Sei sulla pagina 1di 11

» Natural Law » Print [Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy] http://www.iep.utm.

edu/natlaw/print/

Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy - http://www.iep.utm.edu

Natural Law
The term “natural law” is ambiguous. It refers to a type of moral theory, as well as to a type of legal
theory, but the core claims of the two kinds of theory are logically independent. It does not refer to
the laws of nature, the laws that science aims to describe. According to natural law moral theory,
the moral standards that govern human behavior are, in some sense, objectively derived from the
nature of human beings and the nature of the world. While being logically independent of natural
law legal theory, the two theories intersect. However, the majority of the article will focus on natural
law legal theory.

According to natural law legal theory, the authority of legal standards necessarily derives, at least in
part, from considerations having to do with the moral merit of those standards. There are a number
of different kinds of natural law legal theories, differing from each other with respect to the role that
morality plays in determining the authority of legal norms. The conceptual jurisprudence of John
Austin provides a set of necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of law that
distinguishes law from non-law in every possible world. Classical natural law theory such as the
theory of Thomas Aquinas focuses on the overlap between natural law moral and legal theories.
Similarly, the neo-naturalism of John Finnis is a development of classical natural law theory. In
contrast, the procedural naturalism of Lon L. Fuller is a rejection of the conceptual naturalist idea
that there are necessary substantive moral constraints on the content of law. Lastly, Ronald
Dworkin’s theory is a response and critique of legal positivism. All of these theories subscribe to one
or more basic tenets of natural law legal theory and are important to its development and influence.

Table of Contents

1. Two Kinds of Natural Law Theory


2. Conceptual Naturalism
a. The Project of Conceptual Jurisprudence
b. Classical Natural Law Theory
3. The Substantive Neo-Naturalism of John Finnis
4. The Procedural Naturalism of Lon L. Fuller
5. Ronald Dworkin’s “Third Theory”
6. References and Further Reading

1. Two Kinds of Natural Law Theory


At the outset, it is important to distinguish two kinds of theory that go by the name of natural law.
The first is a theory of morality that is roughly characterized by the following theses. First, moral
propositions have what is sometimes called objective standing in the sense that such propositions
are the bearers of objective truth-value; that is, moral propositions can be objectively true or false.
Though moral objectivism is sometimes equated with moral realism (see, e.g., Moore 1992, 190:
“the truth of any moral proposition lies in its correspondence with a mind- and convention-
independent moral reality”), the relationship between the two theories is controversial. Geoffrey
Sayre-McCord (1988), for example, views moral objectivism as one species of moral realism, but
not the only form; on Sayre-McCord’s view, moral subjectivism and moral intersubjectivism are
also forms of moral realism. Strictly speaking, then, natural law moral theory is committed only to
the objectivity of moral norms.

The second thesis constituting the core of natural law moral theory is the claim that standards of
morality are in some sense derived from, or entailed by, the nature of the world and the nature of

1 of 11 9/8/2010 10:50 PM
» Natural Law » Print [Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy] http://www.iep.utm.edu/natlaw/print/

human beings. St. Thomas Aquinas, for example, identifies the rational nature of human beings as
that which defines moral law: “the rule and measure of human acts is the reason, which is the first
principle of human acts” (Aquinas, ST I-II, Q.90, A.I). On this common view, since human beings
are by nature rational beings, it is morally appropriate that they should behave in a way that
conforms to their rational nature. Thus, Aquinas derives the moral law from the nature of human
beings (thus, “natural law”).

But there is another kind of natural law theory having to do with the relationship of morality to law.
According to natural law theory of law, there is no clean division between the notion of law and the
notion of morality. Though there are different versions of natural law theory, all subscribe to the
thesis that there are at least some laws that depend for their “authority” not on some pre-existing
human convention, but on the logical relationship in which they stand to moral standards.
Otherwise put, some norms are authoritative in virtue of their moral content, even when there is no
convention that makes moral merit a criterion of legal validity. The idea that the concepts of law
and morality intersect in some way is called the Overlap Thesis.

As an empirical matter, many natural law moral theorists are also natural law legal theorists, but
the two theories, strictly speaking, are logically independent. One can deny natural law theory of
law but hold a natural law theory of morality. John Austin, the most influential of the early legal
positivists, for example, denied the Overlap Thesis but held something that resembles a natural law
ethical theory.

