Sei sulla pagina 1di 48

New York University, School of Law

Public Law and Legal Theory Research Paper Series


Research Paper No. 68
and

University of Texas Law School


Public Law and Legal Theory Research Paper Series
Research Paper No. 55
August 2003

The Many as One:


Integrity and Group Choice in Paradoxical Cases

Lewis A. Kornhauser
Lawrence G. Sager

This paper can be downloaded without charge from the Social Science Research Network
Electronic Paper collection: http://ssrn.com/abstract_id=441466
THE MANY AS ONE: INTEGRITY AND GROUP CHOICE IN PARADOXICAL
CASES 1

by

Lewis A. Kornhauser2 and Lawrence G. Sager3

I. PARADOX AND THE LIMITS OF INTEGRITY

A. Integrity.

A recurring theme in recent discourse about political morality is the idea that political

communities should be understood not merely as the collective instrumentalities through which

individuals improve their well-being and discharge their obligations to their fellow citizens but as though

they themselves were moral agents,. This understanding of political communities permits -- or more

importantly, requires -- communities to hold and to act upon values and beliefs that may not

predominate, or. in combination, even exist, among the individuals that compose the community. The

obvious fact that political communities can only act through individuals does not undercut the idea of

community agency: In assessing what acts may appropriately be taken in the name of the community,

these theories direct officials to recognize and conform to the moral responsibilities that attach to the

community that underwrites their public acts.

1
Copyright 2002 Lewis A. Kornhauser and Lawrence G. Sager
2
Alfred and Gail Engelberg Professor of Law, New York University
3
Alice Jane Drysdale Sheffield Regents Chair in Law, University of Texas. We thank Jean-
Pierre Benoit, Brian Leiter, ? and participants in faculty seminars at NYU School of Law and The
University of Texas School of Law. Both authors gratefully acknowledge the financial support of the
Filomen d’Agostino and Max E. Greenberg Research Fund of New York University School of Law.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 2

Ronald Dworkin has given a name and a paradigmatic form to the idea of community agency,

arguing for the independent political virtue of "integrity". 4 Integrity requires that the normative choices of

a political community enjoy the same constancy and coherence that we would expect of the

comparable decisions of single person. For an independent political virtue of community behavior in

general, integrity in Dworkin's hands seems oddly fixated on the behavior of judges, but that is not our

principal concern here. For our purposes, Dworkin's integrity is a quintessential instance of community

agency, requiring that the community behave as though it were an individual, with responsibilities keyed

to its own communal acts.

More recently, Philip Pettit has adopted a view of "republican community" and deliberative

democracy that takes the idea of integrity seriously as a requirement of political life generally.5 While

Pettit does not invoke the virtue of integrity in name, he, like Dworkin, wants to personify the political

community (and many other groups as well), making the group as a whole -- rather than its members

individually--accountable for reasoned choice. To this end, Pettit has argued that collective action by a

political community or other deliberative group is justified only when there is agreement on the reasons

underlying the action in question; agreement merely on outcomes is not sufficient. This demand assumes

special force in a group of cases – which we have in our earlier writing called paradoxical cases –

where a group’s consensus on underlying reasons diverges from that group’s consensus on the ultimate

4
Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire esp. Chapters 5 and 6. (Harvard University Press 1986)
5
Philip Pettit, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government, (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1997); Pettit, “Democracy, Electoral and Contestatory,” Nomos (forthcoming); Pettit,
“The Discursive Dilemma and Social Ontology” mimeo.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 3

outcome. In paradoxical cases, Pettit's insistence on the priority of underlying reasons will lead to

outcomes that would be rejected by the community in a referendum, and could lead to combinations of

outcomes that would be supported by few if any members of the community.

We first encountered the phenomenon of paradoxical cases in the course of our study of

adjudication by multi-judge courts. A multi-judge court has at least two quite distinct ways of collecting

the votes of its member judges and producing results in the cases before the court: the court can

decide each salient issue by a vote among the judges, and then arrive at an outcome by assembling

these results of these salient issues according to the logic dictated by doctrine. In a contract case for

example, the court as a whole can decide first whether there was a valid contract entered into by the

parties, and second, whether there was a material breach of that contract. Doctrine then dictates that

the court find that there is an actionable breach of promise if and only if the plaintiff prevailed on each of

these questions. Or the court can decide the case as a whole. Assuming in this instance that there is no

controversy as to the correct remedy, each judge then will vote directly on the question of whether the

conduct of the plaintiff was an actionable breach of promise, and the court will tally these bottom-line

votes to arrive at its aggregate judgment in the case. To be sure, in this second instance doctrine will

dictate that each judge decide for herself whether there was valid contract and whether there was a

material breach, but the relevant judgment from the court’s standpoint will be the judges’ bottom line on

the case as a whole. In most cases, nothing will turn on this choice of voting protocols. But in some

cases, the views of the judges will be such that tallying their votes on salient issues will produce a

different outcome than will tallying their votes on the case as a whole. These are what we call
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 4

paradoxical cases, and in paradoxical cases – where reasons and outcomes pull apart – the court’s

choice of voting protocols will be decisive to the outcome of the case.

When we encountered the phenomenon of paradoxical cases, we asked whether multi-judge

courts should proceed on an issue-by-issue or case-by-case basis. Even in the relatively bounded and

formal context of Anglo-American adjudication, we found ourselves strongly of the view that a

sweeping choice in favor of either multi-judge protocol would be a mistake: there are good reasons

which cut in favor of each; and in some circumstances the best course for a multi-judge court clearly

will be to attend to issues while other circumstances will demand that a multi-judge court attend to

outcomes.6 {{Say a bit more}}

We revisit paradoxical cases in this essay, and do so in the broader setting of democratic

group choice. In this setting, we conclude, it is even clearer that a blanket norm ceding priority to

either reasons or outcomes is neither practical nor desirable: In real world political communities such a

blanket norm would be impossible to effectuate without radical alteration of existing institutions; and,

were we willing and to make such radical changes, we would be if anything worse off for the venture.

Also of interest to us in this essay is the conceptual difficulty that paradoxical cases pose for an

integrity theorist. As we shall see, the salient feature of paradoxical cases is precisely that a group

which confronts such cases cannot behave as would an ideal individual decision-maker. A group

6
Kornhauser and Sager, “Unpacking the Court,” 96 Yale L.J. 82 -117 (1986); Kornhauser,
"Modeling Collegial Courts I: Path Dependence," 12 Internat'l Rev. Law & Econ. 169 (1992).;
Kornhauser, "Modeling Collegial Courts. II. Legal Doctrine," 8 J. Law, Econ. & Org. 441 (1992);
Kornhauser and Sager, "The One and the Many: Adjudication in Collegial Courts," 81 Calif. L. Rev.
1 (1993) .
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 5

which decides a paradoxical case has to choose between integrity in reasons and integrity in outcomes.

Perfect integrity is impossible. That being so, a theorist who argues for group integrity has to be

satisfied with partial integrity, and moreover, has to explain why the part of integrity upon which he is

insisting is the right part. Seen in this light, the work of both Phillip Pettit and Ronald Dworkin is

conceptually incomplete: Both offer what are in fact partial conceptions of integrity; partial conceptions

that are at radical odds with each other. But neither acknowledges the partial quality of his conception

and perforce neither fully defends the particular slice of integrity upon which he insists.

B. The Impossibility of Perfect Integrity in Paradoxical Cases

Layered Choices. Most decisions by individuals (and therefore by groups) are layered: in

potential, at least, they can be described or motivated at more than one level. If, for example, Liza

decides to put down her murder mystery and turn to the enterprise of writing an essay, we could stop

just there and observe that Liza had made a choice. But we could press further and try to understand

how to justify or explain that choice: It might be that as of that moment Liza found writing more

pleasant than reading her mystery. But quite the reverse could also be true and she could have acted

out of a realization that the essay has a deadline attached that begs for action. Or she may feel that in

some other way she will be letting her co-author down if she does not work on the essay. Or perhaps

she has a view about how one should spend one’s time. Or perhaps she believes that the publication of

her essay is vital to the world in some way.

