Sei sulla pagina 1di 15

Journal of Occupational Science

ISSN: 1442-7591 (Print) 2158-1576 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rocc20

Occupational justice as social justice: The moral


claim for inclusion

Clare Hocking

To cite this article: Clare Hocking (2017) Occupational justice as social justice: The moral claim for
inclusion, Journal of Occupational Science, 24:1, 29-42, DOI: 10.1080/14427591.2017.1294016

To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/14427591.2017.1294016

© 2017 The Author(s). Published by Informa


UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis
Group.

Published online: 15 Mar 2017.

Submit your article to this journal

Article views: 8069

View Crossmark data

Citing articles: 10 View citing articles

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at


http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rocc20
JOURNAL OF OCCUPATIONAL SCIENCE, 2017
VOL. 24, NO. 1, 29–42
http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/14427591.2017.1294016

Occupational justice as social justice: The moral claim for inclusion


Clare Hocking
Professor, Auckland University of Technology, Auckland, New Zealand

ABSTRACT KEYWORDS
Occupational justice is typically framed as an aspect of social justice, a Occupational justice;
philosophical perspective that has traditionally emphasised treating occupational rights; social
people with respect and equitable distribution of societal resources. justice; moral claims;
occupational deprivation;
Contemporary views emphasise acknowledging difference and what
choice; opportunities
people have the capability to do and be, rather than what they receive.
This presentation questioned whether working towards occupational
justice can contribute to realising a just and inclusive society by
analysing how occupational justice issues have been argued. A
systematic review of diverse literature documenting occupational
injustices was completed, looking for whether social or occupational
justice was emphasised, what recourse authors made to human or
occupational rights, whether moral or ethical claims were made, and
how authors positioned their work. All authors were found to invoke
social justice concepts and relate previous or current human rights
abuses. Occupational deprivation was almost always cited and breaches
of people’s occupational rights were identified. Claims for social and
occupational justice were interrelated, with the right to work
emphasised. Moral claims to occupational justice were revealed in
descriptions of people experiencing occupational injustice as worthy
citizens and as suffering. Mechanisms that create and hold occupational
injustices were identified, and responsibility for achieving occupational
justice was situated within policy structures and with policy makers.

Occupational justice is a powerful idea, bridging human person, a just society is one in which
the gap between people’s well-being and harmful people are treated equitably. Second, all citizens
social conditions that restrict what they can do should receive a fair share of societal resources
and be. Evidencing its importance, by 2014 at (Robinson, 2016). Social justice addresses
least 19 book chapters and 63 articles discussed important social goals, whether acting in ways
occupational justice or injustice (Durocher, Gib- that befit an equitable and compassionate
son, & Rappolt, 2014). Through much of that lit- world, respecting human dignity, or creating
erature, occupational justice is taken to be an an inclusive society. Accordingly, a great deal
aspect, subset, derivative or complementary to of faith is put into its ideals. In actively promot-
social justice (Wilcock & Hocking, 2015; ing social justice, the United Nations holds it up
Stadnyk, Townsend, & Wilcock, 2010). While as a global force against “a future marred by vio-
the exact nature and outcome of social justice lence, repression and chaos” (United Nations,
has been long debated, the arguments seem to 2006, p. 6). The overarching question addressed
boil down to two key ideas. First, anchored to in this presentation is whether occupational jus-
belief in the dignity and sovereignty of the tice can contribute to realising a just and

CONTACT Clare Hocking clare.hocking@aut.ac.nz


© 2017 The Author(s). Published by Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group.
This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/),
which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
30 C. HOCKING

inclusive society, characterised by dignity and depends on whose opinion you seek. Two pro-
equity rather than cruelty and disarray. minent theorists of social justice are John
Towards answering that question, I review Rawls (1921-2002, US) and David Miller (born
what is meant by social justice and how that 1942, UK). Rawls (2001) promoted a vision of
fits with human rights. I begin with more tra- justice as fairness when protecting people’s
ditional views, before outlining how those access to civil liberties, human rights, and oppor-
views are contested by philosophers who assert tunities to lead a fulfilling and healthy life.
they do not give sufficient attention to what Inclusion, from his perspective, refers to civic
people can do and be, or to society’s responsibil- inclusion, meaning equitable opportunities to
ity to preserve people’s health. I then turn to access “health, education, personal fulfilment,
occupational justice, identifying its conceptual creativity, and so on” (Mann, 2012, p. 3).
foundations, how injustice is described from an Rawls explicitly addressed the liberties, rights
occupational perspective, and the issue of occu- and opportunities of the least advantaged mem-
pational rights. Having thus set the scene, I bers of society – those lacking freedom of
report a systematic review of seven accounts of thought and movement, power, income and
occupational injustice. The review investigated wealth, choice of occupation (meaning work),
how justice and human rights are represented, and the social basis of self-respect. Rawls’ version
and the extent to which researchers and social of justice is served by equity of opportunities,
change agents draw on those ideas to frame rather than equality of outcomes, so long as
their observations and findings. Pulling that everyone has a reasonable chance of taking up
together, I conclude by considering the contri- those opportunities. In specifying equity rather
bution occupational justice might make towards than equality, Rawls envisioned justice to mean
creating an inclusive society. fair and impartial distribution of opportunities
rather than, for example, a redistribution of
resources to ensure all citizens had equal status
Social Justice and Human Rights
and rights. His principle of fairness also applies
Justice is a theoretical concept that varies across to allocating the burdens of sustaining each
people, place and time. Humans have no need of other’s liberties, rights and opportunities. While
such a concept until we observe inequities between a fair share does not imply an equal share,
people that we perceive to be untenable. Within Rawls’ stance rejects the utilitarian principle of
modern democratic societies at least, inequities “the greatest amount of good for the greatest
that reach the threshold of being an injustice are number”, which could be used to justify “sacrifi-
commonly considered from the perspective of cing” individuals or minority groups for the com-
social justice, which functions as a moral compass, mon good. Addressing how social justice might
guiding both reasoning and action. When we be achieved, Rawls identified the role of political
frame justice as social justice we are acknowled- and social institutions as assigning basic rights,
ging two things. First, some inequities are created duties and burdens, and regulating the division
by societies rather than, for example, the forces of of benefits accrued from people’s cooperative
nature or god’s will. Second, we are asserting that input to society.
societies could do something different – alter the Where Rawls was a theorist, Miller (2001)
social arrangements in some way – to make the took a more pragmatic approach to identifying
situation more equitable. And in accepting that the basis of social justice, which he described
proposition, we are conceding that social insti- in terms of how advantages and disadvantages
tutions – politics, the economy, religion, schools should be allocated to members of society. Dis-
and the family - have a real world impact on advantages relevant to social justice include
people’s material circumstances. Some are dangerous work, military service and other hard-
favoured; many are not. ships. Advantages are personal security, prop-
As stated earlier, a just society is generally erty, money, transportation, housing, medical
considered to be one in which all citizens are care, care of children and elderly people, edu-
regarded with equal concern (Dworkin, 2000; cation, jobs and opportunities for leisure. Taking
Rawls, 1993). Exactly how that should play out the stance of full and equal participation of all
JOURNAL OF OCCUPATIONAL SCIENCE 31