Indeed, Austin explicitly endorsed the view that it is not necessarily true that the legal validity of a
norm depends on whether its content conforms to morality. But while Austin thus denied the
Overlap Thesis, he accepted an objectivist moral theory; indeed, Austin inherited his utilitarianism
almost wholesale from J.S. Mill and Jeremy Bentham. Here it is worth noting that utilitarians
sometimes seem to suggest that they derive their utilitarianism from certain facts about human
nature; as Bentham once wrote, “nature has placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign
masters, pain and pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we ought to do, as well as to
determine what we shall do. On the one hand the standard of right and wrong, on the other the
chain of causes and effects, are fastened to their throne” (Bentham 1948, 1). Thus, a commitment to
natural law theory of morality is consistent with the denial of natural law theory of law.

Conversely, one could, though this would be unusual, accept a natural law theory of law without
holding a natural law theory of morality. One could, for example, hold that the conceptual point of
law is, in part, to reproduce the demands of morality, but also hold a form of ethical subjectivism
(or relativism). On this peculiar view, the conceptual point of law would be to enforce those
standards that are morally valid in virtue of cultural consensus. For this reason, natural law theory
of law is logically independent of natural law theory of morality. The remainder of this essay will be
exclusively concerned with natural law theories of law.

2. Conceptual Naturalism
a. The Project of Conceptual Jurisprudence

The principal objective of conceptual (or analytic) jurisprudence has traditionally been to provide
an account of what distinguishes law as a system of norms from other systems of norms, such as
ethical norms. As John Austin describes the project, conceptual jurisprudence seeks “the essence or
nature which is common to all laws that are properly so called” (Austin 1995, 11). Accordingly, the
task of conceptual jurisprudence is to provide a set of necessary and sufficient conditions for the
existence of law that distinguishes law from non-law in every possible world.

While this task is usually interpreted as an attempt to analyze the concepts of law and legal system,
there is some confusion as to both the value and character of conceptual analysis in philosophy of
law. As Brian Leiter (1998) points out, philosophy of law is one of the few philosophical disciplines
that takes conceptual analysis as its principal concern; most other areas in philosophy have taken a
naturalistic turn, incorporating the tools and methods of the sciences. To clarify the role of

2 of 11 9/8/2010 10:50 PM
» Natural Law » Print [Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy] http://www.iep.utm.edu/natlaw/print/

conceptual analysis in law, Brian Bix (1995) distinguishes a number of different purposes that can
be served by conceptual claims: (1) to track linguistic usage; (2) to stipulate meanings; (3) to
explain what is important or essential about a class of objects; and (4) to establish an evaluative test
for the concept-word. Bix takes conceptual analysis in law to be primarily concerned with (3) and
(4).

In any event, conceptual analysis of law remains an important, if controversial, project in


contemporary legal theory. Conceptual theories of law have traditionally been characterized in
terms of their posture towards the Overlap Thesis. Thus, conceptual theories of law have
traditionally been divided into two main categories: those like natural law legal theory that affirm
there is a conceptual relation between law and morality and those like legal positivism that deny
such a relation.

b. Classical Natural Law Theory

All forms of natural law theory subscribe to the Overlap Thesis, which asserts that there is some
kind of non-conventional relation between law and morality. According to this view, then, the notion
of law cannot be fully articulated without some reference to moral notions. Though the Overlap
Thesis may seem unambiguous, there are a number of different ways in which it can be interpreted.

The strongest construction of the Overlap Thesis forms the foundation for the classical naturalism
of Aquinas and Blackstone. Aquinas distinguishes four kinds of law: (1) eternal law; (2) natural law;
(3) human law; and (4) divine law. Eternal law is comprised of those laws that govern the nature of
an eternal universe; as Susan Dimock (1999, 22) puts it, one can “think of eternal law as comprising
all those scientific (physical, chemical, biological, psychological, etc.) ‘laws’ by which the universe is
ordered.” Divine law is concerned with those standards that must be satisfied by a human being to
achieve eternal salvation. One cannot discover divine law by natural reason alone; the precepts of
divine law are disclosed only through divine revelation.

The natural law is comprised of those precepts of the eternal law that govern the behavior of beings
possessing reason and free will. The first precept of the natural law, according to Aquinas, is the
somewhat vacuous imperative to do good and avoid evil. Here it is worth noting that Aquinas holds
a natural law theory of morality: what is good and evil, according to Aquinas, is derived from the
rational nature of human beings. Good and evil are thus both objective and universal.

But Aquinas is also a natural law legal theorist. On his view, a human law (that is, that which is
promulgated by human beings) is valid only insofar as its content conforms to the content of the
natural law; as Aquinas puts the point: “[E]very human law has just so much of the nature of law as
is derived from the law of nature. But if in any point it deflects from the law of nature, it is no longer
a law but a perversion of law” (ST I-II, Q.95, A.II). To paraphrase Augustine’s famous remark, an
unjust law is really no law at all.