Behind each of these reasons, however they cut, are other reasons. Liza may like to write
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 6

because it exercises her mind in a way that she finds pleasant or gratifying. Or she may not like to

write because it makes her anxious. The deadline may be important because Liza likes the journal or

because she feels indebted to its editors, and so on.

At the individual level, at least in principle, it ought to be possible to make sense out of Liza’s

decision to lay the book aside and fire up her computer. Her interests and judgments may press in

different ways and need to be set off against one another; and it is unlikely that she has in any

conscious way taken account of all reasons she has for choosing one course against the other. And

heavens knows that akrasia – a failure of the will -- is more than a theoretical possibility. But in

principle, Liza can hope that her decision, all-things-considered, connects rationally to the things that

she values.

Group Choice and Paradox. When we move to group decisions, however, this rational

connection between decisions (outcomes) and reasons may not be possible, even setting aside human

foibles and the limits of vision and understanding. We can hope that the interests and judgments of

each individual who is contributing to the decisions are rationally supportive of the chosen outcome of

the matter at hand; but when we aggregate the views of the participating individuals it may be logically

impossible to line up the prevailing views at each pertinent level with those at other levels.

Multi-judge courts offer a clear instance of the impossibility of group rationality in certain cases.

Suppose that a panel of three judges must decide a tort case that raises both a causation and a duty

issue. For plaintiff to prevail, she must show that defendant’s negligence caused her injury and that the
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 7

defendant had a duty to take care.7 The question of whether the defendant had a duty towards the

plaintiff is clearly a legal one. The causation questions, framed as a question of law, is: Could a

reasonable person have concluded that the defendant’s actions caused the harm? Legal doctrine

determines the relation between the various resolutions of these two issues and the outcome in the case.

Actual tort doctrine requires that, for plaintiff to prevail, she must prevail on each issue. Suppose that

the judgments of each of the three judges is as in table 1:

Table 1

Palsgraf v. Long Island Railroad


Causation Duty Individual View of Case

Judge X Y Y Y

Judge Y N Y N

Judge Z Y N N

Aggregated View of Issues Y Y Y / N

The court might aggregate its votes in either of two ways. First, under a case-by-case protocol

(outcome-based voting), each judge considers each issue and, given the doctrine, reaches a decision in

the case. In the case in table 1, then, the court rules that plaintiff has no right to recover because a

majority of the court – judges Y and Z – believe that plaintiff has no right to recover.

Alternatively, the court might choose to aggregate its judgments issue-by-issue (reason-based

voting). Under this procedure, each judge reaches a judgment on each issue and the court renders

7
These two issues are presented by Palsgraf v. Long Island Railroad.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 8

judgment on each issue by a majority vote. Doctrine then determines the resolution of the case. Under

this aggregation procedure, the court rules that plaintiff is entitled to recover because two of three

judges – X and Z – conclude that defendant caused plaintiff’s injury while two judges – X and Y

conclude that defendant had a duty. 8 The result of the adjudication thus depends critically on which

voting procedure the court adopts.

“Perfect” Integrity and Paradoxical Group Decisions. In our earlier work we called this

conflict between the results of the different aggregation methods the doctrinal paradox; when it

obtains, a court must choose between aggregating its members’ judgments over the relevant issues and

aggregating its members’ judgments over the case itself. As Philip Pettit has emphasized, a

comparably paradoxical distribution of preferences or judgments could exist in any group with regard to

a looming decision. We might then do well to change vocabularies from “issues” and “cases” to the

more generic “reasons” and “outcomes”, but the paradoxical distribution makes much the same

mischief: In paradoxical cases a group can rationally order its impulses over the applicable reasons by

voting on them; or it can rationally order its impulses over the applicable outcomes by voting on them,

but it cannot do both. In contrast, an idealized individual who had worked out all the kinks could

rationally order her views over both her reasons and her bottom-line choices or outcomes. If that is

what integrity requires, perfect integrity is impossible for groups.

8
The U.S. Supreme Court does not in fact use either procedure. As we noted in “The One and
the Many,” supra note?, the choice between the two procedures described in the text is not centralized
by formal Court rule or even by settled by Court practice. In actual practice, each justice determines
how to aggregate votes when s/he casts her own ballot.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 9

Integrity and Paradox in Ronald Dworkin’s and Philip Pettit’s Work. The demand that

the decisions of groups be integrated in the way that we think the decisions of individuals should be

integrated can assume a number of forms. Integrity might be concerned with the integration of different

views held by members of a decision-making group with regard to a single decision; for convenience

we can call this synchronic integrity. Integrity might be concerned with the integration of a string of

decisions made by the group over time; we can call this diachronic integrity. Both synchronic and

diachronic integrity can be further subdivided: Either might be concerned with the integration of the

reasons behind a group’s decision or with the outcomes reached by the group. We can depict these

possible targets of the demand for integration in a simple matrix:

INTEGRITY Synchronic Diachronic

Reasons I: Synchronic, Reasons III: Diachronic, Reasons

Outcomes II: Synchronic, Outcomes IV: Diachronic, Outcomes

For Ronald Dworkin, integrity is concerned solely with Box IV on this matrix, with the

integration of the substantive outcomes over time. Dworkinian judges must have reasons for their

decisions, and their reasons are constrained and inspired by prior decisions; but it is the bottom line of

those prior decisions, not the reasons contemporaneously offered to justify them that matters. So

Hercules – Dworkin’s idealized judge– labors to find the best normative principle that retrospectively

fits the outcomes of his court’s prior decisions.

Synchronic integration has never been part of Dworkin’s articulated view of the requirements of
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 10

integrity. This may account for a prominent limitation in Dworkin’s otherwise rich vision of legal

adjudication. However busy Hercules finds himself to be, he is condemned to labor on alone;

Dworkin has never turned his attention to the fact that appellate adjudication is conducted by groups,

and hence has never taken up the variety of questions involving group deliberation and group resolution.

Given the great emphasis on adjudicatory responsibility in his work, this lacuna is a misfortune, since it

leaves many interesting and problematic choices of a conscientious judge unaddressed. Why does an

increase in the number of judges contribute to the capacity of an appellate court to arrive at the best

decision?9 Should the judge who would be Hercules always render the best decision conceived of in

isolation, or should she compromise her views of the best decision with an eye to bringing the court of

which she is a member as close as possible to the best decision? Is the license of a judge to continue to

dissent from principles upon which the majority of the court has agreed measured strictly and simply by

the demands of fit and value that Hercules would confront on his own, or are there additional variables

of obligation introduced by the group nature of appellate adjudication? One of the matters

pretermitted by Hercules’ solipsism and Dworkin’s underlying preoccupation with diachronic

integration is the doctrinal paradox and its threat to perfect integrity.10

9
Kornhauser and Sager, “Unpacking the Court,” 96 Yale L.J. 82 -117 (1986).
10
When a judge Liza sits on a collegial court, she does not have complete control over the
outcome of the case. Her judgment with the judgment of the other judges on the panel will determine
the result in the case before her. What does it mean, in these circumstances, for her to make the law
the best it can be? Dworkin might answer this question in a variety of distinct ways. He might
contend, for example, that Liza ought to behave as the single judge does in his current theory; she
should vote for the outcome dictated by her best interpretation of the law and express those reasons in
her opinion regardless of how other judges might vote. On the other hand, Dworkin might believe
that, in some circumstances, Liza should write (or join) an opinion that expresses reasons that differ in
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 11

Philip Pettit, in contrast, is acutely concerned with synchronic integration, with the appropriate

connection between a given decision by a group and the distribution of opinions within that group as to

the decision in question. For him, accordingly, paradoxical cases are very much in the picture, not so

much as a problem, perhaps, as an opportunity – an opportunity because when a group’s consensus

over reasons and its consensus over outcomes pull apart we have the occasion to ask which consensus

should matter and why.

Pettit, as we have seen, emphatically casts his lot with group reasons. His reasons for a

sweeping embrace of reasons grow out of his visions of deliberative democracy and the justification of

a group’s authority over members of the group whose interests may be adversely affected by the

exercise of that authority. Pettit believes that a group is justified in imposing on its members when it

has committed itself to underlying premises – to reasons– underlying a proposed imposition. Further,

he stresses, members of the group must have had a well-formed opportunity to contest the relevant

underlying premises or reasons. It follows, Pettit, believes, that it is the collective state of the group’s

judgment as to reasons that must matter.

