Sei sulla pagina 1di 19

Angelaki

Journal of the Theoretical Humanities

ISSN: 0969-725X (Print) 1469-2899 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cang20

INFINITE GRIEF

James A. Godley

To cite this article: James A. Godley (2018) INFINITE GRIEF, Angelaki, 23:6, 93-110, DOI:
10.1080/0969725X.2018.1546994

To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2018.1546994

Published online: 05 Dec 2018.

Submit your article to this journal

View Crossmark data

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at


http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=cang20
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 23 number 6 december 2018

Jarovit by Zuzana Ridzoň ová.


james a. godley
He had made it his: that long line, of which
we knew only Mama and Daddy. And he
was giving it back, as everything must be
INFINITE GRIEF
given back, so that, passing through death, freud, hegel, and lacan on
it can live forever.
James Baldwin, “Sonny’s Blues”1 the thought of death
a beloved abstraction
veryone knows the event of a loved one’s while ostensibly being rooted in such questions,
E death can change the mourner’s fundamen-
tal convictions about reality, their basic outlook
end up multiplying the terms of the problem to
the point where the initial inquiry has become
or Weltanschauung, but why this is the case is obscured.
not easy to account for. We ask ourselves how On one side are matters of the corpse – that
the remembered life of that person affects the is, the finite individuality, localizable (if non-
still living, how it makes a difference and locatable) within infinitesimal circles of histori-
changes the given, but it is hard to know cal, cultural, familial networks of signification.
whether such ideas really come from the truth Then there is what is sometimes called the “dia-
of our dead, or if they are just an extension of lectics of mourning” that concern larger scale
ourselves. Theoretical treatments of such frameworks like ideology or metaphysics, and
issues, faced with a quandary that quickly whose implication is probably best described
becomes overwhelming, tend to cleave to one as one of critique.2 Mourning here has more to
side or another of an interdisciplinary do with abstract loss: structures or orientations
approach – historical, anthropological, socio- that assume loss in some way, “take it up,” even
logical, psychoanalytic, philosophical – that, “work through” it. Such directions can seem
ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/18/060093-18 © 2018 Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis
Group
https://doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2018.1546994

93
infinite grief

exciting and give us consolatory hope even in of inspiring others to do so as well. At best,
their statement, for to be able to “work the dead are our monuments and examples.
through” a loss implies a passage that, if it We look to them to know what to repeat.
does not leave death behind exactly, at least But there can also be monstrous implications.
allows us to build a road around it or, To see the death of a loved one as an opportunity
perhaps, a bridge over it. It implies that the dis- for advancement, even if that means a moral
aster of the other’s non-existence need not entail improvement or an overture to a new way of
their end as such and can, in effect, lead to thinking, can smack of a frightful disrespect.
something new. Such a promise, supported by Thus, in “Mourning and Melancholia” (1914)
a simple narrative telos – for example, the “pro- when Freud regards as proper and normal the
gress” from hopelessness to triumph – is reiter- survivor’s desire for detachment (Lösung)
ated through centuries of consolatory literature, from the loving bonds of the deceased in order
from Boethius and Bunyan to modern-day to clear the way for the libido to eventually
guides for grievers. But can the death of reinvest in a new object,3 it can remind us of
someone really provide an adequate object of unfeeling pragmatic calculations, economic
“work” – psychical, intellectual, or otherwise? investments, the conversion of loss into profit.
To put it more pointedly, can the theoretical At its worst, it implies faithlessness to the
work of making mourning into an object of dead and the exploitation of grief, turning the
thought, of turning the experience of grief into occasion of mourning – one’s own or others’ –
a general concept (as in the passage of Erriner- into a narcissistic resource to be utilized for
ung into Gedächtnis) offer any hope of “over- private gain.4
coming” the anguish of loss? Along these lines, Tammy Clewell in her
There appears to be a tacit ethical proposition influential essay “Mourning beyond Melancho-
implied in these considerations, which we would lia” criticizes the early Freudian conception of
do well to investigate at its extremities. Let us grief-work (Trauerarbeit) as “self-serving [ … ]
consider the implications – the noblest and the less a lament for the passing of a unique other,
most monstrous – of proposing that mourning and more a process geared toward restoring a
could be the means of adopting a new concep- certain economy of the subject.”5 Emphasizing
tual orientation. At the noble end, if what theor- the fact that during the years Freud wrote his
ists hope is true and the work of mourning can principal essays on mourning he devoted much
accomplish what it proposes, then it offers a of his attention to the economics of narcissism,
praxis that not only will console us for our loss Clewell argues that Freud’s view of the experi-
but can even change the way we are disposed ence of grief was myopically focused on issues
toward death, hence change the way we live. If of self-preservation rather than the ethics of
the other’s loss brings me to face the remainder remembrance. “Mourning and Melancholia,”
of my finite existence, as well as to pay better the fifth of the extant metapsychological
attention to the way others confront theirs, essays, mainly discusses mourning in compari-
then the ethics of the singular can readily be son with his clinical observations of melancholia
seen to intersect with the politics of the univer- as a disturbance of “self-regarding feelings” that
sal. So when I think about how best to honor the also, paradoxically, featured a sharp reduction of
dead or how to deal with the pain her death (and libido directed toward others. Like melancholia,
life) have caused (recognizing that this is the mourning featured the withdrawal of libido but
way to honor her) then I am likewise reflecting not to the extent of disturbing self-regard, as in
on how best to elevate life, how best to live, the pathological condition. Given this clue,
and thus to honor the life of the loved one Freud was able to discover important differences
through championing what she leaves behind. in the way the two conditions identified with the
The vicissitudes of mourning can make me lost object. For example, whereas the mourner
feel the pull of truths that lead me toward a ends up asserting distance relative to the
more ethical life and thereby of finding ways object, letting it be in its estrangement, the

94
godley

melancholic identifies with the lost object, also know we shall remain inconsolable and
reeling it into the self where it gets jumbled.6 will never find a substitute. No matter what
Although Clewell’s main concern is to uphold may fill the gap, even if it be filled comple-
the irreplaceability of the deceased, the “self- tely, it nevertheless remains something else.
serving” implication of her criticism is thickly And actually this is how it should be. It is
the only way of perpetuating that love
entwined with Freud’s theoretical focus on nar-
which we do not want to relinquish.8
cissism as such, leading her to downplay the
differences between the two states in order to Many have taken this personal letter as indica-
hone in on their similarity. By focusing on the tive of a turning point in Freud’s ethics,
economic management of the survivor’s pain, almost a private mea culpa of his earlier theor-
Freud’s theory appeared to regard constant etical stance. Here, rather than to choose the
devotion to the dead as pathological. By exten- path of forcing oneself to look for something
sion, Clewell argues that this position made to fill the “gap,” he seems resolved to an
him complicit in “a longstanding epistemologi- ethics of dedication and faithfulness to the
cal and cultural tradition in which the subject dead, even if it means remaining inconsolable
acquires legitimacy at the expense of the for the rest of his life. A term like the “lost
other’s separateness.”7 object” to which Freud’s theory of mourning
In my view, mourning in early Freud is more is regularly referred, doesn’t quite capture the
attuned to the other’s separateness than Clewell poignancy of what it means when Freud
allows, but the advantage of her rebuke is that it speaks of his daughter this way. In both extre-
allows us to see the threat implied by the “legit- mely personal and highly abstract terms,
imation” of a theory when given occasion to Freud is indicating what the “object” of mourn-
exert itself against who or what cannot ing is for him – a gap, a hollow of agony that
respond. This is in part why speculation in its never goes away. The difficult implication is
equivocal guises is regarded with such distrust. not that he can’t forget his daughter, but that
Under the conditions of global capitalism, the pain of her loss is unworkable; the loss of
theoretical speculation continues to be attached the loved one is here an immitigable wound
to the same suspicions attendant upon its not-so- that at best can only be temporarily forgotten
distant metaphor, economic reification. Could and at worst means he would retroactively
this be the case with Freudian Trauerarbeit as cancel (“relinquish”) his love for the sake of
well? Is the theory of working through a loss future opportunities.
already to reify the dead, exploiting their If such a declaration is understandable for a
memory for the survivor’s emotional gain? If father, it’s perhaps harder to accept such a
so, then the “detachment” (Lösung) from the bleak conclusion from the father of a thera-
lost object could only mean infidelity and peutic practice. It is tempting to revert back
betrayal; an occasion, moreover, for the distor- to the earlier, “self-serving” model – better to
tion of facts, memories, archives. Such a let go and move on than give up on the good
threat seems tantamount to erasure. It would work of consolation. Or should we take
be to commit the dead to absolute non-existence Freud’s confiding statement to his friend to
– to stop up their transmission. mean that he thinks mourning continues indefi-
Perhaps such a horror occurred to Freud nitely, a “work” that goes on forever, like an
when, late in his career, thinking of the death infinite task? Laplanche sounds a word of
of his daughter Sophie, he admitted to his caution here that only deepens the quandary:
friend Ludwig Binswanger (who had lost a the “seal of authenticity that marks Freud’s
son) that he needed to rethink his earlier pos- ‘necrological notes’ or ‘condolence’ letters
ition about the resolution of mourning: reflects only the pursuit of a self-analysis
which was never abandoned.”9 Troublingly,
Although we know that after such a loss the this would make mourning indistinguishable
acute state of mourning will subside, we from (interminable) analysis, where both one

