Sei sulla pagina 1di 20

Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637 – 656

Inferring the goals of a nonhuman agent


Susan C. Johnsona,*, Amy Boothb, Kirsten O’Hearnc
a
Department of Psychology, Jordan Hall, Building 420, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305, USA
b
Northwestern University, Evanston, IL, USA
c
University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA, USA
Received 1 January 2000; accepted 1 January 2001

Abstract

Johnson, Slaughter, and Carey [Dev. Sci. 1 (1998) 233.] used infants’ ability to follow
the ‘gaze’ of novel objects to claim that infants’ recognition of mentalistic agents is not
isomorphic with person recognition but rather based on a set of nonarbitrary object
recognition cues including the presence of a face and the ability to interact contingently with
other agents. The current studies extend these findings with data based on infant imitation
and the production of communicative gestures. The first study replicated Meltzoff’s [Dev.
Psychol. 31 (1995) 838.] reenactment of goals paradigm with a novel, nonhuman agent.
Fifteen-month-olds were found to reenact both the completed and uncompleted/unseen
goals of a novel object that had a face and interacted contingently with the experimenter and
infant. Concurrently, infants directed many communicative gestures at the object. A second
study excluded the possibility that the communicative gestures apparently directed at the
object in Study 1 were in fact imitations of the experimenter’s own behavior. The
suggestion that novel, nonhuman objects are capable of eliciting such divergent behaviors
as gaze-following, goal reenactment, and communicative gestures from infants, supports
the claim that all of these behaviors are mediated by a central conceptual notion of
mentalistic being, at least by the ages studied, and that that concept is not isomorphic with
the concept person. D 2001 Elsevier Science Inc. All rights reserved.

Keywords: Mentalistic agents; Infant social cognition; Nonhuman agent

* Corresponding author. Tel.: +1-650-725-8964.


E-mail address: scj@psych.stanford.edu (S.C. Johnson).

0885-2014/01/$ – see front matter D 2001 Elsevier Science Inc. All rights reserved.
PII: S 0 8 8 5 - 2 0 1 4 ( 0 1 ) 0 0 0 4 3 - 0
638 S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656

1. Introduction

One commonly held position in the study of infant social cognition is that (1)
infants distinguish between people and nonpeople and (2) infants’ earliest
understanding of other minds maps directly onto this distinction. While the first
claim has been well documented, the second has been largely taken for granted
(see Johnson, 2000; Legerstee, 1992, 1994; Meltzoff, 1995; Poulin-Dubois,
1999; Wellman, 1993 for related reviews). This second point can be broken
down into two related questions. When do children first attribute mental states to
others and when they do, whom do they attribute mental states to? The answer to
these questions may well provide insight into the nature of the representational
systems underlying mentalistic reasoning.
Mental states are unobservable constructs that must be inferred by observers
rather than perceived directly. They are distinguished from other sorts of
unobservables or internal states by the specific kind of relationship they hold
with the world. That is, mental states are directed at the world; they are about
things. Other commonplace, commonsense unobservables (e.g., life, essences,
atoms, etc.), although presumed by lay thinkers to exist in the world, are not
presumed to be about the world. The ability to construe ourselves and others as
agents with mental states such as perceptions, attention, desires, and beliefs is
critical. With this mentalizing ability, we can communicate referentially, predict
and explain others’ behaviors, and manipulate both our own and others’ mental
states for the purposes of complex problem-solving and learning, not to mention
deception. Mentalizing is so critical, in fact, that its absence is thought by some
to be a central cause of autism (Baron-Cohen, 1995; Baron-Cohen, Tager-
Flusberg, & Cohen, 1993).
Garnering evidence sufficient to demonstrate mentalizing is difficult how-
ever. Many behaviors that could potentially serve as indices of mentalizing
(e.g., gaze-following, pointing, and goal imitation) can typically be interpreted
in both mentalistic and nonmentalistic ways. Nonmentalistic explanations
based on signal releasers, attentional enhancement, and object affordances
have all been proposed to explain the variety of behaviors produced by
prelinguistic infants (Butterworth & Jarrett, 1991; Gerwitz & Pelaez-Nogueras,
1992; Hood, Willen, & Driver, 1998; Moore & Corkum, 1994). The inter-
pretative problems are particularly acute for the attribution of mental states that
are correlated with reality (e.g., perception or goals) and can thus be mimicked
by conditioned or reality-driven behaviors. It was this problem that led Dennett
(1978) to suggest that the only convincing evidence for mentalizing must come
from successful reasoning about false beliefs, because false beliefs drive
behaviors not otherwise predicted by reality. Dennett’s argument motivated
an entire generation of research on the development of successful false belief
reasoning in children between the ages of 2 and 4 years (Flavell & Miller,
1998; Fodor, 1992; Gopnik & Astington, 1988; Leslie, 1994a; Wellman, 1993;
Wimmer & Perner, 1983).
S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656 639