Our contrast of Dworkin’s and Pettit’s view reveals another important dimension of theories of

integrity: integrity’s plausibility, normative appeal practical requirements may vary across political

institutions. Here too the views of Dworkin and Pettit present a sharp and largely undefended contrast:

some respects from her own best interpretation. This latter view is more plausible when one believes
that Liza’s interpretation must make sense not only of the result in a case – whether plaintiff prevailed or
not– but also of the reasons offered in the opinion for that result. If one adopted this second position on
Dworkinian adjudication, distributions of opinion that yield a doctrinal paradox will indeed present
difficult cases for Dworkinian judges.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 12

Dworkin, while stipulating in passing that integrity binds all political actors, is all but exclusively

preoccupied with the decisions of judges; Pettit, on the other hand, largely ignores judges and courts,

and focuses on legislators. The polarity of Dworkin’s and Pettit’s views is thus perfect: Dworkin offers

a conception of diachronic, outcome-based judicial integrity; Pettit provides a conception of

synchronic, reason-based legislative integrity.

To summarize: (1) It is in the nature or definition of paradoxical cases that perfect integrity is

impossible; (2) Neither Dworkin nor Pettit in fact aims at perfect integrity; and (3) On the most salient

integrative criteria, Dworkin and Pettit find themselves at nearly polar odds, with Dworkin concerned

with integrity of outcomes across cases and Pettit concerned with integrity of reasons across the

opinions held by the members of a given group with regard to a particular decision,.11 and (4) The

contrast between Dworkin and Pettit extends to the level of institutions, with Dworkin all but exclusively

preoccupied with courts and Pettit with legislatures or their equivalent.

In much of what follows, our concern is with extended our consideration of paradoxical cases

into the broader domain of democratic group choice. Broadly, our critical focus will be on the idea of

reason-based, legislative integrity. But there are at least two propositions that we hope to draw from

the refinement of the idea of integrity made possible by a comparison of Dworkin’s and Pettit’s versions

11
In Section __, below, we observe that Pettit’s concern with integrity across a group’s
member’s reasons for resolving a single question before it irresistibly entails a concern with integrity of
a group’s decision across cases. It is possible that Dworkin’s concern with integrity across a group’s
outcomes over time has a similar entailment regarding integrity across a group’s members basis for their
choice in an individual case. We are unaware of any such entailment, however. We mention the
possibility of symmetry to signal the rich and largely unexplored territory of integrity as a norm of group
behavior.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 13

of integrity. First, however appealing the basic idea of holding groups to account as though they were

individuals may be, it cannot without more be the grounds for either Pettit’s insistence on the priority of

reasons or Dworkin’s view of the behavior of the ideal judge. In paradoxical cases, at least, perfect

integrity is impossible, and the partial conceptions of integrity favored by both Pettit and Dworkin

require a defense before they can do any work at all. Second, although the brunt of our argument is

directed against Pettit’s position, we will spend some time suggesting that while Dworkin is exempt

from our criticisms of Pettit, precisely those features of Dworkin’s view that exempt him from the

difficulties faced by Pettit are grounds for some of most serious doubts about Dworkin’s view.

But, for the moment, it is reason-based, legislative integrity that draws our attention. We begin

by showing that groups make many different kinds of decisions, and further, that the demands or

reason-based integrity are obviously implausible with regard to many types of group decisions.

II. GROUPS AND REASONS

A. The Choice of a Restaurant. Suppose three friends plan to go to dinner together, and

undertake to choose a restaurant. Only two restaurants are in contention, and the friends divide as

follows: Jane and Patricia favor Jean Pierre's Bistro, and Lisa favors Ribs-R'-Us. Barring some

exceptional circumstance, Jean Pierre's Bistro carries the day, a commonplace instance of petit (not

Pettit) democracy. There are good reasons for this outcome, reasons sounding both in treating each

friend as an equal and in roughly maximizing their aggregate welfare.

Each of the friends’ choice of restaurant, of course, is an “outcome” of sorts, driven by her own
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 14

reason or reasons. But nothing encourages us to push past the friends' bottom line choices of restaurant

to their reasons for their respective choices; it is clear that the trio should simply go to the restaurant

favored by two of them, full stop. If somehow we were tempted to learn of their reasons, nothing

would change.

Imagine, for example, that we learn that Patricia favors Jean Pierre's because she knows the

owner, and strongly prefers a friendly environment when she dines out; Jane's choice of Jean Pierre's is

based on the quality of the food served there; and Liza's choice of Ribs-R'-Us is based on its location

(It's a cold day, and the ribs joint is just around the corner). Note that the absence of any agreement

on reasons is unproblematic from the vantage of either equity or welfare.

Or imagine that we encounter a somewhat more interesting structure of reasons. In this

variation, we learn that within broad geographic and other ancillary concerns, Patricia's restaurant

choices are only driven by the quality of the food served, and that in her view, Jean Pierre's wins hands

down; Liza too is motivated by concerns of quality, but she believes Ribs R.Us is the better restaurant.

Jane, by contrast, is relatively indifferent to food quality, and always chooses on grounds of

convenience, and in this variation, Jean Pierre's is just around the corner. If pressed to offer her view of

quality, Jane would emphatically agree with Liza that Ribs R’Us produces a better meal. It may help to

view this structure of reasons schematically:


Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 15

Table 2

The Restaurant Case With A Paradoxical Structure of Reasons


Quality Convenience Grounds of Choice Individual

Outcomes

Patricia BISTRO -- Quality BISTRO

Lisa RIBS -- Quality RIBS

Jane RIBS BISTRO Convenience BISTRO

Aggregated Reasons RIBS ? Quality RIBS / BISTRO

This distribution of reasons is, as a formal matter, paradoxical. If a vote were taken first on the

question of whether quality or proximity should be the test, Patricia and Lisa would prevail on quality

being the guide. And if then the question of which restaurant served better food was put, the views of

Jane and Lisa would prevail and Ribs-R'-Us would win the day. But asked simply which restaurant

they wanted to eat at, Patricia and Lisa would agree on Jean Pierre's.

This case, however, is paradoxical in form only. As we noted at the outset, the reasons the

friends have for their choices are unimportant in a case like this, and the choice of Jean Pierre’s Bistro

thus remains the unexceptional outcome. It would be bizarre to deny Jane her capacity to vote for

Jean Pierre's on grounds of proximity, notwithstanding the preference of her compatriots for quality

over convenience.

B. Group Decisions That Aggregate Preferences. We can generalize from the restaurant

example: group choices that depend on the aggregation of individual preferences are poor candidates
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 16

for the claim that it is individual reasons rather than individual outcomes that should govern if the two

should pull apart. The scope and force of this observation, of course, depend on what we mean when

we speak of individual preferences and of groups decisions that depend on them. It is to this prior

question that we now turn.

1. Preferences and Judgments. Preferences are those qualitative rankings or choices over

which the individual is in a familiar way sovereign. Consider Marina who must choose her diet. She

may express a preference for fish over meat –all things considered she would rather eat sole than

sirloin. Contrast this expression of preference with the rendering of a judgment concerning the same

dietary choice, in which Marina asserts that fish is healthier than meat. Marina’s preference for fish

differs from her parallel judgment about its healthiness in at least two respects.

First, Marina’s expression of preference is a personal claim; her assertion that she prefers sole

to sirloin does not imply that others do or ought to do likewise. Second, an individual is sovereign over

her preferences but not over her judgments. Sovereignty, in this context, means that the individual has

the final say on the content of her preferences. So, if Marina’s friend Henry expresses a preference for

meat over fish, that gives, Marina no reason to reconsider her own preference. To be sure, Henry can

plausibly assert that Marina in fact prefers meat to fish;12 Marina can surely be wrong about her

preferences, as, for example, she might discover when she finally relented and permitted herself to

12
Henry might point to instances in which Marina chose meat over fish or to remarks she made
when she tasted each. These assertions are evidence of Marina’s preference and Marina might have
erred in her initial expression of preference for fish. But she may not have. She can always reconcile
her prior choices in some way; she may even assert that her preference has changed.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 17

enjoy sirloin -- or for that matter, green eggs and ham. And she could be mistaken about the

connection between her preferences and her preference-driven choices, as could be the case with

Patricia in the paradoxical form of our restaurant story if unbeknownst to her the chef and menu of Jean

Pierre's had changed for the worse; or with Jane if it turned out that there was a shortcut to Ribs R’ Us

that made the trip there the shortest and most protected from the rain and cold. But in all of these

cases and others like them, in the end, it is ultimately a claim about Marina and about her preferences

among various states of affairs that must govern. In this sense Marina is sovereign in the domain of her

preferences.

