Sei sulla pagina 1di 11

PAUL DURO

What Is a Parergon?

abstract
Despite important recent work, the rehabilitation of parergon as a critical concept in the history of art has yet to be fully
broached. From the time Jacques Derrida introduced the term into contemporary critical theory in The Truth in Painting,
its character and function have been largely understood as referencing a threshold or boundary—in particular, that of the
border of the artwork. Yet a review of the term’s long history suggests a meaning that differs in significant ways from its
current near-univocal characterization as a synonym for a frame. In particular, premodern art theory and criticism identifies
a parergon with matters such as the background action in a history painting, the inclusion in a landscape of picturesque
embellishments, or, following Kant, the addition of ornament to a painting, a statue, or a building. This article therefore
proposes we ask again: What is a parergon?

Although historically the parergon (para: beside, the historical parergon, we need to look beyond
ergon: work) contributes much to our understand- its current incarnation in critical theory to trace
ing of such weighty matters in art theory and crit- its history as a critical term in art history under
icism as the hierarchy of the genres, the role of three distinct but closely related heads—as frame
the subject, and pictorial composition, it has never or border, as accessory to the main subject, and as
been in wide circulation in the manner of other ornament. Only then will we be able to gauge the
critical terms such as disegno, imitatio, or beau importance of this uncommon word that, despite
idéal. Yet this infrequence of use is not the only its relatively infrequent use by artists and critics,
reason for our ignorance. Much of our present offers the possibility of filling a gap that is not
disregard of the parergon’s broader historical im- otherwise adequately addressed in the discourse
portance is due to its current celebrity as the key on art.
term in Jacques Derrida’s The Truth in Painting,
where the parergon’s character and function are
largely understood to denominate a threshold or i. parerga without borders
border—in particular, that of a frame (Derrida
1987, 15–147).1 Historically, ‘parergon’ does not reference an in-
It is not my purpose here to rehearse Derrida’s dependent entity, but “something subordinate or
argument in extenso, nor to question the impor- accessory to the main subject” (Oxford English
tance of boundaries, borders, and frames in the Dictionary 2018). A classic account of this kind
constitution of the artwork; rather, I want to con- of pictorial accessory appears in Strabo’s Geogra-
sider the role of the parergon in antiquity and phy, where the first-century BCE geographer and
early modern history in order to engage with a historian describes a painting by Protogenes of a
broader understanding of the term than that al- flute-playing satyr leaning on a column:
lowed by Derrida. Why this is important will, I
hope, become clear as this article unfolds, but the On the top of the column was a partridge. The bird
fundamental justification may be stated immedi- strongly attracted, as was natural, the gaping admira-
ately. In order to assess the scope and meaning of tion of the people, [such that] . . . the Satyr, although
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 77:1 Winter 2019
C 2019 The American Society for Aesthetics
24 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

executed with great skill, was not noticed. . . . When Pro- one work, the principal figure is admirably beautiful,
togenes observed that the principal [έργον: ergon] had and the adjunct, or assigned emblem or attribute, is far
become the subordinate part [πάρεργον: parergon] of inferior to it, then I believe we may conclude from this
his work, he obtained permission of the curators of the circumstance that the part which is deficient in form and
temple to efface the bird, which he did. (Strabo 1857, 30, workmanship was regarded as an accessory or Parergon,
vol. 3; translation modified) as it was also termed by artists. For these accessories are
not to be viewed in the same light as the episodes of a
Protogenes’s decision to include the partridge con- poem, or the speeches in history, in which the poet and
flicted with established ideas of what constituted historian have displayed their utmost skill. (1850, 246).
the subject. The satyr is the subject (ergon), and
the partridge the parergon, yet the satyr, “al- In one sense, Winckelmann’s example is the op-
though executed with great skill, was not noticed.” posite of Protogenes’s satyr and partridge, where
It is this quality of insufficiency with a hierarchy it is the artist’s skill in painting the avian acces-
of genres (where the human subject is overlooked sory that wins the plaudits of the crowd. In all
in favor of a bird), that prompted Pliny the Elder other respects, however, Winckelmann, as one
to remark, in reference to another work by Proto- might expect from an eighteenth-century scholar
genes, “he painted among those by-works (which steeped in classicism, presents a clear justification
painters call Parerga), certaine small gallies and for considering the human figure as the main sub-
little long barks, to shew therby the small begin- ject (ergon), and the chair as a mere accessory
nings of his art” (Pliny 1601, 542, vol. II)—a refer- (parergon).2 In a similar manner, Winckelmann’s
ence to the belief that Protogenes had begun his emphasis on the narrative (“accessories are not
career as a painter and decorator of ships—that is, to be viewed in the same light as the episodes of
as an artisan. a poem”) reminds us that embellishments, sub-
Like the satyr and partridge, the “small gal- sidiary motifs, and accessories are subordinate to
lies” anecdote underlines the importance of the the main subject, thus functioning as parergon to
subject in the matter of art. Protogenes’s self- the principal action.
identification as an artist is dependent on his It is this fundamental distinction between prin-
choice of subject. The little ships were there to cipal and subordinate elements that is the ground-
show how much he had grown from “the small ing condition for the operation of a parergon in
beginnings of his art” and should now be consid- pre-Derridean art theory. In his treatise On Paint-
ered an artist. Little wonder the popular reaction ing of 1435, Leon Battista Alberti praises work
to the partridge he carelessly positioned atop a that offers variety and interest in the composi-
column so frustrated him; the skill with which he tion; but his enthusiasm turns to censure when
had painted the partridge was precisely not the these embellishments interfere with the principle
recognition he was looking for, showing that not subject:
how but what artists painted was preeminent in
establishing their rank. I disapprove of those painters who, in their desire to
Johann Joachim Winckelmann commented on appear rich or to leave no space empty, follow no system
this hierarchy in noting that classical painters were of composition, but scatter everything about in random
wary of being seen as mere imitators of everyday confusion . . . In a ‘historia’ I strongly approve of the
nature and that the work of the artist was to avoid practice I see observed by the tragic and comic poets, of
the representation of the trivial, the marginal, and telling their story with as few characters as possible. In
the mundane: my opinion there will be no ‘historia’ so rich in variety of
things that the nine or ten men cannot worthily perform
The slight regard paid by the ancient artists to ob- it. (Alberti 1991, 65–66, 78; italics in original)
jects which were seemingly not within their province,
is shown, for instance, by the painted vases, on which Like Winckelmann, Alberti insists that the com-
the chair of a seated figure is indicated simply by a bar position should follow the lead of the poets and
placed horizontally. But, though the artist did not trou- avoid extraneous detail or minor distractions that
ble himself as to the way in which a figure should be detract from the main story. Alberti does not name
represented sitting, still, in the figure itself, he displays parerga when he criticizes painters who “follow
all the skill of an accomplished master. . . . But if, in any no system of composition,” but he does not need
Duro What Is a Parergon? 25

