Sei sulla pagina 1di 38

Reviews Young.

Honored ancestors include Alain Daniélou, Ivor Darreg,


Adriaan Fokker, Harry Partch, Nicola Vicentino, and Joseph
Yasser.3
W. A. Mathieu. Harmonic Experience. Rochester, Vermont: Inner W. A. Mathieu—who has written about the role of music in a
Traditions, 1997. number of traditional contexts, including ethos, affect, and to
some extent, cosmology—is a musician with a long and impres-
Reviewed by Norman Carey sive vita. After a stint as an arranger for the Stan Kenton and Duke
Ellington bands in the early 1960s, Mathieu has been composing
The resurgence of interest over the past thirty years in spiritual- works that bring together and honor an equally impressive array
ity and mysticism has brought in its wake a host of studies in of genres and teachers, including SuQ music with Hazrat Inayat
music, as music claims an illustrious position in esoteric studies. Khan, North Indian music with Pandit Pran Nath, African music
The scholarly presses have, wittingly or not, eased access into the with Hamza El Din, jazz with William Russo, and (in all likeli-
depths of musical arcana with new translations of ancient treatises hood) a host of musical idioms with composer and theorist Easley
with speculative components, including those of Ptolemy, Blackwood. Mr. Mathieu has been on the faculties of the San
Boethius, and Aristides Quintilianus. Other presses, such as Inner Francisco Conservatory of Music and Mills College.
Traditions, Shambhala, Phanes Press, and Samuel Weiser, have Mathieu’s two previous books 4 have prepared the ground for
swelled the tide with reprints of many other old sources (mainly the present study, Harmonic Experience, a large volume of 563
neo-Platonic and Pythagorean treatises) and by presenting new pages. The work is divided into four parts: “Harmonic Purity:
authors. 1 These studies largely focus on the effect that music has Feeling The Numbers” (Chapters 1–18), “The Selective Use of
upon the psyche and, correspondingly, on the musical (“harmo- Equal Temperament” (Chapters 19–26), “The Functional Com-
nious”) nature of the cosmos. mas of Equal-Tempered Tonal Harmony” (Chapters 27–34), and
Studies involving the spiritual effect of music often prescribe a “Harmonic Practice: Analysis and Review of the Theory”
strict regimen of “pure” intervals, i.e., those derived from the Qrst (Chapters 35–44). The material in Parts Two through Four makes
several members of the overtone series. How to mold pure inter- striking claims regarding equal temperament to be discussed
vals into the ideal scale is still very much an ongoing quest. Indeed, presently. Here, it is only important to note that rather than relying
many composers, performers, and theorists are passionately con- upon the methods and results of cognitive science to support his
cerned with matters of tuning and temperament, as journals such claims, the author candidly admits that, above all, the work is a
as David Doty’s 1/1 and John Chalmers’s Xenharmonikon, as well self-examination of his experiences as a singing and listening
as at least one very lively online discussion group attest.2 Aside musician. Avowedly “subjective,” it is, in the end, less a general
from Chalmers and Doty, other champions of the Qeld include theory of harmony than it is an autobiography of harmonic
Easley Blackwood, Lou Harrison, Ben Johnston, Charles Lucy, experiences. Musical examples consist almost exclusively of the
Joel Mandelbaum, William Sethares, Ervin Wilson, and LaMonte
3 The Huygens-Fokker Foundation has assembled a magniQcent Tuning

1For a sampling of what the Qeld offers, consult the works of its preeminent Bibliography as an online resource: http://www.xs4all.nl/,huygensf/doc/bib.
scholar, Joscelyn Godwin: Godwin 1986, 1989, 1995. html
2Online Tuning Group: http://groups.yahoo.com/group/tuning 4Mathieu 1991, 1994.
122 Music Theory Spectrum

author’s own exercises and compositions. The harmonic theories sensible phenomenon of reinforcement occurs. This phenomenon
presented here tacitly, and circularly, rely upon this repertoire of has a rather small bandwidth, in the midst of which stands an in-
original works for their veriQcation. The few examples not of the terval whose ratio is determined by small whole numbers.
author’s own composition are all European music, which is some- However, any interval that appears within the Qeld of tolerance is
what disappointing given the author’s obviously broader interests. resonant to some extent.
(It would have been interesting to see how Mathieu analyzes non- If this is correct, then resonance is a refashioning of a number
Western musics.5) Finally and perhaps most interestingly, with the of theories of consonance and dissonance, although it is important
use of his own form of Tonnetz, Mathieu not only reinvents much to mention that these terms are largely absent from this book.
of neo-Riemannian theory, but also advances it with a signiQcant Resonance provides the foundation for harmony. To Mathieu, har-
new perspective. mony is “not simply chord progressions but the relationships of all
the notes in a piece both to the keynote and to each other” (1).
***** Consulting the glossary again, we Qnd: “harmony: refers primar-
The “harmony” of the title is approached through the principle ily, in this book, to events that can be quantiQed by ratio, as op-
of “resonance.” It takes some effort to uncover exactly what the posed to events that can be measured by interval.” The term “in-
author means by this term. On page one, we read: “By resonance I terval” for Mathieu always signiQes unquantiQed “melodic”
mean those specially reinforcing combinations of tones that in distance. Harmony is two-fold: it is both “chord” as simultaneity
their mutual resounding—their perfect in-tune-ness—evaporate and also (surface) “chord progression.” Harmony is the primordial
the boundary between music and musician.” The glossary offers musical experience, and rules over and regulates all others includ-
this: “resonance: the conventional deQnition is the reinforcement ing melody, counterpoint, and rhythm. As a result, non-harmonic
of tones by synchronous or near-related vibration; as used in this tones are vexatious to Mathieu.
book, the term refers to sensible (that is, singable) combinations
of tones related by low-prime ratios” (528). There seem to be *****
three different deQnitions in all: one on page one, and two more in The Qrst part (“Harmonic Purity: Feeling the Numbers”) stands
the glossary. The deQnition “used in this book” is in fact not the well on its own as a teach-yourself text, whose main focus is
only one in play. At various points, resonance is said to accrue to learning how to hear and sing intervals in just intonation. Indian
all manner of harmonies, and we learn that the effects of reso- solfège syllables (sa, re, ga, ma, pa, dha, ni)7 are used in place of
nance will make themselves felt even in equal temperament.6 Guido’s do, re, mi. The range of instruction is breathtakingly vast.
Concatenating and extrapolating from the two glossary deQni- Readers begin by learning to sing unisons and octaves and, by
tions, the idea seems to be this: when some intervals are sung, a sticking to the program, progress on to produce a plethora of com-
mas. Along the way, Mathieu is there to extol, to challenge, to rail,
5Four measures of a single line taken from dictation given by Pandit Pran
to scold, to nurture, to amuse, to encourage, to exhort, to entertain,
Nath on p. 494 are the only exception.
6Gary Don has recently investigated the music of Debussy from a similar 7The second syllable, re, is taken from rishabha, and often transliterated

perspective. Don’s study, inspired by theoretical work of Ben Johnston, con- ri. One also comes across re, but the pronunciation is the same. A more ac-
cerns “a method whereby just intonation and equal tempered realizations of curate transliteration is r. s.abha, where the dots under the r and s indicate the
[passages in Debussy] can be heard side by side, providing a direct comparison retroRex position of the tongue. The word indicates a bellowing, “like a
of the different structures that result from just intonation” (Don, 2001, 73). bull.”
Reviews 123

to enlighten. Each topic is drawn in painstaking detail. The chapter cisely the trick of perception implicit in reciprocal harmony: A generates
that teaches the student to sing perfect Qfths concludes with in- the harmony, but C is still home—that is, A becomes the harmonic root,
structions to open the vowel “with the steadiness of the sun at mid- but C remains the tonic (48).
day,” to drop the jaw, relax the tongue, and to stand straight (26). The reader will see that, while portentous, this explanation
The very abundance of exercises, cajolings, and meanderings does not stand up to much scrutiny.8
can be of great value. Students who Qnds themselves interested in The progenitors in just intonation are the primes. Each prime
the relationship of tuning and intonation to music making will feel establishes its own line of harmonies extending in both overtonal
a safe and friendly guide near to hand every step of the way. and reciprocal directions, and is endowed with a distinct affect.
Mathieu proposes that in order to center the ear and voice in the Indeed, “Each prime number generates its own musical universe”
resonances, a tonic-Qfth drone should be used. The drone takes on (124). Much attention is given in this work to Qve-limit systems.9
great signiQcance in the modal and tonal theories that follow. There is a fair amount on seven-limit systems, but very little on
Central to Mathieu’s understanding of harmonic experience is systems with larger limits. Mathieu explains, “As the primes as-
the role of the tonic note whose gravitational pull is, if anything, cend father from unity, they become less functional as musical
more forceful here than in other tonal theories. The tonic is both elements, less able to generate their musical worlds” (125).
origin and reference point of all harmony. This is a crucial point. In Qve-limit systems, the primes three and Qve procreate other
The tonic is not only the “keynote” of a composition; it is also the tones, and the octave is responsible for normalizing register.
“generating tone.” Whereas a keynote needs only to be perceived Example 1 shows a portion of the pitch space associated with Qve-
as referential in some respect, a generator must people its realm limit just intonation. Mathieu provides a similar map with Qfths
with its overtones. This double burden brings Mathieu directly to along the x-axis, and thirds on the y-axis, and points out that this
the central dilemma of harmonic dualism: Tonal systems entail re- kind of representation (in fact a Tonnetz 10) is standard in depic-
lationships above and below the tonic, (“overtonal” and “recipro- tions of Qve-limit just intonation. Mathieu’s innovation is to tilt
cal” are Mathieu’s terms), but like a run of Biblical “begats,” the the plane a few degrees counterclockwise so that the points repre-
overtones run asymmetrically, in one direction only. Where do the sent notes in staff notation. The student is encouraged to trace
reciprocals come from? Propagation metaphors falter. If the tonic
is also the generator, metaphysics must be summoned to explain
the riddle of the subdominant: “When you sing F you create C.
8A comical rendering of a similar patrimony paradox is found in Joyce’s
How can you create the creative principle? How does one go
Ulysses: “He proves by algebra that Hamlet’s grandson is Shakespeare’s grand-
about giving birth to a musical god? That is the work of the
father and that he himself is the ghost of his own father” (19).
Musical Mother [the syllable ma stands for the fourth degree of 9Extended just intonation tuning systems are described as p-limit systems,

the scale] . . . You who dare to sing F in the C world become the where p is a prime. The unqualiQed term “just intonation” will refer to Qve-limit
embodiment of the creative and the sacred” (43). Similarly intri- just intonation.
10 Mathieu apparently believes that Alexander Ellis (in Helmholtz [1863]
cate machinery is necessary to explain other notes, such as the
1954) is the originator of the Tonnetz. While Ellis himself makes a similar
“reciprocal” major third below the tonic:
claim, Cohn (1997) awards the palm to Euler in 1739, although it might be
rightly claimed that the so-called lambda diagrams of antiquity (Archytas,
In order to generate A , we momentarily pretended that it was the tonic, Nicole of Oresme, etc.) depicting octaves and perfect twelfths in two dimen-
even though our larger context is C. We are not really in A . That is pre- sions are Tonnetze, rendering all proprietary claims moot.
124 Music Theory Spectrum

Example 1. A portion of the Qve-limit just-intonation Tonnetz with pitch classes represented by pitches in the octave of C = 1. Each cell displays
pitch-class name, ratio, and cents value. Subscripts on pitch-class names indicate syntonic commas; e.g., D-1 (10:9) is lower than D (9:8) by 80:81.

B22 F 22 C 22 G 22 D 22 A 22 E 22
(50:27) (25:18) (25:24) (25:16) (75:64) (225:128) (675:512)
1067¢ 569¢ 71¢ 773¢ 275¢ 977¢ 478¢

G21 D21 A21 E21 B21 F 21 C 21


(40:27) (10:9) (5:3) (5:4) (15:8) (45:32) (135:128)
680¢ 182¢ 884¢ 386¢ 1088¢ 590¢ 92¢

E B F C G D A
(32:27) (16:9) (4:3) (1:1) (3:2) (9:8) (27:16)
354 (or 358 )

294¢ 996¢ 498¢ 0¢ 702¢ 204¢ 906¢

C +1 G +1 D +1 A +1 E +1 B +1 F+1
(256:135) (64:45) (16:15) (8:5) (6:5) (9:5) (27:20)
1108¢ 610¢ 112¢ 814¢ 316¢ 1018¢ 520¢

A +2 E +2 B +2 F +2 C +2 G +2 D +2
(1024:675) (256:225) (128:75) (32:25) (48:25) (36:25) (27:25)
722¢ 223¢ 925¢ 427¢ 1129¢ 631¢ 133¢

3 32 (or 334 )

journeys through harmonic space upon this map, which will rein- minor third illustrates: E , the minor third up from C, is derived by
force and deepen the aural understanding. Mathieu’s Tonnetze re- generating G a 3:2 Qfth up from C, and then appending a 5:4 third
quire a tonic, which is the pitch-class C for the most part in this downward. There is no direct path from C to E . Because the
book. The tonic is endowed with its own symbol, a sunburst. “overtonal” direction is strongly privileged here, the minor triad is
Due to their roles as generators, perfect Qfths and major thirds not conceived as the simple inversion of the major: C is the tonic;
and their direct descendents have the most privileged status, and G is an overtone of the tonic; E is formed reciprocally downward
all other intervals are “secondary.” Mathieu’s derivation of the from G. There is some resemblance here between Mathieu’s
Reviews 125

explanation and Moritz Hauptmann’s “twin generator” idea of the Example 2. A jazz cadence (Mathieu’s Example 37.9)
minor chord. 11
Mathieu’s modal and tonal theories, introduced in this section,
are a direct outgrowth of the concept of “dronality.” The glossary
deQnes “dronal,” “dronality,” and “drone” without pinning down
the central concept. It appears that the drone is called upon to act
as a disambiguating agent in the realm of tones. The drone is the
power of the tonic made immanent. The authoritarian dronal tonic
will brook no insurrection, no usurpation. (The primary discussion chords to the C tonic. That is, the Qrst chord is to be understood as
about modulation does not begin until p. 306.) As Mathieu admits, C phrygian, the second as C lydian. Note the effect of this explana-
“If a drone is sufQciently assertive—that is, loud—you can put tion. What bubbles to the surface is something that routinely re-
anything above it, even a chain saw, and it will prevail as the mains submerged: the C common tone. (That its dronal companion
tonic” (234). Its disciplining power is summoned out of what G also forms a common tone here can only add fuel to Mathieu’s
seems like uneasiness that without it, the tones will lose sight of Qre.) A linear analysis of the cadence would have the C in the Qrst
their rightful ruler, form unauthorized allegiances among them- chord acting as a dissonance needing to be resolved—to be re-
selves, or worse, form none at all. “Unambiguous” harmonic pro- solved, indeed, into the B of the second chord. In Mathieu’s inter-
gressions are, for Mathieu, those in which there is a direct rela- pretation, the C has the same degree of structural importance in
tionship between the tonic and every note of every harmony. both chords. In other words, the cadence is not to be realized as a
Dronality admits no second-order relationships. The drone insists lydian mode on D followed by another on C, but by two different
on direct contact with each of its subordinates. modes of C (384). In like fashion, Mathieu rails against hearing
Two examples illustrate the megalomaniacal nature of the any non-tonic chord as giving rise to its own scale (359).
drone. The Qrst is Mathieu’s analysis of a jazz cadence, a pair of The second example is one of the few that is not the author’s
parallel thirteenth chords from D down to C, shown in Example own music. Instead, Mozart is taken to task for spelling errors.
2. Mathieu tells us that this formula is “typical to the point of This example splendidly demonstrates the skew that dronality ap-
being a cliché” (384). Half step cadences are certainly common in plies to tonality. Example 3(a) reproduces Mathieu’s Example
jazz. This variant has no particular prototypical status however, 15.5, taken from mm. 49–51 of the Qrst movement of the F Major
but rather seems arrived at by a careful process of stacking the Sonata for piano, K. 332. Example 3(b) (Mathieu’s 15.6) shows
deck. Like other jazz theorists, Mathieu assigns scales to chords, the author’s emendations to Mozart’s notation. A linear analysis
which is here quite easy to do, since both chords are heptatonic. of this passage would likely depict both the D and the F as as-
While the progression can be analyzed within the context of tri- cending chromatic appoggiaturas, while only the F is susceptible
tone substitution, this explanation is not invoked. Nor does the to that interpretation in Example 3(b). 12 As a chromatic lower
smooth, all-half-step voice leading come into play. Instead,
Mathieu insists upon a Qrm anchoring of all of the tones of both 12 I don’t think it succumbs to it, however. The fact that Mathieu leaves the