The idea that a norm that does not conform to the natural law cannot be legally valid is the defining
thesis of conceptual naturalism. As William Blackstone describes the thesis, “This law of nature,
being co-eval with mankind and dictated by God himself, is of course superior in obligation to any
other. It is binding over all the globe, in all countries, and at all times: no human laws are of any
validity, if contrary to this; and such of them as are valid derive all their force, and all their
authority, mediately or immediately, from this original” (1979, 41). In this passage, Blackstone
articulates the two claims that constitute the theoretical core of conceptual naturalism: 1) there can
be no legally valid standards that conflict with the natural law; and 2) all valid laws derive what
force and authority they have from the natural law.

It should be noted that classical naturalism is consistent with allowing a substantial role to human
beings in the manufacture of law. While the classical naturalist seems committed to the claim that
the law necessarily incorporates all moral principles, this claim does not imply that the law is
exhausted by the set of moral principles. There will still be coordination problems (e.g., which side
of the road to drive on) that can be resolved in any number of ways consistent with the set of moral
principles. Thus, the classical naturalist does not deny that human beings have considerable

3 of 11 9/8/2010 10:50 PM
» Natural Law » Print [Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy] http://www.iep.utm.edu/natlaw/print/

discretion in creating natural law. Rather she claims only that such discretion is necessarily limited
by moral norms: legal norms that are promulgated by human beings are valid only if they are
consistent with morality.

Critics of conceptual naturalism have raised a number of objections to this view. First, it has often
been pointed out that, contra Augustine, unjust laws are all-too- frequently enforced against
persons. As Austin petulantly put the point:

Now, to say that human laws which conflict with the Divine law are not binding, that is to
say, are not laws, is to talk stark nonsense. The most pernicious laws, and therefore those
which are most opposed to the will of God, have been and are continually enforced as laws
by judicial tribunals. Suppose an act innocuous, or positively beneficial, be prohibited by
the sovereign under the penalty of death; if I commit this act, I shall be tried and
condemned, and if I object to the sentence, that it is contrary to the law of God, who has
commanded that human lawgivers shall not prohibit acts which have no evil
consequences, the Court of Justice will demonstrate the inconclusiveness of my reasoning
by hanging me up, in pursuance of the law of which I have impugned the validity (Austin
1995, 158).

Of course, as Brian Bix (1999) points out, the argument does little work for Austin because it is
always possible for a court to enforce a law against a person that does not satisfy Austin’s own
theory of legal validity.

Another frequently expressed worry is that conceptual naturalism undermines the possibility of
moral criticism of the law; inasmuch as conformity with natural law is a necessary condition for
legal validity, all valid law is, by definition, morally just. Thus, on this line of reasoning, the legal
validity of a norm necessarily entails its moral justice. As Jules Coleman and Jeffrey Murphy (1990,
18) put the point:

The important things [conceptual naturalism] supposedly allows us to do (e.g., morally


evaluate the law and determine our moral obligations with respect to the law) are actually
rendered more difficult by its collapse of the distinction between morality and law. If we
really want to think about the law from the moral point of view, it may obscure the task if
we see law and morality as essentially linked in some way. Moral criticism and reform of
law may be aided by an initial moral skepticism about the law.

There are a couple of problems with this line of objection. First, conceptual naturalism does not
foreclose criticism of those norms that are being enforced by a society as law. Insofar as it can
plausibly be claimed that the content of a norm being enforced by society as law does not conform
to the natural law, this is a legitimate ground of moral criticism: given that the norm being enforced
by law is unjust, it follows, according to conceptual naturalism, that it is not legally valid. Thus, the
state commits wrong by enforcing that norm against private citizens.

Second, and more importantly, this line of objection seeks to criticize a conceptual theory of law by
pointing to its practical implications ñ a strategy that seems to commit a category mistake.
Conceptual jurisprudence assumes the existence of a core of social practices (constituting law) that
requires a conceptual explanation. The project motivating conceptual jurisprudence, then, is to
articulate the concept of law in a way that accounts for these pre-existing social practices. A
conceptual theory of law can legitimately be criticized for its failure to adequately account for the
pre-existing data, as it were; but it cannot legitimately be criticized for either its normative quality
or its practical implications.

A more interesting line of argument has recently been taken up by Brian Bix (1996). Following John
Finnis (1980), Bix rejects the interpretation of Aquinas and Blackstone as conceptual naturalists,

4 of 11 9/8/2010 10:50 PM
» Natural Law » Print [Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy] http://www.iep.utm.edu/natlaw/print/

arguing instead that the claim that an unjust law is not a law should not be taken literally:

A more reasonable interpretation of statements like “an unjust law is no law at all” is that
unjust laws are not laws “in the fullest sense.” As we might say of some professional, who
had the necessary degrees and credentials, but seemed nonetheless to lack the necessary
ability or judgment: “she’s no lawyer” or “he’s no doctor.” This only indicates that we do
not think that the title in this case carries with it all the implications it usually does.
Similarly, to say that an unjust law is “not really law” may only be to point out that it does
not carry the same moral force or offer the same reasons for action as laws consistent
with “higher law” (Bix 1996, 226).

