Sei sulla pagina 1di 8

QUANTUM NO-GO THEOREMS AND CONSCIOUSNESS

Danko Georgiev
Our conscious minds exist in the Universe, therefore they should be identified with physical states
that are subject to physical laws. In classical theories of mind, the mental states are identified with
brain states that satisfy the deterministic laws of classical mechanics. This approach, however, leads
to insurmountable paradoxes such as epiphenomenal minds and illusionary free will. Alternatively,
one may identify mental states with quantum states realized within the brain and try to resolve
the above paradoxes using the standard Hilbert space formalism of quantum mechanics. In this
essay, we first show that identification of mind states with quantum states within the brain is
biologically feasible, and then elaborating on the mathematical proofs of two quantum mechanical
no-go theorems, we explain why quantum theory might have profound implications for the scientific
understanding of one’s mental states, self identity, beliefs and free will.
Keywords: brain · classical mechanics · compatibilism · determinism · free will · indeterminism ·
mind · no-cloning theorem · quantum mechanics
Published in Axiomathes 2013; 23 (4): 683-695. DOI: 10.1007/s10516-012-9204-1

I. INTRODUCTION brain such as mass, charge, length and time [35, 52]. For
epiphenomenalists our subjective (intuitive) feeling that
In neuroscience it is assumed that consciousness is our consciousness is causally effective is just an illusion
a product of the brain whose function is governed by produced by the brain [60]. However, according to the
Newtonian (classical) physical laws. In this viewpoint, evolution theory something that is not causally effective
all brain processes that give rise to conscious experience cannot lead to evolutionary advantage and cannot be se-
can be reduced to chains of causes and effects, which al- lected by natural selection [36, 37].
though immensely complex operate as a clockwork mech-
Problem 2. Because the future in classical deterministic
anism [36]. In contrast, quantum mechanics tells us that
physical theories is predetermined, genuine free will and
the fundamental constituents of matter obey probabilis-
moral responsibility are impossible. If there are no future
tic laws, such that there is not a single predetermined
alternatives allowing for choices to be made, then we can-
future outcome, but a multitude of potentialities, only
not be responsible for our actions, no more than a falling
one of which is to be actualized [10, 31, 53]. The predic-
stone is morally responsible for breaking someone’s leg.
tions of quantum theory were experimentally proven to
Subjectively (intuitively) it feels as if our consciousness
be so accurate that at present there is a little doubt that
is able to make choices between alternative future possi-
the nature is governed by quantum laws.
bilities, but for classical determinists this is just another
Because consciousness is an ambiguous term that may
illusion produced by the brain [9, 55, 56, 60].
refer to many different things, we introduce a formal def-
inition, which is more or less identical to the one given Since the counterintuitive results from the classical ap-
by Thomas Nagel [44] and David Chalmers [16]. proach to the theory of consciousness stem from the de-
terministic laws, any quantum theory of consciousness at-
Definition 1. Consciousness is a collective term that
tempting to resolve Problems (1) and (2) cannot be based
refers to the subjective character of our mental states,
on interpretations of quantum mechanics that endorse a
our ability to experience or to feel. A conscious state is a
form of conspiracy determinism (description of such con-
state of experience. The terms consciousness, mind and
spiracy theories of quantum mechanics can be found in
experience will be used interchangeably hereafter.
[42]). The indeterminism provided by the standard ax-
There are several unresolved problems in the theory of ioms of quantum mechanics (including the Born rule)
consciousness, which might benefit from quantum me- motivates an increasing number of scientists to search
chanical analysis. Here, we will formulate only those for a reinterpretation of quantum theory in which con-
problems that are relevant for our discussion and will sciousness is fundamentally connected with the process
refer the reader elsewhere for a general introduction to of choice making or actualization of alternative future
the theory of consciousness [22]. possibilities [7, 26, 27, 47, 51, 61]. Noteworthy, the inde-
terminism is not the only important feature of quantum
Problem 1. Because the material world in classical de- mechanics, which makes it relevant to the study of bi-
terministic physical theories is causally closed, there is no ological systems and consciousness (cf. [2–6, 25, 28]).
