Sei sulla pagina 1di 276

Hispanic Studies: Culture and Ideas 50

William Rowlandson
50
Borges, Swedenborg

William Rowlandson • Borges, Swedenborg and Mysticism


Jorge Luis Borges was profoundly interested in the ill-defined and shape-
shifting traditions of mysticism. However, previous studies of Borges have not
focused on the writer’s close interest in mysticism and mystical texts, especially
in the Swedish mystic Emanuel Swedenborg (1688–1772). This book examines
the relationship between Borges’ own recorded mystical experiences and his
and Mysticism
appraisal of Swedenborg and other mystics. It asks the essential question of
whether Borges was a mystic by analysing his writings, including short stories,
essays, poems and interviews, alongside scholarly writings on mysticism by
figures such as William James. The book locates Borges within the scholarship
of mysticism by evaluating his many assertions and suggestions as to what is
or is not a mystic and, in so doing, analyses the influence of James and Ralph
Waldo Emerson on Borges’ reading of Swedenborg and mysticism. The author
argues further that Swedenborg constitutes a far richer presence in Borges’
work than scholarship has hitherto acknowledged, and assesses the presence of
Swedenborg in Borges’ aesthetics, ethics and poetics.

William Rowlandson is Senior Lecturer in Hispanic Studies at the University


of Kent.

ISBN 978-3-0343-0811-3

www.peterlang.com Peter Lang


Hispanic Studies: Culture and Ideas 50
William Rowlandson
50
Borges, Swedenborg

William Rowlandson • Borges, Swedenborg and Mysticism


Jorge Luis Borges was profoundly interested in the ill-defined and shape-
shifting traditions of mysticism. However, previous studies of Borges have not
focused on the writer’s close interest in mysticism and mystical texts, especially
in the Swedish mystic Emanuel Swedenborg (1688–1772). This book examines
the relationship between Borges’ own recorded mystical experiences and his
and Mysticism
appraisal of Swedenborg and other mystics. It asks the essential question of
whether Borges was a mystic by analysing his writings, including short stories,
essays, poems and interviews, alongside scholarly writings on mysticism by
figures such as William James. The book locates Borges within the scholarship
of mysticism by evaluating his many assertions and suggestions as to what is
or is not a mystic and, in so doing, analyses the influence of James and Ralph
Waldo Emerson on Borges’ reading of Swedenborg and mysticism. The author
argues further that Swedenborg constitutes a far richer presence in Borges’
work than scholarship has hitherto acknowledged, and assesses the presence of
Swedenborg in Borges’ aesthetics, ethics and poetics.

William Rowlandson is Senior Lecturer in Hispanic Studies at the University


of Kent.

ISBN 978-3-0343-0811-3

www.peterlang.com Peter Lang


Borges, Swedenborg and Mysticism
Hispanic Studies: Culture and Ideas

Volume 50
Edited by
Claudio Canaparo

PETER LANG
Oxford • Bern • Berlin • Bruxelles • Frankfurt am Main • New York • Wien
William Rowlandson

Borges, Swedenborg
and Mysticism

PETER LANG
Oxford • Bern • Berlin • Bruxelles • Frankfurt am Main • New York • Wien
Bibliographic information published by Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek.
Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche National-
bibliografie; detailed bibliographic data is available on the Internet
at http://dnb.d-nb.de.

A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data:

Rowlandson, William.
Borges, Swedenborg and mysticism / William Rowlandson.
pages cm. -- (Hispanic Studies: Culture and Ideas ; 50)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0811-3 (alk. paper)
1. Borges, Jorge Luis, 1899-1986--Criticism and interpretation. 2. Swedenborg,
Emanuel, 1688-1772--Influence. 3. Mysticism in literature. I. Title.
PQ7797.B635Z91635 2013
868’.6209--dc23
2012048394

Cover image: Cameron Adams, Lotus © 2013.

ISSN 1661-4720
ISBN 978-3-0343-0811-3 (print)
ISBN 978-3-0353-0438-1 (eBook)

© Peter Lang AG, International Academic Publishers, Bern 2013


Hochfeldstrasse 32, CH-3012 Bern, Switzerland
info@peterlang.com, www.peterlang.com, www.peterlang.net

All rights reserved.


All parts of this publication are protected by copyright.
Any utilisation outside the strict limits of the copyright law, without the
permission of the publisher, is forbidden and liable to prosecution.
This applies in particular to reproductions, translations, microfilming,
and storage and processing in electronic retrieval systems.

Printed in Germany
It seemed only proper that a blind man might be able
to be my guide to the world of darkness
— michael harner, The Way of  the Shaman
Contents

Acknowledgments ix

Introduction 1

Chapter One
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 47

Chapter Two
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 79

Chapter Three
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 125

Chapter Four
Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges 165

Chapter Five
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 193

Conclusion – Confronting the shadow:


The hero’s journey in ‘El Etnógrafo’ 225

Bibliography 243

Index 253
Acknowledgments

When I was sixteen my Spanish teacher at school, Claire McWilliams,


lent me a copy of  Fictions which still sits on my bookshelf. It is a 1985 John
Calder edition, which I have never seen for sale elsewhere, with a cover
illustration of zany zigzag arrows dancing through a labyrinth towards
two expressionless eyes. I thank and blame Miss McWilliams for push-
ing me down the rabbit hole into the Borges Wonderland, from which I
have never returned. If we should meet again, I will happily and gratefully
return her book.
Thanks to the University of  Kent for granting me study leave of one
semester in order to work on this and other projects.
Thanks to Claudio Canaparo, series editor of  Peter Lang’s Hispanic
Studies: Culture and Ideas. Thanks also to Hannah Godfrey, Mary Critchley
and Holly Catling at Peter Lang.
My thanks to Jeremy Carrette for his helpful perspectives on William
James, Henry James Sr. and the James family’s relationship with Swedenborg.
Thanks to Sophia Wellbeloved for her investigation into possible Borges-
Gurdjieff connections. Thanks also to Patricia Novillo Corvalán for many
corridor chats and email exchanges about Borges and for lending me books
(which I have returned) from her vast library of  the Borges scholarship.
Many of  the ideas set forward in this book were discussed in the former
Centre for the Study of  Myth at the University of  Kent. My thanks to
those who tolerated my ramblings and who shared their ideas and insights;
in particular Geoffrey Cornelius, Maggie Hyde, Vered Weiss, Matthew
Watkins, Lyndsay Radermacher and Cameron Adams. Additional thanks
to Cameron for the use of his artwork for the cover image.
Thanks in particular to Angela Voss, for the constant interchange of
memories, dreams and ref lections.

Thanks above all to the wonderful and beautiful Eva, Lucía and Blanca, to
whom this book is dedicated.
Introduction

Every time I read something, that something is changed. And every time
I write something, that something is being changed all the time by every
reader. Every new experience enriches the book. […] People read my
stories and read many things into them that I have not intended, which
means that I am a writer of stories. A writer who wrote only the things
he intended would be a very poor writer. A writer should write with a
certain innocence. He shouldn’t think about what he is doing. If not,
what he does is not all his own poetry.
— Borges, Borges at Eighty

I’m sorry to say that people have written fifty or sixty books about me. I
haven’t read a single one of  them, since I know too much of  the subject,
and I’m sick and tired of it.
— Borges, Borges at Eighty

They tell me there are some 300 books that have been written about me.
But I think the writers should choose a better subject.
— Borges: interview with William F. Buckley

Todo hombre memorable corre el albur de ser amonedado en anécdotas


[‘Every memorable man runs the risk of  being minted in anecdotes’]
— Borges, Atlas

Emanuel Swedenborg writes in the Preface of  Heaven and Hell (1758):
‘it has been granted me to be with angels and to talk with them person
to person. I have also been enabled to see what is in heaven and in hell, a
process that has been going on for thirteen years’ (§1).1 He writes later in

1 All citations of  Swedenborg’s Heaven and Hell are from the translation of  George F.
Dole for the Swedenborg Foundation’s New Century Edition, 2000. As is customary
2 Introduction

the work: ‘I have been allowed to talk with some people who lived more
than two thousand years ago, people whose lives are described in history
books and are therefore familiar’ (§480). He repeatedly claims that ‘I can
bear witness from all my experiences of what happens in heaven and in
hell’ (§482), and begins many paragraphs with statements such as ‘Angels
have told me that …’ (§184, §222, §302, §310, §480). Swedenborg, it would
appear, was fully aware that his accounts would constitute a challenge to his
readership, and, indeed, he famously writes in Arcana Cœlestia: ‘I am well
aware that many will say that no one can possibly speak with spirits and
angels so long as he lives in the body; and many will say that it is all fancy,
others that I relate such things in order to gain credence, and others will
make other objections. But by all this I am not deterred, for I have seen, I
have heard, I have felt’ (§68). How is the reader to judge this? What herme-
neutic tools does the reader employ in order to judge the literary aesthetic
of  Swedenborg’s texts against works of  fantasy or voyages of discovery?
Borges admired Swedenborg and wrote extensively about him; indeed
the strong presence of  Swedenborg in Borges’ work constitutes a curious
absence in the scholarship. Following the lead of  Ralph Waldo Emerson,
Borges delivered lectures on Swedenborg which he later transcribed and
published and in which he called Swedenborg ‘un místico mucho más
complejo que los otros’ (2005: 202) [‘a mystic far more complex than the
others’] (my translation). In the lecture and in other writings Borges paid
close attention to the otherworld journeys of  Swedenborg, to his commu-
nication with angels and demons and with the discarnate souls of  the dead.
Whilst uncomfortable with the theological dimension of  Swedenborg’s
writings, arguing that his originality and innovation demonstrated a strong
degree of  heterodoxy, Borges greatly admired the ethical aspect of  his works.
Furthermore, Borges repeatedly defended Swedenborg against charges
of insanity, arguing that the man was remarkably lucid, that his accounts
were the product of a profoundly intellectual mind, and that his voyages
constituted journeys of discovery akin to Swedenborg’s Viking ancestors.

with the Swedenborg scholarship, I will use throughout paragraph marks: §, rather
than page references.
Introduction 3

‘Swedenborg,’ wrote Borges, ‘es el primer explorador del otro mundo, el


explorador que debemos tomar en serio’ (2005: 202) [‘Swedenborg is the
first explorer of  the other world. An explorer we should take seriously’]
(my translation). Whilst the reader of  Swedenborg is presented with chal-
lenges to assumptions about life, death, angelic beings and the divine, the
reader of  Borges’ texts concerning Swedenborg is presented with an equally
challenging set of questions concerning the relationship between fact and
fiction, realism and fantasy, voyages of discovery and poetry, orthodoxy
and heterodoxy. Expanding this, it becomes clear that all of  Borges’ writ-
ings concerning the ill-defined tradition of mysticism are characterized by
equally puzzling questions of  the nature of  the real.
I have been reading and encouraging others to read Borges for twenty
years, and have taught his works, especially the poetry, at university level
for a decade. In a class discussion at the end of a semester’s course, one
member of  the seminar remarked that the word that best sums up Borges
was ‘unsettling.’ We pursued this, enquiring what exactly is unsettling and
what exactly is unsettled. Her response was curious: ‘After reading so much
Borges nothing is stable any more. Things are unhinged.’ Another student
had suggested that the course ‘is not for the fainthearted’. Over the weeks
we had followed a more or less chronological assessment of  Borges’ tales,
essays and poems, spending proportionally longer on his later works (1960s
onwards) than the prolific era of  the 1940s and 1950s, culminating in the
whimsical tales of  El Hacedor [Dreamtigers], El Libro de Arena [The Book
of  Sand] and La Memoria de Shakespeare [Shakespeare’s Memory], the medi-
tative lectures of  Siete Noches [Seven Nights], the poem and prose pieces
of Elogio de la sombra [In Praise of  Darkness] and Los Conjurados, and the
many interviews. We ref lected on the ‘unsettling’ aspect of  Borges. How
do things appear ‘unhinged’? Why is the course not for the fainthearted?
The class unanimously agreed that not only had the texts been puzzling,
challenging, and at times infuriating, but that over the course of  their
reading something had changed within them, that their relationship with
reality had been somehow af fected by the many questions and conundrums
thrown up by the Borges texts.
The discussion, with books closed, lasted a full two hours, and follow-
ing the lead of  the first student, more members of the group felt empowered
4 Introduction

to discuss their personal reactions to the texts and the manner in which the
course had af fected them. Some discussed curious dreams of  labyrinthine
landscapes; others described sleepless nights or late-night discussions with
friends puzzling over the metaphysical riddles crafted by Borges. I myself
recalled reading The Book of  Sand at the age of seventeen, and how I had
struggled to conceptualize and accommodate such alluring horrors as the
infinite book, the monstrous Preetorius, and the meeting of  the young and
old Borges on a bench by a river. To this day I still feel the same vertiginous
thrill at contemplating the one-sided disc. What could possibly be on the
other side? Clearly there is something transformative in the process of close
reading of  Borges’ works and spirited group discussion.
A word that had surfaced at repeated moments throughout the course,
especially when we dwelt on the tales ‘El Aleph’ and ‘La escritura del dios’
[‘The God’s Script’] was ‘mysticism’. Nothing, it was soon revealed, is
straightforward about this troublesome term, firstly because the defini-
tions of  the word are strikingly variant and contradictory, and secondly
because the terms ‘mysticism’, ‘mystical’ and ‘mystic’ raise some profound
epistemological questions about the nature of reality. Furthermore, in rela-
tion to the act of interpretation of, for example, the ecstatic episode of  ‘El
Aleph’, questions emerged in class discussion about how to reconcile the
text with the author and with the reader. Is a ‘mystical’ text necessarily the
product of a ‘mystic’? Is ‘El Aleph’ a mystical text? What is a mystical text?
Was Borges a mystic? What is a mystic? Can a text itself  be mystical, or is it
merely the description of a mystical state? Can there be a mystical reading
of a non-mystical text, and vice-versa? If, for example, a reader experiences
something profoundly ‘mystical’ in reading ‘El Aleph’, what would be the
implications of  finding out that the text were a parody of mystical texts?
Is ‘El Aleph’ a parody of mystical texts?
Borges was profoundly interested in the ill-defined and shape-shifting
traditions of mysticism, writing numerous essays and poems about mys-
tical writers in the Christian traditions: Scotus Erigena, Dante, Meister
Eckhart, Jakob Böhme (also written Boehme and Behmen), Angelus
Silesius, Emanuel Swedenborg, William Blake, Novalis, and Emerson;
exploring Sufi mystical poetry, Buddhist and Zen doctrines of spiritual
philosophy, the Kabbalah, and various traditions of  Neoplatonism and
Introduction 5

western esotericism. There is, however, an absence in the scholarship con-


cerning Borges’ close involvement with mysticism and mystical texts, espe-
cially – as this book explores – Swedenborg. Whilst his interest in religious
philosophies and practices such as the Kabbalah and Buddhism has been
explored in some excellent books and articles, his relationship to specific
mystical writers and texts has received far less attention, and for the most
part appears only as oblique and generally unexplored references. This is
unsurprising for three reasons that I can identify.
Firstly, there is no easily delineated school of mystical writers; the tra-
ditions are characterized by heterogeneity. Indeed one of  the central tasks
of  the various scholars of mysticism has been to identify precisely what it is
that binds historical figures like Erigena, Eckhart, Teresa de Ávila, Böhme,
Swedenborg and Blake. Likewise, the concepts of mystics, mysticism,
mystical visions and mystical states are dif ficult to define and categorize.
This is of crucial importance, as whilst Borges may call Plotinus, Silesius,
Swedenborg, Blake and his friend Xul Solar ‘místicos’, and whilst he may
claim that Pascal, Teresa de Jesús, Juan de la Cruz and Luis de León were
not mystics, it is surprisingly dif ficult to arrive at any clear understanding
of what the term means, despite over a century of rigorous scholarship. The
scholarship of mysticism reveals countless attempts, pioneered by William
Inge and William James, to define mysticism according to key characteris-
tics. However, as I explore in Chapter Two, these defining characteristics
are generally themselves vague and dif ficult to define. Furthermore, these
terms are often refuted by the proceeding scholar’s defining characteristics
(Underhill’s list, for example, is strikingly dif ferent from James’s; Stace’s
is very dif ferent from Underhill’s). There is consequently no consensus.
Secondly, Borges himself described mystics and mystical texts with
a confusing blend of philosophical scepticism, literary awe, metaphysical
perplexity and personal fondness. As such, and in tune with the well-known
bon mot from ‘Tlön, Uqbar, Orbis Tertius’ that ‘la metafísica es una rama
de la literatura fantástica’ (1974: 436) [‘metaphysics is a branch of  fantas-
tic literature’] (1976: 34), it is dif ficult to distinguish between his af fec-
tion for the imagined worlds of  H. G. Wells, the fantastical adventures of 
Stevenson, the biblical accounts of  the Virgin Birth or the Resurrection,
Dante’s poetical visions of  the circles of  Hell, Purgatory and Heaven, and
6 Introduction

Swedenborg’s visions of  the angelic realms.2 Are all these texts fantasy,
or does Borges develop separate textual hermeneutics for fiction, science
fiction, mystical, metaphysical and theological texts? In brief, as I explore
in Chapter One, does Borges appraise Swedenborg’s angels in the same
ontological light as the genies of  the Thousand and One Nights, or do his
repeated claims of  Swedenborg’s ‘authenticity’ suggest a dif ferent and curi-
ous distinction between fantasy and mystical vision?
Thirdly, and importantly, it would appear that Borges scholarship, tied
as it is to the Academy, treats the shape-shifting and ill-defined landscape of
mysticism and mystical texts with reservation. This, as Kripal (2001) argues,
relates to a general mistrust of  the numinous within a scholarly methodol-
ogy that seeks robust conclusions to robust hypotheses. Mysticism, and the
many cognate aspects of anomalous human experience generally appraised
under the titles of parapsychology, paraphenomena or the occult, appear to
defy such a methodology. This aspect is explored in detail in Chapter Two.
Borges is, of course, ideal fodder for academic discourse. The complex
literary structures of  the great Ficciones, the meta-textual game-playing, the
web of  literary and philosophical inf luences upon his work, his inf luence
upon other writers, the rigorous and meticulous scepticism, the interplay
of philosophies, theologies and metaphysics, the dazzling intellect – all
such attributes of  his work provide limitless scope for further levels of
interpretation for research papers and rich material for teaching. There
is something academically reliable in Borges, as a judicious choice of  his
fictions can illustrate with suf ficient complexity aspects of  literary theory,
literary movements, the style of  the short story, the interplay of  literature
and philosophy, and so on. His works are studied to illustrate characteristics
of modernism and postmodernism, magical realism (however obliquely),
Argentine and Latin American literature, and even postcolonialism (see
Warnes 2009). However, I feel that something is often lost in the habitual
employment of  Borges to illustrate such academic concepts, and it was in
response to this that I developed a course dedicated exclusively to the works

2 See Brescia (2008) for an evaluation of  how Borges (and Bioy Casares) blurred genre
distinctions in their anthologies of  the fantastic.
Introduction 7

of  Borges in which close reading of  the texts and responsive discussion are
encouraged over a teaching of  literary schools and movements, genre buzz­
words or single attributes of  Theory. What, though, is lost?
Borges regularly urged the students at his lectures, whether in Argentina
or the US, to seek the transformative dimension of  literature, to seek ‘el
encanto’ that a text can bring: ‘El encanto es, como dijo Stevenson, una
de las cualidades esenciales que debe tener el escritor. Sin el encanto, lo
demás es inútil’ (1989: 209)’ [‘Enchantment, as Stevenson said, is one of 
the special qualities a writer must have. Without enchantment, the rest is
useless’] (1984: 9). He likewise discusses the importance of  the love of  lit-
erature: ‘I think that compulsory reading is wrong. You might as well talk
of compulsory love or compulsory happiness. One should be reading for the
pleasure of  the book. I was a teacher of  English literature for some twenty
years and I always said to my students: if a book bores you, lay it aside. It
hasn’t been written for you’ (Barnstone 1982: 113).3 As I have discovered
through conversations with occasional disheartened readers of  Borges,
an over-examination of  his most famous tales – such as ‘Pierre Menard,
autor del Quijote’, ‘Tlön, Uqbar, Orbis Tertius’, ‘La muerte y la brújula’, ‘La
biblioteca de Babel’ or ‘El jardín de senderos que se bifurcan’ – can lead to
a reception of  Borges as cold, scholastic, passionless and claustrophobic,
whose texts are mere springboards for further academic displays of erudi-
tion. This is a fair reading, especially amongst pressured undergraduates
in full lecture theatres; but it is not the only reading, and it saddens me to
consider readers who consequently assume that the text ‘hasn’t been writ-
ten for them’ and who feel dissuaded from exploring further. Reading need
not be a purely intellectual exercise. To argue, however, that there is a more
numinous aspect to Borges is problematic, owing to the radical scepticism
and spiritual agnosticism that characterize his extensive works.

3 ‘I said to my students […] I can’t teach you English literature because I don’t know
it. But I can teach you the love of  English literature. […] They all fell in love with
some book or another, and that’s the gist, that’s the important thing, yes?’ (Burgin
1998: 209).
8 Introduction

There are striking similarities, for example, between the experience


of  the Borges narrator on the basement stairs in ‘El Aleph’ and the dream
revelation of  Tzinacán in ‘La escritura del dios’. These two passages may be
read in isolation of  their surrounding texts and may with good reason be
considered examples of ecstatic mystical writing akin to Eckhart or Teresa
de Ávila; indeed they constitute remarkable examples of visionary art.
Giskin (1990), confirming this aspect, appraised in particular ‘El Aleph’
as embodying the four characteristics of mystical experience as described
by William James: Inef fability, Noetic quality, transiency and passivity. He
concludes that Borges was consequently a mystic. However, when the tales
are read in their entirety, it is apparent that they are carefully constructed
fictions, revealing a radically more sceptical, philosophical and literary
quality than the brief isolated passages, and may even be considered paro-
dies of mystical texts. Akin to the uselessness of  Funes’ perpetual rapture,
the impossible Aleph serves the narrator only as a means of prying into
the private correspondence of  his former lover and her cousin, and serves
Daneri only as material for pretentious poetry. Tzinacán’s communion
with god serves him only to allay the horrors of  his people’s destruction
and his incarceration. So are these texts, in tune with Giskin’s assessment,
mystical, or are they parodic critiques of mysticism?
One means of addressing this question, in addition to an appraisal of 
the scholarship of mysticism, is to consider the textual traditions of mysti-
cism as ‘another branch of  fantastic literature’, and thus to evaluate Borges’
exploration of such traditions and his employment of  them for the purposes
of crafting fiction. In this respect one must first consider his intricate engage-
ment with various traditions of philosophy, and his repeated claims that
he was not a philosopher himself  but a mere poet/author whose interest
in philosophy was for aesthetic aims. Is there a parallel between his use of
philosophy for aesthetic purposes and his use of mysticism?
Introduction 9

Mysticism for aesthetic purposes

The relationship between Borges and philosophy has been extensively ana-
lysed; and the heart of many of  these studies is described by Bosteels (2006:
23) as the perennial question from the audience member in the front seat
who, ‘with the triumphant smile of an ironist, remark[s] that the Argentine
should not be taken so seriously since, after all, he is not a philosopher but
a literary writer, that is, someone who merely toys with philosophical ideas
for the sake of entertainment and aesthetic pleasure, without implying
any systematic philosophy of  his own.’ To put it more simply: was Borges
a philosopher? This question has been approached from the perspective
that yes, he was a philosopher, if  taking the etymological roots of  the term
as a lover of wisdom; that no, he was instead an ‘antiphilosopher’, in that
his scepticism of philosophical discourses was itself systematic.4 Other
responses to the contrary have been of fered, encapsulated in Victor Lange’s
preface to the original English translation of  El Hacedor [Dreamtigers]:

The ancestors of  this philosophy of detachment and self-doubt seem present at every
moment of  Borges’ ref lections: the voice of  Pascal or Berkeley, of  Hume and Kant
join to liberate the spirit of man from the confining reality of  this world; Heraclitus,
Spinoza, Schopenhauer, and Nietzsche testify to the eternal recurrence in which the
single act becomes myth and symbol. Yet there is in Borges’ writings no coherent

4 ‘[…] such a rejection of systematic thinking is in itself astonishingly systematic – so


systematic, in fact, that it ceases to be astonishing at all. Indeed, the objection that
Borges’s own delightful sense of irony defeats any and all attempts to of fer a systematic
account of  his thinking falls squarely in line with a longstanding argument according
to which all philosophers, in their millenarian love of  truth, sooner or later become
prey to an arrogant illusion of mastery, and that the sheer thrill of  happiness, of
enjoyment, or of pleasure, though perhaps no less inaccessible to us mere mortals,
nonetheless is a worthier object of pursuit than the ever-elusive line of demarcation
between opinion and truth that completely seems to absorb the philosopher since
at least Plato. The reaction against philosophy as system not only forms a systematic
tradition in its own right, but this tradition moreover hides a prestigious genealogy
that as a minimum would have to include the likes of  Saint Paul, Pascal, Rousseau,
Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, and the early Wittgenstein’ (Bosteels 2006: 24).
10 Introduction

attempt at elaborating his own or others’ philosophical positions; indeed, his dis-
taste for any supposition of meaning leads him to insist that all systems of  thought,
all philosophical or theological speculations are merely evidence of  that desperate
compulsion to ref lect upon our own delusions; as such they are instances of  fan-
tastic literature. And it is the agony of philosophical perplexity, those moments at
which ‘the scruples and wonders of  thought’ appear at their most illusory, that are
the matter of  Borges’ art. (Lange, in Borges 1970: xiii)

Borges himself emphasized that his appreciation of philosophers lay prin-


cipally in his admiration of  the aesthetic value: the poetic language, the
elegance of  the rhetoric and the finery of argumentation. Whilst admiring
the aesthetics, he was nevertheless sceptical about the very nature of phi-
losophy and its pretence to eternal truths. And yet, sceptical as he was, he
nevertheless delved deeply into philosophy and its histories, exploring with
delight the intellectual complexities and conundrums, the claims to truth,
the inf luence of social context and the passing of philosophical fashions.
He gently exposed what for him was the beautiful futility of philosophy
in its attempt to explain the riddle of  the universe: ‘We can go on making
guesswork – we will call that guesswork philosophy, which is really mere
guesswork. We will go on weaving theories, and being very much amused
by them, and then unweaving and taking other new ones’ (Barnstone 1982:
111), and he was keen to address this aesthetic quality of philosophical or
theological systems. In the epilogue to Otras Inquisiciones, he argued that
‘Dos tendencias he descubierto [en] este volumen. Una, a estimar las ideas
religiosas o filosóficas por su valor estético y aun por lo que encierran de
singular y maravilloso. Esto es quizás indicio de un escepticismo esencial’
(1974: 775) [‘the first tendency [of  this volume] is to evaluate religious or
philosophical ideas on the basis of  their aesthetic worth and even for what is
singular and marvelous about them. Perhaps this is an indication of a basic
skepticism’] (1964: 201). He declared to Ronald Christ that ‘I am a man of 
letters who turns his own perplexities and that respected system of perplexi-
ties we call philosophy into the forms of  literature’ (Alazraki 1988: 31). To
Richard Stern he declared: ‘I’m not really a thinker. I’m a literary man and
I have done my best to use the literary possibilities of philosophy’ (Burgin
1998: 8). In a 1973 interview with María Esther Vázquez, he asserted that:
Introduction 11

No soy filósofo ni metafísico; lo que he hecho es explotar, o explorar – es una pala-


bra más noble –, las posibilidades literarias de la filosofía. […] Yo no tengo ninguna
teoría del mundo. En general, como yo he usado los diversos sistemas metafísicos y
teológicos para fines literarios, los lectores han creído que yo profesaba esos siste-
mas, cuando realmente lo único que he hecho ha sido aprovecharlos para esos fines,
nada más. Además, si yo tuviera que definirme, me definiría como un agnóstico, es
decir, una persona que no cree que el conocimiento sea posible. (Vázquez 1977: 107)

[I am neither philosopher nor metaphysician. What I have done is exploit, or explore


– a more noble word – the literary possibilities of philosophy. […] I have no theory
of  the world. In general, seeing that I have used diverse metaphysical and theologi-
cal systems for literary objectives, readers have believed that I have professed those
systems, when really all that I have done has been employ them for those ends,
nothing more. Furthermore, if  I had to define myself, it would be agnostic; that’s
to say, someone who does not believe that knowledge is possible.] (My translation)

Lastly, he declared to Michael Palencia-Roth that his interest in all systems


of  thought lay in the application of such systems for aesthetic purposes:

MP-R: You say you’re not a thinker …


Borges: No, what I mean to say is that I have no personal system of philosophy. I
never attempt to do that. I am merely a man of  letters. In the same way,
for example that – well, of course, I shouldn’t perhaps choose this as an
example – in the same way that Dante used theology for the purpose
of poetry, or Milton used theology for the purposes of  his poetry, why
shouldn’t I use philosophy, especially idealistic philosophy – philosophy
to which I was attracted – for the purposes of writing a tale, of writing a
story? I suppose that is allowable, no? (Dutton 1977: 339)

From his repeated and emphatic statements, we can suggest that Borges
employed a degree of  Kantian logic and Schopenhaurian scepticism in
order to expose the frailty of philosophical, theological and metaphysical
systems and doctrines. This does not derive from a position of intellectual
arrogance, but more from a Jamesian location in which such belief systems
are shown to be true only insofar as they relate to provisory human af fairs.
Thus the ‘antiphilosophical’ stance of  Borges, which is indeed systematic,
is gloriously inclusive, not selective, and celebrates the intellectual and
aesthetical splendour of  his treasured artists, philosophers and metaphysi-
cians. It is an agnostic position in its fullest sense.
12 Introduction

‘Being an agnostic’ Borges argued, ‘means all things are possible, even
God, even the Holy Trinity. This world is so strange that anything may
happen, or may not happen. Being an agnostic makes me live in a larger, a
more fantastic kind of world, almost uncanny. It makes me more tolerant’
(Shenker 1971).5 Agnosticism here should be appreciated in its etymologi-
cal sense – not a position of disinterest in matters religious or spiritual, as
it is habitually understood to signify, nor as simply not belonging to any
particular faith group – but, as Borges describes, an acceptance that ulti-
mate knowledge of  the mysteries of existence is not forthcoming. There
are two immediately recognisable characteristics within Borges’ fiction,
poetry, essays and interviews that demonstrate this agnostic position. Firstly,
numerous texts conclude with a bathetic absence of revelation. For example,
the narrator of  the tale ‘Pedro Salvadores’ of Elogio de la sombra concludes
with ‘Como todas las cosas, el destino de Pedro Salvadores nos parece un
símbolo de algo que estamos a punto de comprender’ (1974: 995) [‘As
with so many things, the fate of  Pedro Salvadores strikes us as a symbol of
something we are about to understand, but never quite do’] (1975a: 65).
Most well-known, perhaps, is the conclusion of  ‘La Muralla y los Libros’
[‘The Wall & the Books’] (1950):

La música, los estados de felicidad, la mitología, las caras trabajadas por el tiempo,
ciertos crepúsculos y ciertos lugares, quieren decirnos algo, o algo dijeron que no
hubiéramos debido perder, o están por decir algo; esta inminencia de una revelación,
que no se produce, es, quizá, el hecho estético. (1974: 635)

[Music, states of  happiness, mythology, faces molded by time, certain twilights and
certain places – all these are trying to tell us something, or have told us something
we should not have missed, or are about to tell us something; that imminence of a
revelation that is not yet produced is, perhaps, the aesthetic reality.] (1964: 4)

5 Ever mercurial, Borges also recognized that ‘agnostic’ and ‘gnostic’ are vague and
mutable words. He humorously def lects the sombre tone of  Barnstone’s question:
‘“Returning to the question of a personal god, are you a gnostic?” “I am an agnostic.”
“No, a gnostic.” “Ah yes, I may be. Why not be Gnostics today and agnostics tomor-
row? It’s all the same thing”’ (Barnstone 1982: 103).
Introduction 13

Secondly, in countless interviews and essays Borges emphasized that this


state of agnosticism leads not to despair but to rapt wonder at the mys-
teries inherent in the universe; indeed there is scarcely an interview in
English in which Borges does not express his ‘amazement’, ‘baf f lement’,
‘wonder’ and ‘puzzlement’ confronted with these mysteries. He also
repeatedly locates the English word ‘maze’ within ‘amazement’, and con-
sequently perceives the motivation for his lifelong employment of  the
maze or labyrinth in his art. ‘Mazes are to be explained by the fact that
I live in a wonderful world. I mean, I am baf f led all the time by things.
I am astonished at things’ (Barnstone 1982: 36). These many citations of 
his late interviews do, of course, reveal a lessening of  the claustrophobic
nature of  the earlier labyrinthine tales, such as ‘La Biblioteca de Babel’
or ‘La muerte y la brújula’, and a greater sense of joy that the mysteries
will remain always mysteries:

I think of  them [mazes and labyrinths] as essential tokens, as essential symbols. I
have not chosen them. They were given me. I stick to them because I find that they
are the right symbols for my state of mind. I am always being baf f led, perplexed, so
a maze is the right symbol. They are not, at least to me, literary devices or tricks. I
don’t think of  them as tricks. They are part of my destiny, of my way of  feeling, of 
living. I haven’t chosen them. (Barnstone 1982: 37)

There is, consequently, a profound paradox expressed in the agnostic posi-


tion of  Borges. The philosophically-orientated mind seeks to understand
a mystery whilst knowing it to be essentially mysterious.