Thus, Bix construes Aquinas and Blackstone as having views more similar to the neo- naturalism of
John Finnis discussed below in Section III. Nevertheless, while a plausible case can be made in
favor of Bix’s view, the long history of construing Aquinas and Blackstone as conceptual naturalists,
along with its pedagogical value in developing other theories of law, ensures that this practice is
likely, for better or worse, to continue indefinitely.

3. The Substantive Neo-Naturalism of John Finnis


John Finnis takes himself to be explicating and developing the views of Aquinas and Blackstone.
Like Bix, Finnis believes that the naturalism of Aquinas and Blackstone should not be construed as
a conceptual account of the existence conditions for law. According to Finnis, the classical
naturalists were not concerned with giving a conceptual account of legal validity; rather they were
concerned with explaining the moral force of law: “the principles of natural law explain the
obligatory force (in the fullest sense of ‘obligation’) of positive laws, even when those laws cannot be
deduced from those principles” (Finnis 1980, 23-24). On Finnis’s view of the Overlap Thesis, the
essential function of law is to provide a justification for state coercion (a view he shares with Ronald
Dworkin). Accordingly, an unjust law can be legally valid, but it cannot provide an adequate
justification for use of the state coercive power and is hence not obligatory in the fullest sense; thus,
an unjust law fails to realize the moral ideals implicit in the concept of law. An unjust law, on this
view, is legally binding, but is not fully law.

Like classical naturalism, Finnis’s naturalism is both an ethical theory and a theory of law. Finnis
distinguishes a number of equally valuable basic goods: life, health, knowledge, play, friendship,
religion, and aesthetic experience. Each of these goods, according to Finnis, has intrinsic value in
the sense that it should, given human nature, be valued for its own sake and not merely for the sake
of some other good it can assist in bringing about. Moreover, each of these goods is universal in the
sense that it governs all human cultures at all times. The point of moral principles, on this view, is
to give ethical structure to the pursuit of these basic goods; moral principles enable us to select
among competing goods and to define what a human being can permissibly do in pursuit of a basic
good.

On Finnis’s view, the conceptual point of law is to facilitate the common good by providing
authoritative rules that solve coordination problems that arise in connection with the common
pursuit of these basic goods. Thus, Finnis sums up his theory of law as follows:

5 of 11 9/8/2010 10:50 PM
» Natural Law » Print [Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy] http://www.iep.utm.edu/natlaw/print/

[T]he term ‘law’ … refer[s] primarily to rules made, in accordance with regulative legal
rules, by a determinate and effective authority (itself identified and, standardly,
constituted as an institution by legal rules) for a ‘complete’ community, and buttressed by
sanctions in accordance with the rule-guided stipulations of adjudicative institutions, this
ensemble of rules and institutions being directed to reasonably resolving any of the
community’s co-ordination problems (and to ratifying, tolerating, regulating, or
overriding co-ordination solutions from any other institutions or sources of norms) for the
common good of that community (Finnis 1980, 276).

Again, it bears emphasizing that Finnis takes care to deny that there is any necessary moral test for
legal validity: “one would simply be misunderstanding my conception of the nature and purpose of
explanatory definitions of theoretical concepts if one supposed that my definition ‘ruled out as
non-laws’ laws which failed to meet, or meet fully, one or other of the elements of the definition”
(Finnis 1980, 278).

Nevertheless, Finnis believes that to the extent that a norm fails to satisfy these conditions, it
likewise fails to fully manifest the nature of law and thereby fails to fully obligate the citizen-subject
of the law. Unjust laws may obligate in a technical legal sense, on Finnis’s view, but they may fail to
provide moral reasons for action of the sort that it is the point of legal authority to provide. Thus,
Finnis argues that “a ruler’s use of authority is radically defective if he exploits his opportunities by
making stipulations intended by him not for the common good but for his own or his friends’ or
party’s or faction’s advantage, or out of malice against some person or group” (Finnis 1980, 352).
For the ultimate basis of a ruler’s moral authority, on this view, “is the fact that he has the
opportunity, and thus the responsibility, of furthering the common good by stipulating solutions to
a community’s co- ordination problems” (Finnis 1980, 351).