room for consciousness, or if consciousness is allowed it There are several quantum mechanical no-go theorems
can only be in the form of a causally ineffective epiphe- that may be important for neuroscience and philosophy
nomenon. If the brain states produce conscious expe- of mind provided that following weak proposition is true:
riences, then these experiences cannot possibly have an
effect upon brain dynamics, which is already fully de- Proposition 1. The brain can sustain quantum coher-
termined by the fundamental physical quantities of the ence for any (possibly short but physically feasible) period
2

of time and the mind state produced by the brain depends information and with muscles to output information us-
on or could be identified with the quantum state of the ing electric impulses propagating along the nerve fibers
brain for this short period of time. (axons), this does not imply that the conscious process-
ing and the duration of mental states within the brain
In order to justify this proposition, first we will note cortex occur also at a millisecond timescale. On the con-
that quantum physical calculations do not show that trary, any attempt to construct a quantum mechanical
quantum coherence cannot occur at all in the hot, noisy
theory of brain function leads to the prediction that the
and wet brain. Instead, the calculations show that the
relevant dynamical timescale is not slower than picosec-
life-time of quantum coherent states in the brain cannot
onds [24, 26, 27, 58].
be on a millisecond timescale [43, 54, 58]. Thus we come
to a central question in neuroscience and theory of con- Another group of experimental tests trying to esti-
sciousness, namely, is there any evidence that conscious mate the duration of each conscious step are based on
processes operate on a millisecond timescale? The cal- subjective reports of perceived temporal order of non-
culated decoherence time for quantum states within cy- simultaneous sensory inputs. The first such psychophys-
toskeletal proteins was estimated to be ≈ 0.1 picosecond ical “investigation of the simplest mental processes” was
[58] and it was argued that quantum effects on a picosec- performed by Sigmund Exner [19–21], and further corrob-
ond timescale could have impact upon the brain function orated by different research groups [34, 38, 49]. It was
[24, 27]. Therefore, if conscious processes in the brain found that the minimal time window between two dif-
were not assumed to be on a millisecond timescale, but ferent sensory inputs allowing for subjective assessment
on a picosecond timescale or faster, there would be no of their non-simultaneity and temporal order is ≈ 30 ms
physical objection to quantum effects being involved in [34, 38, 49]. These data, together with clinical reports
consciousness. In fact, classical neuroscience provides no of patients with time agnosia (who are conscious but do
proof that our minds operate on a millisecond timescale, not experience subjective passage or flow of time) con-
it only establishes that our minds do not operate on a firm the possibility of having consecutive conscious steps,
timescale slower than that. which are nonetheless experienced as “simultaneous” [24].
A major group of experimental tests trying to esti- Therefore, subjective reports on experienced passage of
mate the duration of each conscious step are based on time cannot be used to determine the duration of each
measuring of reaction times [12–15]. While it is true conscious step. The psychophysical tests, too, can estab-
that reaction times are of the order of tens to hundreds lish only an upper bound on the duration of each con-
of milliseconds, such measurements provide only an up- scious step, which cannot be longer than ≈ 30 ms.
per bound on the duration of each conscious step. If Finally, there is a group of experimental tests such
we can perform a cognitive task and react in millisecond as electroencephalography (EEG) or functional magnetic
timescale, it would be incorrect to construct a theory in resonance imaging (fMRI) that can monitor changes in
which each conscious step lasts seconds or minutes. On brain activity in real time. Although it is possible to
the other hand, such experiments cannot show that each monitor the brain activity with arbitrarily high tempo-
conscious step was not in fact much shorter, for exam- ral resolution, there is no whatsoever theoretical way to
ple picoseconds [24]. To further clarify why measuring of determine from such data what is the duration of each
reaction times provides only an upper bound for the du- conscious step. Establishing certain correlations between
ration of conscious steps, let us consider the operation of wakefulness and patterns of brain activity cannot pro-
a personal computer. The personal computer has a hu- vide even an upper bound for the duration of each con-
man interface to get the input (keyboard and mouse) and scious step. Functional observations are meaningful only
provide the output (monitor), and a processor equipped when combined with psychophysical tests, but the lat-
with working memory, which is used to perform the com- ter will just show that each conscious step is no longer
putational tasks. The devices that provide the human than ≈ 30 ms as discussed above. What is remarkable
interface operate at a millisecond timescale, for example is that those who believe that the mind is a product of
the image on the monitor usually is refreshed every 10 classical millisecond brain processes calculate quantum
ms corresponding to a frequency of 100 Hz. However, mechanically brain decoherence timescale of the order of
the processor could operate at a much faster timescale picoseconds and from that conclude that quantum me-
of picoseconds, which for modern processors could corre- chanics is irrelevant for mental processes and theory of
spond to a frequency of 5 GHz. It is clear that measuring consciousness [40, 58]. But we have just shown that such
the refresh rate of the monitor does not really say how argument is fallacious. The reaction times, psychophysi-
fast the processor of the computer is. Such measurement cal tests or functional studies could provide at best only
can establish only an upper bound according to which the an upper bound for the duration of each conscious step.
processor could not operate at a timescale longer than 10 If one constructs a theory in which the conscious pro-
ms (or equivalently, at frequency lower than 100 Hz). Es- cesses are much faster than the reaction times measured
sentially the same argument applies to physiological ex- by physiological experiments, then the calculated brain
periments measuring reaction times of human volunteers. decoherence timescale of the order of picoseconds would
While it is true that the brain cortex communicates at a just confirm or corroborate the quantum mechanical the-
millisecond timescale with the sensory organs to obtain ory of mental states instead of disproving it [24].