If  life’s meaning were explained to us, we probably wouldn’t understand it. To think
that a man can find it is absurd. We can live without understanding what the world
is or who we are. The important things are the ethical instinct and the intellectual
instinct, are they not? The intellectual instinct is the one that makes us search while
knowing that we are never going to find the answer. (Burgin 1998: 241)

This paradox may lead to a Sartrean despair at the absurdity of existence;


indeed, two oft-quoted lines from the period of  the great Ficciones may be
considered synoptic of  this worldview. The first, from the essay ‘El idioma
analítico de John Wilkens’ [‘The analytical language of  John Wilkens’]
summarizes the conjectural and wholly anti-Platonic nature of categorized
14 Introduction

systems of  thought: ‘notoriamente no hay clasificación del universo que


no sea arbitraria y conjetural. La razón es muy simple: no sabemos qué
cosa es el universo’ (1974: 708) [‘obviously there is no classification of  the
universe that is not arbitrary and conjectural. The reason is very simple:
we do not know what the universe is’] (2000: 231). The other is uttered
by the pedantic narrator of  ‘Pierre Menard’: ‘No hay ejercicio intelectual
que no sea finalmente inútil. Una doctrina es al principio una descripción
verosímil del universo; giran los años y es un mero capítulo – cuando no
un párrafo o un nombre – de la historia de la filosofía’ (1974: 449–50)
[‘There is no exercise of  the intellect which is not, in the final analysis,
useless. A philosophical doctrine begins as a plausible description of  the
universe; with the passage of  the years it becomes a mere chapter – if not
a paragraph or a name – in the history of philosophy’] (1976: 70). This
uselessness, however, need not be the cause of despair, but the perpetual
epistemological challenge that maintains our intellectual drive. Indeed, the
Borges narrator of  ‘John Wilkens’ qualifies his earlier assertion by stress-
ing the necessity of such provisory systems: ‘La imposibilidad de penetrar
el esquema divino del universo no puede, sin embargo, disuadirnos de
planear esquemas humanos, aunque nos conste que éstos son provisorios’
(1974: 708) [‘But the impossibility of penetrating the divine scheme of 
the universe cannot dissuade us from outlining human schemes, even
though we are aware that they are provisional’] (2000: 213). As such, the
deep exploration of philosophical systems inevitably creates a critical
distance that allows for conf licting or even contradictory systems not
to compete but to combine and enrich the tapestry of epistemologies.
In philosophical matters, this critical distance may be seen simply as not
advocating any one philosopher or school of  thought over another. In
religious and theological matters, this of course implies not placing faith
in a particular doctrine.
Introduction 15

‘Undr’ and ‘Utopía de un hombre que está cansado’:


the tension of wonder and despair

This critical distance can become a conundrum. Throughout his writing


career, Borges displayed a tension between a radical and deep-rooted
scepticism and a fascination with and deep respect for religious, spiritual
and mystical aspects of  human experience. This is present in his essays
from the 1920s, such as the 1926 ‘Historia de los ángeles’ [‘History of 
Angels’] (from El tamaño de mi esperanza), where his examination of angels
throughout history provides them with some undetermined ontological
status akin to the unconscious archetypes that Jung described, and the
1922 ‘La nadería de la personalidad’ [‘The Nothingness of  Personality’]
(from Inquisiciones), in which his deconstruction of  the self – rigorous,
rational and to an extent nihilist – has nevertheless been interpreted as a
germinating aspect of  his fascination with Buddhism (Barili 1998). The
tension is illustrated powerfully in El Libro de Arena, in which opposing
forces exert their exacting power over two tales: the devastation, empti-
ness, meaninglessness and utter bleakness of  ‘Utopía de un hombre que
está cansado’ [‘Utopia for a Tired Man’], and the rapt, ecstatic, mystical
‘wonder’ of  ‘Undr’.
Borges presented a Gnostic sensibility, akin to Jung’s narrative of 
Answer to Job, in which man is empowered by his understanding that he
is part of  the divine – that the divine needs man to be whole. He discussed
in many interviews his fondness for Shaw’s perspective that ‘God is in the
making’ (Burgin 1998: 209). In the dystopian landscape of  ‘Utopía de un
hombre que está cansado’ man has lost his sense of  the divinity, and has
consequently lost the sense of wonder at the mystery of  life. The old man
tells the narrator: ‘Hay quienes piensan que es un órgano de la divinidad
para tener conciencia del universo, pero nadie sabe con certidumbre si
hay tal divinidad’ (1989: 54) [‘Some people think man is an organ of  the
godhead for universal consciousness, but nobody knows for sure whether
such a godhead exists’] (1979: 68). Reason, intellect and cynicism have
trumped the passion for existence and sense of awe at the mysteries of
16 Introduction

nature. In this Gulliver-esque tale the future is full of old, tired, people,
free of earthly trappings but having found no illumination concerning the
riddle of existence. The Borges-like narrator and his Borges-like host have
abandoned themselves to despondent cynicism, dulled by governments and
politics, dulled by nations and peoples, dulled by language and history;
indeed the old man sees it as hubris to attempt to gather meaning from
existence. Once having lived out their allotted one hundred years, the old
folk end their days by voluntarily entering the gas chamber designed by
the ‘filántropo’ Hitler. Knowing Borges’ reaction to Hitler and the Third
Reich, the irony in this is severe. In the epilogue to the volume, Borges says
of  this tale: ‘[…] es, a mi juicio, la pieza más honesta y melancólica de la
serie’ (1989: 72) ‘[[it] is in my judgement the most honest and melancholy
piece in the collection’] (1979: 93).
The opposite polarity is presented in ‘Undr’, a tale brimming with
movement, energy and desire, with the narrator visiting strange lands with
strange kings and strange languages, searching throughout for the Word –
a single word that combines all the mystery of  the poetic craft and as such
all the wonder of existence. At end of  tale the narrator recounts his travels
to Thorkelsson, an old poet, who responds:

‘A mí también la vida me dio todo. A todos la vida les da todo, pero los más lo
ignoran. Mi voz está cansada y mis dedos débiles, pero escúchame.’ Dijo la palabra
Undr, que quiere decir maravilla. Me sentí arrebatado por el canto del hombre que
moría, pero en su canto y en su acorde vi mis; propios trabajos, la esclava que me dio
el primer amor, los hombres que maté, las albas de frío, la aurora sobre el agua, los
remos. Tomé el arpa y canté con una palabra distinta. ‘Está bien’, dijo el otro y tuve
que acercarme para oírlo. ‘Me has entendido.’ (1989: 51)

[‘Life gave me everything as well. Life gives everything to everyone, but most men
are unaware of it. My voice is tired and my fingers weak, but listen to me.’ He took
up his harp and uttered the word ‘undr’, which means ‘wonder’. The dying man’s song
held me rapt, but in it and in his chords I recognized my own verses, the slave woman
who gave me my first love, the men I had killed, the chill of dawn, daybreak over the
water, the oars. I took up the harp and sang to a dif ferent word. ‘All right,’ the other
man said, and I had to draw close to hear him. ‘You have understood.’] (1979: 63)
Introduction 17

Both tales construct their narrative upon a foundation of ignorance of  the
divine, yet they portray radically contrasting perspectives of  this agnostic
position. The narrator and the aged euthanist of  ‘Utopía …’ have followed
the trail that Borges beat in ‘La nadería de la personalidad’ of exposing the
substancelessness of  the fabric of reality. Politics, nations, language and even
the human race have been hollowed out and jettisoned as mere ephemera
of endless and useless cycles and repetitions; and suicide is the inevitable
cessation of  this meaningless existence. The narrator of ‘Undr’, on the other
hand, has no firmer teleological understanding, but is empowered to kiss
the joy as it f lies and sing to this glorious meaninglessness. In scrutinising
the many interviews that Borges performed throughout the 1960s, 1970s
and early 1980s, it is strikingly clear how both visions are present in his
philosophical outlook: his exclamations of delighted baf f lement and rapt
wonder come in equal measure to his anticipation of  ‘being blotted out,
[of  being] sick and tired of myself, [and] greedy for death’ (Barnstone
1982: 17). Whilst on the one hand this is a polarity of despair and joy, it is
a dialectic that can be perceived at many further levels: reason and intui-
tion, intellect and emotion, empiricism and esotericism, the revealed and
the occult, fact and fiction, reality and fantasy.
These are dif ficult polarities to reconcile. Borges, for example, main-
tained the same degree of critical distance vis-à-vis mysticism as he main-
tained with philosophy: ‘Many people have thought of me as a thinker, as
a philosopher, or even as a mystic. […] People think that I’ve committed
myself  to idealism, to solipsism, or to doctrines of  the cabala, because I’ve
used them in my tales. But really I was only trying to see what could be
done with them’ (Burgin 1998: 79). Whilst we should be cautious of  leap-
ing to call Borges a mystic, for the reasons that are explored in Chapter
Two, nevertheless we need to appraise the deeper ramifications of  this
insistence that his interests in all systems of  thought were purely aesthetic.
My reading of  Borges over the last five years has accompanied a close read-
ing with weekly group discussions of  the works of  Jung. It has become an
increasingly motivating enterprise to perceive the close af finities between
Jung and Borges, not at the level of personal connections (although Borges
did read Jung and commented on his works, and there are intermediary
contacts between them, such as Victoria Ocampo and Gershom Scholem),
18 Introduction

but at the level of  their shared interests.6 Of most concern for us here is the
tension of opposites that is central to both their works.

The case of  Jung

Jung underwent a period of psychic crisis in his thirties, yet kept secret the
harrowing accounts of  his experience with the unconscious entities and the
discarnate dead, documenting them in great majesty in the Liber Novus
which he never published (it was published in 2009 as The Red Book). He
was aware that his experiences constituted a radical discord with the onto-
logical certainties held by himself and the wider public, and he was fully
cognizant of  the ridicule that he would face amongst friends and peers if he
claimed that he conversed with Old Testament prophets and the dead. Even
as late as 1958, his essay on UFOs concentrates almost entirely in evaluating
the ‘psychic cause’ and ‘psychic ef fect’ of  the phenomenon, and not the
phenomenon itself. Jung was emphatic in the critical distance maintained

6 There is much to link Borges and Jung at three levels: firstly, as I discuss in Chapter
Five, Borges’ engagement with Jung’s psychological works. Secondly, Jung’s and
Borges’ debt to William James; their reading of mystics, especially Swedenborg,
Dante, Jakob Böhme, Angelus Silesius, Meister Eckhardt, Blake; their admiration
of  Schopenhauer and Kant; their reading of  Gnosticism, hermeticism and alchemy,
especially Paracelsus; their interpretation of  the Book of  Job; their critical reading of 
Joyce; their critique through a mythological prism of  the Third Reich; their inter-
est in the epistemological value of  fantasy, imagination, myth, symbols and dreams.
Thirdly, biographical parallels: their association with Gershom Scholem; their con-
nection with Victoria Ocampo (she met Jung and sponsored Ramón Gómez de la
Serna to translate Psychological Types [Tipos psicológicos: Buenos Aires 1945], the first
Spanish translation). One might object to a comparative appraisal of  Borges and Jung
based on the idea that Jung was a psychologist and Borges an artist. I would argue,
however, that Jung was manifestly an artist (viz The Red Book) and that Borges was
fascinated by the complexities of  the psyche. In this and other respects their projects
have far more in common than has hitherto been acknowledged.
Introduction 19

through scientific objectivity, which permitted him, like Borges, to explore


with great enthusiasm all manner of alchemical, gnostic, mystical, hermetic
and occult texts without abandoning robust ‘empiricism’. Whilst Borges
may have stressed that his interest lay in ‘the merely aesthetic’, Jung would
argue that his interest was in the psychological aspect of  these systems of 
thought. Yet it becomes apparent through a scrutiny of  Jung’s work that
he felt torn between his desire to be a scientist and his inclination towards
philosophy, theology and metaphysics as maps not only of  the human
psyche, but of reality itself. That is to say that his concerns were not merely
epistemological but ontological also. This is evident in his strident riposte
as footnote in his work on UFOs: ‘It is a common and totally unjustified
misunderstanding on the part of scientifically trained people to say that
I regard the psychic background as something “metaphysical,” while on
the other hand the theologians accuse me of  “psychologizing” metaphys-
ics. Both are wide of  the mark: I am an empiricist, who keeps within the
boundaries set for him by the theory of  knowledge’ (1958: 328).7 There is
so much to be elucidated from this, especially given the arbitrary nature of 
the terms employed, such as ‘empiricist’ and ‘theory of  knowledge’. Jung
was obviously pulled between intuition and education, and even when he
did consider the ontological possibility of  the UFO (in the final chapter

7 A number of commentators, not least Jung himself, have observed his vociferous
appeal to the reader not to consider him anything other than a rational scientific
empiricist. Note a later footnote to the text on UFOs: ‘Here I must beg the reader
to eschew the popular misconception that this background is “metaphysical”. This
view is a piece of gross carelessness of which even professional people are guilty. It is
far more of a question of instincts which inf luence not only our outward behaviour
but also the psychic structure. The psyche is not an arbitrary fantasy; it is a biological
fact subject to the laws of  life’ (1958: 346). It is important to note that this footnote
pertains to a paragraph in which he declares: ‘Since the discovery of  the empirical
unconscious the psyche and what goes on in it have become a natural fact and are
no longer an arbitrary opinion’ (346). Some may suggest that in equating the uncon-
scious to a natural law of physics, he is demonstrating a level of dogmatic faith in
his discovery such as he observed in Freud’s defence of  ‘pleasure and its frustration’
(348) being the sole roots of psychic illness.
20 Introduction

of  his investigation) he concentrated not on the phenomenon itself, but


on the psychic response to it, the projection of psychic energy upon it.
In a similar fashion, Borges would argue that his interests lay in their
aesthetic value, as if  that negates any speculation about the actual questions
raised in metaphysics, psychology (and parapsychology) and religious and
mystical texts. Yet both Borges and Jung were clearly deeply drawn to such
liminal, mysterious, levels of  human experience, and their safety lines in
these dark caves were literature and psychology respectively. The publica-
tion of  The Red Book has inspired a fresh approach to Jung, an approach
hinted at since early publications of  Von Franz, Jaf fé, Hannah, Jacobi and
others, but rarely stated outright: that Jung did consider such matters at
their ontological level. Of f-beat scholars and certain leftfield practitioners
have been calling Jung a mystic and a shaman for decades (at least since
1962 when Memories Dreams Ref lections was published in English). Aniela
Jaf fé’s essay ‘Was C.G. Jung a mystic?’ (1989) focuses from the opening
page on the tension between Jung’s mystic sensibilities and his insistence
on principles of empiricism, observing that Jung reacted strongly against
any claims that he was anything other than a scientific observer. Gary
Lachman’s recent Jung the mystic (2010), as the title suggests, testifies to
the mystical nature of  Jung, and he appraises with sensitivity the double
nature present in Jung: ‘Jung seemed to have two minds about the super-
natural: a public one that wanted to understand it “scientifically,” and a
private one that acknowledged ghosts, visions, and premonitions as part of 
the essential mystery of  life’ (4). Lachman also cites Anthony Storr, who
writes in his book Feet of  Clay: A Study of  Gurus that ‘Jung was a guru’ (in
Lachman 2010: 6). Jungian analyst Roger Woolger, in his review of  Jung’s
Red Book (Woolger’s final publication prior to his death in 2011), declared
outright that Jung displayed all the characteristics commonly associated
with shamans, calling Jung ‘the Hidden Shaman’:

Now that we have the record of  Jung’s struggles to integrate the polarities of scientist-
philosopher versus mystic within his soul we can also see how they urged upon him
another mantle that he was very reluctant to wear – because so many have been
ridiculed and persecuted for wearing it – that of shaman-prophet. […] The evidence
of  the Red Book and of  those who knew him intimately us that Jung was very much
Introduction 21

a shaman. […] Perhaps Shamdasani shies away from calling Jung a ‘shaman’ because
‘shamanism’ is not politically correct in academic or conservative professional circles
in Britain. (2011: 4–5).

I have no intention of suggesting that Borges was a shaman or guru, terms


which have a stricter definition than mystic, though equally problematic.
However, the parallel drawn with Jung here is helpful in illustrating a
perplexing dialogue between polarities present in Borges. Neither am I
assuming that an equivalent Red Book – a secret illuminated manuscript
of  Borges’ encounters with the dead – will be unearthed and published
to corroborate such a position. I would argue that such a discovery is not
necessary; the published work of  Borges – poems, tales, essay, reviews and
interviews – is replete with subtle indications that Borges, like Jung, was
fascinated with the more anomalous aspects of  human experience at a level
beyond the ‘mere aesthetic’.
In an appraisal of  his many writings, it becomes evident that he read
extensively and sympathetically in the traditions of mystical, spiritual and
esoteric texts. My argument is that there is a limit to the capacity of a
reader to explore such texts to the extent that Borges did if, ultimately,
one is not predisposed towards them. Borges, like Jung, was a reader of
alchemical texts, dramatizing, for example, the aged figure of  Paracelsus
in one of  his final tales ‘La Rosa de Paracelsus’. One can also identify
his inveterate interest in hermetic philosophy (he discusses Ficino and
Giordano Bruno in Libro de los seres imaginarios [Book of  Imaginary Beings]
with Margarita Guerrero), Neoplatonism (‘Historia de la eternidad’ [‘A
History of  Eternity’]), daimonic beings (Libro de seres imaginarios [Book
of  Imaginary Beings], ‘Las Ruinas circulares’ [‘The Circular Ruins’]), eso-
teric societies (‘Tlön’, ‘Los Conjurados’, ‘El Congreso’), Gnosticism (‘Una
vindicación del falso Basílides’ [‘A Vindication of  the False Basilides’],8

8 ‘That Borges’ work demonstrates certain Gnostic leanings and concepts is well-
documented, but it is generally ignored in deconstructive criticism’s haste to erase
the logos in the name of its own brand of indeterminacy and deferral. It is much fairer
to view Borges’ Gnosticism, particularly his af finity for the “malevolent demiurge”
who creates an imperfect universe, as his own attempt to work through the concerns
22 Introduction

‘Tres versiones de Judas’ [‘Three Versions of  Judas]), anomalies in time


(‘J. W. Dunne’, ‘El milagro secreto’ [‘The Secret Miracle’]), persistence of 
the soul after death (‘Diálogo de muertos’ [‘Dead men’s dialogue’]), the
many discussions of  transmigration of  the soul, depth psychology (his
many citations of  Jung), eschatology (poem ‘Doomsday’), and so on. He
was likewise a devoted reader of  Angelus Silesius, and translated Silesius’
challenging Cherubinischer Wandersmann with María Kodama.9 He was
a dedicated reader of  Dante, of  William Blake and Sufi poets. He was also
a reader of  Theosophy, describing his surprise at being unable to find the
works of Swedenborg in Theosophical bookshops, a statement which would
imply that he frequented them.10 He made many references to William
James, Jung, Rudolf Steiner and the later works of  Aldous Huxley. I would
argue that it is dif ficult to make meaningful statements about James, Jung,
Steiner, or Huxley without entering their challenging works with energy
and sympathy. He cites Ouspensky (‘Historia de la eternidad’, ‘Los con-
jurados’), a perplexing writer whose works are dif ficult to summarize based
on only a rudimentary reading.11 Likewise, as I explore in Chapter One,

of  theodicy, and his sense of  the inadequacy of orthodox religions’ ef forts to do so’
(Soud 1995: 748).
9 ‘I was translating, with María Kodama, Angelus Silesius’ Cherubinischer Wandersmann
and we came to the same statement that if a soul is damned it is forever in hell’
(Barnstone 1982: 8).
10 ‘Yo sé que en la Biblioteca Nacional hay un ejemplar de Del cielo, del infierno y sus
maravillas. Pero en algunas librerías teosóficas no se encuentran obras de Swedenborg’
(2005: 202) [‘I know that in the National Library there is an edition of  Heaven and
Hell. But you will not find Swedenborg’s works in Theosophical bookshops’] (my
translation).
11 Ouspensky is a name generally associated with Gurdjief f, a particularly curious guru
figure of  the early twentieth century whose inf luence was felt upon writers, painters,
film directors, philosophers and even politicians on both sides of  the Atlantic. The
Borges-Gurdjief f-Ouspensky connection is obscure, and whilst I can find no refer-
ence to Gurdjief f in Borges’ writing, it would seem likely that Borges’ knowledge of 
Ouspensky’s works would guarantee him at least a passing knowledge of  Gurdjief f.
James Webb (1987: 492) writes that Borges attended a Gurdjief f group in Argentina
though provides no evidence. Likewise Gurdjief f scholar Sophia Wellbeloved (2003:
xxvii) attests that Borges attended meetings on Gurdjief f ’s Work in Buenos Aires,
Introduction 23

Borges read Swedenborg with great devotion, and died with the project
still unrealized of writing an entire book on Swedenborg’s voyages to the
heavens and hells. He paid close attention to Swedenborg’s otherworld
journeys, the angelic and demonic beings Swedenborg encountered there,
his communication with the discarnate dead, and his description of  the
process of death, all the while adamant that Swedenborg was not a madman.
In defending Swedenborg against charges of insanity, therefore, Borges
would appear to defend the possibility that Swedenborg’s adventures were
neither fantasy, fiction nor hallucination. This splendidly tolerant attitude,
which Borges would correlate with the tolerance inherent in agnosticism,
needs to be assessed in light of  Borges’ scepticism – even cynicism – regard-
ing faith. There is a sensitivity and sensibility to such matters visible in
Borges’ work that demonstrate something more than mere material for
story-telling. Borges, as I explore in this book, investigated mysticism in
particular with a series of questions and arguments that reveals a level of
deep personal investment.
This tension of polarities is likewise visible in the Libro del cielo y del
infierno, which Borges edited with Bioy Casares, which contains passages

but provides no evidence that Borges even read Gurdjief f : ‘Jorge Luis Borges is said
to have attended meetings in Argentina in the 1950s. By then Gurdjief f ’s inf luence
was widespread in South America.’ In email communication with Wellbeloved, she
explained to me that this notion derived not from Webb, but from her communica-
tion with Gurdjief f scholar Martin Wallace who had, she wrote, met Borges and had
asked him whether he knew Ouspensky’s – and by extension Gurdjief f ’s – works.
Wellbeloved explained to me: ‘Martin Wallace wrote the introduction to the second
edition of my Gurdjief f, Astrology and Beelzeub’s Tales. I asked him by email if  he
thought that Borges had been inf luenced by Ouspensky, and he sent me an email
recounting meeting Borges and asking him the same question, Borges replied by
immediately reciting the entire list of cosmoses from memory, an achievement as
you can see, you can find them in In Search of  the Miraculous (1949), which gives
and account of  Gurdjief f ’s teaching in Russia before the revolution. Ouspensky was
obsessed with theories of  time and also recurrence, this was an aspect of what he
taught that was in addition to Gurdjief f ’s teaching’ (private email correspondence).
The true extent of  the inf luence or co-interests of  Borges, Gurdjief f and Ouspensky
remains to be fully explored.
24 Introduction

from Swedenborg alongside an extract from Bertrand Russell’s An Outline


of  Intellectual Rubbish. The brief passage from Russell that Borges and Bioy
included comes from an essay in which Russell systematically lambasts all
manner of woolly-brained thinking that he detected in religious, spiritual
and superstitious texts and practices throughout the ages and across the
cultures. It was published in 1943 and much of  Russell’s venom is directed
against the Nazis and their political mythologies. It is noteworthy, there-
fore, that Borges and Bioy chose to include an extract from this essay, as
the essence of  the essay would clearly dismiss any notion of  heavens, hells
or the afterlife as nonsense; indeed the brief extract concerns Russell’s snide
dismissal of  F. W. H. Myers’ claims to have been able to communicate with
the dead.12 There is much of  Russell in Borges: the disdain for the dogma
of  faith, the baf f lement at the readiness of  the faithful to abandon not
only reason but also the authority of experience, the prodigious memory,
cruel wit and sharp intellect. Their comments on the Nazis and the Third
Reich are equally scornful. However, Russell was keen to dismiss matters
of  theology, esotericism, spiritualism, religion, as ‘nonsense’, ‘absurdity’,
and ‘rubbish’. Despite their intellectual kinship, the same cannot be said
for Borges, whose tolerance would permit him greater warmth to such mat-
ters. The appearance of  Russell, therefore, in a book by Borges which claims
in its prologue to seek ‘lo esencial, sin descuidar lo vivido, lo onírico y lo
paradójico’ (1983: 7) [‘the essential, without overlooking the experiential,
the oneiric and the paradoxical’] (my translation) of matters of  the afterlife
is therefore particularly arresting, as it demonstrates the presence of radi-
cal scepticism and philosophical scrutiny alongside intellectual curiosity,
aesthetic appreciation, and metaphysical wonder.

12 It would be fascinating to find further references to Myers in Borges’ work, as Myers


– a close friend of  William James – maintained a strongly scientific methodology,
married to a healthy scepticism, in his exploration of  the survival of  the soul after
death.
Introduction 25

‘Defiéndeme Dios de mi’

Borges writes in ‘Avatares de la Tortuga’ [‘Avatars of  the Tortoise’] of  the
dream-like nature of reality, and postulates that the anomalies and vagu-
eries that are encountered might suggest our own participation in the
construction of reality:

‘El mayor hechicero (escribe memorablemente Novalis) sería el que se hechizara hasta
el punto de tomar sus propias fantasmagorías por apariciones autónomas. ¿No sería
ése nuestro caso?’ Yo conjeturo que así es. Nosotros (la indivisa divinidad que opera
en nosotros) hemos soñado el mundo. Lo hemos soñado resistente, misterioso, visible,
ubicuo en el espacio y firme en el tiempo; pero hemos consentido en su arquitectura
tenues y eternos intersticios de sinrazón para saber que es falso. (1974: 258)

[‘The greatest sorcerer (writes Novalis memorably) would be the one who bewitched
himself  to the point of  taking his own phantasmagorias for autonomous apparitions.
Would not this be true of us?’ I believe that it is. We (the undivided divinity that
operates within us) have dreamed the world. We have dreamed it strong, mysterious,
visible, ubiquitous in space and secure in time, but we have allowed tenuous, eternal
interstices of injustice in its structure so we may know that it is false.] (1964: 120)

This is a powerful statement, and deserves to be appraised as more than


a mere philosophical reference to Novalis; indeed the fictional nature
of reality forms a deep hermeneutic current throughout Borges’ work.
Importantly, Borges identifies here the ‘intersticios de sinrazón’ that sug-
gest that not all aspects of reality conform to patterns identifiable with
the epistemological tool of reason. Some matters, as Jung argued with
regard anomalies of reality, operated acausally. One such anomaly that
was of such interest to Jung was the contested phenomenon of  ‘meaning-
ful coincidence’, which he dubbed ‘synchronicity’. It is important to stress
that the impact of  Jung’s theory lies not with the idea that a subject can
attribute meaning to a series of random coincidences – an idea that bears
no ontological inference – but that the psyche of  the individual and the
external events are in some undetermined mutual exchange (Main 2004).
This, as a scientific rather than a religious theory, is still notably challenging,
as it presupposes a conscious dimension to reality. Borges took this matter
26 Introduction

seriously whilst never abandoning his sceptical scrutiny. In an interview


with Burgin he described a possible synchronistic event and suggested an
explanatory conclusion that displays sympathy with the deeper ontologi-
cal implications of  Jung’s theory, whilst maintaining a sceptical, almost
cynical, standpoint. So illustrative is the episode of  the curious tension in
Borges between scepticism and a predisposition to religious experience
that it deserves citation in full:

Borges: […] I’m on the lookout for symmetries.


Burgin: You’ve criticized yourself  before for always looking for the symmetries,
the mirrors, the labyrinths in life. Do you really feel that way or …
Borges: No, no, I feel that way. But perhaps coincidences are given to us that
would involve the idea of a secret plan, no? Coincidences are given to us
so that we may feel there is a pattern – that there is a pattern in life, that
things mean something. Of course, there is a pattern in the sense that we
have night and day, the four seasons, being born, living and dying, the
stars and so on, but there may be a more subtle kind of pattern, no?
Burgin: Within each individual’s life.
Borges: Yes, within each individual’s life, because I find so many coincidences. Of
course, as many things happen, coincidences are bound to happen also,
but I find very strange coincidences and they are of no use whatever to
me except for the fact that they leave a pattern. For example, Bioy Casares
and I were working on a translation of  Sir Thomas Browne. That transla-
tion never found its way into print, because the editors said there was no
interest in that and forgot all about it. Now we found a sentence in Sir
Thomas Browne in Spanish, ‘defiéndeme Dios de mí.’ Only he made a
mistake and he wrote ‘defiéndeme Dios de me.’ Now where else could he
have got that from? Well, of course, we corrected the mistake and wrote
‘defiéndeme Dios de mí.’
A day or so later, I went to Mitchell’s Book Store in Buenos Aires […] and
in the basement I found a new translation of  Montaigne into English.
I opened one of  the volumes at random and there I found ‘defiéndeme
Dios de mí,’ and with the same misprint, ‘de me.’ The editor, of course he
had no Spanish, he thought that Montaigne knew all about it. And then,
as I knew that Sir Thomas Browne had been a close reader of  Montaigne,
there was the clue I had been looking for. He had found that quotation
in Montaigne, and the proof  lay in the misprint, no?
Well, I felt greatly elated at the discovery and I went that night to see Bioy
Casares and I had jotted down where the edition of  Montaigne might be
Introduction 27

found. And we were working over an anthology of  Spanish verse. He had
those books of  Rivadeneyra in a collection, he had a pile of  them on the
table. While I was talking to him, he opened one of  the books, and there
he found a poem of  Cristóbal de Castillejo, Garcilaso’s enemy, glossing the
line ‘defiéndeme Dios de mí.’ I said, ‘Look here, I found it in Montaigne
this morning.’ We would have had to have examined thousands of vol-
umes in thousands of years and perhaps never found out these things.
And then we felt very proud. Of course, we wrote a short note (in the
translation), saying Sir Thomas Browne took this quotation from essay
number so and so of  Montaigne where the same misprint is found and
so on. […] You see, there you had a coincidence, and the coincidence was
of no use whatever. (Burgin 1969: 110–12)13

There is much to glean from this quite remarkable episode. Firstly, and
significantly, Burgin does not respond to Borges’ lengthy account, but
changes the subject. This demonstrates the unease that such a radical posi-
tion presented by Borges can occasion in his readers and listeners. Secondly,
it is striking how like a ficción this episode is, most of all the parallels with
‘Tlön’: a furtive citation discovered by Borges and Bioy; further discover-
ies of  the citation in arcane volumes; links through literary-philosophical
authors: Castillejo, Garcilaso, Montaigne; and the shadowy presence of  Sir
Thomas Brown. Borges’ language is also revealing. He suggests, for exam-
ple, that ‘coincidences are given to us’, and that ‘there may be a more subtle
kind of pattern’. Such statements, whimsical as they may be, nevertheless
imply some manner of extrinsic guiding principle upon life – an external
authorship – a divine force. Again, I am not seeking the deist in Borges, but
I am revealing the Jungian perspective present in Borges of perceiving an
interrelationship between psyche and matter. He also twice mentions the
uselessness of  the coincidence, emphasizing that the only use was ‘the fact
that they leave a pattern’. This, conversely, is a most valuable use as it serves

13 Importantly, Bioy Casares writes of  this episode, presenting it with exactly the same
detail as Borges. He titles it ‘un recuerdo’ (2006: 1540). So close is Bioy’s rendition
of  the episode to Borges’ that one wonders whether he was using Borges’ interview
extract as his basis. Bioy obviously felt the episode to be intriguing enough to war-
rant its own inclusion in his memoirs, yet he of fers no assessment of  the nature of 
the coincidence, nor any examination of  the phrase itself.
28 Introduction

to demonstrate this challenging assumption that there may be a conscious


dimension to what is otherwise considered mere non-conscious matter.
Furthermore, as any Jungian analyst would immediately do, one must
consider the nature of  the mysterious phrase itself, ‘defiéndeme Dios de me/
mí.’ The issue of misspelling is important, as curiously both Montaigne and
then Brown write: Defenda me Dios de me. Montaigne includes it whilst
discussing the pain to the soul of physical illness,14 Browne, whilst inveigh-
ing against the split between spiritual righteousness and bodily desire.15 The
phrase itself, as Bioy suggested, originated from St Augustine’s City of  God,
in which Augustine pertinently confronts the tension between righteous-
ness and the desire for sin, though why Montaigne selected the Spanish
version is unclear. Montaigne, Browne and, by extension, Augustine, are
consequently concerned with the tension of opposites, and they summon
God to help reconcile these opposites. Yet Montaigne and Brown resort to a
misspelt expression in Spanish in order to summon that help, thereby unwit-
tingly entangling themselves in the very human limitations of  language.
Borges, in highlighting this episode, appears fully cognizant of its curious
nature, yet he appears not to dwell on the phrase itself. Why the curious
plea to the divine? Why should Borges call on God to save himself  from
himself ? One might argue that the phrase embodies the friction generated
between rational, sceptical enquiry and an intuition of  the non-rational.
There is far more to be elucidated from this, not least an exploration of 
Castillejo. However, this wholly overlooked episode, ignored even by the
interviewer, is charged with meaningful relationship with the very tension
that I have highlighted in Borges.