95
infinite grief

and the other amount to the auscultation of the luxury of disbelieving, though we may well
“gap” that holds the place of death and necess- deny many of its effects. Here, on the contrary
arily fails to get anywhere. It appears, in other to what might be supposed from the quote
words, that in Freud, the work of mourning, above, there are unconscious beliefs about
however this is meant – whether productive or death, if by this we mean thought-constructions
endless, whether its focus is the other or the that are taken to have truth value but that are
self that auto-analyzes – presupposes an object derived secondhand, as it were, from experi-
that is non-finite. ences of loss. Through mourning, our speculat-
This idea only really makes sense when we ive thoughts of death, including mortality and
recall Freud’s materialist insistence that there immortality, are given a highly refined concate-
is no unconscious belief in death. This is nation. In Totem and Taboo, Freud even goes
stated most famously in “Thoughts for the so far as to propose that “man’s first theoretical
Times on War and Death”: achievement – the creation of spirits” arose in
response to the necessity to make sense of the
It is impossible to imagine our own death; death of another.12 The incipit of theory, its
and whenever we attempt to do so we can per- inaugural gesture, is mourning. Granted that
ceive that we are in fact still present as spec- this is not a syllogism; there is a subduction
tators. Hence, the psychoanalytic school
here that is not entirely clear. Why wouldn’t
could venture on the assertion that at
the intellectual awareness of finitude suffice as
bottom no one believes in his own death,
or, to put the same thing another way, that origin of reflection? What special process does
in the unconscious every one of us is con- the emotional reality of death involve that
vinced of his own immortality.10 forces this leap to theory?
One famous line from “Mourning and Mel-
This assertion, which continues to scandalize ancholia” serves to orient these speculative
philosophers, is not so much to say that death implications: “Mourning is regularly the reac-
is refused or denied as that it is literally tion to the loss of a loved person, or to the
unthinkable as such. The emphasis therefore loss of some abstraction which has taken the
is less on the naive disavowal of the facticity of place of one, such as one’s country, liberty, an
mortality as on identifying the limits of reflec- ideal, and so on.”13 There are three remarkable
tive consciousness. Simply knowing that death things about this sentence. First, mourning here
is or that we are finite changes nothing for us does not react to death as such but the “loss of a
because we do not have an experience that loved person” (Verlust einer geliebten Person).
would refer to it. Rather, all that the belief in Despite its simplistic phrasing, this already
finitude can evoke is precisely what death implies an intersubjective dialectic: a loved
would mean for consciousness, wherewith a person, beloved, is loved by a lover. In losing
limit is exposed that is precisely the limits of the beloved, the mourner is without that
the thinking being. Such a confrontation, in which made him what he was (viz. the lover of
effect, is often one of the principal fears of this beloved).14 Consequently, he becomes
obsessional neurotics, where loss of conscious- other to himself, whether by remaining
ness equates to death. If the unconscious holds devoted – continuing to love what is no longer
no belief for finitude, then, it nonetheless can existent, or by letting go and moving on,
provide a sense of the kind of death the loss of thereby ceasing to be the lover. In any event,
belief in the omnipotence of consciousness sig- this “loved person” stands for the difference
nifies (i.e., the threat of castration).11 the Other’s inexistence makes. Recognition
The corollary to the non-belief in finitude, so founders upon misrecognition in this “loved
often misunderstood, is that there is nonetheless person” – now that she no longer exists, the
a very palpable experience of death that most of beloved remains as an abstraction. I cannot
us have, which is the death of a loved one. Such be sure that this abstraction is the same as she
an experience is not something we have the whom I loved. What is remarkable here to the

96
godley

point that it almost seems to resound with the tenable, whereupon it takes up residence in
most crushing cynicism is the idea that what the personality of the survivor as a spectral
we loved in another might only be a semblance. inhabitation.
Is that all she ever was? In fine, condensed into Freud’s definition, is
The second thing to notice is that this the theory that mourning is regularly the reac-
abstraction – the beloved that is missing – is tion to the sense of loss that afflicts us when
nonetheless a privileged abstraction that we realize that a certain belief has been
resists any equivalence with other ideas that negated in its existence and is no longer
are also marked with loss, even as it connects tenable – when the place of the beloved has
to them. This is because the abstraction sticks lost the validity of that abstraction that keeps
in the “place” (Stelle) of loss. Strictly speaking, her attached to a continued existence. In mourn-
this place can be occupied by anything that a ing, it is this singular thought-construction
subject values in a highly intensive (“libidinal”) (inclusive of memories and fantasies of the
manner: a nation, a concept, even life itself, pro- dead) whose sacrifice appears to be at stake in
vided that it is an abstraction that, as Freud the perishing of the body of the beloved
says, stands for the loss of a loved person. In person, because it is a belief that appears imper-
other words, it must signify the truth of that iled by negation. Hence, the agony of the melan-
loss. We could say, then, that what is at stake cholic mourner would be that invalidating that
is the truth-value of a belief, a word whose abstraction is too much, a greater loss than it’s
English etymology, derived from German, feli- worth, so it’s preferable to try and hold on to
citously gives us the combination “be” and an untenable belief rather than to submit to
“leif” – beloved or dear; literally, “be-loved.”15 the necessity demanded in the name of finitude.
Such a “beloved belief” is what grounds and However, if the perishing of the abstract belief
gives ultimate shape to an abstraction of a that keeps the other “alive” is possible, so too
complex human relationship, the condensation is it possible to conceive of finitude itself as a
of innumerably various lived experiences in specific thought-construction, a determinate
metonymically reduced form.16 What this tells negation that is not the “final word” but pre-
us is that if our beloveds can be reduced to cisely a thought of death that is itself subject
abstractions, so can our beliefs be loved as to the possibility of being negated. Whereupon
flesh-and-blood lovers. Here, cynicism is the enigmatic place of the beloved, like the
turned on its head and becomes dewy-eyed “gap” that opens up within Freud following
idealism: beliefs matter. Even the cynicism of the death of his daughter Sophie, bears
the cynic takes the place of a beloved. witness to the persistence of a love that passes
Finally, what makes belief matter, or at least beyond death. In this way, the love at issue in
what allows us to recognize how much it matters mourning stages an encounter with infinitude.
to us, is what we feel when this place of belief
has been vacated through death. Mourning is a
“reaction” to a loss that reveals that the subjec-
paradoxes of transience
tive truth-effect of the beloved belief is defined In the midst of World War I, Freud wrote the
strictly in consequence of its having been essays that defined his speculative approach to
negated. In other words, death provokes a the question of death and mourning, among
response that tests whether a belief can remain which was “On Transience.”18 Wandering the
what William James would call a “living hypoth- countryside with two literary companions
esis” – a proposition that elicits the emotionality (most likely Rainier Maria Rilke and Lou
of conviction – after it is countermanded by the Andreas Salome), Freud enthuses about the
“command of reality,” which is to say, the law of beauty of the mountains and trees, while his
finitude.17 Either the belief must be abandoned companions find no joy in the pastoral scene.19
so that something else may take its place, or it is One of them, a celebrated poet (Rilke, prob-
held to despite the fact that it is no longer ably), says that though he admires the sights,