Finnis’s theory is certainly more plausible as a theory of law than the traditional interpretation of
classical naturalism, but such plausibility comes, for better or worse, at the expense of naturalism’s
identity as a distinct theory of law. Indeed, it appears that Finnis’s natural law theory is compatible
with naturalism’s historical adversary, legal positivism, inasmuch as Finnis’s view is compatible
with a source-based theory of legal validity; laws that are technically valid in virtue of source but
unjust do not, according to Finnis, fully obligate the citizen. Indeed, Finnis (1996) believes that
Aquinas’s classical naturalism fully affirms the notion that human laws are “posited.”

4. The Procedural Naturalism of Lon L. Fuller


Like Finnis, Lon Fuller (1964) rejects the conceptual naturalist idea that there are necessary
substantive moral constraints on the content of law. But Fuller, unlike Finnis, believes that law is
necessarily subject to a procedural morality. On Fuller’s view, human activity is necessarily
goal-oriented or purposive in the sense that people engage in a particular activity because it helps
them to achieve some end. Insofar as human activity is essentially purposive, according to Fuller,
particular human activities can be understood only in terms that make reference to their purposes
and ends. Thus, since lawmaking is essentially purposive activity, it can be understood only in terms
that explicitly acknowledge its essential values and purposes:

The only formula that might be called a definition of law offered in these writings is by
now thoroughly familiar: law is the enterprise of subjecting human conduct to the
governance of rules. Unlike most modern theories of law, this view treats law as an
activity and regards a legal system as the product of a sustained purposive effort (Fuller
1964, 106).

To the extent that a definition of law can be given, then, it must include the idea that law’s essential

6 of 11 9/8/2010 10:50 PM
» Natural Law » Print [Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy] http://www.iep.utm.edu/natlaw/print/

function is to “achiev[e] [social] order through subjecting people’s conduct to the guidance of
general rules by which they may themselves orient their behavior” (Fuller 1965, 657).

Fuller’s functionalist conception of law implies that nothing can count as law unless it is capable of
performing law’s essential function of guiding behavior. And to be capable of performing this
function, a system of rules must satisfy the following principles:

(P1) the rules must be expressed in general terms;


(P2) the rules must be publicly promulgated;
(P3) the rules must be prospective in effect;
(P4) the rules must be expressed in understandable terms;
(P5) the rules must be consistent with one another;
(P6) the rules must not require conduct beyond the powers of the affected parties;
(P7) the rules must not be changed so frequently that the subject cannot rely on them; and
(P8) the rules must be administered in a manner consistent with their wording.

On Fuller’s view, no system of rules that fails minimally to satisfy these principles of legality can
achieve law’s essential purpose of achieving social order through the use of rules that guide
behavior. A system of rules that fails to satisfy (P2) or (P4), for example, cannot guide behavior
because people will not be able to determine what the rules require. Accordingly, Fuller concludes
that his eight principles are “internal” to law in the sense that they are built into the existence
conditions for law.

These internal principles constitute a morality, according to Fuller, because law necessarily has
positive moral value in two respects: (1) law conduces to a state of social order and (2) does so by
respecting human autonomy because rules guide behavior. Since no system of rules can achieve
these morally valuable objectives without minimally complying with the principles of legality, it
follows, on Fuller’s view, that they constitute a morality. Since these moral principles are built into
the existence conditions for law, they are internal and hence represent a conceptual connection
between law and morality. Thus, like the classical naturalists and unlike Finnis, Fuller subscribes to
the strongest form of the Overlap Thesis, which makes him a conceptual naturalist.

Nevertheless, Fuller’s conceptual naturalism is fundamentally different from that of classical


naturalism. First, Fuller rejects the classical naturalist view that there are necessary moral
constraints on the content of law, holding instead that there are necessary moral constraints on the
procedural mechanisms by which law is made and administered: “What I have called the internal
morality of law is … a procedural version of natural law … [in the sense that it is] concerned, not
with the substantive aims of legal rules, but with the ways in which a system of rules for governing
human conduct must be constructed and administered if it is to be efficacious and at the same time
remain what it purports to be” (Fuller 1964, 96- 97).

Second, Fuller identifies the conceptual connection between law and morality at a higher level of
abstraction than the classical naturalists. The classical naturalists view morality as providing
substantive constraints on the content of individual laws; an unjust norm, on this view, is
conceptually disqualified from being legally valid. In contrast, Fuller views morality as providing a
constraint on the existence of a legal system: “A total failure in any one of these eight directions
does not simply result in a bad system of law; it results in something that is not properly called a
legal system at all” (Fuller 1964, 39).

