular Participation of Organizers:The Institutional Origins of Civic Voluntarism in the
and the Limits of American Government. New York: Basic Books. United States."American Political Science Review 94 (September):
Myrdal, Gunnar. 1944. An American Dilemma: The Negro Problem 527-46.
and Modern Democracy. New York: Harper & Brothers. Skowronek, Stephen. 1993. The Politics Presidents Make: Leader-
North, Douglass. 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change and Eco- ship from John Adams to George Bush. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
nomic Performance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. University Press.
Orren, Karen. 1996a. "Structure, Sequence, and Subordination in Skrentny, John David. 1996. The Ironies of Affirmative Action: Poli-
American Political Culture: What's Traditions Got to Do with It?" tics, Culture,and Justice in America. Chicago: University of Chicago
Journal of Policy History 8 (4): 470-78. Press.

711
Ideas, Institutions,and Political Order December 2002

Smith, Rogers M. 1992. "If Politics Matters: Implications for a 'New Institutionalism in Comparative Analysis, ed. Sven Steinmo,
Institutionalism."' Studies in American Political Development 6 Kathleen Thelen, and Frank Longstreth. Cambridge: Cambridge
(Spring): 1-36. University Press.
Smith, Rogers M. 1993. "Beyond Tocqueville, Myrdal, and Hartz: Tocqueville, Alexis de. 1955. The Old Rdgime and the French Revo-
The Multiple Traditions in America." American Political Science lution. Trans. Stuart Gilbert. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.
Review 87 (September): 549-66. Trilling, Lionel. 1950. The Liberal Imagination: Essays on Literature
Smith, Rogers M. 1996. "Response to Karen Orren."Journal of Policy and Society. New York: Viking.
History 8 (4): 479-90. Truman,David B. 1971. The Governmental Process: Political Interests
Smith, Rogers M. 1997. Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship and Public Opinion. 2nd ed. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
in New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Tulis, Jeffrey K. 1987. The Rhetorical Presidency. Princeton, NJ:
U.S. History.
Smith, Rogers M. 1999. "Liberalism and Racism: The Problem of Princeton University Press.
Analyzing Traditions."In The Liberal Traditionin American Poli- Whalen, Charles, and Barbara Whalen. 1985. The Longest Debate: A
tics: Reassessing the Legacy of American Liberalism, ed. David F Legislative History of the 1964 Civil Rights Act. Cabin John, MD:
Ericson and Louisa Bertch Green. New York: Routledge. Seven Locks Press.
Stein, Judith. 1998. Running Steel, RunningAmerica: Race, Economic Wood, Gordon S. 1969. The Creation ofthe American Republic, 1776-
Policy, and the Decline of Liberalism. Chapel Hill: University of 1787. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.
North Carolina Press. Wood, Stewart. 2001. "Labour Market Regimes under Threat?:
Stone, Deborah. 1997. Policy Paradox: The Art of Political Decision Sources of Continuity in Germany, Britain, and Sweden." In The
Making. New York: W. W. Norton. New Politics of the WelfareState, ed. Paul Pierson. Oxford: Oxford
Tarrow,Sidney. 1994. Power in Movement: Social Movements, Collec- University Press.
tive Action, and Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Zuckerman, Alan S. 1997. "Reformulating Explanatory Standards
Thelen, Kathleen. 1999. "Historical Institutionalism and Compara- and Advancing Theory in Comparative Politics." In Compara-
tive Politics."Annual Review of Political Science 2: 369-404. tive Politics: Rationality, Culture, and Structure, ed. Mark Irving
Thelen, Kathleen, and Sven Steinmo. 1992. "Historical Institution- Lichbach and Alan S. Zuckerman. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
alism in Comparative Politics." In Structuring Politics: Historical versity Press.

712

Potrebbero piacerti anche