97
infinite grief

he is disturbed that all the beauty they behold is impossible perspective of non-perspective. Like-
only fated for extinction. Disputatious of his wise, the mournful reaction to the passing away
friend’s vanitas, Freud finds that he does not of all things presupposes an unchanging stand-
share his friend’s thought of death. Instead, he point, as of some uniquely transcendent “seer”
considers that they might be experiencing “a who was capable of penetrating an ultimate
foretaste of mourning over decease,” wherein meaning beyond the shifting surfaces of experi-
the threat of impending loss intrudes, casting ence and passing judgment. On the other hand,
a pall upon the spectacle’s transience rather when we appreciate the beauty of transient
than elevating its beauty.20 things we are enjoying something that surpasses
To account for the aesthetic he wishes to the boundedness of finite duration, the miracle
defend, Freud proposes an economic formula: of desire’s insistence. As we are taken up in
“Transience value is scarcity value in time. the flux of time, what we take to be most
Limitation in the possibility of an enjoyment worthy of love is carried within us and may
raises the value of the enjoyment.”21 At first, well survive our deaths.
such a formulation, which sounds like the “scar- Not without a trace of bathos, Freud notices
city principle” in economics, might suggest that his entreaties have had little effect upon
merely that a thing’s worth is determined by his friends. The poignancy of transience seems
the exclusivity by which it is separated from to him to have been misrecognized, as one
the circulation of goods. By its rarefication, it might say of a gloomy companion that “the
is more “special,” like an exclusive commodity. moment is wasted on him.” Nor can Freud con-
But this would be to incorrectly place it within vince himself that his own point of view is incor-
the same logic of finitude that Freud wants to rect – after all, like everyone, he is perfectly
criticize, treating time as though it were an aware of finitude, but that does not prevent
arbiter of judgment. By extension, we would him from feeling joy when he contemplates
be led to infer that the capacity to enjoy any- the countryside’s transience. Dismayed, he
thing is likewise limited by time, as in advertise- senses that some obstacle prevents him from
ments that shriek, “Enjoy NOW while supplies sharing the same thought of death with his
last!” Once the rush to “seize the moment” sub- friends so that they can bond over this shared
sides, the enjoyment dissipates as well. feeling. Freud is moved to speculate upon the
But the drift of Freud’s logic goes in a decid- economic riddle of mourning:
edly different direction: an object’s “transience
We possess, as it seems, a certain amount of
value” is its subjective significance not as a
capacity for love – what we call libido –
limited, exclusive thing that can be consumed
which in the earliest stages of development
or used up within the span of a certain duration is directed towards our own ego. Later,
but something enjoyed for its own sake without though still at a very early time, this libido
diminishment in the quality of that enjoyment: is diverted from the ego on to objects,
“since the value of all this beauty and perfection which are thus in a sense taken into our
is determined only by its significance for our ego. If the objects are destroyed or if they
own emotional lives, it has no need to survive are lost to us, our capacity for love (our
us and is therefore independent of absolute dur- libido) is once more liberated; and it can
ation.”22 Immersed in time we are; but it is not then either take other objects instead or can
because of time that we enjoy, nor is Freud temporarily return to the ego. But why it is
that this detachment of libido from its
saying that temporal finitude is the condition
objects should be such a painful process is a
for our enjoyment. Such would erroneously
mystery to us and we have not hitherto
attribute the quality of a condemning judgment been able to frame any hypothesis to
to time, making it into a subject-supposed-to- account for it. We only see that libido
judge. The point is comparable to the reason clings to its objects and will not renounce
Freud gave for why we cannot imagine our those that are lost even when a substitute
own death: the attempt to do so assumes an lies ready to hand. Such then is mourning.23

98
godley

There is a troubling ambiguity in this formu- theory of mourning that we see it confronted
lation that threatens to contradict Freud’s explicitly as a problem that squares a certain
earlier point that the capacity to enjoy is not abstract love (or beloved) with death via the
limited by duration. Freud’s hypothesis of tran- logic of finitude. As it happens, it was also a
sience, consistent with his economic theory of problem that Hegel struggled to clarify.
the pleasure principle, depends upon the idea
that libido is simultaneously quantitatively
limited (different in intensity), and qualitatively infinite grief
unrestricted (plastic in its choice of object). Of In his 1820s lectures on aesthetics, Hegel uses
course, Freud does not quantify the libido the phrase “infinite grief” (unendlichen
because of any assumed substantialism (hence Schmerz) to describe the image of Christ’s cruci-
it is not a measurable quantity of libido like fixion in Romantic art as an allegorical significa-
200 ml), but as an abstract comparative quantity tion. For Hegel, Christ’s life and death
that can differentiate the degree of relative dramatize the realization of absolute subjectiv-
attachment to certain objects. But at the same ity, which is not immediately given to it, but
time, the objects to which the libido becomes accomplished through subjective destitution,
attached are themselves understood as tem- “the elevation of the spirit out of the finitude
porally limited, but in a way that does not of its immediate existence into its truth.”25
affect the quantity of libido. In other words, But before this elevation takes place, the
time (hence, finitude) is not a condition of subject must first “detach[ … ] itself from
attachment but of the object. A quantity of itself” in a “self-diremption” or splitting,
libido may be bound or liberated from its whereby infinity is at first opposed to it as the
objects but none of the vicissitudes that affect image of an Ideal to which it strives to overcome
the object affect the quantity of libido. It is itself as finite and merely natural, a “process in
not only an abstract but a fixed quantity. the course of which a struggle and a battle
When it is a question of loss, the libido does arises, and grief, death, the mournful sense of
not lose anything of itself. What is lost, what nullity, the torment of spirit and body enter as
death destroys, is only the object, which is an essential feature.”26
finite, not the capacity for love, which is Traditionally, this Romantic agony is read as
unbounded or in-finite. And despite the fact a purifying episode whereby the life of the indi-
that this capacity is defined quantitatively, its vidual bestial man with all its carnal pleasures,
fixity as such, its imperviousness to any funda- lust, etc. is ascetically forsaken in favor of the
mental alteration or loss in number, means it sanctification of spirit. But Hegel describes
is insusceptible to mortality. this moment as an “infinite grief” for a good
Thus there is something that doesn’t quite reason – because what is at stake is a process
add up that leads to the strange situation that where subjectivity treats itself as an object and
the libido in Freud’s account is unlimited or kills off its finitude:
in-finite because it is determinately fixed as
finite. It is this finite quantification of the poten- For just as God first cuts himself off from
tial for love, in other words, that conditions finite reality, so finite man, who begins of
Freud’s notion of death as determinative of himself outside the Kingdom of God,
the object’s “transience value.” Paradoxically, acquires the task of elevating himself to
God, detaching himself from the finite, abol-
libido is finitely infinite. The theory of mourn-
ishing its nullity, and through this killing of
ing suffers from this ambiguity, and echoes of
his immediate reality becoming what God
this theoretical problematic also haunt Freud’s in his appearance as man has made objective
later formulations of the infamous economic as true reality. The infinite grief of this sacri-
paradoxes of the death drive and the problem fice of subjectivity’s very heart, as well as suf-
of interminable analysis (as the notorious fering and death, which were more or less
“quantitative problem”).24 But it is in the excluded from the representations of classical