Fuller’s procedural naturalism is vulnerable to a number of objections. H.L.A. Hart, for example,
denies Fuller’s claim that the principles of legality constitute an internal morality; according to
Hart, Fuller confuses the notions of morality and efficacy:

[T]he author’s insistence on classifying these principles of legality as a “morality” is a


source of confusion both for him and his readers…. [T]he crucial objection to the
designation of these principles of good legal craftsmanship as morality, in spite of the
qualification “inner,” is that it perpetrates a confusion between two notions that it is vital

7 of 11 9/8/2010 10:50 PM
» Natural Law » Print [Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy] http://www.iep.utm.edu/natlaw/print/

to hold apart: the notions of purposive activity and morality. Poisoning is no doubt a
purposive activity, and reflections on its purpose may show that it has its internal
principles. (“Avoid poisons however lethal if they cause the victim to vomit”….) But to call
these principles of the poisoner’s art “the morality of poisoning” would simply blur the
distinction between the notion of efficiency for a purpose and those final judgments about
activities and purposes with which morality in its various forms is concerned (Hart 1965,
1285-86).

On Hart’s view, all actions, including virtuous acts like lawmaking and impermissible acts like
poisoning, have their own internal standards of efficacy. But insofar as such standards of efficacy
conflict with morality, as they do in the case of poisoning, it follows that they are distinct from
moral standards. Thus, while Hart concedes that something like Fuller’s eight principles are built
into the existence conditions for law, he concludes they do not constitute a conceptual connection
between law and morality.

Unfortunately, Hart overlooks the fact that most of Fuller’s eight principles double as moral ideals
of fairness. For example, public promulgation in understandable terms may be a necessary
condition for efficacy, but it is also a moral ideal; it is morally objectionable for a state to enforce
rules that have not been publicly promulgated in terms reasonably calculated to give notice of what
is required. Similarly, we take it for granted that it is wrong for a state to enact retroactive rules,
inconsistent rules, and rules that require what is impossible. Poisoning may have its internal
standards of efficacy, but such standards are distinguishable from the principles of legality in that
they conflict with moral ideals.

Nevertheless, Fuller’s principles operate internally, not as moral ideals, but merely as principles of
efficacy. As Fuller would likely acknowledge, the existence of a legal system is consistent with
considerable divergence from the principles of legality. Legal standards, for example, are
necessarily promulgated in general terms that inevitably give rise to problems of vagueness. And
officials all too often fail to administer the laws in a fair and even-handed manner even in the best of
legal systems. These divergences may always be prima facie objectionable, but they are inconsistent
with a legal system only when they render a legal system incapable of performing its essential
function of guiding behavior. Insofar as these principles are built into the existence conditions for
law, it is because they operate as efficacy conditions and not because they function as moral ideals.

5. Ronald Dworkin’s “Third Theory”


Ronald Dworkin’s so-called third theory of law is best understood as a response to legal positivism,
which is essentially constituted by three theoretical commitments: the Social Fact Thesis, the
Conventionality Thesis, and the Separability Thesis. The Social Fact Thesis asserts it is a necessary
truth that legal validity is ultimately a function of certain kinds of social facts; the idea here is that
what ultimately explains the validity of a law is the presence of certain social facts, especially formal
promulgation by a legislature.

The Conventionality Thesis emphasizes law’s conventional nature, claiming that the social facts
giving rise to legal validity are authoritative in virtue of a social convention. On this view, the
criteria that determine whether or not any given norm counts as a legal norm are binding because
of an implicit or explicit agreement among officials. Thus, for example, the U.S. Constitution is
authoritative in virtue of the conventional fact that it was formally ratified by all fifty states.

The Separability Thesis, at the most general level, simply denies naturalism’s Overlap Thesis;
according to the Separability Thesis, there is no conceptual overlap between the notions of law and
morality. As Hart more narrowly construes it, the Separability Thesis is “just the simple contention
that it is in no sense a necessary truth that laws reproduce or satisfy certain demands of morality,
though in fact they have often done so” (Hart 1994, 185-186).

Dworkin rejects positivism’s Social Fact Thesis on the ground that there are some legal standards

8 of 11 9/8/2010 10:50 PM
» Natural Law » Print [Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy] http://www.iep.utm.edu/natlaw/print/

the authority of which cannot be explained in terms of social facts. In deciding hard cases, for
example, judges often invoke moral principles that Dworkin believes do not derive their legal
authority from the social criteria of legality contained in a rule of recognition (Dworkin 1977, p. 40).

In Riggs v. Palmer, for example, the court considered the question of whether a murderer could
take under the will of his victim. At the time the case was decided, neither the statutes nor the case
law governing wills expressly prohibited a murderer from taking under his victim’s will. Despite
this, the court declined to award the defendant his gift under the will on the ground that it would be
wrong to allow him to profit from such a grievous wrong. On Dworkin’s view, the court decided the
case by citing “the principle that no man may profit from his own wrong as a background standard
against which to read the statute of wills and in this way justified a new interpretation of that
statute” (Dworkin 1977, 29).

