Sei sulla pagina 1di 6

HLA Hart, The Concept of Law

Introduction

Herbert Lionel Adolphus Hart (H L A Hart) was born in 1907, and graduated from New College, Oxford, where
he read classics, ancient history and philosophy. He was born in Yorkshire in to second generation Jewish
immigrants, he went on to become the most famous legal philosopher of the twentieth century. Hart received his
early education at Cheltenham College and Bradford Grammar School. He then enrolled in New College, Oxford,
where he studied under H.W.B. Joseph. Hart earned his bachelor's degree in 1929 and was admitted to the bar in
1932. Eight years later Hart returned to Oxford to take up a philosophy fellowship, later to become Professor of
Jurisprudence. Hart died on 19th December 1992.

H.L.A Hart single-handedly reinvented the philosophy of law and influenced the nation's thinking in the 1960s on
abortion, the legalization of homosexuality, and on capital punishment. He sought to form a concept of law which
would be of relevance to all forms of law, wherever or whenever they arose. His most significant writings include
Causation in the Law (1959), The Concept of Law (1961), Law, Liberty and Morality (1963), and Essays on
Bentham (1982). The Concept of Law is one of the most noteworthy and original works of legal philosophy
written in the twentieth century. The Concept of Law, dominated British jurisprudence in the final decades of the
20th century. It has been argued that Hart had redefined the domain of jurisprudence and moreover established it
as a philosophical inquiry of the "nature" or "concept" of law.

In this assignment I seek to critically explain Hart‟s concept of law, the nature of rule, the idea of obligation and
the rule of recognition.

CONCEPT OF LAW

What is law? A question which has many answers. Throughout the centuries different scholars have answered this
question in different ways. Some definitions were accepted others were ridiculed. It is possible to describe law as
the body of official rules and regulations, generally found in constitutions, legislation, judicial opinions, and the
like, that is used to govern a society and to control the behavior of its members. John Austin's answer was that law
is "commands, backed by threat of sanctions, from a sovereign, to whom people have a habit of obedience".
Natural lawyers, such as Jean-Jacques Rousseau, argue that law reflects essentially moral and unchangeable laws
of nature.

Hart, set about explaining the concept of law not by way of definition but by striving to clarify the function that
legal words perform when used in the progression of a legal system. Hart argued law is a system of rules, divided
into primary (rules of conduct) and secondary ones (rules addressed to officials to administer primary rules).

Page 1 of 6
Secondary rules are further divided into rules of adjudication (to resolve legal disputes), rules of change (allowing
laws to be varied) and the rule of recognition (allowing laws to be identified as valid).

Hart disapproves of the concept of law which was formulated by John Austin. Hart begins explaining his concept
of law by first critically examining Austin‟s command theory. According to Austin, all laws are commands of a
sovereign backed up by sanctions. Hart argued that a legal system is not a compilation of individual laws, but
rather a union of primary and secondary rules.

Primary rules impose an obligation: what a citizen can or cannot do. Primary rules either forbid or require certain
actions and can generate duties or obligations. For a citizen with an internal perspective to the law, the existence
of a primary rule will create an obligation for him or her to behave a specific way.

Secondary laws define particulars of the primary rules these secondary rules gives power to certain bodies to
create, declare or modify laws, and define their powers and procedures. In common law systems, the secondary
rules define the law making powers of the legislatures and confer on the courts the authority to interpret and
declare relevant law in particular cases that come before them. The secondary rules may be found in a written
constitution or may exist, as in the case of the UK, in the form of custom.

Hart called his theory a version of soft positivism. It is „soft‟ in two ways. First, it accepts that law may exist in
society as a matter of practice and observance, even if it is not officially declared to be law. Second, it accepts that
the legal system may permit a court to apply moral standards in resolving a case before it. This does not mean that
morality gains an upper hand over law, but only that the rules of recognition in the legal system hands the court a
discrete power to take morality into account in identifying the law or in making new law.