3

Having shown that the current status of the classi- III. QUANTUM STATES ARE NOT
cal theory of mind operating at millisecond timescale OBSERVABLE
is nothing but a pure belief, we proceed with analysis
of two quantum mechanical no-go theorems that are lit- Theorem 1. Unambiguous determination of an un-
tle known to neuroscientists and classical philosophers of known individual quantum state (wavefunction) |ΨA i of
mind, and discuss the scope of their implications. The a q-bit A is impossible [11].
subsequent exposition is organized as follows: in Section
II we explain why the wide-spread philosopher practice Proof. In order to determine the state of a quantum sys-
to take as granted that one can read, copy, clone, mul- tem we could perform a measurement. Every measure-
tiply and/or erase safely information is fundamentally ment can be represented by some observable (that is a
flawed; then in Sections III and IV we provide the proofs
Hermitian operator) P̂ = P̂ † whose eigenvalues are ex-
of two quantum mechanical no-go theorems and discuss
hibited as the measurement outcomes. In order to be
how they are interconnected; finally in Section V we ap-
able to decide from the outcomes whether or not the
ply those theorems to the mind-brain problem and obtain
system was in a given state |ΨA i, there needs to be
novel insights into one’s self identity, beliefs and free will.
at least one outcome which occurs with certainty if the
state was |ΨA i, and which will certainly not occur if the
state was some state |ΦA i different from |ΨA i. Since
the quantum mechanical probabilities are expectations
II. CLASSICAL INFORMATION VERSUS of some positive semidefinite operators P̂ representing
QUANTUM INFORMATION the event in question, it follows that hΨA |P̂ |ΨA i = 1
and hΦA |P̂ |ΦA i = 0. These equations are equivalent to
P̂ |ΨA i = |ΨA i and P̂ |ΦA i = 0. Therefore, hΦA |ΨA i =
Current neuroscience is exclusively built upon the con-
cept of classical information, which can be read, copied, hΦA |P̂ |ΨA i = hΨA |P̂ |ΦA i∗ = 0 which is to say that |ΨA i
multiplied, stored, processed with the use of irreversible and |ΦA i are mutually orthogonal. Because there is no
Boolean gates and/or erased. An example of classical in- measurement of q-bit A that would allow one to distin-
formation is the string of bits, 0’s and 1’s, that encode guish unequivocally between any pair of non-orthogonal
a digital movie recorded onto DVD. One can watch the states, it follows that unambiguous determination of an
DVD, copy the information from the DVD any number of individual quantum state |ΨA i of a q-bit A is impossi-
times, and even erase the DVD in order to re-write it with ble by only measuring the q-bit A. This weaker result
new information. The classical bits of information or c- is sufficient for proving the subsequent Theorem 2. We
bits, possess all of the above properties and intuitively note that if there were a way to copy the original q-bit
these properties seem to be essential for our understand- A multiple times before we measure the q-bit A, then we
ing of what information is. would have been able to measure these copies as well and
use the results to reconstruct the quantum state of the
Nevertheless, in quantum mechanics the individual original q-bit A. However, the impossibility to clone un-
carriers of information do not share most of the prop- known quantum states is established by Theorem 2 and
erties possessed by c-bits. We will refer to the carriers of this concludes the proof of Theorem 1.
quantum information as quantum bits, or simply q-bits.
One of the peculiar properties of the quantum informa-
tion contained in the quantum state (wavefunction) of Here, we would like to remark that Theorem 1 follows
a q-bit is that in general it cannot be observed or read from the standard Hilbert space formalism of quantum
(i.e. cannot be deduced from experimental data) as in the mechanics in which the space of states of a quantum me-
case of the c-bits stored on DVD [1, 11]. If we have a chanical system forms a vector space instead of a set [57].