Judgments, in contrast, are general rather than personal in their scope. When Marina judges

sole healthier than sirloin, she makes a broader claim, one that extends to others. That is, Marina does

not claim merely that sole is healthier than sirloin for her but that it is healthier for some class of

individuals.13

Moreover, judgments perforce appeal to external standards of validity. The speaker is not

sovereign over the judgments she renders; she cannot, simply by rendering a judgment, insure its

validity. If Henry contradicts her claim that sole is healthier than sirloin, Marina has reason to reconsider

her judgment. Both Marina and Henry are subjects of the best answer to the question of the healthiness

13
In some instances, Marina’s claim might be “x is healthier than y for me”. If Marina has low
blood pressure, for example, she might assert that a very salty dish is healthier for her than a low salt
dish even if the low salt dish is healthier for most people. Even in this context, however, Marina’s claim
applies to everyone similarly situated; i.e., to everyone with a similar physiology. Her preference for
fish over meat, however, is purely personal; it does not generalize to anyone else, no matter how
similar. Marina’s identical twin Bovia, with identical genetic make-up, raised in the same family, and
the product of the same schools quite sensibly may express a preference for meat over fish.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 18

of the two foods: Neither is sovereign over that question.

2. Preference Aggregation And The Primacy Of Outcomes. As the restaurant example

illustrates, groups engaged in the business of aggregating preferences typically will have very good

reasons for ignoring the reasons underlying their members’ preferences.

The obvious primacy of overall preferences or outcomes in the restaurant cases in not an

artifact of the relative banality of the stakes in these cases or of some other special aspect of the

example. Preference-driven group decisions will typically look like this. Consider an example where

members of a community are deciding whether to give road-building or enhancement of the commons

first call on a budgetary surplus. And imagine that the members who favor one alternative or the other

have very different reasons for preferring their alternative of choice: Some want a commons for sheep-

grazing, some for bucolic beauty, and so forth. Likewise the road project, whose supporters are

composed by sub-groups with very different reasons for their common enthusiasm. Like our first

restaurant variation, it seems unimportant that the favored alternative is supported by a collection of

reasons, no one of which commands majority support; and this would be true even if one of the reasons

for the disfavored alternative commanded more support than any one of the reasons for the favored

alternative. Or, suppose that the distribution of community preferences over the choice is paradoxical,

so that a choice has to be made between reasons and outcome. Where a clear majority favor one

alternative on an overall, all-things-considered basis, it seems obvious that the favored alternative is the

one that ought to be pursued.

Many political choices made by legislatures will have this structure. The polity aims to
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 19

maximize the welfare of its citizens – or, at least, to further that welfare. That task requires the

determination and aggregation of the preferences of the citizenry. When these preferences conflict, as

they do in the example in the previous paragraph, a concern for equality supports the use of majority

rule to resolve the conflict. If an individual contests the community decision, the community need not,

and does not, respond, at the level of reasons underlying individual preferences but at the level of

reasons for the choice of majority rule as the appropriate mechanism for aggregating conflicting

preferences.

The point, it bears emphasis, is not that preference-driven choices by groups are unreasoned.

Rather, the point is that groups have the best of reasons -- equity and overall welfare -- for responding

to the bottom-line preferences of their members when confronted with such choices.

B. Group Decisions That Aggregate Judgments

We turn, then, to group decisions that aggregate judgments. Here another distinction presents

itself: the distinction between judgments of fact and judgments of value. We might express this

distinction more accurately as the distinction between descriptive and evaluative judgments, thereby

evading some questions concerning the ontology of values.

1. Aggregating Judgments of Fact. Imagine that a community is considering a proposal to

reduce automobile emissions radically (RAD), at a considerable cost to the present economy and to the

welfare of many present members of the community. The goad to consider such a dramatic proposal is

a view among some that failing such a step, the greenhouse effect in the foreseeable future will produce

so substantial a rise in temperature as to diminish drastically the welfare of the community (HOT).
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 20

There is unanimous agreement that if this dire prophesy is correct then RAD is the appropriate course.

The only disagreement is factual. Some are confident of HOT. Some think that the science upon which

HOT is based is simply wrong, and that even if the community continues on the trajectory of its present

behavior and technology, the greenhouse effect will be trivial or possibly even non-existent. Some hold

yet another view (NEW), to the effect that even if HOT were an accurate prediction under present

technology, new technology will come along which will rescue the community from HOT without the

painful remedy of RAD under present technology. But everyone agrees that if HOT is true and NEW

is false, then and only then is RAD justified. Imagine that the decision has been confided to a panel of

three expert policymakers, who, as it happens, exactly mirror the distribution of factual judgments

among the entire scientific community, as well as the community as a whole:

Table 3

Factual Judgments With Regard to RAD


HOT NEW INDIVIDUAL SUPPORT OF RAD

PM X Y N Y

PM Y Y Y N

PM Z N N N

AGGREGATED REASONS Y N Y / N

Note that once we have moved from the realm of preference to that of judgment, it no longer

seems nonsensical to suggest that reasons rather than outcome should be favored in the event that they
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 21

paradoxically pull apart.

There are two concerns --possibly overlapping --implicated by the choice of voting

protocols in such a case. The first is epistemic: the community has a large stake in getting the

answer to this predictive question right. The second is democratic: In the face of entrenched

factual disagreement the question is whether fairness sponsors the choice of one voting protocol

over the other.

On epistemic grounds the choice of voting protocol would seem to depend on close

questions of the state of empirical conviction. Imagine, first, the following case, with the

numbers reflecting the state of certainty with which the policy makers hold their various views:

Table 4

Convictions With Regard to RAD


HOT NEW INDIVIDUAL SUPPORT OF RAD

PM X Y,.55 N,.55 Y

PM Y Y,.55 Y,.92 N

PM Z N,.92 N,.55 N

AGGREGATED REASONS Y N Y / N
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 22

We assume that each policymaker’s individual views are structured so that HOT and NEW are

exhaustive of the concerns that motivate their bottom line judgments as to RAD, and that the

strength and direction of their bottom line judgments are connected with perfect rationality to their

judgments about HOT and NEW.

The panel must resolve two questions in reaching its decision. The first question confronts

even a single individual: what relation ought rationally to hold between her degrees of belief in the

three propositions HOT, NEW, and RAD? The second question addresses the problem of

aggregation: given that individuals have different beliefs about a given proposition or set of

propositions, how ought these differences be reconciled?

Economists and many others offer an unequivocal answer to the first question. The logic of

belief is the logic of probability. If an individual’s convictions concerning HOT and NEW rest on

independent grounds, then her degree of belief in RAD ought simply to be the product of her

degree of belief in HOT times her degree of belief in not-NEW. If we construe depth of conviction

as a judgment as to the probability of the relevant events (first: global warming absent technological

rescue, second: technological rescue) occurring, then PM X should actually believe that there is

only about a 30 per cent chance that the risk against which RAD would be deployed would

eventuate in the absence of RAD;14 PM Y would believe that there is less than one-half of one per

cent chance of that risk eventuating;15 and PM Z would evaluate the risk similarly to PM Y.16

14
.55 (HOT) * .55(~NEW)=.3025.
15
.55(HOT) * .08(~NEW)=.044.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 23

The economic approach to depth of conviction is not uncontroversial. The practice of

fact-finding in a civil trial, for example, seems to require that someone who believes HOT with a

degree of conviction of .55, and disbelieves NEW, again with a degree of conviction of .55, should

endorse RAD; probability calculus, on the other hand, would require the rejection of RAD as it is

only supported by a probability of roughly .3. And the segmented approach to questions of fact

pursued by the civil jury has academic defenders.17 But for our present purposes, we shall assume

that the economic approach of multiplying probabilities or something very much like it would be a

rational guide to individual judgment in our RAD example.