groups in society, he proposed that these advan- Bringing Rawls’ and Miller’s perspectives
tages, or “goods,” be assigned on the basis of: together, social justice is broadly concerned
with the contract between a society and its mem-
. need, which is defined as having the basic bers, which sets up the conditions within which
necessities to function, or when people are citizens live and interact. That contract, as Rawls
being harmed or at risk of harm and Miller saw it, centred on allocating social
. what people deserve, given their level of per- advantages and disadvantages commensurate
formance in relation to the aims and purposes with people’s needs and performance, and pro-
of the community, and tecting them from gross injustices. In return
. equality, in the sense of upholding the human for state protection, citizens accept their respon-
rights of all citizens equally, an ideal that sibilities, fulfil their duties, and shoulder their
Miller held to be closely linked to “fellowship, share of the civic burden. Also central is treating
solidarity, social cohesion and social people fairly and respectfully, a principle that
inclusion” (Rashbrooke, p. 89). rests on ideas about equality and impartiality.
However, as feminist Iris Young (1990)
Needs are determined by what the community exposed, this is a normative view that favours
understands an adequate human life to be, and hegemonic norms of reason and respectability,
are differentiated from “wants.” Depending on thereby devaluing and suppressing differences
their ability to do so, all citizens are expected between social groups. Instead, her politics of
to contribute to meeting the needs of other difference affirm a differentiated, culturally
members of the community. Injustice, then, is plural society that counters group-based dis-
when government policy or social conditions crimination and oppression. This is a perspec-
interfere with getting the necessities to function, tive on inclusion that respects diversity and
harm people’s capacity to function, obstruct focuses on creating opportunities for people to
receiving what is deserved, or impede equal live, work, play, develop and age without exploi-
opportunity or treatment (Robinson, 2016). tation or violence. Another important consider-
Like Rawls, Miller sees the state as capable of ation is that, in considering the conditions of
instigating reforms, using force if necessary to people’s daily lives, both Rawls and Miller speci-
ensure compliance. Finally, Miller’s theory of fied income, wealth, property and money as the
social justice is pluralistic – in that need, desert, advantages deserved by those who fulfil their
and equality must be in balance. Remembering contract with society. Thus, lacking these
that equity refers to upholding human rights, resources is what distinguishes society’s least
Miller thus positions rights as central to social advantaged members. In describing social justice
justice. in these terms, they accepted a perspective cur-
While neither Rawls nor Miller enumerated rently held in many Western economies, that
the rights to be accorded to citizens, a point of wealth is directly and robustly connected to
reference is provided by the United Nations’ well-being (Venkatapuram, 2011).
(1948) Universal Declaration of Human Rights An additional compelling challenge to
(UDHR) and its subsequent conventions and Rawls and Miller’s assumption that justice is
covenants (See: A summary of UN Agreements achieved by fairly allocating society’s resources
on Human Rights, 1997). Those documents lay is that it neglects differences in people’s ability
out a set of universal principles addressing enti- to use those resources to generate outcomes
tlements to legal protections, having input to they value. An alternative, first espoused by
major life decisions such as marriage, and par- Nobel Laureate economist Amartya Sen, is
ticipation. Of note, the UDHR specifies cultu- capability theory. It proposes that well-being
rally important occupations; work, education, is not a matter of what people have – rather,
leisure, and the cultural life of the community. what they are able to do and be, and whether
Access to those occupations is thus implied by or not that enables them to lead a minimally
theories of social justice, whether Rawls’ oppor- dignified life for a human being (Sen, 1982).
tunities to lead a fulfilling and healthy life or In addressing the capability to do things
Miller’s basic necessities to function. people have reason to value, both human
32 C. HOCKING