to. In identifying the representation of a historia of the body or argument thereof is Landskip, Par-
(subject) as the artist’s principal task, he connects ergon, or by-work,” he is categorically excluding
historia with Aristotle’s description of tragedy as parergon from the “body or argument” of the
“a mimesis of an action, and only for the sake “poesia,” instead identifying it with background
of this is it a mimesis of the agents [characters] or landscape. He drives home his point with an
themselves” (Aristotle 1987, 38). example:
While Alberti cites the demands of historia
to justify the compositional order of painting, [I]n the Table of our Saviour’s Passion, the picture of
Gabriele Paleotti, archbishop of Bologna, insists Christ on the Rood (which is the antient English word
on a doctrinal distinction based on decorum: for Cross) the two Theeves, the blessed Virgin Mary, and
St. John, are the Argument: But the City Jerusalem, the
Elements that have nothing to do with the main subject Country about, the clouds, and the like, are Landskip.
. . . are called parerga in Greek, and examples would (Blount 1656)
include paintings of our Lord being cruelly whipped at
the column in which are added to one side, even if off in As in a historia, the subject is the representation of
the distance, a boy playing with a dog, or a battle of birds, human actions, distinguished from the “by-work”
or a peasant catching frogs, or other things that painters through their involvement in the plot or narrative.
imagine without caring whether or not they correspond Christ’s agony, or the thieves’ responses to dying
to the main subject. (2012, 231) in the presence of the Son of God, or Mary and
St. John’s anguish, constitute the central elements;
Paleotti’s treatise, Discorso intorno alle imagini everything else is parerga.
sacre e profane (Discourse on Sacred and Profane In a letter to his patron Paul Fréart de
Images), explains his interest. As we know from Chantelou of 1658, Nicolas Poussin describes this
the opposition Paolo Veronese experienced when distinction between subsidiary elements and the
he painted a Last Supper in the House of Simon main subject in his painting Holy Family in Egypt,
(the title later changed to Feast in the House of now in the Hermitage Museum:
Levi), for the refectory of Santi Giovanni e Paolo
in 1573, the Counter-Reformation paid particu- I promised to make known the parerga which are in the
lar attention to the all-important relation between background of the painting that I have done for you. . . . I
subject matter and treatment. Accused of profan- have put into the painting all those things there to delight
ity by the Roman Catholic Inquisition for secular- by their novelty and variety and to show that the Virgin
izing a narrative drawn from the Bible, Veronese who is represented there is in Egypt. (Poussin 1911, 448–
was asked why he had included a “man dressed as 449)
a buffoon with a parrot on his wrist,” and replied,
perhaps unwisely, “for ornament,” thereby iden- Poussin’s remarks perfectly illustrate the nature of
tifying the jester as a mere parergon to the action this kind of parerga. They are there to ornament
(Holt 1958, 68). the composition—“to delight by their novelty and
Veronese’s reply confirms how closely con- variety”—and in this case to emphasize that the
nected the question of what Paleotti calls “el- Holy Family is in in Egypt (and not still en route
ements that have nothing to do with the main as in the more frequently portrayed Flight into
subject” is for the emerging concept of decorum Egypt). This subordinate element includes, in the
in painting. When Thomas Blount included ‘par- mid-distance, a procession of priests of the cult
ergon’ under the head of ‘Landskip’ in his 1656 of Serapis, who bear aloft an ark of relics. These
dictionary Glossographia, he did so understand- background details are not part of the main story,
ing that landscape formed a separate category of which concerns the miraculous provision of food
painting from the historia of Alberti or the sa- for the Holy Family; rather, its importance derives
cred theme the Last Supper. The historia, called from the distinction it draws between the Chris-
“poesia” by Titian and later and more generally tian subject matter of the foreground (ergon) and
“history painting,” were hedged around with re- pagan rituals of the background (parergon).
strictions and protocols of what should, and should Let us stay with Poussin a moment longer to
not, be represented (Puttfarken 2005, 10). When examine another work, his celebrated Eliezer and
Blount asserts, “All that which in a Picture is not Rebecca at the Well (1648), now in the Louvre
26 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