F notation unaltered has more to do with the fact that F comes on the “over-
tonal” side of C—either up six Qfths, or up two Qfths and a third—than with
11Harrison (1994, 228–9) provides a good summary. any secondary relationship between G and F .
126 Music Theory Spectrum

Example 3. Rewriting Mozart K. 332, Qrst movement While the D notation subordinates an appoggiatura to its reso-
(a) Mozart’s original notation (Mathieu’s Example 15.5) lution, the choice of E connotes an uneasy oscillation within the
chordal third. Neither third accepts the subordinate position. The
dissonance is entirely acoustic rather than syntactic.13 Mathieu’s
explicit avowal of the identity of tonality (“truly in the key of C”)
and dronality (“over a C drone”) is very telling, however the
conceptual amalgamation comes at the expense of both idioms. It
should be noted that when modulation is discussed later on, multi-
layered levels of tonal relationships are acknowledged.
(b) Mathieu’s corrections (Mathieu’s Example 15.6) Example 4 reproduces Mathieu’s Example 38.28. We are told
that being in a key is not always sharply deQned. There are degrees
and shades of gray. In this passage, “the C is heard as the leading
tone of the 10:9 re, giving that re Reeting credibility as a tonic.”
This reading is subtler than, and inconsistent with, the Mozart
analysis. Mathieu nicely revises the analogy of scale and ladder to
include sliding rungs for notes altered by a chromatic half step
(102). Perhaps the Mozart passage is best understood in terms of a
D rung that has been slid up to be nearer to the E, than as an E rung
(c) “Major/minor” seventh chord that slides up and down while we are standing upon it.
Mathieu makes an interesting claim in this context, namely,
that Bach never falls into Mozart’s kind of notational error. In the
given circumstances this is a claim that cannot be tested, because
the use of an unsupported 2̂ as a chromatically altered lower
neighbor to 3̂ is simply not in the Baroque language. The only way
for Mathieu to prove his case here would be to present a passage
in which Bach employs a notation such as the one in Example
neighbor, the D assumes a leading-tone quality, a perspective 3(b), eschewing that of 3(a).
openly mocked by Mathieu: I cannot leave this passage without suggesting another reason
for Mathieu’s E preference. Mathieu tells us that he Qrst came to
The passage obviously does not imply the key of E minor, so the D in
harmonic experience through jazz, and only later discovered
Mozart’s spelling is not its diatonic major seventh . . . Nor is the D in the
key of C. Or is it? Can you (honestly) hear a D over a C drone—that is,
truly in the key of C—as a raised second without it either becoming a minor 13 That dissonance has anything other than an acoustic basis is never chal-

third in your head (in which case it is E ), or modulating to E Minor? I lenged in this book. Among many works that might modify this view are
think the D in this harmonic context is simply a wrongness . . . a kind that Tenney 1968 and Krumhansl 1990. Recently, William Sethares (1998) has
appears increasingly as equal temperament becomes the European norm. demonstrated the intimate connection between timbre and the perception of
(105–6) consonance and dissonance.
Reviews 127

Example 4. Weak tonicization of D minor (Mathieu’s Example 38.28) Modality is given a modern triadic treatment, and harmonic pro-
gressions for Mathieu’s thirty-two modes, particularly for the
more familiar types, are suggested. Part 2 is concerned with com-
positional techniques whereby all harmonic progressions can be
mapped into a just-intonation prototype. Mathieu identiQes har-
monic ambiguity as arising from two causes: the appearance of
two versions of a single tone differing by a comma, and progres-
sions that leap over Tonnetz adjacencies. Ambiguity is avoided to
European art music. Example 3(c) shows a common jazz/funk begin with by forbidding both of these. “Matchstick” harmony is
chord, a “major/minor” seventh chord. In its context, this chord is the name given to the allowable “stepwise” progressions along the
quite stable, and easily carries tonic function. (Mathieu shows one Tonnetz. 14 Ambiguity and its attendant commas are introduced
with a dominant function on p. 355.) Neither of the thirds embel- gradually, leaving matchstick harmony to do the job of harmonic
lishes the other, and, in fact, the sonority suggests a “bent” blues clariQcation. (As I discuss later, Mathieu is equivocal about ambi-
third. The E is perfectly correct here. However, it would not be guity. It is “a dramatic—even dark—force in music” [349]. Part of
correct to propose the chord in Example 3(c) as an idiomatic har- his difQculty comes from presuming tonality to be inherently
monization for the Qrst measure of the Mozart melody. unambiguous.)
The modal system presented at the end of the Qrst part is There are three commas that come under consideration: the
unique, although its names are derived from the church modes and syntonic comma 81:80 (21.5¢), that represents the difference be-
its process of organization is somewhat akin to the Indian tween Pythagorean ditone and just major third, the diaschisma,
melakartas. Mathieu’s modes involve a lower tetrachord begin- 2048:2025 (19.55¢) that represents the difference between an oc-
ning on C, and an upper one beginning on G. There are four step tave and the sum of a Pythagorean ditone, and two just major
patterns allowed for the upper tetrachord: 2–2–1, 2–1–2, 1–3–1, thirds, and the minor diesis, 128:125 (41¢), that represents the dif-
1–2–2, and eight for the lower: these same four, and four tritonal ference between an octave and three just major thirds. Mathieu ap-
variants of these that add one to the last member of each: 2–2–2, parently conRates the minor diesis and the major diesis, 648:625
2–1–3, 1–3–2, 1–2–3. The resultant set of thirty-two modes in- (62.57¢) that is the difference between an octave and four minor
cludes all of the “white key” modes except locrian, both harmonic thirds. He may have overlooked this larger comma because of the
and melodic forms of the minor, and a remainder made up of inferior status accorded to the minor third. In the beginning of
those the process admits. Mathieu also proposes a “Magic Mode” Chapter 30, describing what neo-Riemannians call a “PR” cycle,
that contains all 12 notes needed for the set of thirty-two. The ab- the major diesis is achieved, but the references here are all to the
sence of locrian is telling. The inRuence of dronality commands
that, by construction, all modes must have a perfect Qfth above the
Qnal. Quite reasonably we are told that locrian is a “latter-day the-
14 The Tonnetz reminds Mathieu of “the matchstick puzzles and games we
oretical construct” (234), and with respect to the usages of
played as kids” (158). One puts a match down, connecting two points. The
European modality, this is certainly true. match may be moved so that one end stays Qxed. For example, from C major
Parts 2 through 4 recount the adventures of the modes and their one can get to G major, or E minor, or A minor, or F major, or F minor, or C
harmonies as they are transformed by equal temperament. minor.
128 Music Theory Spectrum

“Great Diesis,” Mathieu’s unfortunate name for the minor Let us nonetheless try to understand what Mathieu is telling us
diesis.15 Mathieu does not consider the Pythagorean comma, about equal temperament. The conclusion at the end of the book is
531441:524288 (23.46¢), to be of great practical signiQcance that in the simplest contexts, the sounds of equal temperament
since there are few compositional contexts in which its presence is stand unambiguously for the resonances of just intonation. This
felt. The schisma, 32768:32805 (1.953¢), the difference between unambiguous reference is equated with “tonality.” Then, “as ambi-
an octave and the sum of a just major third plus four Pythagorean guity increases, tonality weakens, resulting Qnally in the emer-
whole tones, is never mentioned, but would be, at 2¢, cognitively gence of the affective force inherent but hidden in the tuning: its
irrelevant for Mathieu’s purposes. symmetry and ultimate atonality” (508). The possibility of ambi-
After presenting exercises that teach the student to sing the guity being absent even at the beginning of this process is ques-
commas in just intonation, Mathieu goes on to track their effect in tionable; ambiguity is present ab ovo if melody and harmony are
equal temperament. There are Qne insights in this part of the book, conjoined.
yet much of it remains exasperatingly elusive: Mathieu attempts to demonstrate how context can reveal the
pure intervallic prototypes for harmonies sounding in equal tem-
The primary concern of this book is the behavior of twelve-tone equal
temperament, and we raise a question central to it: Physiologically and perament. Triads imply just intonation, and stacks of Qfths imply
psychologically, how can we accept a musical approximation for the real Pythagorean tuning. The syntonic (“Didymic”) comma is invoked
thing [i.e., just intonation]? Any answer to this question, at least at the by harmonizing E4 in two different ways: Qrst, using a C-major
present state of our knowledge, must be subjective, evanescent, and non- triad (E = 80), and then with a stack of four perfect Qfths from C2
quantiQable. Even the terms of the question cannot be rigorously deQned. through E4 (E = 81). Through a kind of homeopathic view of into-
ScientiQc method cannot save us. We do, however, have ourselves, not nation, Mathieu would have us believe that even in equal tempera-
only individually but also collectively. By examining deeply our own ment, the comma is still operant: “[In just intonation we] hear a
responses to musical phenomena, we can shed light on our musical small change in pitch as a large change in function. In equal tem-
behavior. (137–8) perament, the pitch difference is gone, yet the harmonic effect,
Indeed, the scientiQc method cannot save us, but it might pro- washed out as it may be, is not washed away” (254).16 Any retention
vide our inner examination with a structure that is intersubjective, of this effect is further diluted by the fact that there are often multi-
not completely evanescent, and enumerable. We may even boldly ple contexts for a single harmonic event. As Mathieu points out, the
and rigorously deQne our question. The problem with not wanting stack-of-Qfths chord producing E = 81 is often employed in jazz
to say anything too precisely is that of not in the end saying any- as a tonic-triad surrogate, and so clearly the E4 would need to be
thing at all. modeled after the just-intonation 5:4 major third as it sits atop the
stack of 3:2 perfect Qfths. Which third is the clear prototype here?
This would be a likely place to discuss meantone tempera-
15More evidence of this problem is found in Table 41.1 (473). Here the dif-
ments, but “meantone temperament” has a single entry in the
ference between four 6:5 minor thirds and an octave is equated incorrectly
with one diaschisma plus one (minor) diesis. Curiously, Mathieu posits a “su-
perdiesis” on p. 501. This is none other than the missing “major diesis,” 16 “Hearing” a harmonic effect in an interval that is acoustically identical to

648:625. Here it is correctly equated with one syntonic comma plus one unison is reminiscent of the passage in Plato’s Republic (VII:531) in which the
(minor) diesis, and then incorrectly equated with “four pure thirds plus four “teachers of harmony” put their ears close to the strings to see who can hear the
perfect Qfths.” “Plus” probably should have been “minus.” smallest pyknon.
Reviews 129

index. The history of intonation presented here traces a more or shadows melody. Harmony can exist without melody, but not the
less straight shot from Qve-limit just intonation directly into equal other way around. This view is in direct conRict with the notion
temperament. The reader would accordingly get the impression that melody is historically prior to harmony and, arguably, con-
that the historical tuning for the church modes was Qve-limit just ceptually prior as well. Mathieu proposes a thought experiment by
intonation, despite the clear evidence of medieval treatises (e.g., way of support of his position (390). He asks us to hear a cadence
Dialogus in musica) explaining in great detail how to establish the performed in Shepard tones (without calling them such). There is
monochord in Pythagorean tuning—three-limit just intonation, if no melody to speak of, but the harmonic syntax would remain
you will.17 completely clear. Another hypothesis, tested and proven in fact by
Mathieu is absolutely right in saying that learning to hear and Roger Shepard, suggests that the inRuence of melody is so great,
sing intervals in just intonation is a fabulously enriching, even em- the ear would tend to create melodies out of the smallest potential
powering musical experience. It opens a door from the Ratland of intervals of every interval class.18 If asked to sing what was heard,
equal temperament into a multi-dimensional new world. It can be some such derived melody would be the result. Thus, melody and
exhilarating to the point of vertigo. It can also give new respect for harmony share equally in the cadential effect. Neither can be fac-
equal temperament through a deeper appreciation of what it so tored out.
elegantly accomplishes. We acknowledge with greater insight all Melodic principles and harmonic ones generate different kinds
of the intonational conRicts it is able to quell and delight in its of tonal spaces. Curt Sachs proposed “cyclic” and “divisive” prin-
own alluring duodecimal symmetries. ciples of scale construction. 19 The cyclic principle is that of a gen-
Furthermore, there are many circumstances in which it is pos- erated set, while the divisive one uses arithmetic or harmonic
sible to disambiguate the intervals that we hear in equal tempera- means in order to subdivide the octave. Melodic contexts favor the
ment; for example, we expect our students to spell their chords cyclic principle, harmonic ones the divisive. The cyclic systems,
correctly, even when they are taking dictation from the piano. such as Pythagorean tuning, offer both a manageably low number
However, as earlier examples have shown, some enharmonic func- of step-interval types and a great range of potential tonics or
tions have become so fused in equal temperament that it is not pos- modal “Qnals,” and they also easily adapt to the challenges of
sible to disambiguate the harmonies without removing some of the modulation. They may, however, be poorer in what Mathieu calls
harmonic signiQcations. A many-to-one mapping is not reversible. resonance. The divisive systems, such as just intonation, are more
For Mathieu then, just intonation is authentic harmonic experi- tonic speciQc, maximizing harmonic purity for the sake of the
ence, but equal temperament will allow, when conditions are right, central tone and showing less regard for the remaining ones. If
a close replica. While this position is reasonable enough, there is other tones are to be made into Qnals, intonational adjustments are
no real acknowledgement of the snake in the garden in the story of generally required. The number of melodic step intervals tends to
tuning, the sinuous allure of melody unadorned. The slighting of be higher in divisive tone-spaces. While enthusiasts of Qve-limit
melodic study in this book could be easily justiQed—this is a book just intonation can delight in its subtle varieties of major and
about harmony, after all, and not melody. However, this masks a minor tone, Pythagorean tuning has at least equal pedigree, and no
more serious issue—namely, that harmony and melody are not such differences.
equal partners in the author’s view. Harmony commands and over-
18 Shephard 1964.
17 Strunk 1965, 103–16. 19 Sachs 1948, 14 ff.
130 Music Theory Spectrum