functioning (i.e. doing and being), and external disability, religious or political affiliation, and
capabilities (opportunities) that make it poss- other characteristics. Thus, controversy exists
ible for people to do and be are brought into as to whether health disparities constitute a
play (Bailliard, 2016). What Sen left open social injustice that puts the inclusion of sick
was which doings and beings matter to people, and disabled people at risk. Without that
and whether that varies across different cir- acknowledgement there is less perceived need
cumstances. Martha Nussbaum’s (1999, 2011) for policies targeting the social conditions
formulation of 10 basic capabilities answers that create disparities in health status and
those concerns. They encompass aspects of longevity. Examples of such policies might
being; life, senses, emotion, affiliation. More include provision of a decent standard of liv-
important in this context, they point to the ing, adequate housing, participation in the
capacity for occupation (health, bodily integ- workforce and safe work conditions, urban
rity, thought, planning one’s life), the motives planning to create health-promoting physical
for occupation (adequate nourishment and environments, education to a standard and
shelter, sexual satisfaction, education, produ- level to support full participation, and social
cing expressive works, pleasurable experiences, acceptance, respect for and inclusion of
showing concern for other people, living with all subgroups within society (Braveman et al.,
animals and plants, play and recreation, 2011).
employment) and the resources required to Countering Rawls’ view, Sen (1999) strenu-
participate (property, goods). In combination, ously argued that health is a fundamental capa-
Sen and Nussbaum’s capabilities frameworks bility for functioning in society that ought to be
provide a means of determining what is just protected. He asserted that justice must attend to
– what people are able to do and be – and a the choices actually offered to people. On that
means to determine the parameters of a life basis, he argued that because ill-health further
that accords people at least a minimal level disadvantages socially disadvantaged groups, it
of dignity. is a barrier to realising their human rights and
participation in society. Following Sen’s lead,
Nussbaum identified health as one of her 10
Social Justice and Health
basic capabilities. Taking that argument one
At first sight, social justice appears to encom- step further, Venkatapuram (2011) spelled out
pass health. It seems implicit to Rawls’ notion that “social arrangements in the production, per-
of leading a fulfilling and healthy life or Mill- sistence through generations, levels, distribution
er’s basic necessities to function. Despite that patterns or differential experience of impair-
appearance, Rawls did not recognise that ments and death” (p. 5) are moral concerns;
health is a social good, and thus not part of people are not just disadvantaged – they are
social justice. Even with mounting evidence wronged. As such, the clearly recognizable dis-
of systematic disparities between rich and parities that exist are justice issues precisely
poor, he maintained that health is a “natural because societies could act to protect, nurture,
good,” something that lucky people might sus- and restore people’s capability to be healthy,
tain over their life course (Venkatapuram, through fair distribution of the determinants of
2011). Consistent with that viewpoint the health. In this, health disparities are a matter
right to health, and thus societal action to of justice.
reduce health disparities, is not specified in
human rights declarations. Rather, until late
Occupational Justice and Injustice
last century, health disparities were not
regarded as unnecessary, unfair, and avoidable Echoing Sen’s “capability to do and be” and
consequences of socioeconomic differences Venkatapuram’s health justice, occupational jus-
(Whitehead, 1991). Neither was the health tice has been defined as equitable or fair oppor-
impact of being stigmatised, discriminated tunities and resources “to do, be, belong and
against or marginalised because of your age, become what people have the potential to be
gender, sexual orientation, ethnicity, illness, and the absence of avoidable harm” (Wilcock
JOURNAL OF OCCUPATIONAL SCIENCE 33

& Hocking, 2015, p. 414). The concept of occu- so deficient as to seriously retard children’s
pational justice has three foundational ideas. development, result in substantive health
First, because humans are inherently occu- issues, or shorten people’s lifespan. At a societal
pational, the things people do are a determinant and community level, occupational injustice is
of health (Wilcock & Hocking, 2015). That purported to undermine the economy by wast-
implies that occupational justice is only served ing human potential and creating a health bur-
when conditions allow people to engage in den, reduce social cohesion by planting the
occupations in ways that are consistent with seeds of discontent and social unrest, and
their culture and beliefs (WFOT, 2006) and threaten people’s sense of safety (Christiansen
sustain well-being (Hammell & Iwama, 2012). & Townsend, 2010).
Additionally, occupational justice has an inclus- In teasing out the causes and effects of occu-
ive agenda, in specifying that people are appro- pational injustice, five variants have been
priately supported to participate in occupation identified:
(Townsend & Wilcock, 2004; WFOT, 2006).
Second, occupation is contextually embedded, . Occupational deprivation points to externally
which means that structural factors (the econ- imposed barriers to valued, meaningful occu-
omy, policies – at regional, national and inter- pations necessary for well-being
national levels, the values underlying those . Occupational imbalance is due to occu-
policies, and cultural values) and personal pational patterns of being over or under occu-
characteristics (age, gender, nationality, ethni- pied, due to excessive work demands,
city, religion, abilities and impairments, wealth enforced idleness, or burdensome responsi-
and income, work, social networks, and rural bilities to care for the environment, depen-
or urban location) are determinants of occu- dants or oneself
pation (Stadnyk et al., 2010). Third, engaging . Occupational alienation has been defined as
in occupation can improve the lives of people “deep feelings of incompatibility with the
in vulnerable situations (Whiteford & Hocking, occupations associated with a place, situation,
2012). Occupational justice, then, is concerned or others to the extent that basic needs and
with enabling, mediating and advocating for wants appear impossible to attain or main-
environments in which all people’s opportu- tain” (Wilcock & Hocking, 2015, p. 258). It
nities to engage in occupation are just, health- may manifest as aggressive occupations
promoting and meaningful. associated with social unrest or self-destruc-
Like justice, how occupational justice mani- tive behaviours
fests will vary across different cultures, times . Occupational marginalisation is usually
and places. As such, occupational justice associated with discrimination, such that
involves allowing that there are multiple, people are systematically relegated to occu-
equally legitimate ideas, traditions, and ways pational opportunities and resources that
of life that shape people’s occupational pat- are less valued within a society (jlucido93,
terns, standards and performances. Whilst 2013)
broad variation is acknowledged, it is also . Occupational apartheid refers to the systema-
recognised that established occupational pat- tic segregation of groups of people and delib-
terns and structures might be inherently unjust erately denying them access to occupations
(Wilcock & Townsend, 2000). Picking up on such as quality education or well-paid work,
the ideas central to social justice, breaches of or occupational contexts, based on prejudice
occupational justice occur when participation about their capacities or entitlement to the
in health enhancing occupations is inequitable benefits of culturally valued occupations
across different groups in society, with some (Wilcock & Hocking, 2015).
people unfairly benefiting and others subjected
to patterns of occupation that are detrimental As with discussions of social justice, there is a
to health and well-being. Indicating the ser- sense that such situations are not natural or
iousness of claiming an occupational injustice, immutable: the social conditions that give rise
it is further defined as patterns of occupation to occupational injustice could be changed.
34 C. HOCKING