Although the point is well-taken, the absence of successful false belief


reasoning before the age of 4 does not mean that younger children and infants
do not attribute any mental states to agents; only that sufficient evidence for such
a claim is difficult to generate. It does mean, however, that as long as the agents
used to test infants’ competency are highly familiar to infants, as are people,
nonmentalistic explanations are difficult, if not impossible, to rule out. Much of
the work in this area has nonetheless presupposed the role of people in infants’
attributions of mental states. Between the ages of 9 and 18 months, infants have
begun to interact with people as though they believe people have minds. They
produce communicative gestures such as points, requests, and displays for other
people (Bates, Camaioni, & Volterra, 1975; Bretherton, McNew, & Beeghly-
Smith, 1981; Butterworth & Grover, 1988; Leung & Rheingold, 1981); they
follow adults’ gazes (Butterworth & Jarrett, 1991; Corkum & Moore, 1998;
D’Entremont, Hains & Muir, 1997; Lempers, 1979; Scaife & Bruner, 1975) and
they guide their own behavior toward objects on the basis of other people’s
emotional and goal-directed behavior toward those objects (Baldwin & Moses,
1996; Meltzoff, 1995; Repacholi & Gopnik, 1997; Woodward, 1998; see also
Johnson, 2000 for a recent review).
The emphasis on humans as the target of infants’ mentalizing is not accidental.
A great deal of evidence has accumulated showing that very young infants can
and do distinguish between humans and nonhumans. At birth, infants preferen-
tially track the movement of faces (Morton & Johnson, 1991) and imitate the
facial and hand gestures of people (Field, Woodson, & Greenberg, 1982; Meltzoff
& Moore, 1977, 1983) but not inanimate objects (Legerstee, 1991). From 3
months to 1 year, infants smile, vocalize, and gesture more in the presence of
people than inanimate objects while visually fixating and reaching more towards
animals or inanimate objects, even when the inanimate objects resemble people in
very salient ways both perceptually and behaviorally such as dolls, interactive
robots, and animals (Ellsworth, Muir, & Hains, 1993; Klein & Jennings, 1979;
Legerstee, 1994, 1997; Legerstee, Pomerleau, Malcuit, & Feider, 1987; Poulin-
Dubois, Lepage, & Ferland, 1996; Ricard & Allard, 1993; but see Frye, Rawling,
Moore, & Myers, 1983 for contradictory results).
The ability to discriminate people from nonpeople, however, is no more
sufficient evidence of mentalizing abilities than any of that described above. It is
possible that person discrimination could develop in support of important social
and cognitive processes that are independent of mental state attributions (e.g.,
attachment and/or observational learning). Neither is person discrimination
logically necessary for mentalizing abilities. That is, object recognition processes
for identifying mentalistic agents need not be isomorphic with the processes for
identifying people.
Given these two concerns, (1) the problem of interpreting infants’ behavior
in the context of highly familiar agents like people and (2) the still under-
specified function of the person/nonperson distinction in infancy, it may be time
to look more closely at infants’ interpretation of nonhumans. It is particularly
640 S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656

important to do so using measures that are more directly associated with


mentalizing abilities, such as communicative behaviors, joint attention behav-
iors, and so on.
In fact, several largely untested theoretical proposals have been offered about
the cues that lay thinkers may use to identify mentalistic agents, human or
otherwise. The features proposed fall into several overlapping classes: morpho-
logical features such as faces and eyes (Baron-Cohen, 1995; Carey & Spelke,
1994, 1996), asymmetry along one axis (Baron-Cohen, 1995; Premack, 1990,
1991), nonrigid transformation (Gibson, Owsley, & Johnson, 1978), self-propul-
sion (Baron-Cohen, 1995; Leslie, 1994b, 1995; Premack, 1990, 1991), and the
ability to engage in contingent and reciprocal interactions with other agents
(Spelke, Phillips, & Woodward, 1995; Premack, 1990).
Drawing on these proposals, Johnson, Slaughter, and Carey (1998) examined
whether any of the cues would elicit gaze-following (a putative reflection of
mentalizing) by 12-month-olds in the context of a novel, nonhuman object. To do
this, they created a small novel object that could be introduced to infants as the
agent in a standard gaze-following paradigm (Scaife & Bruner, 1975). Infants’
willingness to follow the ‘gaze’ of the object when it reoriented itself in space
was then measured. Several potential mentalistic cues were studied, including the
presence of a face, self-generated behavior/movement, and contingent interaction
with the subject. Only the presence of a face and/or the ability to interact
contingently with the infant elicited gaze-following by the infant. Importantly,
infants did not follow the gaze of the same faceless object producing exactly the
same self-generated behaviors seen in the contingent condition if those behaviors
were not contingent upon the infants’ own behavior. Based on this, Johnson et al.
argued that around the same age that infants seem able to attribute mental states
such as perception and attention to people (12 months), infants also seem able to
attribute these mental states to novel entities other than people.
Of course, even these findings could be reinterpreted as a generalization of
previously conditioned behavior from people to novel objects that share some
relevant but nonmentalistically interpreted feature (e.g., see Corkum and Moore’s
(1998) account of gaze-following in infancy), thus leading us back to Dennett’s
original quandary. However, nonmentalistic accounts in this domain give rise to a
prediction not made by the theorists described above. That is, under non-
mentalistic accounts, the infant’s behavioral competency will vary across differ-
ent behavioral contexts (e.g., gaze-following, communication, and imitation). For
instance, in an account of gaze-following based purely on conditioned associa-
tions, there is no reason to assume that the production of head turns as seen in
gaze-following should agree with measures of object manipulation as seen in
imitation. Similarly, with signal-releaser accounts, different behavioral responses
will depend on the existence of independent, evolutionarily specified mecha-
nisms. Conversely, the degree to which putative mentalizing is manifested across
a variety of diverse behaviors and contexts is evidence against nonmentalistic
interpretations. It is, therefore, all the more important to reexamine the person/
S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656 641

nonperson distinction in infancy using as wide a variety of putative mentalizing


behaviors as possible.
The current study is a first attempt to extend this reasoning and the results
of Johnson et al. (1998) to behavioral contexts other than gaze-following. If
results consistent with mentalistic interpretations are obtained in divergent
methodological paradigms, objections based on local interpretative issues of
individual methods will no longer obtain. To this end, two additional behav-
ioral methods have been adapted in such a way that infants can be introduced
to a novel, contingently interacting agent and then given the opportunity to (1)
reenact the agent’s unseen goals (Meltzoff, 1995) and (2) interact communica-
tively with the agent by directing greetings, object requests, and object displays
at the agent.

2. Study 1

In Meltzoff’s (1995) paradigm, 18-month-olds were shown to reenact the


object-related goals of human actors (for instance, dropping a string of beads into
a cup). When a human actor tried but failed to accomplish his goal, 18-month-
olds reenacted the inferred, unseen goal rather than the spatiotemporally
witnessed event. Meltzoff argued that the infants’ performance could not be
motivated purely by the spatiotemporal information in the action itself, because in
a condition in which the human actor was replaced by a mechanical set of pincers
performing the same spatiotemporal actions, infants failed to reenact any unseen
actions. Meltzoff attributed this differential behavior to an early naive psychology
based on and restricted to the infants’ knowledge of people.
Study 1 examines the degree to which infants do in fact restrict their
attribution of goals to human actors. A nonhuman actor is used that, like the
novel object in Johnson et al. (1998) and unlike Meltzoff’s mechanical pincers,
embodies some of the characteristics thought to imply the presence of a mind,
specifically the presence of a face and hands, self-generated behavior, and the
ability to engage in contingent interactions.