14 ‘“Defenda me Dios de me.” I am sorry when I am sick, that I have not some longing
that might give me the pleasure of satisfying it; all the rules of physic would hardly
be able to divert me from it. I do the same when I am well; I can see very little more
to be hoped or wished for. ’Twere pity a man should be so weak and languishing, as
not to have even wishing left to him’ (Montaigne 1910: 613).
15 ‘I feel that original canker corrode and devour me; and therefore Defenda me DIOS
de me, “LORD deliver me from my self,” is a part of my Letany, and the first voice of
my retired imaginations. There is no man alone, because every man is a Microcosm,
and carries the whole World about him’ (Browne 2003: 114).
Introduction 29

Like Jung, Borges achieved fame and success in his life, travelled widely
and met with many well-known figures. Jung describes at the beginning of 
Memories, Dreams, Ref lections that none of  these experiences was of  last-
ing importance in his later reminiscences; instead it was the experience
of  the unconscious – of  the numinous – that characterized his life’s work.

In the end the only events in my life worth telling are those when the imperishable
world irrupted into this transitory one. That is why I speak chief ly of inner experi-
ences, amongst which I include my dreams and visions. These form the prima materia
of my scientific work. They were the fiery magma out of which the stone that had to
be worked was crystallized. All other memories of  travels, people and my surround-
ings have paled beside these interior happenings. ( Jung 1989: 4–5)

Were Borges to have produced the equivalent of  Jung’s memoirs (beyond
the ‘Autobiographical essay’) it is highly likely that his recollections would
likewise have concentrated on the more ‘timeless’ aspects of  his life experi-
ences, and not on the more mundane. I would argue, indeed, that the many
interviews of  the 1970s and 1980s themselves constitute his oral autobi-
ography, and that his dialogues with Burgin, Barnstone, Enguídanos, di
Giovanni, Barili and others inevitably encircle the deep wells of  timeless
moments – poetry, dreams, literature, symbols – rather than his encounters
with political and cultural figures. Mystical experience, as we will inves-
tigate in Chapters Two and Three, was for Borges a sensation of moving
beyond the mundane passage of  time into a of state of  timelessness. It is at
this level, as Jung also acknowledged, that the ‘intersticios de sinrazón’ are
most prone to occur: a conversation with a dead friend, a glimpse of  the
future or a moment of deep inspiration.16 Borges paid particular attention
to this deeper area of consciousness, suggesting in two particular texts that

16 ‘[Y]ou know there are these peculiar faculties of  the psyche, that it isn’t entirely
confined to space and time. You can have dreams or visions of  the future, you can
see around corners, and such things. Only ignorance denies these facts, you know;
it’s quite evident that they do exist, and have existed always. Now these facts show
that the psyche, in part at least, is not dependent upon these confinements. And then
what? When the psyche is not under that obligation to live in time and space alone,
and obviously it doesn’t, then to that extent the psyche is not subjected to those
30 Introduction

his truest sense of self was that area of  the psyche ‘untouched by time’. He
dedicated Historia universal de la infamia to S. D., of fering her [in English]
‘that kernel of myself  that I have saved, somehow – the central heart that
deals not in words, traf fics not with dreams, and is untouched by time,
by joy, by adversities’ (1974: 293). He dedicated the ‘Two English Poems’
(1934) to Beatriz Bibiloni Webster de Bullrich of fering her also ‘that kernel
of myself  that I have saved, / somehow – the central heart that deals not /
in words, traf fics not with dreams, and is / untouched by time, by joy, by
adversities’ (1993: 179). This is the visionary element, the deeper, transper-
sonal part of  his being, the dark layers of unconscious described by Jung.
These are the depths that I seek to explore in this book.

‘Hypotheses that transcend reason are more appealing’

But wait! The reader may cry, the fact that Borges wrote fictions in which
anomalous episodes emerge does not mean either that he experienced such
matters nor that he gave them any credence. This is a valid point, and indeed
we should never forget that Borges was an artist, and therefore a merchant
of artifice. The writer of a ghost story need not believe in ghosts; a scholar
of religion need not be religious. For example, when Borges writes in Atlas
(1985): ‘veo en los sueños o converso con muertos, sin que ninguna de esas
dos cosas me asombre’ (1989: 430) [‘Asleep, in my dreams, I see or converse
with the dead. None of  these things surprises me in the least’] (1985: 54);
or when he writes of a dream, also in Atlas: ‘En un restaurante del centro,
Haydée Lange y yo conversábamos. […] De pronto recordé que Haydée
Lange había muerto hace mucho tiempo. Era un fantasma y no lo sabía.
No sentí miedo; sentí que era imposible y quizá descortés revelarle que
era un fantasma, un hermoso fantasma’ (1989: 438) [‘Haydée Lange and I

laws, and that means a practical continuation of  life, of a sort of psychical existence
beyond time and space’ ( Jung 1993: 437).
Introduction 31

were conversing in a restaurant in the center of  town. […] All of a sudden,
I remembered that Haydée Lange had died a long time ago. She was a
ghost and didn’t know it. I felt no fear, but felt it would not be right, and
perhaps rude, to reveal to her that she was a ghost, a lovely ghost’] (1985:
67), one can only conjecture what level of personal experience provided
the background for such textual creations. We know, for example, that
Borges placed great noetic value on dreams and nightmares. What level
of communication, consequently, occurred between Borges and the dead
Haydée Lange? I argue in Chapter Two, with reference to Jef frey Kripal’s
(2001) evaluation of  the key scholars of mysticism, that a level is clearly
reached at which thorough exploration of a phenomenon like mysticism
cannot be sustained by sceptical, objective, impartiality if it is to succeed
with any integrity. A threshold of scepticism is always crossed if  the scholar
of mysticism is able to contribute anything of any value to the scholarship.
This, I argue, is the case with Borges.
And yet, in true mercurial fashion, Borges danced back and forth across
this threshold; in his earlier writings demonstrating a more rigorous, intel-
lectual scepticism, in his later works displaying a more world-weary, whim-
sical acquiescence to the persistence of mystery. Nevertheless, like Jung, he
brandished his keen intellect and encyclopaedic knowledge of  texts as the
means of preventing credulity or adherence to doctrine. There is not the
sense, such as Lachman identifies in Jung, that Borges was determined not
to be ‘draped in the unwanted robes of mysticism’ (2010: 4); rather I would
argue that his inveterate iconoclasm, mistrust of doctrine, and admiration
of  heresy made him defensive of  being taken for credulous. Note that in
the essay on nightmares in Siete Noches, Borges criticizes British anthro-
pologist, folklorist, and classical scholar, Sir James Frazer for being ‘muy
crédulo, ya que parece aceptar todo cuanto le cuentan los viajeros’ (1989:
222) [‘extremely credulous, as it seems he believed everything reported by
the various travellers’] (1984: 28). Borges, it would appear, would be more
wary of  being labelled credulous than a mystic. As his numerous interviews
and essays testify, Borges appeared to equate belief – whether religious,
philosophical or even political – with a surrender of one’s intellect and
faculty of critical enquiry. One senses in Borges that believers are some-
how gullible. When evaluating a peculiar coincidence of dreams associated
32 Introduction

with Coleridge’s poem Kubla Khan, for example, Borges displays a similar
defensive position observable in Jung: ‘Quienes de antemano rechazan lo
sobrenatural (yo trato, siempre, de pertenecer, a ese gremio) juzgarán que la
historia de los dos sueños es una coincidencia, un dibujo trazado por el azar,
como las formas de leones o de caballos que a veces configuran las nubes’
(1974: 644) [‘Those who automatically reject the supernatural (I try, always,
to belong to this group) will claim that the story of the two dreams is merely
a coincidence, a chance delineation, like the outlines of  lions or horses we
sometimes see in the clouds’] (1964: 16). This may sound a straightforward
comment, in which Borges maintains that the narrative similarities across
time are merely coincidental and inconsequential. Yet like Lönnrot rejecting
Treviranus’s suggestion that the murder of  Yarmolinsky was a blunder, and
choosing instead to seek the symbolic, Borges rejects his declared position
to explore the more poetic, mysterious dimension of  this parallel.

Otros argüirán que el poeta supo de algún modo que el emperador había soñado el
palacio y dijo haber soñado el poema para crear una espléndida ficción que asimismo
paliara o justificara lo truncado y rapsódico de los versos. Esta conjetura es verosímil,
pero nos obliga a postular, arbitrariamente, un texto no identificado por los sinólogos
en el que Coleridge pudo leer, antes de 1816, el sueño de Kubla. Más encantadoras
son las hipótesis que transcienden lo racional. Por ejemplo, cabe suponer que el alma
del emperador, destruido el palacio, penetró en el alma de Coleridge, para que éste lo
reconstruyera en palabras, más duraderas que los mármoles y los metales. (1974: 644)

[Others will argue that the poet somehow found out that the Emperor had dreamed
the palace, and then said he had dreamed the poem in order to create a splendid fic-
tion that would also palliate or justify the truncated and rhapsodic quality of  the
verses. That conjecture seems reasonable, but it obliges us to postulate, arbitrarily, a
text not identified by Sinologists in which Coleridge was able to read, before 1816,
and about Kubla’s dream. Hypotheses that transcend reason are more appealing. One
such theory is that the Emperor’s soul penetrated Coleridge’s, enabling Coleridge to
rebuild the destroyed palace in words that would be more lasting than marble and
metal.] (1964: 16, emphasis mine)

The implications of  Borges’ comments are striking. He would reject a priori
the supernatural, and yet the explanation of  the repeated vision of  Kubla
Khan he most favours is one of  the transmigration of souls. This appears
contradictory, not least when we correlate this assertion with Borges’ other
Introduction 33

speculation on transmigration. Reason cannot accommodate the possibil-


ity of  transmigration of  the soul, he suggests in the lecture ‘Inmortalidad’
(2005: 185–94), as it is inherently unreasonable for the soul to remember
who it has been in previous incarnations. It would require a passage back
to the source as each life recalls the previous; and a passage forward to
the eschaton, as each life resounds in the next. Furthermore, he argues in
the lecture ‘El Tiempo’ [‘Time’], an awareness of such plenitude would
overwhelm and annihilate us, and hence whether there is or not transmi-
gration of  the soul, we cannot be aware of it: ‘felizmente no lo sabemos.
Felizmente, creemos en individuos. Porque si no estaríamos abrumados,
estaríamos aniquilados por esa plenitud’ (2005: 217) [‘happily we do not
know it. Happily, we believe in individuals. Because if not we would be
overwhelmed, annihilated by this plenitude’] (my translation).17 It is, how-
ever, a great theme of  literature and the imagination that persists across the
centuries. ‘La transmigración’ he writes in the lecture ‘Budismo’ of  Siete
Noches, ‘ha sido un gran tema de la literatura. La encontramos, también
entre los místicos. Plotino dice que pasar de una vida a otra es como dormir
en distintos lechos y en distintas habitaciones. Creo que todos hemos
tenido alguna vez la sensación de haber vivido un momento parecido en
vidas anteriores’ (1989: 248–9) [‘Transmigration has been a great theme
of  literature. We also encounter it among the mystics. Plotinus says that to
pass from one life to another is like sleeping in dif ferent beds in dif ferent
rooms. I imagine all of us have had the sensation of  having lived previous

17 Borges returns to this theme in a later interview: ‘William Blake says: “Time is the gift
of eternity.” Let’s try to expand on those truly wise words: if all Being were revealed
to us – the Being rather than the world – at a single instant, undoubtedly we would
be annihilated, killed. Thus, as Blake says, “time is the gift of eternity”; that is to say,
eternity allows us all those experiences in succession. Thus, we have days and nights,
hours and years. We have memory, we have our present perceptions, and then we
have the future whose shape we are ignorant of, but which we foresee or fear. All,
absolutely all, is given to us sequentially, and wisely so, I should add, for if it were
given to us all of a sudden, it would be impossible for human beings to endure such
a terrible vision – the unbearable burden of  the whole Being of  the universe. […]
The totality of  Being is unattainable to us. All is given us, but, thankfully, gradually’
(Alifano 1984: 63–4).
34 Introduction

lives’] (1984: 68). Again a dialogue between opposing perspectives is visible


here: transmigration of souls is a literary artifice, and yet it has resonance
because, he argues, it is an intrinsic aspect of  human experience; indeed
he declares outright that it is a feeling that ‘all of us’ have shared. It is, he
describes in the essay ‘Quevedo’, a false doctrine, but it is nevertheless
enchanting and compelling: ‘Hay en la historia de la filosofía doctrinas,
probablemente falsas, que ejercen un oscuro encanto sobre la imaginación
de los hombres: la doctrina platónica y pitagórica del tránsito del alma
por muchos cuerpos’ (1974: 661) [‘In the history of philosophy are doc-
trines, probably false, that exercise an obscure charm on human imagina-
tion: the Platonic and Pythagorean doctrine of  the transmigration of  the
soul through many bodies’] (1964: 38). He qualifies this tension between
perspectives further by suggesting that discrediting a priori the notion of 
transmigration is the activity of a dry empiricist, resistant to the literary
charms of  the concept. He criticizes Quevedo, who being ‘sólo estudioso de
la verdad, es invulnerable a ese encanto. Escribe que la transmigración de las
almas es “bobería bestial” y “locura bruta”’ (1974: 661) [‘merely a student of 
the truth, is invulnerable to that charm. He writes that the transmigration
of souls is “bestial foolishness” and “brutish folly”’] (1964: 38). Herein lies
the conundrum: Borges would reject the supernatural out of principle, yet
he ridicules Quevedo for upholding this very position. He would prefer
to call himself a rationalist, a sceptic and a disbeliever, and yet his natural
af finities lie with the non-rational, the mysterious, the poetic and those
fields of experience beyond the confines of materialist philosophies – the
‘intersticios de sinrazón’.
It becomes clear that despite his misgivings on matters of  faith, Borges
placed great epistemological importance in the non-causal, the non-rational,
the non-logical. In this realm we find dreams, nightmares, fantasy, mystical
vision, poetry, otherworld journeys, daimonic beings, communication with
the dead, ancestral voices, timelessness and ecstasy. In addition to favouring
the supernatural whilst simultaneously disavowing the supernatural, we find
numerous instances in Borges’ essays and interviews in which, like Lönnrot,
he seeks the anomalous aspect of  human experience before the strictly
rational. He writes longingly, for example, about Stevenson’s accounts of
receiving inspiration and fully-formed narratives, such as Strange Case of 
Introduction 35

Dr Jekyll and Mr Hyde, from the Brownies whom he encountered in his


dreams and reveries.18 He cites Bede’s description of  how Cædmon was
first amongst poets, ‘porque no aprendió de los hombres sino de Dios’
[‘because he did not learn from men, but from God’], and he indicates that
‘esperemos que [Caedmon] volvió a encontrarse con su ángel’ (1974: 643)
[‘Let us hope he met his angel again’] (1964: 16). He writes in absolutely
clear terms that he gave great credence to the possibility that nightmares
have a demonic origin, writing in the lecture on nightmares in Siete Noches:

Ya que hemos visto estas diversas etimologías, tenemos en francés la palabra cauche-
mar, vinculada, sin duda, con la nightmare del inglés. En todas ellas hay una idea
(voy a volver sobre ellas) de origen demoníaco, la idea de un demonio que causa la
pesadilla. Creo que no se trata simplemente de una superstición: creo que puede
haber – y estoy hablando con toda ingenuidad y toda sinceridad – , algo verdadero
en este concepto. (1989: 225)

[We also have the French word, cauchemar, which is probably linked to nightmare.
In all of  these words there is an idea of demonic origin, the idea of a demon who
causes the nightmare. I believe it does not derive simply from a superstition. I believe
that there is – and I speak with complete honesty and sincerity – something true
in this idea.] (1984: 32)

18 ‘Son hombrecitos serviciales de color pardo, del cual han tomado su nombre. Suelen
visitar las granjas de Escocia y durante el sueño de la familia, colaboran en las tareas
domésticas. Uno de los cuentos de Grimm refiere un hecho análogo. El ilustre escri-
tor Robert Louis Stevenson afirmó que había adiestrado a sus Brownies en el oficio
literario. Cuando soñaba, éstos le sugerían temas fantásticos; por ejemplo, la extraña
transformación del doctor Jekyll en el diabólico señor Hyde, y aquel episodio de
Olalla en el cual un joven, de una antigua casa española, muerde la mano de su her-
mana’ (1978: 17) [‘Brownies are helpful little men of a brownish hue, which gives
them their name. It is their habit to visit Scottish farms and, while the household
sleeps, to perform domestic chores. One of  the tales by the Grimms deals with the
same subject. Robert Louis Stevenson said he had trained his Brownies in the craft
of  literature. Brownies visited him in his dreams and told him wondrous tales; for
instance the strange transformation of  Dr Jekyll into the diabolical Mr Hyde, and
that episode of  Olalla, in which the scion of an old Spanish family bites his sister’s
hand’] (1974: 32).
36 Introduction

Again we must ask, if  he ‘automatically reject[ed] the supernatural’ then


how does one reconcile his inclination towards demons? When he empha-
sized that Swedenborg ‘recorrió este mundo y los otros, lúcido y laborioso.
[…] ese escandinavo sanguíneo, que fue mucho más lejos que Erico el Rojo’
(2005: 152) [‘journeyed, lucid and laborious, through this and all other
worlds […] that sanguine Scandinavian who went much further than Eric
the Red’] (1995: 3), and at the same time compared Swedenborg’s ‘authen-
tic’ experiences with Dante’s ‘poetic’ ones, upon what basis was he making
this most radical of distinctions?
Reason can be an unwieldy tool, Borges appeared to argue, as it can
disprove phenomena that can be experienced as real, such as transmigra-
tion of  the soul or Stevenson’s Brownies. Annette Flynn, in her recent
meticulous appraisal of  the spiritual quest that dominates Borges’ work,
identifies the paradox in Borges’ relationship with God in which reason
can be employed to disprove God, but experience compelled him to a rec-
ognition that there is nevertheless some divine order, some divine force or
presence remaining in this absence.

He oscillates between disavowal of  God, and desire for verification of a divine exist-
ence. On the one hand he at times intellectualizes God and seems to be dismissing his
existence on rational grounds; on the other, he continuously searches for something
bigger than himself or the intellect. […] The tension lies in the balance which Borges
struggles to strike between his enquiring intellect and a faith reality. (Flynn 2009: 4–5)

In a similar fashion Borges employed logical, reasoned, arguments to dis-


prove the existence of  time, arguing that there is no extension to the pre-
sent, being the mere conjunction of past and future, and thus it cannot
be considered as occupying any time. Accordingly the past, which is the
mere congregation of such non-extant moments, can have no extension,
and neither can the future. There is, consequently, no time; and yet we
experience time.

Se ha dicho que si el tiempo es infinito, el número infinito de vidas hacia el pasado


es una contradicción. Si el número es infinito, ¿cómo una cosa infinita puede llegar
hasta ahora? Pensamos que si un tiempo es infinito, creo yo, ese tiempo infinito tiene
que abarcar todos los presentes y, en todos los presentes, ¿por qué no este presente,
Introduction 37

en Belgrano, en la Universidad de Belgrano, ustedes conmigo, juntos? ¿Por qué no


ese tiempo también? Si el tiempo es infinito, en cualquier instante estamos en el
centro del tiempo. (2005: 189)

[It has been said that if  time is infinite, how can an infinite thing reach the present?
We think that if  time is infinite, and I believe it is, then that infinite time must
include all the presents and, among all the presents, why not this present here, in
the University of  Belgrano, with you and I together? Why not that time also? If 
time is infinite, at any given moment we are in the center of  time.] (2000: 487–8)

The self, Borges argues in ‘La nadería de la personalidad’ is equally devoid


of extension or location, and consequently cannot exist; and yet Borges,
desgraciademente was Borges and therefore experienced some state of self-
hood. Reason and experience are not, therefore, necessarily in concord. In
many respects, this dialectic may be considered a fundamental response
to the dualist binary developed with Enlightenment thought, in which
faith and reason, science and magic, history and myth, are assigned firmly
contraposed locations. Borges was sensitive to this catalogue of  binaries,
and wrote with admiration of  the ability of  Swedenborg to harmonize his
pursuit of  knowledge in material sciences with his explorations of spiritual
realities. Repeatedly Borges emphasized that there simply was no epistemo-
logical division, that Swedenborg’s immense intellect bore him as deeply
into the material as into the non-material. Plato and Socrates, for Borges,
likewise did not feel compelled to distinguish one mode of enquiry from
another, and were as comfortable exploring the dreamworld as the waking
world. Indeed, suggested Borges, it is not only a consequence of modernity
that we are unable to treat both with the same lucidity, but only modern
man would even assume that a division existed.

With Plato, you feel that he would reason in an abstract way and would also use
myth. He would do those two things at the same time. But now we seem to have
lost that gift. I mean, you have gone from myth to abstract thinking. But Plato could
do both at the same time. […] I suppose at that time it could be done. But nowadays
those things seem to be in watertight compartments. Either we are thinking or we
are dreaming. But Plato and Socrates could do both. (Burgin 1998: 160)
38 Introduction

This harmonising of opposites appears to be the most compelling


epistemological attraction for Borges in the varied traditions of mystical
texts. Reality is poetic and poetry is reality; Swedenborg’s heavens were as
real to Swedenborg as the minerals that he catalogued. As discussed above,
Borges’ entire literary career, both as a reader and a writer, was grounded
in his fascination with the ‘intersticios de sinrazón’ that have character-
ized human experience since the earliest texts. Poets, artists, dreamers
and mystics have explored such liminal matters, and in this respect the
aesthetic – allied to dreams, visions and the imagination – constitutes
the avenue of exploration into such mysterious interstices in the fabric of
reality. We recall the labyrinth as a perennial symbol in the work of  Borges
to signify, amongst other things, the human state of unknowing. Whilst
the critical attention to the labyrinth over the years is colossal, of greatest
pertinence to our present study is a question that di Giovanni posed Borges
in interview, concerning the possibility of mysticism to shine some light
into the darkness and to provide some genuine insights into the inher-
ent mysteries: ‘Do you see mysticism as a way out of  the maze?’ Borges
replies: ‘For all I know, mysticism is the only way; but my gods, whoever
they may be, have not allowed me that particular way’ (Burgin 1998: 129,
emphasis mine). This is a powerful response, as Borges suggested that the
walls of  the labyrinth may not be as impregnable as imagined, and that the
mystic may be capable, through exploring the ‘intersticios’, of increasing
our knowledge of reality.
Swedenborgian scholar Wilson Van Dusen, whose chapter accompa-
nies Borges’ in Testimony to the Invisible writes that: ‘A mystic is one who
experiences God. […] Some might ask, “Don’t all people experience God?”
And I would answer yes, but many are not aware of it. The mystic is aware
of it’ (1995: 105). In the perspective of  Borges such a statement could be
rephrased: ‘Don’t all people experience intersticios de sinrazón? Yes, but
the mystic is aware of it.’ Indeed, one may argue, the whole heavenly theol-
ogy of  Swedenborg constitutes a dazzling penetration into such ‘intersti-
cios’. Hence one can query Borges’ interest in such mysterious matters as
being merely ‘for aesthetic purposes’ and merely as fodder for fiction. Flynn
addresses this very issue: can we trust Borges’ statement of critical distance?
Introduction 39

Certain much-quoted declarations by Borges – which do deserve closer attention – as


to the purely aesthetic, intellectual, narratorial and inspirational value of philosophi-
cal and theological doctrines, may have to be reconsidered, and the role of the divine
assigned a more prominent place than accorded by the majority canon of critics, and
not least, as is often held, by Borges himself. His remarks, typically understated and
subtle, as to the significance of  theologies and philosophies have been taken as cat-
egorical dismissals of  these inf luences, or as admitting to an agnostic outlook. This
is a view which is highly contestable. Far from solely driving the story or supplying
intriguing, inspirational or outlandish backdrops to the events narrated, the desire
for a union with the absolute, a divine, higher order is not only what underlies and
drives the story, it also compels Borges. (Flynn 2009: 12)

This is a compelling statement, and an invitation to pay ‘closer attention’


to Borges’ repeated declarations. This book is such a response.

‘Teaching a contemplative methodology that fosters insight’


(Amelia Barili)

Kripal (2001: 3) argues that there is a general reluctance within academia


to incorporate into the research and teaching methodology the academ-
ics’ or the students’ own religious, mystical, numinous, transpersonal or
anomalous experiences. There is a sense that the numinous is somehow
taboo, and consequently is hidden in the ‘shadows of self-censorship, discre-
tion, and whispered enthusiasms’. Borges himself, as I have argued above,
maintained a critical distance that displays a tension between intellect and
intuition, reason and faith, fact and fiction. The Borges scholarship, with
some notable exceptions, has tended likewise and with good reason to
follow Borges’ lead, and explore the areas of  Borges’ interest – Kabbalah,
esotericism, mysticism, Buddhism – with the same necessary critical dis-
tance. This, I emphasize, is fully commensurate with the critical distance
that Borges himself maintained. There is, however, a tendency to treat this
scholarly method of critical distance not as a hermeneutic tool to analyse
the texts and phenomena encountered, but as a defence to prevent further
40 Introduction

exploration; that is to say, to take Borges on his word and treat these sub-
jects as mere picturesque arcana and entertaining superstitions worthy
only of providing thematic for fiction. Academic analysis, I would argue,
should in no way prohibit a close, personal, transformative, engagement
with Borges’ texts, and an equally close engagement with the texts and
philosophies that he explored. Amelia Barili (2009: 47–8), who knew
Borges when she was editor of  La Prensa, outlines this pedagogical ten-
sion in brave and lucid terms:

I have sensed more and more that our times demand that we integrate into our
teaching a contemplative methodology that fosters insight. We are in the midst of
a content explosion that quickly outdates any instruction based on content alone.
Further, students are increasingly anguished, and it is important that they find ways
to more deeply understand this vast amount of information, to sort out what matters
to them and to their communities, and to create new meaning from what is present to
them. […] We need a paradigm shift in education. Universities need to be sources of
creative solutions and of engaged citizens. They should be centers of transformation,
not just repositories of information. […] For deep learning to occur, there needs to
be ref lection about intra- and inter- subjectivity.

Barili perceives a tendency within the academic environment to favour


the transmission and recollection of information over the assimilation
of  knowledge within a process of personal development. This is clearly a
highly generalized statement, but nevertheless such a tendency is visible,
especially as – at least in the UK – universities are under increasing pressure
to market degree programmes according to a narrative of  ‘employability’
and are thus placing non-vocational courses (the reading of  Borges’ poetry
for its own sake, rather than as a tool to learning Spanish or Latin American
literatures) under increasing scrutiny. Barili is one of  the few scholars that
I have encountered to incorporate the teaching of  Borges texts in a fully
integrated environment that encourages uniting discussion of  the texts
with attention to transformative processes of  the readers. She seems fully
cognizant of  the tension present within modes of critical enquiry between
reason and feeling, intellect and intuition, theory and practice. In particu-
lar, she concentrates on Borges’ close involvement with Buddhist texts as a
rich pathway towards a full engagement with Buddhism itself. Accordingly
Introduction 41

there is no disconnection in beginning a seminar of  the course ‘Borges,


Buddhism, and Cognitive Science’ with meditation sessions prior to a
critical reading of ¿Qué es el Budismo? or Ficciones.
Buddhism itself is of  key importance, she suggests, as it chimes per-
fectly with the mode of critical enquiry present within Borges himself: ‘A
characteristic that Borges greatly valued in Buddhism is that its core teach-
ings are more a process of critical enquiry than an assertion of certitude.
Borges found this uncertainty very liberating and stimulating, since it frees
us to create our own meaning’ (2009: 52). It also, she argues, chimes with
Borges’ inherently accommodating views of religion and spiritual prac-
tices: ‘Borges attributed the durability of  Buddhism over the centuries to
this characteristic of  tolerance, which is naturally related to an emphasis
on personal inquiry and verification’ (2009: 52). Barili’s consideration of 
the Buddhist sensibilities of  Borges is fully borne out by an evaluation of 
his philosophical critical attitude and his wariness to commit to faith. In
the lecture ‘Budismo’ of  Siete Noches Borges makes much of  the demands
of credulity that most faiths place upon the faithful. ‘Las otras religiones
exigen mucho de nuestra credulidad. Si somos cristianos, debemos creer
que una de las tres personas de la Divinidad condescendió a ser hombre
y fue crucificado en Judea. Si somos musulmanes tenemos que creer que
no hay otro dios que Dios y que Muhammad es su apóstol. Podemos ser
buenos budistas y negar que el Buddha existió’ (1989: 243) [‘The other
religions demand much more credulity on our part. If we are Christians we
must believe that one of  the three persons of  the Divinity condescended
to become a man and was crucified in Judea. If we are Muslims we must
believe that there is no other god than God and that Mohammad is his
apostle. We can be good Buddhists and deny that Buddha existed’].19
There is, consequently, a harmonious balancing of opposites in Borges’
relationship with Buddhism; it is a religious path that, for him, places doubt
at the heart of  the spiritual attitude. Consequently, one may well argue
that his closing comments of  the lecture, in which he professes not to be

19 Translation Frank Thomas Smith <http://www.southerncrossreview.org/48/borges-


buddhism.htm>.
42 Introduction

Buddhist, are conversely strikingly Buddhist sentiments: ‘Lo que he dicho


hoy es fragmentario. Hubiera sido absurdo que yo expusiera una doctrina a
la cual he dedicado tantos años – y de la que he entendido poco, realmente
– con ánimo de mostrar una pieza de museo. Para mí el budismo no es una
pieza de museo: es un camino de salvación’ (1989: 254) [‘What I have said
tonight is fragmentary. It would have been absurd if  I had expounded a
doctrine to which I have dedicated some years – and of which I have actu-
ally understood little – with the intention of displaying a museum piece.
Buddhism is not a museum piece; it is a path to salvation’] (trans. Smith).
It is likewise perfectly commensurate with a reading of  Borges’ works on
Buddhism to include a meditation session. Borges himself spoke about
Buddhism that ‘Lo que nos pide es la meditación, una meditación que
no tiene que ser sobre nuestras culpas, sobre nuestra vida pasada’ (1989:
252) [‘What it requires is meditation, and meditation that has nothing to
do with our sins, with our past lives’] (trans. Smith). In the pedagogical
method described by Barili, therefore, centred on Borges’ relationship with
Buddhism, a certain gulf is bridged between theory and practice, reason
and faith, text and meta-text; and the tension of opposites described above
is tempered and harmonized. In this way Barili would appear to perceive
in Borges a greater degree of investment in the mystical, spiritual, religious
and metaphysical texts than is customarily af forded him. Here one may
see a method developed cognate with the call for transformation outlined
by Ferrer (2002: 123):

The transformative quality of  the human participation in transpersonal and spiritual
phenomena has been observed by a number of modern consciousness researchers
(e.g. Grof, 1985, 1988; Harman, 1994) and scholars of mysticism (e.g. Barnard, 1994,
Staal, 1975). One needs to be willing to be personally transformed in order to access
and fully understand most spiritual phenomena. The epistemological significance
of such personal transformation cannot be emphasized enough, especially given that
the positivist denial of such a requisite is clearly one of  the main obstacles for the
epistemic legitimization of  transpersonal and spiritual claims in the modern West.