We turn now to the problem of aggregating the varying depths of conviction across

individuals. Consider the following rough, intuitively plausible analysis.18 If we assume, in the

absence of information to the contrary, that each policymaker is as reliable as each other, and

further, give the degree of conviction with which each holds her view the same weight, then we have

good reason to reject RAD on empirical grounds. On the question of HOT, the total units of

conviction (on a scale of 1 to 100) in favor of HOT is 118 (55 + 55 + 8); and against HOT, 182

16
.08 (HOT) * .55(~NEW)=.044.
17
For example, see Brilmayer and Kornhauser, "Review: Quantitative Methods in the Law,"
46 University of Chicago Law Review 116 (1978); L. Jonathon Cohen The Probable and the
Provable; Glenn Shafer,
18
We are aware of no widely accepted approach to this question. Genest and Zidek,
“Combining Probability Distributions: A Critique and an Annotated Bibliography,” 1 Statistical Science
114-118 (1986) reviews the relevant literature. It is not clear that our intuitive approach conforms to
any of the procedures surveyed in Genest and Zidek, though it might be represented by a weighted
average approach.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 24

(45 + 45 + 92). By the same margin of aggregated units of conviction, NEW prevails. Thus HOT

would be rejected and NEW accepted and RAD would be rejected on redundant grounds. If we

apply the same method directly to the bottom line convictions of the policymakers, RAD is rejected

by exactly the same margin ( RAD: 30 + 44 + 44 = 118; ~RAD: 70 + 56 + 56 = 118). Outcome

voting reflects the epistemic advantage of ~RAD. Even if each policymaker ignores the strength of

her judgments simply combines her judgments statically to arrive at an outcome, outcome voting

favors the rejection of RAD, by the vote of two to one (See Table 4). And if each policymaker

combines her judgments dynamically, and takes account of the probabilistic consequences of

combining her judgments the picture will be even more stark. Under these, dynamic,

circumstances, PM X will decide that while she believes HOT and disbelieves NEW, her

probabilistic confidence in the combination of these judgments is so low (.30) that she ought to

disfavor RAD; the outcome vote would then b e 3-0 against RAD, while the premise vote would

continue to favor RAD 2-1.19 Under these circumstances, accordingly, epistemic concerns would

seem to strongly favor outcome voting rather than premise voting.

Now, we could certainly cook the books in the other direction. Suppose the distribution of

confidence among the policy-makers as to their judgments ran something like this:

19
All this is put a little too crudely perhaps, since the rational community will presumably want
RAD even when there is a less than even chance of unabated global warming, if that chance is
substantial. But this simply means that the thresholds of HOT, NEW and RAD have to be redefined in
a more subtle and complex way to include a more precise statement of the costs of global warming and
RAD, and the community’s vector of risk-adverseness. This redescription does not affect the analysis
we offer here.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 25

Table 5

Altered Convictions With Regard to RAD


HOT NEW INDIVIDUAL SUPPORT OF RAD

PM X Y,.92 N,.92 Y

PM Y Y,.92 Y,.55 N

PM Z N,.55 N,.92 N

AGGREGATED REASONS Y N Y / N

Under these circumstances, premise voting has considerably more epistemic appeal. Our point,

bear in mind, is not that epistemic concerns favor either premise or outcome voting in factual

judgment cases; our point is that a sweeping claim on behalf of either protocol under these

circumstances is suspect.

So far in our discussion of factual judgments by groups with the RAD example, we have

been assuming that the policymakers individual views are structured so that HOT and NEW are

exhaustive of the concerns that motivate their bottom line judgments as to RAD, and that the

strength and direction of the policymakers’ bottom line judgments are connected with perfect

rationality to their judgments about HOT and NEW. But while that assumption may hold in some

instances, there are surely others where it will not. We can imagine some circumstances – focusing

for the moment on the structure of convictions held by a single Policymaker – in which what we

have for these purposes been treating as an outcome is more firmly supported by the conviction of

a Policymaker than could be accounted for by her conviction with regard to those smaller elements

of judgment that we have described as reasons for the outcome. In the RAD case, for example,
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 26

PM Y and PM Z could be either substantially more or substantially less convinced of the bottom

line proposition that the community ultimately will evade the dire effects of global warming despite

its decision not to adopt RAD than would be justified by the simple arithmetic combination of their

confidence in their views on HOT and NEW. We can easily imagine experience-based instinct or

other variables not exhausted by HOT and NEW convincing one or both that RAD is

inappropriate, even if they could not fully defend their bottom-line convictions in terms of HOT and

NEW, and possibly even if they could not fully defend their bottom-line convictions at all.

Here, and in many if not all group judgments of fact, it is somewhat misleading to speak of

reasons and outcomes. We presented RAD as a policy proposal supported by factual judgments

bearing a fixed logic to each other. But just behind RAD, and invisible in our schematic

presentation is a bottom-line factual question: Does the community need RAD to evade disaster or

not? In this (artificially) pure case of factual judgment, it is fact all the way up, and there is no a

priori reason why little or simple factual judgments should inevitably be preferred to large or

complex ones.

Democratic concerns are similarly unhelpful to the sweeping prescription of premise-based

voting for the deliberative democratic resolution of paradoxical questions. Suppose, in our RAD

example, we imagine that the community as a whole evenly divides itself into three parties on the

RAD question, parties whose views are perfectly represented by the PM who stands in for them.

(We could, in effect, simply read "PM X" as "Members of Party X", and so forth. If the state of

empirical conviction puts more certainty on the question of RAD than then questions of HOT or
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 27

NEW, there is no fairness-related reason to make judgments on HOT and NEW govern. On the

contrary, fairness would seem to insist on RAD as the governing question. In our example, after all,

two-thirds of the members of the community are convinced that the community will evade disaster

without RAD. Their bottom line judgments are rejected and those of a mere one-third of the

community acted upon. That might be a democratically acceptable result in some circumstances,

but it seems an improbable candidate for democratic sponsorship as a general rule. To be sure,

contestability and commitment may be democratic virtues; but where the state of empirical

commitment favors the bottom line rather than its more discrete factual elements, it is the bottom

line that is the natural target of both contest and commitment.

III. GROUP DECISIONS INVOLVING JUDGMENTS OF VALUE

Judgments of value for these purposes are not merely invocations of the things persons

value; that better characterizes preferences. Rather, judgments of value implicate those things

which it is sensible to speak of a political community as having an obligation (or, possibly, being

committed) to value. Propositions of justice or political morality more generally are the most

obvious objects of such judgements; they may not be the only such objects.

The argument for reasons over outcomes in the domain of normative judgment goes

something like this: Reasons, by hypothesis, are the premises that justify outcomes; accordingly, on

views of democracy that emphasis contest over, and commitment to, those things that drive

decisions, it is reasons that must be the focus of debate and agreement. What distinguishes
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 28

normative decisions in this argument is an implicit view about judgments of value: Judgments of

value in this argument are implicitly regarded as unidirectional, with the arrow of reason and

justification moving from the normatively active material of established value to the passive,

derivative material of operational instruction.

On this view, a successful colloquy with a four year old essentially reverses the logic of

justification. She asks: Why are there traffic lights? You reply: So cars coming to a place where

two roads cross each other won't bang into each other. She asks: why don't people want cars to

bang into each other? And you reply with an explanation that is close enough to bedrock to be

normatively freestanding (or so you hope). Reasons on this account are like your last reply, and the

logic of justified choice proceeds upward from them. Reasons are justifying premises.

This seems the understanding of normative judgment upon which the linkage of integrity and

reasons depends. And, on first blush, it seems promising. But consider this unidirectional-arrow-

of-justification-picture of normative reason more closely

A. Individual normative reasons. Let us begin by focusing upon the demands of

normative choice on a individual. At the moment we meet the individual in question, she is deeply

convinced that it is unjust for the state to prevent women from obtaining abortions under reasonable

conditions. In conversation with herself or with others, however, she is pressed to justify her

conviction. Consider the rough shape of the process of reasoning involved. In particular, what is a

justifying premise for an individual who is engaged in such a process of normative reflection?