Occupational Justice and Human also been proposed. Thus stipulated, the overlay
Rights of social justice principles becomes evident in
the notion of fair privileges and demand for
Just as theorists of social justice call on human
acknowledgement of difference. While no con-
rights to define the conditions all people ought
sensus has been reached, occupational rights
to be assured, occupational scientists invoke
have been defined as “the right of all people to
access to occupation as a “right”. Claiming a
engage in meaningful occupations that contrib-
right to occupation can be supported both philo-
ute positively to their own well-being and the
sophically and pragmatically. Drawing on the
well-being of their communities” (Hammell,
argument that health disparities are inequitable,
2008, p. 62). Working to secure occupational
thus revealing the right to health, occupation can
justice requires public awareness of breaches of
be considered a right because it is also socially
occupational rights and their impact, and colla-
determined and occupational inequities are
borative action to bring about occupationally
associated with real harm. More pragmatically,
just and inclusive societies.
occupational justice can be directly linked to
human rights through the United Nation’s
(1948) Universal Declaration of Human Rights. Instances of Occupational Injustice: A
Considered from an occupational perspective, Rights Focus?
the UDHR specifies particular kinds of occu-
Thus far, I have argued that human rights are
pations, such as slavery or servitude, and par-
central to current conceptions of social justice,
ticular occupational contexts, such as unjust or
and that the rights articulated internationally
unfavourable work conditions, with unreason-
directly address people’s access to occupation,
able working hours or without just remunera-
conditions relating to engagement in occu-
tion, as contravening human rights. Equally,
pation, and protection from exploitative occu-
being barred from certain occupations, for
pations. That acknowledgement gives credence
instance not having access to voting, rest and
to the concepts of occupational justice and injus-
leisure, education, enjoyment of the arts, or reli-
tice. In addition, through ongoing scholarship,
gious observances, would be in breach of human
variants of occupational injustice have been pro-
rights. Occupations that amount to torture or
posed and described, societal outcomes of occu-
“cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or pun-
pational justice and injustice outlined, and
ishment” (Article 5) are clearly identifiable as
structural determinants of occupational justice
human rights abuses. These universal rights are
identified. Thus informed, occupational justice
largely carried through to the World Federation
and occupational rights are often discussed in
of Occupational Therapists’ (WFOT; 2006) Pos-
tandem.
ition Statement on Human Rights. Synthesising
However, Hammell and Iwama (2012) have
the principles presented in the position paper,
argued against justice as a guiding concept
Stadnyk et al. (2010) identified four generic
because it is primarily concerned with equity
occupational rights to:
in the distribution of material advantages (prop-
erty, money, education, work, and leisure) and
1. Participate in a range of occupations to sup- burdens – not occupation. In addition, they
port health, development and inclusion attest, justice “does not address the causes of
2. Make choices and share decision making injustice or inequality” (p. 386), which seems
power in daily life an important omission if injustices are to be
3. Experience meaning and enrichment, and righted. Their final argument is that inquiries
4. Receive fair privileges from participation. into the justice of any situation always require
making a judgement about what is fair, and are
The WFOT position paper also stipulates the thus open to debate. In contrast, they claim,
right to be supported to participate in occu- human rights directly concern doing and “con-
pation. An additional right, to maintain different ditions that enable or constrain action”
views about occupation and traditional ways of (p. 386) and state unequivocally what people
doing things (Wilcock & Hocking, 2015), has are entitled to. Alternatively, Bailliard (2016)
JOURNAL OF OCCUPATIONAL SCIENCE 35

followed Venkatapuram (2011) in articulating . Jakobsen’s (2004) account of factors


an alternate discourse of moral entitlements, impeding participation in work for three
assertions and ends. Positioning occupational Norwegian women with rheumatoid
justice within that discourse would mean arthritis
encompassing multiple worldviews and engen- . Galvaan’s (2012) account of socio-economic
dering “different notions of health, justice, and and political influences on the occupational
how to affect them” (p. 3). In that way, the risk choices of “coloured” youths in a margina-
of imposing foreign ways of being on other lized community in Cape Town, South
people might be avoided. In light of those con- Africa
flicting methods of advancing an occupational . McElroy, Muyinda, Atim, Spittal, and Back-
justice agenda, it is instructive to examine docu- man’s (2012) analysis of ethnographic data
mented accounts of occupational injustice to on rural families in internal displacement
find out how researchers have framed their camps and on return to their homes in
work. Northern Uganda
. Bailliard’s (2013) ethnography of undocu-
Methods mented Latino migrants in a town in North
Carolina
In determining which accounts of occupational . Thibeault’s (2013) account of the community
rights and injustices to examine, I decided on a
consequences of an ill-conceived educational
couple of criteria. First, because judgements
programme delivering foreign aid in
about justice and injustice are contextual, I
Nicaragua
would need accounts that included relevant . Crawford, Turpin, Nayar, Steel, and Dur-
information about the sociocultural, political,
and’s (2016) analysis of the intersection of
historical, institutional, economic and occu-
structural and personal factors in the occu-
pational context. Second, to guard against the
pational deprivation of asylum seekers in
possibility that discussions of occupational jus-
Australia.
tice and occupational rights have taken a specific
focuses in particular contexts, I needed to select
My method was to read each article or chapter
literature focusing on diverse populations and
in full, looking for mentions of social justice
circumstances, and different variants of occu-
and associated concepts (inequality, fair distri-
pational injustice. Within those criteria, I
bution, rights, fair privileges, capabilities,
accepted both research and observational
citizens, and the phrase “all people”), the out-
accounts of occupational injustices. The ques-
comes of social justice (equity, inclusion), refer-
tions guiding the review were:
ences to United Nations’ declarations, and
1. What are authors pinning their discussions concepts used in the context of breaches of
to: principles of social justice or occupational human rights (discrimination, stigmatisation,
justice? racism, poverty and so on). I also looked for
2. Is there reference to specific human or occu- mentions of occupational justice and related
pational rights? concepts (occupational deprivation, imbalance,
3. Are moral or ethical appeals made? alienation, marginalisation, apartheid), and
4. Are the authors’ aims and recommendations terms associated with occupational rights
pinned to social or occupational justice or (range of occupations, choice, decision making,
rights? meaning, valued occupations, well-being). To
establish whether moral or ethical claims were
I reviewed 5 articles and 2 chapters (see Table 1), made I searched for those terms, while also
listed in order of publication: interpreting the tenor of claims made in
relation to the background to the study, the
. Whiteford’s (1997) description of the occu- findings, and any recommendations. Finally, I
pational deprivation of inmates in a special went back to the aims and recommendations
needs unit in a maximum security prison in to identify how authors situated the signifi-
New Zealand cance of their work.
36 C. HOCKING