quantum version of DVD storing a string of q-bits, in In the early days of quantum mechanics many of the im-
general we cannot copy the string of q-bits [17, 62], we portant quantum mechanical results were considered to
cannot process the stored quantum information using ir- be a consequence of the Heisenberg uncertainty principle,
reversible Boolean gates [59], and we cannot erase the which was understood as an empirical regularity (em-
quantum information (at best we can achieve swapping ploying no or only a bare minimum of theoretical terms)
that is moving the information around without deleting whose purpose was to build up a fully fleshed physical
it) [46]. Furthermore, the Bell and Kochen-Specker no-go theory explaining the empirical data [33]. At present we
theorems [8, 41] do not allow for quantum mechanics to already have constructed a powerful axiomatization of
be completed and/or explained with the use of classical quantum theory (see [48]), so we derive Heisenberg un-
hidden variables that are local or non-contextual [32]. At certainty relations as theorems and no longer use them as
a first glance all this could be perplexing, however these a starting point for derivation of other quantum mechan-
results are provable as mathematical theorems using the ical results. Indeed, manipulation of vectors in a Hilbert
standard Hilbert space formalism of quantum mechanics. space is much more easier compared to detailed analysis
Here we will provide mathematical proofs only of the first of thought experiments in the fashion Heisenberg did (cf.
two no-go theorems. [33]).
4

IV. QUANTUM NO-CLONING THEOREM states for which our copying machine is originally de-
signed, the putative copy will be entangled with the origi-
Theorem 2. An unknown quantum state |ΨA i of a q-bit nal q-bit. If we measure the original q-bit, we will corrupt
A cannot be cloned to another q-bit B [17, 62]. the entangled copy as well. In general, the copy that we
can achieve is a pseudo-copy, because it is entangled with
Proof. Suppose that we have a two-level q-bit A, whose the original q-bit and will be corrupted when the original
unknown quantum state |ΨA i we wish to copy. The state q-bit is measured. For completeness we could add that
can be generally written as if |ΨA i were in one of the two basis states, the copy will
be a true copy, yet we will not know this. Since there is
an infinite number of possible basis states, the chance for
|ΨA i = α|0A i + β|1A i (IV.1) production a true copy is equal to the chance of guessing
correctly the unknown quantum state, which is one out
where |0A i and |1A i are two orthogonal basis states in
of infinite number of possible states. Or in other words,
two-dimensional Hilbert space H, and the complex coef-
there is an infinite number of copying machines that can
ficients α and β are unknown. In order to make a copy,
copy only a pair of basis states, and since originally the
we take a q-bit B with an identical Hilbert space and
quantum state is unknown to us, the chance to choose at
initial state |eB i, which must be independent of |ΨA i
random the correct copying machine is zero.
(of which we have no prior knowledge). The composite
system is then described by the tensor product
V. IMPLICATIONS FOR THE MIND-BODY
|ΨA i ⊗ |eB i (IV.2) PROBLEM

There are only two ways to manipulate the composite sys- Physics is a scientific discipline supposed to study all
tem. One possibility is to perform an observation (mea- things that exist within the Universe. Because our minds
surement of q-bit A), which forces the system into some do exist in the Universe, they are physical by definition
eigenstate of the observable and corrupts the informa- and should be subject to physical laws. The important
tion contained in the q-bit A. This precludes achieving question, however, is what kind of physical laws: classi-
a copy of q-bit A. A second alternative is to control the cal or quantum? Every scientific theory addressing the
Hamiltonian of the composite system, and thus the time mind-body problem should have an entity referred to as
evolution operator Û , which is linear. For any fixed time mind even though in mind-brain identity theories the
interval, Û would act as a copier provided that term brain is usually preferred for reasons that have to
do with conventions and/or personal taste, not logic (log-
ically if two terms are identical you can use them inter-
Û |ΨA i ⊗ |eB i = |ΨA i ⊗ |ΨB i (IV.3)
changeably). Furthermore, the mind in every scientific
for all Ψ. This must be true for the basis states as well, theory should be subject to certain (classical or quantum)
so physical laws. The third option, according to which the
mind is not subject to any physical laws, should be con-
sidered experimentally rejected since we cannot perform
Û |0A i ⊗ |eB i = |0A i ⊗ |0B i (IV.4) miracles at will.
In a classical theory of mind (in which the mind is
Û |1A i ⊗ |eB i = |1A i ⊗ |1B i (IV.5)
governed by classical physical laws), one could in princi-
ple conceive thought experiments in which one is able to
Then eq.IV.1 and the linearity of Û imply
observe and/or create perfect copies of one’s mind (and
brain). As a consequence one is able to prove various
Û |ΨA i ⊗ |eB i = Û (α|0A i + β|1A i) ⊗ |eB i paradoxical results such as (i) the observability of men-
tal states from third person perspective, (ii) the existence
= αÛ |0A i ⊗ |eB i + β Û |1A i ⊗ |eB i of self-locating beliefs, (iii) the non-existence of self iden-
= α|0A i ⊗ |0B i + β|1A i ⊗ |1B i (IV.6) tity, and (iv) Frankfurt’s thesis that free will could exist
in cases where the subject could have not done otherwise.