In Mathieu’s “dronal” circumstances, vertical relationships are relation to tonal harmony—but Mathieu is willing to shore it
all-powerful. But while much ancient and traditional music made up at the expense of considerably problematizing melodic
use of drones, this is not a musical universal. There is, for ex- composition.
ample, no evidence that the Gregorian chant repertoire originated Perhaps, like many others, Mathieu believes that harmony
with an accompanying drone. Without the drone, purely melodic can be taught, but melody cannot. When telling us how to Resh
considerations take over. out a harmonically constructed skeleton, we are reassured that,
There is, then, a conRict between (at least) two “natural” into- “the tones seem to spontaneously generate melodies on their
national systems, one that rules the harmonic realm, one the own” (38). Similarly, “in a way these melodies write themselves.
melodic. In the mythic language of love, the vertical agape, con- If a harmonic progression is balanced, the melodies inside it are
necting the human and divine, would be all harmonious were it eager to be awakened” (170). This is not likely to be much
not for a conRicting horizontal eros connecting beings of the same consolation to beginners who cannot get their melodic kites
kind. Dionysius’s passionate aulos discords with the rational lyre airborne.
of Apollo. The history of temperament, including equal tempera- There is very little information about chordal inversion in this
ment, tells of the mediation between these conRicting “natural” book, but this, too, is consistent with the view of harmony pre-
claims. sented here. What attention the subject does get is both sketchy
That there is a difference between the intonational norms of and misleading. On p. 370, we are told that 63 stands for Qrst inver-
harmony and melody is implicit in Mathieu’s presentation of his sion and 3 stands for root position, but are not told why, nor that 63
modal theory. After Qrst introducing the major and minor tones in may be abbreviated to 6, nor that root position is generally abbre-
Chapter 10, the step patterns of the primary modes are illustrated viated with no Qgure at all. On the following page, jazz-based Qg-
in Chapter 11 using step sizes of “1” and “1/2.” What has hap- ures are introduced, and we are told that a 7 standing by itself al-
pened to 9:8 and 10:9? The maps depicting these modes clearly ways means to add a minor seventh above the bass. All of these
show that they must be understood in just intonation. Even for are true in some context, but there is no single context in which
Mathieu, the melodic need for intervallic parsimony has tran- they are all true. (Some pages later, we are informed that 65 means
scended the harmonic need for purity. (The interval labeled “1/2” Qrst inversion of a seventh chord, and 42 means third inversion. The
that connects leading tone to tonic is invariably 16:15 in this book. Qgures are never explained; nor is there ever a 43.) On the other
There is virtually no mention of the smaller, more melodically ori- hand, the cadential 64 chord, although always labeled “I64 ” is lu-
ented Pythagorean half step, 256:243.) cidly described as a double suspension whose content may be
With the strong emphasis on resonance and verticality, embel- tonic, but whose context is clearly dominant. He is oddly ill at
lishments and tones of Qguration have little chance to Rourish. ease with the dominant seventh chord. He Qnds V with the seventh
The approach is in agreement with Schoenberg’s assertion that to be more “dramatic” but no more “compelling” than it is with-
“non-harmonic tone” is a misnomer.20 This proposition is one that out. Monitoring his own inner responses to the chord, he reports,
Schoenberg ultimately found difQcult to support— at least in “When I hear it without thinking about it, and respond to it sim-
ply, there remains a mystery at the heart of it. I get it and I don’t
20 Schoenberg [1911] 1978. See in particular Chapter 17, “Non-Harmonic get it. Maybe this mystery is the actual deQnition of tonality: the
Tones,” pp. 309–44. mystery of the center” (391).
Reviews 131

***** enharmonicism.22 Even if one travels far out in one direction along
Mathieu has a fresh approach to many issues that have come the Tonnetz, if one returns by means of a continuous path back to
under the rubric “neo-Riemannian” theory. Diatonic and chro- the tonic (here is where the “matchstick” approach pays off ), there
matic sequences are examined very carefully throughout the sec- is no enharmonic legerdemain. He invents a kind of “shape note”
ond half of the book. On p. 157, there is a description of the system for the analysis: each Qfth-based horizontal of the Tonnetz
Leittonwechselklang (not called such), connecting a “major triad has its own note shape. The approach, as one may expect, is com-
to its mediant” or a “minor chord and its submediant.” The various pletely non-mathematical, although the choice to formalize these
“cycles” that have become the focus of Neo-Riemannian theory procedures within the strictures of transformation theory is more a
are all present without the now conventional nomenclature. At the matter of style than it is of substance.
beginning of Chapter 30, which deals with the minor diesis Mathieu’s analysis of the rondeau Fumeaux fume par fumée
128:125, the “PR” cycle is illustrated on p. 286. This cycle would (pp. 495–9), by the Ars Subtilior composer Solage is the most
eventually create the major diesis, 648:625; however, as men- convincing analysis of the four he presents. Without much com-
tioned earlier, the major diesis is not distinguished from the minor mentary, Mathieu demonstrates that, despite the extreme chro-
in this book. (His claim that “[the PR cycle] is not commonly maticism, no comma shifts are employed and all enharmonic
heard harmony” is not supported by Neo-Riemannian studies, in debts are paid. The work does not proceed, out and back, literally
which a number of examples from nineteenth-century composi- stepwise along the lattice. However, the analysis shows that the
tions are cited.) The “LP” cycle is described on p. 348, here prop- piece may be performed within a closed region of the Tonnetz
erly illustrating the minor diesis. The “RL” cycle, evoking the without the need for topological “loops.”23 There is even a playful
Pythagorean comma, is fully described on pp. 448–9, using an text/music relationship drawn out of his analytical method. While
example that might have been suggested by the Scherzo of situating the piece within a triadic context is anachronistic, there
Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony.21 is nothing about the analysis that relies upon the conventions of
Whereas the cognitive claims about commas in equal tempera- common practice-tonality. There would seem to be a great deal
ment are perhaps questionable, Mathieu has some interesting of repertoire that could yield to this method, including essentially
things to say about commas with regard to their capacity to struc- the whole of the Renaissance, particularly the chromatic works
ture and delimit Tonnetze. He describes a method he calls “posi- of either the fourteenth or sixteenth centuries. Less successful is
tional analysis” that tracks the harmonic path of a piece along the his positional analysis of the Qrst movement of the Beethoven
Tonnetz. He is especially concerned with topological issues that Appassionata sonata (p. 506). Its fervently chord-by-chord ap-
cast commas in the roles of delimiters. The gist of the method is to proach arrives at the conclusion that, counting all comma cross-
determine whether the excerpt in question is forced to employ an ings, the piece begins in F minor and ends in A minor.

21Measures 132–71. Again, the dearth of examples from the literature is un-

22Brian Hyer (1995, 106) describes Riemann’s sensitivity to the pathways


fortunate. Mathieu shows us that while the bass moves down by minor and
major thirds alternately (with some upward sixths for registral normalization), along the Tonnetz for their role in determining intonation.
each of the three upper voices travels in one of the three different octatonic 23In Hyer (1995, 119) the topological transformations of the Tonnetz are de-

scales. This elegant result is found also in Cohn 1991, 1992, 1997. See also picted as they are mapped from inQnitely extended just intonation into equal
Douthett & Steinbach 1998. temperament.
132 Music Theory Spectrum

***** with octaves, the only “directly intelligible intervals.” Finally,


While clearly passionate about his topic and eager to spread Mathieu reveals that “harmony is form.” Summing up the main
the joy of his discoveries, Mathieu is often woefully vague in the contributions his harmonic theory makes, he writes:
deQnition of terms. Aside from examples already given, deQni-
The theory . . . demonstrates how elemental harmonic principles are
tions of the terms “scale,” “mode,” and “key” are either mislead-
architectonic— that is, how their structure controls or directs other
ing or simply uninformative. Like many autodidacts, Mathieu can
structures— and how this active, forming energy cuts both ways across the
be rather desultory in recounting the histories of his topic. Neither orders of magnitude . . . One begins to grasp . . . how the smallest ele-
is he averse to casting a wide but tattered net of aspersions on ments and the largest formal shapes are mutually nourishing. (510)
predecessors. This is perhaps the most troubling aspect of the
book. For example, we are told on p. 1 that “there exists no satis- A lofty vision, indeed; however, it would not have been remiss
factory general theory of harmony,” and “We have no comprehen- to acknowledge the powerful manifestation of this same vision in
sive music theory today.” Later, Mathieu writes: “Over the cen- the work of Heinrich Schenker.
turies, classical music theory has developed a wide variety of Most of all, Mathieu criticizes European music theory (“classi-
misleading concepts” (319). Telling music-historical tales with lit- cal theory” as he calls it) for not concerning itself with affect. “I
tle regard for precision, and having reached the Qfteenth century, could not Qnd—try as I might—the connection between classical
Mathieu opines, “Remember that there was no unifying viable theory and the palette of feeling that its music inspires” (2). The
music theory at the time—certainly no practical one—that clariQed apparent assumption, that the feelings are caused by harmonies
procedures. (There still isn’t, unless this is it.)” (135). So what is themselves, is carried by the force of revelation here, and alterna-
new? Mathieu claims that what “clariQes procedures” is deriving tives to it barely merit mentioning. We are, he concludes, designed
the laws of harmony from resonance or from the overtone series. to respond to certain harmonies in certain ways: “The forces that
While there may not be much information on the overtone series govern the production of overtones govern our ears also, and our
in standard college harmony texts, it would have been well to con- ears’ responses” (41). In short, “pure harmony is hard-wired”
sider the contributions of some of his true predecessors in the Qeld (141). Furthermore, the wiring takes the shape of “Qfth-by-third”
of harmonic theory. Taking, for example, three well-known theorists Tonnetze: “The ease with which we comprehend the nested geog-
with important things to say about harmony, Rameau, Riemann, and raphy of music indicates that the harmonic lattice is not merely a
Schenker, we notice that none of them Qnd their way into this book, metaphor for musical behavior, but corresponds to a spatial geog-
and yet all were at least as concerned as Mathieu to derive harmony raphy in the brain” (359).
from the sonorities of the overtone series in some way (nor are they This is not a book with scholarly pretenses, and so an extensive
unique in this respect). Rameau’s notion of the corps sonore, for ex- citation of the work of others is not the point. To be sure, in the
ample, closely mirrors Mathieu’s “resonance.” Like Riemann and very Qnal section entitled, “Whose Theory Is It?” he graciously ac-
Oettingen, Mathieu derives systems of sonorities in dualist terms knowledges a debt to his teachers, and is quick to confess that he
and displays them in Tonnetze. There is even a lovely recasting of has not “created anything new.” Nevertheless, before we get to this
Hauptmann’s “having an overtone—being an overtone” solution to point, we have been told repeatedly that all harmonic theory up to
the undertone problem (42). Furthermore, Mathieu would agree but not necessarily including the present opus is unsatisfactory,
with Hauptmann that perfect Qfths and major thirds are, along misleading, and impractical.
Reviews 133

***** LIST OF WORKS CITED


Perhaps Mathieu’s greatest unacknowledged debt is to
Moritz Hauptmann. It is quite possible that Hauptmann is un- Aristides Quintilianus. 1983. Aristides Quintilianus On Music In
known to Mathieu, but he would nonetheless Qnd in Hauptmann Three Books. Translation with introduction, commentary, and
an ancestor worthy of his esteem. Let me recapitulate some of annotations by Thomas J. Mathiesen. New Haven: Yale Univer-
the points of correspondence between the two theorists: in addi- sity Press.
tion to the understanding of octaves, Qfths, and thirds as the Barker, Andrew. 1989. Greek Musical Writings II: Harmonic and
only “directly intelligible intervals” and the solving of the “un- Acoustic Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
dertone” problem with the device of “having/being” an over- Boethius, Anicius Manlius Severinus. 1989. Fundamentals of Mu-
tone, both employ a “twin generator” approach to the origin of sic. Translated by Calvin Bower. New Haven: Yale University
the minor chord; both are concerned with the church modes as Press.
well as derivatives thereof in the context of just intonation; both Cohn, Richard. 1991. “Properties and Generability of Transpo-
are guided fundamentally by dualism and committed to its sitionally Invariant Sets.” Journal of Music Theory 35: 1–32.
metaphysical underpinnings. Whereas the roots of Hauptmann’s ———. 1992. “Dramatization of Hypermetric ConRicts in the
thought are found in Hegel, Mathieu himself takes an occa- Scherzo of Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony.” 19th-Century
sional Hegelian turn: “We need to elevate the status of the Music 15.3: 22–40.
equal-tempered comma from that of a pun, where a single thing ———. 1997. “Neo-Riemannian Operations, Parsimonious Tri-
stands for two incidentally related things, to that of a match- chords, and Their Tonnetz Representations.” Journal of Music
maker, where complementary energies are conjoined and syn- Theory 41: 1–66.
thesized into a higher meaning” (347). Daniélou, Alain. 1943. Music and the Power of Sound: The In-
There is no more exacting discipline than that of looking Guence of Tuning and Interval on Consciousness. Revised edi-
within and reporting accurately on one’s Qndings. Mathieu is tion of Introduction to the Study of Musical Scales. Rochester,
brilliant in describing his own inner journey of harmonic dis- Vermont: Inner Traditions.
covery. He writes with a distinct voice, and his passion for his Douthett, Jack, and Peter Steinbach. 1998. “Parsimonious Graphs:
subject is profound and profoundly moving. It Qnally does not A Study in Parsimony, Contextual Transformations, and
matter knowing how much of his tongue may have been in his Modes of Limited Transposition.” Journal of Music Theory 42:
cheek as he intones a “Hymn to the Great Diesis” (298). We in- 241–63.
tone along with him. Nor can one respond with anything other Don, Gary. 2001. “Brilliant Colors Provocatively Mixed: Over-
than fondness as he conjures up his alter ego, “Dr. Overtone.” tone Structures in the Music of Debussy.” Music Theory
The range of encomiums on the back cover from the likes of Spectrum 23: 61–73.
John Coltrane, Pete Seeger, and Ben Johnston attest to a life Godwin, Joscelyn, ed. 1986. Music, Mysticism And Magic: A
lived in great devotion to his subject, a profession in the truest Sourcebook. New York: Arkana.
sense. While problematic in the respects I have addressed, this ———. 1989. Cosmic Music: Musical Keys to the Interpretation of
book has much to offer to every musician who is beguiled and Reality. Essays by Martius Schneider, Rudolf Haase, and Hans
beckoned by the mystery at the center of the musical art. Erhard Lauer. Introduction by Joscelyn Godwin. Translated by
134 Music Theory Spectrum

Marton Radkai and Joscelyn Godwin. Rochester, Vermont: McClain, Ernest G. 1978. The Pythagorean Plato. York Beach,
Inner Traditions. Maine: Nicolas-Hays.
Godwin, Joscelyn. 1995. Music and the Occult: French Musical Sachs, Curt. 1948. Our Musical Heritage. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.:
Philosophies, 1750–1950. Rochester, N.Y.: University of Prentice Hall.
Rochester Press. Schoenberg, Arnold. [1911] 1978. Theory Of Harmony.
Harrison, Daniel. 1994. Harmonic Function In Chromatic Music: Translated by Roy E. Carter. Berkeley: University of California
A Renewed Dualist Theory and an Account of its Precedents. Press.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Sethares, William. 1998. Tuning, Timbre, Spectrum, Scale.
Hauptmann, Moritz. [1853] 1991. The Nature Of Harmony And London: Springer.
Metre. Translated and edited by W. E. Heathcote. New fore- Shepard, R. N. 1964. “Circularity in Judgments of Relative Pitch.”
word by Siegmund Levarie. New York: Da Capo Press. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 36: 2346–53.
Helmholtz, Hermann. [1863] 1954. On The Sensations of Tone. Strunk, W. Oliver. 1965. Source Readings In Music History:
Translated by Alexander Ellis. New York: Dover. Antiquity and the Middle Ages. New York: W. W. Norton.
Hyer, Brian. 1995. “Reimag(in)ing Riemann.” Journal of Music Tenney, James. 1988. A History Of “Consonance” And “Disso-
Theory 39: 101–38. nance.” New York: Excelsior.
Krumhansl, Carol. 1990. Cognitive Foundations of Musical Pitch.
New York: Oxford University Press. WEB BASED SOURCES:
Mathiesen, Thomas. 1999. Apollo’s Lyre. Lincoln: University of Huygens-Fokker Foundation, Tuning Bibliography. URL: http://
Nebraska Press. www.xs4all.nl/~huygensf/doc/bib.html
Mathieu, W. A. 1991. The Listening Book: Discovering Your Own Tuning Group. URL: http://groups.yahoo.com/ group/tuning
Music. Boston: Shambhala.
———. 1994. The Musical Life: ReGections On What It Is And
How To Live It. Boston: Shambhala.
Reviews 135