museum. The painting was the object of a dispute 2005, 690–691). As artists from Protogenes to
in the Académie royale de peinture et de sculp- Le Brun realized, to applaud a painter for the
ture over whether Poussin should have included uncritical depiction of external nature was to
the train of camels—conspicuous by their absence praise the lesser achievement of mimesis over
in his painting—described in the Bible. The di- invention. This explains Protogenes’s anger that
rector of the Académie, Charles Le Brun, offered his satyr was overlooked in favor of an avian
cogent reasons why the inclusion of such “bizarre interloper; the partridge was never intended to be
objects,” and therefore parergonal to the sacred the principal part of the painting—a frustration
narrative, would militate against the decorum of that must have only intensified when he realized
the “principal action” of the representation: his popular success was at the expense of his
standing as a figure painter. Little wonder he
M. Poussin, seeking always to purify and clarify the sub- erased the offending element.
ject of his works and to agreeably demonstrate the prin- This distinction between the genres, and the
ciple action he was addressing, had rejected bizarre ob- scant importance accorded to the representation
jects that could lead the eye of the spectator astray and of the lower orders, prompts Edward Norgate,
amuse him only with trivia; that the field of representa- writing about Raphael’s tapestry cartoons ac-
tion is destined exclusively for the figures necessary to quired by Charles I in 1623 and now in the Victoria
the subject and for those who are capable of an inge- and Albert Museum, to remark:
nious and agreeable expression; such that [Poussin] was
correct not to concern himself with a train of camels that It doth not appeare that the antients made any other
would have been as unprofitable for the work as em- Accompt or use of [landscape] but as a servant to their
barrassing by their number. (Mérot 2003, 130–139; my other peeces, to illustrate or sett their Historicall paint-
translation) ing by filling up the empty Corners, or void places of
Figures and story, with some fragment of Landscape . . .
Le Brun is not recorded as having used the term as may be seene in those incomparable Cartoni of the
‘parergon’ in his remarks, but he could, with pro- Acts of the Apostles. . . . (1919, 44)
priety, have done so. “Objects that could lead the
eye of the spectator astray and amuse him only Norgate’s reference to landscape as a servant,
with trivia” is highly reminiscent, at a remove of “filling up the empty Corners” describes one kind
almost two millennia, of the criticism of Proto- of parergon very well. Where the landscape is
genes’s misstep in including a partridge atop a part of the representation, as in an Acts of the
column. Le Brun’s justification for their exclu- Apostles or as described in Blount’s Crucifixion,
sion shows that parerga cannot be separated from it is compositionally and iconographically a “by-
questions related to subject matter, nor accom- work,” designed to support the principal narra-
modated into a historia, ranked as the most no- tive. But were a landscape to assume dominion
ble form of picturing (the equivalent of tragedy over the main subject, then it would undermine
in drama) without doing violence to the received the hierarchy, making a subject like the act(ion)
idea of ambitious painting. of the Apostles subservient to a minor genre. It
is for this reason that Poussin instructs his pa-
tron Chantelou, when considering his new acqui-
ii. parerga and the hierarchy of the genres sition, Israelites Gathering the Manna, to “read the
story and the painting, in order to discern if each
A parergon cannot be identified as a thing in itself, thing is appropriate to the subject” (1911, 20–21).
but only in relation to something already recog- The purpose is to ensure that Chantelou sees the
nized as the main work (the ergon). It therefore miraculous appearance of the manna as the main
follows that the link between the main subject and subject, in which the setting—the rocky and arid
the parergonal elements of a painting broaches desert landscape—is there purely to lend credence
the question of the formulation, codified by André to the hunger and thirst of the Israelites.
Félibien in 1668, of a hierarchy of the genres, in Why this mattered is closely allied to the ques-
fact a hierarchy of art and artists, that had been in- tion of the status of parerga. Where a significant
creasingly important in art theory at least since the subject is present, as in a Christ at the Column, a
early sixteenth century (Mérot 2003, 50–51; Duro Crucifixion, or a Eliezer and Rebecca at the Well,
Duro What Is a Parergon? 27

then the minor genre could be what the main hierarchy. While this mattered little to the lesser
subject always intended such elements to be—a genres (they were already lumped together as ir-
parergonal support to the narrative; but if there is redeemably minor, forever excluded from history
no main subject, no Aristotelian emphasis on dra- painting’s charmed circle), it mattered crucially
matic action, then the subject would exhibit a lack when it was a question of maintaining the author-
for which no amount of skill in the depiction of an- ity, and representational practices, of narrative
cilliary elements could compensate. Jean-Baptiste painting. This collapse of subject into setting
Dubos refers precisely to this kind of absence in allows for the dissolution of the ergon/parergon
his 1719 treatise, Réflexions critiques sur la poésie relationship and the consequent marginalization
et sur la peinture: of the ergon. In this scenario the loss of a subject,
which the parergon, by definition, cannot replace,
How shall our attention be engaged by a picture repre- means that neither landscape nor the pastoral
senting a peasant driving a couple of beasts along the pursuits of those engaged in work there (such as
highway, if the very action which this picture imitates, Dubos’s drover) can be characterized merely as
has no power of affecting us? . . . There is nothing in the setting for a painting, nor for that matter is
the action of a country feast, or in the amusements of a the one able to serve as a foil to establish the
parcel of soldiers in the guardhouse, that is capable of distinction between genre painting and historia
moving us. . . . [W]e disapprove of his choice of objects that brought about the ergon/parergon in the first
that have so little in them to engage us. (Dubos 1748, place.
43–44, vol. I) The examples examined so far all share the
characteristic of placing the parergon in a subor-
The dismissive characterization of a drover as a dinate or supplementary role to the ergon, and the
subject unworthy of our interest alerts us to the terms used to characterize this relationship have
importance of the hierarchy of subject matter in included ‘accessory,’ ‘embellishment,’ and ‘orna-
the appreciation of painting. Implicit in Dubos’s ment,’ suggesting an affinity of purpose that is
remarks is not only the idea that a hierarchy—with borne out by the historical evidence. But it is just
history painting at its apex—should exist, but also this abolition of the boundary between subject
that the distinction between the representation of and setting that Wood speaks of that is given life
human action and the depiction of inanimate na- in Pieter Bruegel the Elder’s Landscape with the
ture could be drawn as an unbridgeable divide Fall of Icarus (c.1555). The drama of the narrative
separating main action from minor themes. (the fall) is relegated to a distant corner of the
But if the hierarchy continued to be a major composition—Icarus drowns while a fisherman
factor in the choice of subject matter in Italy fishes on, and the ploughboy on the cliff top steers
and particularly in France down to the end of the plough and sees nothing. Several writers have
the eighteenth century, in northern Europe it produced ekphrasis on the painting, most perti-
was always less influential. Christopher S. Wood, nently for the present discussion W. H. Auden in
in his study of the early sixteenth-century artist “Musée des Beaux-Arts,” who comments that the
Albrecht Altdorfer, speaks of the artists as “old masters” realized that the site of any tragedy
“abolish[ing] the boundary between subject and (ergon), however terrible, contains on its margins
setting, as well as the hierarchy, by banishing the (parergon), episodes of quotidian normalcy:
subject and funnelling setting toward the literal
centre of the image” (2014, 69). Wood’s remark In Breughel’s Icarus, for instance: how everything turns
productively distinguishes between ergon and away
parergon, introducing the concept of border or Quite leisurely from the disaster; the ploughman may
boundary between pictorial elements within a Have heard the splash, the forsaken cry
composition, thereby distinguishing the idea of But for him it was not an important failure. (Auden 1991,
the boundary or border from that of the frame. 179)
As Wood shows, if, in certain settings, the genres
were to be ranked categorically, to serve both as iii. the parergon as ornament
guide and limit to the various ways of representing
nature, then each (whether major or minor) was A parergon is also an ornamental addition or em-
open to subversion by other categories within the bellishment to the main work. This aspect of the
28 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