99
infinite grief

art or rather appeared there as mere natural and its aftermath in the Protestant culture of
suffering, acquire their real necessity only sentimentality. Kant’s philosophy, he argued,
in romantic art.27 had succeeded in dispelling the Enlighten-
ment’s spurious ideas about God only to estab-
To kill off one’s finitude in this sense is not just lish new spurious ideas about the thinking
to die, but to commit something to death: here it subject. That is, in the interest of Enlighten-
is God that dies in the guise of man. In the image ment’s project to place Man at the center of
of crucifixion such as we might find in, say, Car- the universe formerly occupied by God, Kant
avaggio or Peter Paul Rubens what Hegel finds had formalized the reflective subject through
is the vanishing point of spirituality, as in the transcendental categories, and thereby
Christ’s cry “My God, My God, why have You demonstrated the infinite capacity of thought,
forsaken me?” – a moment of nihilism or “the purity and infinity of the negative” that
radical atheism wherein God abandons himself exceeds the positive form of experience.29 But
and ceases to believe that he himself exists.28 in so doing he also ended up replacing the “dog-
But this destruction of the finite subjectivity is matism of being” with the “dogmatism of think-
a passage at the same time that it is a nullity. ing”: by positing the transcendental form of the
If Hegel were using this language just to describe “I” Kant effectively psychologized the infinite,
the harrowing of Christ’s torment unto death, he thus tainting reason with finitude and dooming
would not be telling us anything particularly it to passing away.30 Moreover, this did not
new. But by thinking of it as a description of really do away with God but only elevated him
mourning, we see something markedly different. into an even higher station, beyond the limits
Here, Christ’s accomplished Resurrection of finite cognition. We see this most explicitly
weirdly means he has endured his own finitude in Religion within the Boundaries of Mere
as a loss that he retrospectively mourns. When Reason, where Kant notoriously leaves some
Christ dies, his “infinite grief” corresponds not of the most irrational elements of the religious
just to his death as mortal but to the death of imaginary very much intact on the margins of
the possibility of the infinite as a higher exist- reason. Here, in what he calls the parergon (a
ence. Needless to say, there is something enig- supplemental note or aside) can be found
matic about what it could mean to “grieve” works of grace, miracles, mysteries, and means
existence as such. At stake is a distinction that of grace as phenomena in which only an act of
appears to confound any empirical comprehen- strictly blind faith can be spoken of.31 Kant
sion no less than a reflective or transcendentalist had preserved these religious experiences as
approach. How to reconcile mourning with the unknowable and inconceivable “beyonds” of
thought of reflective finitude, without erasing the limits of rational faith, but Hegel’s point is
the former with the melancholy of the latter? precisely that by granting such free reign to a
The answer for Hegel is that it is not an strictly inconceivable set of impossible possibili-
either/or. When regarded as a moment within ties he had kept them alive precisely as sacred
the process of mourning, death itself changes beliefs about finitude.
and ceases to be the mere abstract belief in fini- In this way, Kant’s philosophy paralleled the
tude. The qualification of the subject’s grief as historical development of the Protestant culture
infinite in “infinite grief” therefore needs to be of sentimentality in which God now had to be
taken literally: there are good reasons why it conceived strictly in the form of the inconceiva-
should be both an infinite “grief,” that is, an ble, thus forcing religious desire onto the
endless or impossible mourning, and an “infi- avenue of sublime feeling and the artistic
nite” grief, a mourning of the infinite. forms of the ineffable, as in Romantic art.
In his early essay Faith and Knowledge With God thus removed into an unknown and
(1802), “infinite grief” appears in a more expli- unknowable beyond, He nonetheless lurked in
citly diagnostic sense to criticize a kind of mel- the void of the empty heaven the subject fills
ancholia that developed in the Enlightenment with fruitless longing. The problem is that if

100
godley

the thinking being meets its absolute negation purely as a moment of the supreme Idea,
in physical death, a certain subjective vanity and no more than a moment. Formerly, the
arises, such that one may legitimately wonder infinite grief only existed historically in the
what point there is in attempting to find a way formative process of culture. It existed as
of thinking beyond this limit if the mortal the feeling that “God Himself is dead,”
upon which the religion of more recent
limit of finitude is the limit of all possible
times rests; the same feeling that Pascal
thought for this being that thinks. But for this expressed in so to speak sheerly empirical
same reason it limited knowledge only to the form: “Nature is such that it signifies every-
finite and restored eternity as an empty ideal where a lost God both within and outside
point to which knowledge could only attempt man.” By marking this feeling as a moment
to make a Sisyphus-like journey: an infinite pro- of the supreme Idea, the pure concept must
gress that, as Hegel never tired of pointing out, give philosophical existence to what used to
amounts to a spurious progress since there is no be either the moral precept that we must
possibility of movement but an absolute fixity. sacrifice the empirical being, or the concept
Hegel returned to a similar argument in The of formal abstraction [i.e., the categorical
Science of Logic when discussing “the most imperative]. Thereby it must re-establish
for philosophy the Idea of absolute freedom
obstinate of the categories of the understand-
and along with it the absolute Passion, the
ing,” the logic of abstract finitude: “The deter- speculative Good Friday in place of the his-
mination of finite things does not go past their toric Good Friday.34
end. The understanding persists in this sorrow
of finitude, for it makes nonbeing the determi- Like the analogous moment in Christ’s Passion,
nation of things and, at the same time, this non- insoluble despair gives way to the resolve of
being imperishable and absolute.”32 The mourning: upon realizing that transcendence is
subject of finitude supports the illusory idea impossible, the subject is at first paralyzed
that life is geared toward a teleology of loss: with despair, but by marking infinite grief as a
the ideal point of death casts its shadow over “feeling” that has already occurred, the
all of life, as if everything that comes before subject historicizes it and in the process realizes
the end is just an anticipatory foretaste of a that he has already moved on. Hence, a truer
final (anti)climax. apprehension of the absolute, in Hegel’s sense,
The victory of the Enlightenment sealed by would realize itself as the inaugural point of a
Kant’s transcendental subject had thereby passage from the “historic Good Friday” of nihi-
resulted in the defeat of the subject by the over- listic despair to the “speculative Good Friday”
whelming pressure of time as an ever-impending that would recapture the speculative Idea as
death. But this flawed notion of finitude had absolute – that is, not just as an abstract
merely held infinity in place, instead of letting formal freedom like Kant’s categorical impera-
it “directly somersault into the positivity of tive or as the “moral precept” that we should
the absolute Idea.”33 In other words, the infinite conceive of our existence as an enforced martyr-
had to cease to be a fixity and become other to dom or moral masochism, but as the inherited
itself in the flux of time. The fixity or fixation truth of a previous form of existence.
of the (infinitely) finite had to pass into a Only once the emotional and intellectual
newly secularized infinity. It is this element of dimension of absolute negativity is articulated
passage – that is, the full avowal of transience and affirmed can mourning’s confrontation
– that Hegel emphasizes in his conclusion to with the infinite effectively get underway.
Faith and Knowledge as the traversal of the Having survived the Other’s death, the subject
despair of infinite grief: becomes aware of what it signifies. Pascal’s
quote here is felicitous: “Nature is such that it
But the pure concept or infinity as the abyss signifies everywhere a lost God both within
of nothingness in which all being is engulfed, and outside man.” The psychoanalytic theory
must signify the infinite grief [of the finite] of mourning could not put it more directly:

101
infinite grief

the event of death reduces the Other to a lost prospective death to give us an idea of what mor-
object (objet petit a), such that the symbolic tality signifies for life; now the only thought of
order reflects the cataclysm of this loss just as death that has any real weight leads us to the
the subject also feels it as a loss within past, or, more precisely to signifiers (which are
himself. The “death of God” in this sense is historical by definition). Most of our fears and
translated directly into signifiers of loss, that hopes about the final instant of life is thereby
is to say, precisely “signifiers that are subject a displacement from a catastrophe that has
to other signifiers.” Bypassing Nietzsche and already happened. In what remains perhaps
Freud, Hegel anticipates Lacan: the death of the clearest literary presentation of this
God is less a fable of paternal law, guilt and cas- paradox we are like Gatsby, believing in the
tration but the triumph of the signifier over “orgiastic future that year by year recedes
finitude. Death itself changes its meaning, its before us,” while in fact we “beat on, boats
reality emerges as the “place” of the lost against the current, borne back ceaselessly into
object whose existence can only be given the past.”37
through signifiers that mark or commemorate According to Lacan, the thought of “death”
the traces of that loss. When the death of God in Freud’s death drive was a genuine novelty,
is apprehended and lamented, it occurs as a the latter’s own “creationist sublimation.”38
moment that passes, the same as the death of a This does not just mean that Freud came up
loved one. Thereby the signifier makes death with a new idea of death, but that death, con-
into a passage through which the subject is radi- sidered psychoanalytically, is a satisfaction
cally transformed. Everything in the world – that takes sublimated form. This is the defi-
that is, the world of signifiers – everywhere sig- nition of sublimation for Freud, as Joan
nifies a lost God that is also lost to itself, a God Copjec puts it: “the satisfaction of the drive
that has undergone infinite grief, leaving in its through the inhibition of its aim.”39 That is,
wake the acute vulnerability of the subject the drive pushes on toward satisfaction only to
bereft of its transcendent illusions. In its place continually reinvent a detour. Keeping in
is a speculative inheritance – the Absolute, for mind the disbelief in finitude that Freud main-
Hegel. For psychoanalysis: the death drive. tained as a rule for the unconscious, the
paradox of the death drive is that its aim is
nothing other than its inhibition. To achieve
“death” in the circuit “death” is nothing less than to fail to achieve
Although it might seem an unlikely candidate, it, instead taking a circuitous path through sig-
the Todestrieb, or “death drive” might point nifiers. There is therefore no teleology of the
to a new beginning for what death could mean drive other than itself: in its aspect of radical
apart from God or finitude. Far from abandon- destructiveness, the notion of the “death” of
ing his earlier “naive” view that there is no the death drive is the pure repetition inaugu-
death in the unconscious, the death drive was rated by the signifier, the “will to create from
Freud’s response to centuries of tradition that zero, a will to begin again.”40 Finitude passes
cemented finitude as the iron law that decides into repetition and thereby is resurrection.
what is and is not possible in life given one’s The inaugural moment of death’s elaboration
ultimate prospects. Here, Freud revises two is born again from zero in each iteration of the
key premises of finitude: its restrictive aspect chain. Such pure repetition of the drive is none-
and its prospective dimension. As he defines it theless historical, however, in that the signifier
in Beyond the Pleasure Principle, “death” is is “memorable and memorized” in connection
not an ultimate restriction but an ultimate satis- to other signifiers according to a specific
faction, the “aim of all life.”35 At the same time, sequence or mnemonic circuit.41
it expresses the tendency of life to go not for- One of the clearest demonstrations of this cir-
wards but backwards, to “return to an earlier cuitous death is Freud’s classic example of the
state of things.”36 We no longer look ahead to forgetting of the name “Signorelli” in The

102
godley

Psychopathology of Everyday Life. During a tension. As Lacan describes it, the real reason
conversation with a stranger, Freud failed to why the forgetting of the name and unconscious
recall the painter of the frescoes of the “Four formation takes shape – the reason why “Herr”
Last Things” in the Orvieto (which is itself an and “Signor” restlessly circulate in his
allegory of death). In his efforts to recover the memory – is that they ultimately implicate
artist’s name, Freud retains only the “-elli,” Freud himself.45 Lacan does not spell out
while “Signor” undergoes repression and trans- exactly what he means by this, but Freud gave
lates into “Herr,” crossing wires with an earlier us enough clues to guess what it could be. If
moment in the conversation when he relayed an the first part of the unconscious thought of
anecdote he had heard about the Turks of death posed a fairly typical idea of finitude as
Bosnia-Herzegovina: “If one has to inform a necessity against which the physician is ulti-
them that nothing can be done for a sick mately powerless to help his patient, the
person, their reply is: ‘Herr [Sir], what is there second part of the unconscious thought-circuit
to be said? If he could be saved, I know you implies why this is a particularly painful
would have saved him.”42 Displaced in thought for Freud – of all physicians, Freud
Freud’s memory we find that “Signor” meets had discovered more about human sexuality
up, via the “Her-” in Herzegovina, with the atti- than anyone and had actually succeeded in
tude of resignation before a good doctor (Herr) helping others overcome their sexual impotence;
who is, however, powerless in the face of death. hence, he might have been able to do some-
This, as Lacan reminds us, is the thought of thing. Hence, there is a reproach: he did not
death as “absolute Herr,” the law of finitude.43 seize the opportunity he might have had to
Note, however, the past tense modals, which prevent the preventable. The point, of course,
are called the “modals of lost opportunities”: is not that this is more or less objectively plaus-
“If you could have, you would have saved ible, but that a cruel self-judgment resides in the
him,” but death overpowers us all. The doctor place of death, one that also extends from a
never had a chance, an opportunity never pre- thought of the failure of a sexual relationship
sented itself, so there is nothing to regret. (Freud’s failure to help his patient’s impotence,
But this is only one side of the unconscious itself a threat of impotence).
circuit: as Freud fails to remember “Signorelli,” In Seminar XI, Lacan explicitly links the
he first says “Botticelli” (via the “Bo” of Signorelli episode to Nietzsche’s death of
Bosnia), then “Boltraffio.” With the latter God.46 Like Freud’s “myths of the death of
word, Freud subsequently remembered he had the father” (the Oedipus complex, the father
momentarily thought of “Traffoi” – the name of the primal horde in Totem and Taboo, etc.)
of the town where, days ago, he had learned the death of God, for Lacan, is a fable that
the disturbing news that a former patient attempts to obfuscate a traumatic reality, not
(“over whom I had taken a great deal of just of loss or death but of a certain implication
trouble”) killed himself because he could not about death. They are so many frescoes in the
bear living with sexual impotence.44 Without Orvieto, intensely generative networks of
fully realizing what was going through his traces that contain death and invoke an explana-
mind, Freud even almost made an inappropriate tory meaning precisely to evoke a “law” that
joke related to the tragedy. He wanted to say would restrain a dangerous excess of enjoyment.
(but suppressed) an observation he had made For his part, Lacan says he “distrusts” these
that Turkish men love sex so much that it is a myths “precisely as myths,” which is to say,
common expression that a man would rather insofar as they function as explanatory of a fun-
die than become impotent. The intermediate damental law of existence. However, when read
layer of the jest only throws the tragedy it obfus- psychoanalytically, myths, like dreams, sympto-
cates into starker relief. The suicide was cer- matic acts, and slips of the tongue, are ulti-
tainly no joke to Freud, but it makes sense mately successful in that they point toward the
that he wanted to ease some of his inner truth in fictional form. For Lacan, the truth of