Table 1. Reviewed Articles and Chapters


Year of
Authors Publication Title Source
Bailliard, A. 2016 Justice, difference, and the Journal of Occupational Science, 23(1), 3–16.
capability to function. doi:10.1080/14427591.2014.957886
Crawford, E., Turpin, M., 2016 The structural-personal interaction: Journal of Occupational Science, early online.
Nayar, S., Steel, E., & Occupational deprivation and doi:10.1080/14427591.2016.1153510
Durand, J-L. asylum seekers in Australia.
Galvaan, R. 2012 Occupational choice: The In G. E. Whiteford & C. Hocking (Eds.),
significance of socio-economic Occupational science: Society, inclusion,
and political factors. participation (pp. 152–162). Oxford: Wiley-
Blackwell.
Jakobsen, K. 2004 If work doesn’t work: How to enable Journal of Occupational Science, 11(3), 125–134.
occupational justice. doi:10.1080/14427591.2011.9686540
McElroy, T., Muyinda, 2012 War, displacement and protective Journal of Occupational Science, 19(3), 198–212.
H., Atim, S., Spittal, P., occupations in Northern Uganda. doi:10.1080/14427591.2011.614681
& Backman, C.
Thibeault, R. 2013 Occupational justice’s intents and In M. Cutchin, & V. Dickie (Eds.), Transactional
impacts: From personal choices to perspectives on occupation (pp. 245–256).
community consequences. New York: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-
4429-5_19
Whiteford, G. 1997 Occupational deprivation and Journal of Occupational Science: Australia, 4(3),
incarceration. 126–130. doi:10.1080/14427591.1997.9686429

Findings There were claims of atrocities that intentionally


targeted the civilian population (McElroy et al.,
Invoking social justice and human rights
2012). Asylum seekers were identified as fleeing
Social justice was directly invoked in three of the persecution and as socially excluded and stigma-
articles, as an end in itself and the context in tised in the country where they sought asylum
which concerns about occupational justice were (Crawford et al., 2016). Undocumented Latino
manifested (Bailliard, 2013; Jakobsen, 2004; Thi- families were described as subject to discrimi-
beault, 2013). The aspects of social justice specified nation, exploitation, oppression and persecution
were its application to “all people”, governmental (Bailliard, 2013). Similarly, claims of discrimi-
responsibility to create a fair society, and the “jus- nation, exclusion, stigmatisation and marginali-
tice of distribution” (Jakobsen, 2004, p. 125). Even sation were made in relation to people with
when the term social justice was not used, issues of disabilities (Jakobsen, 2004), and the ongoing
social justice were evident. South Africa’s historic marginalisation of people of mixed ethnic des-
apartheid era was named, with specific reference cent as a consequence of apartheid (Galvaan,
to the South African Group Areas Act of 1950, 2012) was voiced. Finally, a “colonialist mental-
which enacted the material power and privilege ity of exploitation” (Thibeault, 2013, p. 248) by
enjoyed by one group within society through gov- foreign aid programmes was asserted.
ernment policies of forced relocation of other Crawford and colleagues (2016) substantiated
groups (Galvaan, 2012). There were explicit claims their appeal to justice by citing asylum seekers’
of injustice (Crawford et al., 2016) and accounts of history of human rights violations, including
injustices, such as the forced internal displacement torture, along with exclusionary policies denying
of a large proportion of a rural population into them legal status as citizens. They also identified
camps with inadequate infrastructure for water, failure to fulfil legal responsibilities for human
food and sanitation (McElroy et al., 2012). Discre- rights to health, work, self-care, family, cultural,
pancies between statements in a penal manage- religious, leisure and learning occupations, and
ment plan about “respecting the dignity of all supported those claims with specific reference
persons” (Whiteford, 1997, p. 129) and how to the Universal Declaration of Human Rights
inmates were actually treated also point to social (United Nations, 1948), the Convention Relating
justice concerns. to the Status of Refugees (United Nations, 1951),
In some of the literature, the language and the International Covenant on Economic,
authors used highlighted issues of social justice. Social and Cultural Rights (United Nations,
JOURNAL OF OCCUPATIONAL SCIENCE 37

1966). Another strategy to give weight to human how individuals respond to those circumstances.
rights claims was to refer to local organisations They raised the question of whether occupational
that promulgate that perspective. For instance, deprivation is an action, something inflicted on
Norway’s Independent Living Organisation was others, or an experience of being occupationally
cited in relation to disability rights, with the deprived. Similar observations have been made
right to work and “actively participate in society in relation to being socio-economically deprived
as equal citizens” (Jakobsen, 2004, p. 126) (Bassouk & Donelan, 2003).
described as a requirement of inclusive societies.
In addition, authors invoked the right to work
Occupational rights
without recourse to international declarations
or covenants (e.g. Whiteford, 1997). Some Of the literature reviewed, only Thibeault (2013)
interpretation of human rights was also evident, explicitly addressed the occupational rights pro-
such as Crawford et al.’s (2016) reference to the posed by Stadnyk et al. (2010). None of the lit-
right to work as the right to earn a livelihood erature referred to the WFOT (2006) position
and, in the case of disabled women, failure to paper on human rights. Nonetheless, all the
enable the right to work being attributed to articles and chapters described breaches. The
lack of policy and material support (Jakobsen, right to a range of occupations was most vividly
2004). depicted for special needs inmates, who could
list multiple benefits of being occupied but in
the face of severe limitations in the environment,
Invoking occupational justice
resorted to sleeping (Whiteford, 1997). Imposed
Four of the articles and chapters directly referred restrictions were also identified as problematic
to occupational justice in the title, keywords or for asylum seekers, whose engagement in work,
as an opening claim (Crawford et al., 2016; Gal- study and daily occupations was disrupted, con-
vaan, 2012; Jakobsen, 2004; Thibeault, 2013). trolled and prevented by the policies governing
Another referenced a specific framework of them (Crawford et al., 2016). In contrast to
occupational justice and defined occupational these direct restrictions, self-imposed limits on
injustice (Bailliard, 2013). One other both their occupations were reported by undocumen-
defined occupational justice and identified it as ted Latino families, because driving to the venue
an aspiration dependent on national priorities or to fetch necessary resources carried the immi-
and social values (Jakobsen, 2004). Of the var- nent risk of being stopped and deported
iants of occupational injustice, occupational (Bailliard, 2013).
deprivation was almost always invoked The right to occupations that are chosen, self-
(Bailliard, 2013; Crawford et al., 2016; Jakobsen, selected (Jakobsen, 2004) or self-determined
2004; McElroy, 2012; Thibeault, 2013; (Crawford et al., 2016) was unambiguously
Whiteford, 1997) but the discussions were also asserted. However, the notion of choice was pro-
framed in terms of occupational marginalisation blematized by Galvaan’s (2012) discussion of the
(Galvaan, 2012; Jakobsen, 2004), occupational ways occupational choices are constrained by
alienation (Jakobsen, 2004) and occupational socio-economic and political environments.
imbalance (Bailliard, 2013). While most authors That constraint, she asserted, is not adequately
worked to current definitions of these concepts, ameliorated by providing access to a wider
Bailliard (2013) critiqued a current framework range of occupations, as has been previously
of occupational justice for failing to conceptual- suggested. Similarly, the right to experience
ise a threshold beyond which restricted partici- meaningful and enriching occupation, particu-
pation constitutes deprivation. In addition, larly work, was emphasised in six of the seven
Crawford and colleagues (2016) debated the articles and chapters. This occupational right
nature of occupational deprivation. Where it was breached by policies prohibiting asylum see-
has previously been described as a situation kers’ engagement in paid work, while at the same
imposed by external forces, they argued that it time restricting what they could study and do to
is better understood as an interaction of external purposefully use time (Crawford et al., 2016).
factors and personal characteristics that modify Prolonged lack of productive work options,
38 C. HOCKING