Heinrich Schenker. The Art of Performance. Edited by Heribert derstand this problem. I will explain it to you again.” He describes
Esser. Translated by Irene Schreier Scott. New York: Oxford how Schenker, for whom “rule and masterwork were one and the
University Press, 2000. same,” invariably illustrated theoretical rules with practical ex-
amples, which he always had at his Qngertips. 3 Another student,
Reviewed by David Gagné and Hedi Siegel the theorist and composer Felix-Eberhard von Cube, is reported as
praising “his teacher’s sense of humor, his patience, and above all
Heinrich Schenker’s major theoretical works are widely known his insistence that the piece his pupil is studying be learned thor-
today, thanks to a series of translations as well as a vast secondary oughly, down to the Qnest detail, so that all of the pianist’s
literature and numerous textbooks. Because of this dissemination resources contribute to a uniQed performance.”4
of his ideas, Schenker’s work is often perceived in purely theoreti- But these are second-hand reports. We are most fortunate that
cal terms. But viewing Schenker solely in relation to such con- Oxford University Press has published Heribert Esser’s edition of
cepts as structural levels results in a limited and distorted picture The Art of Performance in a lucid translation by Irene Schreier
of this preeminent Qgure in twentieth-century music theory. Scott. This book is a Qrst-hand account of what Schenker taught:
Schenker began his professional career not as a theorist, but as a it permits us to eavesdrop on his lessons, so to speak, putting us in
pianist, conductor, and composer. (His compositions were favor- the position of one of his students. William Rothstein commented
ably regarded by Brahms and Busoni.) Between 1891 and 1901, on the value of such piano instruction when discussing the as yet
Schenker was also active as an author of essays and reviews; his unpublished materials—Vom Vortrag (“On Performance”) and
subsequent theoretical work developed in part from the desire to Entwurf einer “Lehre vom Vortrag” (“Sketch of a Theory of
establish a more satisfactory basis for criticism of composition and Performance”)—that he consulted at the Oswald Jonas Memorial
performance.1 Harmonielehre demonstrates that he saw himself as Collection at the University of California in Riverside:
an artist Qrst: when Schenker published it, the words “von einem
The subject of hand motions on the piano may seem an esoteric one to the
Künstler” (by an artist) appeared in place of his own name on the non-pianist. It is surely far from the realm of what is generally considered
title page.2 He remained an active practical musician and teacher music theory. Yet both Vom Vortrag and the Entwurf contain important
throughout his life, giving private lessons in piano and theory. sections on hand motions, Qngering, and other aspects of piano technique.
Schenker’s teaching methods went far beyond those of conven- Despite appearances to the contrary, there is no contradiction here: in-
tional piano and theory instruction. Some of his students have deed, it is Qtting that Schenker, who saw his mission as the reuniting of
written about their lessons with him. One student, the conductor theory and practice, and who often used the lowly piano lesson as the ve-
Hans Wolf, speaks of the interest Schenker took in all aspects of hicle for his theoretical teaching, should have paid so much attention to
his musical life and recounts how Schenker quizzed him about the such practical matters. 5
details of performances that he had heard. Writing of the close at- Schenker’s theoretical and analytical approach was developed
tention he received, he records Schenker as saying at the begin- chieRy to serve the performer—to impart an understanding of the
ning of a theory lesson (consulting the detailed notes he kept on
each student): “Last time I noticed that you didn’t completely un- 3Wolf 1937, 176–77.
4From William Drabkin’s summary of von Cube’s letter to his father (10
1 Schenker’s early writings are collected in Federhofer 1990. January 1924). See Drabkin 1984–85, 184.
2 See Schenker 1906. 5Rothstein 1984, 21.
136 Music Theory Spectrum

true content of the music. Many of his analytic essays conclude Schenker’s hand, most dating from the late 1920s. 8 Soon after her
with a section on performance, and his critical editions likewise husband’s death in 1935, Jeanette Schenker and Schenker’s stu-
contain practical performance advice. Two early works, Ein dent Oswald Jonas together organized the Vortrag materials found
Beitrag zur Ornamentik (1904, revised 1908) and J. S. Bach, in Schenker’s Nachlass. Jonas was occupied with them for the rest
Chromatische Phantasie und Fuge: Kritische Ausgabe (1910), in- of his life, transcribing, compiling, and annotating the manu-
clude discussions of such topics as tempo, dynamics, touch, and scripts, as well as lecturing and writing about his Qndings. 9 In the
Qngering that are directly linked to his work on a separate perfor- 1950s he worked intensively with the editor of the present vol-
mance study.6 ume, Heribert Esser, and, in consultation with Ernst Oster, laid the
Holding the book in one’s hand and looking at the author and foundation for the publication of the book which Schenker had
title, one might think that it represents Heinrich Schenker’s com- hoped to publish himself.10
pletion of his long-promised monograph on performance.7 But in Thus, Esser, who was asked to take over the editorial work
fact this slim book (fewer than 100 pages of text) is a compilation after Jonas’s death in 1978, has a long history of involvement with
of drafts and fragments: it could have been published as an essay the Vortrag project. His collaboration with Jonas perhaps led him
called something like “Schenker’s UnQnished Theory of to edit the book very much in Jonas’s spirit. Jonas, without whose
Performance.” The editor and translator, however, made the deci- editorial efforts many of Schenker’s works would never have be-
sion to shape the material into a book that has the appearance of a come widely available, edited with a free hand; his aim, under-
Qnished work, and give it Schenker’s intended title, Die Kunst des standable given the climate of his time, was to present Schenker’s
Vortrags (The Art of Performance) even though they knew it could writings in the best possible light. 11 Adopting a similar editorial
“never be the ‘book’ Schenker intended to write” (xii). We think policy, this time in the interest of practicality, Esser modiQed the
they were right to do so, given the diverse and unQnished nature of structure of Schenker’s early text and liberally interpolated the
the manuscripts, and they have accomplished their aim to create a later material contained in the sketches. Stating that he “felt
practical work attractive to the performing musician. The material the need of handling the material with a certain amount of free-
is too valuable to be treated as an archival study and thus be con- dom,” and that it “would have been extraordinarily pedantic
sulted mainly in libraries; it seems to demand application in the to present the sources literally in every detail” (xx), he provides
studio and the concert hall. little or no correlation of the text passages with the original. One
The text of the book originated mainly in the two manuscripts
found in the Jonas Collection. As mentioned above, the Qrst is a
8 These are Esser’s sources A and B; see his listing of source materials
draft with the title Vom Vortrag, and consists of twelve chapters
(xvii–xviii).
taken down from dictation by Jeanette Schenker in the summer of 9Jonas 1962 discusses and quotes several important Vortrag passages.

1911; the second is a gathering of fragmentary notes mainly in 10 The typescripts that emerged from this collaboration are listed by Esser as

sources C and D (xviii). Copies that Esser made of some of the source material
found their way into the Oster Collection of the New York Public Library,
which also houses related material.
6 See Schenker 1976, 44 ff., and Schenker 1984, 63 ff. 11 Jonas issued the following new editions: Schenker 1954 (a revision and

7 Statements regarding its forthcoming publication abound in Schenker’s translation of the 1906 edition), Schenker 1956 (a revision of the 1935 edition),
writings, e.g., in Beethovens neunte Sinfonie (Vienna: Universal Edition, 1912), Schenker 1969 (a revision of the 1910 edition), and Schenker 1971–72 (a revi-
quoted by Esser at the beginning of his introduction (xi). See Schenker 1992, 8. sion of the 1913–20 editions).
Reviews 137

cannot help wishing that a way had been found to provide fuller In the text of The Art of Performance it is the language of
documentation—and even to include the original German text— Schenker’s more mature theory that invites detection. Even in the
without sacriQcing the orderliness and clarity that gives the book chapters that seem to derive largely from the manuscript of 1911,
its wide appeal. For now, the scholar interested in tracing the text one Qnds interpolations or additions drawn from the later material.
to its sources must consult the material in the Oster and Jonas These are recognizable from the use of such terms as “back-
Collections. 12 ground” and “foreground,” familiar from Schenker’s writings be-
Characterized by its editor as the Qrst major publication to ginning with the Tonwille essays of the 1920s. This sometimes re-
come out of Schenker’s Nachlass, this book is unique among sults in a mixture of varying stages of Schenker’s thought. Yet it
Schenker’s writings, not only because of its focus on performance seems appropriate that the editor supplement the earlier text with
matters, but also because it represents a reconstruction of incom- later passages such as the following fragment, rich in poetic im-
plete and fragmentary material. One is reminded of analogous agery: “Light and spirited renditions are made possible only by an
projects in the realm of musical composition—the completion of overall view, by thinking ahead, thereby giving wings to the hand.
works left unQnished at a composer’s death.13 With his free juxta- The ear, too, like the eye, must offer us perspective. This ability
position of material from various sources, Esser is in a sense emu- comes from understanding the background” (73). 14 Despite the dis-
lating Schenker’s own procedures. The manuscripts Schenker cre- parity of the source material, the incorporation of such passages
ated with his wife, now in the Oster and Jonas Collections, often enriches the text. A decision was made, however, to exclude ex-
show signs of having been literally cut and pasted together. Even amples that would require readers to be familiar with the mature
Free Composition originated in this way: in the early 1920s, as theory presented in Free Composition. 15 The editor’s desire to cre-
Schenker set out to revise a version he had dictated around 1917, ate a practical rather than theoretical work is understandable; nev-
he started by rearranging the original chapters and inserting new ertheless the absence of this material is to be regretted. Surely,
ones. He eventually abandoned his efforts to create a composite room could have been made for the examples in an appendix, as
text; the Qnal version of Der freie Satz is based mainly on a was done with the two chapters of Vom Vortrag (the 1911 manu-
freshly dictated manuscript. But, in a few places, vestiges of the script) that were omitted from the main part of the book. 16
earlier versions can be detected. About half of the chapters, mainly those that include musical
examples, seem to derive almost entirely from the later material.
A representative illustration will demonstrate the difQculties
12 Some of the original source material may be found in Rothstein 1984.
posed by the notes Schenker hastily jotted down on scraps of
Rothstein includes passages he translates from Vom Vortrag (the early text that
Schenker dictated, Esser’s source A), and from the Entwurf einer “Lehre vom
Vortrag,” a 38-page typescript prepared by Jonas from Schenker’s later frag- 14 Part of this passage, which is from the Entwurf, is quoted in Rothstein

mentary sketches (Esser’s source D). The German original (and its location in 1984, 25 and 28 (note 60).
15 See Esser’s introductory remarks (xv–xvi and xxi).
the sources) is given for each quoted passage. We are grateful to William
Rothstein for making available to us his transcription and photocopies of the 16 Summaries are given of these chapters, “On the Technique of the Piano in

Vortrag material he consulted at the Jonas Collection. Particular” (Appendix A), and “On the Degeneracy of the Virtuoso” (Appendix
13 This analogy is only approximate, of course, since new material is sup- B). We agree with the editor’s decision regarding the polemical latter chapter,
plied in the completion of a musical work, whereas Esser reorganized which is now mainly of historical interest. The reason given for moving and
Schenker’s text without adding to it. However, given the substantial nature of curtailing the former chapter is enigmatic: “Its publication in full is planned in a
the revision, such a comparison is perhaps not misplaced. different context” (81).
138 Music Theory Spectrum

paper. The small collection of illustrations from the manuscripts Example 1. Schenker’s manuscript sketch (The Art of Performance,
offered in the introductory pages of the book includes a sketch we from Plate 2, xxv)
reproduce in Example 1. A transcription of the Qrst musical illus-
tration within the sketch is given in Example 2.
Schenker’s barely legible and telegraphic notes, shown in
Example 1, were transcribed and reconstructed by Jonas as follows:
Die Hand darf nicht lügen, sie muß dem Sinn der Stimmführung folgen.
Sie lügt, wenn sie gegen die Stimmführung verstößt: Mozart, A dur
Sonate, Thema [example]

also [die] Hand darf nicht die Oktave a2–a1 spielen, muß verbinden
vielmehr: [example] 17

In the book, this passage appears in the chapter entitled “The


Technique of Playing the Piano”; it expands on Schenker’s state-
ment that “the meaning of the phrase determines the position and
motion of the hands” (8):
The hand may not lie; it must conform to the meaning of the voice-
leading. It lies if in Example 3.5 [rendered here as Example 2] this is Example 2. Mozart, Sonata K. 331, Qrst movement, theme, bars
violated by playing a2–a1; the connection must be f 2 and c 2. (9)
17–18 (The Art of Performance, Example 3.5, 10)
The translation preserves Schenker’s vivid endowment of the
player’s hand with the power of speech,18 found again in the chap-
ter on Qngering: “Fingering also must be honest; the hand—like
the mouth—must speak the truth; it must correspond to the
voice-leading” (34).19
Irene Schreier Scott, the translator of Esser’s reconstruction of
Schenker’s text, is a pianist and teacher.20 As Oswald Jonas’s step-
daughter and student, she literally grew up with Schenker’s ap-
17 From the Entwurf, page 21, under the heading “Klavier Hand”; part of this proach to performance; her Qrst piano teacher was Moriz Violin,
passage is quoted in Rothstein 1984, 21 and 27 (note 47). Schenker’s close lifelong friend. Her translation of the German
18 At Qrst glance, the translation of “die Hand darf nicht lügen” as “the hand
text is generally accurate, elegant, and smooth. She provides quite
may not lie” is ambiguous; the German word “lügen” has none of the double literal translations for the terms Schenker coined, e.g., “piano
meaning of the English “to lie.” Translating the phrase as “the hand may not tell
singing” for Klaviersingen, “light-point” for Lichtstelle, and
a lie” might have removed the ambiguity.
19 See Rothstein 1984, 21 and 27 (note 47). “painting gestures” for malende Bewegungen (8–9), although the
20 Esser, a conductor, is also a performing musician; thus both the editor and German original could perhaps have been revealed in more in-
translator approached their work from a performer’s point of view. stances, as is done for the term Luftpedal, rendered as “air pedal”
Reviews 139

with the German term given in brackets (12). She understandably ings. Its content is organized according to various aspects of per-
retains the German word Rahmenanschlag (literally “framing formance, especially on the piano, as in “The Technique of
touch”), a term Schenker invented to characterize a kind of touch Playing the Piano” (Chapter 3), “Legato” (Chapter 5) “Staccato”
used to emphasize main notes that “frame” those of lesser impor- (Chapter 6). Details of technique are presented in the context of a
tance (49–52). larger view of the composition and in light of the performer’s role
In addition to the question of source identiQcation discussed as interpreter of the composer’s vision.
above, some minor aspects of documentation should be men- The book begins with a chapter entitled “Musical Composition
tioned. While explanations and supplementary material supplied and Performance” that opens with this statement: “Basically, a
by the editor are mainly relegated to the notes at the back of the composition does not require a performance in order to exist” (3).
book, some commentary is included as part of the text or example If a composition is performed, however, it must not be misrepre-
captions. Referring to Schenker by name in the midst of his own sented; to this end Schenker characteristically requires the per-
words (33–4) can be jarring to the reader, even when this occurs former to have a thorough knowledge of the laws of composition.
within example captions, as in Example 8.16 (50) and Example In addition, an understanding of the signiQcance of the notated
9.20 (63). These comments would have been better as notes, espe- score is held to be crucial; this is discussed in the second chapter,
cially where reference is made to modern editions or Schenker’s “Mode of Notation and Performance.” While Schenker afQrms
other writings (note 3 to Chapter 9 is, in fact, used for just such a that scores should preserve the composer’s original notation, he
purpose). Another aspect of the example captions could impede also states: “The author’s mode of notation does not indicate his
the reader: where examples and text are placed on the same page, directions for the performance but, in a far more profound sense,
it is sometimes difQcult to distinguish the captions from the text, represents the effect he wishes to attain. These are two separate
since they are both set in the same type size (see, for example, things” (5). Despite his belief that great composers are “as in-
p. 36). There are also formatting problems in the bibliography, spired in their notation as they were in the actual composing” (6),
particularly in the “Related Works” list.21 Schenker makes suggestions such as the following recommenda-
Overall, however, the book is an outstanding achievement. tion, found in the chapter on legato playing: “In some instances, it
Surmounting considerable difQculties, the editor and translator proves to be appropriate in a longer series of notes to hold some
have created a coherent text that presents Schenker’s ideas about Qngers down longer than written” (22). Thus to discern the inten-
performance in a style and manner consistent with his other writ- tion of a composer one must see beyond the palpable symbols of
the notation.
Schenker’s approach is both poetic and Rexible. In Chapter 8,
21 There are some misprints in the bibliography (96): in lines 2–4, an article “Dynamics,” we read: “Pianissimo under certain circumstances
by Oswald Jonas is erroneously included under the heading “Works of Heinrich means nothing other than stillness—that particular kind of still-
Schenker” (it is listed again, in the correct place, under “Related Works,” ness which does not lose its character even if one or more voices
where, in the second line, “pp. 122–129” should read “pp. 127–129”); in the Roat through space” (40). His discussion of Qngering (Chapter 7)
last line on the page, “vol. 7” should read “vol. 8.” For additional corrections,
is also highly evocative, as in the following comment: “The free
the comprehensive list of the book’s misprints (that incorporates an inventory of
errata prepared by Yosef Goldenberg) is available on the smt web site; it is one mobility of the ‘soul’ of a work of art ever will demand total free-
of the book errata lists included in the Virtual Poster Session managed by Dave dom of Qngering” (34). His sense of Rexibility is particularly evi-
Headlam. dent in Chapter 9, “Tempo and Tempo ModiQcations”: “Repeated
140 Music Theory Spectrum