parergon is not in opposition, or even at variance, enclosed in exuberantly ornamental cartouches,


with the parergon of subject matter; rather ‘orna- distinguish between the subject and supplemen-
ment’ serves to emphasize the properties of the tary matter that comments on them. Jacques Gom-
parergon as an accessory or embellishment to the boust’s 1652 Plan de Paris shows, along with a map
main work (ergon), and frees the parergon to func- of the city, framed topographical views inserted
tion less as a subordinate element to the main into each corner, the whole further surrounded by
story and more as an adornment or ornament of a dense written commentary. A further example
the work. An early and instructive example of this of this kind of parerga is found in Abraham Or-
kind of parergon is found in Galen’s On the Use- telius’s atlas, Theatrum orbis terrarium (1579), the
fulness of the Parts of the Body, in which the Greek second edition of which contained a supplement
physician and philosopher compares the way na- entitled Parergon Theatri, a supplement that dis-
ture has ornamented certain parts of the human played maps of, for the most part, ancient his-
body to the way good craftsmen “give an extra torical locations and mythical sites such as the
proof of their skill by modeling some ornament voyages of Jason and the Argonauts and the lo-
or device for the work beyond what is useful,” cation of Utopia. Unlike the main atlas, which
such as crafting designs of “ivy, or the tendrils represented the most rigorous and scientific car-
of grapevine, or a spray of cypress, or some other tographical research of the day, the supplement
such thing” on shields, sword hilts, or bowls (Galen contrasts these values with a degree of literary and
1968, II 529).3 poetic license (as one might expect from a map of
Galen’s characterization of the parergon as an Utopia), imparting imaginative commentary that
ornamental addition is echoed by Alberti, who served as a counterpoint to the main work’s sci-
writes, “Ornaments done by artificers that are entific rigor. And while cartouches in the main
added to painting, such as sculpted columns, bases, atlas were used to represent or comment on the
and pediments, I would not censure if they were in unmapped or inaccessible parts of continents and
real silver and solid or pure gold, for a perfect and uncharted oceans, the supplement announced its
finished painting is worthy to be ornamented even status by framing the supplement with the title
with precious stones” (Alberti 1991, 85–86). Al- “Parergon” within a quadrilateral surround in im-
berti thinks about ornamenting the frame, almost itation of a picture frame (Heuer 2009, 131).
certainly that of an altarpiece where the archi-
tectural surround (“sculpted columns, bases, and
pediments”) is integral to the painting. Even so, he iv. the parergon as pictorial embellishment
distinguishes between painting and border. Else-
where in his treatise, he disapproves of the use There is a significant difference between the be-
of gold leaf within the pictorial field, where its jeweled surround to an altarpiece, or a cartouche
monetary value would compete with the artist’s on a map, where the parergon operates as a formal
ingenium as the source of the painting’s value. distinction between work and frame, and the sub-
While a fifteenth-century altarpiece is a very dif- ject/accessory distinction familiar from my earlier
ferent kind of artwork from the detachable quadri- examples. There is, however, another focus where
lateral surround of easel paintings that became a parergon functions as a compositional embel-
the norm from the sixteenth century onwards, Al- lishment within the bounds of the work. Blaise
berti’s characterization of the frame as an essen- de Vigenère, writing in the late sixteenth century,
tially ornamental enclosure, conceptually and ma- illustrates this form of parergonality:
terially separate from the picture field, lays the
groundwork for the Kantian work/frame distinc- Among their works painters paint perspectives, shrubby
tion that is at the heart of much contemporary trees, little animals, old ruins, and collapsed buildings,
theorizing of the boundaries of the artwork. mountains and valleys, together with such other acces-
Another important instance of ornamental sories and incidents that serve to enrich and give grace
additions that address the main subject from to their task, and fill out that which otherwise would
the frame/margins of the composition concerns remain uselessly denuded and empty, in danger of be-
the borders of maps and printed matter more ing an eyesore. The Greeks call them παρεργα [par-
generally, where marginal embellishments, such erga], or superfluous additions, besides what is needed.
as captions, topographies, and grotesques, often (1999, 131)
Duro What Is a Parergon? 29