I would argue that the ‘participatory turn’ discussed by Ferrer is present in


two fundamental levels in Borges: firstly, through a broad reading of  his
many tales, poems, essays and interviews, it becomes clear that despite his
Introduction 43

oft-proclaimed radical scepticism and his mistrust of  faith and religious
doctrine, as a reader he himself was deeply af fected and transformed by the
mystical and religious texts that he read. Secondly, it becomes clear that
many of  Borges’ texts themselves may be considered deeply transformative
texts if  the reader is open to such qualities in the works. Thus, as I explore in
Chapter Two, whilst ‘El Aleph’ and ‘La escritura del dios’ may be interpreted
as parodies or even satires of mystical texts, they may also be considered
profoundly mystical texts in their own right. Such an interpretation, as I
explore, is not without its dif ficulties, yet such a quality must be addressed.
Both Barili and Ferrer would argue, furthermore, that the personal and
transpersonal experiences of  the students may be given greater value than
many traditional pedagogical practices would customarily permit. In this
work I hope to pursue the avenue proposed by Barili and Ferrer in explor-
ing Borges’ relationship with mysticism as a field of investigation that was
of greater significance for Borges than mere exercises in gathering material
to craft into fiction and poetry.

‘Borges is our Virgil; only he knows the way’ (Alastair Reid)

Borges often suggested that he would like to be remembered as a reader


more than as a writer; and in particular as a friend, as someone who hap-
pily recommends a book, poem or author, and would then delightedly
pass the hours discussing the symbols, allusions, references, narrative twists
and literary devices of  the given texts. As such, it is important to assess the
relationship between Borges the reader and the reader of  Borges. What
terrain does he traverse with us? Into which dark caverns in Dante’s cir-
cles of  hells does he lead us? What interpretative tools does he teach us
when reading Swedenborg’s dialogues with angels and with the dead? As
he explores the ‘intersticios de sinrazón’ that are themselves explored by
Dante, Swedenborg, Silesius or Blake, what knowledge does he reveal to us
about the nature of  the real? These are also questions that have concerned
44 Introduction

readers and critics of  Borges from his early publications to the present. For
example, Garayalde (1978: 27), in her exploration of  the inf luence of  Sufi
mysticism upon Borges’ works, addresses the aspect of  Borges as guide in
the dark world beyond reason: ‘Once we have lost our faith in reason as a
means of seeking truth, Borges does not abandon us but opens up a new
range of possibilities by following the path of intuition. […] Borges is trying
in this way to familiarize us with intuition, a kind of  knowledge that man
no longer takes into account and which he has completely forgotten.’ As
discussed earlier, and as Garayalde identifies, Borges demonstrates a shifting
balance of reason and intuition, scepticism and tolerance, in such matters
of poetic obscurity.
The question of  Borges as guide and fellow traveller can perhaps be
best illustrated with a literary analogy. In his many writings and lectures
about Dante, Borges paid particular attention to the enigmatic figure of 
Virgil as guide and close friend of  the poet-narrator Dante. There are many
attributes to Virgil in the Commedia which, as Borges notes, the scholarship
over the centuries has investigated. What concerned Borges above all other
matters was the friendship between Dante and Virgil and the consequent
anguish that Dante experienced in acknowledging that Virgil, as pagan,
would be forever consigned to the nobile castello and would be unable to
achieve union with the godhead:
Dante viene a ser un hijo de Virgilio y al mismo tiempo es superior a Virgilio porque
se cree salvado. Cree que merecerá la gracia o que la ha merecido, ya que le ha sido
dada la visión. En cambio, desde el comienzo del Infierno sabe que Virgilio es un
alma perdida, un réprobo; cuando Virgilio le dice que no podrá acompañarlo más allá
del Purgatorio, siente que el latino será para siempre un habitante del terrible nobile
castello donde están las grandes sombras de los grandes muertos de la Antigüedad,
los que por ignorancia invencible no alcanzaron la palabra de Cristo. En ese mismo
momento, Dante dice: Tu, duca; tu, signore; tu, maestro … Para cubrir ese momento,
Dante lo saluda con palabras magníficas y habla del largo estudio y del gran amor
que le han hecho buscar su volumen y siempre se mantiene esa relación entre los
dos. Esa figura esencialmente triste de Virgilio, que se sabe condenado a habitar
para siempre en el nobile castello lleno de la ausencia de Dios … En cambio, a Dante
le será permitido ver a Dios, le será permitido comprender el universe. (1989: 213)
Introduction 45

[Dante comes to be the son of  Virgil, yet at the same time he is superior to Virgil for
he believes he will be saved, since he has been given the vision. But he knows, from
the beginning, that Virgil is a lost soul, a reprobate. When Virgil tells him that he
cannot accompany him beyond Purgatory, he knows that the Latin poet will always
inhabit the terrible nobile castello with the great shades of  Antiquity, those who never
heard the word of  Christ. At that moment, Dante hails him with magnificent words:
‘Tu, duca; tu, signore; tu, maestro …’ He speaks of  the great labor and of  the great love
with which his work has been studied, and this relation is always maintained between
the two. But Virgil is essentially a sad figure who knows he is forever condemned to
that castle filled with the absence of  God. Dante, however, will be permitted to see
God; he will be permitted to understand the universe.] (1984: 14)20

As we explore in the following chapter, whilst Borges held Dante in great


esteem, he was troubled by the adherence to ecclesiastical doctrine that he
perceived throughout the Commedia, and he praised the rebelliousness –
even heresy – that he detected in Dante. Borges was no Dante; the agnosti-
cism and the disdain for faith would likewise condemn him to the nobile
castello. As Alastair Reid writes in the Introduction of  Seven Nights ‘Borges
is our Virgil; only he knows the way.’ Like Virgil, Borges as reader and as
poet has descended with Aeneas through Black Avernus into the realm
of  the Shades (Aeneid Book VI), and has communicated with the great
Classical poets. He leads us through the hellish swamps and the celestial
paradise of  Swedenborg’s Heaven and Hell. He guides us through Blake’s
complex mythologies. He describes for us the martial halls of  Valhalla that
he discovers in the Icelandic sagas. He reads to us about the song of  Bede’s

20 Dante knows that Virgil is a damned soul, and the very moment that Virgil tells
him that he will not be able to accompany him beyond purgatory, Dante feels that
Virgil will always be an inhabitant of  that ‘nobile castello’ where the great shadows
of  the great men of antiquity dwell, those that through unavoidable ignorance did
not accept or could not reach the word of  Christ. […] Dante salutes him with the
highest epithets and speaks of  the great love and the long study to which Virgil’s
writings have led him, and of  their relationship which has always been constant. But
Virgil is sad since he knows that he is condemned to the ‘nobile castello,’ far from
salvation and full of  God’s absence; Dante, on the other hand, will see God, he will
be allowed to, and he will also be allowed to understand the universe. (Alifano 1984:
97)
46 Introduction

Cædmon and he recounts Stevenson’s relationship with the Brownies. He


presents before our gaze oriental celestial dragons, subterranean goblins,
elves, hippogrif fs, the Minotaur and the Banshee (see El libro de los seres
imaginarios). And yet, like Virgil, he cannot lead us to the divine. That is
for the faithful and Borges, I imagine, would be happier to remain with
the reader in the pagan castle, engaging in merry dialogue with Homer,
Ovid, Lucan, Horace and Virgil, than rising towards the heavenly rose.
This book, I hope, is part of  that dialogue.
Chapter One

Fantastic or real?
Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg  1

Hay un curioso género literario que independientemente se ha dado en


diversas épocas y naciones: la guía del muerto en las regiones ultraterre-
nas. El Cielo y el Infierno de Swedenborg, las escrituras gnósticas, el Bardo
Thödol de los tibetanos (título que, según Evans-Wentz, debe traducirse
‘Liberación por Audición en el Plano de la Posmuerte’) y el Libro Egipcio
de los Muertos no agotan los ejemplos posibles. Las simpatías y diferencias
de los dos últimos han merecido la atención de los eruditos; bástenos aquí
repetir que para el manual tibetano el otro mundo es tan ilusorio como
éste y para el egipcio es real y objetivo.
— Jorge Luis Borges and Margarita Guerrero,
El Libro de los Seres Imaginarios, ‘El Devorador de las Sombras’

[There is a strange literary genre which, spontaneously, has sprung up in


various lands and at various times. This is the manual for the guidance
of  the dead through the Other World. Heaven and Hell by Swedenborg,
the writings of  the Gnostics, the Tibetan Bardo Thödol (which, according
to Evans-Wentz, should be translated as ‘Liberation by Hearing on the
After-Death Plane’), and the Egyptian Book of  the Dead do not exhaust
the possible examples. The similarities and dif ferences of  the latter two
books have attracted the attention of esoteric scholarship; for us, let it be
enough to recall that in the Tibetan manual the Other World is as illusory
as this one, while to the Egyptians it has a real and objective existence.]
— The Book of  Imaginary Beings, ‘The Eater of  the Dead’

1 An earlier version of  this chapter was published as an article in Variaciones Borges:
‘Borges’s reading of  Dante and Swedenborg: Mysticism and the real’, 32 (October
2011), 59–85. Many thanks to the journal editors for kind permission to reproduce
the text here.
48 Chapter One

Borges, as is well documented, subverts genre distinctions between real-


ism and fantasy, declaring in countless interviews, prologues and essays
that the joy of  literature is the appeal to the imagination, that history is
memory and that a literary experience is as real as any other experience.
Furthermore, he famously equates metaphysics with the fantastic, claim-
ing, for example, in a review of a work of  the English theologian Leslie
Weatherhead: ‘¿qué son las prodigios de Wells o de Poe […] confrontados
con la invención de Dios? […] ¿Quién en el unicornio ante la Trinidad?’
(1974: 281) [‘What, in fact, are the wonders of  Wells or Edgar Allan Poe
[…] in comparison to the invention of  God? […] What is the unicorn to
the Trinity?’] (2000: 255). However, in his reading of  the ill-defined tra-
dition of mystical writing, Borges appears to betray this disdain for genre
distinction, and adheres with an odd rigor to a categorical assessment of
real versus fictional, fantastic versus genuine, authentic versus inauthentic.
Borges wrote passionately about Dante and about Swedenborg, both of
whom depicted heaven and the angelic denizens therein. He pursues, as
we shall see, a line of enquiry in which he asserts that Dante’s visions were
purely aesthetic, purely artistic, and did not hail from genuine experience;
whilst Swedenborg’s visions were genuine, authentic and experiential.
In this chapter I will appraise Borges’ abiding admiration of  both
visionary writers and his critical response to them, and will evaluate the
complex and at times paradoxical criteria that Borges employs in his assess-
ment of  the authentic in opposition to the imaginal. My hypotheses can be
summed up in three statements. Borges’ writings lead to the erasure of  fact
and fiction; however, Borges himself retreats into the very realist-fantasy
division that he was at pains to dispel in his fictions and essays when evalu-
ating mysticism and mystical vision. Similarly, for Borges originality is not
prized. He does, however, place great emphasis on originality in relation
to mystical vision. Lastly, his assessment of putative authenticity is itself
an aesthetic judgment based upon his own iconoclasm and mistrust of
doctrine. This is the touchstone for his emphatic distinction.
Borges’ manifest love for Dante’s Divine Comedy is crystallized in his
laudatory lecture in Siete Noches: ‘La Comedia es un libro que todos debemos
leer. No hacerlo es privarnos del mejor don que la literatura puede darnos, es
entregarnos a un extraño ascetismo. ¿Por qué negarnos la felicidad de leer la
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 49

Comedia?’ (1989: 217) [‘The Comedia is a book that everyone ought to read.
Not to do so is to deprive oneself of  the greatest gift that literature can give
us; it is to submit to a strange asceticism. Why should we deny ourselves
the joy of reading the Comedia?’] (1984: 20). The Divine Comedy is also
the book that he would choose to rescue from the hypothetical destruc-
tion of all books (Cortínez 1986: 87). There is much to say about Borges’
appreciation of  Dante, and whilst the Borges scholarship has approached
numerous elements, one central feature prevalent in most of  Borges’ writ-
ings of  Dante has been curiously overlooked. This is Borges’ strident af fir-
mation that Dante was not a visionary, but that he was a visionary poet.
Borges explains: ‘No creo que Dante fuera un visionario. Una visión es
breve. Es imposible una visión tan larga como la de la Comedia. La visión
fue voluntaria: debemos abandonarnos a ella y leerla, con fe poética. Dijo
Coleridge que la fe poética es una voluntaria suspensión de la incredulidad’
(1989: 211) [‘I don’t think that Dante was a visionary. A vision is brief. A
vision as large as the Comedia is impossible. His vision was voluntary: we
may abandon ourselves to it and read it with poetic faith. Coleridge said
that poetic faith is the willing suspension of disbelief ’] (1984: 12).2
Firstly, therefore, Borges asserts that Dante’s vision was not a vision
in the mystical sense, because, rather than being spontaneous and unbid-
den (i.e. grace of  the divine), it was voluntary. Secondly, Dante was not
a visionary because of  the length of  this vision, which, Borges maintains,
would be unsustainable. Thirdly, Dante was not a visionary because the

2 This af firmation is reiterated elsewhere. He tells Roberto Alifano: ‘Dante reveals to


us in his narrative that at thirty-five (Nel mezzo del cammin di nostra vita) a vision
comes to him. I don’t believe that Dante was a visionary; a vision is something more
f leeting, something more ethereal. A vision as prolonged as The Divine Comedy is
impossible. I think that his vision was voluntary. His vision was the result of his poetic
faith – but that would be a theme in itself, a very interesting one which should be
pursued’ (Alifano 1984: 95). He tells Willis Barnstone: ‘It is very clear to me that
when Dante had his dream of  hell and his dream of purgatory, he was imagining
things’ (Barnstone 1982: 95); and he writes in the last of  the Nueve ensayos dantescos:
‘Retengamos un hecho incontrovertible, un solo hecho humildísimo: la escena ha
sido imaginada por Dante’ (1989: 374) [‘We must keep one incontrovertible fact in
mind, a single, humble fact: the scene was imagined by Dante’] (2000: 304–5).
50 Chapter One

vision itself was inspired by poetic faith, and was therefore culturally condi-
tioned within established theological and artistic frameworks. Furthermore,
argues Borges elsewhere, Dante wrote in verse, and there is no possible way
that he could have experienced the various circles of  the Divine Comedy in
such an aesthetic language.

En el caso de Dante, que también nos ofrece una descripción del Infierno, del
Purgatorio y del Paraíso, entendemos que se trata de una ficción literaria. No pode-
mos creer realmente que todo lo que relata se refiere a una vivencia personal. Además,
ahí está el verseo que lo ata: él no pudo haber experimentado el verso. (2005: 202)

[In the case of  Dante, who also of fers us a description of Hell, Purgatory and Paradise,
we understand that we’re dealing with literary fiction. We cannot really believe that
all that he relates refers to personal experience. Furthermore, there is the verse which
binds it: he could not have experienced verse.] (My translation)

The whole poetic cycle is thus, for Borges, resolutely and beautifully a lit-
erary fiction, a poetic text, an artifice. At face value this assertion does not
seem too problematic, indeed it attunes perfectly to Borges’ love of  fantasy
and fiction in all their guises. However, complications begin to emerge
when assessing Borges’ discussion of  Swedenborg.
The most extensive appraisal of  Swedenborg in Borges’ works is his
biographical essay on Swedenborg.3 This text abounds in highly revealing
passages in which Borges af firms the authentic, non-fictive, genuine experi-
ences of  Swedenborg, and in which he emphasizes precisely the opposite
of what he maintains about Dante, that Swedenborg was a visionary.

3 Borges’ 1972 essay ‘Swedenborg, testigo de lo invisible’ was published as prologue to


a Spanish edition of  The Essential Swedenborg by Sig Synnestvedt: Swedenborg, testigo
de lo invisible (1982), translated into English by Richard Howard and Cesar Rennert
as ‘Testimony to the Invisible’ in the homonymous volume of essays edited by James
F. Lawrence (1995). The original prologue is also found in the section Prólogos, con
un prólogo de prólogos (2005, 152–60), entitled, ‘Emmanuel Swedenborg: Mystical
Works’. Eliot Weinberger’s English translation of  this prologue/essay appears in Total
Library: Non-Fiction (2000a) 449–57.
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 51

En una epístola famosa dirigida a Cangrande Della Scala, Dante Alighieri advierte
qué su Comedia, como la Sagrada Escritura, puede leerse de cuatro modos distintos
y que el literal no es más que Uno de ellos […]. Pasajes como Lasciate ogni speranza,
voi ch’entrate fortalecen esa convicción topográfica, realizada por el arte. Nada más
diverso de los destinos ultraterrenos de Swedenborg. (2005: 156)

[In a famous letter to Cangrande Della Scala, Dante Alighieri points out that his
Commedia, like Sacred Scripture, can be read four dif ferent ways, of which the literal
way is only one […]. Passages such as Lasciate ogni speranza, voi ch’entrate (‘All hope
abandon, ye who enter here’) reinforce the topographical conviction created through
art. Nothing is farther from the ultra-terrestrial destinations of  Swedenborg.] (1995: 9)

The Divine Comedy, he asserts, is the pinnacle of artistic expression, and


the fact that Dante outlines modes of reading (literal, allegorical, moral,
anagogical), testifies to this artifice. The mystical works of  Swedenborg,
however, are wholly free from artifice, being the direct account of genu-
ine experience of a man ‘que recorrió este mundo y los otros, lúcido y
laborioso. […] ese escandinavo sanguíneo, que fue mucho más lejos que
Erico el Rojo’ (2005: 152) [‘who journeyed, lucid and laborious, through
this and all other worlds […] that sanguine Scandinavian who went much
further than Eric the Red’] (1995: 3). Significantly, Borges maintains that
the literal reading of  the Divine Comedy would impoverish the text, as the
reader would fail to appreciate the allegorical, moral and mystical levels
of meaning.4 It would also betray a stultifying credulity on behalf of  the
reader. To illustrate this, Borges makes reference on more than one occa-
sion to the observation that the heaven of  Dante would correspond to no
heaven putatively encountered after death.

Paul Claudel ha observado que los espectáculos que nos aguardan después de la agonía
no serán verosímilmente los nueve círculos infernales, las terrazas del Purgatorio o
los cielos concéntricos. Dante, sin duda, habría estado de acuerdo con él; ideó su

4 Aside, however, from the opening couplet of  the cycle: ‘Nel mezzo del cammin di
nostra vita / mi ritrovai per una selva oscura. Es decir, a los treinta y cinco años ‘me
encontré en mitad de una selva oscura’ que puede ser alegórica, pero en la cual cree-
mos físicamente’ (1989: 211) [‘That is, at thirty-five I found myself in a dark forest.
It may be allegorical, but we physically believe it’] (1984: 12).
52 Chapter One

topografía de la muerte como un artificio exigido por la escolástica y por la forma


de su poema. (1989: 344)

[Paul Claudel has observed that the sights that await us after dying will not, in all
likelihood, include the nine circles of  Hell, the terraces of  Purgatory, or the concentric
heavens. Dante would undoubtedly have agreed; he devised his topography of death
as an artifice demanded by Scholasticism and by the form of  his poem.] (2000: 268)5

On the contrary, he maintains, it would be dif ficult to read the works


of  Swedenborg in any manner other than the literal. This is because, for
Borges, Swedenborg’s writings were the genuine expression of experience,
and were not written with any attempt at parable, symbol or allegory. He
emphasizes Swedenborg’s dry and meticulous Latin prose as being wholly
free from f lowery literary technique, especially metaphor: ‘A diferencia
de otros místicos, prescindió de la metáfora, de la exaltación y de la vaga
y fogosa hipérbole’ (2005: 154) [‘unlike other mystics, he eschewed meta-
phor, exaltation, and vague, fiery hyperbole’] (1995: 6).6 He examines the

5 Borges also derives this observation from Flaubert: ‘Por eso me parece justo lo que
ha dicho Flaubert diciendo que Dante al morir debe haberse asombrado al ver que el
Infierno, el Purgatorio o el Paraíso – vamos a suponer que le tocó la última región –
no correspondía a su imaginación. Yo creo que Dante no creía, al escribir el poema,
haber hecho otra cosa sino haber encontrado símbolos adecuados para expresar de
un modo sensible los estados de ánimo del pecador, del penitente y del justo’ (Borges
2002: 205–6) [‘For that reason, Flaubert’s comments seem to me apt, that Dante,
upon dying, must have been astonished to see that Hell, Purgatory and Paradise – let
us suppose that he reached this final region – did not correspond to his imagination.
I believe that Dante did not believe, when he wrote his poem, that he was doing
anything other than finding symbols to express in an understandable manner the
states of  the soul of  the sinner, the penitent, and the just’] (my translation).
6 The literary style of  Swedenborg intrigues his readers. Henry James Sr. (father of 
William and Henry) labels him ‘insipid with veracity’ (in Johnson 2003), which is
echoed in his friend Emerson’s comments that Swedenborg ‘remained entirely devoid
of  the whole apparatus of poetic expression’ (Emerson 2003: 54). This is then fur-
ther iterated in William James: ‘But why should he be so prolix and so toneless – so
without emphasis?’ (in Johnson 2003) W. B. Yeats comments: ‘And all this happened
to a man without egotism, without drama, without a sense of  the picturesque, and
who wrote a dry language, lacking fire and emotion’ (1920: 299). Kathleen Raine,
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 53

objective of such a studious and prosaic language, suggesting that it was the
product of an almost mimetic reproduction of  his visionary experiences.

La explicación es obvia. El empleo de cualquier vocablo presupone una experiencia


compartida, de la que el vocablo es el símbolo. Si nos hablan del sabor del café, es
porque ya lo hemos probado, si nos hablan del color amarillo, es porque ya hemos
visto limones, oro, trigo y puestas del sol. Para sugerir la inefable unión del alma del
hombre con la divinidad, los sufíes del Islam se vieron obligados a recurrir a analo-
gías prodigiosas, a imágenes de rosas, de embriaguez o de amor carnal; Swedenborg
pudo renunciar a tales artificios retóricos porque su tema no era el éxtasis del alma
arrebatada y enajenada, sino la puntual descripción de regiones ultraterrenas, pero
precisas. Con el fin de que imaginemos, o empecemos a imaginar, la ínfima hondura
del Infierno, Milton nos habla de No light, but rather darkness visible; Swedenborg
prefiere el rigor y – ¿por qué no decirlo? – las eventuales prolijidades del explorador
o del geógrafo que registra reinos desconocidos. (2005: 154)

[The explanation is obvious. The use of any word whatsoever presupposes a shared
experience, for which the word is the symbol. If someone speaks to us about the f lavor
of cof fee, it is because we have already tasted it; if about the color yellow, because we
have already seen lemons, gold, wheat, and sunsets. To suggest the inef fable union of
man’s soul with the divine being, the Sufis of  Islam found themselves obliged to resort
to prodigious analogies, to images of roses, intoxication, or carnal love. Swedenborg
was able to abstain from this kind of rhetorical artifice because his subject matter
was not the ecstasy of a rapt and fainting soul but, rather, the accurate description of
regions that, though ultra-terrestrial, were clearly defined. In order for us to imagine,
or to begin to imagine, the lowest depth of  hell, John Milton speaks to us of  ‘No
light, but rather darkness visible.’ Swedenborg prefers the rigor and – why not say
it? – possible wordiness of  the explorer or geographer who is recording unknown
kingdoms.] (1995: 7)

Borges admires the intellectual capacity, determinism and exploratory


drive of  Swedenborg – the very qualities that had furnished his abilities
to write tables of mining and metallurgy, design aircraft and submarines,
and create ‘un método personal para fijar las longitudes y un tratado sobre
el diámetro de la luna’ (2005: 153) [‘a personal method of  fixing longitudes

meanwhile, calls his writing ‘stilted and voluminous’ (1995: 54). Borges is part of a
long tradition of critical reception of  Swedenborg’s language.
54 Chapter One

and a treatise on the diameter of  the moon’] (1995: 4).7 These accounts
of  heaven and hell, Borges maintains, were subject to the same degree
of rational scrutiny that Swedenborg employed in his assessment of  the
natural world, and consequently were unadulterated by religious dogma.8
Similarly, Borges emphatically defends Swedenborg against the reader’s
incredulity, stressing that any of  the arguments commonly employed to
discredit Swedenborg – deceit or madness – are invalid. Swedenborg was
not attempting to proselytize, because, Borges asserts, ‘A la manera de
Emerson (Arguments convince nobody) y de Walt Whitman, creía que los
argumentos no persuaden a nadie y que basta enunciar una verdad para
que los interlocutores la acepten’ (2005: 155) [‘Like Emerson and Walt
Whitman, he believed that arguments persuade no one and that stating a
truth is suf ficient for its acceptance by those who hear it’] (1995: 8). Had he
been mad, he argues, ‘no deberíamos a su pluma tenaz la ulterior redacción
de miles de metódicas páginas, que representan una labor de casi treinta
años y que nada tienen que ver con el frenesí’ (2005: 155) [‘we would not
owe to his tenacious pen the thousands of methodical pages he wrote
during the following thirty years or so, pages that have nothing at all to do
with frenzy’] (1995: 8). Herein lies a puzzling feature of  Borges’ admiration
of  Swedenborg. Who, we may ask, is this reader that Borges so stridently
conceptualizes and answers? Why would he seek to defend Swedenborg

7 Conan Doyle (in McNeilly ed., 2005: 105) suggests that Swedenborg ‘was a great
authority upon […] the determination of  latitude’ [2005: 96], whilst Borges asserts:
‘We are indebted to him for a personal method of  fixing longitude’. It would appear,
however, that Conan Doyle mistook ‘latitude’ for ‘longitude’, as the title of  the work
in which Swedenborg established this nagivational principle is the delightfully-
named Försök at finna östra och westra lengden igen, igenom månan, som til the lärdas
ompröfwande framstelles [Attempt to find the East and West Longitude by means of  the
moon. Put forward for the examination of  the learned]. I have not seen any attempt
to correct Conan Doyle’s (or his editor’s) mistake.
8 Yeats also notes the similarity in style between Swedenborg’s scientific journals and
his visionary journals: ‘He considered heaven and hell and God, the angels, the whole
destiny of man, as if  he were sitting before a large table in a Government of fice put-
ting little pieces of mineral ore into small square boxes for an assistant to pack away
in drawers’ (1920: 299).
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 55

(and himself ) against the charge of  ‘la deliberada impostura de quien ha
escrito esas cosas extrañas’ (2005: 154) [‘deliberate imposture on the part
of  the man who wrote such strange things’] (1995: 7) if, having included
Swedenborg in El libro de los seres imaginarios he had already established
his fantastical nature? To address this question, it is first necessary to qualify
the statement made earlier that the distinction between fact and fiction,
reality and imagination, is not present in Borges as writer or reader.
Whilst we may assert, as Borges himself repeatedly does, that his admi-
ration of philosophical and theological discourses lay in their aesthetic
value, this should not impoverish the aesthetic as mere elegance or literary
finery. In the work of  Borges the aesthetic – as related to poesis and imagina-
tion – is a pathway to knowledge. Like Lezama Lima’s vision of poetry, in
which there is a gnosis in the aesthetic, or Blake’s ‘Imagination’ or ‘imagi-
native energy’, which is the true path to the divine, or Corbin’s mundus
imaginalis, in which the secret nature of  the divine is revealed, Borges
places a strong epistemological value to the imagination, the dreamworld,
and the aesthetic.9 The aesthetic is neither simply linguistic nor simply the
sonorous play of words. Arguments themselves can be the index of aesthetic
brilliance, typified by Schopenhauer’s elegant philosophy. Borges professes
an admiration for Blake, emphasizing that ‘Blake asimismo afirmará que
no bastan la inteligencia y la rectitud y que la salvación del hombre exige
un tercer requisito: ser un artista’ (2005: 158) [‘Blake also af firms that the
salvation of man demands a third requirement: that he be an artist’] (1995:
13). Such a sentiment is strikingly akin to Borges’ own ars poetica, exempli-
fied in his calm belief in the persistence of literature: ‘I don’t think of  life as
being pitted against literature. I believe that art is a part of  life’ (Barnstone
1982: 96). Borges paid close attention to the spiritual power that Blake
associated with the aesthetic, and it would seem that this Blakean vision
inspired his relationship to Art and Imagination, borne out in his comment

9 See Mualem 2004. See also Núñez-Faraco (2009: 41): ‘Despite his scepticism and
anti-religious stance, there is in Borges a conspicuous interest in mysticism and in its
revelation of divine truth. […] Borges’s interest in religion, like his fascination with
metaphysics, hinges on an aesthetic perception of  the world’.
56 Chapter One

to Barnstone (1982: 102): ‘We are creating God every time that we attain
beauty’. This moving aphorism could come from the illuminated pages of 
Blake’s Marriage of  Heaven and Hell.
Borges’ relationship to imagination, to fantasy and to the dreamworld
is perhaps the most striking feature of  his poetics, is discussed in the majority
of  his interviews, and is illustrated in so many of  his tales. Yet to approach
the dreamworld epistemologically is an intriguing endeavour which reveals
Borges’ kinship with, amongst others, Blake, Corbin and Jung. Kathleen
Raine, whose essay appears alongside Borges’ in Lawrence’s Testimony to
the Invisible, emphasizes this path of wisdom:

The ultimate knowledge, according to Blake and Swedenborg, is that the universe is
contained in mind – a view to be found also in the Gnostic writings, in the Vedas,
and in other spiritually profound cosmologies of  the East, but long forgotten in the
West with its preoccupation with externality. (Raine 1995: 62)