2.1. Method

2.1.1. Participants
Fifty-six 15-month-olds (M = 15 months 12 days; range 14 months 27 days –
15 months 28 days) completed three conditions: Baseline (n = 20), Completed
Target Actions (Complete; n = 16), and Incompleted Target Actions (Incomplete;
n = 20). Infants were recruited through a mailing list of new parents in a mid-
Atlantic American city. Only healthy, full-term infants were included. Nine
infants were excluded for fussiness (2), experimenter error (3), equipment error
(1), and for failing to engage in the task by refusing to touch any toys (2; both in
the Complete condition).
642 S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656

2.1.2. Materials

2.1.2.1. The agent. A store-bought stuffed orangutan was adapted in the lab to
fit these requirements (see Fig. 1). The orangutan was approximately the size of a
15-month-old infant, sitting 18 in. high and 12 in. wide. It was covered in long
reddish-brown fur, with black vinyl hands, feet, and belly. It also had a black
vinyl face with two brown glass eyes and a nose sculpted of the same black
fabric, but no mouth. The face was encircled with long white fur. The
orangutan’s arms and hands were modified to allow an experimenter to fit his
or her own hands and arms inside them in the manner of a puppeteer. When
operated by the puppeteer, the orangutan agent was capable of contingent and
reciprocal action with both the experimenter and infant as well as perceptually
guided and goal-directed behavior and possessed the morphological features of
both a face and hands. It also necessarily exhibited self-generated and bio-
logically real movement. The experimenter operating the orangutan never spoke
or produced any sounds.

2.1.2.2. The setup. The child was seated on a caretaker’s lap at a table. The
orangutan agent was seated on top of the table directly across from the infant.
The orangutan backed up against a floor-length curtain behind which sat the
puppeteer. Two holes were cut in the curtain, allowing the puppeteer to extend

Fig. 1. The novel agent for Study 1 (left) and the surrogate for Study 2 (right).
S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656 643

Fig. 2. The experimental setup for Study 1.

her/his own arms through the curtain and into the arms of the orangutan (see
Fig. 2). The puppeteer’s own arms were never visible to the infant. The
puppeteer could watch the scene in front of the curtain via a TV monitor linked
to a videocamera that was mounted to the side of the setup and on which the
entire procedure was videotaped.

2.1.2.3. The objects. Four object sets compatible with the manual dexterity of
15-month-olds were selected, including beads in a cup, an elastic band on a peg, a
dumbbell, and a cap placed on a column (see Fig. 3).

2.1.3. Procedure
The experimental procedure followed Meltzoff’s (1995) original paradigm as
closely as possible. Infants were randomly assigned to one of the three
conditions: the Completed Action condition, the Incompleted Action condition,
or the Baseline condition.

2.1.3.1. The warm-up period. In all three conditions, the experimental trials
were preceded by a brief period designed to allow infants to acclimate to the
presence of the novel orangutan. The experimenter brought the infant into the
experimental room with their caretaker and introduced the infant to the
644 S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656

Fig. 3. The object sets for Study 1.

orangutan. The experimenter called the agent by name (‘‘Tang’’) and encour-
aged the infant to wave and ‘‘say hello to Tang.’’ The agent also waved to the
infant at the experimenter’s request. The infant was then encouraged to play
with a warm-up toy — a wooden box with an accompanying block — in the
presence of the orangutan. A variety of holes were cut in the lid of the box so
that differently shaped blocks could be dropped through. The infant was
allowed to keep the toy briefly, then she was asked to pass it to ‘‘Tang’’ so
that ‘‘Tang could have a turn.’’ The agent reached out his hands to accept the
toy and played with it by dropping the block into one of the holes. The
S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656 645

experimenter then asked him to give the toy back to the child. This continued
until the experimenter judged the child to be comfortable enough in the
orangutan’s presence to attend to the experimental task and had at least
touched the toy. In all cases, all of the information provided to the infant
about the orangutan and its behavioral capabilities during the warm-up period
was also available during the experimental trials. Following the warm-up
period, each infant completed four experimental object trials, including the
dumbbell, beads in a cup, an elastic band on a peg, and an inverted cup
placed on a column.

2.1.3.2. Completed and Incompleted Action trials. In the Completed and


Incompleted conditions, the child watched the agent act on each set of objects
three times, either successfully or unsuccessfully (see below). The object(s) was
then placed in front of the child by the experimenter in the same orientation used
with the agent. Each test trial lasted 20 s from the moment the child first touched
one of the objects. They were as follows.
The cup and beads. In all cases, the cup was presented to the agent (and the
child) upside down with the beads placed on the table to the side of the cup. For
the completed action, the agent turned the cup over, picked up the beads, lifted
the string above the edge of the cup, and dropped the beads inside the cup. This
was repeated three times with the experimenter retrieving the beads and inverting
the cup between each attempt. For the Incompleted action, the agent turned the
cup over, picked up the beads, lifted the string above the edge of the cup, wavered
slightly over the cup, and then dropped the beads so that they landed just outside
the cup on the table. Again, this was repeated three times, each in a slightly
different fashion by alternating hands and having the beads land in a different
spot on the table each time.
The peg and elastic band. The peg was always presented with the board flat
on the table and the peg sticking straight up. The elastic band was placed on the
table next to it. For the completed action, the agent uprighted the board so that the
peg was parallel to the surface of the table. Then, it picked up the elastic band and
hung it on the peg. In the Incompleted action, the agent uprighted the board,
picked up the elastic band, and raised it up toward the peg while releasing it just
before it circled the peg, thus dropping it on the table. Again, this was attempted
three times, alternating hands each time.
The dumbbell. For the completed action, the agent simply grasped one end
of the dumbbell in each hand and with an exaggerated effort pulled the two
ends apart. In the Incompleted action, the agent grasped the dumbbell the same
way, exerted the same exaggerated effort, but allowed one hand to slip off the
end of the dumbbell before it came apart. The hand that slipped alternated
between attempts.
The column and cap. For this item, the column was always presented on its
side, with the cap presented in an inverted position next to it. For the completed
action, the agent uprighted the column, picked up and turned over the cap, and
646 S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656

then with an exaggerated motion placed the cap on the column, leaving it resting
on top. In the Incompleted action, the agent went through the same motions but
never fully fit the cap into a level position on the column so that when it was
released it fell to the table. Again, the hands were alternated between attempts.