De Vigenère’s comment encompasses the usual instancing a pictorial trope that ornaments the
range of motifs that may be called parerga— landscape (Gilpin 1792, 27–28; 55–56). There is
“shrubby trees, little animals, old ruins, and col- nothing here that suggests Gilpin wishes for any
lapsed buildings, mountains and valleys” (131)— other subject other than a picturesque prospect
but in characterizing parerga as “superfluous addi- or seeks to raise the standing of landscape paint-
tions, besides what is needed,” he anticipates what ing in the manner of Claude or Poussin, through
I might call the definitive characterization of orna- reference to the Bible or mythology. Rather, he
mental parerga that appears in Henry Peacham’s explains his intention more fully by drawing on
Graphice, or The Most Ancient and Excellent Art the vocabulary of picturesque sketching:
of Drawing and Limming, published early in the
seventeenth century as “needeless graces”: “For In adorning your sketch, a figure, or two may be intro-
your Parergas or needlesse graces, you may set duced with propriety. By figures I mean moving objects,
forth the same with Farme-houses, Water-milles, as wagons, and boats as well as cattle, and men. But they
Pilgrims travelling, the ruines of Churches, Cas- should be introduced sparingly. In profusion they are
tles, &c.” (1612, 45). affected. Their chief use is, to mark a road—to break a
It is these “needeless graces” that engage the piece of foreground—to point out the horizon in a sea-
prelate and historian Paolo Giovio, writing about view—or to carry off the distance of a retiring water by
the paintings of Dosso Dossi early in the sixteenth the contrast of a dark sail, not quite so distant, placed
century: before it. But in figures thus designed for the ornament
of a sketch, a few light touches are sufficient. Attempts
The gentle manner of Dosso of Ferrara is esteemed in his at finishing offend. (Gilpin 1792, 77)
proper works, but most of all in those which are called
parerga. For devoting himself with relish to the pleasant Although Gilpin does not use the term ‘par-
diversions of painting he used to depict jagged rocks, erga,’ his reference to “embellish his pictures with
green groves, the firm banks of traversing rivers, the pleasing shapes” shows a remarkable homogene-
flourishing work of the countryside, the gay and hard ity with earlier usage. Above all, such figures
toil of the peasants, and also the far distant prospects add interest to the representation of the action,
of land and sea, fleets, fowling, hunting, and all that serving as “staffage,” that is, what Cassell’s dic-
genre so pleasing to the eyes in a lavish and festive style. tionary describes as “accessories, decoration . . .
(Gombrich 1966, 113–114) such as figures in a landscape” (1978, ‘Staffage’).
But whether called staffage or picturesque ele-
This insistence that parerga were not “proper ments that stimulate the artist’s powers of inven-
works” but rather “the pleasant diversions of tion, these parerga remain just that—“needlesse
painting,” associates parerga with genre painting graces,” ancillary to the composition, yet serving
(“the gay and hard toil of the peasants”), cement- to engage the interest of the spectator.
ing its place in the lower echelons of the hierarchy
of the genres.
These examples conform to the idea of parerga v. the borders of paintings
as ornament, a means of embellishing the compo-
sition, and in this respect anticipate the fashion for To read Derrida on the parergon is to experience
the picturesque in late eighteenth-century Britain. at once a dizzying sense of possibility for the re-
The Reverend William Gilpin, whose Three Es- formulation for the boundaries of the artwork, yet
says on the Picturesque (1792) largely defined the also to find oneself drawn toward an occasionally
movement, argued that ‘picturesque’ should be convoluted and overly narrow definition of what
understood as anything that is suitable for includ- a parergon is. Approaching the artwork as the site
ing in a picture. Gilpin’s interest lies with the of a “lack,” Derrida seeks to reveal the inherent
role of parerga that “embellish [an artist’s] pic- weakness of a symbolic form, such as art, that pur-
tures with pleasing shapes.” When he writes that ports to inclusivity and autonomy, yet relies on all
“[a] group of cattle, standing in the shade on the manner of liminal devices to reinforce its inher-
edge of a dark hill, and relieved by a lighter dis- ently unstable boundaries.4 While common sense
tance beyond them, will often make a complete might suggest that such marginal matter merely
picture without any other accompaniment,” he is serves to demarcate the inside from the outside
30 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