This is generally not equal to |ΨA i ⊗ |ΨB i, as may be Interestingly, the two quantum mechanical no-go the-
verified by plugging in α = β = √12 . Indeed if one starts orems proved in Sections III and IV show that most of
with |ΨA i being a superposition of the basis states |0A i the intuitive properties of classical information (the abil-
and |1A i, the time evolution operator Û will create an ity to be observed, copied or multiplied) do not hold for
entangled state, so Û cannot act as a general copier. The quantum systems. For example, if we have a quantum
latter result is known as the no-cloning theorem. version of DVD with unknown file on it, in general we
will be able neither to copy the DVD, nor to read it
The above argument illustrates something very inter- (even though imperfect copying or partial reading is pos-
esting, namely that if |ΨA i is not in one of the two basis sible). Thus in quantum theories of mind (in which the
5

mind is governed by quantum physical laws), the quan- us imagine the fictitious situation in which a malicious
tum mechanical no-go theorems forbid mind observations creature called Dr. Evil is in orbit around Earth in its
or copies to be made and invalidate the proofs of the spaceship, which is indestructible. After 24 hours Dr.
above-mentioned paradoxical results. The latter conclu- Evil will be able to destroy the Earth by bomb. Unfortu-
sion is our novel contribution to the main-body problem. nately for him, just before doing so, he receives a letter
from Earth’s Philosophy Defense Force, which never lies.
In the letter is said that they have created 99 duplicates
A. Privacy of mental states of Dr. Evil, which have exactly the same experiences
as Dr. Evil himself and that for example at the very
A physical state is observable, if it can be deduced same moment each duplicate is also reading the letter.
from performed experimental measurements upon the Moreover, if the duplicates do not surrender at once, the
state. In classical physics all physical states are observ- Earth’s Philosophy Defense Force will torture the dupli-
able in principle. In quantum physics, however, unknown cates. The question is: “how seriously should Dr. Evil
quantum states are unobservable and cannot be deduced consider that he is a duplicate?”. Elga (2004) argues that
from experimental measurements as shown by Theorem the answer is: “very seriously” and that Dr. Evil should
1. Most people intuitively feel that our mental states are surrender. In this case the belief that there is a 99%
private and cannot be observed from third person per- chance that he is a duplicate should be self-locating in
spective. Nevertheless, the successful application of func- the real Dr. Evil too. If however the Dr. Evil’s mind is
tional brain imaging techniques, such as positron emis- a product of quantum coherent process in his brain, the
sion tomography (PET) or functional magnetic resonance no-cloning theorem implies that the Earth’s Philosophy
imaging (fMRI), for studying cognitive processes in hu- Defense Force cannot create even a single duplicate of
mans, provided certain researchers with optimism that Dr. Evil. Therefore the concept of self-locating belief is
mental states could be observed from third person per- bogus and Dr. Evil cannot be defeated.
spective [29, 30, 39]. Such optimism might be pseudo-
justified with the use of Karl Popper’s demarcation cri-
terion according to which scientific theories should be
experimentally testable [50]. If unobservable entities can-
not be directly deduced from experimental tests, then any
C. Self identity
theory proposing entities unobservable from third person
perspective must be pseudoscience. However, such con-
clusion might be premature because one can similarly In classical neuroscience the idea that the personal
apply the demarcation criterion to quantum mechanics identity including one’s own mind, self, and free will is
and argue that it is pseudoscience due to the fact that entirely contained in the molecular and biological struc-
it contains unobservable quantum wavefunctions. Since ture of the brain (c-bits) implies that a duplicate iden-
quantum mechanics is the most successful physical the- tity could be created that is identical in every way ex-
ory we currently have, it is more reasonable to conclude cept physical location. Thus the neural net organization,
that Karl Popper’s demarcation criterion has its limits neurons, synapses, molecules would be identical and in
of application. In particular, neither quantum mechanics identical physical relationship to the others in the du-
nor the theories of mind appear to be within the domain plicate, and every neuron and synapse would be in an
where the demarcation criterion should be applied. Fur- identical state of depolarization at the instant of dupli-
thermore, there are good (intuitive) reasons to think that cation. This creates well known problem with the no-
a successful theory of mind will come out with essentially tion of one’s self identity as it leads to paradoxical exis-
unobservable mental states. If the proposal for mental tence of one mind in two different places. Moreover the
states being quantum coherent states in the brain turns whole construction of the duplicate is conceived by some
out to be true, then Theorems 1 and 2 automatically philosophers as an argument against the existence of the
ensure the privacy of mental states making them unob- self or at least that preservation of one’s important psy-
servable for external measuring devices (with the caveat chological features does not suffice for self identity [45].