103
infinite grief

the Signorelli circuit concerns the same object from Até) that makes her a formidable and
as that of the “death of God.” This object is even terrifying figure.49 But the Até is not an
not “death” in the sense of empirical or biologi- isolated personal quality, even if it is inseparable
cal demise, but the singular object-cause of from Antigone herself. It inscribes the entire
desire at stake in sexual difference. That is, to travail of the Labdacids, inclusive of its
be precise: at stake in Freud’s thought of wearing upon Antigone’s body and the blight
death is not finitude, but the gap constituted that she expresses as one whose “race is
by “death-and-sex.” What the work of analysis already run” from the beginning of the play.50
uncovers are the signifiers that quiver in that Lacan doesn’t mince words: after everything
gap, which implicate the subject’s desire. As that’s happened with her father, the war of her
in Hegel’s analysis of infinite grief, after the siblings, the ruin of her homeland and the irre-
death of God there remain certain signifiers parable loss of her family’s prestige – she’s
that indicate not just that an irreversible cata- ready to go. But the route Antigone takes is
strophe has occurred but that there are “immor- not melancholic; she does not withdraw pre-
tal truths” that remain with us that are emptively from fate or time’s cruelty. Instead,
imperishable and absolute. Speculative beliefs she is resolved to see it through in her act, to
– beloved abstractions – emerge from the elevate not her individual existence but the
ashes of the dead God. legacy of that which burns within her of pride
and love. In short, there is something excessive
about her that is also indistinguishable from her
the act of inheritance resolution to bury her brother and thereby to
I think it would be fair to say that Lacan inherits immortalize her love’s inheritance. From his
the death drive through his theory of the signif- discussion of Antigone’s Até, Lacan is able to
ier. Inheritance in this sense is true to the Freu- formulate an ethical final judgment that
dian definition, as given in a quotation from answers to the judgment of finitude: “Have
Goethe at the end of Freud’s posthumously pub- you acted in conformity with the desire that is
lished work, An Outline of Psychoanalysis: in you?”51
“What thou hast inherited from thy fathers, To recall the outlay at the beginning of the
acquire it to make it thine.”47 In other words, play – after Oedipus dies at Colonus, Antigone
inheritance is retroactive invention – we take returns to Thebes to find it has been ruined by
from what has come before and honor it by a war over her father’s succession waged by
adding something new, which also reorients her brother Eteocles, loyal to Creon, and
the past. Perhaps this is what “death” can lead rebels led by Antigone’s brother Polynices.
to in psychoanalysis, a new fate against fatality. Creon, the new King of Thebes, has killed Poly-
A new orientation that answers or resolves, and nices and left his body to rot outside the per-
thereby gives back, what has come before. I imeter of the city, forbidding anyone to honor
would like to propose that such an act of inheri- it with customary rites or bury him. Antigone
tance could answer to the dilemma of mourning decides, against the wishes of her sister
that I identified at the beginning of this piece. Ismene, that she will bury her brother and
Lacan’s reading of Sophocles’ Antigone in the prevent his body from dishonor due to the
Ethics seminar might offer a possibility here. In lack of a symbolic commemoration. Precisely
the figure of Antigone, Lacan is struck by what the horror that galvanizes Antigone from the
the text of the play repeatedly calls her Até, beginning of the play is the idea that her broth-
loosely translated to mean “inflexibility” but er’s corpse, deliberately exposed to the
that he gives us to understand is actually the elements, has been reduced to its bare finitude.
enigmatic, unyielding insistence that is charac- Branded by shame, his bare corpse would stand
teristic of the death drive.48 Because of this for a denuded existence, prey to indifferent
characteristic, Antigone shines with a splendor nothingness. This monstrosity is unthinkable:
that is also “atrocious” (a word that comes there simply is no question but that she will

104
godley

violate Creon’s law. This, indeed, is part of what intended to redress an affront to the dignity of
Lacan means to emphasize by her Até. There is her family’s inheritance, an affront that, no
an insistence within her of something that, less, arises from within her family.
beyond the appeal of reason, practical morality, We should remember that the unresolved
or the threat of death, resolves her to carry out mourning of Oedipus, too, is implicated in the
her task, where Até “designates the limit that play. When Oedipus dies at Colonus, after all,
human life can only briefly cross,” a beyond of he refuses to allow his daughters to know the
the mortal threshold.52 location of his tomb, but gives the “secret”
For Lacan, this crossing of the limit is expli- only to Theseus and tells him to pass it down
citly related to the crucifixion and the moment to the patriarch rulers in each successive gener-
Hegel identified as an “infinite grief” (where ation.55 Despite the fact that she was by his side,
Christ cries “Father, why hast thou forsaken and exiled herself along with him, she was not
me?”), but Antigone’s resolve forms a counter- given to know what would have given her
point to the Christian cathexis because it is some solace: the location of the grave. Derrida
not about self-sacrifice but honoring the death is right to point out that this situation creates
of a beloved; an act of mourning.53 She goes for Antigone an “infinite mourning,” an infinite
through with her act and takes all its conse- grief that haunts her afterwards that is also a
quences because his place is ineffaceable, “mourning of mourning” inasmuch as Oedi-
though love may come to fill it with some beau- pus’s death represents a burning problem for
tiful memorial or other, it cannot replace it. In her that puts the resolution of her grief precisely
that respect the fact that Antigone’s act involves in suspense.56 Her later act of burying her
her brother’s corpse is of capital importance, for brother can therefore be seen as her answer,
it consecrates the material with the creative not just to Creon but to Oedipus, and through
capacity of the drive to seek death in symbolic him, the tradition of the patriarchs and the
form at the limit of a second death that would cult of death that remains the esoteric heritage
otherwise be an erasure. Likewise, there is no of the polis. Antigone’s act of burying her
escaping the uncanniness in the propinquity of brother fulfills a circuit of death that followed
Antigone’s devotion to taboo, both of her from a crisis of infinite grief, her unresolved
incest-tinged affection and of the taboos of “mourning of mourning,” which, as can be
handling an exposed corpse. It is only by seen clearly in terms of its spiritual impli-
keeping these elements in mind that we can cations, has to do with the installation of the
understand Lacan’s point that in commemorat- singular “abstract” object of her inheritance
ing her brother, Antigone “perpetuates, eterna- within a larger structure of infinity.
lizes, immortalizes that Até.”54 What this means But it would be insufficient to limit Anti-
is not that Antigone immortalizes herself, but gone’s act to a political protest, let alone the
that the love that is “in her more than her,” messianic form of the promise, so long as this
the excessive object of her drive, takes up and still means (as it does for Derrida) a certain dis-
surpasses the finitude of the beloved. Through position toward finitude as an eventuality. Anti-
sublimated immortality, the object is inherited, gone’s defiance is more elevated than that – it
what has come down from the circuit of her has a spiritual significance that should not be
family is acquired and given back. Such inheri- discounted, where the relation to immortality
tance involves the signifier of the beloved’s deserves to be especially emphasized. The
truth: through her resolve to commit this ethics of her act, properly speaking, is not
object to eternity Antigone literally makes limited to an empirical circumstance but,
sense out of her brother’s death, she invents a beyond it, aims at a universal significance that
new meaning that retroactively re-determines only the precise conditions of her desire’s
the history that preceded it and becomes the inheritance can mark. Antigone’s act is privi-
sublime object of a new tradition. There is a leged in the sense that it assumes responsibility
fury in her act that is not just sacrificial but for this inheritance. Her mourning is done not