of the artwork, Derrida focuses on what one critic beautiful form, if it is, like a gilt frame, attached merely in
has called the “logic of the frame” to challenge order to recommend approval for the painting through
the idea that the artwork possesses an essence its charm—then it is called decoration, and detracts from
that is already present and complete (Bernstein genuine beauty. (Kant 2000, §14, 110–111).6
1992, 168). The frame around a painting is just
such a device, and Derrida argues that the par-
ergonal frame comes to trouble the either/or, in- When Kant defines “the borders of paintings” as
side/outside, pure/impure binaries that establish “that which is not internal to the entire represen-
the identity of the artwork in the first place: tation of the object as a constituent, but only be-
longs to it externally as an addendum,” he seems
Parergon: neither work (ergon) nor outside the work to insist on the liminal nature of his example.
[hors d’oeuvre], neither inside nor outside, neither above But Kant’s definition relates not to the frame as
nor below, it disconcerts any opposition but does not re- such but to the kind of frame (gilt or plain) and
main indeterminate and it gives rise [donne lieu] to the the purposes to which it is employed—whether it
work. It is no longer merely around the work. That which serves the painting by modestly deferring to the
it puts in place—the instances of the frame, the title, the depiction (plain) or whether it draws attention to
signature, the legend, etc.—does not stop disturbing the itself through a show of charm (gilt), designed to
internal order of discourse on painting, its works, its com- appeal to the eye and not the intellect: “but if the
merce, its evaluations, its surplus-values, its speculation, ornament itself does not consist in beautiful form,
its law, and its hierarchies. (1987, 9) if it is, like a gilt frame, attached merely in order to
recommend approval for the painting through its
For Derrida, the frame is that part of the artwork charm—then it is called decoration, and detracts
that “gives rise” to the artwork, completing the from genuine beauty” (2000, §14 110, 111).
work in a way that the work, in and of itself, is Kant’s other examples of parerga (“draperies
incapable of achieving (Derrida 1987, 42–43, 59).5 on statues, or colonnades around magnificent
But if there is no need to question the value of buildings”) (111), likewise serve to illustrate this
an argument that has been instrumental in turning distinction between form and decoration, al-
attention “from work to frame” (to borrow the ti- though not all commentators have been willing
tle of a seminal essay by Craig Owens), opening to forgo a quip that the columns of a colonnade,
up a discourse that has proved invaluable for the far from being merely ornaments, or decoration,
study of the conceptual and material boundaries to the building, surely hold up the roof. (In fact,
of the artwork, Derrida’s narrow association of columns are often non-integral to the main struc-
parergon with frame has served to occlude other, ture and serve rather to designate the peristyle, as
incompatible meanings of parergon, to say noth- in a classical Greek temple. Heidegger’s comment
ing of his complete disregard for the term’s histor- that “the building encloses the figure of the god,
ical importance (Owens 1994; Duro 1996; Jonietz and in this concealment lets it stand out into the
2016, 1042). But what of Kant? Is he not in some holy precinct through the open portico,” is rel-
measure responsible for the displacement of the evant here (1993, 167). In a similar way, Kant’s
parergon onto the frame? His reference to “the “draperies on statues” may seem to make little
borders of paintings” in Critique of the Power of sense. What is it about a clothed statue that sus-
Judgment—the reference on which Derrida bases tains Kant’s thesis? Again, we need to see beyond
his analysis—might make it seem so. Let us look the apparent oddity of the example. A recent study
again at this passage, which appears in §14 “Elu- of the nude in art has referred to nudity as “the
cidation by means of examples”: zero point of material” (Nancy and Ferrari, 2014).
This is well said. The human form has been the
Even what one calls ornaments (parerga), i.e., that which basis of much Western art and architecture from
is not internal to the entire representation of the object the classical era to the present, and extraneous el-
as a constituent, but only belongs to it externally as an ad- ements of any kind—such as clothing—are seen
dendum and augments the satisfaction of taste, still does as interfering with the (naked) truth of the repre-
this only through its form: like the borders of paintings, sentation. Hence, Kant contrasts the unadorned
draperies on statues, or colonnades around magnificent essence of the form (the nude) with drapery that
buildings. But if the ornament itself does not consist in serves to ornament the essential body.7
Duro What Is a Parergon? 31

Although footnoted in all recent editions, few theory has paid scant attention to its historical
critics have remarked that neither “parerga” nor importance for much of the time. It is wrong to
“borders of paintings” were included in the first blame Derrida for this oversight; he merely bor-
edition of the Third Critique. Kant added them rowed the term from Kant, without bothering, it
to his revisions for the second, 1793 edition. So must be said, very much about Kant’s intentions
why are they there? If we reread his comments in employing the term in the first place (Jonietz
with these terms mentally excised, the reference 2016). As a corrective, I have focused on the par-
to a “gilt frame” appears somewhat abruptly, un- ergon in two areas—its connection to the question
related to the examples that precede it. It seems of subject matter (the hierarchy of the genres) and
probable that Kant belatedly included “the bor- as ornament or pictorial embellishment. If this has
ders of paintings” to make his reference appear achieved its purpose, then the expanded parergon
more logically within his argument. Whatever the offers us the possibility of seeing a value beyond
reason these terms were added, the effect, as that of its relation to the frame or border, and one
surely Kant intended, was to associate ‘parerga” that informs on protocols and norms that form the
with ornament and ‘frame’ with decoration, both basis of art theory in both antiquity and the early
terms that fit into the historical definition of ‘par- modern period.
ergon’ as “ornamental addition, embellishment” Although relatively few in number, references
(Oxford English Dictionary 2018).8 to parerga in the history of art offer an insight
Kant’s gilt frame example aligns closely with into picture theory out of all proportion to the
a letter Nicolas Poussin sent from Rome to infrequency of the term’s appearance in the liter-
his patron Paul Fréart de Chantelou in April ature of art. There is no concept in current use
1639, informing him that he had dispatched that duplicates its frame of reference or offers
his painting, Israelites Gathering the Manna, to the potential for a better understanding of the
Paris unframed—a logical enough decision, as the way the genres are discussed, at least with respect
weight of the frame would have added to the ship- to the all-important early modern period. The so-
ping costs and risked damage to the fragile canvas. called “parts” of painting—including imitation,
Having dealt with these practical considerations, invention, expression, delight, decorum—all of
Poussin emphasizes the importance of a suitable which have something to add to our understanding
frame for the painting: “When you receive it, I of the parergon, assume their full importance only
beg of you, if you find it good, decorate it with when they are understood relationally the one to
a bit of a frame [un peu de corniche], because it the other, the “part” to the whole, in a manner
needs it in order that, considering [the painting] similar to the way the parergon is understood rela-
in all its parts, the rays of the eye are held in check tionally to the ergon.9 If this is the case, then a par-
. . . ” Then, in a caveat that anticipates Kant’s ref- ergon, which by definition must be understood in
erence to “a gilt frame” with astonishing preci- relation to the ergon, has an important role to play.
sion, Poussin adds a rider: “It would be much to One reason for this is the continued attention
the purpose if the aforementioned molding were paid to the Derridean parergon at the expense
simply gilded in matt gold, as it will blend harmo- of other, and in many cases, any other, under-
niously [très doucement] with the colors without standing of the term. This is not to advocate for a
clashing.” (1911, 20–21). Poussin does not use the revision of Derrida’s argument or to question of
term ‘parergon’ in this instance, but the precision the value of his conclusions (Duro 1996); rather,
with which he describes his preferred frame makes my attempt here is to open up the parergon
clear his aversion to the kind of frame Kant de- to a range of meanings and to connect them,
scribes as “decoration.” as far as possible, to their known instances of
historical usage. However, while I have for the
most part limited my discussion to examples
vi. conclusion where the term parergon/parerga has been
explicitly cited, it would be a mistake to assume
This article has attempted to look beyond the all- a broader understanding of parergon has no
consuming presence of Derrida’s “Parergon” es- place other than in these examples. The way
say in order to reveal the parergon’s historical forward is surely to see that a parergon is being
dimension—even if, as seems to be the case, art discussed even when it is not explicitly named.
32 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