that what can be observed should be an eigenvalue of Though none of the proposed classical solutions to the
some observable P̂ , hence providing only incomplete in- outlined paradox is satisfying, if mind states are quan-
formation about the quantum state). tum states of the brain, then one can use Theorem 2 to
argue against the possibility for duplication of the self. In
contrast with classical theories where one can in principle
B. Self-locating beliefs duplicate complex systems such as the brain, in quantum
theory such duplication is impossible and the duplication
In an interesting paper Elga proposed the existence elsewhere in space would be as likely as the miracle of
of self-locating beliefs, which might be used to create a spontaneous creation of one’s brain. Thus, quantum the-
serious doubt in one’s mind whether he himself is the ory provides a better physical formalism for the existence
original or he is just a duplicate of the original [18]. Let of the self compared to the classical Newtonian theory.
6

D. Compatibilism and free will intended conclusions about one’s mental states and free
will from the postulated c-bit properties. Without the
Compatibilism is a philosophical position according to implicit c-bit assumption it becomes impossible to con-
which free will is possible even if the physical world is struct a thought experiment in which a subject has no
governed by deterministic laws and one does not have the choice to do otherwise, yet exerts his free will. It seems
option to choose among multiple future possibilities. Al- that Frankfurt makes the error because it is inconceiv-
though it looks impossible to explain how one can have able for him that there could be any form of information
free will without given the option to choose among at that is different from a c-bit. Thus, quantum mechan-
least two future possibilities, an argument proposed by ics not only provides alternative future possibilities that
Frankfurt [23] was widely celebrated as providing such could be actualized, but also guarantees the existence of
explanation. Frankfurt’s argument attempts to establish free choices by forbidding external monitoring of one’s
that one might act on one’s own will despite of the fact mental states.
that one could have not done otherwise [23]. For the con- VI. CONCLUDING REMARKS
struction of the argument Frankfurt supposes that (1) an
external agent could observe (deduce from experimental It has been argued that quantum coherence in the
measurements performed with an advanced device) your brain might be too short and therefore irrelevant for the
mental states and monitor your future decisions and (2) mind-brain problem [58] or that quantum mechanics has
could use an advanced device in order to rearrange the nothing to contribute to the mind-brain problem [63].
firing of your neurons in such a way that you will do The authors of the latter work [63] have expressed the
a certain action A only in case you have not chosen to “hope that the rejection of the role of consciousness in
do A. From the given premises it is easy to see that quantum mechanics will also lead us to re-evaluate the
if you have chosen to do A you have done it on your proposals that quantum mechanics is vital for explaining
own will, despite of the fact you could not have done the consciousness. Having these two deep mysteries dis-
otherwise. Although Frankfurt’s argument seems to es- entangled one from the other might be an important step
tablish the credibility of compatibilism in the framework forward towards understanding each of them.” In this
of classical theory of mind, it is completely demolished work we have shown that such skepticism is premature
if the mind states happen to be quantum states of the because if mental states are even short-lived quantum
brain. As a consequence of Theorem 1, it follows that brain states then quantum mechanical no-go theorems
if one’s mental states are quantum states then no exter- apply and provide novel insights for the understanding
nal agent would be capable to observe or monitor the of one’s mental states, self identity, beliefs and free will.
mental (quantum) state of a quantum coherent system, In particular, if the mental states are quantum states of
because any measurement itself will alter the state of the the brain they cannot be observed (deduced from exper-
observed quantum system. Indeed, it is impossible for a imental measurements) by an external observer and the
classical philosopher to defend any form of compatibilism privacy of our mental life is guaranteed by quantum me-
without utilizing some of the main operations that could chanical laws. Furthermore, the concept of self-identity is
be performed upon classical information such as observ- not subject to classical paradoxes resulting from putative
ing or copying of c-bits. Furthermore, within the light of duplications of the self. In addition, the quantum no-go
the discussed quantum mechanical no-go theorems, it be- theorems invalidate Frankfurt’s celebrated argument for
comes transparent that Frankfurt’s argument is a logical compatibilism and restore the credibility of our intuition
fallacy based on the assumption that “mental states are that we could not have exerted our free will if there were
c-bits with free will” with subsequent derivation of the no alternative options to choose from.