According to Hart no society has the man power to appoint officials to inform every member of that society of the
things he was supposed to do and supposed to omit. Therefore it can be said that law is general. It generally asks
people to behave in a specific way to keep their actions in a specific. Officials from the government or sovereign
won‟t come each day to check whether each and every member is following the law. If the primary instructions
are being avoided by a citizen then officials will draw his attention to them and demand compliance, or the
disobedience may be officially recorded and the threatened punishment imposed by a court

THE NATURE OF RULE

One of the principal lessons of The Concept of Law is that legal systems are not only made up of rules, but legal
systems are founded on them as well. According to Bentham and Austin, sovereign makes all of the rules, on the
other hand with a totally contrasting opinion Hart argued that the rules make the sovereign. Hart insisted that the
command theorists had lost sight of the internal aspect. The internal aspect of a rule reveals the sense of
obligation to observe the rule. The external aspect of a rule is its objective existence.
Page 2 of 6
A rule is, according to Hart, a certain kind of complex social practice that consists of a general and regular pattern
of behavior among some group of persons, together with a widely shared attitude within the group that this pattern
is a common standard of conduct to which all members of the group are required to conform. To use the rule is to
conform one's own conduct to the relevant pattern, and to accept the rule is to adopt the attitude that the pattern is
a required standard both for oneself and for everyone else in the group.

According to Hart, a legal system may be best considered a "union" of primary rules of obligation or duty and
secondary rules of recognition, change, and adjudication. Hart characterizes the distinction between primary and
secondary rules in the following way: primary rules either forbid or require certain actions and can generate duties
or obligations; secondary rules confer powers, public or private and sets up the procedures through which primary
rules can be introduced, modified, or enforced. Secondary rules can be thought of as rules about the rules. Primary
rules concern actions involving physical movement or changes; secondary rules provide for operations which lead
not merely to physical movement or change, but to the creation or variation of duties or obligations.

When we think of something being against the law, or required by the law, we are generally in the realm of
primary rules. When analyzing the necessity for secondary rules, Hart imagines a simple society, with only
primary rules, but concludes that such a society would face a number of challenges: because there would be no
systematic method of rule creation, there would be uncertainty about what the rules actually are; the system would
be very static, since any changes in the rules would have to occur organically; finally, without a defined
adjudication method, inefficiencies would arise from disputes over whether a rule was actually broken. These
three problems can be remedied with the introduction of three types of secondary rules, in order: rules of
recognition, rules of change, and rules of adjudication.

THE IDEA OF OBLIGATION

Rules‟ are of two types. Hart refers to them as „primary‟ and „secondary‟ rules. Essentially, the primary rules of
obligation are the fundamental prohibitions which ensure necessary regularity in a legal system, such as the rules
of the criminal law or the law of tort. They are binding because of practices of acceptance which people are
required to do or to abstain from certain actions. Rules of obligation are distinguishable from other rules in that
they are supported by great social pressure because they are felt to be necessary to maintain society.

The key to understanding Hart‟s positivism is to appreciate the nature of obligation. Hart argued that the concept
of law as sovereign command backed by a threat overlooks the element of obligation that characterizes law. We
know that in some societies people are forced into obeying the commands of rulers. Yet in a normal society there
are a vast number of rules that people observe, not because they fear sanction but because they think that it is the
morally right thing to do. If people does not voluntarily follow the law most of the time, something is terribly
wrong in that society. Perhaps there is no society at all, as society is founded on shared rules of behavior. There
are many laws that individuals do not like for example smokers will despise anti-smoking laws or laws which
Page 3 of 6
increase taxation on tobacco, but most people will agree that the rules made according to certain accepted
processes needs to be followed.

The idea of a rule implies an obligation, but not all rules are thought to be obligatory. Rules of social etiquette and
rules of grammar are also rules. But there may not be a sense of obligation attached to them that one must strictly
follow them. The sense of obligation arises from social pressure. The point at which a rule becomes a rule of
obligation is uncertain, but the fact that it happens is not.

Hart argues that a small community, closely knit by common sentiment and belief, and placed in a stable
environment, might be able to live with a set of rules approximating to the „primary rules of obligation‟ he has
described. But this would not be possible in a large community, because of the very nature of the primary rules.
Because as society gets larger and more complex, the shortcomings of a rudimentary set of laws based on
diffused social pressure become evident and the need for a different type of rules is felt. Hart called these
“secondary rules of obligation”.

The separation of rules into these two different categories allows him to establish a method to determine the
validity of a law, which is what determines whether it creates an obligation among citizens in a society or not.
Laws may also be different from coercive orders in as much as they may not necessarily impose duties or
obligations but may instead confer powers or privileges without imposing duties or obligations on individuals.