105
infinite grief

just to commemorate her brother or to defy the circuit of signifiers that form specific problems
war that led to his death, the cruelty of Creon’s or dilemmas, as in the case of “Signorelli,” the
injunction or the harshness of her father’s drive sublimates death. Likewise, for Antigone,
having kept the secret of his death to the line whose ethics consists in her act of keeping faith
of ruling sons, but inclusive of these impli- with the inheritance that she carries within her,
cations raises to the nobility of infinity the her Até, which is a problem and a curse but also
metonymic piece of her beloved’s truth, a a point of honor. By elevating her Até to the
desire that she herself inherited from her level of an immortal truth in the act of
father and consecrates in a way that he did burying her brother and formally mourning
not. When Sophocles monumentalizes Anti- him, she turned the death of finitude into a
gone, what is consecrated is a privileged meto- properly symbolic death. Through her act of
nymy, a piece of the real taken for the whole, mourning, Antigone actively inherited her
a singular-universal truth-value that is added inheritance and posited a new signifier in the
to the totality and thereby retroactively heavens – one that retroactively
changes the meaning of the totality. Something changed the meaning of what
finite passes over to the infinite through the had come before. In this way,
singularity of her act, for which she pays with mourning is radically opposed
her life. On the other hand, not all of her dies. to death, or rather, to existence
as an infinite grief.
conclusion
disclosure statement
In these overlapping accounts of Freud, Hegel,
and Lacan I have been traversing the problem No potential conflict of interest was reported by
of finitude as an infinite grief in pursuit of a the author.
concept of speculative mourning. I began by
showing that in Freud’s original definition of
notes
mourning there was already a link between the
empirical and the speculative, the historical This article has benefited from peer review. The
death of a loved one and the problem of what author wishes to thank Salah el Moncef and Angela-
happens to a loved belief that has fallen into ki’s reviewer for their generous and helpful input in
consideration of this article.
negation through the imposition of finitude.
Analyzing the idea of finitude in psychoanalytic 1 Baldwin 122. The phrase “thought of death” in
terms, Freud argued that it presupposes a struc- the title is partly inspired by Crépon.
ture of pre-emptive mourning. Turning to 2 Breitwieser, for example, describes mourning as
Hegel, we located a similar trouble in the way “dialectic’s purest case.” See Breitwieser, American
the Kantian subject maintained belief in the sac- Puritanism 42; Stern 386. Staten defines “dialectic of
redness of finitude. Hegel similarly discovered mourning” as “the field of movement of all affective
that this construction was really a melancholy phenomena determined by the mortality of a love
fantasy; a grieving over the infinite which had object, as this field is articulated in certain influen-
profound implications for the culture of nihi- tial texts of the Western tradition” (xi). Although
lism. By pointing out that “infinite grief” is she doesn’t explicitly define it as such, Comay in
also the expression of a desire and longing, Mourning Sickness strongly implies a mode or
method of Hegelian “dialectical mourning.” Also,
however, Hegel was able to show that the
there is the critical sense of “structural mourning”
problem was also the solution. The desire to
that Santner evokes against Paul de Man’s attempts
mourn the infinite also meant that the infinite to “displace and disperse the particular and histori-
was an object of desire. The “death of God” cal tasks of mourning” with the “structural mourn-
had left behind a wealth of signifiers. Then, ing [ … ] for those catastrophes that are
back to Freud via Lacan we followed how the inseparable from being-in-language” (29). See also
death drive disengages from finitude. As a White.

106
godley

3 Freud, “Mourning and Melancholia” 244. analysis of the dialectic of intersubjectivity in


Plato’s Symposium. See Lacan, Transference 50–54.
4 For a discussion of pragmatic opportunism as
the obverse of mourning, see Breitwieser, National 15 “Belief” and “believe” are based on “ylief,”
Melancholy 33. coming from Old English gelíefan, derived from a
mixture of Old Saxon (gilôbjan), Old High German
5 Clewell 47.
(gilouben) and Gothic (galaubjan). From the latter
6 Freud, “Mourning and Melancholia” 244–45. As comes the combined senses of laub̵ -dear, leub̵ -lief
Rickels situates the difference: and lub̵ -love. See OED Online, “believe, v.”

in Freud’s essay the catastrophe of another’s 16 It has already been noticed that Freud’s defi-
death summons mourner and melancholic nition of mourning is the reaction to the loss of a
alike while turning them apart: the loss that belief. See, for example, Peter Homans’s term
afflicts the former is conscious, whereas the “symbolic loss.” Homans 20.
occasion for the latter’s interminable grieving 17
is kept in the unconscious. Which reception
of loss is available depends upon the Reality testing has shown that the loved
channel of the original object choice. Thus object no longer exists, and it proceeds to
Freud agrees with Otto Rank that whereas demand that all libido shall be withdrawn
the mourner disengages his ego from an from its attachments to that object [ … ]
object loved for its separateness and Normally respect for reality gains the day.
otherness, the melancholic discards Nevertheless, its orders cannot be obeyed
a narcissistic choice by consummating the at once. They are carried out bit by bit, at
ego’s rapport with this cherished object great expense of time and cathectic energy,
through identification, internalization, and and in the meantime the existence of the
idealization. (4) lost object is psychically prolonged [ … ]
Why this compromise by which the
7 Clewell 48. Clewell’s solution, which is taken up command of reality is carried out piecemeal
indirectly in what follows, critically reconstructs should be so extraordinarily painful is not at
Freud’s later ego theory, in order to propose a all easy to explain in terms of economics.
normative melancholia that would attempt to (Freud, “Mourning and Melancholia” 245)
overcome itself by engaging in what she calls
“endless mourning” – that is, keeping a constant “Living hypothesis”: see James 2.
channel open with the dead. My argument here is
18 The others, of course, are “Mourning and Mel-
less concerned with her readings of Freud and
ancholia” and “Thoughts for the Times on War and
more with the theoretical implications of endless
Death.” But just as significant is Freud’s prewar
mourning or infinite grief. My aim is to reconcile
theory of funerary rituals in Totem and Taboo. See
Clewell’s conclusion while rejecting her over-
Freud, Totem and Taboo 51–74.
reliance on the subjectivist premises of the post-
structuralist emphasis on finitude. 19 Prater 233 qtd in Ricciardi 213 n. 31.
8 Freud, “Letter 239” 386. 20 Freud, “On Transience” 306.
9 Laplanche 6. 21 Ibid. 305.
10 Freud, “Thoughts for the Times on War and 22 Ibid. 306; my emphasis.
Death” 289.
23 Ibid. 306–07.
11 For a vivid example of this fear of death, see
Leclaire. 24 See, for example, Freud, “Analysis Terminable
and Interminable” 226–30.
12 Freud, Totem and Taboo 93.
25 Hegel, Aesthetics 522.
13 “Mourning and Melancholia” 243.
26 Ibid.
14 The terms and logic of the “lover” and the
“beloved” are based on Lacan’s use of them in his 27 Ibid.

107
infinite grief

28 See Žižek 14, 126, 171. 47 Freud, An Outline of Psychoanalysis 207.


29 Hegel, Faith and Knowledge 56. For an excellent 48 Lacan, The Ethics of Psychoanalysis 263. My
and important study of the link between the death reading draws from Copjec’s masterful study of
of God as a crisis of finitude and the ethics of the death drive in Lacan’s study of Antigone. See
tragedy in both Hegel and Nietzsche, see Williams 25–47.
1–30, 161–67.
49 Lacan, The Ethics of Psychoanalysis 314.
30 Hegel, Faith and Knowledge 189.
50 Ibid. 263.
31 Kant 72.
51 Ibid.
32 Hegel, The Science of Logic 101, 102. 52 Ibid. 262–63.
33 Hegel, Faith and Knowledge 190. 53 Ibid. 255, 273.
34 Ibid. 190–91; emphasis in original. 54 Ibid. 283.
35 Freud, Beyond the Pleasure Principle 38. 55 Sophocles 375–76, 386.
36 Ibid. 37. 56 Derrida 93, 109–10.
37 Fitzgerald 180.
The two daughters lament but they do not
38 Lacan, The Ethics of Psychoanalysis 212. bemoan only the fact of never more seeing
their father [ … ] but on the other hand,
39 hidden in the secret of a foreign land, that
his corpse, their paternal corpse, should
The full paradox of the death drive, then, is this:
also be buried without a tomb. Not at all,
while the aim (Ziel) of the drive is death, the
perhaps, without a grave, but without a
proper and positive activity of the drive is to
tomb, without a determinable place,
inhibit the attainment of its aim; the drive, as
without monument, without a localizable
such, is zielgehemnt, that is, it is inhibited as to
and circumscribed place of mourning,
its aim, or sublimated, “the satisfaction of the
without a stopping point [arrêt]. Without a
drive through the inhibition of its aim” being
fixed [arrêté] place, without a determinable
the very definition of sublimation. (Copjec 30)
topos, mourning is not allowed. Or, what
40 Lacan, The Ethics of Psychoanalysis 213, 212. comes down to the same thing, it is promised
without taking place, a determinable place, so
41 Ibid. 212. thenceforth promised as an interminable
mourning, an infinite mourning defying all
42 Freud, The Psychopathology of Everyday Life 2–3.
work, beyond any possible work of mourn-
43 Lacan, Formations of the Unconscious 50. ing. The only possible mourning is the
impossible mourning. (109–10)
44 Freud, Psychopathology of Everyday Life 3.
45 Lacan, Formations of the Unconscious 32.
46
bibliography
The term Signor, Herr passes underneath –
the absolute master, I once said, which is in Baldwin, James. “Sonny’s Blues.” Going to Meet the
fact death, has disappeared there. Further- Man. New York: Dell, 1968. 101–42. Print.
more, do we not see, behind this, the emer-
“Believe, v.” OED Online. Mar. 2017. Oxford UP.
gence of that which forced Freud to find in
Web. 1 Mar. 2017. <http://www.oed.com>.
the myths of the death of the father the regu-
lation of his desire? After all, it is to be found Breitwieser, Mitchell. American Puritanism and the
in Nietzsche, who declares, in his own myth, Defense of Mourning: Religion, Grief and Ethnology in
that God is dead. (Lacan, The Four Fundamen- Mary White Rolwlandson’s Captivity Narrative.
tal Concepts of Psychoanalysis 27) Madison: U of Wisconsin P, 1990. Print.