Blake, it should be remembered, explicitly equated the imaginal world with


the eternal, with the space-time the discarnate soul enters after death: ‘This
world of  the Imagination is the world of  Eternity; it is the divine bosom
into which we shall all go after the death of  the Vegetated body. This World
of  Imagination is Infinite and Eternal, whereas the world of  Generation,
or Vegetation, is Finite & Temporal’ (in Raine 1995: 70). Likewise, innu-
merable passages from Borges testify to the power of dreams to grant the
dreamer knowledge of  further dimensions, landscapes and times. Borges
often alludes to the poetic question of  Coleridge’s f lower retrieved from
the dreamworld, and he contemplates whether Chuang Tzu experienced
being a butterf ly in his dream or whether the butterf ly experienced being
Chuang Tzu. Most well known are the multiple layers of dream creation in
‘Las ruinas circulares’ [‘The Circular Ruins’]. It is therefore striking to note
that Swedenborg’s initiation into the heavenly realm lay in his troubled
dreams. As is so clear from a reading of any of  Borges’ work, the distinctions
between fiction and reality, history and myth, fact and artifice, are hazy:
‘I suppose there is no dif ference between fact and fiction. […] What is the
past but all memory? What is the past but memories that have become
myth?’ (Barnstone 1982: 117), or, to borrow an expression from Lezama
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 57

Lima: ‘no hay nada más real que la imaginación’ (2001: 133) [‘there is noth-
ing more real than the imagination’] (my translation). Furthermore, and
considering the imagination epistemologically, the question of authentic-
ity of experience is problematic. Borges discusses the tale ‘El Congreso’
[‘The Congress’] in the afterword to El Libro de Arena, suggesting that ‘el
fin quiere elevarse, sin duda en vano, a los éxtasis de Chesterton o de John
Bunyan. No he merecido nunca semejante revelación, pero he procurado
soñarla’ (1989: 72) [‘its end tries, doubtless in vain, to match the ecstasies
of  Chesterton and John Bunyan. I have never been worthy of such a rev-
elation, but I managed to dream one up’] (1979: 93). This is paradoxical if
we follow the very f luidity of  fact and fiction, reality and fantasy, present
in Borges. If  he has dreamt one up then he has been worthy of such a rev-
elation. Upon what principles could a distinction be based, if we judge
imagination to be itself experiential? Borges repeatedly emphasizes that
dreaming and artistic – poetic – creativity are aspects of  the same process:

The essential dif ference between the waking experience and the sleeping or dreaming
experience must lie in the fact that the dreaming experience is something that can
be begotten by you, created by you, evolved out of you […] not necessarily in sleep.
When you’re thinking out a poem, there is little dif ference between the fact of  being
asleep and that of  being awake, no? And so they stand for the same thing. If you’re
thinking, if you’re inventing, or if you’re dreaming, then the dream may correspond
to vision or to sleep. That hardly matters. (Barnstone 1982: 29)

Surely one of  the most abiding sensations delivered to the reader of  Borges
is that reality is fictional and fiction is real. Is he not declaring at every stage,
therefore, that we really are in no position to judge so firmly between an
event of  the imagination and one of empirical experience? Borges, for
example, makes no distinction between the experience of reading and the
experience of  travelling. That is to say, the textual and the meta-textual are
epistemologically no dif ferent. He declares to Richard Burgin:

I think of reading a book as no less an experience than traveling or falling in love. I


think that reading Berkeley or Shaw or Emerson, those are quite as real experiences
to me as seeing London, for example. Of course, I saw London through Dickens and
through Chesterton and through Stevenson, no? Many people are apt to think of
real life on the one side, that means toothache, headache, traveling and so on, and
58 Chapter One

then you have on the other side, you have imaginary life and fancy and that means
the arts. But I don’t think that that distinction holds water. I think that everything
is a part of  life. (Burgin 1998: 14)

Bioy Casares and Borges dined together regularly, whilst discussing lit-
erature, poetry and metaphysics. One conversation could be recorded by
Borges in a recollection; another could be recorded at the beginning of 
‘Tlön, Uqbar, Orbis Tertius’. It would be a step into a rigid binary pattern
of  thinking to attempt to distinguish between a factual and a fictional
conversation between these two. Both are fantastic, both are textual, both
are factual and fictional at the same time. ‘I don’t see how things can be
unreal’ Borges opined. ‘I don’t see any valid reason why Hamlet, for exam-
ple, should be less real than Lloyd George’ (Burgin 1998: 77), ‘or why
Macbeth should be less real than today’s newspaper’ (Burgin 1998: 85). It
is abidingly evident, therefore, that in all matters of  human expression, and
in whichever system he was contemplating – whether fantastical, poeti-
cal, mythological, theological, philosophical, or political – experience is
experience whether it derives from physical or imaginal travel. Memory is
creative and thus a fiction, and yet the experience of  fiction is tangible and
real. Why, therefore, does Borges draw such a firm distinction between
the real experiences of  Swedenborg and the unreal or fictional experiences
of  Dante? In order to address this question, it is important to focus on
Borges’ assessment of other writers of mystical vision and eschatology,
and in particular, on the presence of doctrine that Borges could perceive
looming over them.
Borges reviewed Leslie Weatherhead’s After Death, and he damns
Weatherhead for being a mediocre and almost non-existent writer, for
being ‘estimulatado por lecturas piadosas’ [‘stimulated by pious readings’]
and for making unconvincing ‘conjeturas semiteosóficas’ (1974: 282) [‘semi-
theosophical conjectures’] (2000: 255–6). Weatherhead’s poor writing
status betrays an aesthetic poverty that is not only clearly indicative of a
wholly unappealing metaphysical vision, but is, furthermore, inauthentic,
derivative, and, importantly, non-experiential. At the beginning of  his pug-
nacious review, Borges reasserts the famous declaration of  the narrator of 
‘Tlön’, that metaphysics is but another branch of  fantastic literature. Here
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 59

he embellishes this with a mention of  his own book of  fantastic literature,
and his guilty omission of  the masters of  the fantastic genre: ‘Parménides,
Platón, Juan Escoto Erígena, Alberto Magno, Spinoza, Leibniz, Kant,
Francis Bradley’ (1974: 280) [‘Parmenides, Plato, John Scotus Erigena,
Albertus Magnus, Spinoza, Leibniz, Kant, Francis Bradley’] (2000: 255).
He then, as if  to confirm his agnostic credentials, compares the fantastic
with the religious, mocking the theological discourse that Weatherhead
presents:

En efecto, ¿qué son los prodigios de Wells o de Edgar Allan Poe – una f lor que nos llega
del porvenir, un muerto sometido a la hipnosis – confrontados con la invención de
Dios, con la teoría laboriosa de un ser que de algún modo es tres y que solitariamente
perdura fuera del tiempo? ¿Qué es la piedra bezoar ante la armonía preestablecida,
quién es el unicornio ante la Trinidad, quién es Lucio Apuleyo ante los multiplica-
dores de Buddhas del Gran Vehículo, qué son todas las noches de Shahrazad junto
a un argumento de Berkeley? He venerado la gradual invención de Dios; también el
Infierno y el Cielo (una remuneración inmortal, un castigo inmortal) son admirables
y curiosos designios de la imaginación de los hombres. (1974: 280–1)

[What, in fact, are the wonders of  Wells or Edgar Allan Poe – a f lower that visits
us from the future, a dead man under hypnosis – in comparison to the invention
of  God, the labored theory of a being who in some way is three and who endures
alone outside of  time? What is the bezoar stone to pre-established harmony, what
is the unicorn to the Trinity, who is Lucius Apuleius to the multipliers of  Buddhas
of  the Greater Vehicle, what are all the nights of  Scheherazade next to an argument
by Berkeley? I have worshiped the gradual invention of  God; Heaven and Hell (an
immortal punishment, an immortal reward) are also admirable and curious designs
of man’s imagination.] (2000: 255)

A beautiful Borgesian conundrum is thus established. Heaven and hell


derive from imagination, and yet they are nevertheless real. Herein lie his
motives for including Swedenborg’s angels and devils in El libro de los seres
imaginarios yet all the while proclaiming the authenticity of  Swedenborg’s
visions.10 How real are the angels, and can we detect in Borges any attempt –

10 One might assume that Borges could well have included a passage from Swedenborg
in his Extraordinary Tales (1973). As it is, he and Bioy Casares include a brief  text
60 Chapter One

however futile it may be – to separate an empirical angel somehow extrin-


sic to human imagination from an intrinsic, imaginative angel? Borges’
sister, Norah, a painter whose impact on Borges’ writing career has now
been fairly deeply studied, painted angels (indeed, one of  her angel paint-
ings hung in the parlour of  Borges’ apartment on Belgrano [Burgin 1998:
100]), and allegedly maintained conversations with angels as a child. Borges
develops a strikingly Jungian approach to angels, in that they are creatures
of  the imagination, but that consequently they are real. They develop the
particular substance of  Jung’s archetypal beings, in that they belong to the
psyche, but that the realm of  the psyche extends into transpersonal, time-
less dimensions, beyond the control of  the individual ego, and therefore
operational, as it were, extrinsic to the individual.11 For Borges, angels, for
example, are one more creation of  the imagination, but whose persistence
in the human imagination grants them some undefined ontological status.
A 1926 essay entitled ‘A History of  Angels’ describes this perspective.

Ya estamos orillando el casi milagro que es la verdadera motivación de este escrito: lo


que podríamos denominar la supervivencia del ángel. La imaginación de los hombres
ha figurado tandas de monstruos (tritones, hipogrifos, quimeras, serpientes de mar,
unicornios, diablos, dragones, lobizones, cíclopes, faunos, basiliscos, semidioses, levia-
tanes y otros que son caterva) y todos ellos han desaparecido, salvo los ángeles. ¿Qué
verso de hoy se atrevería a mentar la fénix o a ser paseo de un centauro? Ninguno;
pero a cualquier poesía, por moderna que sea, no le desplace ser nidal de ángeles y
resplandecerse con ellos. Yo me los imagino siempre al anochecer, en la tardecita de los
arrabales o de los descampados, en ese largo y quieto instante en que se van quedando
solas las cosas a espaldas del ocaso y en que los colores distintos parecen recuerdos o
presentimientos de otros colores. No hay que gastarlos mucho a los ángeles; son las
divinidades últimas que hospedamos y a lo mejor se vuelan. (1994: 67)

from ‘The False Swedenborg’ of 1873. I have not been able to locate this source. It
might well be one of  their many invented texts.
11 Philemon, for example, was both ‘real’ and ‘psychological’ for Jung. The distinction
is, ultimately, irrelevant. It must also be noted that Borges was a sympathetic reader
of  Jung: ‘I’ve always been a great reader of  Jung’ (Burgin 1969: 109). He also makes
reference to Jung in ‘Nathaniel Hawthorne’ (1974: 670), and to Jung’s Psychologie und
alchemie in ‘Kafka y sus precursores’ (1974: 710) and in El libro de los seres imaginarios.
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 61

[Here we arrive at the near miracle that is the true motive for this writing: what we
might call the survival of  the angel. The human imagination has pictured a horde
of monsters (tritons, hippogrif fs, chimeras, sea serpents, unicorns, devils, dragons,
werewolves, cyclopes, fauns, basilisks, demigods, leviathans, and a legion of others)
and all have disappeared, except angels. Today, what line of poetry would dare allude
to the phoenix or make itself  the promenade of a centaur? None; but no poetry,
however modern, is unhappy to be a nest of angels and to shine brightly with them.
I always imagine them at nightfall, in the dusk of a slum or a vacant lot, in that long,
quiet moment when things are gradually left alone, with their backs to the sunset,
and when colors are like memories or premonitions of other colors. We must not be
too prodigal with our angels; they are the last divinities we harbor, and they might
f ly away.] (2000: 19)12

It is interesting to note that all the monsters he mentions in this passage


later appear in El libro de los seres imaginarios, yet he awards a dif ferent
degree of compassion to angels, derived perhaps from his sister’s relation-
ship with them. The hard-lined Kantian logic present in the 1922 essay ‘La
nadería de la personalidad’ appears to be able to dismiss angels as creatures
of  the imagination, yet unlike Kant, this approach would nevertheless
permit such imaginary beings to be more real than simple illusions and,
furthermore, to be worthy of philosophical speculation.
And yet the paradox runs deeper: he praises Swedenborg’s visions yet
derides Weatherhead’s on the assumption that the former’s are genuine
whilst the latter’s are merely conforming to dogmatic theology. Borges’
assertion of authenticity is itself a clear ref lection of  his own ‘free-think-
ing’ or ‘agnostic’ (both terms which he regularly employs) position. His
mistrust of  Christian doctrine was such that Carlos Cortínez observes it
even manifesting in a distrust of  the treasured dreamworld, when Borges’

12 Borges was notoriously scathing of  the book in which this essay appeared – El
tamaño de mi esperanza: ‘I am thoroughly ashamed of  that book […] I try to forget
it. A very poor book’ (Barnstone 1982: 82). The legend (that Borges promoted) was
that he gathered any copies of  the book he could find and burned them. He also,
though, says the same about Inquisiciones (Barnstone 1982: 110). One cannot help
feeling that Borges is actually a canny promoter of  his own works; by claiming in
countless interviews that both Tamaño and Inquisiciones should not be read, he is
actually encouraging people to read them.
62 Chapter One

mother claims that her dead father had returned to her in a dream to
assure her of  the existence of  God.13 He unpicks the nature of vision of 
Swedenborg, and opens (though does not explore) a thorny question that
arises regularly in the nebulous scholarship of mysticism: are experiences
unique to the individual or are they universal? Are experiences exceptional
or culturally conditioned? Or, put in a dif ferent way, did Teresa de Ávila
encounter Christ, or did she encounter the same ‘source’ or ‘power’ that
non-Christian mystics might encounter, but that she interpreted this power
as Christ? Yeats, for example, attributes a strong cultural inf luence upon
Swedenborg’s own appreciation of  the angelic realm: ‘Swedenborg because
he belongs to an eighteenth century not yet touched by the romantic revival
feels horror amid rocky uninhabited places, and so believes that the evil are
in such places while the good are amid smooth grass and garden walks and
the clear sunlight of  Claude Lorraine’ (1920: 303), and he maintains that

13 ‘En la entrevista con Carlos Cortínez encontramos, por desgracia, muy sintetizada,
aquella famosa conversación que tuvieron Borges con su madre acerca de Dios. “No
recuerdo cómo la conversación derivó hacia las creencias religiosas de cada cual.
Entonces ella me declaró su fe con una simplicidad no exenta de dramatismo … me
contó un sueño que ella tuvo cuando murió su padre: él se le acercaba, muy fatigado,
y le aseguraba, de un modo que no ha podido olvidar, que Dios existe. … Dos o tres
veces fue interrumpido por su hijo que oponía razones de su escepticismo. Era para-
dójico oír a Borges desconfiar de la seriedad de los sueños, para no dejarse convencer
por la belleza del relato de su madre. En una de esas, ella sin molestarse pero con
la superioridad del creyente lo hizo callar: – ¡Deja Georgie, tú no piensas en estas
cosas …!”’ (Romero 1977: 492)
[‘In the interview with Carlos Cortínez we regretfully find that famous conversation
that Borges had with his mother about God: “I don’t remember how the conversation
moved towards their religious beliefs. She declared to me her faith with a simplicity
not lacking drama … she told me about a dream she had when her father died: he,
exhausted, had approached her and had assured her in a way she could not forget that
God exists. … Two or three times she was interrupted by her son who put forward
reasons for his scepticism. It was paradoxical to hear Borges mistrust the serious-
ness of dreams, in order not to allow himself  to be convinced by the beauty of  his
mother’s tale. On one of  those interruptions she calmly and with the superiority of
a believer made him silent: Enough Georgie! You don’t believe in such matters!”’]
(my translation).
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 63

Blake’s outlandish mythologies derived from the absence of established


doctrine.14 Raine addresses this perennial question when considering the
inf luence of  Swedenborg on Blake: ‘it may be that we also have to conclude
that those gifted with the clear vision of  the imaginal world are in essential
agreement because describing the same reality’ (Raine 1995: 67). Borges
brushes aside the implications of specific doctrinal mystical experiences:
‘Swedenborg, como Spinoza o Francis Bacon, fue un pensador por cuenta
propia y que cometió un incómodo error cuando resolvió ajustar sus ideas
al marco de los dos Testamentos’ (2005: 155) [‘Swedenborg, like Spinoza
or Francis Bacon, was a thinker in his own right who made an awkward
mistake when he decided to adapt his ideas to the framework of  the two
Testaments’] (1995: 9).15 Quite clearly, for Borges, the aesthetic power of 

14 ‘He was a man crying out for a mythology, and trying to make one because he could
not find one to his hand. Had he been a Catholic of  Dante’s time he would have
been well content with Mary and the angels; or had he been a scholar of our time he
would have taken his symbols where Wagner took his, from Norse mythology’ (1903:
174). Borges, it must be recalled, was often reserved about Blake’s complex mytholo-
gies, claiming: ‘La obra de Blake es una obra de lectura extraordinariamente difícil,
ya que Blake había creado un sistema teológico, pero para exponerlo, se le ocurrió
inventar una mitología sobre cuyo sentido no están de acuerdo los comentadores’
(Borges 2002: 215) [‘The work of  Blake is extraordinarily dif ficult to read, seeing
that Blake created a theological system, but that, in order to express it, it occurred
to him to invent a mythology that none of  the commentators can agree upon’] (my
translation). He also at one stage calls Blake ‘generally long-winded and ponderous’
(Barnstone 1982: 26), and he states that one would need a dictionary of  Blake to
understand Blake.
15 This is, indeed, a pervasive question. Robert Moss suggests that Swedenborg’s religious
upbringing was contributory towards his visions: ‘These encounters [with the dead]
also gave him a first-hand understanding of  the conditions of  the afterlife. Previously,
his religious faith had convinced him that the spirit survives physical death. Now he
could begin to study how it survives’ (1998: 188). Colin Wilson, meanwhile, pursues
a line similar to that of  Yeats and Borges: ‘[Swedenborg] lived in a religious age; his
father was a bishop; he had studied the Bible since childhood. It was, therefore, natural
that his visions expressed themselves in terms of  the Bible. If  he had been brought
up on the works of  Shakespeare or Dante, no doubt his ideas would have expressed
themselves in the form of gigantic commentaries on Shakespeare’s tragedies or the
Divine Comedy. The chief obstacle to the modern understanding of  Swedenborg is
64 Chapter One

Swedenborg lay in an authentic experience unmediated by doctrine aside


from in a few infelicitous moments and despite its Christian clothing,
whereas the ‘mediocre’ Weatherhead simply reproduced established dogma.
In a similar fashion, Barnstone asks Borges about the Spanish mystics, and
about his own mystical experiences:

Barnstone: You’ve been immersed in the writings of  the Gnostics, the mystics,
in the Kabbalah, the Book of  Splendor.
Borges: I’ve done my best, but I am very ignorant.
Barnstone: You have been interested in the mystics –
Borges: At the same time I am no mystic myself.
Barnstone: I imagine that you would consider the voyage of  the mystics a true
experience but a secular one. Could you comment on the mystical
experience in other writing, in Fray Luis de León …
Borges: I wonder if  Fray Luis de León had any mystical experience. I should
say not. When I talk of mystics, I think of  Swedenborg, Angelus
Silesius, and the Persians also. Not the Spaniards. I don’t think they
had any mystical experiences.
Barnstone: John of  the Cross?
Borges: I think that Saint John of  the Cross was following the pattern of  the
Song of  Songs. And that’s that. I suppose he never had any actual
experience. In my life I only had two mystical experiences and I can’t
tell them because what happened is not to be put in words, since
words, after all, stand for a shared experience. And if you have not
had the experience you can’t share it – as if you were to talk about
the taste of cof fee and had never tried cof fee. Twice in my life I had
a feeling, a feeling rather agreeable than otherwise. It was astonish-
ing, astounding. I was overwhelmed, taken aback. I had the feeling
of  living not in time but outside time. It may have been a minute or
so, it may have been longer. […] Somehow the feeling came over me
that I was living beyond time, and I did my best to capture it, but it
came and went. I wrote poems about it, but they are normal poems
and do not tell the experience. I cannot tell it to you, since I cannot
retell it to myself, but I had that experience, and I had it twice over,
and maybe it will be granted me to have it one more time before I
die. (Barnstone 1982: 10–11)

that few of us can take the Bible for granted in the way that our great-grandfathers
did. This is a sad ref lection on the modern age’ (1995: 100).
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 65

Again, his dismissal of  ‘the Spaniards’ lies in his sense of  their doctrinal
adherence. Whilst Borges admires John of  the Cross’s poetic craft, he nev-
ertheless perceives the same sense of inauthenticity of experience that he
does in Weatherhead. John of  the Cross was merely ‘following the pattern
of  the Song of  Songs’ in the same fashion that Weatherhead was merely
parroting ‘conjeturas semiteosóficas’ (1974: 282). Furthermore, he derides
Pascal for doctrinal adherence claiming that his derision of  Pascal was
itself derived from Swedenborg: ‘No es [Pascal] un místico; pertenece
a aquellos cristianos denunciados por Swedenborg, que suponen que el
cielo es un galardón y el infierno un castigo y que, habituados a la medi-
tación melancólica, no saben hablar con los ángeles’ (1974: 704) [‘He is
not a mystic; he belongs to those Christians, denounced by Swedenborg,
who suppose that heaven is a reward and hell a punishment and who,
accustomed to melancholy meditation, do not know how to speak with
the angels’] (1964: 99). Borges’ own mystical experiences, as he describes,
were unique and personal, purportedly uninspired by textual sources, and
consequently inexpressible. Here lies the nub of  the paradox. Whilst we
are all the products of our inf luences, and whilst he repeatedly maintains
that all great literature is merely the re-articulation of a few perennial
symbols, nevertheless, for Borges the mystical experience by necessity must
be somehow free of inf luence in order to shine with authenticity. It is my
hypothesis that this opinion of authenticity is a smokescreen, and that what
really is at stake is not a metaphysical judgment about the true substance
and structure of  heaven, nor of  the ontology of angelic beings. Rather, it
is Borges’ inveterate iconoclasm, his mistrust of doctrine, and his love of 
heterodoxy, heretics, heresy and heresiarchs.
Doctrine, and its constellation as dogma, was, for Borges a denial of
individual will and creative liberty. Political doctrine merely entertains
people, or, in the case of  Juan and Evita Perón, only entertains the igno-
rant.16 In the case of  Nazism, its appeal can lead them to outrageous acts

16 See ‘L’illusion Comique’ (Borges 2000a: 409–11).


66 Chapter One

of  brutality.17 Philosophical doctrine, he argues, ‘is really mere guesswork’


(Barnstone 1982: 111). Theological doctrine, especially if allied to blind
faith, naturally and reasonably, leads to great intolerance.18 Borges even
declares that his abiding love for Dante and for the Divine Comedy derives
from its aesthetics in spite of  the theology: ‘Lo que menos me ha interesado
en La divina comedia es el valor religioso. Es decir, me han interesado los
personajes […] sus destinos, pero todo el concepto religioso, la idea de
premios y de castigos, es una idea que no he entendido nunca’ (Sorrentino
2001: 144) [‘What least interests me in The Divine Comedy is the religious
value. That’s to say, I am interested in the characters […] their destinies, but
all the religious dimension, the idea of reward and punishment, is an idea
that I have never understood’] (my translation). Swedenborg, conversely
in Borges’ view, underwent journeys into imaginal landscapes of  heavens
and hells and was so untouched by the pressure of doctrinal adherence that
he risked being branded a heretic.
Whilst observing the doctrinal geometry of  Dante’s Divine Comedy,
it becomes clear that a central thrust of  Borges’ veneration for Dante lies,
conversely, in his subtle heterodox, even heretical, dimensions. In the Nueve
ensayos dantescos (1989: 339–72), Borges elaborates the degree to which
Dante pushes the boundaries of orthodoxy to an alarming degree. There are
many facets to this reading of Dante, and many areas that Borges investigates

17 Recall the oft-quoted statement of  the narrator of  Tlön ‘Hace diez años bastaba
cualquier simetría con apariencia de orden – el materialismo dialéctico, el antisem-
itismo, el nazismo – para embelesar a los hombres. ¿Cómo no someterse a Tlön, a la
minuciosa y vasta evidencia de un planeta ordenado? Inútil responder que la realidad
también está ordenada’ (1974: 442) [‘Ten years ago, any symmetrical system what-
soever which gave the appearance of order – dialectical materialism, anti-Semitism,
Nazism – was enough to fascinate men. Why not fall under the spell of  Tlön and
submit to the minute and vast evidence of an ordered planet? Useless to reply that
reality, too is ordered’] (1976: 34).
18 ‘No church – whether Catholic or Protestant – has ever been tolerant, nor is there
any reason for them to be tolerant. If  I believe I am in possession of  the truth there
is no reason for me to be tolerant of  those who are risking their own salvation by
holding erroneous beliefs. On the contrary, it’s my duty to persecute them’ (Burgin
1998: 73–4).
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 67

are common to exegetic commentaries on the Comedy; other areas are perti-
nent, so it would appear, only to Borges. Firstly, Borges identifies in almost
every passage that he composed on Dante the essential motivation behind
Dante’s vast poetic cycle: the union not with the godhead but with Beatrice.

Retengamos un hecho incontrovertible, un solo hecho humildísimo: la escena ha


sido imaginada por Dante. Para nosotros, es muy real; para él, lo fue menos. (La
realidad, para él, era que primero la vida y después la muerte le habían arrebatado a
Beatriz). Ausente para siempre de Beatriz, solo y quizá humillado, imaginó la escena
para imaginar que estaba con ella. Desdichadamente para él, felizmente para los siglos
que lo leerían, la conciencia de que el encuentro era imaginario deformó la visión.
De ahí las circunstancias atroces, tanto más infernales, claro está, por ocurrir en el
empíreo la desaparición de Beatriz, el anciano que toma su lugar, su brusca elevación
a la Rosa, la fugacidad de la sonrisa y de la mirada, el desvío eterno del rostro. En las
palabras se trasluce el horror: come parea se refiere a lontana pero contamina a sorrise
y así Longfellow pudo traducir en su versión de 1867:
   Thus I implored; and she, so far away,
   Smiled as it seemed, and looked once more at me …
También eterna parece contaminar a si tornò. (1989: 374)

[We must keep one incontrovertible fact in mind, a single, humble fact: the scene was
imagined by Dante. For us, it is very real; for him, it was less so. (The reality, for him,
was that first life and then death had taken Beatrice from him.) Forever absent from
Beatrice, alone and perhaps humiliated, he imagined the scene in order to imagine
he was with her. Unhappily for him, happily for the centuries that would read him,
his consciousness that the meeting was imaginary distorted the vision. Hence the
appalling circumstances, all the more infernal for taking place in the empyrean: the
disappearance of  Beatrice, the elder who replaces her, her abrupt elevation to the
Rose, the f leetingness of  her glance and smile, the eternal turning away of  the face.
The horror shows through in the words: come parea refers to lontana but contaminates
sorrise, and therefore Longfellow could translate, in his 1867 version:
   Thus I implored; and she, so far away,
   Smiled as it seemed, and looked once more at me …
And eternal seems to contaminate si tornò.] (2000: 304–5)19

19 Enamorarse es crear una religión cuyo dios es falible. Que Dante profesó por Beatriz
una adoración idolátrica es una verdad que no cabe contradecir; que ella una vez se
burló de él y otra lo desairó son hechos que registra la Vita nuova. Hay quien man-
tiene que esos hechos son imágenes de otros; ello, a ser así, reforzaría aún más nuestra
68 Chapter One

This immediately evokes a pathetic quality to the cycle that betrays Dante’s
earthly, human love over the love of  the divine.
Secondly, this aspect cannot be separated from the equally pathetic
envy and regret that Borges identifies in Dante’s portrayal of  the lovers
Paola and Francesco:

Infinitamente existió Beatriz para Dante; Dante, muy poco, tal vez nada, para Beatriz;
todos nosotros propendemos, por piedad, por veneración a olvidar esa lastimosa

certidumbre de un amor desdichado y supersticioso. Dante, muerta Beatriz, perdida


para siempre Beatriz, jugó con la ficción de encontrarla, para mitigar su tristeza;
yo tengo para mí que edificó la triple arquitectura de su poema para intercalar ese
encuentro. Le ocurrió entonces lo que suele ocurrir en los sueños, manchándolo de
tristes estorbos. Tal fue el caso de Dante. Negado para siempre por Beatriz, soñó con
Beatriz, pero la soñó severísima, pero la soñó inaccesible, pero la soñó en un carro
tirado por un león que era un pájaro y que era todo pájaro o todo león cuando los
ojos de Beatriz lo esperaban (Purgatorio XXXI, 121). Tales hechos pueden prefigurar
una pesadilla; ésta se fija y se dilata en el otro canto. Beatriz desaparece; un águila,
una zorra y un dragón atacan el carro; las ruedas y el timón se cubren de plumas; el
carro, entonces, echa siete cabezas (Transformato così’l dificio santo/mise fuor teste …);
un gigante y una ramera usurpan el lugar de Beatriz. (1989: 371)
[‘To fall in love is to create a religion with a fallible god. That Dante professed an
idolatrous adoration for Beatrice is a truth that cannot be contradicted; that she
once mocked and on another occasion snubbed him are facts registered in the Vita
nuova. Some would maintain that these facts are the images of others; if so, this would
further reinforce our certainty of an unhappy and superstitious love. With Beatrice
dead, lost forever, Dante, to assuage his sorrow, played with the fiction of meeting
her again. It is my belief  that he constructed the triple architecture of  his poem in
order to insert this encounter into it. What then happened is what often happens in
dreams: they are stained by sad obstructions. Such was Dante’s case. Forever denied
Beatrice, he dreamed of  Beatrice, but dreamed her as terribly severe, dreamed her as
inaccessible, dreamed her in a chariot pulled by a lion that was a bird and that was
all bird or all lion while Beatrice’s eyes were awaiting him (Purgatorio XXXI, 121).
Such images can prefigure a nightmare; and it is a nightmare that begins here and
will expand in the next canto. Beatrice disappears; an eagle, a she-fox, and a dragon
attack the chariot, and its wheels and body grow feathers: the chariot then sprouts
seven heads (“Transformato così’l dificio santo/mise fuor teste” {Thus transformed, the
holy structure put forth heads upon its parts}); a giant and a harlot usurp Beatrice’s
place’] (2000a: 300–1).
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 69

discordia inolvidable para Dante. Leo y releo los azares de su ilusorio encuentro y
pienso en dos amantes que el Alighieri soñó en el huracán del segundo círculo y que
son emblemas oscuros, aunque él no lo entendiera o no lo quisiera, de esa dicha que
no logró. Pienso en Francesca y en Paolo, unidos para siempre en su Infierno (Questi,
che mai da me non fia diviso …) Con espantoso amor, con ansiedad, con admiración,
con envidia. (1989: 371).

[Beatrice existed infinitely for Dante. Dante very little, perhaps not at all for Beatrice.
All of us tend to forget, out of pity, out of veneration, this grievous discord which
for Dante was unforgettable. Reading and rereading the vicissitudes of  his illusory
meeting, I think of  the two lovers that Alighieri dreamed in the hurricane of  the
second circle and who, whether or not he understood or wanted them to be, were
obscure emblems of  the joy he did not attain. I think of  Paolo and Francesca, forever
united in their Inferno: ‘questi, che mai da me non fia diviso’ (this one, who never
shall be parted from me). With appalling love, with anxiety, with admiration, with
envy.] (2000: 300–1)20

Thirdly, Borges writes with passion of  the abiding love and respect
that Dante bore for Virgil, and for Homer, Horace, Ovid and Lucan, and
the deep sadness and regret that Dante experienced in acknowledging their
banishment to the nobile castello.