2.1.3.3. Baseline trials. In the Baseline condition, each trial began with the
child being allowed to manipulate the object(s) for 20 s. After the child
manipulated the object(s), they were given to the agent. The agent then randomly
manipulated them in a non-goal-directed way for 20 s. The agent was given a turn
with the objects in order to keep the overall level of activity, interest, and pace of
the trials comparable to the other conditions.
The order of objects was counterbalanced across all three conditions.

2.2. Results

Infants were said to have produced a target outcome if they satisfied the
following criteria.

2.2.1. The cup and beads


Any action that placed the beads in the cup with or without touching the
bottom was counted as a success. Infants need not actually release the beads,
although if they did and some of them fell over the edge of the cup or if they
knocked the cup over, this was not counted against them.

2.2.2. The peg and elastic band


Any action that placed the elastic band over the peg such that the peg
protruded through the center of the band was counted as a success. The
orientation of the peg and board relative to the table was ignored.

2.2.3. The dumbbell


Any action that resulted in the dumbbell coming apart into two separate parts
was counted as a success.

2.2.4. The column and cap


Any action that succeeded in orienting the inverted cap over the end of the
upright cone so that the cap was more horizontal than vertical was considered a
success regardless of whether the infant released the cap.
Three infants (one in the Completed and two in the Incompleted conditions)
completed only three of the four object trials. One infant in the Baseline condition
completed only two of the four trials. For the purpose of data analysis, missing
data in those cases were replaced by the mean for that subject. Otherwise, a blind
coder coded all of the infants’ behaviors from videotape. A second coder
achieved 93% agreement with the first coder. Disagreements were resolved
through review and discussion of the tapes.
S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656 647

Preliminary analyses revealed no main effects of sex so it was removed from


further analyses. The resulting overall mean values for each condition and item
are shown in Table 1. An analysis of variance (ANOVA) was performed on the
remaining factors of Condition (between-subjects) and Item (within-subjects).
A main effect of Item was found [ F(3,159) = 3.02, P < .001], possibly reflect-
ing the low rate of reproductions with the peg relative to the other items.
(Review of the tapes suggested that the hairband used to loop over the peg was
in fact too difficult for the children to manipulate.) Importantly, there were no
Item  Condition interactions. Therefore, it does not appear that the overall low
production rate of the peg outcome should interfere with our ability to interpret
any effects of Condition, the factor of central interest. The Condition factor
produced a main effect [ F(2,159) = 6.56, P < .001].
Infants produced the target outcomes only 10% of the time in the Baseline
condition, thus confirming that these outcomes were rarely produced sponta-
neously by infants of this age. On the other hand, when infants saw the target
outcome successfully produced by the novel agent, they reproduced it 52% of the
time. Using a Bonferroni procedure to control for inflated P values, a post-hoc
comparison between these two conditions revealed that the infants were signifi-
cantly more likely to produce the target outcome if they first saw it modeled by
the agent ( P < .001).
The condition of most interest was the Incompleted Action condition in which
infants saw the agent attempt to produce the target outcomes but fail. In this
condition, infants produced the target outcomes 37% of the time even though
they had never actually seen it achieved. Again, a Bonferroni-corrected compar-
ison confirmed that this rate of target production differed significantly from that
in the Baseline condition ( P < .001). The Completed and Incompleted conditions
did not differ from each other.
The percentages of infants in each condition who produced at least one of the
target outcomes were also calculated and are shown in Table 2. About 94% of the
infants (15/16) in the Complete condition produced at least one of the target
outcomes, 80% of the infants (16/20) in the Incomplete condition did so, and only
40% (8/20) in the Baseline condition did (i.e., 60% of the Baseline infants never
spontaneously produced a target outcome on any trial). These results yielded a
significant main effect of condition [c2(2) = 13.73, P < .001]. Pairwise compar-
isons between individual conditions revealed the same pattern of results seen in

Table 1
Mean target actions completed in Meltzoff’s replication with nonhuman agent
Individual objects Overall mean target
Condition Beads Dumbbell Cap Peg actions per trial
Baseline 0.10 (20) 0.15 (20) 0.16 (19) 0.00 (19) 0.10
Complete 0.75 (16) 0.50 (16) 0.56 (16) 0.27 (15) 0.52
Incomplete 0.47 (19) 0.30 (20) 0.55 (20) 0.16 (19) 0.37
Exact n’s for each cell are shown in parentheses.
648 S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656

Table 2
Number of infants completing target actions in Meltzoff’s replication with nonhuman agent
Total number of infants
Condition Never completed target actions Completed one or more target actions
Baseline 12 (60) 8 (40)
Complete 1 (6) 15 (94)
Incomplete 4 (20) 16 (80)
Percentages shown in parentheses.

the group averages [Complete vs. Baseline c2(1) = 11.13, P < .001; Incomplete vs.
Baseline c2(1) = 6.67, P < .01; and Complete vs. Incomplete c2(1) = 1.40, n.s.].
Overall, these results replicate the patterns seen in Meltzoff’s (1995) original
reenactment paradigm. Not only were infants able to reproduce the same literal
outcomes of a series of actions produced by an agent on objects but they were
also able to produce the same target outcomes even when the agent tried but
failed to produce them himself. As argued by Meltzoff, this suggests that the
infants interpreted the agent’s actions in terms of the agent’s goals rather than the
spatiotemporal characteristics of the movements themselves.