A justifying premise is a comparatively durable unit of normative judgment. In the moral


Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 29

sphere, it is an appealing moral stipulation. So understood, a justifying premise could be a strong

intuitive response to a specific, morally-charged case, an appealing moral principle, or what we

might call a moral axiom -- one of a fairly small set of grounding moral principles from which other

principles can draw justification.

In one sense, these different levels of moral instinct or judgment are hierarchical: In a fully

realized moral view they can be accurately described as running from the most general and abstract

to the most narrow and particular. And in some purely abstract sense, one might be tempted to

think of the arrow of justification as running in just that direction. But this is at most a plausible view

about the logical structure of a fully realized moral view: It is emphatically not a plausible view about

the process by which moral understandings and commitments are formed by thoughtful persons

acting in good faith; nor is it a plausible view of the nature of the moral understandings and

commitments such persons will find themselves holding.

The process of moral formation -- we often call it moral reasoning, but reason is not the

only element in the process -- does not a priori privilege one level of moral commitment over

another. Reactions to specific cases, principles that collect and explain those reactions, and axioms

that collect and explain those principles, are all candidates for leadership roles in the process of

moral reflection and all candidates for rethinking and amendment in the midst of that process.

When the woman seeking to justify her conviction about laws restricting abortion considers the

matter, she is seeking a state of equilibrium between and among her views at any and potentially all

of these levels. In order to achieve this, she may have to tack back and forth between and among
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 30

these views, adjusting them where necessary. At any level, the durability of her view is determined

by its intrinsic appeal -- the native strength of its attractiveness to her -- and its connectedness --

the support it gives to other appealing conclusions and the support it derives from other appealing

conclusions.

This picture of what is sometimes described as the process of reflective equilibration is

highly schematized and idealized of course. But the point is this: In the real and imperfect world of

moral reflection, what counts as a justifying premise, as the salient unit of moral commitment, will

depend on the extant state of the relevant individual's moral commitment. It may be that after

thinking about the matter for a bit, our woman pondering the moral status of abortion laws may

decide that she does not yet have satisfactory moral principles to explain her conviction. She might

think that this gives her good reason to rethink her position; or she might be quite sure of her

position and realize that she has not yet succeeded in teasing out a fully satisfactory explanation of

her position. Even if the picture is in a certain sense worse for her in that she finds that her position

on abortion laws conflicts with moral principles to which she feels allegiance, it remains an open

question as to whether she will in the end find it necessary to modify her position on abortion or

necessary to reshape the moral principles.

B. Group Normative Premises. When we move from individuals to groups these

observations continue to hold. If integrity insists that a group openly contest and reach agreement

on the premises that justify its decisions, then the target of that requirement will be as variable as it is

in the individual case: What will be required is contest over and commitment to the most durable
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 31

normative convictions held by the members of the community.

In one respect, this is helpful to the claim that integrity insists that group voting protocols

favor reasons over outcomes when the two pull apart in paradoxical cases. One of the difficulties

faced by the claim is the problem of knowing when you've gone deeply enough in the regression

towards first principles to be able to say that you have reached a reason instead of merely an

outcome. This is not too great a problem when dealing with the decisions of multi-judge courts,

since doctrine somewhat arbitrarily designates the nature of the reasons that justify outcomes in the

cases that come before the court. Deeper reasons -- reasons for the doctrinal premises -- are

conveniently offstage. But when the structure of the doctrinal paradox is taken out of its native

environment and applied to group deliberations generally, a reason-favoring view has to contend

with the question of when you know you've reached a reason. The observation that reasons are

fixed by the shape of the convictions held among the members of the group -- that reasons are

those propositions that enjoy durable normative commitment -- helps here, since it offers a

conceptual grounds for picking out those things that count as reasons.

But this is help that a proponent of the integrity/premise-favoring thesis cannot afford to

accept. That thesis depends on the idea that when a group's judgments are distributed

paradoxically there will be normatively-charged, active components of those judgments (reasons)

that give on to normatively passives results by virtue of their arithmetic combination (outcomes).

But what in this picture are superficially identified as reasons on the one hand, and what are

superficially identified as outcomes on the other, are both contenders for the status of what is
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 32

morally most salient for purposes of agreement.

Imagine that there is a proposal on the table to change the law regarding abortion

procedures, to significantly enlarge the capacity of women to elect such procedures. The group

considering this law is equally divided among three views: One subgroup holds that abortion

involves taking the life of a person, and would maintain the present restrictive law; one subgroup

rejects that view of abortion, holds that the present law violates principles of gender equality and

would support the proposal to change the law; the remaining sub-group joins the second in

rejecting the view that abortion involves taking the life of a person, and would also support the

proposal to change the law, but its reason for doing so involves a view of autonomy rather than

equality. And imagine finally that the members of the second and third sub-groups are normatively

exclusive of each other: none of those in the equality party are attracted to the autonomy view, and

vice versa. This, of course, is a paradoxical distribution of views:


Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 33

Table 6

Abortion And The Justifying Premise


Equality Autonomy Ease Restrictions

Subgroup X N N N

Subgroup Y Y N Y

Subgroup Z N Y Y

Column Outcome N N N/Y

But it is entirely possible that the members of Subgroups Y and Z are substantially more committed to

the view that it is unjust for the state to restrict the option of a woman to have an abortion than they are

committed to the specific principal upon which they would rely in justifying their view. Both would say

they are the party of choice, not the party of equality or autonomy. After full debate and vote, the

community has a reason for easing restrictions on abortion: Two-thirds of the people in the community

believe the present law to be unjust. That agreed-upon judgment is the justifying reason for changing

the law.

IV. The Structure of Group Choice

These last observations about the elusive nature of what should count as a “reason” in a reason-

driven voting protocol bring us at last to the question of the complexity of real world decision-making in

political communities. At an abstract remove from actual institutional arrangements, the champion of
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 34

reason-based voting could agree with our insistence that reasons are not necessarily the smallest

elements of judgment, but rather those premises around which commitment most durably forms. But it

is far from clear that any real-world voting process could reliably identify reasons so understood, and

far from clear what sort of voting protocol would do the best job overall of even approximating the

result-driven outcome so understood. In this section, we will lay out some of the difficulties that must

be faced in bridging the gap between an abstract attraction to reason-driven voting and the real world

of decision-making in political communities.

A. The Practical Difficulty of Disciplining Legislative Practice.

We discovered the doctrinal paradox in the course of our work on multi-judge courts. In the

milieu of judicial decision procedure, it is a relatively straight-forward matter to observe the existence of

the doctrinal paradox in real world cases, and further to consider various practical responses to the

paradox, including the option of an across-the-boards choice of issue-by-issue voting. This is so

because Anglo-American adjudication occurs within a characteristic structure. In adjudication,

doctrine creates a fixed relation between decisions about discrete sub-parts of a case (issues) and the

final decision (outcome). Consider, for example, a contract case. Plaintiff will prevail in her case if she

can prove both (a) that the defendant and she had a contract and (b) that the defendant failed to

perform. Alternatively, plaintiff will prevail on her case if she prevails on either one of two causes of

actions, say a action based on contract or an action grounded in promissory estoppel. 20 Further, the

20
For a more elaborate and complete discussion of the structure of doctrine, see Kornhauser,
“Modeling Collegial Courts II. Legal Doctrine.”
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 35

doctrinal structure of judicial decision making is fully visible by virtue of the judicial practice of writing

opinions which both announce the bottom-line outcome of the case and set forth the doctrinal

justification of that outcome -- opinions which articulately address the issues that compose a justification

for the outcome. So in a contract case in which the plaintiff prevails, the court will explain how it came

to determine both that a contract existed and that the defendant failed to perform.

In a relatively centralized decision-making environment like a multi-judge court, where reasons

are comparatively transparent and stable by virtue of extant doctrine, and the agenda relatively immune

to manipulation, reason-based voting is a practical option. We remain convinced that a sweeping

commitment to reason-based voting in paradoxical cases occurring in multi-judge courts would not be a

good thing; but such a commitment is clearly within the capacity of a multi-judge court to implement.