Dante knows that Virgil is a damned soul, and the very moment that Virgil tells
him that he will not be able to accompany him beyond purgatory, Dante feels that
Virgil will always be an inhabitant of  that ‘nobile castello’ where the great shadows of 
the great men of antiquity dwell, those that through unavoidable ignorance did not
accept or could not reach the word of  Christ. […] Dante salutes him with the highest
epithets and speaks of  the great love and the long study to which Virgil’s writings

20 He also reiterates this in Siete noches: ‘esos dos réprobos están juntos, no pueden
hablarse, giran en el negro remolino sin ninguna esperanza, ni siquiera nos dice
Dante la esperanza de que los sufrimientos cesen, pero están juntos. Cuando ella
habla, usa el nosotros: habla por los dos, otra forma de estar juntos. Están juntos para
la eternidad, comparten el Infierno y eso para Dante tiene que haber sido una suerte
de Paraíso’ (1989: 216) [‘They cannot speak to each other, they turn in the black
whirlwind without hope, yet they are together. When she speaks, she says “we,”
speaking for the two of  them, another form of  being together. They are together for
eternity; they share Hell – and that, for Dante, must have been a kind of  Paradise’]
(1984: 18).
70 Chapter One

have led him, and of  their relationship which has always been constant. But Virgil
is sad since he knows that he is condemned to the ‘nobile castello,’ far from salvation
and full of  God’s absence; Dante, on the other hand, will see God, he will be allowed
to, and he will also be allowed to understand the universe. (Alifano 1984: 97)21

Fourthly, in composing the cycle, and thus acting as judge in con-


demning Virgil to the absence of  God, Dante, in Borges’ eyes, was deeply
unsettled at his own god-like status.

21 ‘En el caso de Dante, el procedimiento es más delicado. No es exactamente un con-


traste, aunque tenemos la actitud filial: Dante viene a ser un hijo de Virgilio y al mismo
tiempo es superior a Virgilio porque se cree salvado. Cree que merecerá la gracia o
que la ha merecido, ya que le ha sido dada la visión. En cambio, desde el comienzo
del Infierno sabe que Virgilio es un alma perdida, un réprobo; cuando Virgilio le
dice que no podrá acompañarlo más allá del Purgatorio, siente que el latino será para
siempre un habitante del terrible nobile castello donde están las grandes sombras de los
grandes muertos de la Antigüedad, los que por ignorancia invencible no alcanzaron
la palabra de Cristo. En ese mismo momento, Dante dice: Tu, duca; tu, signore; tu,
maestro … Para cubrir ese momento, Dante lo saluda con palabras magníficas y habla
del largo estudio y del gran amor que le han hecho buscar su volumen y siempre se
mantiene esa relación entre los dos. Esa figura esencialmente triste de Virgilio, que
se sabe condenado a habitar para siempre en el nobile castello lleno de la ausencia de
Dios … En cambio, a Dante le será permitido ver a Dios, le será permitido comprender
el universo’ (1989: 213).
[‘In the case of  Dante, the matter is more delicate. It is not exactly a contrast, although
there is a filial relationship. Dante comes to be the son of  Virgil, yet at the same time
he is superior to Virgil for he believes he will be saved, since he has been given the
vision. But he knows, from the beginning, that Virgil is a lost soul, a reprobate. When
Virgil tells him that he cannot accompany him beyond Purgatory, he knows that
the Latin poet will always inhabit the terrible nobile castello with the great shades of 
Antiquity, those who never heard the word of  Christ. At that moment, Dante hails
him with magnificent words: “Tu, duca; tu, signore; tu, maestro …” He speaks of  the
great labor and of  the great love with which his work has been studied, and this
relation is always maintained between the two. But Virgil is essentially a sad figure
who knows he is forever condemned to that castle filled with the absence of  God.
Dante, however, will be permitted to see God; he will be permitted to understand
the universe’] (1984: 14).
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 71

Otra razón, de tipo técnico, explica la dureza y la crueldad de que Dante ha sido
acusado. La noción panteísta de un Dios que también es el universo, de un Dios
que es cada una de sus criaturas y el destino de esas criaturas, es quizá una herejía y
un error si la aplicamos a la realidad, pero es indiscutible en su aplicación al poeta y
a su obra. El poeta es cada uno de los hombres de su mundo ficticio, es cada soplo y
cada pormenor. Una de sus tareas, no la más fácil, es ocultar o disimular esa omni-
presencia. El problema era singularmente arduo en el caso de Dante, obligado por
el carácter de su poema a adjudicar la gloria o la perdición, sin que pudieran advertir
los lectores que la Justicia que emitía los fallos era, en último término, él mismo. Para
conseguir ese fin, se incluyó como personaje de la Comedia, e hizo que sus reacciones
no coincidieran, o sólo coincidieran alguna vez en el caso de Filippo Argenti, o en
el de Judas, con las decisiones divinas. (1989: 346)

[There is a technical explanation for the hardheartedness and cruelty of which Dante
has been accused. The pantheistic idea of a god who is also the universe, a god who
is every one of  his creatures and the destiny of  those creatures, may be a heresy and
an error if we apply it to reality, but it is indisputable when applied to the poet and
his work. The poet is each one of  the men in his fictive world, he is every breath and
every detail. One of  his tasks, and not the easiest of  them, is to hide or disguise this
omnipresence. The problem was particularly burdensome in Dante’s case, for he was
forced by the nature of  his poem to mete out glory or damnation, but in such a way as
to keep his readers from noticing that the Justice handing down these sentences was,
in the final analysis, he himself. To achieve this, he included himself as a character in
the Commedia, and made his own reactions contrast or only rarely coincide – in the
case of  Filippo Argenti, or in that of  Judas – with the divine decisions.] (2000: 270)

Lastly, Borges acknowledges with great respect that Dante himself was
torn between the need (and desire) to adhere to orthodoxy, and the desire
to operate with poetic, aesthetic and, indeed, metaphysical freedom. In
almost all the nine Dantesque essays, and in Siete noches, Borges describes
the tension apparent in Dante between adhering to doctrine and expressing
his own artistic vision. He talks of  Dante’s ‘own invention’ of  the limbo
for the pre-Christian elevated souls (the Classical poets):

Para mitigar el horror de una época adversa, el poeta buscó refugio en la gran memoria
romana. Quiso honrarla en su libro, pero no pudo entender – la observación per-
tenece a Guido Vitali – que insistir demasiado sobre el mundo clásico no convenía
a sus propósitos doctrinales. Dante no podía, contra la Fe, salvar a sus héroes; los
pensó en un Infierno negativo, privados de la vista y posesión de Dios en el cielo, y
72 Chapter One

se apiadó de su misterioso destino. […] En la invención y ejecución de este canto IV


Dante urdió una serie de circunstancias, alguna de índole teológica. Devoto lector
de la Eneida, imaginó a los muertos en el Elíseo, o en una variación medieval de esos
campos dichosos. […] Urgido por razones dogmáticas, debió situar en el Infierno a su
noble castillo. (1989: 348)

[To allay the horror of an adverse era, the poet sought refuge in the great memory of 
Rome. He wished to honor it in his book, but could not help understanding – the
observation is Guido Vitali’s – that too great an insistence on the classical world did
not accord well with his doctrinal aims. Dante, who could not go against the Faith
to save his heroes, envisioned them in a negative Hell, denied the sight and posses-
sion of  God in heaven, and took pity on their mysterious fate. […] In the invention
and execution of  Canto IV, Dante plotted out a series of circumstances, some of 
them theological in nature. A devout reader of  the Aeneid, he imagined the dead
in the Elysium or in a medieval variant of  those glad fields. […] For pressing reasons
of dogma, Dante had to situate his noble castle in Hell.] (2000: 274 italics mine)

These central arguments of  Borges’ appreciation of  Dante reveal a


similar element of disdain for the doctrinal that we see manifest in his
dismissal of  the visions of  St John of  the Cross and of  the eschatology of 
Weatherhead. Beyond the beauty of  the couplets, Borges’ aesthetic apprecia-
tion of  Dante lay, precisely, in this tension between doctrine and original-
ity. We can see, therefore, that whilst originality is a quality rarely prized
elsewhere in Borges, viz his inclusion of other author’s tales in his tales,
his recognition that the ‘Las ruinas circulares’ is a rewriting of  ‘El Golem’,
his admission in the prologue to El informe de Brodie [Dr Brodie’s Report]
that ‘unos pocos argumentos me han hostigado a lo largo del tiempo; soy
decididamente monótono’ (1974: 1022) [‘A mere handful of arguments
have haunted me all these years; I am decidedly monotonous’] (2006: 20),
and his assertion that all great literature is merely the repetition of certain
perennial symbols within shifting cultural contexts; nevertheless, in mat-
ters of metaphysics and mysticism, originality is a treasured value due to
its resistance to doctrine and dogma.
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 73

Conclusion

The presence of  Dante in Borges has been widely acknowledged. The pres-
ence of  Swedenborg has not. It is striking, however, to notice the depth
of inf luence of  Swedenborg’s thought upon Borges. This inf luence is vis-
ible not least the inclusion of extracts of  Swedenborg’s texts in Historia
Universal de la Infamia and in El libro de los seres imaginarios, but through
the adumbration of  Swedenborg’s visions in so many of  Borges’ tales, and
the manifest af finity to Swedenborg. This forms the basis of  Chapter Five.
Similarly, such considerations must be accompanied with an assessment of 
Borges’ own considerations of  the landscape of death. Whilst again here is
not the space to elaborate, it is worth explaining that throughout his work,
in many facets of  his writing, Borges appears pulled by two polarities: the
inevitability of oblivion or annihilation and the possibility of continuity.
In countless interviews, especially in his later years, he expresses a firm
wish for annihilation:

I look forward to being blotted out. But if  I thought that my death was a mere illu-
sion, that after death I would go on, then I would feel very, very unhappy. For really,
I’m sick and tired of myself. Now, of course if  I go on and I have no personal memory
of  having ever been Borges, then in that case, it won’t matter to me; because I may
have been hundreds of odd people before I was born, but those things won’t worry
me, since I will have forgotten them. When I think of mortality, of death, I think
of  those things in a hopeful way, in an expectant way. I should say I am greedy for
death, that I want to stop waking up every morning, finding: ‘Well, here I am, I have
to go back to Borges.’ (Barnstone 1982: 17)

His reading, however, of  Plato and other philosophers reveals a curiosity
about the soul’s persistence after corporeal death, and even the transmi-
gration of souls. The Borges-protagonist of  ‘Delia Elena San Marco’, for
example, lamenting Delia’s loss, declares: ‘Anoche no salí después de comer
y releí, para comprender estas cosas, la última enseñanza que Platón pone en
boca de su maestro. Leí que el alma puede huir cuando muere la carne’ (1974:
790) [‘Last night I stayed in after dinner and reread, in order to understand
these things, the last teaching Plato put in his master’s mouth. I read that
74 Chapter One

the soul may escape when the f lesh dies’] (1970: 32). There are many tales
and poems that demonstrate this tension between ‘olvido’ [oblivion] and
afterlife, expressed most succinctly in a brief comment in interview:

In spite of oneself, one thinks. I am almost sure to be blotted out by death, but some-
times I think it is not impossible that I may continue to live in some other manner
after my physical death. I feel every suicide has that doubt: Is what I am going to do
worthwhile? Will I be blotted out, or will I continue to live on another world? Or
as Hamlet wonders, what dreams will come when we leave this body? It could be a
nightmare. And then we would be in hell. Christians believe that one continues after
death to be who he has been and that he is punished or rewarded forever, accord-
ing to what he has done in this brief  time that was given to him. I would prefer to
continue living after death if  I have but to forget the life I lived. (Burgin 1998: 240)

The question of  faith here arises. Borges’ position as agnostic is of crucial
concern for us, and it is important to note that for Borges agnosticism
was not apathy to spiritual matters; on the contrary, it leads to a greater
opening to the numinous.22 Faith, in Borges’ worldview, is an indication
of  belief in matters about which we have no knowledge, and thus betrays
a limitation of one’s imagination. It would seem restrictive, he maintains,
to limit oneself  to a particular doctrine of  life after death unless, as in the
case of  Swedenborg, one has visited such a realm. His statement that ‘I have
never been worthy of such an experience’ is the acknowledgment that in
matters metaphysical, he must rely on his reading and his imagination. In
both cases, though, no firm conviction can be reached.

There are many speculations about life after death. Swedenborg describes in detail
hells and paradises. Dante’s poem is also about hell, purgatory, paradise. Where does
this tendency of man come from, to try to imagine and describe something that he
cannot possibly know? (Burgin 1998: 247)

22 ‘Being an agnostic means all things are possible, even God, even the Holy Trinity.
This world is so strange that anything may happen, or may not happen. Being an
agnostic makes me live in a larger, a more fantastic kind of world, almost uncanny.
It makes me more tolerant’ (Shenker 1971).
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 75

In the absence of empirical, experiential evidence, how can we judge Borges’


criteria for appraising authenticity to such metaphysical matters of  heaven
or eschatology? Logic, for example, cannot be employed in such mat-
ters. An example of  this is that Borges, as mentioned, quotes Flaubert and
Claudel in suggesting that Dante would be horrified to see, when dying,
that the Otherworld has no resemblance to his poetic vision. Borges also
quotes Swedenborg in stating that the dead project a vision of their bidding
around them. According to this logic, Dante would justifiably have been
able, upon death, to be surrounded by the landscape of  his poetic cycle, in
the presence of  Virgil. Logic is an inappropriate system in such matters.
James Lawrence, editor of  Testimony to the Invisible, seizes this question of
credibility, and suggests that for Borges the criteria for judging authentic-
ity lie within a certain aesthetic integrity. So convinced is Lawrence that
Borges is convinced by Swedenborg, he goes so far as to claim Borges as
one of  their own – a Swedenborgian:

Borges professes his profound admiration of  Swedenborg’s mode of  knowing in this
essay, and one quickly discerns that he also feels a kindred spirit to the Swedish mystic.
Borges declares that he himself is not a mystic, but that mysticism is an important
and fascinating subject for him. When the epistemology of  the knower is of solid
pedigree, he believed, then the ensuing perceptions are the most sublime humanity
has known. Borges felt that he shared with Swedenborg the same fundamental objec-
tives; they simply traversed the same terrain in somewhat dif ferent ways. […] Borges
believed in Swedenborg’s spiritual journeys more profoundly than many artists and
poets who have expressed perhaps some admiration or inspiration but who have
not been so deeply inclined to explore the same realities with as much conviction
and daring as Borges. It is in this sense that Borges is most deeply Swedenborgian.
(Lawrence 1995: x–xi)23

23 ‘Swedenborgian’ need not mean being a member of any Swedenborgian church.


Eugene Taylor, a scholar of  Swedenborg and his inf luence on Emerson and his com-
panions, writes: ‘Swedenborgianism […] refers to a Christian denomination that
follows the biblical interpretation of  Emanuel Swedenborg, an eighteenth-century
scientist and interpreter of religious experience. It can also refer more generally to
avid readers of  Swedenborg’s works, such as the New England transcendentalists,
who were not members of  the religious movement, but who used Swedenborg’s ideas
to corroborate their own interior journey toward self-realization’ (1997: xvii).
76 Chapter One

This is a powerful assessment of  Borges, and whilst readers familiar with
Borges would smirk at Lawrence’s naïveté in assuming that Borges was
a believer in a particular theological tradition (albeit heterodox), such a
reading is nevertheless fully borne out both in the language of Borges and,
as mentioned, in the strong presence of  Swedenborg in Borges. So what
is the nature of  this belief ? Clearly, as this chapter has elucidated, there is
a paradoxical question at the heart of  Borges’ reading of mystics. Reality
and artifice are indistinguishable. The text and the meta-text are both text.
Hamlet is as real as Bioy Casares. This, as established, is an abiding element
of  Borges. Upon this basis, therefore, an invented text of  heaven is as real
as a genuinely experienced text of  heaven. And upon this basis, despite
Borges’ acknowledgment that the mystical passage in ‘The Aleph’ was an
imitation of mystical texts, it is nonetheless a mystical text.24 If we follow
the Borges who maintains that the London of  Chesterton or Dickens is
as real as the ‘real’ London and that ‘there is no dif ference between fact
and fiction’ (Barnstone 1982: 117), then the Aleph, ‘the Spaniards’, Dante

24 Borges explains the artifice, or the invention, of  this passage: ‘A man in Spain asked
me whether the aleph actually existed. Of course it doesn’t. He thought the whole
thing was true. I gave him the name of  the street and the number of  the house. He
was taken in very easily. […] That piece gave me great trouble, yes. I mean, I had to
give a sensation of endless things in a single paragraph. Somehow, I got away with
it.
Q: Is that an invention, the aleph, or did you find it in some reference?
No. I’ll tell you, I was reading about time and eternity. Now eternity is supposed to
be timeless. I mean, God or a mystic perceives in one moment all of our yesterdays,
Shakespeare says, all the past, all the present, all the future. And I said, why not
apply that, well, that invention to another category, not to time, but to space? Why
not imagine a point in space wherein the observer may find all the rest. I mean, who
invented space? And that was the central idea. Then I had to invent all the other
things, to make it into a funny story, to make it into a pathetic story, that came
afterwards. My first aim was this: in the same way that many mystics have talked of
eternity … that’s a big word, an eternity, an everness. And also neverness; that’s an
awful word. Since we have an idea of eternity, of  foreverness in time, why not apply
the same idea to space, and think of a single point in space wherein the whole of
space may be found? I began with that abstract idea, and then, somehow, I came to
that quite enjoyable story. (Burgin 1998: 212)
Fantastic or real? Borges’ reading of  Dante and Swedenborg 77

and Weatherhead are all as authentic as Swedenborg. But if we follow the


Borges who maintains that John of  the Cross is simply parodying the Song
of  Songs, and Fray Luis de León is simply doctrinally-inspired, then we have
a separate order of  hermeneutics, and, despite its numinous glow, the Aleph
is simply an imitation and is consequently inauthentic. The judgment, as
Lawrence suggests, lies in the ‘solid pedigree’ of  the epistemology of  the
author and the text, not in the experience qua experience.25
To complete the circle of  this argument, therefore, we can maintain
that the appreciation of mimesis – of a real description of experience unbi-
ased by artifice, is in essence an aesthetic judgment. Borges as reader of
mystics does not require empirical proof of  their experiences; what he
requires is persuasion that the vision is genuine. If  Swedenborg is convinc-
ing, it is because, for Borges, the texts are suitably persuasive, precisely
through their lack of rhetorical features, artifice and doctrine. Ultimately
it is a question of style. Borges sums this up succinctly in his description
of  the mimetic style of  his friend and mystic Xul Solar: ‘I once asked Xul
how he defined his own painting, and he told me that he considered him-
self a Realist painter, since the things he painted were what he saw in his
visions’ (Alifano 1984: 120). Thus the riddle unfolds. Realism, for Borges,
is a fiction, and yet realism, for Borges, is fully operational in the peculiar
and perplexing theory of mimesis of  the imagination. Swedenborg, for
Borges, is a Realist of  the Fantastic.

25 A colleague of mine made this clear to me, stating that reading the paragraph in ‘The
Aleph’ in which the narrator attempts to vocalize the vision of  the Aleph af fected
her in a profound and ‘spiritual’ manner.
Chapter Two

Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter?

The range of mystical experience is very wide, much too wide for us to
cover in the time at our disposal.
— William James, Varieties of  Religious Experience

Knowledge of  God, the realization of one’s union with God, in a word,
mysticism, is necessary.
— Alan Watts, Behold the Spirit

Borges repeatedly denied being a mystic:

Many people have thought of me as a thinker, as a philosopher, or even as a mystic.


[…] People think that I’ve committed myself  to idealism, to solipsism, or to doctrines
of  the cabala, because I’ve used them in my tales. But really I was only trying to see
what could be done with them. (Burgin 1998: 79)

At the same time, he recognized that he experienced two mystical states


in his life:

In my life I only had two mystical experiences and I can’t tell them because what
happened is not to be put in words, since words, after all, stand for a shared experi-
ence. And if you have not had the experience you can’t share it – as if you were to
talk about the taste of cof fee and had never tried cof fee. Twice in my life I had a
feeling, a feeling rather agreeable than otherwise. It was astonishing, astounding. I
was overwhelmed, taken aback. I had the feeling of  living not in time but outside
time. It may have been a minute or so, it may have been longer. […] Somehow the
feeling came over me that I was living beyond time, and I did my best to capture it,
but it came and went. I wrote poems about it, but they are normal poems and do
not tell the experience. I cannot tell it to you, since I cannot retell it to myself, but I
had that experience, and I had it twice over, and maybe it will be granted me to have
it one more time before I die. (Barnstone 1982: 10–11)
80 Chapter Two

An important distinction is made here that we will explore in this chapter


and the next: a mystic is not necessarily someone who has mystical experi-
ences. Borges, of course, did do his best to capture the experience, describing
it in a passage which he labelled ‘sentirse en muerte’ [‘feeling in death’] in
El idioma de los argentinos (1928), in ‘Historia de la eternidad’ (1936) and in
‘Nueva refutación del tiempo’ (1952), and referring to it in many interviews.
When discussing his two timeless moments, he even compared himself  to
his mystic friend: ‘My friend, a mystic, abounds in ecstasies. I don’t. I’ve
had only two experiences of  timeless time in eighty years’ (Barnstone 1982:
73). It is highly likely, given his other discussions, that he is referring to Xul
Solar in this comment. Estela Canto recalled the mystical spirit of  Borges,
whom she did not consider a mystic even though she saw in him a tendency
towards becoming one: ‘Cuando se publicó El Aleph, yo lo comenté en una
revista (Sur). Allí me refería yo a un estado de ánimo místico; a él le gustó
el comentario. El agnóstico Borges no era un místico, por supuesto, pero
sí una persona capaz de momentos místicos’ (1999: 13) [‘When The Aleph
was published, I wrote about it in the literary journal Sur, referring to a
state of mystical rapture. He liked my comment. The agnostic Borges was
no mystic, clearly, but he was someone capable of mystical moments’] (my
translation). It is significant for this study that Canto declares assertively
that an agnostic, por supuesto, could not be a mystic; the implications being
that some adherence to religious orthodoxy is a pre-requisite. This, as will
be explored, is a problematic assertion. Canto further explains that Borges,
many years later, congratulated her on her acuity in the article:

Muchos años más tarde, un periodista me preguntó de repente: ‘¿Qué es El Aleph?’


y yo contesté: ‘Es el relato de una experiencia mística’. Cuando mencioné esto a
Georgie, me encontré con que él no había olvidado mi artículo, escrito treinta y cinco
años antes. Me dijo: ‘Has sido la única persona que ha dicho eso’, dando a entender
que podía haber cierta verdad en la cosa. Le gustaba esta apreciación, que se oponía
a la difundida idea entre los escritores argentinos, que lo juzgaban un autor frío y
geométrico, un creador de juegos puramente intelectuales. (1999: 14)

[Many years later, a journalist suddenly asked me, ‘What is the Aleph?’ and I replied,
‘it is the tale of a mystical experience.’ When I mentioned this to Georgie, I realized
that he hadn’t forgotten my article, written thirty-five years earlier. He said to me,
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 81

‘you have been the only person to say this,’ implying that I had been right in my sug-
gestion. He liked my appreciation, which was contrary to the idea circulated around
Argentine writers, which depicted Borges as a cold and geometric author, a creator
of purely intellectual games.] (My translation)

Importantly, according to Canto, Borges was dismayed that his fellow


Argentines ignored the mystic rapture of  his tales in favour of intellectual
game-playing. This is a valid perspective; the Borges-narrator of  ‘El Aleph’
does, after all, ridicule the mystical illumination it grants by highlighting
the overwrought poetry of  the Aleph’s custodian, Daneri; and by dismiss-
ing the Aleph as ‘falso’. Canto further explores this mystical/non-mystical
aspect of  Borges, suggesting that whilst not a mystic, he nevertheless strove
to achieve the state of enlightenment commonly attributed to mystics:

Los místicos hablan de ‘la noche oscura del alma’. ‘¿Quién puede distinguir entre la
oscuridad y el alma?’, se pregunta Yeats, un poeta muy admirado por Borges. Y más
allá de esa noche están los éxtasis de la liberación. A su manera tenue, pero empeci-
nada, él luchaba por alcanzar esa liberación. Los místicos suelen ser tácitos, a veces
escriben, rara vez hablan. (1999: 14)

[Mystics speak of  ‘the dark night of  the soul.’ ‘Who can distinguish darkness from
the soul?’ asks Yeats, a poet whom Borges admired. Beyond the dark night are the
ecstasies of  liberation. In his own tenuous yet tenacious way, Borges strove to achieve
that liberation. Mystics are often taciturn, they sometimes write but they rarely
speak.] (My translation)

With further reference to ‘El Aleph’, Canto then appears to contradict her-
self  by saying that Borges was a mystic, albeit an unsuspecting one: ‘La difer-
encia está en que Borges era un místico sin quererlo. Los místicos buscan
el éxtasis y a veces lo alcanzan tras sacrificios, ascesis, renuncias. Borges no
renunciaba a nada: el elemento místico estaba en él, funcionaba sin que él
lo quisiera, tal vez sin que lo sospechara’ (1999: 211). [‘The dif ference is that
Borges was a mystic without wishing to be so. Mystics seek ecstasy and at
times they achieve it through sacrifice, aestheticism, renunciation. Borges
renounced nothing: the mystical element was in him without him desiring
it, perhaps without him even aware of it’] (my translation). Canto, as we
shall see, unwittingly enters the perennial debate within the scholarship of
82 Chapter Two

mysticism concerning bidden or unbidden states of mystical consciousness,


the category of mysticism defined by William James as ‘passive’.1
Alicia Jurado cites Estela Canto (from what I assume was the same
review to which Canto herself was referring), revealing that Canto went
further than suggesting that Borges merely had the potential to be a mystic,
but that he was one of  the greatest ‘mystical thinkers of our time’:

Pocas personas han advertido las relaciones de Borges con el misticismo; una de ellas
fue Estela Canto. Dijo, en una crítica sobre los cuentos de El Aleph, que llamó rela-
tos, ensayos y también leyendas: ‘El universo, su contradicción aparente, sus sentidos
ocultos y la angustia del hombre frente a él, aparece de lleno en todos los cuentos de
Borges. Una de las características de los pensadores místicos es su afición a expresarse
por símbolos. Yo diría que la mejor definición de Borges es la de unos de los gran-
des – y escasísimos – pensadores místicos de nuestra época’. Pensador místico, desde
luego; no místico a secas. (1996: 98)

[Few people have noticed Borges’ relationship with mysticism; one of  them was
Estela Canto. In a review of  the tales in El Aleph, which she called tales, essays and
also legends, she said: ‘The universe, its apparent contradictions, its hidden mean-
ings and man’s anxieties faced with it, are the mainstay of all of  Borges’ tales. One of 
the characteristics of mystical thinkers is their inclination to express themselves by
means of symbols. I would say that the best definition of  Borges is that he is one of 
the greatest – and rarest – mystical thinkers of our time.’ Mystical thinker, obviously,
not just mystic.] (My translation)

It is revealing that Jurado’s ‘desde luego’ echoes Canto’s ‘por supuesto’, as in


both cases their statements are grounded in the postulate that it is consensu-
ally recognized that Borges was no mystic. As we investigate in the following
chapter, the distinction between ‘mystic’ and ‘mystical thinker’ is of prime
importance in the scholarship of mysticism, with countless scholars, such
James, Underhill and Jung denying their own mystical experiences yet mani-
festly appraising such experiences in their overall evaluation of mysticism.2

1 James’ use of  ‘passive’ as a definition of mysticism is problematic owing to his own
use of nitrous oxide and ether to activate the mystical consciousness in himself.
2 Kripal (2001) investigates the extent to which the mystical experiences of  James and
Underhill inf luenced their scholarship.
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 83

I would argue that there is no consensus on the matter of whether Borges


was or was not a mystic, as I hope to demonstrate in this chapter.
J. M. Cohen, translator and friend of  Borges, was likewise curious
about the depiction of mystical experiences in Borges’ work, especially in
the three tales: ‘El Aleph’, ‘El Zahir’ and ‘La escritura del dios’. Similar to
the discussion in the Introduction concerning Borges’ perplexing state-
ments about employing mystical themes for purely aesthetic purposes,
Cohen appears similarly suspicious of such simple assertions, arguing that
Borges maintained a deep interest in such matters owing in part to his own
mystical experiences:

It is true that he talked about the mystics, but as writers who recorded certain curi-
ous experiences, whose statements concerning time and timelessness, recurrence,
cosmology had a great speculative interest for him, but nothing more. He did not
admit to any personal concern with such things. Yet so many of  Borges’ stories […]
firmly contradict Borges’ defensive denial of personal involvement in this matter
[…]. His references to Christianity or Buddhism, to Plato, Swedenborg, the Sufis,
show a fascination with magic, and particularly with the magical moment, which is
identified in his poetry with the moment of déjà vu in which he first saw the pink
painted street corner in the Buenos Aires suburb, and to other such moments in
childhood or in his nocturnal walking in which things looked dif ferent; moments,
one may say, in which ‘time stopped’, as it did for Hladík when he faced the firing
squad. We may leave the subject of  Borges’ personal involvement in this area with
the remark that he shows an uncanny familiarity with the stages of  the mystic search
for one only speculatively interested in such matters. (1973: 78–9).