At the same time, it is important to avoid a Grasskamp Anna. 2015. “Frames of Appropriation: Foreign Ar-
proliferation of the term where it has scant rele- tifacts on Display in Early Modern Europe and China.” In
Qing Enounters: Artistic Exchanges Between China and the
vance. We need to be guided by historical usage if West, edited by Petra Ten-Doesschate Chu and Ning Ding,
we are to avoid narrowing the parergon to a frame, 29–42. Los Angeles: Getty Research Institute.
on the one hand, or adding unwarranted examples Heidegger, Martin. 1993. “The Origin of the Work of Art,” In
Basic Writings from Being and Time (1927) to The Task of
with the otherwise laudable intention of associ-
Thinking (1964), edited by David Farrell Krell, 143–212. San
ating the term parergon with concepts that have Francisco: HarperCollins.
little of the parergonal to recommend them.10 Heller-Andrist, Simone. 2012. The Friction of the Frame: Der-
rida’s Parergon in Literature. Tübingen: Franke verlag.
Heuer, Christopher P. 2009. The City Rehearsed: Object, Archi-
PAUL DURO tecture, and Print in the Worlds of Hans Vredeman de Vries.
Department of Art History/Visual and Cultural Studies New York: Routledge.
University of Rochester Holt, Elizabeth Gilmore. 1958. Michelangelo and the Mannerists,
the Baroque and the Eighteenth Century. Vol. 2 of A Docu-
Rochester, New York 14627-0001 mentary History of Art. Garden City, New York: Doubleday.
Jonietz, Fabian. 2016. Review of Parergon: Attribut, Material
internet: paul.duro@rochester.edu und Fragment in der Bildästhetik des Quattrocento by Anna
Degler. Renaissance Quarterly 69: 1042–1044.
references Kant, Immanuel. 1960. Religion within the Limits of Reason
Alone. Translated by Theodore M. Greene and Hoyt H. Hud-
Alberti, Leon Battista. 1991. On Painting. Translated by Cecil son. New York: Harper.
Grayson, introduction and notes by Martin Kemp. London: . 2000. Critique of the Power of Judgment, edited by
Penguin. Paul Guyer. Translated by Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews.
Aristotle. 1987. The Poetics of Aristotle. Translation and com- Cambridge University Press.
mentary by Stephen Halliwell. University of North Carolina Lee, Rensselaer W. 1967. Ut Pictura Poesis: The Humanistic The-
Press. ory of Painting. New York: Norton.
Auden, W. H. 1991. Collected Poems, edited by Edward Mendel- Mérot, Alain, ed. 2003. Les Conferences de l’Académie royale
son. New York: Vintage International. de peinture et de sculpture au XVIIe siècle. Paris: ENSBA.
Bernstein, J. M. 1992. The Fate of Art: Aesthetic Alienation from 130–139.
Kant to Derrida and Adorno. Pennsylvania State University Nancy, Jean-Luc, and Federico Ferrari. 2014. Being Nude: The
Press. Skin of Images. Translated by Anne O’Byrne and Carlie An-
Blount, Thomas. 1656. Glossographia, or, A Dictionary . . . With glemire. Fordham University Press.
Etymologies, Definitions and Historical Observations on the Norgate, Edward. 1919. Miniatura or the Art of Limning, edited
Same. London: Humphrey Moseley and George Sawbridge. by Martin Hardie. Clarendon Press.
Cassell’s German-English English-German Dictionary. 1978. Owens, Craig. 1994. “From Work to Frame, or, Is There Life Af-
London: Cassell. ter ‘The Death of the Author’?” in Beyond Recognition: Rep-
Cassirer, Ernst. 1992. An Essay on Man: An Introduction to a resentation, Power, and Culture, edited by by Scott Bryson,
Philosophy of Human Culture. Yale University Press. Barbara Kruger, Lynne Tillman, and Jane Weinstock. Intro-
Degler, Anna. 2015. Parergon: Attribut, Material und Fragment duction by Simon Watney. University of California Press.
in der Bildästhetik des Quattrocento. Paderborn: Wilhelm 122–139.
Fink. Oxford English Dictionary. 2018. “parergon, n.” OED On-
De Piles, Roger. 1743. The Principles of Painting. London: line. Oxford University Press. http://www.oed.com/view/
J. Orborn. Entry/137856.
De Vigenère, Blaise. 1999. La Renaissance du regard: textes sur Paleotti, Gabriele. 2012. Discourse on Sacred and Profane Im-
l’art, edited by Richard Crescenzo. Paris: ENSBA. ages. Introduction by Paolo Prodi, translated by William Mc-
Derrida, Jacques. 1987. The Truth in Painting. Translated by Cuaig. Los Angeles: Getty Research Institute.
Geoff Bennington and Ian McLeod. University of Chicago Peacham, Henry. 1612. Graphice, or The Most Ancient and Ex-
Press. (First published in 1978 as La Vérité en peinture. Paris: cellent Art of Drawing and Limning. London: John Browne.
Flammarion.) Pliny the Elder. 1601. The Historie of the World, commonly called
Dubos, Jean-Baptiste. 1748. Critical Reflections on Poetry, Paint- the Naturall Historie of C. Plinius Secundus. 2 vols. Translated
ing and Music. Translated by Thomas Nugent. 3 vols. London: by Philemon Holland. London: Adam Islip.
John Nourse. Poussin, Nicolas. 1911. Correspondance de Nicolas Poussin,
Duro, Paul, ed. 1996. The Rhetoric of the Frame: Essays on the edited by Charles Jouanny. Paris: Jean Schemit.
Boundaries of the Artwork. Cambridge University Press. Puttfarken, Thomas. 2005. Titian and Tragic Painting: Aristotle’s
. 2005. “Giving Up on History? Challenges to the Hi- Poetics and the Rise of the Modern Artist. Yale University
erarchy of the Genres in Early Nineteenth-Century France.” Press.
Art History 28: 689–711. Sharpe, Matthew. 2016. “In the Margins of Philosophy;
Galen. 1968. On the Usefulness of the Parts of the Body. Trans- Plato to Footnotes.” The Conversation. August 13. https://
lation and introduction by Margaret Tallmadge May. 2 vols. theconversation.com/in-the-margins-of-philosophy-plato-
Cornell University Press. to-footnotes-63918.
Gilpin, William. 1792. Three Essays on the Picturesque. London: Strabo. 1857. The Geography of Strabo. 3 vols. Translated by
R. Blamire. H. C. Hamilton and W. Falconer. London: G. Bohn.
Gombrich, E. H. 1966. “The Renaissance Theory of Art and the Winckelmann, Johann Joachim. 1850. The History of Ancient Art
Rise of Landscape.” In Norm and Form: Studies in the Art of Among the Greeks. Translated by G. Henry Lodge. London:
the Renaissance, Vol. I, 107–121. London: Phaidon. John Chapman.
Duro What Is a Parergon? 33