Legislative procedures operate in marked contrast to adjudication. Imagine a group meeting

as a committee of the whole, and proceeding by way of Robert's Rules of Procedure or an equivalent

set of operating rules.21 We can think of these rules as falling into two broad categories: framing rules

and decisional rules. Framing rules set the agenda; they determine how proposals get to the floor of

the body and whether they are amended, tabled, presented in a given order, conjoined or determined in

isolation. Decisional rules determine the voting protocol on the final question of enactment.

For our present purposes, it is nature of the framing rules that most importantly distinguishes

what we are calling legislative procedures from judicial procedures. In particular, it is the free-form,

21
We offer this example rather than a more recognizable legislature, because that introduces
the additional complications of one group deciding for another, which we take up below in Section __.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 36

highly variable nature of the output of the framing rules that is salient. The question of whether final

votes are addressed to broad final outcomes or more narrow parts of or reasons for such outcomes,

for example, is guided by the largely arbitrary sequence of framing events within the legislative

assembly.

Thus, even if most members of a legislative assembly happen to share the belief that outcome X

is appropriate only if propositions A and B are both true, the choice to vote only on X, or on A, then B

(or for that matter, the choice of whether to abandon X after a negative vote on A) is a function of a

succession of votes guided only by the substantively blind dictates of Robert's Rules or the equivalent.

Accordingly, in legislative environments, there is normally no mechanism available to insure that reasons

or premises are revealed, much less acted upon in any formal way, and legislative procedures are

notoriously porous to the manipulation of their agendae. And it is far from obvious that legislatures in

any recognizable form could be remade to accommodate the discipline of deconstructing legislative

proposals into their component reasons and to constrain the address of formal votes to such reasons.

The practical difficulty of constructing mechanisms to impose the discipline of reason-based

voting on legislative bodies by a conceptual aspect of that project that we have already encountered:

What counts as a reason is a matter not of a linear structure of justification but rather of the depth and

durability of normative commitment. Accordingly, what counts as a reason for a group should itself be

a matter of democratic contest and commitment. It is hard to imagine how any mechanism that forced a

decomposition of bottom-line legislative outcomes into predetermined judgmental segments could be

consistent with the appropriate scope of democratic choice or with the possibility that a community’s
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 37

most durable normative commitments might at any given time be unredeemable in what might be

logically prior judgmental segments. Indeed, given the community-specific nature of what should be

understood as counting as a reason, it is far from clear that democratic concerns with contest and

commitment would be best served by segmented voting on component “reasons,” even if the means of

enforcing such voting could be devised. Free-form framing devices familiar in legislative settings – like

Roberts Rules – might do a better job overall of composing the questions over which the community

should direct its legislative contests and form its legislative commitments.

B. The Justificatory Domain of Integrity Over Reasons. There is a second wrinkle that

attaches to the idea of legislative integrity that serves to magnify the practical difficulty of implementing

reason-based voting in the legislative arena. Earlier, we noted that integrity could concern itself with the

synchronic problem of rationality across persons with regard to a single decision, or with rationality

across decisions. While we might expect that the virtue of group integrity makes demands of both

sorts, neither Phillip Pettit and Ronald Dworkin seem to consider this possibility; instead, each has hold

of half of what integrity might be understood to require. Pettit appears to be largely concerned with

group integrity over a single decision; while Dworkin focuses exclusively on Hercules’s obligation

across cases.

For our present purposes, this is the rub: As difficult as it is to imagine mechanisms by which a

legislature could maintain the discipline of reason-based voting over a single legislative decision, it is far

more difficult to imagine how this could be maintained across whole legislative programs. Further, it is

hard to see how a commitment to reason-based integrity in legislative decision making could sensibly
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 38

stop short of demanding rationality across cases.

Suppose the group in question is considering a simple legislative proposal (L) which

decomposes neatly into sub-questions (A, B) which in combination offer good reason for deciding L.

The democratic claim for reason-based voting goes something like this: the group can justify its choice

of L to an objecting member by noting that the group has engaged in active democratic contest over

substantive matters A and B, and has committed itself to both A and B, which in combination justify L.

But the logic of this account has entailments requiring a significant amount of continuity across

group decisions. Suppose there were three different pieces of legislation (L, M, and N), which

connected to reasons (A, B, and C) as follows: L= A & ~B; M= ~A & ~B; and N= A & B. Now, a

community that enacted all three pieces of legislation could not justify itself in the democratic terms that

we have just canvassed. Suppose legislation M was being complained of. Voting on reasons (setting

aside the problem of what sort of legislative mechanism could do that), the community would have had

to vote both ~A and ~B in order to have enacted M. But when the community enacted L, it would

have had to have voted in support of A; and when it enacted N it would have had to have voted in

support of B. Without continuity, reason-based voting cannot does not seem to offer the community

anything more by way of justification for its decisions than outcome-based voting. Indeed, the

community that enacted L, M & N by reason-based votes would seem to be if anything less justified in

the imposition of these legislative strictures on its members.

The logic of democratic justification that underlies reason-based legislative integrity thus has a

conceptual scope that is at least as broad as whole legislative programs. Indeed, one might argue that
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 39

consistency must extend over the legislative programs of successive legislatures. On this account,

Pettit’s position ought to parallel, in the legislative domain, the requirements of integrity across cases

that Dworkin imposes on adjudication.

There is some appeal to such a requirement. Voters elect representatives to the legislature on

the basis of the legislative programs they advocate, and often may have in mind the connection between

specific legislative programs and broad patterns of legislative choice over time. But legislatures,

whether committed politically to broad programs or not, generally proceed statute by statute,22 or even

provision by provision.23 The demand for reason-based legislative voting thus depends on the

availability and desirability of mechanisms of legislative choice that not only will sensibly fix on what

counts as the reasons for a community decision, and not only will require that legislatures vote on the

sub-units of judgment that count as reasons, but will further impose some substantial requirement of

continuity on decisions over time.24 The introduction of this last requirement makes a sweeping

22
Legislatures do feel some pressure towards enactment of legislative programs as a whole.
The Congressional budgeting procedure, for example, attempts to induce Congress to contemplate the
full legislative program that it plans to enact when it makes individual budgeting decisions. The process,
however, arose not in order to generate consistency among reasons but to force some spending
discipline on Congress.
23
Under an open rule in which any amendment may be made from the floor, Roberts Rules of
Order permit consideration of a bill first on a provision by provision basis and then subsequently as an
entirety.
24
Continuity across time presents serious problems for the reason-based theorist. Recall our
earlier example of statutes L, M, and N. Suppose that L is proposed in to Congress at time t, M to
Congress at time t+1 and N to Congress at time t+2. Suppose further that L is enacted. When
Congress considers M at time t+1 does it consider the merits of M alone? Or must it consider its
impact on L? Specifically, does the enactment of M, implicitly repeal L because it rejects the premise
A necessary for the adoption of L?
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 40

commitment to reason-based voting still less feasible and still less appealing for a democratic

community.25

VI. Groups deciding for Groups-- Legislative Integrity and the Problem of Representation.

In real-world democratic communities, courts, legislatures and administrative agencies are the

key actors, and they almost always act on behalf of a larger polity. In this section we consider how this

feature of agency bears on our prior analysis of the conflict between reason-based and outcome-based

group decision-making in general, and in particular on the case for reason-based procedures. The

particular form of agency that is relevant to this question is representation; and representation is

problematic for a reason-based approach to group decision making.

A group or an individual (the representative) can be thought to represent another group or

individual (the constituency) when one important criteria of the representative’s success is the degree to

which the representative makes those choices that the constituency would make on its on behalf under

some specified decisional circumstances. All agency relationships involve the agent acting on behalf of

the principal but there are a variety of ways in which one group or individual can act on behalf of

another. A trustee or fiduciary, for example, might be thought to be under a stringent obligation to act

on behalf of another, but this may involve doing what is best for the beneficiary of the relationship, not

what the beneficiary would do on her own behalf. In public life, however, representation is a common

25
This is reflected in Dworkin, who nominally believes that integrity applies to legislative as well
as adjudicative choices, but who excuses legislatures from any serious or visible obeisance to integrity
on grounds of democratic choice (paragraph in Law’s Empire).
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 41

motif of agency.