[1] Alter O, Yamamoto Y (2001) Quantum Measurement of [6] Baianu IC, Glazebrook JF, Brown R (2011) Quantum
a Single System, Wiley, New York symmetries, operator algebra and quantum groupoid rep-
[2] Baianu IC (1971) Organismic supercategories and qual- resentations: paracrystalline systems, topological order,
itative dynamics of systems. Bulletin of Mathematical supersymmetry and global symmetry breaking. Interna-
Biophysics 33(3):339–354 tional Journal of Research and Reviews in Applied Sci-
[3] Baianu IC (2006) Robert Rosen’s work and complex sys- ences 9(2):163–206
tems biology. Axiomathes 16(1):25–34 [7] Beck F, Eccles JC (1992) Quantum aspects of brain ac-
[4] Baianu IC (2007) Categorical ontology of levels and tivity and the role of consciousness. Proceedings of the
emergent complexity: an introduction. Axiomathes National Academy of Sciences of the USA 89(23):11357–
17(3):209–222 11361
[5] Baianu IC, Brown R, Glazebrook JF (2007) Categorical [8] Bell JS (1966) On the problem of hidden variables
ontology of complex spacetime structures: the emergence in quantum mechanics. Reviews of Modern Physics
of life and human consciousness. Axiomathes 17(3):223– 38(3):447–452
352
7

[9] Bode S, He AH, Soon CS, Trampel R, Turner R, [30] Haynes JD, Sakai K, Rees G, Gilbert S, Frith C, Passing-
Haynes J-D (2011) Tracking the unconscious generation ham RE (2007) Reading hidden intentions in the human
of free decisions using ultra-high field fMRI. PLoS One brain. Current Biology 17:323–328
6(6):e21612 [31] Heisenberg W (1925) Über quantentheoretische Umdeu-
[10] Born M (1926) Zur Quantenmechanik der Stoßvorgänge. tung kinematischer und mechanischer Beziehungen.
Zeitschrift für Physik 37(12):863–867 Zeitschrift für Physik 33(1):879–893
[11] Busch P (1997) Is the quantum state (an) observable? In: [32] Held C (2012) The Kochen-Specker Theorem. In: Stan-
Potentiality, Entanglement and Passion-at-a-Distance: ford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Zalta EN, Nodelman U,
Quantum Mechanical Studies for Abner Shimony, Vol- Allen C (editors), Stanford, California, Stanford Univer-
ume Two, R. S. Cohen, M. Horne and J. Stachel (eds.), sity, Stanford
Dordrecht, Kluwer, pp 61–70 [33] Hilgevoord J, Uffink J (2012) The Uncertainty Princi-
[12] Cattell JM (1886a) The time taken up by cerebral oper- ple. In: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Zalta EN,
ations. Parts I-II. Mind 11:220–242 Nodelman U, Allen C (editors), Stanford, California,
[13] Cattell JM (1886b) The time taken up by cerebral oper- Stanford University, Stanford
ations. Part III. Mind 11:377–392 [34] Hirsh IJ, Sherrick Jr CE (1961) Perceived order in differ-
[14] Cattell JM (1887) The time taken up by cerebral opera- ent sense modalities. Journal of Experimental Psychology
tions. Part IV. Mind 11:524–538 62(5):423–432
[15] Cattell JM (1890) Mental tests and measurements. Mind [35] Huxley TH (1874) On the hypothesis that animals are au-
15:373–381 tomata, and its history. The Fortnightly Review 16:555–
[16] Chalmers DJ (1995) Facing up to the problem of con- 580
sciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 2(3):200– [36] James W (1879) Are we automata? Mind 4(13):1–22
219 [37] James W (1890) The principles of psychology. Holt, New
[17] Dieks D (1982) Communication by EPR devices. Physics York
Letters A 92:271–272 [38] Kanabus M, Szelag E, Rojek E, Pöppel E (2002) Tempo-
[18] Elga A (2004) Defeating Dr. Evil with self-locating belief. ral order judgement for auditory and visual stimuli. Acta
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69:383–396 Neurobiologiae Experimentalis 62(4):263–270
[19] Exner S (1873) Experimentelle Untersuchung der ein- [39] Kay KN, Naselaris T, Prenger RJ, Gallant JL (2008)
fachsten psychischen Processe. I. Die persönliche Gle- Identifying natural images from human brain activity.
ichung. Pflügers Archiv European Journal of Physiology Nature 452:352–355
7(1):601–660 [40] Koch C, Hepp K (2006) Quantum mechanics in the brain.