Cohen judiciously avoids labelling Borges a mystic, primarily in respect


to Borges’ insistence that he had no religious or mystical inclination: ‘My
own attempts to open the subject in 1953 [with Borges] were brusquely
repulsed’ (1973: 78). Consequently he entitles the chapter in which he analy-
ses these matters ‘The “mystical” experience’, where the inverted commas
imply a sense of parody or critical distance in the treatment of mysticism
in Borges’ tales. Nevertheless it is significant that Cohen cannot accept
Borges’ claims and argues coherently that, parody aside, the three tales in
particular constitute powerfully ‘mystical’ texts.
María Kodama discusses mysticism in the introduction of  her edited
volume of  Borges’ works On Mysticism (Borges 2010). Kodama, who
84 Chapter Two

through her employment of  the terms ‘passive’ and ‘inef fable’ appears in her
understanding of mysticism to be inf luenced by both Borges and William
James, does an admirable job in making simple a strikingly complex area of 
thought, though in so doing she overlooks some of  these complexities. For
example, she cites St John of  the Cross’s description of  the contemplative,
spiritual path that can lead to the mystical state, yet fails to appreciate that
Borges himself denied that St John of  the Cross was a mystic (Barnstone
1982: 11). She concludes her overview of  the essential characteristics of  the
mystical state by stating: ‘Once we have determined these characteristics,
we can see that they appear repeatedly in Borges’ poems and short stories’
(Borges 2010: viii). Again, this position is more complex than it may appear.
The fact that mystical states are represented in poems and stories does not
necessarily imply that the author experienced this particular state. And yet
this assertion is problematic: as I argue in Chapter One, Borges constantly
blurs the division between text and meta-text, and emphasizes the Blakean
position that imagination is experiential. Consequently one can argue that
the invention of a text describing a mystical state constitutes an experience
of  the mystical state. The text is the experience. Kodama appears to intuit
this conundrum, suggesting that ‘I believe that we could speak, in the case
of  Borges, of a mysticism of creation’ (viii), where, I suppose, she locates
the mystical moment in the act of  textual creation.
Giskin (1990) considers Borges’ fictions in the light of  the principles
of mysticism as defined by William James: Inef fability, Noetic experience,
Transiency, and Passivity. Giskin’s analysis has provided a fruitful avenue
of enquiry in the Borges course at the University of  Kent, and students
find it a helpful guide for orientating themselves through the unnerving
texts of  ‘El milagro secreto’, ‘Las ruinas circulares’, ‘La escritura del dios’,
and in particular, ‘El Aleph’. Giskin concludes that owing to the fact that
certain texts of  Borges embody the defining characteristics of mysticism
as articulated by William James, Borges was consequently a mystic. This
conclusion, however, leaves many questions unanswered: is a ‘mystical’ text
necessarily the work of a mystic? Can an author parody a mystical text, and
if so, does that negate the mystical qualities of  the text? What on earth is
a mystical text? What on earth is a mystic? These questions are not mere
‘frivolidad escolástica’ [‘scholastic frivolity’] (a term Borges employs in
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 85

‘Duración del Infierno’) nor specious hair-splitting, as the discussion of


mysticism, as we shall see, raises questions that strike at the heart of our
understanding of reality and challenge our ontological certainties. It seems,
therefore, that whilst Giskin may be praised for his clarity in making the
equation: ‘The mystical experience in Borges includes four characteristics
which are common to all epiphany, as cited by William James’ (Giskin
1990: 71) ergo Borges was a mystic, his analysis raises far more questions
at levels of  literary, phenomenological and ontological analysis than he
had perhaps intended.
Lastly, Wallace, writing in the New York Times, suggests that Borges
was, indeed, a mystic, and he of fers his own brief exposition of  the mean-
ing of such a term:

Borges’s stories […] are designed primarily as metaphysical arguments; they are dense,
self-enclosed, with their own deviant logics. Above all, they are meant to be imper-
sonal, to transcend individual consciousness […] One reason for this is that Borges
is a mystic, or at least a sort of radical Neoplatonist – human thought, behavior and
history are all the product of one big Mind, or are elements of an immense cabalistic
Book that includes its own decoding. (2004)

There is an evident problem in all these assertions, as the authors avow that
Borges was or was not a mystic based upon a rudimentary examination of
what the word itself means, and without any exploration of  the long and
often contradictory nature of  the scholarship of mysticism, which has for
decades grappled precisely with the definition of  this troublesome term.
As such, Canto’s analysis almost inevitably trips over itself as her position
appears derived more from an ethical and perhaps emotive than an intel-
lectual response to the question in the assumption that agnosticism and
mysticism are contradictory enterprises. Kodama does venture away from
the James/Borges position to include a Vedantic perspective, but still the
reader is left with questions about the nature of experience-author-text-
reader. Wallace, meanwhile, makes one sweeping comment about ‘one big
Mind’ as the determining position, and concludes that Borges fits within
this category. Giskin, perhaps the most thorough examiner of  the mystical
aspect of  Borges, nevertheless bases his full analysis only on the four char-
acteristics outlined by James, with no exploration either of  the distinction
86 Chapter Two

between author, text and reader (that is to say, is the text mystical, or is it
the reader’s response?), nor of  the many other scholars of mysticism, such
as Underhill, Zaehner, Stace, Watts or Staal, who often refuted James and
whose salient characteristics are markedly dif ferent. It is doubtful, for
example, that Borges’ scepticism, agnosticism and literary game-playing
would qualify him as a mystic in Zaehner’s strictly theistic and theological
approach to mysticism. Núñez-Faraco (2006: 41) sums up the nature of the
problem, indicating that ‘if  the term “mystic” applies to Borges, it becomes
necessary to define the precise meaning of such a designation’. Promising as
this sounds, Núñez-Faraco pursues this line no further, and so the reader is
left in suspense as to how such a designation is, indeed, defined.
It becomes clear that we cannot rely on any immediate consensual
understanding of  the term ‘mystic’ in order to judge whether a certain
individual was or was not a mystic. One can only arrive at such a conclu-
sion by plotting the figure and his/her literary works against a checklist of
defining characteristics as determined by a respected scholar such as James.
This implies, however, not only an agreement with these characteristics as
suitable definitions of mystic and mysticism, but, importantly, an accord
over the meaning of  the terms employed in these characteristics themselves.
As such, when James suggests ‘noetic’ as one such criterion, we must assume
a consensual understanding of  this term. This may sound pedantic, but it
is alarming how often one encounters a declaration that a certain poet-
author-theologian was or was not a mystic because their experience was
or was not ‘unitive’, ‘extravertive’ or ‘inef fable’. These terms themselves are
thorny. Surely the root of  the inef fability of  the mystical state might lie
less with the experience than with the linguistic skills of  the experiencer?
As we examine in Chapter Four, for over a century readers of  Emerson
have battled over whether he was or was not a mystic through arguing, for
example, that he may not have experienced God, but that he did experience
Nature, and hence he was a ‘nature mystic’ (Quinn 1950).3 Little, I would
argue, is clarified in employing God or Nature as distinctive definitions
of mysticism, as owing to their inherent arbitrariness they would them-

3 A new term, indeed, was coined for Emerson based on his particular religious yet
anti-ecclesiastical spiritual philosophy: ‘Yankee mystic’ (Hurth 2005: 336).
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 87

selves require further definition. Bertrand Russell (1961) pays particular


attention to these semantic vagaries in his essay ‘Mysticism’, suggesting
three definitions of mysticism,4 then enquiring exactly what is meant by,
for example, his own definition ‘that time is unreal’. As is customary with
Russell’s meticulous method, he takes nothing for granted either regard-
ing mysticism or regarding the many prof fered defining characteristics.

What is mysticism?

So how does one judge these textual accounts of mystical experiences against
the scholarship? Which of  the many classifications does one turn to in order
to qualify or refute the mystical nature of a given author or text? The essen-
tial standpoint for many of  the scholars that justifies this array of of ferings
is the inherent inexplicability of  the mystical experience. From the early
scholarship of  the end of  the nineteenth century through to the present,
scholars have identified the initial problem of identifying what exactly it is
that they are investigating. William Ralph Inge (known normally as Dean
Inge), in his Christian Mysticism (1899) begins his investigation with the
assertion that the word itself is semantically slippery:
No word in our language – not even ‘Socialism’ – has been employed more loosely
than ‘Mysticism.’ Sometimes it is used as an equivalent for symbolism or allegorism,
sometimes for theosophy or occult science; and sometimes it merely suggests the
mental state of a dreamer, or vague and fantastic opinions about God and the world.
In Roman Catholic writers, ‘mystical phenomena’ mean supernatural suspensions of
physical law. Even those writers who have made a special study of  the subject, show
by their definitions of  the word how uncertain is its connotation. (1913: 3)

4 ‘(1) that all division and separateness is unreal, and that the universe is a single indivis-
ible unity; (2) that evil is illusory, and that the illusion arises through falsely regarding
a part as self-subsistent; (3) that time is unreal, and that reality is eternal, not in the
sense of  being everlasting, but in the sense of  being wholly outside time’ (Russell
1961: 179).
88 Chapter Two

However, many years later Inge revisited the designations, this time categori-
cally expunging from his definitions those matters contrary to orthodoxy,
such as supernatural, erotic, etc.

I cannot accept any definition which identifies mysticism with excited or hysterical
emotionalism, with sublimated eroticism, with visions and revelations, with super-
natural (dualistically opposed to natural) activities, nor, on the philosophical side,
with irrationalism. I suggest that a generation which treats its experience of ghosts
with respect ought not to be rude about the experience of  God. I propose to divide
my subject into three sections ontological, the doctrine of ultimate reality; episte-
mological, the doctrine of  knowledge; and ethical, the chart by which the mystic
finds his way up the hill of  the Lord. (Inge 1947: 154)

William James, who cited Inge in Varieties of  Religious Experience and
who argued like Schopenhauer that the mystical experience is at the heart
of all religious experience, maintained that both mysticism and religion
are themselves impossible to define: ‘Most books on the philosophy of
religion try to begin with a precise definition of what its essence consists
of. […] The very fact that they are so many and so dif ferent from one
another is enough to prove that the word “religion” cannot stand for any
single principle or essence, but is rather a collective name’ (1913: 26). Like
Inge’s use of  ‘socialism’ James used as analogy the word ‘government’, sug-
gesting that it signifies many dif ferent and at times conf licting things,
yet its full meaning relies on a composite of all these disparate meanings.
Importantly, and in tune with so much of  Borges’ philosophical outlook,
James acknowledged that in so many cases, an investigation into religion
or mysticism is in essence an investigation into the language employed to
describe these ideas: ‘the question of definition tends to become a dispute
about names’ (1913: 30). This linguistic variance, as we shall see later in this
chapter when discussing the problem of  textual hermeneutics of mystical
texts, is of crucial importance.
Frits Staal, in Exploring Mysticism (1975: 8), likewise identified the
problem of names, arguing that ‘The study of mysticism [has] tended to
deteriorate into enumerations and classifications of a variety of narratives,
without any attempt at a critical evaluation.’ Whilst I would argue that
there is critical evaluation (as, curiously, does Staal himself in his book),
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 89

Staal does identify the problem that I will discuss in the following chapter
concerning the semantic circularity that can ensue in a debate about mys-
ticism. It is defined according to other terms whose meaning then often
needs defining. In some cases this chain of signifiers can lead back to the
use of  the word ‘mysticism’ to define one of  these sequential terms. Jaf fé
(1989: 12) is, for example, admirably precise in suggesting that mysticism
is ‘the experience of  the numinous’, but in this matter one needs to define
the term ‘numinous’, a similarly tricky exercise. Staal also identifies the
many dif ficulties in studying mysticism; most notable among them is that
‘it is not so simple’ (1975: 124). ‘We call a mystic anyone who for a certain
length of  time has mystical experiences’ (125). That is fair enough, but
what exactly is a mystical experience? More recently, David Wulf f, in one
of  the chapters of  Cardeña, Lynn and Krippner’s James-inspired Varieties
of  Anomalous Experience (2000), has argued that: ‘Falling by definition
outside the realm of ordinary discourse, mystical experience eludes any
precise description or characterization. Furthermore, as relatively recent
constructions that serve diverse and even opposing purposes, the terms
mystical and mysticism are themselves hard to pin down’ (2000: 397). This
emphasis on meaning variance is important, as whilst Canto and Jurado
assert that – por supuesto – Borges was no mystic, they of fer little explana-
tion as to why this assertion is so immediately obvious. Were they to have
attempted to qualify the assertion with a more thorough investigation
into the meaning of  the term ‘mystic’, they would have encountered many
choices of definitions, often contradictory.
James suggested that the terms can have dif ferent values attached to
them depending on the situation in which they are employed. Likewise,
he explored the definitions of mysticism according to certain aspects of 
human experience that are not mysticism:

The words ‘mysticism’ and ‘mystical’ are often used as terms of mere reproach, to throw
at any opinion which we regard as vague and vast and sentimental, and without a
base in either facts or logic. For some writers a ‘mystic’ is any person who believes in
thought-transference, or spirit-return. Employed in this way the word has little value:
there are too many less ambiguous synonyms. So, to keep it useful by restricting it, I
will do what I did in the case of  the word ‘religion,’ and simply propose to you four
90 Chapter Two

marks which, when an experience has them, may justify us in calling it mystical for
the purpose of  the present lectures. In this way we shall save verbal disputation, and
the recriminations that generally go therewith. (1913: 379)

Evelyn Underhill, whose inf luential work Mysticism challenged James’s


definitions in Varieties, likewise attempted to define mysticism initially
by suggesting some aspects of  human experience that are categorically not
mysticism:

What then do we really mean by mysticism? A word which is impartially applied to


the performances of mediums and the ecstasies of  the saints, to ‘menticulture’ and
sorcery, dreamy poetry and mediaeval art, to prayer and palmistry, the doctrinal
excesses of  Gnosticism, and the tepid speculations of  the Cambridge Platonists –
even, according to William James, to the higher branches of intoxication – soon
ceases to have any useful meaning. (1912: 86)

This method of defining mysticism according to that which it is not was


pursued also by Walter Stace (1960: 10–12) in his attempt to isolate the
specifics of  the term ‘mystic’ from a catalogue of other terms popularly
employed interchangeably with mystic:

Some Things Which Mysticism Is Not. The word ‘mysticism’ is popularly used in a
variety of  loose and inaccurate ways. Sometimes anything is called ‘mystical’ which
is misty, foggy, vague, or sloppy. It is absurd that ‘mysticism’ should be associated
with what is ‘misty’ because of  the similar sound of  the words. And there is nothing
misty, foggy, vague, or sloppy about mysticism. A second absurd association is to
suppose that mysticism is sort of mystery-mongering. There is, of course, an etymo-
logical connection between ‘mysticism’ and ‘mystery.’ But mysticism is not any sort
of  hocus-pocus such as we commonly associate with claims to be the elucidation
of sensational mysteries. Mysticism is not the same as what is commonly called the
‘occult’ – whatever that may mean. Nor has it anything to do with spiritualism, or
ghosts, or table-turning. Nor does it include what are commonly called parapsycho-
logical phenomena such as telepathy, telekinesis, clairvoyance, precognition. These
are not mystical phenomena. It is perhaps true that mystics may sometimes claim
to possess such special powers, but even when they do so they are well aware that
such powers are not part of, and are to be clearly distinguished from, their mystical
experience […]. Finally, it is most important to realize that visions and voices are
not mystical phenomena, though here again it seems to be the case that the sort of
persons who are mystics may often be the sort of persons who see visions and hear
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 91

voices […]. What mystics say is that a genuine mystical experience is nonsensuous.
It is formless, shapeless, colorless, odorless, soundless. But a vision is a piece of visual
imagery having color and shape. A voice is an auditory image. Visions and voices
are sensuous experiences.

The separation of mysticism from other anomalous experiences, there-


fore, is a mainstay in the scholarship. Yet mysticism can involve much more
than a mere transient experience. Such other matters are themselves hard
to define and evaluate, and the scholarship here is also large and varied.
Whilst James, Underhill and Stace have listed such non-mystical aspects as
‘thought-transference or spirit-return’, ‘sorcery, dreamy poetry and medi-
aeval art, prayer and palmistry’ ‘visions and hearing voices’, the chapter
headings of  Varieties of  Anomalous Experience provide an indication of
what, precisely, these matters are: ‘Hallucinatory Experiences, Synaesthesia,
Lucid Dreaming, Out-of-Body Experiences, Psi-related Experiences, Alien
Abduction Experiences, Past-Life Experiences, Near-Death Experiences,
and Anomalous Healing Experiences’ (vii–viii). Importantly, Wulf f ’s chap-
ter, ‘Mystical Experiences’, demonstrates the kinship between mysticism and
these other matters, principally because the non-ordinary activities occur
to a mystic alongside the more definite ‘mystical’ experiences. Indeed in
many cases the category of  ‘mystic’ depends precisely upon these anomalous
experiences. The case of  Swedenborg is a pertinent example. Not one of  the
many biographies of  Swedenborg, from Wilkinson’s Emanuel Swedenborg:
A Biography (1849), which informed Emerson, to Borges’ biographical
essay ‘Testigo de lo invisible’ (1995) which was informed by Emerson, to
Gary Lachman’s recent Swedenborg: An Introduction to His Life and Ideas
(2012) fails to emphasize his dazzling psychic abilities. It may even be sug-
gested that Swedenborg’s enduring reputation lies not so much with his
voluminous biblical exegesis, nor even with his accounts of  heavens and
hells, but with his well-documented psychic abilities. Conan Doyle, for
example, dismisses in one paragraph the entire theological dimension of 
Swedenborg’s works, ‘and his tiresome exegesis of  the Scriptures’ (2005:
97), and focuses exclusively on the ‘psychic powers’: ‘Swedenborg’s theol-
ogy is neither simple nor intelligible, and that is its condemnation. […]
Not in that direction does the worth of  Swedenborg lie. That worth is
92 Chapter Two

really to be found in his psychic powers and in his psychic information


which would have been just as valuable had no word of theology ever come
from his pen’ (97–8).5 Van Dusen, in his biographical analysis The Presence
of  Other Worlds (1974) includes a whole chapter on Swedenborg’s ‘minor
miracles’ of clairvoyance and mediumship, in particular the location of  the

5 In addition to being creator of  Sherlock Holmes, Conan Doyle was a committed
researcher into spiritualism and related anomalous matters. Whilst I can find in
Borges no mention of  Conan Doyle’s essay on Swedenborg, there are a couple of
areas of great similarity with Borges’ essay ‘Testigo’ that might indicate that Borges
was familiar with the essay:
‘They may say that the man was mad, but his life in the years which followed showed
no sign of mental weakness. Or they might say that he lied. But he was a man who
was famed for his punctilious veracity’ (Conan Doyle 2005: 99). ‘Dos conjeturas:
La deliberada impostura de quien ha escrito esas cosas extrañas o el inf lujo de una
demencia brusca o gradual. La primera es inadmisible. […] La hipótesis de la locura
no es menos vana. […] Si se hubiera enloquecido, no deberíamos a su pluma tenaz
la ulterior redacción de miles de metódicas páginas, que representan una labor de
casi treinta años y que nada tienen que ver con el frenesí’ (Borges 2005: 155) [‘Two
assumptions: deliberate imposture […] or the inf luence of sudden or progressive mad-
ness. The first is inadmissible. […] The hypothesis of madness is equally unfounded
[…] If  he had gone mad, we would not owe to his tenacious pen the thousands of
methodical pages he wrote during the following thirty years or so, pages that have
nothing at all to do with frenzy’ (Borges 1995: 7–8)].
‘In spite of all his theological symbolism, his name must live eternally as the first
of all modern men who has given a description of  the process of death, and of  the
world beyond, which is not founded upon the vague ecstatic and impossible visions
of  the old Churches, but which actually corresponds with the descriptions which we
ourselves obtain from those who endeavour to convey back to us some clear idea of 
their new existence’ (Conan Doyle 2005: 104). ‘Swedenborg pudo renunciar a tales
artificios retóricos porque su tema no era el éxtasis del alma arrebatada y enajenada,
sino la puntual descripción de regiones ultraterrenas, pero precisas’ (Borges 2005:
154). [‘Swedenborg was able to abstain from this kind of rhetorical artifice because
his subject matter was not the ecstasy of a rapt and fainting soul but, rather, the
accurate description of regions that, though ultra-terrestrial, were clearly defined’]
(Borges 1995: 7).
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 93

lost receipt,6 the knowledge of  the queen’s secret,7 and, most famously, his
contemporaneous knowledge of  the fire in Stockholm whilst he was dining
in Gothenburg.8 Kant, it is to be assumed, would have paid little attention

6 ‘In April or May 1761, a countess de Marteville came to Swedenborg. Her husband,
ambassador extraordinary of  the Netherlands, had died in Sweden. He had given
her a valuable silver service before he died. Now the silversmith was demanding a
payment she could not af ford even though she was sure her husband had paid for
it. The matter was urgent to the woman. She had heard Swedenborg could contact
the souls of  the departed. Would he contact her husband and ask of  the receipt?
Swedenborg said he would. Three days later he returned and said he had spoken with
her husband. The receipt was in a bureau upstairs. The woman said she had already
searched the bureau. The husband had told Swedenborg that a certain drawer was to
be pulled out and a false back removed. The woman and her company went upstairs
and found the receipt and other lost papers as directed. This incident was related by
eleven dif ferent sources, most of whom agreed on the above account. When ques-
tioned on the matter Swedenborg also af firmed its occurrence’ (Van Dusen 1974:
142).
7 ‘Swedenborg met the queen [Louisa Ulrica of  Sweden] [who] lightly asked if  he had
a message from her [dead] brother. Swedenborg answered yes and suggested that
they speak alone, and he related what he had learned from the queen’s brother. The
queen was variously described as in shock, disturbed, or so indisposed that she had
to retire. She said later that Swedenborg had reported what no other living person
knew’ (Van Dusen 1974: 143).
8 ‘On July 17, 1759, Swedenborg and fifteen others were guests of  the prominent mer-
chant William Castel in Gothenburg at his fine home on Canal Street. At six in the
evening Swedenborg appeared quite pale and alarmed. When asked what was wrong,
he described a fire burning at that moment in Stockholm, three hundred miles away.
He paced in and out of  the house evidently agitated by the fire. His detailed descrip-
tion and evident sincerity upset the guests, many of whom were from Stockholm.
Swedenborg described exactly where the fire was burning, where it had started, and
when, and was dismayed to see a friend’s house already in ashes. The next day, Sunday,
the governor, having heard of  the incident, asked to see Swedenborg and received a
detailed report. The news spread through the city. Two days after the fire, messengers
arrived and confirmed every detail as Swedenborg had reported it, including when
and how it started, what it burned, and where and when it was contained. There were
several separate reports of  this incident that agreed on essentials. Even the German
philosopher Immanuel Kant was impressed and sent his own agent to check the
details’ (Van Dusen 1974: 141).
94 Chapter Two

to Swedenborg’s extensive theology and his mystical explorations had he not


become intrigued by these psychic occurrences. Van Dusen even suggests
that Swedenborg himself was aware that without these demonstrated psy-
chic abilities, his readership would remain limited. This statement implies
that the acts of mediumship and clairvoyance were themselves miracles for
the purpose of  bringing his heavenly theology to public attention. Borges,
as is clear from a reading of  his many texts dealing with Swedenborg, was
equally unconcerned with the theological works and treated the doctrine
of correspondences with tepid reservation, but was fascinated particularly
by Swedenborg’s declared explorations of other worlds. This last attribute of 
Swedenborg’s – voyages to other dimensions – is rarely one of  the charac-
teristics of mysticism in the scholarship, and would fit more within aspects
of anomalous, parapsychological experiences. (In fact, claims of planetary
voyages by non-astronauts would normally be considered delusions, and
hence psychopathological. We recall that Conan Doyle and Borges insisted
on Swedenborg’s lucidity). Furthermore, as is to be expected in such a nebu-
lous field as mysticism, terms merge with each other, despite the attempts
to maintain strict divisions. As such Otto’s exploration of  the ‘numinous’,
Suzuki’s ‘satori’, Jung’s studies of  ‘religiosity’ and the numinous, Joseph
Campbell’s ‘transparent to the transcendent’ (2004), Wilber or Daniels’
‘transpersonal’, Stanislav Grof ’s ‘holotropic’,9 Huxley’s ‘self-transcendence’,
Humphry Osmond’s ‘psychedelic’, Terence McKenna’s ‘shamanic’, Borges’
‘timelessness’, inevitably embody much that may be integrally related to
the mystical.

9 ‘The content of  holotropic states of consciousness is often philosophical and mys-
tical. In these episodes, we can experience sequences of psychospiritual death and
rebirth or feelings of oneness with other people, nature, the universe, and God. We
might uncover what seem to be memories from other incarnations, encounter pow-
erful archetypal beings, communicate with discarnate entities, and visit numerous
mythological domains’ (Grof 1998: 7).
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 95

The varieties of  taxonomies

The eccentric Chinese encyclopaedia entitled ‘Emporio celestial de cono-


cimientos benévolos’ [‘Celestial Empire of  benevolent Knowledge’] that
Borges describes in ‘El idioma analítico de John Wilkins’ and that so tick-
led Michel Foucault demonstrates the possible arbitrariness of systems of
classification. Borges would have delighted in the colourful and at times
contradictory taxonomies that have been proposed to define mysticism
over the last century. Inge, in an appendix of  Christian Mysticism, cites the
definitions of mysticism of  twenty-six separate poets and theologians, in a
heterogeneous list that includes Goethe and Charles Kingsley. Striking to
note that in the time of  Inge, as with today (see Daniels 2003), the most
notable feature of any compendium of definitions is the level of contradic-
tion between one definition and another (to say nothing of  the level of
passion and invective). William James, the grandfather of  the systematic
appraisal of  the mystical traditions, concluded his inclusive analysis with
the well-known ‘four marks which, when an experience has them, may
justify us in calling it mystical […] inef fability, noetic quality, transiency,
passivity’ ( James 1913: 380). Underhill (1911) dismissed James’s categories,
snidely rebuking him for daring to include ‘intoxication’ as a pathway to
mystical consciousness, and of fered instead:
1. True mysticism is active and practical, not passive and theoretical. It is an organic
life-process, a something which the whole self does; not something as to which its
intellect holds an opinion. 2. Its aims are wholly transcendental and spiritual. It is in
no way concerned with adding to, exploring, re-arranging, or improving anything
in the visible universe. […] 3. This One is for the mystic, not merely the Reality of
all that is, but also a living and personal Object of  Love; never an object of explora-
tion. […] 4. Living union with this One – which is the term of  his adventure – is
a definite state or form of enhanced life. It is obtained neither from an intellectual
realization of its delights, nor from the most acute emotional longings. (1912: 96)

Underhill’s classifications were driven, she argued, by five fundamental


stages in the development of  the mystical individual:
96 Chapter Two

(1) The awakening of  the Self  to consciousness of  Divine Reality. […] (2) Purgation
[self-knowledge] […] (3) Illumination […] a certain apprehension of  the Absolute,
a sense of  the Divine Presence: but not true union with it. It is a state of  happiness.
(4) […] the final and complete purification of  the Self, which is called by some con-
templatives the ‘mystic pain’ or ‘mystic death,’ by others the Purification of  the Spirit
or Dark Night of  the Soul. […] This is the ‘spiritual crucifixion’ so often described by
the mystics: the great desolation in which the soul seems abandoned by the Divine.
The Self now surrenders itself, its individuality, and its will, completely. It desires
nothing, asks nothing, is utterly passive, and is thus prepared for (5) Union: the true
goal of  the mystic quest. In this state the Absolute Life is not merely perceived and
enjoyed by the Self, as in Illumination: but is one with it. This is the end towards
which all the previous oscillations of consciousness have tended. It is a state of equi-
librium, of purely spiritual life; characterized by peaceful joy, by enhanced powers,
by intense certitude. (1912: 205–7)

Suzuki (1956), a close reader of  Swedenborg and admirer of  James, and
the figure widely credited with introducing Zen spiritual practices into
the West in the early twentieth century, likened the word Satori to the
word mysticism, and thus arrived at his own salient eight characteristics:
Irrationality, Intuitive Insight, Authoritativeness, Af firmation, Sense of  the
Beyond, Impersonal Tone, Feeling of  Exaltation, Momentariness (103–8).
Stace (1961), arguing from a perennialist position – i.e. that there is a com-
monality in the mystical experience across time and cultures – divided the
mystical experience into ‘extrovertive’ and ‘introvertive’, whose character-
istics in common are: ‘1. The Unifying Vision – all things are One. 2. The
more concrete apprehension of  the One as an inner subjectivity, or life,
in all things. 3. Sense of objectivity or reality. 4. Blessedness, peace, etc. 5.
Feeling of  the holy, sacred, or divine. 6. Paradoxicality 7. Alleged by mystics
to be inef fable’ (1961: 131–2). Zaehner (1961), drawing on a wider field than
James or Underhill in including his knowledge of  Buddhist and Hindu
traditions, limited the field to three essential characteristics:

Nature mysticism, based on all-in-one or panenhenic experience, such as the experi-


ence of cosmic consciousness (Bucke, 1901/2001). For Zaehner, nature mysticism
is essentially non-religious. 2. Monistic mysticism, based on the absorptive experi-
ence of one’s own self or spirit as the Absolute (e.g., Advaita Vedanta). 3. Theistic
mysticism, based on the experience of  loving communion or union with a personal
God. (Daniels 2003).
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 97

Pahnke, drawing principally on Stace, added: ‘1) sense of unity, 2) tran-


scendence of  time and space, 3) sense of sacredness, 4) sense of objective
reality, 5) deeply felt positive mood, 6) inef fability, 7) paradoxicality and
8) transiency’ (Doblin 1991: 7).
In addition to the articulation of defining characteristics, it is charac-
teristic of  the scholars to allow their religious, moral, ethical or ideological
assumptions to create a hierarchy of  the mystical experience. In this sense,
there are ‘higher’ and ‘lower’ forms of mysticism. Daniels, in his informative
essay ‘Making sense of mysticism’ highlights this particular abiding feature
of  the scholarship: ‘I see no clear grounds for imputing here any moral,
spiritual or developmental hierarchy. There is, in my opinion, no rational
basis for assuming that god-focused (theistic) mysticism generally represents
a higher (lower), better (worse), or more mature (immature) form than that
represented in any of  the other contexts’ (2003, no pagination). And yet,
despite this levelling perspective, Daniels still does assume some variance
of value based upon intensity or ‘increasing involvement with the Real’.
Consequently, ‘union’ is greater in mystical value than mere awareness of 
the numinous. ‘From this point of view, it seems reasonable to argue, for
example, that unitive mysticism is more advanced than numinous mysti-
cism. Thus the spiritual marriage of  St Teresa is a more sublime experience
than that of  the presence of  the mysterium because the implied relationship
with the Real is closer’ (2003). Daniels proceeds to construct an alarm-
ingly elaborate model in order to locate every type of mystical experience
in the literature, east and west, modern and ancient. Such a complex model
may be of use in order to locate a particular mystic, as if pinning them to a
grid in order to compare them with other mystics, but I cannot dispel the
arbitrariness of  Borges’ Chinese encyclopaedia when considering how such
an elaborate model can serve to confuse and befuddle rather than clarify.
Whilst this simple catalogue of  the scholars’ classifications does not
do justice to the depth and breadth of  their research, it must neverthe-
less be recognized that the scholars themselves engineered their research
precisely towards these robust, decisive and portable conclusions, and as
such subsequent studies have for many years been fully justified in referring
simply to James’s four, or Stace’s seven defining points. In appraising this
inconclusive list of classifications, therefore, the vision of  Borges’ Chinese
98 Chapter Two

encyclopaedia is again evoked. Taxonomies and lists of definitions seek to


order and classify the particular elements under scrutiny, and in this respect
they may both be considered, in a manner that so appealed to Borges, maps
of reality. However, these catalogues of definitions taken individually sub-
vert the pretence to order through employing defining terms that themselves
require further definition, such as ‘objective’ or ‘inef fable’; whilst taken as
a composite – as Daniels (2003) and I have done – the list becomes wild
and unwieldy and characterized by contradiction.

Was Borges a mystic?

Therefore, I ask again, was Borges a mystic? Borges himself would answer
brusquely – of course not! Yet when we scrutinize the scholarship, we
encounter many markers that would, indeed, qualify him for the term; and
in order to address this question, one would need to position the reading
of  Borges’ texts – including his autobiographical sketches in interviews –
alongside the many systems of classification. Underhill’s insistence upon the
intuitive approach over and above the intellectual or the theoretical would
fit only uneasily with an approach to mysticism concerning Borges, who,
as we have seen, praised the intellectual capacity of  Swedenborg and Blake
above all other qualities. Williamson (2004: 444) records how Borges was
keen to seek the guidance from Shinto monks while in Japan.10 His desire

10 ‘During a visit to the Rioan-ji Temple, a centre of  Zen Buddhism, he met a monk,
Morinaga Yushoku, with whom he had the most searching conversation of his entire
visit to Japan. As with the nun, Borges wished to learn something of Yushoku’s com-
mitment to the contemplative life, but above all he wanted to know whether the
monk had ever experienced a mystical enlightenment. María recalled that Borges kept
pressing this point, and Yushoku replied that he had twice experienced nirvana but
that it was impossible to convey such an experience to someone who had not himself 
found enlightenment. All the same, Borges described to the monk an experience he
had undergone one night in the 1920s while roaming the outskirts of  Buenos Aires,
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 99

in particular was to correlate his own timeless moments with the pathways
to enlightenment developed by the religious teachings of  Japan. Borges
refers to Suzuki in the essay ‘El Budismo’ of  Siete Noches as one of  the
leading scholars of  Buddhism in his time, to be applauded furthermore for
revitalizing Zen in his own native Japan. Consequently Suzuki’s equation
of satori and mystical vision is perfectly in tune with Borges’ meditation
on the close af finities between Oriental spiritual practices and western
mystical traditions.
Schopenhauer, whom Borges acclaimed as the most lucid and sound of
all philosophers, argued that mysticism is the origin and also the culmina-
tion of all religion, but that, unlike James’s suggestion of noetic value, no
knowledge is to be derived from the ecstatic mystical state. Indeed, argued
Schopenhauer in The World as Will and Representation (a book of which
Borges was particularly fond), mysticism opposes philosophy and cannot
constitute a pathway to consensual knowledge owing its inherently subjec-
tive rather than objective relationship with the individual.