108
godley

Breitwieser, Mitchell. National Melancholy: Freud, Sigmund. The Psychopathology of Everyday


Mourning and Opportunity in Classic American Life. The Standard Edition of the Complete
Literature. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2007. Print. Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud. Trans. James
Strachey et al. Vol. VI. London: Hogarth, 1953–
Clewell, Tammy. “Mourning beyond Melancholia:
74. Print.
Freud’s Psychoanalysis of Loss.” Journal of the
American Psychoanalytic Association 52.1 (2004): Freud, Sigmund. “Thoughts for the Times on War
43–67. Print. and Death.” The Standard Edition of the Complete
Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud. Trans. James
Comay, Rebecca. Mourning Sickness: Hegel and the
Strachey et al. Vol. XIV. London: Hogarth, 1953–
French Revolution. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2011.
74. 273–90. Print.
Print.
Freud, Sigmund. Totem and Taboo. The Standard
Copjec, Joan. Imagine There’s No Woman: Ethics and
Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of
Sublimation. Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 2002. Print.
Sigmund Freud. Trans. James Strachey et al. Vol.
Crépon, Marc. The Thought of Death and the XIII. London: Hogarth, 1953–74. Print.
Memory of War. Trans. Michael Loriaux.
Hegel, G.W.F. Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art. Vol. 1.
Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2013. Print.
Trans. T.M. Knox. Oxford: Clarendon, 1975. Print.
Derrida, Jacques. Of Hospitality: Anne Duformantelle
Hegel, G.W.F. Faith and Knowledge. Trans. Walter
Invites Jacques Derrida to Respond. Trans. Rachel
Cerf and H.S. Harris. Albany: State U of
Bowlby. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2000. Print.
New York P, 1977. Print.
Fitzgerald, F. Scott. The Great Gatsby. New York:
Hegel, G.W.F. The Science of Logic. Trans. George
Scribner, 2004. Print.
di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2010.
Freud, Sigmund. “Analysis, Terminable and Print.
Interminable.” The Standard Edition of the
Homans, Peter. Symbolic Loss: The Ambiguity of
Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud.
Mourning and Memory at Century’s End. Ed. Peter
Trans. James Strachey et al. Vol. XIV. London:
Homans. Charlottesville: U of Virginia P, 2000.
Hogarth, 1953–74. 216–54. Print.
Print.
Freud, Sigmund. Beyond the Pleasure Principle. The
James, William. “The Will to Believe.” The Will to
Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological
Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy.
Works of Sigmund Freud. Trans. James Strachey
New York: Dover, 1956. 1–31. Print.
et al. Vol. XVIII. London: Hogarth, 1953–74. Print.
Kant, Immanuel. Religion within the Boundaries of
Freud, Sigmund. “Letter 239.” The Letters of
Mere Reason: And Other Writings. Trans. Allen
Sigmund Freud. Trans. Tania Stern and James
Wood and George di Giovanni. Cambridge:
Stern. Ed. Ernst L. Freud. New York: Basic, 1960.
Cambridge UP, 1998. Print.
386. Print.
Lacan, Jacques. The Formations of the Unconscious:
Freud, Sigmund. “Mourning and Melancholia.” The
The Seminar of Jacques Lacan, Book V. Trans.
Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological
Russell Grigg. Cambridge: Polity, 2017. Print.
Works of Sigmund Freud. Trans. James Strachey
et al. Vol. XIV. London: Hogarth, 1953–74. 243– Lacan, Jacques. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan, Book
58. Print. VII: The Ethics of Psychoanalysis 1959–1960. Trans.
Dennis Porter. New York: Norton, 1992. Print.
Freud, Sigmund. “On Transience.” The Standard
Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Lacan, Jacques. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan, Book
Sigmund Freud. Trans. James Strachey et al. Vol. XI: The Four Fundamental Concepts of
XIV. London: Hogarth, 1953–74. 303–08. Print. Psychoanalysis. Trans. Alan Sheridan. New York:
Norton, 1998. Print.
Freud, Sigmund. An Outline of Psychoanalysis. The
Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Lacan, Jacques. Transference: The Seminar of Jacques
Works of Sigmund Freud. Trans. James Strachey Lacan, Book VIII. Trans. Bruce Fink. Cambridge:
et al. Vol. XXIII. London: Hogarth, 1953–74. Print. Polity, 2015. Print.

109
infinite grief

Laplanche, Jean. Life and Death in Psychoanalysis.


Trans. Jeffrey Mehlman. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
UP, 1976. Print.
Leclaire, Serge. “Jerome, or Death in the Life of the
Obsessional.” Returning to Freud: Clinical
Psychoanalysis in the School of Lacan. Trans. Stuart
Schneiderman. New Haven: Yale UP, 1980. 94–
113. Print.
Prater, Donald. A Ringing Glass: The Life of Rainier
Maria Rilke. Oxford: Clarendon, 1986. Print.
Ricciardi, Alessia. The Ends of Mourning:
Psychoanalysis, Literature, Film. Stanford: Stanford
UP, 2003. Print.
Rickels, Laurence A. Aberrations of Mourning:
Writing on German Crypts. Detroit: Wayne State
UP, 1988. Print.
Santner, Eric L. Stranded Objects: Mourning, Memory
and Film in Postwar Germany. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
UP, 1993. Print.
Sophocles. “Oedipus at Colonus.” The Three
Theban Plays: Antigone; Oedipus the King; Oedipus
at Colonus. Trans. Robert Fagles. New York:
Penguin, 1984. 279–88. Print.
Staten, Henry. Eros in Mourning: From Homer to
Lacan. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1995. Print.
Stern, Julia. “To Represent Afflicted Time:
Mourning as Historiography.” American Literary
History 5.2 (1993): 378–88. Print.
White, Richard. “Dialectics of Mourning.” Angelaki:
Journal of the Theoretical Humanities 20.4 (2015):
179–92. Print.
Williams, Robert. Tragedy, Recognition and the
Death of God: Studies in Hegel and Nietzsche.
Oxford: Oxford UP, 2012. Print.
Žižek, Slavoj. The Puppet and the Dwarf: The Perverse
Core of Christianity. Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 2003.
Print.

James A. Godley
306 Clemens Hall
University at Buffalo, SUNY
Buffalo, NY 14260-4601
USA
E-mail: jamesgod@buffalo.edu

Potrebbero piacerti anche