notes demand hurrying on to the next downbeat . . . Neighboring summarized as an appendix, “On the Degeneracy of the Virtuoso,”
notes, chromatics, diminutions of the lowest order want expressive compares the pursuit of virtuosity for its own sake with the play-
treatment; without pushing ahead—holding back, this would be ing of composers such as Handel, Bach, C. P. E. Bach, Mozart,
impossible” (54–5). The following comments on legato playing Beethoven, Mendelssohn, and Brahms, who were brilliant impro-
are characteristic of his expressive yet precise way of writing: visers and who performed a work as an integrated whole.
Technique, expression, and understanding should be fused; we
The identity of legato technique in violin, voice, and piano can be ob-
served in a particular type of legato. This consists of individual notes read in Chapter 12, “On Practicing”: “Technical difQculties in a
within a group that receive pressure separately, notwithstanding a strictly work of art can be equated with the difQculties fate brings in
observed legato. The violinist can Qnger individual notes while continuing life—but they must be generated by the synthesis” (77). Keeping
to draw his bow in undulating motions without compromising the legato. the entirety of a work in view is essential. Schenker observes:
The singer, similarly, is able to emphasize individual notes within one “The requirement that a composition’s form not be exposed too
single breath. The same effect can be attained by the pianist if he plays nakedly frequently demands considerably quicker playing where
legato as described previously with strictly held keys, simultaneously mov- the seam occurs . . . Played in this way, the separate sections are
ing the arm and hand in an elastic, swaying motion in order to play the fol- pulled together, whereas without such a tempo deviation they
lowing key from a higher point than he would otherwise. Perhaps a differ- would fall apart needlessly, compromising the texture of the form”
ent image describes this technique more suitably: it is as if the arm were
(55–7). Yet ultimately he places the focus not on the composition
striding back and forth in the keys, which serve as its Qrm ground. (24–5)
or its performance alone but rather “on the listener, who at all
Schenker frequently compares the piano to the orchestra (espe- times is the object and measure of the effect” (54).
cially the strings) and to the voice. He describes the use of the We have quoted generously from the book in order to convey
pedal by saying: “Since the piano cannot provide all sustaining the Ravor of its language and the nature of its content in relation to
voices as the orchestra can, pedal gives it the possibility of com- Schenker’s theoretical writings. Despite its brevity, The Art of
pensating for these missing parts. The damper pedal unshackles Performance contains an extraordinary profusion of ideas that are
the overtones, whose radiance substitutes for the orchestra’s sus- expressed in highly original terms—ideas that can potentially
taining voices” (10). He describes ways in which the hand can have a wide audience in the musical community. They are of such
create a type of “pedal” that produces orchestral effects: “hand quality as to deserve that audience.
pedal,” a way of holding keys down to create a sustained, French-
horn-like sound, and “air pedal,” the use of an extremely short
touch to produce an effect analogous to the fading out of breath or
LIST OF WORKS CITED
bow strokes. He pays particular attention to the left hand, noting,
for example: “When the bass moves in octaves, the result often is Drabkin, William. 1984–85. “Felix-Eberhard von Cube and the
a certain orchestral interaction of registers, as if the lower note North-German Tradition of Schenkerism.” Proceedings of the
were played by the basses and the higher one by the cellos” (14). Royal Musical Association 111: 180–207.
While the book focuses on many practical aspects of tech- Federhofer, Hellmut. 1990. Heinrich Schenker als Essayist und
nique, it also emphasizes Schenker’s conviction that a perfor- Kritiker. Hildesheim: Olms.
mance is not a mechanical playing of notes, but comes from Jonas, Oswald. 1962. “Die Kunst des Vortrages nach Heinrich
within the performer and the work. One of the drafted chapters Schenker.” Musikerzeihung 15: 127–9.
Reviews 141

Rothstein, William. 1984. “Heinrich Schenker as an Interpreter of ———. 1971–72. Beethoven, Die letzten Sonaten: Erlaüterungs-
Beethoven’s Piano Sonatas.” 19th-Century Music 8: 3–28. ausgabe, of Op. 101, 109, 110, 111. Revised editions. Edited
Schenker, Heinrich. 1906. Neue musikalische Theorien und by Oswald Jonas. Vienna: Universal Edition.
Phantasien, Vol. I: Harmonielehre. Stuttgart: Cotta. Reprint ———. 1976. “A Contribution to the Study of Ornamentation.”
edition, with a foreword by Rudolf Frisius, Vienna: Universal Translated by Hedi Siegel. In The Music Forum 4: 1–139.
Edition, 1978. ———. 1984. J. S. Bach’s Chromatic Fantasy and Fugue:
———. 1954. Harmony. Edited by Oswald Jonas. Translated by Critical Edition with Commentary. Translated and edited by
Elisabeth Mann Borgese. Chicago: University of Chicago Hedi Siegel. New York, Longman.
Press. Reprint edition, Cambridge, Mass: mit Press, 1973. ———. 1992. Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony. Translated and
———. 1956. Der freie Satz. Revised edition. Edited by Oswald edited by John Rothgeb. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Jonas. Vienna: Universal Edition. Wolf, Hans. 1937. “Schenkers Persönlichkeit im Unterricht.” Der
———. 1969. J. S. Bach, Chromatische Phantasie und Fuge: Dreiklang 7 (October): 176–84.
Kritische Ausgabe. Revised edition. Edited by Oswald Jonas.
Vienna: Universal Edition.
142 Music Theory Spectrum

Understanding Charles Seeger, Pioneer in American Musicology. Yung & Rees’s organization of these diverse yet interconnected
Edited by Bell Yung and Helen Rees. Urbana: University of essays is exemplary. One essay Rows to the next, gracefully pick-
Illinois Press, 1999. ing up a theme or idea. As a companion volume to Taylor Greer’s
recent book on Seeger’s philosophy of music (Greer 1998),
Reviewed by Ellie M. Hisama Understanding Charles Seeger offers theorists a number of signif-
icant and novel avenues of exploration.
Understanding Charles Seeger, Pioneer in American Musicology In “The Dynamics of Dissonance in Seeger’s Treatise and
contributes new perspectives on the wide-ranging intellectual en- Crawford’s Quartet,” Greer does a superb job of writing lucidly
terprises of polymath Charles Seeger. Many of Seeger’s ideas about the intricate web of Seeger’s ideas presented in his land-
from the 1930s through the 1970s resonate with music theorists’ mark treatise “Tradition and Experiment in (the New) Music”
present-day concerns—for example, his forward-looking insis- (Seeger 1994). Seeger’s legendary prose often requires the reader
tence on studying music in its contexts; his advocacy for expan- to mine the text multiple times for the idea, and Greer’s long en-
sion of the repertoire studied by scholars to include American gagement with Seeger’s writing (Greer 1994 and 1998) makes
music, world music, folk music, and orally transmitted music; and him the ideal guide to this theoretical work. Greer skillfully navi-
his bridging of philosophical concerns with musical ones. Further, gates the waters of Seeger’s treatise, setting his sights upon a
his invention in the 1950s of the melograph, an electronic tool for single piece to illustrate the analytical application of Seeger’s
transcribing a performance or recording, anticipates work in ideas, the third movement of Crawford’s String Quartet 1931.
music theory published several decades later that examines sound Greer is not the Qrst scholar to apply Seeger’s ideas to Crawford’s
through its visual representation. 1 music—as he notes, David Nicholls, Joseph Straus, and Judith
This collection of eight essays by theorists, musicologists, and Tick have also done so—but Greer’s reading of this quartet move-
ethnomusicologists celebrates the variety and evolution of ment through the lens of Seeger’s work in “Tradition and
Seeger’s thought while sounding common themes that emerged in Experiment” is still original and revealing.2 Greer’s explication of
his writings over a span of some sixty years. As noted by the Seeger’s six functions of musical experience that are divided into
book’s co-editors, Bell Yung and Helen Rees, Seeger published two groups, tone (encompassing pitch/dynamics/timbre) and
approximately eighty musicological papers on topics as varied as rhythm (encompassing proportion/accent/tempo), and his applica-
contemporary composition, the European art-music tradition, the tion of Seeger’s ideas about dynamics and accent to Crawford’s
melograph, folk music, music of the Americas, applied musicol- quartet movement whose underlying plan the composer herself
ogy, music education, and the philosophy of music. On p. 6, they identiQed as “heterophony of dynamics—a sort of counterpoint of
identify six themes in Seeger’s writings: (1) the deQnition of crescendi and diminuendi” (Crawford [1948] 1997, 357) is ab-
music and musicology, (2) the relationship between language and sorbing. 3 One especially interesting feature of the piece that Greer
music, (3) language as the lens through which music is under-
stood, (4) theories of value, (5) the social responsibility of musi-
2See Nicholls 1990, Tick 1990, and Straus 1995. Burkett 2001 also explores
cians and musicologists, and (6) the social contexts of music.
the relationship between Seeger’s theories and Crawford’s music. Slottow 2001
discusses Seeger’s theories in relation to compositions by Carl Ruggles.
1 Examples of visual representations of music are in Cogan 1984, 3Other analyses of this movement can be found in Straus 1995, 158–72,

Clendinning 1995, Bernard 1999, Brackett 2000, and Hisama 2001. Hisama 1995, and Hisama 2001, 12–34.
Reviews 143

examines is the pattern of dynamic peaks in mm. 13–18 (played by points detract minimally from an effective fusing of theory and
the viola, second violin, and cello on beats 1, 2, and 3), which oc- analysis.
curs a total of six times, and the completion of the pattern in m. 19 In “The American Composer in the 1930s: The Social Thought
by the Qrst violin on beat 4. Although Greer notes that he hopes his of Seeger and Chávez,” Leonora Saavedra explores Seeger’s and
“brief discussion of the quartet [he discusses 19 of the movement’s Carlos Chávez’s attempts to reconcile their leftist politics with
99 measures] serves as an initial step to help stimulate other, more their interest in modernist music. Saavedra’s decision to place
detailed analyses of the relationship between philosophical theory Chávez alongside Seeger, both of whom were struggling to under-
and compositional method” (24), I would have liked for him to stand the social relevance of modernist music during the 1920s
continue; his discussion of the opening bars made me to want to and 1930s, makes for an interesting pairing. In Saavedra’s words:
discover how he hears the subsequent passages, particularly the “In the course of trying to examine the links between art and soci-
striking climax and subsequent descent that contribute to the ety, Seeger and Chávez came to understand music as a social
movement’s structural fascination and dramatic power. Greer’s dis- product with a social function rather than as the suprasocial cre-
cussion might also have contemplated the relation of Seeger’s ideas ation of an individual mind” (53). Initially opposed to folk music,
to Crawford’s own observation in her brief analysis of this piece which in 1934 he labeled “conventional, easy going, subservient”
that “the melodic line grows out of this continuous increase and de- (Seeger 1934), Seeger came to champion the traditional music of
crease; it is given, one tone at a time, to different instruments, and the working class: “Plainly, if we are to compose for more than an
each new melodic tone is brought in at the high point of a inQnitesimal fraction of the American people, we must write in an
crescendo,” as well as her accompanying sketch of a portion of this idiom not too remote from the one most of them possess—their
composite melodic line (Crawford Seeger [1948] 1997, 358). own musical vernacular.” (Seeger [1939] 1994, 387). One won-
One aspect of Greer’s discussion of the quartet warrants fur- ders what Seeger would have thought of postmodernism; would
ther discussion. His statements that “there is an overall balance of he have embraced postmodern music because it allows a com-
musical functions [in Crawford’s quartet movement] whereby a poser to reach a broad audience through repackaged vernacular
constant Rux in one function is counterbalanced by less activity styles? Or would he have sided with its critics who regard post-
among the others” (23) and “these observations . . . suggest that modern pastiche and stylistic juxtaposition as lacking in value and
the sense of balance exhibited in Crawford’s quartet can be inter- content, and therefore devoid of any political meaning and efQ-
preted as a musical realization of . . . Seeger’s philosophical the- cacy? Saavedra’s essay reminds contemporary readers of the so-
ory of mediation” (23) seem at odds with his conclusion, in cial responsibilities of composers and scholars as well as the po-
which he writes: “It seems rather ironic that the one composer tential impact of their work on society, issues that were central to
who had the beneQt of studying closely Seeger’s theories about Seeger and evident in the directions his research, teaching, and
the ideal of balance, Ruth Crawford, wrote several works that children would take.4
were distinguished by the imbalance among functions” (24, em-
phasis added); the endnote to this sentence then mentions the
quartet’s third movement as well as Crawford’s Piano Study in 4 Numerous recordings and books chronicle the musical contributions of
Mixed Accents. It is unfortunate that the reproduction of the Qrst three of Seeger’s children, Peggy Seeger, Mike Seeger, and Pete Seeger. A sam-
page of the Presser score, given in Figure 1.3, is of poor quality pler includes Mike Seeger 1964 and 1998, Peggy Seeger 1998a and 1998b, and
in this otherwise well-produced book (22). Still, these minor Pete Seeger 1993 and 1998.
144 Music Theory Spectrum