Hart states that the idea of obligation makes sense only in the context of (normative) social rules. Yet not all rules
imply the existence of an obligation; rules of etiquette, for example, do not impose obligations. Hart explicates
three characteristics that distinguish social rules that impose obligations from those that do not.
(1) Rules imposing obligations are those rules for which the demand for conformity is insistent and the pressure
against those who deviate or threaten to deviate is great.
(2) These rules are thought to be important because they are believed necessary to the maintenance of social life.
(3) The obligations and duties required by these rules are thought of as involving sacrifice of renunciation.
As with the internal point of view, the person under obligation need not experience any particular psychological
feelings; one need not feel obligated or under compulsion as a result of the serious social pressure supporting
rules of obligation.

Page 4 of 6
THE RULE OF RECOGNITION

Hart formally introduced the rule of recognition in his famed book “The Concept of Law”. In that book Hart
considered a community which does not have a legal system and then explains the various social problems which
could arise in such a community and how the introduction of certain rules, such the rule of recognition would
solve these problems.

Hart‟s thesis that a rule of recognition exists in every legal system is the central feature of his positivistic theory
of law, for it is that feature which distinguishes which things are law and which are not and also provides a means
for identifying the law in a morally neutral approach. It also affords an answer to the question of when a legal
system exists. According to Hart, a simplest version of the rule of recognition in the English system is whatever
the Queen in the Parliament enacts is law.

The rule of recognition tells us how to identify a law. In modern systems with multiple sources of law such as a
written constitution, legislative enactments, and judicial precedents, rules of recognition can be quite complex and
require a hierarchy where some types rules overrule others . But, by far the most important function of the rule of
recognition is that it allows us to determine the validity of a rule. Validity is what allows us to determine which
rules should be considered laws, and therefore, which rules should create obligations for citizens with an internal
perspective to the law.

According to Hart, validity is not determined by whether a rule is obeyed, its morality, or its efficiency, but by
whether it fits the criteria set forth by the rule of recognition. The question of the validity of law is to be answered
with reference to the rule of recognition or with reference to the constitution. Hart states, “The rule of recognition
is ultimate in the sense that while the validity of other rules is determined by their conformity to the criteria
specified in the rule of recognition, there can be no question concerning the validity of the rule of recognition
itself.” So any law which is not valid according to the constitution is an invalid law. Hart states that once a rule is
established according to the rule of recognition, whether by the legislature or by judicial precedent, it becomes
part of the legal pedigree and there is little further uncertainty about its meaning or validity.
The reason that Hart gave for the necessity of a rule of recognition was to solve the problem of uncertainty about
the rules by making it easy for people to clearly identify what the laws are. But if new laws can be created every
time a judge makes a difficult decision, it makes identifying the rules just as difficult as if there were no rule of
recognition at all. This means that judges cannot be free and unconstrained to make new law in any way they
wish every time a case comes up where existing laws are undefined or when the factors that influence a decision
are not explicitly part of a distinct set of secondary rules. The rule of recognition is clustered under powers as a
secondary rule, but it looks more like the acceptance of a special kind of rule than a power. Moreover, there

Page 5 of 6
appear to be some rules of recognition which are not powers, such as those which indicate the criteria to be
applied , for example constitutive rules of procedure.

Hart articulates that acceptance of a rule of recognition rests on social facts, but he does not concern himself with
the reasons why, or the circumstances in which it comes to be accepted. Social and moral considerations may well
set limits on a rule of recognition at the time of acceptance so that it may have built-in limitations that provide
safeguards against certain abuses of power. Where there is an accepted constitution in a society that accepted
constitution is the rule of recognition. In most countries the rule of recognition is stated in the constitution. In
England, it is accepted that the common law overrides custom and that laws of Parliament override common law.

CONCLUSION

In conclusion, Hart‟s analysis of primary and secondary rules provides a very useful framework for understanding
the sources of law and how we can distinguish valid laws from invalid ones without entering into subjective moral
territory.

Hart‟s system creates a way to reconcile some of the inconsistences in Austin‟s theory, while also incorporating
some of the more normative nuances of the law without making any moral claims. Hart observes that people feel
an obligation to follow primary laws, even in cases where the likelihood of being caught and punished is slim to
none. Since Austin defines laws as demands issued by a sovereign under threat of sanctions, this observation
cannot be explained by Austin‟s theory.

Hart has contributed a lot to the modern legal system through his different works, all though there are criticisms it
can be said that he had further refined the positivist views. Hart has not only defined what law is but also has shed
light upon what makes a law into a law , how it can be recognized and what obligations it imposes upon the
society.


LLB Year 4 – 2016

Spongebob: “What do you usually do when I'm gone?


Patrick: waiting for you to come back.”
Page 6 of 6

Potrebbero piacerti anche