3. Discussion

One major difference sets these results apart from Meltzoff’s. The goals in this
study were assigned to a nonhuman agent. This was true despite the fact that
infants are known to distinguish between people and nonpeople — as documented
by measures of attention, smiling, vocalizing, and reaching — even when the
nonhuman objects are perceptually or behaviorally similar to people as in the case
of dolls, animals, and contingently behaving robots (Legerstee, 1994, 1997;
Legerstee et al., 1987; Poulin-Dubois et al., 1996; Ricard & Allard, 1993). This
result therefore supports the prediction based on Johnson et al.’s (1998) claim that
infants attribute mentalism broadly, based on both the morphological and
behavioral features of objects — in this case, the presence of a face and hands,
self-generated movement, and contingent interactions with other social agents. It
is at some variance to Meltzoff’s (1995) claim that infants restrict their mental state
attributions to people. Nonetheless, both views agree that when infants reproduce
an unseen target action, they do so based on the attribution of a goal to the actor.
As with all paradigms searching for nonverbal evidence of mentalistic
reasoning, however, alternative explanations exist for the mentalistic interpreta-
tion of the goal reenactment paradigm. These alternative explanations are based
on very different underlying mechanisms than those found in the gaze-following
case but are nonetheless applicable to the novel agent in the current study. The
leading alternative in this paradigm is an explanation based on a combination of
stimulus enhancement and object-based ‘‘affordances.’’ In short, the social agent
serves to direct the infant’s attention to the object, who can then discover the
S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656 649

target outcomes herself, based on the objective, discoverable properties of the


object. Meltzoff (1995) discussed this alternative at length and included a fourth
condition to control for the effects of both. In his version, infants saw the agent
manipulate the object in an undirected way. If infants’ performance in the
Incomplete condition were based on the combined effects of attentional enhance-
ment and object discovery, they should have performed just as well in this case.
However, they did not. In fact, they performed no differently in this condition
than they did in the Baseline spontaneous play condition. Nonetheless, alternative
versions of the counterarguments can be made based perhaps on fine-grained
analyses of attentional enhancement or the priming of action-based schema. As
with gaze-following, compelling evidence against all possible forms of a non-
mentalistic view is difficult (if not impossible) to generate from within the
paradigm. Therefore, it is still somewhat possible that the novel agents in both the
original gaze-following and the current goal reenactment paradigms elicit
‘‘successful’’ attributions for different, independent, and completely nonmental-
istic reasons.
The original motivation behind testing infants’ interpretations of nonhumans
in this goal reenactment paradigm (after the earlier gaze-following study by
Johnson et al., 1998) was to block just such paradigm-specific arguments.
Therefore, following the logic of collecting multiple behavioral measures, an
additional analysis was performed on the current videotapes — measuring the
infants’ nonverbal communicative gestures (Bates et al., 1975; Bretherton et al.,
1981; Tomasello, 1995) toward the novel object.
We reasoned that if infants were producing the target outcome in the
Incomplete condition because they interpreted the orangutan as a mentalistic
agent with goals, then they should also interact with it as a mentalistic agent (in
all three conditions). Alternatively, if the infants’ performance was based on
attentional enhancement and object discovery alone in the absence of mentalistic
attributions to the agent, they would not attempt to wave to it, show it toys, offer
it toys, make requests of it, or socially reference it (that is, alternate their own
gaze between it and the toys). Indeed, informal coding of the infants in Study 1
revealed that the majority of infants in all three conditions directed some sort of
social/communicative behavior at the agent at least once, including waving,
showing or giving objects, requesting objects, or alternating attention between
the agent’s face and a toy. This finding is consistent with the interpretation that
infants produced the target actions in the Incompleted Action condition, because
they viewed the orangutan as an agent with unfulfilled goals.
However, before the production of these communicative gestures can be taken
as converging evidence of a mentalistic attribution, one further alternative
explanation must be ruled out. Infants in the goal reenactment study received
a great deal of verbal and behavioral support from the experimenter over the
course of the procedure. The experimenter facilitated the infant’s interaction with
the novel agent by introducing them, passing objects back and forth between
them, and in general modeling a mentalistic interpretation of the agent by
650 S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656

directing communicative acts at it (talking, waving, giving objects, requesting


objects, etc.). Given infants’ propensity to imitate at this age, it is possible that
what appeared to be self-induced communicative gestures directed at the agent
by the infant were in fact merely instances of the infant imitating the exper-
imenter’s behavior toward the object. Note, however, that this explanation
applies only to the infants’ communicative gestures and cannot account for the
infants’ tendency to reenact the agent’s unseen and unachieved goals since the
experimenter herself never attempted any object manipulations.
To rule out this possibility, a faceless and handless surrogate for the agent was
created that the experimenter could direct communicative acts toward but that
would not respond.

4. Study 2

4.1. Method

4.1.1. Participants
Twenty-four 15-month-olds (M = 15 months 15 days; range 15 months 2
days –15 months 30 days) were tested in two conditions based on a modified
version of the Baseline condition of the goal reenactment study, an Agent
condition (n = 11) and a Surrogate condition (n = 13).

4.1.2. Materials
In the Agent condition, the orangutan from Study 1 was used. It was thus
capable of contingent and reciprocal action with both the experimenter and infant
as well as perceptually guided behavior and possessed the morphological features
of both a face and hands. It also necessarily exhibited self-generated and
biologically real movement. In the Surrogate condition, a new object was designed
that was roughly perceptually and morphologically similar to the orangutan
(Fig. 1) but incapable of self-generated movements of any sort — contingent,
reciprocal, perceptually guided, or biologically real. The surrogate was created by
covering a common table lamp of approximately the same size and proportions as
the orangutan with padding and a soft reddish-brown fabric. Like the orangutan,
it sat 18 in. high and 12 in. wide. A set of visually complex black and brown
features were attached to the lamp’s otherwise white shade in lieu of a face, and a
small, black, operational turntable was attached to the base of the lamp in lieu of
manipulatible hands. Thus, for the most part, both novel objects were soft
reddish-brown shapes, with black and white peripherals.