[20] Exner S (1874) Experimentelle Untersuchung der ein- Nature 440:611–612
fachsten psychischen Processe. II. Ueber Reflexzeit und [41] Kochen SB, Specker EP (1967) The problem of hidden
Rückenmarksleitung. Pflügers Archiv European Journal variables in quantum mechanics. Journal of Mathematics
of Physiology 8(1):526–537 and Mechanics 17(1):59–87
[21] Exner S (1875) Experimentelle Untersuchung der ein- [42] Lewis PJ (2006) Conspiracy theories of quantum mechan-
fachsten psychischen Processe. III. Der persönlichen Gle- ics. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science
ichung zweiter Theil. Pflügers Archiv European Journal 57(2):359–381
of Physiology 11(1):403–432 [43] McCrone J (2003) Quantum mind. The Lancet Neurology
[22] Feser E (2007) Philosophy of Mind: A Beginner’s Guide. 2:450
Oneworld, Oxford [44] Nagel T (1974) What is it like to be a bat? The Philo-
[23] Frankfurt H (1969) Alternate possibilities and moral re- sophical Review 83(4):435–450
sponsibility. Journal of Philosophy 66(23):829–839 [45] Olson ET (2012) Personal Identity. In: Stanford Ency-
[24] Georgiev DD (2004) Consciousness operates beyond the clopedia of Philosophy, Zalta EN, Nodelman U, Allen C
timescale for discerning time intervals: implications for (editors), Stanford, California, Stanford University, Stan-
Q-mind theories and analysis of quantum decoherence in ford
brain. Neuroquantology 2(2):122–145 [46] Pati AK, Braunstein SL (2000) Impossibility of deleting
[25] Georgiev DD (2011) A linkage of mind and brain: an unknown quantum state. Nature 404:164–165
Sir John Eccles and modern dualistic interactionism. [47] Penrose R (1989) The Emperor’s New Mind: Concern-
Biomedical Reviews 22:81–84 ing Computers, Minds and The Laws of Physics. Oxford
[26] Georgiev DD, Glazebrook JF (2006) Dissipationless University Press, Oxford
waves for information transfer in neurobiology - some im- [48] Pitowsky I (2005) Quantum mechanics as a theory
plications. Informatica (Slovenia) 30(2):221–232 of probability. In: Festschrift for Jeffrey Bub, De-
[27] Georgiev DD, Glazebrook JF (2007) Subneuronal pro- mopoulos W, Pitowsky I (editors), Kluwer, Dordrecht,
cessing of information by solitary waves and stochastic arXiv:quant-ph/0510095
processes. In: Nano and Molecular Electronics Hand- [49] Pöppel E (1997) A hierarchical model of temporal per-
book, S. E. Lyshevski (ed.), CRC Press, pp 17-1–17-41 ception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 1(2):56–61
[28] Georgiev DD, Glazebrook JF (2012) Quasiparticle tun- [50] Popper KR (2002). The Logic of Scientific Discovery,
neling in neurotransmitter release. In: Handbook of Routledge, London
Nanoscience, Engineering, and Technology, Third Edi- [51] Popper KR, Eccles JC (1984) The Self and Its Brain: An
tion, Goddard III WA, Brenner D, Lyshevski SE, Iafrate Argument for Interactionism. Routledge & Kegan Paul,
GJ (editors), CRC Press, pp 983–1016 London
[29] Hassabis D, Chu C, Rees G, Weiskopf N, Molyneux PD, [52] Robinson W (2012) Epiphenomenalism. In: Stanford En-
Maguire EA (2009) Decoding neuronal ensembles in the cyclopedia of Philosophy, Zalta EN, Nodelman U, Allen
human hippocampus. Current Biology 19:546–554 C (editors), Stanford, California, Stanford University,
8

Stanford [58] Tegmark M (2000) Importance of quantum decoherence


[53] Schrödinger E (1926) An undulatory theory of the in brain processes. Physical Review E 61(4):4194–4206
mechanics of atoms and molecules. Physical Review [59] Vedral V, Plenio MB (1998) Basics of quantum compu-
28(6):1049–1070 tation. Progress in Quantum Electronics 22:1–39
[54] Seife C (2000) Cold numbers unmake the Quantum Mind. [60] Wegner DM (2002) The Illusion of Conscious Will. The
Science 287(5454):791 MIT Press, Cambridge
[55] Smith K (2011) Taking aim at free will. Nature [61] Wigner E (1961) Remarks on the mind-body problem. In:
477(7362):23–25 The Scientist Speculates, I. J. Good (ed.), Heinemann,
[56] Soon CS, Brass M, Heinze H-J, Haynes J-D (2008) Un- London, pp 284–302
conscious determinants of free decisions in the human [62] Wootters WK, Zurek WH (1982) A single quantum can-
brain. Nature Neuroscience 11(5):543–545 not be cloned. Nature 299:802–803
[57] Susskind L (2012) The Theoretical Minimum: [63] Yu S, Nikolić D (2011) Quantum mechanics needs no
Quantum Mechanics. Stanford Continuing Studies, consciousness. Annalen der Physik 523(11):931–938
YouTube:PL701CD168D02FF56F

Potrebbero piacerti anche