particularly for men held in camps for displaced to occupational justice issues, when she asserted
people, disrupted traditional lifestyles with resul- the need for “fair occupational participation for
tant breakdown of family and societal roles and all members” of a community (p. 248), and pro-
values. The associated loss of skills, identity, and cesses that respect their dignity, leadership abil-
sense of purpose and control, as well as enforced ity and control over defining their needs and
idleness, contributed to endemic substance goals. She also raised gender discrimination as
abuse and violence (McElroy et al., 2012). At a social and occupational issue, in relation to
an individual level, lack of real access to work the “negligible recognition and compensation”
was depicted as having negative psychological attached to women’s occupations (p. 250). As
and social impacts (Jakobsen, 2004), thus evok- well, Crawford and colleagues (2016) aligned
ing the right, as proposed by WFOT (2006), to human rights, as stipulated by the United
be supported to participate in occupation. The Nations, and occupational therapists’ attention
right to fair privileges from participation was to productive, self-care and leisure occupations.
raised in only one paper, in relation to exploita-
tive work arrangements endured by many undo-
Moral and ethical claims
cumented workers (Bailliard, 2013).
None of the seven authors made explicit moral
or ethical claims. However, moral claims were
Inter-relationship of social and
implied in presenting people in vulnerable cir-
occupational justice
cumstances as worthy of social and occupational
Social justice and occupational justice were seen justice. Thus, against the warders’ belief that
to be joint aspirations towards an inclusive special needs inmates “exhibit the whole range
world (Jakobsen, 2004) and mutually supportive. of human deficiencies” and that there would be
In addition, an occupational perspective by itself little value in interviewing them, they were pre-
was proposed to be a mechanism to promote just sented as willing and insightful informants
societies. For example, where distributive the- (Whiteford, 1997, p. 128). Similarly, the exploi-
ories of social justice point to inequitable allo- tation of undocumented Latino workers was
cation of resources, an occupational justice set against harrowing accounts of being detained
perspective can illuminate inequitable access to and deported without notification (Bailliard,
occupation (Bailliard, 2013; Crawford et al., 2013). In the case of women with disabilities,
2016). In so doing, an occupational perspective there was emphasis on their efforts to improve
might assist with determining priorities for their own situation by gaining educational qua-
change. Of note, inequitable access to occu- lifications, persisting in job seeking, displaying
pation is not directly addressed in either the a high work ethic, and making substantial efforts
WFOT (2006) Position Statement on human to sustain a worker role despite jeopardising
rights, nor Stadnyk et al.’s (2010) alternate ren- their health. Breaches of employment law were
dition of occupational rights. In addition, draw- suggested, and experiences of isolation, anger,
ing on the capabilities approach, aspirations for despair and alienation described, when health
occupational justice could be promoted by issues forced them to stop working (Jakobsen,
attending to both people’s capacity for partici- 2004). The ways that “historically predicated
pation in occupation (Bailliard, 2013; Crawford patterns of occupation” (Galvaan, 2012, p. 154)
et al., 2016) and social structures that restrict channel youths’ occupational choices towards
opportunities for occupation (Crawford et al., low quality work and alcohol and tobacco
2016). abuse are morally indefensible. The suffering of
While social and occupational justice were asylum seekers, who give vivid accounts of bore-
generally discussed separately, the linkage dom, anxiety, fear, depression, stress, confusion
between them was suggested in Thibeault’s and hopelessness, made worse by “having noth-
(2013) outrage over the appropriation of local ing to do” and the “harsh conditions in commu-
occupations by aid volunteers, a situation that nity detention” (Crawford et al., 2016, p. 3)
was certainly not equitable. Thibeault’s work is constitutes a moral claim, particularly in relation
also notable in applying social justice principles to more lenient treatment of refugees. The
JOURNAL OF OCCUPATIONAL SCIENCE 39