4.2. Procedure

Infants were guided through a prescribed interaction with either the agent or
surrogate. In both conditions, the experimenter talked throughout the procedure
S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656 651

to the agent/surrogate as though it were a real mentalistic agent. In order to


maintain equal levels of attention-getting activity across the two conditions, each
‘‘active’’ event produced by the orangutan as a self-generated response to the
experimenter or situation was matched by a ‘‘passive’’ event produced by the
experimenter on the lamp.1

4.2.1. Waves
First infants were introduced to the agent/surrogate by name (‘‘Tang’’ for the
orangutan and ‘‘Bob’’ for the lamp) and invited to wave to it. In the Agent
condition, the orangutan waved to the infant in response. In the ‘‘passive’’
condition, the experimenter turned the lamp’s light on and off (and then removed
her hands quickly in order to minimize the time they appeared in the visual field
around the lamp’s ‘‘head’’).

4.2.2. Offers and requests


After their introduction to the agent/surrogate, infants exchanged each of the
four toys with the agent/surrogate (see Study 1 for a description of the toys). At
each exchange, the infant was first asked by the experimenter to either give or
take the object directly from the agent/surrogate. The orangutan was capable of
accepting and passing the object itself. However, because the lamp was not
capable of doing this, in order to keep the experimenter’s participation as
comparable as possible in the two conditions, the experimenter mediated the
exchange in both cases, each time directing her own request or offer gesture at
the agent/surrogate. (It was possible to keep this intervention natural-appearing in
the Agent condition by seating the orangutan far enough away from the infant
that the infant and orangutan could not reach each other in any case). When the
agent received the toy, he held it and turned it over in his hands for 20 s as in the
Study 1 Baseline condition. Again, because the surrogate had no hands with
which to manipulate the toy, in order to maintain the attention-getting activity
level across the two conditions, when the surrogate ‘‘received’’ the toy, the
experimenter placed it on the turntable and spun it, again withdrawing her hands
as quickly as possible.1

4.3. Results

Two independent raters coded the infants’ communicative and social


behaviors into five categories based on general behavioral characteristics

1
It is important to note that although the passive events in the surrogate’s script were physical
rather than psychological events, we do not believe that this constitutes a confound. This is because
physical actions on agents are not considered category mistakes and are not by themselves cues to
category membership. People touch each other, push each other, and pull each other’s hair or clothing.
Such actions are not taken as evidence that the recipient is not an agent or that the actor does not
conceive of the recipient as an agent. Infants’ reactions to these scenarios were recorded on videotape.
652 S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656

Table 3
Mean number of communicative/social gestures per infant directed at the novel objects in Study 2
Behaviors
Condition Greetings Offers Requests Gaze alternation Withdrawal
Orangutan 2.36 2.09 0.54 11.91 0.82
Lamp 0.92 0.38 0.15 3.31 0.00

and direction of gaze. The five categories were Greetings, Offers, Requests,
Gaze Alternation, and Withdrawals. Greetings were counted anytime the infant
lifted the fingers of the hand toward the agent/surrogate in a wave-like motion
while simultaneously looking at the agent/surrogate. Offers were counted each
time the infant held an object out toward the agent/surrogate while simulta-
neously shifting her gaze from the object to the agent/surrogate. Requests
were credited to the infant each time she extended her empty hand toward the
agent/surrogate as the agent/surrogate possessed the object while simultane-
ously shifting her gaze from the object to the agent/surrogate. A Withdrawal
was credited each time the baby actively pulled back from the agent/surrogate
by arching her back or pulling in her hands while glancing at least once at the
agent. Finally, a single act of Gaze Alternation with the agent/surrogate was
credited anytime the infant shifted her gaze from the object to the agent/
surrogate in the absence of other gestural actions. The two coders reached
93% agreement.
The sex of the infants had no effect on the results of a preliminary analysis and
will not be discussed further. As seen in Table 3, infants were quite unlikely to
direct these gestures at the passive lamp, despite the fact that the experimenter
herself both directed gestures at the lamp and talked to it in a communicative
manner. An analysis of variance with condition and gesture as variables showed
that infants were much more likely to produce the target behaviors in the presence
of the contingently behaving orangutan than they were in the presence of the
lamp [ F(1,22) = 22.26, P < .0001]. Furthermore, this result held even when the
disproportionately frequent gaze alternation behaviors were removed from the
analysis [ F(1,22) = 10.03, P < .005]. It appears therefore that infants’ communi-
cative interactions with the orangutan agent, both in this study and in Study 1,
were probably due to infants’ interpretation of the agent itself and not to imitation
of the experimenter’s behavior.

5. General discussion

It was hypothesized that by the beginning of the second year, (1) infants’ have
the ability to attribute mental states to others and (2) that this ability is not
restricted to people. Furthermore, it was argued that the degree to which
putatively mentalistic attributions can be elicited across multiple behavioral
S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656 653