Robert R. Grimes develops the topic of Seeger’s desire to ef- plored repertories.6 Music theorists interested in considering how
fect positive social change in his essay “Form, Content, and Value: one would analyze a repertory whose structural complexity would
Seeger and Criticism to 1940.” Grimes pinpoints Seeger’s water- not be revealed by, for example, Schenkerian analysis, would do
shed article “Systematic and Historical Orientations in Musicology” well to revisit Seeger’s article “Versions and Variants of the Tunes
(1939) as an important turning point in Seeger’s scholarly develop- of ‘Barbara Allen’ ” (Seeger [1966] 1977). The thoroughness of
ment. What Seeger meant by “value” is, as Grimes rightly notes, Seeger’s analysis of a traditional tune dispels preconceived notions
“not always clearly evident … in the context of music” (64). Grimes about the ability of American roots music to bear close study.
does an admirable job of sorting out Seeger’s ideas on value in the Co-editor Helen Rees points out in her excellent essay
1930s by closely examining his writings, both scholarly and jour- “ ‘Temporary Bypaths?’ Seeger and Folk Music Research” that
nalistic, during this period: “For Seeger in his early writings value is “Seeger’s discovery of American folksong contributed actively,
the dynamic form of content; it is the act of valuing. Content, a materially, and discernibly to some of the most sophisticated and
more static term, is the link between internal and external, between inRuential theoretical concerns of his later years” (85). The second
the purely, intrinsically musical and the social function of music” half of Rees’s article is particularly relevant to music theorists. In
(79–80). Like Greer, Grimes locates inRuences on Seeger’s it, Rees explores three interrelated sets of questions crucial to any
thoughts in philosophy (Greer identiQes Bergson, Russell, Perry, analytical enterprise: Qrst, what constitutes the music to be stud-
and Goethe as signiQcant to Seeger, while Grimes discusses the im- ied? That is, what determines the identity of a piece when pitches,
pact of Georgii Plekhanov in addition to Perry). Grimes’s argument rhythm, or other musical parameters may vary performance to
for Seeger’s attraction to Plekhanov’s work and his contention that performance, as in the performance of works transmitted through
Seeger was drawn to Plekhanov’s ability to connect art, society, and the oral tradition? Ethnomusicologists, of course, deal with these
economic forces are convincing, as is his conclusion that Seeger’s questions routinely, but such issues force music theorists who are
concept of value was an evolving one (79). trained to analyze from a Qxed score notated in the Western art
Grimes’s statement that “[Seeger] had found that music is tradition to rethink the very foundations of their analytical pro-
something more than the luxury of an elite class” (80) is rich with jects. Second, what is the relationship between the oral and writ-
implications for music theory’s potential directions in the new mil- ten traditions, and how should we treat music for which there is no
lennium. While professional analytic studies still concentrate on score? Seeger’s musings on these questions some three decades
Western European art music, the tides are certainly shifting. ago are still relevant today as music theorists chart the waters of
Conference program committees, publishers, and search commit- analyzing non-notated music drawn from popular music, vernacu-
tees are showing increased interest in music outside of the canon.5 lar music, and world music traditions. 7 Third, how does an analyst
As the categories of music we consider worthy of theoretical acknowledge and negotiate the shortcomings of Western notation
scrutiny continue to change, we are also Qnding new applications in transcribing music? What does transcription represent?
for traditionally accepted tools and developing new tools for unex- Although Seeger’s work provides no easy answers to these inter-
locking questions, his deliberations provide the foundation for a
contemporary rethinking of these issues.
5I discuss this development in Hisama 2000.
6Examples of analytical work that explores new repertories include Clarke 7Recent analyses of popular music and world music appear in Middleton

1999 and Burns 2000. 1990, Moore 1993, Tagg 2000, Temperley 2000, and Tenzer 2000.
Reviews 145

Ruth Crawford’s dismissal as merely a composition student of people] are, or become familiar with the idiomatic variations of
her teacher Charles Seeger will always best be exempliQed for me American folk singing that they can expect to put approximately
in a comment made in 1989 by a retired musicology professor the right kind of Gesh, blood, and nerve Fbre back on this skeleton
who, upon seeing a graduate student with Crawford’s Diaphonic notation” [118]) and Seeger’s discussion in 1951 of whether tran-
Suite No. 1, exclaimed: “Those were just solutions to exercises scriptions in three regional folksong collections “purport to be a
Charlie gave her!” Judith Tick’s quietly revolutionary essay, “Ruth hypothetical or logical skeletonizing of the tunes.” (Seeger 1951,
Crawford, Charles Seeger, and ‘The Music of American Folk 523). In order to illustrate the analytical complexities encountered
Songs’” encourages us to rethink the received idea that Seeger’s by the transcriber of folksongs, Tick’s essay provides a brilliant
ideas were embodied in Crawford’s work. Tick powerfully argues example in Crawford’s work on the tune “Choose You a Seat ‘n’
that Seeger’s writings on folk songs have antecedents in a little- Set Down” as well as additional evidence of Crawford’s inRuence
known treatise by Crawford that she completed in 1940 entitled on Seeger’s ideas published in “Versions and Variants on the
“The Music of American Folk Song,” published for the Qrst time Tunes of ‘Barbara Allen.’ ”9 As Tick sagely notes, although Seeger
in 2001 (Crawford Seeger 2001). 8 Tick provides example after ex- could have acknowledged publicly the importance of Crawford’s
ample, both in the body of the essay and in an appendix to it, that contribution to the scholarship on folk music, perhaps he did not
Seeger’s ideas resonate with Crawford’s earlier work. For ex- do so because of “the entitlement of a certain kind of intellect and
ample, Tick quotes Crawford on transcription: a certain kind of love” (123).
In “Seeger’s Unitary Field Theory Reconsidered,” Lawrence
A tune is a stream of sound whose variations in pitch and in time can be
represented on paper as a curving line. Figure 5 represents within a mar- M. Zbikowski picks up the topic discussed by Grimes and Rees of
gin of error of approximately .1 second, metrical irregularities observed in Seeger’s interest in the linguistic study of music. He chooses to
the original singing. (116; Crawford Seeger 2001, 9–10) tackle Seeger’s thorny work on the relationship between speech
and music Qrst by examining Gilles Fauconnier’s theory of mental
She then presents a strikingly similar passage in Seeger’s spaces and later discussing what Zbikowski calls “a properly mu-
“Prescriptive and Descriptive Music Writing,” initially published sical concept,” which he concludes to be “a cognitive structure
in 1958. that can be speciFed for what we call music, leaving both ‘we’ and
On the one hand, let us agree, melody may be conceived . . . as a succes- ‘music’ undeQned” (143). Zbikowski’s decision not to clarify the
sion of separate sounds, on the other, as a single continuum of sound—as identities of the investigator and the music to which his idea might
a chain or as a stream. For the present, I am inclined to set . . . 1/10 of a be applied is regrettable, as is the fact that the reference given in
second as fair margins of accuracy for general musicological use. (116; the endnote that might elucidate the discussion is to an unpub-
Seeger [1958] 1977, 169) lished paper (147 n. 8). The reader is thus left to puzzle over a
Tick might also have drawn a link between Crawford’s murky deQnition. Also disappointing is the lack of explanation in
metaphor of transcription as a skeleton, which Crawford uses in the opening paragraph as to what the author precisely means by
her treatise (“. . . it is only the extent to which [city or town “sound images” (“sound images are part of the central business of

8The correct title of the treatise is The Music of American Folk Song (singu- 9Crawford’s published transcription of “Choose You a Seat ‘n’ Set Down”

lar), not The Music of American Folk Songs (plural). appears in Lomax & Lomax 2000.
146 Music Theory Spectrum

what we call music,” 130) and the absence of discussion about the (4) His challenge to the assumption that “the best music is
detailed table in Seeger’s “Toward a Unitary Field Theory for written music.” (161; Seeger 1941, 18)
Musicology.” These gaps are lamentable because Zbikowski offers
Baranovitch’s traversal of these key texts that explore music as
a number of intriguing observations worth pursuing—for ex-
culture provides theorists with a useful reminder of the contempo-
ample, his revelation that “The basic notion of a properly musical
rary value of Seeger’s writings from the 1940s.
concept is inRuenced by my own experience: I can remember hav-
The Qnal essay, a meditation on the relationship between
ing ideas and thoughts about music well before I discovered any
physics and musicology in Seeger’s work, is penned by co-editor
way of describing them to others” (141). One hopes that
Bell Yung, who is well positioned to investigate such a connec-
Zbikowski’s important ideas will be further developed in future
tion, having received advanced training in both physics and music.
Seeger scholarship.
“From Modern Physics to Modern Musicology: Seeger and
Like Zbikowski, Nimrod Baranovitch considers Seeger’s ideas
Beyond” provides an important step toward a fuller understanding
over a span of several decades. His contribution, “Anthropology
of the foundations of Seeger’s music theories. For example, Yung
and Music: Seeger’s Writings from 1933 to 1953,” adroitly
explores Seeger’s interest in “musical space-time” as follows:
demonstrates that Seeger anticipated foundational ideas and
methodological issues in ethnomusicology well before the Qeld Musical space refers to pitch, dynamics, and timbre, while musical time
was ofQcially established. Four of Seeger’s insights presented in refers to tempo, movement, and duration. In combining space and time
Baranovitch’s essay are particularly useful to music theorists who into a hyphenated word, he is clearly borrowing the concept from the
are interested in taking the Qeld in new directions: space-time of the special theory of relativity, implying that musical space-
time consists of six dimensions, but that these six dimensions are inher-
ently related to each other and must be treated as such, just as the four di-
(1) Seeger’s insistence that analysis of the internal workings of
mensions in physical space-time are. (179)
a piece of music is an incomplete project: “The inner, tech-
nical operations of the art of music cannot adequately be Yung convincingly argues for Seeger’s attraction to general
studied without consideration of the outer relations of concepts in physics of the early part of the century, such as
music and the culture of which it is a part.” (158; Seeger particle-wave duality and the theory of relativity, while also show-
1940, 318) ing that the details of Seeger’s six-dimensional model of musical
(2) His criticism (as early as 1940) of the “great man” para- space-time are neither clearly deQned nor consistent (179). The
digm in music scholarship and his promotion of the study depth of Seeger’s knowledge of physics remains little researched
of the musical vernacular of “the common man,” or folk compared to work by scholars on Seeger’s interest in diverse Qelds
music, which he considered a “socially molded thing, with within the humanities and social sciences, and Yung makes a
a deep-set cultural function expressing not so much the va- strong case for the importance of further research about the inter-
rieties of individual experience as the norms of social ex- connections between physics and musicology in Seeger’s theories.
perience.” (159; Seeger 1940, 321) We should be grateful to Yung not only for his efforts to under-
(3) His proposal that European art music is as socially molded stand Seeger through a new portal, but also, in collaboration with
as vernacular traditions, and that it should not be regarded Helen Rees, for this stimulating collection.
as the norm against which non-European musics should be Understanding Charles Seeger does not attempt comprehen-
measured. (160–62; Seeger 1941) sive coverage of Seeger’s plethora of interests and endeavors—an
Reviews 147

impossible task, to be sure. Instead of faulting such an impressive Burns, Lori. 2000. “Analytic Methodologies for Rock Music:
book for not addressing in more depth topics such as Seeger’s own Harmonic and Voice-Leading Strategies in Tori Amos’s
compositions, the impact of Seeger on his children’s music- ‘Crucify’.” In Expression in Pop-Rock Music: A Collection of
making and political beliefs, and the implications of his work for Critical and Analytical Essays. Edited by Walter Everett. New
music education, we should take Yung & Rees’s collection as a York: Garland, 213–46.
Qrm reminder of the lasting signiQcance of Seeger’s work and as Clarke, Eric F. 1999. “Subject-Position and the SpeciQcation of
an invitation to pick up where the book leaves off. Seeger’s revo- Invariants in Music by Frank Zappa and P. J. Harvey.” Music
lutionary ideas are many, including his call to expand the number Analysis 18: 347–74.
and varieties repertories studied, to adapt ideas from disciplines Clendinning, Jane Piper. 1995. “Structural Factors in the
outside of music to projects in theory and analysis, and to embed Microcanonic Compositions of György Ligeti.” In Concert
musical analysis within its social, historical, and political contexts Music, Rock, and Jazz Since 1945: Essays and Analytical
instead of retreating to what Arnold Whittall has called “the safe Studies. Edited by Elizabeth West Marvin and Richard
shores of technical analysis” (Whittall 2001). As Seeger observed Hermann. Rochester: University of Rochester Press, 229–56.
nearly thirty years ago, “The drive to internationalize the world Cogan, Robert. 1984. New Images of Musical Sound. Cambridge:
economically, politically, intellectually—that is, as one cultural Harvard University Press.
whole—is in full swing. Music is an integral factor in the process” Crawford Seeger, Ruth. [1940] 2001. The Music of American Folk
(Seeger [1972] 1994, 434). In the twenty-Qrst century, it becomes Song. Edited by Larry Polansky. Rochester: University of
increasingly necessary for music theory as a profession to Qnd its Rochester Press.
place within a larger social and disciplinary fabric while retaining ———. [1948] 1997. “Analysis of the Third Movement of the
its integrity as a Qeld that considers musical structure and meaning String Quartet 1931.” In Judith Tick, Ruth Crawford Seeger: A
as its primary goals. Developing theories that consider music in its Composer’s Search for American Music. New York: Oxford
global as well as local contexts would be one way to ensure our University Press, 357–60.
survival as a profession and as a discipline in a rapidly changing Greer, Taylor A. 1994. “Critical Remarks about Tradition and
world. Experiment in (the New) Music.” In Studies in Musicology II:
1929–1979. Edited by Ann M. Pescatello. Berkeley: University
of California Press, 27–42.
LIST OF WORKS CITED
———. 1998. A Question of Balance: Charles Seeger’s
Bernard, Jonathan W. 1999. “Ligeti’s Restoration of Interval and Philosophy of Music. Berkeley: University of California Press.
its SigniQcance for His Later Works.” Music Theory Spectrum Hisama, Ellie M. 1995. “The Question of Climax in Ruth
21: 1–21. Crawford’s String Quartet, mvt. 3.” In Concert Music, Rock,
Brackett, David. 2000. Interpreting Popular Music. Berkeley: and Jazz Since 1945: Essays and Analytical Studies. Edited by
University of California Press. Elizabeth West Marvin and Richard Hermann. Rochester:
Burkett, Lyn Ellen Thornblad. 2001. Tensile Involvement: University of Rochester Press, 285–312.
Counterpoint and Compositional Pedagogy in the Work of ———. 2000. “Life Outside the Canon? A Walk on the Wild
Seeger, Hindemith, and Krenek. Ph.D. dissertation, Indiana Side.” Music Theory Online 6 (August). http://smt.ucsb.edu/
University. mto/issues/mto.00.6.3/toc.6.3.html.
148 Music Theory Spectrum

———. 2001. Gendering Musical Modernism: The Music of Ruth Angeles, Institute of Ethnomusicology] 1: 120–67. Reprinted
Crawford, Marion Bauer, and Miriam Gideon. Cambridge: as “Versions and Variants of the Tunes of ‘Barbara Allen’ ” in
Cambridge University Press. Studies in Musicology, 1935–1975. Berkeley: University of
Lomax, John A., and Alan Lomax, coll. and comp. [1941] 2000. California Press, 273–320.
Our Singing County: Folk Songs and Ballads. Edited by Ruth ———. [1972] 1994. “World Musics in American Schools: A
Crawford Seeger. Mineola, N.Y.: Dover. Challenge to be Met.” Music Educators Journal 58 (October):
Middleton, Richard. 1990. Studying Popular Music. Milton 107–11. Reprinted in Studies in Musicology II, 1929–1979.
Keynes: Open University Press. Edited by Ann M. Pescatello. Berkeley: University of
Moore, Allan F. 1993. Rock, the Primary Text: Developing a California Press, 427–34.
Musicology of Rock. Buckingham: Open University Press. ———. 1994. “Tradition and Experiment in (the New) Music.” In
Nicholls, David. 1990. American Experimental Music, 1890–1940. Studies in Musicology II: 1929–1979. Edited by Ann M.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pescatello. Berkeley: University of California Press, 49–266.
Seeger, Charles [Sands, Carl]. 1934. “Thirteen Songs from Eight Seeger, Mike. 1964. Old-Time String Band Songbook. Edited by
Countries Included in Book Put Out by Music Bureau Mike Seeger and John Cohen. New York: Music Sales
Internat’l,” The Daily Worker (1 February): 5. Corporation.
———. [1939] 1994. “Grass Roots for American Composers,” ———. 1998. Southern Banjo Sounds. Smithsonian Folkways
Modern Music 16:143–9. Reprinted in Studies in Musicology 40107.
II, 1929–1979. Edited by Ann M. Pescatello. Berkeley: Seeger, Peggy. 1998a. The Peggy Seeger Songbook, Warts and All:
University of California Press, 383–8. Forty Years of Songmaking. Edited by Irene Scott. New York:
———. 1939. “Systematic and Historical Orientations in Oak Publications.
Musicology.” Acta Musicologica 11: 121–8. ———. 1998b. Period Pieces. Tradition TCD 1078.
———. 1940. “Folk Music as a Source of History.” In The Seeger, Pete. 1993. Where Have All the Flowers Gone: A Singer’s
Cultural Approach to History. Edited by Carolyn F. Ware. New Stories, Songs, Seeds, Robberies. Bethlehem, Penn.: Sing Out.
York: Columbia University Press. ———. 1998. If I Had a Hammer: Songs of Hope & Struggle.
———. 1941. “Inter-American Relations in the Field of Music.” Smithsonian Folkways SF CD 40096.
Music Educators Journal 27: 17–18, 64–5. Slottow, Stephen P. 2001. A Vast Simplicity: Pitch Organization in
———. 1951. Review of Alton C. Morris’s Folksongs of Florida, the Music of Carl Ruggles. Ph.D. dissertation, City University
William A. Owens’s Texas Folksongs, and Byron Arnold’s of New York.
Folksongs of Alabama, in Notes 8: 523. Straus, Joseph N. 1995. The Music of Ruth Crawford Seeger.
———. [1958] 1977. “Prescriptive and Descriptive Music Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Writing.” Musical Quarterly 44: 184–95. Reprinted in Studies Tagg, Philip. 2000. “Analysing Popular Music: Theory, Method,
in Musicology, 1935–1975. Berkeley: University of California and Practice.” In Reading Pop: Approaches to Textual Analysis
Press, 168–81. in Popular Music. Edited by Richard Middleton. Oxford:
———. [1966] 1977. “Versions and Variants of ‘Barbara Allen’ in Oxford University Press, 71–103.
the Archive of American Folk Song in the Library of Temperley, David. 2000. “Meter and Grouping in African Music:
Congress.” Selected Reports [University of California at Los A View from Music Theory.” Ethnomusicology 44: 65–96.
Reviews 149