displaced Ugandan women left to raise children legislation (Bailliard, 2013). This nestling of
alone because of “death, separation, abandon- occupational injustice within a social justice per-
ment or withdrawal by fathers” (McElroy et al., spective supports claims that occupational jus-
2012, p. 203) were depicted as struggling against tice is aligned with or a derivative of social
enormous odds to keep their children safe, fed justice. Only Thibeault (2013), reporting obser-
and educated. vations from the field, framed her argument
Moral claims can also be discerned in from the opposite perspective. Charting the
accounts that exposed the gap between what inadvertent, but nonetheless devastating occu-
people might be capable of going and their pational injustices inflicted by aid agencies
lack of opportunity, thus echoing capability the- working towards social justice, she advocated
ory. For instance, Jakobsen (2004) itemised the the use of an occupational rights framework to
factors leading to an unjust society as lack of think through and monitor the impact aid
genuine access to work for people with disabil- workers have on the occupational patterns and
ities, along with devaluing of their abilities. Simi- livelihood of the recipient community.
larly, the occupational deprivation experienced
by inmates was explained as a direct result of a
Discussion and Implications
“no tools” policy, which not only deprived
them of opportunities for occupation but also Although its meaning is still being debated,
seemed to contribute to further loss of capacity many people perceive social justice to be about
(Whiteford, 1997). creating the social conditions for equality, toler-
ance, and participation, thus securing greater
security, peace, and a more cohesive society
Achieving occupational justice through
(Friesen, 2007). Proponents of occupational jus-
social justice mechanisms
tice likewise emphasise participation and equity
In situating the occupational injustice they in relation to occupational choice, to secure
sought to explore, the authors reporting research enhanced well-being and a more inclusive
findings all came from a social justice perspec- society (Wilcock & Hocking, 2015). Given that
tive. Under the rubric of “social structures,” philosophical alignment, the interweaving of
they identified historic socio-economic policies social and occupational justice concepts in the
(Galvaan, 2012), civil war (McElroy et al., occupational science literature is perhaps pre-
2012), penal policies (Whiteford, 1997), policies dictable. It made sense, in the field and in
governing the treatment of asylum seekers research contexts, to frame occupational justice
(Crawford et al., 2016), the way government pol- concerns with social justice principles – whether
icies are enacted (Bailliard, 2013), and lack of fairness, equality, respect or protection of
effective policy (Jakobsen, 2004) as the root human rights. Indeed, the alignment of social
cause of occupational injustice. Thus positioned, and occupational justice is evident even through
they sought to explain how those structures and the populations occupational scientists investi-
processes created occupational injustices. The gated, with people with disabilities, South Afri-
power of the accounts was in revealing the cans classified as “coloured”, internally
impact on people’s opportunities to participate displaced citizens, prisoners and people with
in culturally valued occupations. Taking an non-citizen status readily identifiable as at risk
occupational perspective put a human face on of social injustices.
injustice, showing the real and personal impact While social justice philosophy appeared to
on communities and individuals. The injustice be used to underline the importance and legiti-
was made tangible. Those who ventured to macy of the arguments presented, occupational
address how wrongs could be put right high- justice concepts proved powerful in revealing
lighted necessary attention to human rights the impact on participation and inclusion. Shift-
(Jakobsen, 2004), policy development ing perspective from participation in society to
(Whiteford, 1997) and changes in policy struc- participation in occupation helped researchers
tures (Crawford et al., 2016), or informing policy identify the specific barriers in place. More
makers of the unintended outcomes of importantly, addressing imposed interruptions
40 C. HOCKING

on occupation uncovered the human suffering in delineate occupational rights, the claims made
terms that can be readily understood, precisely broadly aligned with the rights listed in
because occupation is the stuff of people’s every- WFOT’s (2006) position paper on human rights
day lives. It was clear why men in displacement and their later reformulation (Stadnyk et al.,
camps would spend their days drinking rather 2010). That convergence supports the validity
than caring for their families (McElroy et al., and utility of the occupational rights proposed
2012), why undocumented Latino migrants thus far and, as Thibeault (2013) showed, review-
would accept low wages (Bailliard, 2013), and ing social change initiatives from the vantage
why “coloured” youths would take up the very point of occupational rights might protect the
occupations they had criticized in their parents recipient communities from unintended harm.
(Galvaan, 2012). These are compelling accounts In addition, as with concepts of occupational
of human suffering and wasted potential. The injustice, research is extending and challenging
power of these descriptions lends weight to the the initial formulation of occupational rights.
suggestion that moral claims for the removal of Specifically, Galvaan (2012) problematized the
barriers to participation, rather than accusations right to choose occupation, revealing how appar-
of injustice and human rights violations, may be ently “free” choice is distorted by people’s socio-
more effective in addressing occupational justice economic context. Finally, a gap was exposed in
issues (Bailliard, 2013; Venkatapuram, 2011). that existing renditions of occupational rights
In addressing barriers to participation and fail to address inequitable access to occupation,
inclusion, it was notable that authors were discri- as identified by Bailliard (2013) and Crawford
minating in their use of occupational depri- and colleagues (2016). Their work also points to
vation, occupational imbalance, occupational synergies between the capabilities approach and
marginalisation and occupational alienation, occupational justice aspirations.
even though few offered a definition of the termi-
nology they employed. These terms were also, at
Limitations and Future Directions
times, used in combination. For instance, Bail-
liard (2013) explained how fear of deportation The review of articles and chapters, although sys-
caused both an overall decrease in participation tematic, is clearly limited in scope, in including
in occupations outside the home (deprivation), only 7 sources, and may be subject to bias in
with more marked withdrawal from discretion- that the selection was made from the literature I
ary occupations such as visits to family (imbal- was aware of. A larger scale, systematic review of
ance). Similarly, Jakobsen (2004) described the the literature presenting accounts of occupational
disabled women she studied as experiencing injustices, and measures taken to counter it,
occupational deprivation, but also being isolated would both confirm these findings and generate
from society (occupational marginalisation) and a more nuanced view. In addition to informing
“being part of a life without meaningful occu- ongoing research, one practical outcome would
pation (occupational alienation). Such nuanced be to provide an evidence base from which to cri-
perspectives of occupational injustice suggest tique and update current statements of occu-
that, while occupational justice and occupational pational rights. The review presented here is also
rights claims might not be the most persuasive limited by my expanding but incomplete knowl-
means of promoting participation and inclusion, edge of the social justice literature. Clearly, efforts
they are useful concepts to sensitise researchers to further understand and influence occupational
to occupational justice issues. Additionally, test- justice will benefit from ongoing exploration of
ing occupational justice concepts in the field social justice philosophy, along with further criti-
promises to lead to their refinement, as in cal analysis of the growing body of literature
Crawford and colleagues’ (2016) reframing of reporting occupational justice concerns.
occupational deprivation as a transaction of
environmental restrictions and the personal
Conclusion
characteristics of the people who are deprived.
Finally, although authors of the studies Based on a review of seven accounts of occu-
reviewed might not cite the documents that pational injustices experienced by diverse groups
JOURNAL OF OCCUPATIONAL SCIENCE 41