contexts by novel, nonhuman agents is evidence for a central conceptual


representation of mentalistic being, intermediary in the processing stream
between perception and action.
To this end, two studies were conducted in which 15-month-old infants were
presented with a novel object that either did or did not embody mentalistic cues
and invited to treat that object as a mentalistic agent. In Study 1, 15-month-olds
were presented with a novel agent in the form of a colorful stuffed orangutan
animated by an unseen puppeteer. Infants who saw the novel agent perform
object-directed actions (e.g., place beads inside a cup) reproduced those actions
and their outcomes when given the opportunity to play with the objects
themselves. Similarly, when infants who saw the agent ‘‘try’’ but fail to achieve
the same set of target outcomes were given the toys, they produced the inferred
target outcome rather than the actually witnessed spatiotemporal event. In both
cases, the rate of production of the target outcome was significantly higher than
that produced in a spontaneous play baseline during which infants nonetheless
interacted in the same way with the agent and watched it manipulate the toys
(though only after they themselves had had a chance to). Following Meltzoff
(1995), we interpret this pattern of findings as evidence that the infants attributed
goals to the agent; in this case, an animated, stuffed orangutan. We further argue
that the reason infants attributed goals to the nonhuman agent in these studies,
but not to the mechanical pincers in Meltzoff’s original study, is because
Meltzoff’s pincers embodied none of the features that are thought to characterize
mentalistic agents such as the ability to interact contingently with others or the
presence of a face.
Of course, taken alone, these data do not fully block alternative explanations
of the infants’ performance. Like Meltzoff’s original data on 18-month-olds’
imitation of adults, we need not attribute mentalistic interpretations to the child in
order to explain their behavior. If this were the only evidence offered, we might
be unable to eliminate an explanation of the behavior based on the spatiotemporal
trajectories of the movements, the social enhancement properties of people (or
animated apes), or the child’s own exploratory interest in and representations of
objects and the actions they support. Meltzoff blocked (1) the spatiotemporal
arguments with his pincer condition, (2) the social enhancement objection with a
non-goal-directed human manipulation condition, and (3) the object-discovery
objections with a baseline measure of spontaneous target action productions (or a
combination of all three).
We concur with all of those arguments and add an additional one of our own
based on the finding that the infants in our studies also directed communicative
gestures toward the agent. Infants in all three conditions of Study 1 directed
social communicative gestures at the novel agent, including waves hello and
goodbye, requests for toys the agent was holding or offers to give it a toy the
child was holding, and frequent social referencing — alternation of gaze between
the object and the agent. Study 2 confirmed that infants’ communicative gestures
towards the agent were not merely the result of imitation of the experimenter’s
654 S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656

communicative behavior. Infants directed significantly fewer greetings, offers,


and requests towards a surrogate that grossly resembled the orangutan but
embodied no mentalistic diagnostic cues, even though the experimenter directed
communicative acts toward it such as talking and waving to it as well as offering
and requesting toys from it.
The addition of these two productive behaviors, the reenactment of unseen
goals and communicative gestures, to the existing case of gaze-following
(Johnson et al., 1998) strengthens the argument that infants of this age have
access to a conceptual representation of mentalistic agent, intermediary in the
processing stream between perception and action. In addition, we know from
other research that infants distinguish between people and nonpeople, as
documented by measures of attention, smiling, vocalizing, and reaching, even
when the nonhuman objects are perceptually or behaviorally similar to people as
in the case of dolls, animals, and contingently behaving robots (Legerstee, 1994,
1997; Legerstee et al., 1987; Poulin-Dubois et al., 1996; Ricard & Allard,
1993). Therefore, it seems likely that, at least by 15 months, infants have a
representation of mentalistic agent and it is not isomorphic with their repre-
sentation of people.

Acknowledgments

We thank Craig Glasgow, Nicole Peditto, Demmler Schenk, Erika Sockaci,


and Janine Wilmer for help with data collection and coding. This research was
supported by grants to the first author from the National Science Foundation
(#SBR-9709527) and the University of Pittsburgh’s Central Research Develop-
ment Fund and the Faculty of Arts and Sciences Faculty Grants Program.

References

Baldwin, D. A., & Moses, L. J. (1996). The ontogeny of social information gathering. Child Develop-
ment, 67, 1915 – 1939.
Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). Mindblindness: an essay on autism and theory of mind. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Baron-Cohen, S., Tager-Flusberg H., & D. Cohen (Eds.) (1993). Understanding other minds. Oxford,
England: Oxford Univ. Press.
Bates, E., Camaioni, L., & Volterra, V. (1975). The acquisition of performatives prior to speech.
Merrill-Palmer Quarterly, 21, 205 – 226.
Bretherton, I., McNew, S., & Beeghly-Smith, M. (1981). Early person knowledge as expressed in
gestural and verbal communications: when do infants acquire a ‘‘theory of mind’’? In: M. E.
Lamb, & L. R. Sherrod (Eds.), Infant social cognition ( pp. 333 – 373 ). Hillsdale, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum.
Butterworth, G., & Jarrett, N. (1991). What minds have in common is space: spatial mechanisms
serving joint visual attention in infancy. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 9,
55 – 72.
S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656 655