Tenzer, Michael. 2000. Gamelan Gong Kebyar: The Art of H. Wiley Hitchcock. Edited by Richard Crawford, R. Allen
Twentieth-century Balinese Music. Chicago: University of Lott, and Carol J. Oja. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan
Chicago Press. Press, 405–22.
Tick, Judith. 1990. “Dissonant Counterpoint Revisited: The First Whittall, Arnold. 2001. “Revoicing Expression: Postmodern
Movement of Ruth Crawford’s String Quartet.” In A Classicism.” Lecture presented at University of London (15
Celebration of American Music: Words and Music in Honor of March).
150 Music Theory Spectrum

Susan McClary. Conventional Wisdom: The Content of Musical interpretative approach, McClary ends up relying on a notion
Form. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2000. very close to the “music itself ” to make claims about music as
social construct.
Reviewed by Judy Lochhead The Qve chapters of Conventional Wisdom survey the use of
several formal conventions in Western music. Chapter 1, titled
Conventional Wisdom grew out of McClary’s Bloch Lectures at “Turtles All the Way Down (on the ‘Purely Musical’),” considers
the University of California at Berkeley in 1993—its publication an aria from the oratorio La Susanna (1681) by Alessandro
postponed until 2000 because of professional circumstances. The Stradella and a 1959 gospel performance of the hymn “Near the
delayed appearance of these essays changes rather signiQcantly Cross” by the Swan Silvertones. Chapter 2, “Thinking Blues,” fo-
their impact on the musicological community since many of the cuses on blues from Bessie Smith (her 1928 performance of
issues raised and approaches introduced have been discussed and “Thinking Blues”), Robert Johnson (his 1936 performance of
debated in various contexts over the last eight years. Read in “Cross Road Blues”), and Cream (their live Filmore performance
2001, Conventional Wisdom seems less like a call to change—as it of Johnson’s song issued on Wheels of Fire in 1976). The third
might have in 1993—and more like a conQrmation of issues that chapter, “What Was Tonality?,” investigates a da capo aria from
have enlivened music studies within the last decade. Scarlatti’s opera Griselda (1721), a movement of Vivaldi’s op. 3,
McClary has several simultaneous goals in this book: demon- no. 8, concerto (1715), and the courante from J. S. Bach’s D-
stration of (1) the kinds of roles that formal conventions play in a major Partita for keyboard. Chapter 4, “The Refuge of Counter-
broad spectrum of historical styles and musical traditions, (2) convention,” considers Beethoven’s op. 132 string quartet
how changes in the compositional uses of formal conventions re- (composed 1825), and Chapter 5, “Reveling in the Rubble: The
spond to historical changes, and (3) how musical sound partici- Postmodern Condition,” discusses Glassworks (1982) by Philip
pates in processes of social signiQcation. ConQrming one of Glass, Spillane (1986) by John Zorn, “Kiss” (1986) by the Artist
the long-standing strengths of McClary’s work, Conventional Formerly Known As Prince, “Still Thrives This Love” (1992) by
Wisdom takes musical sound as its focus and afQrms that music is k.d. lang, and “Nighttrain” (1991) by Public Enemy.
not absent from processes of social meaning but participates di- Rather than sampling the kinds of claims McClary makes
rectly in the articulation of cultural systems of value. While I un- about how and what kinds of cultural meanings music produces, I
derstand this focus as a fundamental value, I also recognize that will focus here on the underlying argument of the third chapter
the particular ways that McClary engages musical sound have since it applies to much of the book. As suggested by its title,
been controversial. Often, controversy hinges on issues of “What Was Tonality?,” this chapter considers how “tonality,” as a
whether musical sound participates directly in our daily lives or musical practice emerging in the eighteenth century, conQrms
whether it operates at a more general level of abstract or universal Enlightenment ideals. The three works by Scarlatti, Vivaldi, and
meaning. McClary argues Qrmly against a notion of the purely Bach are analyzed with respect to their articulation of a “tonal
musical, the “music itself,” and for an understanding of the background . . . [which] proceeds through a series of arrivals, be-
“power of music . . . to shape the ways we experience our bodies, ginning in the tonic key, moving through a few other keys, and re-
emotions, subjectivities, desires, and social relations” (7). Here I turning Qnally home to the tonic” (66). And this tonal background
want to demonstrate how, as a consequence of an ahistoricized is interrogated for the way that it “works to produce a particular
Reviews 151

construction of the self” (70). For example, in Scarlatti’s Griselda, ited to François-Joseph Fétis, its fullest discussion occurring in
the title character is able “to pull her conRicting emotions under the 1844 Traité complet de théorie et de la pratique de l’harmonie. 1
one tonal trajectory, thus displaying the centered subjectivity—the Concepts of function, hierarchically related key areas, and long-
belief in the unshakability of that inner core—which is still one of range coherence were not theorized until later in the nineteenth
our favorite myths” (79). McClary’s analysis correlates differing and into the twentieth centuries. One might argue that “the music”
motivic Qgures with the range of affects that depict Griselda’s operated for eighteenth-century musicians and audiences in ways
varying emotional states during her aria “Figlio! Tiranno!” Her identical to those implied by late twentieth-century notions of
account of the tonal progress of the aria tells a somewhat different tonality, but this would be a universalizing argument that runs
story, since it is the continuity of a single “tonal trajectory” that counter to what I take as the spirit of McClary’s project.
enacts the sense of a centered subjectivity. The sense of “self” de- The issue hinges on the status of analytical observations and
picted here is twofold: on one hand, there is the eighteenth- the types of historical and experiential claims that are founded on
century subject that gave rise to the paradigm of tonality as them. Since analytical observation is necessarily contingent upon
embodying Enlightenment values of “progress, rationality, intelli- concepts about musical sound, and since conceptual understand-
gibility, quests after goals, and the illusion of self-contained ing is contingent on historical context, then the extent to which
autonomy,” and on the other hand, there is the contemporary sub- analytical observation about music and subjects of the past is
ject who in “still embrac[ing] these ideals” hears tonality as “nat- grounded in historical context will affect the status of analytical
ural” (68). There is an assumption here that what eighteenth- observation. Thus, in order to address the question of “What was
century listeners heard is identical to what contemporary listeners Tonality?,” one has to ask, For whom does such a concept apply?
hear. The chapter then takes as a central assumption that what Such a prior question will necessarily lead to an investigation of
tonality was is identical to what it is. the socially-constructed cognitive constraints of the concept.
This assumption could be argued in principle on the basis of Inasmuch as I am in sympathy with McClary’s effort to
historical and contemporary accounts of musical experience or of demonstrate how musical sound participates in a wide variety of
how music was understood to work. McClary does not offer such socially-constructed behaviors, I want to make explicit here how
evidence, however, but bases her argument instead on an analytic the universalizing of concepts about music can overthrow the
interpretation that borrows many of its concepts from nineteenth- spirit of the project. This is how I read the underlying procedures
and twentieth-century notions of tonality. in Conventional Wisdom.
For instance, about Scarlatti’s aria McClary writes: tonality McClary offers analytical interpretations of speciQc works that
“possesses . . . a hierarchy of relationships that drew all moments demonstrate how musical effects and structures both reRect and
of the composition together into a single goal-oriented network” enforce socially-constructed behaviors, arguing that musical
(73). And later in the chapter one reads: “Vivaldi sets out with re- sound is subject to the contingencies of ethnicity, gender, class,
markable clarity the background tonal progression that had started and history. She uses analytic concepts in ways that are not, how-
life as a linear cadence pattern but that now stretches out to grant ever, sensitive to the historical contingency of those concepts,
coherence to a full ninety-three measures” (83). It is worth noting
in this regard that a concept of “tonality” per se did not exist in the 1While the term “tonality” did not originate with Fétis, he was the Qrst to

eighteenth century. The initial articulation of that concept is cred- frame the concept in ways consistent with its contemporary understanding.
152 Music Theory Spectrum

while making claims about historical subjects. Such an ahistorical and “tonal coherence” were not part of the conceptual landscape
use of the terminology has the effect of universalizing those con- for eighteenth-century theorists. Rather than building upon
cepts. If we understand concepts about music as not simply reRec- eighteenth-century conceptual understanding in order to under-
tive of but also constructive of experience in accord with what in stand what musical experience might have been, McClary dis-
very general terms I will call “postmodern philosophies,” then the counts it: “The fact that music theorists of the time did not by and
claims made about such phenomena as tonality must be carefully large write about music in these terms should hardly surprise us:
qualiQed.2 But if we understand concepts as “applied to” an un- verbal accounts of ‘structures of feeling’ often appear only long
changing experience, then we must judge these concepts as tools after the fact, if at all” (65). In discounting contemporary evidence
which reveal a thing that is prior to its conceptual understanding. for the project of understanding “what tonality was,” McClary
McClary’s universalizing music-theoretical concepts implies the contradicts one of the fundamental observations of a postmodern
latter—that there is a “music itself ” which is prior to the social philosophical perspective: the contingency of conceptual under-
constructions of language, a position that is clearly not in keeping standing and experience.
with the spirit of her project, which disallows a retreat into “the Concepts such as tonality, cadence, dominant and tonic, har-
purely musical.” monic hierarchy, and coherence do not transparently reveal music.
While the analyses of Conventional Wisdom employ theoretical While McClary’s project of linking musical sound to social be-
tools and make claims about musical experience that are not sensi- haviors is necessary and perhaps even urgent, the analytical base
tive to historical contingencies within the Western tradition of on which it rests needs careful consideration.
music making, McClary seems to be aware at some level of the To conclude, I will simply suggest here that a more considered
conceptual power of theoretical language. In the very Qrst pages and creative approach to analysis through channels of speculative
of the book she writes: “The measuring sticks of Schenker graphs theory might better serve the project of linking musical sound to
or the kabbalistic methods of set-based analysis strive to pull ap- social behaviors. All the chapters of Conventional Wisdom utilize
parently unruly music back inside the horizons of the rational, the universal notions of tonal conventions as a basis for depicting nar-
orderly, and (implicitly) the metaphysical. Why, I have always ratives of subjectivity. Such narratives are typically told through
wondered, do we not label the procedures such theories trace like- key relations, yet such relations are not foregrounded in musical
wise as conventions? And why do we neglect to talk about why experience. Rather, the immediacies of experience are such phe-
these procedures matter so very much to us? . . . In this book, I nomena as texture, timbre, rhythm, and phrasing. One might as-
want to claim that this split between conventions and the ‘purely sume that such aspects of musical sound might more readily be
music’ is itself socially and historically contingent” (3). Despite understood as doing the “cultural work” that interests McClary.
this stated concern for the “conventionality” of music-theoretical While her analyses often refer to such features, they are not
concepts currently in use, McClary’s descriptions of “tonal” pro- considered the signiQcant events that receive detailed analytical
cedures owe much to them: such phrases as “tonal background” attention. For instance, in listening recently to a performance
of Elisabeth-Claude Jacquet de la Guerre’s suite in D minor for
2A very short list of authors who articulate a postmodern philosophical per-
clavecin (1707), I was struck by how the ornamental Qligree
spective include Roland Barthes, Jacques Derrida, Michel Foucault, Frederic
Jameson, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and Richard Rorty. On the speciQc issues of emerged as the structure of the pieces. I was not hearing the “im-
the contingency of experience, see Joan Scott, “The Evidence of Experience,” provised surface” as the icing on the tonally coherent cake.
Critical Inquiry 17 (1991): 773–97. Rather, the animated surface was the source of playful design that
Reviews 153

was anchored by cadential progressions serving as temporal Conventional Wisdom offers many ideas about how music stud-
markers. Structure in this usage is that which assumes the central ies might proceed within the new paradigms of the late twentieth-
focus of musical design, that which makes the piece hold together. century intellectual traditions. Yet it does not offer a new vision of
Since the musicological community does not have sophisticated what kinds of descriptive languages about music the profession
tools for taking account of how the textural effects of ornamenta- should be using to articulate these new approaches. One is re-
tion operate, any analytical account would have to theorize this as- minded of Boulez’s criticism of Schoenberg: his predecessor’s in-
pect of musical design in order to demonstrate the kinds of social novations in pitch were not matched by complementary innova-
behaviors it reRects and engenders. tions in phraseology and form, a failure which blunted the overall
The absence of an appropriate analytical apparatus in Con- effect of the purported revolution in music. As McClary works
ventional Wisdom is also noticeable in McClary’s accounts of sev- through her project of linking musical sound to social behaviors,
eral of the pieces in the last chapter on postmodern musics. One is we have every reason to expect that she will reQne her analytical
aware of McClary’s struggling to evoke the sounds of the pieces tools and more adequately historicize her accounts of subjectivity
by, for instance, John Zorn and Public Enemy. But in the end, the and the nature of musical experience.
reader does not have a clear sense of how the sounds of these mu-
sics accomplish their particular types of musical communication.
154 Music Theory Spectrum

José de Torres’s Treatise of 1736: General Rules for Accom- planned volume is unlikely to alter prevalent conceptions of late-
panying on the Organ, Harpsichord, and the Harp, By Knowing Baroque Spanish music and musical thought.
Only How to Sing the Part, or a Bass in Canto Qgurado. An anno- José de Torres y Martínez Bravo was a composer and maestro
tated bitextual edition by Paul Murphy. Publications of the Early de capilla at the royal chapel in Madrid from 1718 until his death
Music Institute. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2000. in 1738. He is known as well for his publishing house, La
Imprenta de M ◊ sica, founded at Madrid in 1700, through which
Reviewed by David Schulenberg he issued a number of theoretical works including the present trea-
tise. The work comprises four parts, or tratados, whose subjects
The major French and German music-theoretical treatises of are: (1) musical fundamentals: notes, intervals, and modal scales;
the eighteenth century have long been available in facsimiles, (2) progressions of consonant chords; (3) passing tones in the
modern editions, or translations. Some, such as Jean-Philippe bass, suspensions, and transpositions; and (4) realization in the
Rameau’s Traité de l’harmonie and Carl Philipp Emanuel Bach’s Italian style. Torres Qrst published tratados 1–3 in 1702; his sec-
Versuch über die wahre Art das Clavier zu spielen, have been suf- ond edition of 1736 not only added the fourth section but also re-
Qciently familiar and widely distributed in both their own time cast the examples in typeset keyboard notation—a Qrst for
and ours to have had a profound impact on both music theory and Spanish music printers according to Murphy (xi).
musical practice.1 The same cannot be said of writings from else- The present volume offers on facing pages the text of the 1736
where in Europe, including the Iberian peninsula, whose musical edition and a new English translation. The Spanish (Castillian)
culture throughout the Baroque remains a domain of specialists. text is newly set, with the original examples interspersed in fac-
Of Spanish and Portuguese theoretical writings only the Llave de simile; transcriptions in modern notation appear within the
modulación of Antonio Soler is at all well known, thanks in part to English text. In a brief introduction, Murphy places the treatise in
a facsimile published over thirty years ago.2 Harpsichordists and its music-theoretical context, describing it as “the Qrst work in
organists may have at least passing acquaintance with the music Spain to deal speciQcally and completely with thoroughbass
of such major Qgures as Soler or Juan Bautista José Cabanilles accompaniment at the keyboard” (xi).3 More precisely, Torres’s
(1644 –1712), but the instrumental and vocal repertory of chief concern is the correct writing or playing of three simple
eighteenth-century Spain and Portugal remains virtually unknown, contrapuntal parts above a bass line, Qgured or unQgured.
and it is fair to say that most professional theorists and historians, Practical matters of style and performance are largely ignored ex-
if they think at all about eighteenth-century music in these coun- cept in the closing chapters of tratado 3 (which provide examples
tries, have only a vague sense of it as stylistically conservative and of liturgical verses with Qgured bass) and in tratado 4. In both,
derivative. A new edition and translation of a major treatise from Torres acknowledges borrowing material from Francesco Gas-
late-Baroque Spain therefore provides an opportunity for broaden- parini’s L’armonico pratico al cimbalo, which gives a more thor-
ing modern awareness of Iberian musical culture in the eighteenth ough introduction to the types of arpeggiation and the irregular
century. For a variety of reasons, however, this ambitiously