On Dworkin’s view, the Riggs court was not just reaching beyond the law to extralegal standards
when it considered this principle. For the Riggs judges would “rightfully” have been criticized had
they failed to consider this principle; if it were merely an extralegal standard, there would be no
rightful grounds to criticize a failure to consider it (Dworkin 1977, 35). Accordingly, Dworkin
concludes that the best explanation for the propriety of such criticism is that principles are part of
the law.

Further, Dworkin maintains that the legal authority of standards like the Riggs principle cannot
derive from promulgation in accordance with purely formal requirements: “[e]ven though
principles draw support from the official acts of legal institutions, they do not have a simple or
direct enough connection with these acts to frame that connection in terms of criteria specified by
some ultimate master rule of recognition” (Dworkin 1977, 41).

On Dworkin’s view, the legal authority of the Riggs principle can be explained wholly in terms of its
content. The Riggs principle was binding, in part, because it is a requirement of fundamental
fairness that figures into the best moral justification for a society’s legal practices considered as a
whole. A moral principle is legally authoritative, according to Dworkin, insofar as it maximally
conduces to the best moral justification for a society’s legal practices considered as a whole.

Dworkin believes that a legal principle maximally contributes to such a justification if and only if it
satisfies two conditions: (1) the principle coheres with existing legal materials; and (2) the principle
is the most morally attractive standard that satisfies (1). The correct legal principle is the one that
makes the law the moral best it can be. Accordingly, on Dworkin’s view, adjudication is and should
be interpretive:

[J]udges should decide hard cases by interpreting the political structure of their
community in the following, perhaps special way: by trying to find the best justification
they can find, in principles of political morality, for the structure as a whole, from the
most profound constitutional rules and arrangements to the details of, for example, the
private law of tort or contract (Dworkin 1982, 165).

There are, thus, two elements of a successful interpretation. First, since an interpretation is
successful insofar as it justifies the particular practices of a particular society, the interpretation
must fit with those practices in the sense that it coheres with existing legal materials defining the
practices. Second, since an interpretation provides a moral justification for those practices, it must
present them in the best possible moral light.

For this reason, Dworkin argues that a judge should strive to interpret a case in roughly the
following way:

A thoughtful judge might establish for himself, for example, a rough “threshold” of fit
which any interpretation of data must meet in order to be “acceptable” on the dimension

9 of 11 9/8/2010 10:50 PM
» Natural Law » Print [Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy] http://www.iep.utm.edu/natlaw/print/

of fit, and then suppose that if more than one interpretation of some part of the law meets
this threshold, the choice among these should be made, not through further and more
precise comparisons between the two along that dimension, but by choosing the
interpretation which is “substantively” better, that is, which better promotes the political
ideals he thinks correct (Dworkin 1982, 171).

As Dworkin conceives it, then, the judge must approach judicial decision-making as something that
resembles an exercise in moral philosophy. Thus, for example, the judge must decide cases on the
basis of those moral principles that “figure[] in the soundest theory of law that can be provided as a
justification for the explicit substantive and institutional rules of the jurisdiction in question”
(Dworkin 1977, 66).

And this is a process, according to Dworkin, that “must carry the lawyer very deep into political and
moral theory.” Indeed, in later writings, Dworkin goes so far as to claim, somewhat implausibly,
that “any judge’s opinion is itself a piece of legal philosophy, even when the philosophy is hidden
and the visible argument is dominated by citation and lists of facts” (Dworkin 1986, 90).

Dworkin believes his theory of judicial obligation is a consequence of what he calls the Rights
Thesis, according to which judicial decisions always enforce pre-existing rights: “even when no
settled rule disposes of the case, one party may nevertheless have a right to win. It remains the
judge’s duty, even in hard cases, to discover what the rights of the parties are, not to invent new
rights retrospectively” (Dworkin 1977, 81).

In “Hard Cases,” Dworkin distinguishes between two kinds of legal argument. Arguments of policy
“justify a political decision by showing that the decision advances or protects some collective goal of
the community as a whole” (Dworkin 1977, 82). In contrast, arguments of principle “justify a
political decision by showing that the decision respects or secures some individual or group right”
(Dworkin 1977, 82).

On Dworkin’s view, while the legislature may legitimately enact laws that are justified by arguments
of policy, courts may not pursue such arguments in deciding cases. For a consequentialist
argument of policy can never provide an adequate justification for deciding in favor of one party’s
claim of right and against another party’s claim of right. An appeal to a pre-existing right,
according to Dworkin, can ultimately be justified only by an argument of principle. Thus, insofar as
judicial decisions necessarily adjudicate claims of right, they must ultimately be based on the moral
principles that figure into the best justification of the legal practices considered as a whole.