Butterworth, G. E., & Grover, L. (1988). The origins of referential communication in human infancy.
In: L. Weiskrantz (Ed.), Thought without language ( pp. 5 – 24). Oxford, England: Oxford
Univ. Press.
Carey, S., & Spelke, E. (1994). Domain-specific knowledge and conceptual change. In: L. A. Hirsch-
feld, & S. A. Gelman (Eds.), Mapping the mind: domain specificity in cognition and culture
( pp. 169 – 200). New York: Cambridge Univ. Press.
Carey, S., & Spelke, E. (1996). Science and core knowledge. Philosophy of Science, 63, 515 – 533.
Corkum, V., & Moore, C. (1998). The origins of joint visual attention in infants. Developmental
Psychology, 34, 28 – 38.
Dennett, D. (1978). Response to Premack, D. and Woodruff, G. Does the chimpanzee have a theory of
mind? The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 4, 568 – 570.
D’Entremont, B., Hains, S. M. J., & Muir, D. W. (1997). A demonstration of gaze following in 3- to
6-month-olds. Infant Behavior and Development, 20, 569 – 572.
Ellsworth, C., Muir, D., & Hains, S. (1993). Social competence and person – object differentiation: an
analysis of the still-face effect. Developmental Psychology, 29 (1), 63 – 73.
Field, T. M., Woodson, R., Greenberg, R., & Cohen, D. (1982). Discrimination and imitation of facial
expressions by neonates. Science, 218, 179 – 181.
Flavell, J. H., & Miller, P. H. (1998). Social cognition. In: D. Kuhn, & R. S. Siegler (Eds.), Handbook
of child psychology: vol. 2. Cognition, perception, and language (5th ed., pp. 851 – 898). New
York: Wiley.
Fodor, J. A. (1992). A theory of the child’s theory of mind. Cognition, 44, 283 – 296.
Frye, D., Rawling, P., Moore, C., & Myers, I. (1983). Object – person discrimination and communi-
cation at 3 and 10 months. Developmental Psychology, 19, 303 – 309.
Gerwitz, J. L., & Pelaez-Nogueras, M. (1992). Social referencing as a learned process. In: S. Feinman
(Ed.), Social referencing and the social construction of reality in infancy ( pp. 151 – 173). New
York: Plenum.
Gibson, E. J., Owsley, C. J., & Johnson, J. (1978). Perception of invariants by 5-month-old infants:
differentiation of two types of motion. Developmental Psychology, 14, 407 – 416.
Gopnik, A., & Astington, J. W. (1988). Children’s understanding of representational change and its
relation to the understanding of false belief and the appearance – reality distinction. Child Develop-
ment, 59, 26 – 37.
Hood, B. M., Willen, J. D., & Driver, J. (1998). Adults’ eyes trigger shifts of visual attention in human
infants. Psychological Science, 9, 90 – 93.
Johnson, S. C. (2000). The recognition of mentalistic agents in infancy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences,
4 (1), 22 – 28.
Johnson, S. C., Slaughter, V., & Carey, S. (1998). Whose gaze will infants follow? Features that elicit
gaze-following in 12-month-olds. Developmental Science, 1, 233 – 238.
Klein, R. P., & Jennings, K. D. (1979). Responses to social and inanimate stimuli in early infancy.
The Journal of Genetic Psychology, 135, 3 – 9.
Legerstee, M. (1991). The role of person and object in eliciting early imitation. Journal of Exper-
imental Child Psychology, 51, 423 – 433.
Legerstee, M. (1992). A review of the animate – inanimate distinction in infancy: implications for
models of social and cognitive knowing. Early Development and Parenting, 1, 59 – 67.
Legerstee, M. (1994). Patterns of 4-month-old infant responses to hidden silent and sounding people
and objects. Early Development and Parenting, 3 (2), 71 – 80.
Legerstee, M. (1997). Contingency effects of people and objects on subsequent cognitive functioning
in 3-month-old infants. Social Development, 6 (3), 307 – 321.
Legerstee, M., Pomerleau, A., Malcuit, G., & Feider, H. (1987). The development of infants’ res-
ponses to people and a doll: implications for research in communication. Infant Behavior and
Development, 10, 81 – 95.
Lempers, J. D. (1979). Young children’s production and comprehension of nonverbal deictic behav-
iors. Journal of Genetic Psychology, 135, 93 – 102.
656 S.C. Johnson et al. / Cognitive Development 16 (2001) 637–656

Leslie, A. M. (1994a). Pretending and believing: issues in the theory of ToMM. Cognition, 50,
211 – 238.
Leslie, A.M (1994b). ToMM, ToBy, and agency: core architecture and domain specificity. In: L. A.
Hirschfeld, & S. A. Gelman (Eds.), Mapping the mind: domain specificity in cognition and culture
( pp. 117 – 148). New York: Cambridge Univ. Press.
Leslie, A. M. (1995). A theory of agency. In: D. Sperber, D. Premack, & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal
cognition: a multidisciplinary debate ( pp. 121 – 141). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Leung, E. H. L., & Rheingold, H. L. (1981). Development of pointing as a social gesture. Devel-
opmental Psychology, 17, 215 – 220.
Meltzoff, A. N. (1995). Understanding the intention of others: re-enactment of intended acts by
18-month-old children. Developmental Psychology, 31, 838 – 850.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. (1983). Newborn infants imitate adult facial gestures. Child Develop-
ment, 54, 702 – 709.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1977). Imitation of facial and manual gestures by human neonates.
Science, 198, 75 – 78.
Moore, C., & Corkum, V. (1994). Social understanding at the end of the first year of life. Devel-
opmental Review, 14, 349 – 372.
Morton, J., & Johnson, M. M. (1991). CONSPEC and CONLERN: a two-process theory of infant face
recognition. Psychological Review, 98, 164 – 181.
Poulin-Dubois, D. (1999). Infants’ distinction between animate and inanimate objects: the origins of
naive psychology. In: P. Rochat (Ed.), Early social cognition ( pp. 257 – 280). Hillsdale, NJ:
Lawrence Erlbaum.
Puolin-Dubois, D., Lepage, A., & Ferland, D. (1996). Infants’ concept of animacy. Cognitive Develop-
ment, 11, 1 – 16, 19 – 36.
Premack, D. (1990). The infant’s theory of self-propelled objects. Cognition, 36, 1 – 16.
Repacholi, B. M., & Gopnik, A. (1997). Early reasoning of desires: evidence from 14- to 18-month-
olds. Developmental Psychology, 33, 12 – 21.
Ricard, M., & Allard, L. (1993). The reaction of 9- to 10-month-old infants to an unfamiliar animal.
The Journal of Genetic Psychology, 154 (1), 5 – 16.
Scaife, J. F., & Bruner, J. S. (1975). The capacity for joint visual attention in the infant. Nature, 253,
265 – 266.
Spelke, E. S., Phillips, A., & Woodward, A. L. (1995). Infants’ knowledge of object motion and
human action. In: D. Sperber, D. Premack, & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal cognition: a multi-
disciplinary debate. Oxford, England: Oxford Univ. Press.
Tomasello, M. (1995). Joint attention as social cognition. In: C. Moore, & A. Dunham (Eds.),
Joint attention: its origins and role in development ( pp. 103 – 130). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates.
Wellman, H. M. (1993). Early understanding of mind: the normal case. In: S. Baron-Cohen, H. Tager-
Flusberg, & D. J. Cohen (Eds.), Understanding other minds: perspectives from autism
( pp. 10 – 39). Oxford, England: Oxford Univ. Press.
Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: representation and constraining function of
wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition, 13, 103 – 128.
Woodward, A. (1998). Infants selectively encode the goal object of an actor’s reach. Cognition, 69,
1 – 34.

Potrebbero piacerti anche