For a theorist of deliberative democracy, representation must play a big part in bridging the gap

between members of a political community acting as a committee of the whole in town meeting fashion

and standard legislative practice, where a small number of elected legislators make decisions on behalf

of large constituencies. This idea of the members of a political community contesting the substantive

grounds of community choice and then in turn being bound by community-wide commitments to those

grounds, for example, presumably entails a substantial responsibility on the part of legislators to

recreate or reflect the will of their constituents. Indeed, Phillip Pettit’s commitment to reasons rather

than outcomes seems in part designed to assure that voters can choose the legislators who can best be

depended upon to reflect their will.26

There is nothing surprising or disturbing about a view of the function of legislators that makes

their representative role important. But acknowledging this role brings to the fore a number of prickly

questions that are likely to wreak some havoc with a sweeping demand that legislators respond to

paradoxical cases on the basis of reasons rather than outcomes. A full analysis of these questions in

beyond our ambitions here; what follows is merely a sketch of some of the difficulties that a claim for

reason-based community choice must confront.

To organize the discussion, observe that we must consider the relation of the views of four

distinct groups: the constituency, the individual representative, the polity, and the legislature.

Notice that one’s theory of representation (and the structure of the electoral system) will determine the

26
[Cite to Pettit]
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 42

relation between a representative’s views and the (aggregated) views of her constituency. Similarly, the

structure of the legislature and the electoral system will determine in part the relation between the

(aggregated) views of the polity and the (aggregated) views of the legislature. So, for example, the

pattern of individual views in a constituency might be paradoxical though the pattern within the polity as

a whole might not be; in this circumstance, the pattern of views within the legislature may or may not be

paradoxical. Obviously, there are eight possible relations of patterns of belief among these three

groups. The 8 patterns are displayed in table 7.

Table 7: Possible Relations among the Patterns of Views within Three Different Groups
Constituency Polity Legislature

P P P

P P not-P

P not-P P

P not-P not-P

not-P P P
not-P P not-P

not-P not-P P

not-P not-P not-P

P indicates the existence of a pattern of paradoxical views in the relevant group.

. The question for the reason-based integrity theorist is: in which group or groups will the

demands of integrity apply? The answer to that question is fraught with real puzzles in some case.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 43

The earmark of a paradoxical distribution of views, of course is that support for the component reasons

diverges from support for the outcome. To see how the common phenomenon of groups deciding for

groups complicates things for the reason-based integrity theorist, let us suppose that the legislation in

question is a law substantially reducing a particular state’s restrictions on the opportunity of a women to

secure abortion, and that when a paradoxical distribution obtains on Table 7, the distribution assumes

the form we portrayed in Table 6. That is, one third of the relevant group supports the legislation on

equality grounds; a different one third supports the legislation on autonomy grounds; and a the final one

third doesn’t support the legislation at all. So, while each of the two reasons for the legislation is

rejected by two-thirds of the relevant group, the law itself is supported by two-thirds of the same

group. And let us further suppose that when a non-paradoxical distribution obtains on Table 7, the

relevant group still supports the legislation, but the group members agreement on outcome is now

consistent with their agreement on reasons. This could be so for example if all of the sub-group who

support the legislation on autonomy grounds also support it on equality grounds, so that two-thirds of

the community now agree on the equality grounds for the legislation.

Now, suppose we consider this row from Table 7:

Constituency Polity Legislature

not-P not-P P

If integrity binds the Legislature, and the legislators accordingly take themselves to be bound to resolve

the question before them issue-by-issue, then they will reject the legislation, despite the fact that two-

thirds of the polity they represent would adopt the legislation without any ambiguity as to the grounds
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 44

for so doing.

Suppose that candidates for the position of constituent representative adopt the policy positions

that maximize each’s probability of election. Then the positions endorsed by the elected representative

will depend critically on the structure of the electoral system with single member districts in a two party

system yielding very different outcomes than a party list system within the polity as a whole. In either

circumstance, however, it is not clear that the representative will need to endorse views on all the

reasons that underlie a legislative outcome.

Consider these rows from Table 7, will all of our other hypothesized circumstances in place:

Constituency Polity Legislature


P not-P not-P

P not-P P

A representative concerned with reelection would surely be inclined to support the legislature removing

restrictions on abortions, since two-thirds of her constituents want the legislation, notwithstanding their

disagreement on reasons for the legislation. And what reason is there for her not doing so? After all,

once again, two-thirds of the polity as a whole want the law, and as a group are fully committed to one

or both reasons for the law. Were she to defy the wishes of two-thirds her constituency, and cast her

vote against the law because. her constituency as a group did not support a single reason for the law, or

on behalf of her constituency in some overly literal representative mode vote against each of the

reasons, she would not only imperil her reelection, but – were she the deciding vote – she would defeat

a law that two-thirds of the polity wanted and integrity-satisfying grounds for wanting.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 45

VII. The Problems of Integrity – A Reprise

We have identified several formidable hurdles for a working conception of integrity. The first

of these is the need for any such theory to distinguish among and respond to the diverse types of

decisions that groups, including legislatures are called upon to make. Appropriately understood, a

group decision might reflect the aggregated preferences of the group; it might reflect the group’s factual

judgments; or it might reflect the value judgments of the group. As we have seen, the plausible claims

of integrity – particularly with regard to such nice matters as the aggregation of reasons versus

outcomes–are likely to vary substantially among these types. Preference-driven decisions are

appropriately blind to reasons; group judgments of fact seem to invite probabilistic analysis; and group

judgments of value are complicated by the non-linear nature of moral formation and conviction. A

persuasive theory of integrity will have to shape itself around these varying considerations. And that

assumes that the decisions confronting the relevant group will be pure types. Many or most group

decisions will be hybrid among these possibilities, and a theory of integrity somehow will have to absorb

the resulting pushes and pulls.

Our analysis of these pure types of decisions posed a second difficulty, at least for reason-

based conceptions of integrity. We argued that reasons and outcomes are not presented in neatly

labeled packages. In actual deliberation, our commitments to outcomes may sometimes be more basic

and fundamental than our commitment to the “principles” or “reasons” that ostensibly support them. A

process of reflective equilibrium governs our evaluative judgments and this process may point to the

outcome rather than the reason as fundamental. Moreover, commitments within a group may differ.
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 46

One individual may in fact have deeper commitments to underlying (or more abstract) principles than to

the conclusion to which these principles point; other individuals, however, may be less sure of the

theoretical grounds for their conclusion than of the conclusion itself. These features of our deliberative

process pose deep problems for any reason-based conception of integrity.

A third difficulty confronts any theory of integrity that implicates legislative – as opposed to

judicial – practice. An attractive theory of legislative integrity is almost certainly going to have as one of

its conceptual entailments the requirement that the legislature act with a degree of substantive constancy

over time – that it exhibit what we have called diachronic integrity. And synchronic integrity is likely to

require considerable constraint over the kind and sequence of questions the legislature is free to take

up. If integrity is taken to demand voting on reasons rather than outcomes, then the problem of

distinguishing reasons from outcomes will call for singularly self-conscious, self-knowing, and self-

restricting institutional mechanisms. Legislative practice in any of its familiar instantiations is free-form: it

has few if any formal mechanisms that structure the size, shape or timing of the questions that ultimately

come to be voted upon; and it has only occasional resources to provide an institutional memory with

any operational bite. Legislative integrity is thus likely to require radical transformations of legislative

practice as we know it, transformations that well may be inconsistent with the majoritarian virtues of

that practice.

A fourth difficulty for conceptions of integrity involves the complexity that ideal assumes

whenever representation enters the picture. Groups often decide on behalf of other groups and the

decision-makers are meant not only to decide on behalf of the other group but as representatives of
Kornhauser/Sager – 15 August 2003 Page 47

that group. The enterprise of group representation raises the serious question of just whose integrity

matters: The decision-making body itself? Each representative’s discrete constituency, taken one by

one? The polity as a whole? The views of the decision-making body may present a paradoxical case

even when the distribution of views of each representative’s constituency or of the population as a

whole are not paradoxical. Conversely, the distribution of views within the representative body may

not be paradoxical when the views of the population as a whole are. Where integrity touches upon

representation, it must include a theory of representation that offers guidance through this thicket of

possibilities.

And with that, we rest.

Potrebbero piacerti anche