in very different circumstances, occupational jus- Durocher, E., Gibson, B. E., & Rappolt, S. (2014).
tice and occupational rights have been shown to Occupational justice: A conceptual review. Journal of
Occupational Science, 21(4), 418–430. doi:10.1080/
be useful concepts. Those ideas sensitize
14427591.2013.775692
researchers to important inequities, assist them Dworkin, R. (2000). Sovereign virtue: The theory and
to understand the issues, and provide language practice of equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
to frame the actions necessary to make access to University Press.
occupations more inclusive and improve well- Friesen, M. (2007). Perceptions of social justice in New
Zealand. In R. Porter (Ed.), Pursuing social justice in
being. Consistent with understandings that occu-
New Zealand: 14 New Zealanders share their stories
pational justice is an aspect of social justice, of communities helping people in ways government
researchers situated their studies in relation to cannot (pp. 143–158). Auckland: Maxim Institute.
principles of fairness and equity. They encom- Hammell, K. W. (2008). Reflections on … Well-being
passed contemporary views that emphasise the and occupational rights. Canadian Journal of
Occupational Therapy, 75, 61–64. doi:10.2182/cjot.
need to acknowledge difference and to focus on
07.007
what people have the capability to do and be, Hammell, K. R. W., & Iwama, M. (2012). Well-being and
rather than what they receive. However, the occupational rights: An imperative for critical occu-
power of this body of research is in the moral pational therapy. Scandinavian Journal of
claims presented in findings. The immediate Occupational Therapy, 19(5), 385–394. doi:10.3109/
11038128.2011.611821
and intergenerational suffering associated with
jlucido93. (2013). OT occupational deprivation and jus-
occupational injustice is brought to life, made tice. Quizlet. Retrieved from https://quizlet.com/3154
immediate and understandable, when viewed 2250/ot-occupational-deprivation-and-justice-flash-car
from an occupational perspective. This, I suggest, ds/
is the power occupational justice will bring to Mann, M. H. (2012). Ricoeur, Rawls, and capability jus-
tice: Civic phronesis and equality. London, UK:
promoting just and inclusive societies. Bloomsbury.
Miller, D. (2001). Principles of social justice. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
ORCID Nussbaum, M. C. (1999). Sex and social justice.
New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Clare Hocking http://orcid.org/0000-0003-0364-5157 Nussbaum, M. C. (2011). Creating capabilities: The
human development approach. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Rawls, J. (1993). Political liberalism. New York, NY:
References Columbia University Press.
A summary of UN Agreements on Human Rights. (1997). Rawls, J. (2001). Justice as fairness: A restatement (E.
Retrieved from http://www.hrweb.org/legal/undocs. Kelly, Ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
html Press.
Bailliard, A. (2013). Laying low: Fear and injustice for Robinson, M. (2016). What is social justice? Boone, NC:
Latino migrants in Smalltown, USA. Journal of Appalachian State University. Retrieved from http://
Occupational Science, 20(4), 342–356. doi:10.1080/ gjs.appstate.edu/social-justice-and-human-rights/what-
14427591.2013.799114 social-justice
Bassouk, E. L., & Donelan, B. (2003). Social deprivation. Sen, A. (1982). Choice, welfare, and measurement.
In B. L. Green, M. J. Friedman, J. T. V. M. De Jong, S. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
D. Solomon, T. M. Keane, J. A. Fairbank, B. Donelan, Sen, A. (1999). Development as freedom. New York:
& E. Frey-Wouters (Eds.), Trauma intervention in war Random House.
and peace: Prevention, practice, and policy (pp. 33–55). Stadnyk, R., Townsend, E., & Wilcock, A. (2010).
New York City: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Occupational justice. In C. H. Christiansen & E. A.
Boston, J. (2013). What kind of equality matters? In M. Townsend (Eds.), Introduction to occupation: The art
Rashbrooke (Ed.), Inequality: A New Zealand crisis and science of living (2nd ed., pp. 329–358). Upper
(pp. 78–92). Wellington, NZ: Bridget Williams Books. Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Education.
Braveman, P. A., Kumanyika, S., Fielding, J., LaVeist, T., Townsend, E. A., & Wilcock, A. A. (2004). Occupational
Borrell, L. N., Manderschied, R., & Troutman, A. justice. In C. H. Christiansen & E. A. Townsend (Eds.),
(2011). Health disparities and health equity: The Introduction to occupation: The art and science of liv-
issue is justice. American Journal of Public Health, ing (pp. 243–273). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice
101(Suppl. 1), S149–S155. Hall.
Christiansen, C. H., & Townsend, E. A. (Eds.). (2010). United Nations General Assembly. (1948). Universal
Introduction to occupation: The art and science of living declaration of human rights. Paris, France: United
(2nd ed.). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Education. Nations.
42 C. HOCKING

United Nations General Assembly. (1951). Convention Whitehead, M. (1991). The concepts and principles of
relating to the status of refugees. Geneva, Switzerland: equity and health. Health Promotion International, 6
United Nations. (3), 217–228.
United Nations General Assembly. (1966). International Wilcock, A. A., & Hocking, C. (2015). An
covenant on economic, social and cultural rights. occupational perspective of health (3rd ed.).
New York, NY: United Nations. Thorofare, NJ: Slack.
United Nations. (2006). Social justice in an open world: The Wilcock, A., & Townsend, E. (2000). Occupational termi-
role of the United Nations. The International Forum for nology interactive dialogue: Occupational justice.
Social Development, Department of Economic and Social Journal of Occupational Science, 7(2), 84–86. doi:10.
Affairs, Division for Social Policy and Development, ST/ 1080/14427591.2000.9686470
ESA/305. New York, NY: United Nations. World Federation of Occupational Therapists. (2006).
Venkatapuram, S. (2011). Health justice: An argument from Position statement: Human rights. Retrieved from
the capabilities approach. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. http://www.wfot.org/ResourceCentre.aspx
Whiteford, G. E., & Hocking, C. (Eds.). (2012). Young, I. M. (1990). Justice and the politics
Occupational science: Society, inclusion, participation. of difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Oxford, UK: Wiley-Blackwell. Press.

Potrebbero piacerti anche