3References are to the pagination at the bottoms of the pages, not the page

1Rameau 1722; Bach 1753–62. numbers in the running heads, which are repeated on the Spanish and English
2Soler 1762. sides of each opening.
Reviews 155

dissonances, especially acciaccaturas, employed in Italian con- the time of the Qrst edition; for instance, the illustrations of glosas
tinuo playing of the time.4 Elsewhere, too, Torres relies on older (divisions or passing notes) in the bass are reminiscent of what one
writers, including a number of Spanish authors (identiQed by Qnds in Corelli’s trio sonatas (especially those of op. 1, 1681). But
Murphy) and, above all, Lorenzo Penna, whom he cites frequently both the musical illustrations and the fundamental theoretical orien-
as an authority.5 tation as revealed in tratado 1, which is still grounded in liturgical
The opening section on musical fundamentals offers few sur- practice and the church modes, might by 1736 have begun to seem
prises, although it is notable for its adherence to the ninefold divi- old-fashioned in France, Italy, Germany, or Britain. The same is true
sion of the whole tone, a feature also of contemporary German of Torres’s scholastic literary style, untouched by Enlightenment
theory. Thus the chromatic (incantable) half step—the “un- wit or rationalism. Nevertheless, the progressions which Torres
singable” half step in Murphy’s translation—comprises four com- illustrates recur routinely as foreground voice leading in the music
mas, the diatonic (cantable) Qve. This yields, for example, a G of Corelli, Handel, J. S. Bach, and other younger contemporaries.
that is audibly lower than its enharmonic equivalent A , such as Tratado 2 describes the progressions of consonant chords—what
would occur in any of a number of keyboard temperaments that would now be termed root-position and Qrst-inversion triads—that
Torres might have used.6 Because Torres does not discuss tem- can take place over bass lines moving respectively in minor or chro-
perament, the exact size of these intervals is undeQned, but if the matic half steps, major or diatonic half steps, whole steps, and so
intention was to create pure major thirds (e.g., E–G ) then Torres’s on, up to the diminished fourth and augmented Qfth.8 Tratado 3
comma would differ by a minuscule amount from the traditional presents various types of passing motion in the bass as well as the
ditonic or Pythagorean comma.7 most common suspensions with similar rigor.
If not an original thinker, Torres was certainly an organized In its emphasis on actual progressions, Torres’s volume differs
one. The most notable feature of his treatise may be the systematic from what are now the more familiar French and German treatises
manner in which it sets forth the types of voice leading most fre- of the eighteenth century, which are organized according to
quently encountered in early eighteenth-century music. Torres’s chords—that is, individual classes of verticality as deQned by their
focus was presumably the old-fashioned Spanish vocal polyphony Qgured-bass signatures (e.g., 54 , 73 , etc.). Indeed, Torres discusses
of which he himself was an important composer; his few works the Qgures themselves only as an afterthought, after the presenta-
available in modern editions reveal a capable command of imita- tion of the various progressions (164– 6). His strict contrapuntal
tive liturgical counterpoint in the stile antico, in four to eight orientation is also evident in his avoidance of the types of liberties
parts. Many of Torres’s examples would have seemed stylish at which, in the French style of Qgured bass realization, led to the
routine use of the petite sixte—that is, a 63 -chord with an added
fourth—on the second degree of the scale. Rameau understood this
4 Gasparini 1708. chord—which incorporates an unprepared dissonant fourth—as the
5 Penna 1672. equivalent of what we would call a second-inversion dominant
6On German sources for this simpliQed division of the whole tone and its

practical ramiQcations, see Oleskiewicz 2000, 205–8.


7Murphy equates the two intervals (280 n. 11). In fact, the ditonic comma,

deQned as the interval between a major third (5:4) and a ditone (two major
whole steps, or 81:64), corresponds to the ratio 81:80. Eighteen of the latter 8At that point Torres stops, declaring that motion through the sixth is the

yield an interval (81 18:8018) imperceptibly larger than a major third. same as motion through the third (84).
156 Music Theory Spectrum

seventh; contrary to Murphy, I Qnd no evidence of the principle of The book’s utility is diminished by the sketchy background in-
chord inversion in Torres’s treatise.9 formation provided, as well as inaccuracies in the transcription of
Torres’s examples are accompanied by detailed descriptions or the examples, infelicities in translation, and remarkably poor edit-
“rules”—the reglas of the title. But these amount to little more than ing and production. Although conscientious in the discussion of
note-by-note accounts of what is manifest in the illustrations. The selected problems of translation, Murphy directs readers to unpub-
book’s greatest value, particularly for students, probably lies in the lished dissertations (including his own) for substantive informa-
examples themselves, which are sufQciently numerous and well tion about the author’s life and music; consideration of how the
designed to constitute a systematic exposition of the most common present work relates to Torres’s compositions would have been es-
four-part progressions in late-Baroque music. Most examples are pecially welcome here. Other important questions, such as the
presented Qrst as bass lines with numerical Qguration, then in fully sources of the liturgical melodies in tratado 3, which more closely
realized form on two staves. Practicing these illustrations at the resemble seventeenth-century Italian recitative than chant, are left
keyboard would lead to familiarity with each progression in turn— unasked. I would have liked to know how these examples relate to
which seems to have been their primary purpose. The book will the long tradition of accompanied liturgical chant, documented in
prove less useful for practice in reading actual Qgured basses, how- earlier Italian keyboard treatises that Torres probably knew.10
ever, since the initial presentation of each example uses not the Some commentary on the instruments available to Torres (and
sketchy Qguring of real continuo parts but a sort of tablature remi- their tuning and temperament) would also have been appropriate.
niscent of older Spanish keyboard notational systems: every note Despite the mention of three instruments in the title, the account
of the upper voices is indicated by numbers, speciQc registers of musical fundamentals in tratado 1 assumes use of an organ
being indicated through a system of letter abbreviations. with a so-called short octave (lacking C , E , F , and G in the
The examples go well beyond the simple illustrations of typi- lowest octave). The harp enjoyed widespread use in Baroque
cal chords that one Qnds in contemporary French and Italian Spain, but Torres says nothing whatever about it or how his musi-
Qgured-bass treatises, including Book 4 of Rameau’s Traité. cal examples might have been adapted to it. The organ is distin-
Moreover, by offering variations of each basic progression in dif- guished from the harpsichord only in tratado 4, whose examples
ferent keys within continuous passages of music, Torres provides of arpeggiated accompaniment are intended chieRy for the latter
a clearer sense of how each progression occurs in context than do instrument.
German writers, such as Bach. To be sure, the latter reveals a more The parallel Spanish and English texts, both containing illus-
sophisticated sense of the possibilities of voice leading, especially trative material, posed production challenges that were not met
in dissonant and chromatic progressions. Torres never goes be- with complete success. For instance, on page 174 the second mu-
yond the conventional; even tratado 4, which includes numerous sical example in the English text is repeated in place of the third
illustrations of extravagante chords, such as Neapolitan and full example; the examples for the Spanish text on pages 259 and 263
diminished-seventh harmonies, offers little that was out of the or- are exchanged. More troubling is the astounding number of proof-
dinary in contemporary Italian practice. reading errors; for example, throughout the book, the word
“method” appears more often than not as “mehtod,” and in tratado
9Murphy asserts that “this treatise . . . considers chord inversion and voice-

leading in the realization of the bass” but does not specify what passage he has
10 For example, Banchieri 1609.
in mind (xi).
Reviews 157

1 the endnotes are misnumbered, starting on page 20. Even the Unfortunately, the types of problems evident in the rendering
book’s manufacturing is wanting; in my copy many of the pages of the title continue throughout the English translation, which
were incompletely cut. consequently can be understood only by someone already famil-
More substantive problems attend the English version, which is iar with the subject and with eighteenth-century musical termi-
literal to the point of obscurity, often reading like the unedited nology. Sometimes a reliance on cognates leads to unidiomatic
output of an electronic translation program. Problems begin with translations—“the studious” for estudioso, student (50), “cantor”
the title, which in the original Castillian reads Reglas generales de for cantor, singer (123)—or to non-words such as “unisonically”
acompañar, en órgano, clavicordio, y harpa, con sólo saber can- (50). Especies falsas, meaning “dissonances,” appears throughout
tar la parte, o un bajo en canto Fgurado. As Murphy explains as “false intervals”; voces and cuerdes, translated literally as
(xviii), the last two words refer not to Qgured bass (as one might “voices” and “strings,” respectively, more often seem intended
think) but to “Qgural music,” that is, polyphony. In the puzzling metaphorically, as “notes.” Metrical and rhythmic terms present a
phrase “Sing the Part, or a Bass,” Murphy suggests plausibly that particular problem; although Murphy acknowledges the impor-
“the part” (la parte) is the bass (un bajo), that is, a Qgured or un- tance of mensural thinking in Torres’s understanding of rhythm
Qgured bass line; the two nouns are in apposition. But then in (ix), he nevertheless updates Torres’s terminology, offering, for
modern English the comma after “Part” should have been supple- example, “the measure’s downbeat or upbeat” for dar o alzar del
mented by a second one after the word “Bass.” Perhaps, too, the compás (96). I would have preferred “thesis and arsis of the tac-
word cantar (to sing) should be understood metaphorically, yield- tus,” using rhythmic nomenclature consistent with Torres’s archaic
ing an idiomatic rendering of the title as “Rules for Accom- notation, which includes old-fashioned irregular barring and sur-
panying on Organ, Harpsichord, Or Harp From Only the Bass Part vivals of mensural notation such as coloration and proportions.
of a Polyphonic Composition.” This makes it clear that the pur- Murphy updates the latter as well, frequently halving the values of
pose of the book was to teach organists to accompany choral examples in triple time.11
music without a score; evidently, there as yet existed no simpler Numerous wrong notes further mar the examples, sometimes
terminology with which Torres could describe continuo playing obscuring the points they are meant to illustrate. Thus on page 240 the
7 7
for his Spanish-speaking readers. second of two 54 chords is realized instead as a 64 —in modern terms,
2 2
Although I was unable to check the reliability of the Spanish eliminating the dominant-seventh chord (over a tonic pedal) which
text against the original editions, it seems sound, and the English the example was supposed to show. On page 182 the examples
translation rarely contains outright errors. Murphy asserts that under the headings “Chord 1 . . . Chord 2” and “Chord 3 . . .
Torres refers to both perfect and augmented fourths as mayor (282 Chord 4” have been exchanged, and a sharp has been added to a G
n. 18), but this reRects a misreading of the chapter heading “Del in the bass, resulting in a diminished third and a cross relation—
salto de cuarta hacia abajo, o quinta hacia arriba, así mayores highly uncharacteristic dissonances for Torres! In such cases,
como menores.” Murphy gives this as “On the leap downward, or comparison with the original notation on the facing pages will re-
the Qfth upward, both perfect and diminished” (76, 268), but it veal the errors, but sometimes the original is clearly erroneous;
might be better rendered as “Leaps of a fourth downward or a Qfth only occasionally does Murphy offer corrections. Errors seem par-
upward, including augmented and diminished intervals.” Else- ticularly common in tratado 4, suggesting that the aging Torres
where, it is clear that Torres uses mayor only for augmented
11 Contrary to what is stated in the introduction (xxi).
fourths and minor for diminished Qfths.
158 Music Theory Spectrum

did not carefully oversee production of the concluding pages of LIST OF WORKS CITED
his work; a glaring instance occurs on page 250, where all of the
Bach, Carl Philipp Emanuel. 1752–63. Versuch über die wahre Art
Qgures 5 and 7 are errors for 5-6 and 7-6, respectively.
das Clavier zu spielen. 2 vols. Berlin. Facsimile, with
As disturbing as the outright errors is the faulty notation of the
Nachwort by Lothar Hoffmann-Erbrecht and supplement con-
transcriptions, which wherever possible group the noteheads of
taining additions from the edition of 1787–97. Leipzig: VEB
the three upper parts—set on one staff for the right hand—onto
Breitkopf und Härtel, 1981. Translated by William J. Mitchell
single stems. This obscures the contrapuntal character of the voice
as Essay on the True Art of Playing Keyboard Instruments.
leading, and further damage occurs when the stems of passing
New York, Norton, 1949.
notes go in the wrong direction, as is often the case. To be sure,
Banchieri, Adriano. 1609. Conclusioni nel suono dell’organo.
the original is often equally at fault, entirely omitting stems from
Bologna. Facsimile. New York : Broude Brothers, 1975. Partial
the middle (alto) voice in most sonorities. This, however, is a
translation by Lee R. Garrett as Conclusions for Playing the
common feature in typeset keyboard music of the period, for rea-
Organ. Colorado Springs: Colorado College Music Press,
sons logically analogous to those which today create difQculties
1982.
for music-setting software in contrapuntal keyboard textures. It is
Gasparini, Francesco. 1708. L’armonico pratico al cimbalo.
ironic that, although Murphy duly notes the signiQcance of the
Venice. Translated by Frank S. Stillings as The Practical
high-tech printing process that Torres adopted in the 1736 edition,
Harmonist at the Harpsichord. New Haven: Yale University
by the end of the century music publishers were returning to en-
Press, 1963.
graving as the best method for printing graphically complex key-
Oleskiewicz, Mary. 2000. “The Flutes of Quantz: Their
board notation.
Construction and Performing Practice.” Galpin Society Journal
Despite its many shortcomings, this edition will prove valu-
53: 201–20.
able to serious students of Spanish Baroque music and
Penna, Lorenzo. 1672. Li primi albori musicali. Bologna.
eighteenth-century theory. It demonstrates that the strict, four-
Facsimile of the fourth edition (Bologna, 1684). Bologna:
part contrapuntal style of Qgured bass realization best known
Forni, 1969.
today from German sources, such as Bach’s Versuch, was also
Rameau, Jean-Phillipe. 1722. Traité de l’harmonie réduite à ses
typical of what Torres calls “the rigorous Spanish style” (212).
principes naturels. Paris. Facsimile. New York, Broude, 1965.
The extraordinary achievements that this style could produce in
Edited by Erwin R. Jacobi in The Complete Theoretical
the seventeenth century are evident in the contrapuntal keyboard
Writings of Jean-Philippe Rameau, vol. 1. American Institute
works of Cabanilles and other Iberian organist-composers.
of Musicology, 1967. Translated by Philip Gossett as Treatise
Future work might relate Torres’s teaching of this style to his
on Harmony. New York: Dover, 1971.
vocal compositions and those of other eighteenth-century
Soler, Antonio. 1762. Llave de la modulación. Madrid. Facsimile.
Iberian musicians.
New York: Broude, 1967.

Potrebbero piacerti anche