Notice that Dworkin’s views on legal principles and judicial obligation are inconsistent with all three
of legal positivism’s core commitments. Each contradicts the Conventionality Thesis insofar as
judges are bound to interpret posited law in light of unposited moral principles. Each contradicts
the Social Fact Thesis because these moral principles count as part of a community’s law regardless
of whether they have been formally promulgated. Most importantly, Dworkin’s view contradicts the
Separability Thesis in that it seems to imply that some norms are necessarily valid in virtue of their
moral content. It is his denial of the Separability Thesis that places Dworkin in the naturalist camp.

6. References and Further Reading


Thomas Aquinas, On Law, Morality and Politics (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co., 1988)
John Austin, Lectures on Jurisprudence and the Philosophy of Positive Law (St. Clair Shores, MI:
Scholarly Press, 1977)
John Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1995)
Jeremy Bentham, A Fragment of Government (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988)
Jeremy Bentham, Of Laws In General (London: Athlone Press, 1970) Jeremy Bentham, The
Principles of Morals and Legislation (New York: Hafner Press, 1948)

10 of 11 9/8/2010 10:50 PM
» Natural Law » Print [Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy] http://www.iep.utm.edu/natlaw/print/

Brian Bix, “On Description and Legal Reasoning,” in Linda Meyer (ed.), Rules and Reasoning
(Oxford: Hart Publishing, 1999)
Brian Bix, Jurisprudence: Theory and Context (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1996) Brian Bix,
“Natural Law Theory,” in Dennis M. Patterson (ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and
Legal Theory (Cambridge: Blackwell Publishing Co., 1996)
William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Law of England (Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press, 1979)
Jules L. Coleman, “On the Relationship Between Law and Morality,” Ratio Juris, vol. 2, no. 1
(1989), 66-78
Jules L. Coleman, “Negative and Positive Positivism,” 11 Journal of Legal Studies 139 (1982)
Jules L. Coleman and Jeffrie Murphy, Philosophy of Law (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1990)
Ronald M. Dworkin, Law’s Empire (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1986)
Ronald M. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977)
John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980)
John Finnis, “The Truth in Legal Positivism,” in Robert P. George, The Autonomy of Law (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1996), 195-214
Lon L. Fuller, The Morality of Law, Revised Edition (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1964)
Lon L. Fuller, “A Reply to Professors Cohen and Dworkin”, 10 Villanova Law Review 655 (1965),
657. Lon L. Fuller, “Positivism and Fidelity to Law–A Reply to Professor Hart,” 71 Harvard
Law Review 630 (1958)
Klaus F¸þer, “Farewell to ‘Legal Positivism’: The Separation Thesis Unravelling,” in George, The
Autonomy of Law, 119-162
Robert P. George, “Natural Law and Positive Law,” in George, The Autonomy of Law, 321-334
Robert P. George, Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992)
H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, Second Edition (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994)
H.L.A. Hart, “Book Review of The Morality of Law” 78 Harvard Law Review 1281 (1965) H.L.A.
Hart, Essays on Bentham (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982) H.L.A. Hart, “Positivism and the
Separation of Law and Morals,” 71 Harvard Law Review 593 (1958)
Kenneth Einar Himma, “Positivism, Naturalism, and the Obligation to Obey Law,” Southern
Journal of Philosophy, vol. 36, no. 2 (Summer 1999)
Kenneth Einar Himma, “Functionalism and Legal Theory: The Hart/Fuller Debate Revisited,” De
Philosophia, vol. 14, no. 2 (Fall/Winter 1998)
J.L. Mackie, “The Third Theory of Law,” Philosophy & Public Affairs, Vol. 7, No. 1 (Fall 1977)
Michael Moore, “Law as a Functional Kind,” in George, Natural Law Theory, 188- 242
Joseph Raz, The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979)
Joseph Raz, “Authority, Law and Morality,” The Monist, vol. 68, 295-324 Joseph Raz, “Legal
Principles and the Limits of Law,” 81 Yale Law Review 823 (1972)
Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, “The Many Moral Realisms,” in Sayre-McCord (ed.), Essays on Moral
Realism (Ithica: Cornell University Press, 1988)

Author Information

Kenneth Einar Himma


Email: himma@spu.edu
Seattle Pacific University

Article printed from Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://www.iep.utm.edu/natlaw/

Copyright © 2010 The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. All rights reserved.

11 of 11 9/8/2010 10:50 PM

Potrebbero piacerti anche