Wood, Christopher S. 2014 (1993). Albrecht Altdorfer and the section §13, “The pure judgment of taste is inde-
Origins of Landscape. London: Reaktion Books. pendent from charm and emotion” (Kant 2000, 107).
8. A similar point may be made about the inclusion
1. An early version of Derrida’s essay “Parergon” ap- of ‘parerga.’ Kant had used the term in his treatise Reli-
peared in the journal Digraphe 3 and 4 in 1974. gion within the Limits of Reason Alone, published, like the
2. Winckelmann is a little wayward with his analysis. It second edition of the Third Critique, in 1793, to describe
is not a question of whether the “principal figure” is beauti- four “General Observations” appended to the treatise “as
ful or not. The perceived inferiority of the accessory comes it were, parerga to religion within the limits of pure rea-
not from any weakness in the representation, but from its son; they do not belong within it but border upon it” (1960,
subordinate status with respect to the principal subject. 47–48). It is ironic that its inclusion in the Third Critique,
3. There is an informative discussion of “”Metal purely as a clarification of ‘ornament,’ has been mistak-
Mounts as Parerga” in Grasskamp (2015, 29–32). I regret enly paired with ‘border of paintings,’ thereby misrepre-
I discovered this source too late to integrate it into my senting Kant’s intention. For further discussion of the im-
argument. plications of the way Derrida deploys Kant’s terminology
4. For comment on Derrida’s use of liminality as an in- to the advantage of his argument, see Heller-Andrist (2010,
tellectual tool, see Sharpe (2016). The expression “symbolic esp. 26–41).
form” is Cassirer’s, who offers his most accessible discussion 9. The classic study of the humanistic theory of painting
of the concept (1992, 23–26 and 137–170). remains Lee (1967). De Piles’s The Principles of Painting
5. From the first line of the original French edition of (1743) carries on its title page a similar, if more extensive,
The Truth in Painting, the text asserts the primacy of the list of the “parts” of painting.
frame: “Let’s say, to hold fast to the frame, to the limit, 10. ‘Attribute’ is a case in point. The lunar diadem of
I write here four times around painting” (Derrida, 1987, Diana, Saint Catherine’s wheel, Zeus’s thunderbolt, are at-
3; my translation). Simone Heller-Andrist has noted how tributes, not parerga—visual signs that identify their sub-
Derrida insinuates the language of quadrilateralism into the jects. Fragment and detail are also problematic for the same
structure of his argument, from “framed” and “squared up” reason. Degler (2015) includes both attribute and frag-
to “[the parergon] is no longer merely around the work” ment in the title of her study of parerga in Quattrocento
(Heller-Andrist 2012, 30; Derrida 1987, 55, 60, 9). painting.
6. The Guyer and Matthews translation of Kant’s Third I would like to thank my spring 2018 “Rhetoric of
Critique, cited here (2000), renders “Einfassungen der the Frame” graduate class at the University of Rochester
Gemälde” as ‘the borders of paintings’ and not as ‘picture for their support. At a time when they had every right
frames’ as in many earlier translations. The difference may to expect me to devote my pedagogical energies to their
seem trivial; it is not. If Kant had intended to instance a concerns, they generously encouraged me to rehearse
picture frame, he would have used the appropriate term: the argument presented in this article until it began to
Bilderrahmen—but ‘borders of paintings,’ while undoubt- make sense. To Rachel Crawford, Erin Francisco, Tristan
edly encompassing picture frames, is much broader. So Menzies, Yasin Nasirov, Michael Ormsbee, Jacob Ruta,
to claim, as Derrida does, that Kant answers his question Katherine Soules, and Nathan Tosh: Thank you, all—
“What is a frame?” by saying: “it’s a parergon,” is to double you were the best. In addition, I would also like to ac-
down on his misrepresentation of Kant’s example by con- knowledge, with thanks, the enormously helpful anony-
fining it to a narrow interpretation of parergon as ‘frame’ mous readers’ reports. They, together with stern advice
(Derrida 1987, 63). from the journal’s editors, greatly helped me to under-
7. The argument for which these examples serve as stand what needed to be done to ready this article for
markers appears most clearly in the title of the preceding publication.

Potrebbero piacerti anche