[…] we see all religions at their highest point end in mysticism and mysteries, that
is to say, in darkness and veiled obscurity. These really indicate merely a blank spot
for knowledge, the point where all knowledge necessarily ceases. Hence for thought
this can be expressed only by negations, but for sense-perception it is indicated by
symbolical signs, in temples by dim light and silence, in Brahmanism even by the
required suspension of all thought and perception for the purpose of entering into
the deepest communion with one’s own self, by mentally uttering the mysterious
Om. In the widest sense, mysticism is every guidance to the immediate awareness

when the sight of a particular moonlit street had induced a preternatural sense that
time was an illusion [‘Sentirse en muerte’ (‘Feeling in Death’)]. Might such an epi-
sode qualify as a mystical illumination? That was possible, came the reply, since an
illumination could be prompted by any number of  things, such as the ringing of a
bell or the sound of water f lowing over a stone, but true enlightenment would entail a
complete transformation of  the soul and would change everything in a man’s life. The
monk explained that one must dispel the illusion of selfhood in order to experience
enlightenment: our sense of personal identity was the product of our conditioning,
but otherwise there was nothing within us, not basis for the existence of  the self,
and so one must shed all notions of individuality and start again from zero before
one could reach nirvana’ (Williamson 2004: 443).
100 Chapter Two

of  that which is not reached by either perception or conception, or generally by


any knowledge. The mystic is opposed to the philosopher by the fact that he begins
from within, whereas the philosopher begins from without. The mystic starts from
his inner, positive, individual experience, in which he finds himself as the eternal
and only being, and so on. But nothing of  this is communicable except the asser-
tions that we have to accept on his word; consequently he is unable to convince.
(Schopenhauer 1966: 610)

Borges, as we shall see, would appear to agree with this sentiment with
regards his own mystical, ‘timeless’ experiences, and one might argue
that the repeated fictional representations of  that state – the Aleph and
Tzinacán’s ecstasy – were means of objectifying and thereby abstracting
the inef fability of  the experience. Consequently one might suggest that
Borges was a mystic in the Schopenhauerian sense. However, Schopenhauer
emphasizes the ‘blank spot for knowledge’, which would entail a contrary
position to James’s ‘noetic value’. We will explore in the following chapter
the degree to which Borges assumed that knowledge may or may not be
derived from the mystical experience. Schopenhauer, although rarely cited
in the scholarship of mysticism, nevertheless identified a binary division
that pervades all approaches to mysticism, what Daniels (2003) labels
Essentialism versus Constructivism. This particular division, as we will
also see in Chapter Three, is integral to Borges’ understanding both of  the
mystical texts that he read, and of  his own mystical experiences.
Some definitions of mysticism are complex; others are simple. One
of  the most basic definitions I have encountered comes from Wilson Van
Dusen, Swedenborg scholar and self-avowed mystic:

I use the word mystic in its simplest and most basic sense. A mystic is one who
experiences God. There are other associated meanings and very complex analyses
in religious encyclopaedias, but they all rest in this – the experience of  God. Some
might ask, ‘Don’t all people experience God?’ And I would answer yes, but many
are not aware of it. The mystic is aware of it. (Van Dusen 1995: 105)

Compelling as this is, we are nevertheless still in the dark non-consensual


waters when we try to establish what Van Dusen means by God. This, as
most people would agree, is far from easy. Van Dusen, therefore, falls into
the trap of defining one problematic term with another. His perspective,
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 101

however, is perfectly aligned with Ellwood (1999: 2): ‘For others direct
experience of  God is the pinnacle of what religion is all about. Experiences
like these are often called mystical experiences’. Did Borges have direct
experience with God? Flynn (2009) was only able to identify the cease-
less philosophical search for God, not the encounter. Borges would argue
with reference to Shaw that ‘God is in the making’, and hence the divine
is immanent, not transcendent, and within the human soul. It is unlikely
that such an expression would chime with the more orthodox Zaehner.
Ellwood, however, appears fully cognizant of the problem inherent in defin-
ing mysticism, poignantly remarking that: ‘What is it that thousands of
other accounts of  transcendent experience have or do not have in common?
A host of scholars have wrestled with this question in attempting to define
mysticism and mystical experience’ (1999: 15).
Alan Watts describes the mystical experience as the opposite of  feel-
ing ‘that one is a separate individual in confrontation with a world that is
foreign to one’s self, that is “not me.” In the mystical kind of experience,
though, that separate individual finds itself  to be of one and the same nature
or identity as the outside world. In other words the individual no longer
feels a stranger in the world; rather, the external world feels as if it were his
or her own body’ (2006: 35). The crucial aspect here in relation to Watts
is the notion of  harmony and purpose: ‘It is the overwhelming sense that
everything that happens – everything that I or anybody else has done – is
part of a harmonious design and that there is no error at all’ (2006: 36). Be
that as it may, in tune with Borges, the reason for life need not be neces-
sarily to accomplish any thing directed by a divine will – the purpose may
simply to be alive. ‘The mystic has seen that the meaning of  being alive is
just to be alive’ (2006: 37). Furthermore, owing to Borges’ inherently ludic
quality, he would fit with Watts’ description of  the mystic: ‘The mystic is
the person who has realised that the game is a game’ (2006: 39).
As identified, these definitions cannot be considered conclusive, not
least owing to the contradictions amongst them when read as a body.
Likewise, as identified, the practices or experiences that are proposed that
are categorically not mystical experiences cannot be considered either so
easily identifiable or definable, nor so necessarily removed from the mystical
experience. Most of  the features of anomalous experiences that Stace would
102 Chapter Two

so firmly assert do not constitute the mystical are, indeed, the prominent
features of many mystics appraised in the scholarship: Swedenborg, for
example, was a dedicated practitioner of  breath control similar to yogic
techniques, seemingly with no knowledge of eastern practices (Van Dusen
1974: 19–21). One might argue, consequently, that his mystical experi-
ences were induced and therefore not at all passive in the Jamesian sense.
His psychic abilities are described above, and yet they cannot be divorced
from his explorations of  the realm of  the dead – indeed such explora-
tions are the psychic abilities. Lastly, his remarkably lucid dreams are of
paramount importance, as they both herald the onset of a mystical experi-
ence yet also provide the very doorway into these other landscapes. In the
case of  Swedenborg, therefore, breath control, psychic abilities and lucid
dreaming – added to his meditative constitution, his dazzling intellect,
his energy and determination, his vast knowledge of  the Bible and, let us
not overlook, his wealth – were all factors that together constituted the
mystic. Therefore it would seem pernickety to isolate his talents as being
individually not mystic, corporately mystic. The purpose of  this preamble
concerning Swedenborg is not to demonstrate that Borges was divested
with similar talents, but to give some platform from which to demonstrate
that those talents that Borges did have are not so easily consigned to the
category of mere ‘mystery-mongering’ (Stace 1960), and may be appraised
as manifest mystical attributes.

Borges the lucid dreamer

Borges was a remarkably consummate lucid dreamer, appearing fully


cognizant of  the dreams whilst dreaming. He discussed a vivid dream to
Barnstone, in which the way out of  the ‘dream of  the maze’ is to sit down
and wait to wake up – a fascinating position. ‘When I realized it and said,
this is the nightmare of  the maze, and since I knew all about it, I wasn’t
taken in by the maze. I merely sat down on the f loor. […] I waited a moment
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 103

and woke up’ (Barnstone 1982: 21).11 This deserves greater consideration
than has been hitherto granted, as the ability to take positive, conscious
decisions within a dream, to the point of choosing to wake and depart
the dream state, is one that few possess and many strive to achieve. Green
(1994), in her ground-breaking study: Lucid dreaming: the paradox of con-
sciousness during sleep, notes that the technique of  lucid dreaming has for
centuries and in many dif ferent cultures been integrally related to matters
of religious experience and spiritual practice, and has been the hallmark
of so many accounts of mystical experiences. Borges also remarks in the
essay on nightmares in Siete Noches that the experience of vivid dreams of
such lucidity that they resemble waking life is an attribute of children (his
nephew) and mystics: ‘Todo corría para él en un solo plano, la vigilia y el
sueño. Lo que nos lleva a otra hipótesis, a la hipótesis de los místicos […].
Para el salvaje [de Frazer] o para el niño los sueños son un episodio de la
vigilia, para los poetas y los místicos no es imposible que toda la vigilia sea
un sueño’ (1989: 223) [‘Everything, waking and dream, occurred to him on
a single plane. This brings us to another, similar but contrary, hypothesis:
that of  the mystics and the metaphysicians. For [Frazer’s] savage and for
the child, dreams are episodes of  the waking life; for poets and mystics, it
is not impossible for all of  the waking life to be a dream’] (1984: 29).12 It
is clear from this and from many other similar assertions of  Borges, that
one of  the central features of  the mystical life, that he himself shared, was
the vivid, lucid, intense dream.

11 He repeats this, almost verbatim, in another interview in the same volume (Barnstone
1982: 73).
12 It must be noted for the record that Weinberger’s translation of this passage is wrong
and radically alters the sense of  the text. Borges writes that his nephew, having
recounted his dream to Borges in which his uncle had appeared: ‘Se interrumpió
bruscamente y agregó: “Decime, ¿qué estabas haciendo en esa casita?”’ (1989: 223).
Weinberger translates: ‘I interrupted him sharply: “Stop making things up about
my house!”’ (1984: 29). Unfortunately the translation contrasts with the sense of 
the passage, as it suggests that Borges was unsympathetic to his nephew’s confusion,
when in the original text he is delighted by it.
104 Chapter Two

Whilst Borges dramatizes the faculty of  lucid dreaming in the fic-
tion of  the mago of  ‘Las ruinas circulares’, a more precise and less dramatic
account, which seems less fictional and more autobiographical, is ‘Episodio
del enemigo’ [‘Episode of  the Enemy’] from Elogio de la sombra. In this
brief  text, the Borges-protagonist is confronted by an ancient rival whom
he has evaded for years. At the point in which the antagonist is about to
murder him, Borges’ only strategy to save himself is to wake up, which he
does. The perennial narrative motif of revealing that it was all a dream,
when correlated with Borges’ comments to Barnstone, further demon-
strates his vivid experience of  lucid dreaming. Furthermore, and whilst I
am aware that we should treat the passages of  Atlas with the same criti-
cal scrutiny as one should treat any of  the Ficciones, nevertheless there is
a strong autobiographical, reminiscent quality to the pieces. In Atlas, as I
remarked in the Introduction, are passages in which Borges recounts dream-
dialogues with the dead, in particular with Haydée Lange. Three lines of
argument can be pursued. Firstly, as mentioned, one may argue that this
is merely a fiction and therefore of no consequence in the meta-fictional
world; secondly, that it was not a fiction per se, but was only a dream and
therefore likewise of no consequence ‘in the real world’. The third line of
argument is of interest to me and was of manifest interest to Borges: that
in this mysterious world many things are possible, such as the persistence
of  the soul after death, and the possibility for that discarnate soul (Lange)
to enter dialogue with an incarnate soul (Borges) through dreams. This last
possibility was of great interest also to Jung, and was explored by him in
his private accounts that became The Red Book. One question that arises in
this work, in relation to Jung’s dream of  his father, was whether he dreamt
of  his father, or whether his father visited him in his dream. Answers to this
question are unlikely to be forthcoming, but the purpose is to show that
such a question was of great concern to Borges, the non-mystic por supuesto;
and yet dream encounters of  this nature were the bedrock of  Swedenborg’s
communication with spirits of  the spirit-world, and were thus integrally
related to those qualities considered mystical.
The importance of dreams and dream-creativity in Borges’ poems and
fictions is well-documented, and indeed, reading through my extensive
notes of  Borges citations that serve as background for this work, I am struck
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 105

by the hundreds of appearances of  the words ‘dream’ and ‘sueño’. There is
scarcely an essay, tale, poem or interview in which Borges does not discuss
the creative possibility of dreams, the timeless dimension encountered, the
epistemological capacity ( James’s ‘noetic’), the traditional ancient dialectic,
from Chuang-Tzu to Calderón and Shakespeare, of  life as a dream, and,
importantly, his intuition that dreams and visions are a pathway to the
eternal. He declares, for example, in the lecture on the nightmare in Siete
Noches, apropos J. W. Dunne’s Experiments with Time: ‘A cada hombre le
está dado, con el sueño, una pequeña eternidad personal que le permite ver
su pasado cercano y su porvenir cercano’ (1989: 222) [‘Each man is given,
in dreams, a little personal eternity which allows him to see the recent past
and the near future’] (1984: 28). Borges concludes the lecture with the
observation ‘que los sueños son una obra estética, quizá la expresión estética
más antigua’ (1989: 231) [‘that dreams are an aesthetic work, perhaps the
most ancient aesthetic expression’] (1984: 40). He describes in ‘Inferno, I,
32’ (El Hacedor) how Dante was touched by the divine in a dream and was
given an image that would crown his poetic cycle (a narrative not dissimilar
from ‘El milagro secreto’). He wrote plentifully about Coleridge’s reverie-
inspired poem Kubla Khan, and he was likewise fascinated by Stevenson’s
account of receiving plots fully formed in his dreams from the Brownies,
whom Stevenson formally acknowledges and thanks.
However, Borges was not merely speculating on the creative power of
dreams, nor was he merely illustrating an abstract idea in his fictions. He
also described receiving poems and plots fully f ledged in his reveries. For
example, he described to Barnstone how the poem ‘El ciervo blanco’ [‘The
White Deer’] came to him in its entirety in a dream: ‘I don’t feel that I
wrote that poem […]. I physically dictated the words. The poem was given
to me, in a dream, some minutes before dawn. At times dreams are pain-
ful and tedious, and I object to their outrage and say, enough, this is only
a dream, stop. But this time it was an oral picture that I saw and heard. I
simply copied it, exactly as it was given to me’ (Barnstone 2000: 30). He
recalled to Burgin that El Hacedor was his favourite book ‘because it wrote
itself ’ (Burgin 1969: 125). He described in other interviews that sonnets
appeared to enter his conscious mind from some apparent source beyond
consciousness; he described dreams and nightmares as being given to him
106 Chapter Two

for the purpose of making poetry; and he repeatedly described the divine
or demonic source of dreams and nightmares. So whilst Underhill might
boldly assert that mysticism is not a term to be applied ‘to “menticulture”
and sorcery, dreamy poetry’, nevertheless we can assess these matters in light
of  their collective relationship to what may be considered a mystical nature.
We are, consequently, in a dif ficult position with mysticism. Too much
worrying about a definition is proscriptive and becomes an exercise of  hair-
splitting. Too little concern for a definition allows any experience to muscle
in under its banner, and the word becomes meaningless. One solution is to
combine together all the defining characteristics as put forward by over a
century of scholars. This then becomes a wild and unwieldy shopping list
riddled with contradictions, and the selection of one defining category
over another becomes either arbitrary or an attempt to match the text with
the theory. Another solution is to seek a general term, generous enough
to embrace the various scholars’ findings, yet limited enough to guarantee
some purchase on the term. This, of course, is what so many scholars have
attempted to do, and yet no unified theory has emerged that does not jar
with some previous attempt at the unified theory. The only workable solu-
tion, therefore, is to enquire exactly why such a definition is required. Is it
in order to assess whether one figure was or was not a mystic, as is Quinn’s
case with Emerson (see Chapter Four)? If so, the response can only be
articulated by stating that, for the purposes of  the present study, the defi-
nition of  the term as of fered by, say, Underhill, or James, will suf fice; but
that this definition is by no means foundational. The conclusion will be,
therefore, that so-and-so was a mystic, according to certain principles of 
James, was not according to the principles of  Underhill, equally was not
according to the principles of  Zaehner, but may have been according to
Stace. Consequently, and notwithstanding its inconsequentiality, in relation
to our investigation into Borges, one might suggest that he was a mystic
and he was not a mystic.
Borges, as we explored in Chapter One, emphasized the authority of 
the mystical experience unmediated by doctrine or dogma, which makes
the experience somehow atextual. He established a forthright distinction
between the ‘authentic’ experiences of  Swedenborg, and the textually-
inspired, and consequently ‘invented’ texts of  Dante. He declared that the
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 107

visions of  Dante could not have occurred in verse, and that Fray Luis de
León was merely mimicking the Song of  Songs. His own ‘mystical’ experi-
ences he described as being ‘genuine’ and therefore likewise unmediated by
prior textual assumptions. I suggested that this distinction is itself  highly
problematic because it implies that an experience may be free from textual
inspiration – a position that appears contradictory to the whole Borges
project, where texts inspire experiences, experiences inspire texts, texts are
experiences and experiences are texts.
The vast scholarship of mysticism concentrates on approaching the
mystical experience through a variety of epistemological avenues: historical,
theological, psychological (and psychopathological), sociological, philo-
sophical, and phenomenological. Inge, James, Underhill, Zaehner, Stace,
Otto, Watts, Staal, and other scholars, in their variegated and thorough
approaches to the fields of mysticism, move towards helpful categorical
distinctions of  the mystical experience. Yet despite this comprehensive
critical approach, few scholars appear to have considered the complex
dynamic concerning experience, recollection, textual reproduction of  the
experience, and the ensuing act of reading. Where is the mystical moment?
Is there a transmission through these levels? Can there be betrayal of  the
experience, falsehood, parody? Can the putative mystical experience be
invented? If so, and allowing the noetic value of  the imagination as sug-
gested by Blake, Jung, Corbin and Borges himself, can the invention of a
mystical text constitute for the inventor a mystical experience? Stace (1960:
9) was emphatic that the mystic ‘always mean[s] a person who himself  has
had mystical experience’ and that the word should not be applied simply
to ‘anyone who is sympathetic to mysticism’. This would imply that the
mystical encounter is between the experiencer (mystic) and the experience
(mystical state) and not between the textual account of the experience and
the reader or scholar. How do we define the mystical text itself ? William
James, for example, defines ‘inef fability’ as one of  the four attributes of 
the mystical experience, yet can ef fability be given such a clear category?
If  the experience is truly inef fable then both the mystic and the reader of 
the mystic’s text rely on a textual approximation of  the experience, not the
experience itself; and thus a highly accomplished writer would be capable of
crafting a text closer to the experience than one inexperienced in expressive
108 Chapter Two

writing. That is to say, if a mystic is a poor writer or narrator, does he/she


cease to be considered a mystic if  the experience is so poorly related? We
recall that Borges dismissed Weatherhead on being a ‘mediocre’ writer.
And is not the reader’s response also an indicator of precision of  the text?
That is to say, if a text of seeming senselessness is understood by a reader,
does the original mystical experience now cease to have been inef fable?
If  the experience were truly inef fable, then what does the text describe
other than precisely that which was not the experience? I would argue,
furthermore, that it is precisely the ef fability – or clarity – of  Swedenborg
that Borges enthuses about.

‘Sentirse en muerte’ and the vision of  the Aleph:


fiction and reality

Thus I wish to emphasize the role of  the text, and in order to do so, and in
order to address more fully the position maintained by Stace of distinguish-
ing mystic from scholar, I shall compare two ‘mystical’ texts of Borges – one
‘real’ and one ‘fictional’, allowing for the permeability of  these terms. The
first, which he labelled ‘sentirse en muerte’, is a purportedly honest (i.e.
non-fictional) account of a moment of eternity that Borges experienced as
a young man. It is the experience that he later discussed with Barnstone as
one of  his ‘mystical moments’ and which, according to Williamson (2004:
444), spurred him to an exploration of its meaning with Japanese Shinto
monks in 1979. The second is the oft-quoted mystical moment in ‘El Aleph’,
an invented, fictional account of ecstatic vision which Borges described as
based on his ‘reading about time and eternity’ (Burgin 1998: 212). By the
standards that Borges himself applied in his appraisal of  Swedenborg and
Dante, can we establish that the first passage is ‘authentic’ and the second
not so? My first hypothesis here would be that both are real and both are
textual – indeed both are real because they are both textual. My second posi-
tion would be that the text’s mystical qualities can only be judged through
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 109

an understanding of  the transformative ef fect upon the reader, and that
if  this moment of  textual jouissance is somehow impaired by the reader’s
assumption that the text is merely fictional, then the text, for that reader,
is not mystical. However, as a colleague of mine averred, if  the reading of 
the ‘fictional’ ‘Aleph’ constitutes a truly transformative experience, then, for
that particular reader, the text is manifestly mystical. No cross-referencing
the scholarship of mysticism in order to determine the text’s characteristics
will af fect that. Borges’ emphasis on authenticity and fictionality are thus
unworkable platforms for an understanding of mystical texts. Furthermore,
to muddy the waters even more, I hope to establish that the text of  ‘sentirse
en muerte’ reads like one of  Borges’ fictions, and that both his evaluation
of  his own mystical experience and the experience itself were inf luenced by
Borges’ reading of  James. Consequently, and in tune with Borges’ visions
of  the textual nature of experience, I would argue that the ‘non-fictional’
account is, itself, strikingly fictional.
As Flynn identifies, Borges was clearly moved by his experiences of 
timelessness, motivating him to recount the most profound of  the two in
three separate essays; and in the essay ‘Historia de la Eternidad’ to appraise
the experience as a corollary of  the many treatments of eternity and infin-
ity that he analyses.

The liminal revelation of  the timeless moment in ‘Sentirse en muerte’ recalls the
experience of  the nullity of self and personality which Borges had recounted in ‘La
nadería de la personalidad’. The fundamental dif ference between the two, despite their
shared revelatory character, is that the experience of 1923 is perceived as negative, of
annihilating any notion of oneness and plenitude, whereas the experience of 1928 is
positive, albeit unsustained, and recounted by Borges as addenda to various other texts
over three successive decades. It is what he longs for and yet only ever experiences as
a f leeting state of utter contentedness. ‘Sentirse en muerte’ is about the experience of
a union with, and at the same time a transcendence of, the material universe; at once
becoming one with the material universe, and dissolving its very constituents: time
and selfhood. This is reminiscent of  the mystic who, in union with the divine, passes
from time to eternity. But is Borges’ ecstatic moment a life-transforming, mystical
union with God? It surely is a case of momentary transcendence and may well have
been a spiritual moment that was perhaps over analysed and therefore only wistfully
remembered and reiterated over decades. (Flynn 2009: 65–6)
110 Chapter Two

It is important to note that Flynn suggests that the over-interpretation of 


the moment somehow diminishes the ecstatic nature of  the experience.
This would imply that each level of  textual recreation somehow fictional-
izes the original non-fictional moment and thereby falsifies it. This, as we
will examine, is a highly problematic assertion, as it implies firstly that an
experience may be free of  textual inf luence – something Borges would
refute at once – and secondly, that the textual recreation is necessarily less
authentic than the original experience – an assumption that would nullify
centuries of mystical texts.
Borges foregrounds the essay with an idea that remained a key concern
throughout his life: that the principle metaphysical problem is time. He
postulated, with reference to Plato, that eternity is not ‘una agregación
mecánica del pasado, del presente y del porvenir. Es una cosa más sencilla y
más mágica: es la simultaneidad de esos tiempos’ (1974: 354) [‘a mechanical
aggregate of past, present, and future. Eternity is something simpler and
more magical: the simultaneity of  the three tenses’] (2000: 124). He located
his experience alongside the textual recollections of  Plato, Plotinus and
Augustine of  Hippo. Therefore whilst Borges claimed that Swedenborg
‘cometió un incómodo error cuando resolvió ajustar sus ideas al marco de los
dos Testamentos’ (2005: 155) [‘made an awkward mistake when he decided
to adapt his ideas to the framework of  the two Testaments’] (1995: 9), the
reader will naturally conjecture how far the ideas of  Borges concerning his
experience were adapted to the ideas of  Plotinus.

Deseo registrar aquí una experiencia que tuve hace unas noches: fruslería demasiado
evanescente y extática para que la llame aventura; demasiado irrazonable y sentimental
para pensamiento. Se trata de una escena y de su palabra: palabra ya antedicha por
mí, pero no vivida hasta entonces con entera dedicación de mi yo. Paso a historiarla,
con los accidentes de tiempo y de lugar que la declararon. (1974: 365–6)

[I wish to record an experience I had a few nights ago: a triviality too evanescent
and ecstatic to be called an adventure, too irrational and sentimental for thought.
It was a scene and its word: a word I had spoken but had not fully lived with all my
being until then. I will recount its history and the accidents of  time and place that
revealed it to me.] (2000: 137)
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 111

What was this word, with which he was familiar in theory but not in
practical experience? In tune with the essay, the word would be ‘eternity’,
but in tune with other essays, it would be ‘mysticism’. Borges makes firm
declarations about the nature of  the experience. It was too f lighty to be
called adventure, which would chime immediately with James’s decree of 
‘transiency’. We recall that it was the extensive duration of  Dante’s vision,
the fact that it was not transient (plus the versification) that led Borges to
suggest that Dante was not a mystic. Borges’ experience was also too full of 
feeling, too removed from reason, to be called a thought. This would appear
perfectly cognate with James’s category of  ‘inef fable’, which James quali-
fies as ‘[t]he subject of it immediately says that it defies expression, that no
adequate report of its contents can be given in words. […] its quality must
be directly experienced; it cannot be imparted or transferred to others. In
this peculiarity mystical states are more like states of  feeling than like states
of intellect’ (1913: 380). However, he describes a great many thoughts that
he had whilst undergoing this experience; or are these the thoughts that
he had when recalling the experience?
The passage itself is highly textual, reading like one of  his tales; with
familiar symbols that he notes are symbols in his fiction: the dark grasslands
of  the South, the lonely streets of  the rough suburbs, the humble houses,
the scattered symbols of  the bird and crickets. ‘No quiero significar así el
barrio mío, el preciso ámbito de la infancia, sino sus todavía misteriosas
inmediaciones: confín que he poseído entero en palabras y poco en reali-
dad, vecino y mitológico a un tiempo’ (1974: 366) [‘I am not alluding to
my own neighborhood, the precise circumference of my childhood, but
to its still mysterious outskirts; a frontier region I have possessed fully in
words and very little in reality, at once adjacent and mythical’] (2000:
137). He feels that he is walking in a landscape already made literature
by him. He is therefore the character in a fiction, and everything is being
fictionalized by him, either at the point of experience or in its retelling:
‘No habrá manera de nombrar la ternura mejor que ese rosado’ (1974: 366)
[‘Tenderness could have no better name than that rose color’] (138). This
is qualified by his inability to escape literary allusion in the text: ‘me alejó
hacia unos barrios, de cuyo nombre quiero siempre acordarme’ (1974: 366)
[‘gravitation pushed me toward neighborhoods whose name I wish always
112 Chapter Two

to remember’] (2000: 137), and one wonders whether this Cervantine line
came to him at the point of  the experience, during a reminiscence, or at
the point of writing the text.

Pensé, con seguridad en voz alta: Esto es lo mismo de hace treinta años. […] El fácil
pensamiento Estoy en mil ochocientos y tantos dejó de ser unas cuantas aproximativas
palabras y se profundizó a realidad. Me sentí muerto, me sentí percibidor abstracto
del mundo: indefinido temor imbuido de ciencia que es la mejor claridad de la meta-
física. No creí, no, haber remontado las presuntivas aguas del Tiempo; más bien me
sospeché poseedor del sentido reticente o ausente de la inconcebible palabra eternidad.
Sólo después alcancé a definir esa imaginación. (1974: 366–7)

[I stood there looking at this simplicity. I thought, undoubtedly aloud: ‘This is


the same as it was thirty years ago.’ […] The glib thought I am in the year eighteen
hundred and something ceased to be a few approximate words and deepened into
reality. I felt as the dead feel, I felt myself  to be an abstract observer of  the world; an
indefinite fear imbued with knowledge that is the greater clarity of metaphysics. No,
I did not believe I had made my way upstream on the presumptive waters of  Time.
Rather, I suspected myself  to be in possession of  the reticent or absent meaning of 
the inconceivable word eternity. Only later did I succeed in defining this figment of
my imagination.] (2000: 138)

These seemingly innocent expressions of description are deceptively com-


plex. Was he experiencing something that he was fully able to comprehend
and assimilate at the time of  the experience? Was it the recollection after
the event (prior to the writing) that was now problematic? Or was it the
moment of recording the experience in words where its full inef fability
is felt? It would appear from these brief descriptions of  his thought pro-
cesses at the time that he was fully cognizant of  the experience as it was
unfolding, and that the words began to fail him only at a later moment of 
textual recording. Be that as it may, Borges’ mastery of style would suggest
that he was not lost for words, that he was able to capture the experience,
and that consequently the experience was not inef fable. It is impossible
to say how close the textual description is to the experience. Inef fability
is a tricky word.
As discussed in the beginning of  this chapter, the impact of  this epi-
sode (plus another un-narrated one) upon Borges was tremendous, and
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 113

motivated him to seek deeper knowledge of  the experience years later in
Japan. One would suggest that the experience also fuelled his interest in
mystical writers across the world’s literatures. And yet can we consider
this episode to have been, as Borges emphasizes with Swedenborg, some-
how outside of  textual inf luence? As we have seen, the episode conforms
closely to two of  James’s categories: transiency and passivity. Its inef fability
is impossible to judge, as without being Borges we are in no position to
determine the proximity between the textual reproduction and the expe-
rience itself. Its ‘noetic value’ – an arbitrary definition, to be sure – would
appear to be codified into Borges’ philosophical perspective regarding
the f lexibility of  time. Indeed his inclusion of  this episode in the various
essays would demonstrate his consideration of it as an ideal case study to
defend his radical theories of  time. The inclusion of  the passage in the
essay ‘Historia de la Eternidad’ indicates the relationship with the many
philosophical accounts of eternity that Borges encountered in literature,
and his own transient experience. As Kripal argues about the scholarship
of mysticism, James, Underhill and other writers were only able to explore
the nebulous fields of mysticism with such integrity because the texts they
read chimed so closely with their own, often unstated, mystical experiences.
Would Borges the reader, however, judge his own text as a fiction? This
is an important question based, as discussed, on his division of  Dante and
Swedenborg into the fictional (poetic) and the non-fictional (authentic).
Firstly, this may be merely a question of style: many readers across the
decades have been unsettled by the exquisitely realist nature of some of 
Borges’ tales in which time’s f lexibility is explored. ‘El encuentro’ [‘The
Meeting’] from El Libro de Arena concerns the young and the old Borges
sitting by a river each attempting to establish who is dreaming who. Its
realism makes it uncanny, and yet we read it as a fiction primarily because,
despite its outlandishness, it accompanies a selection of  fantastic tales in
the volume. Yet were it to have been included as an episode in one or more
philosophical essays (as in the case of  ‘sentirse en muerte’) and were Borges
to have discussed it autobiographically in interviews, then our interpreta-
tive position would be dif ferent. It is thus the contextual quality beyond
the textual that will determine the reader’s judgment of authenticity. The
sister tale to El encuentro is ‘Veinticinco de agosto, 1983’, from La Memoria
114 Chapter Two

de Shakespeare (1980), which has received so little critical attention it could


have been written by an unknown writer. This oneiric Swedenborg-inspired
tale has only the vaguest pretence to realism, and thus, whilst still haunting
and unsettling, nevertheless is evidently fictional. But is it any less mystical
for its fictionality? In order to explore this question further, the episode
of  ‘sentirse en muerte’ can be appraised alongside the particular ecstatic
episode of  the Borges-narrator of  ‘El Aleph’ (a tale, it must be emphasized,
included in Kodama’s edited volume On Mysticism).
The scholarship on ‘El Aleph’ is too vast to enumerate, and no stone
has been left unturned in pursuing the many cryptic, cabalistic, literary and
autobiographical pathways and references that are embedded in this per-
plexing text. Wilson (2006: 46), for example, argues that ‘Borges’s wicked
mockery of  Gómez de la Serna as “Alef ” is hidden (few literary critics have
noted this)’, and that the tale is a mere ‘study in literary and sexual envy.’
What is of interest here, however, is not to wander in the literary labyrinth
of  the tale, but to consider the well-identified uselessness of mysticism that is
presented; something Bossart (2003: 146) associates also with ‘El Zahir’ and
dubs ‘“failed enlightenment,” [by which] I mean those occasions on which
the conditions for enlightenment seem to be present but are not utilized.
“The Zahir” and “The Aleph” are two examples of such a situation’. Whilst
I find Bossart’s term problematic, for the simple reason stated above that it
is not at all clear how we should interpret a putative ‘successful’ enlighten-
ment, nevertheless I would agree with Bossart, Alazraki and others that
the tale constitutes an overall sense of  failure and futility. Annette Flynn
encapsulates this sentiment in acknowledging that the powerful epiphany
depicted in the tale is, essentially, useless: ‘The experience of divine vision
is ultimately inconsequential’ (2009: 6).
I would argue that a prominent aspect of  the tale is the slightly mel-
ancholy mocking of  textual attempts to capture the moment of mystical
rapture. Does Daneri have a mystical experience? One would assume so,
if  his experience was similar to the Borges-narrator’s. Is he consequently a
mystic? Absolutely not, as all he is capable of performing as a consequence
is clumsy, verbose and voluminous poetry. But, we must ask, is his poetic
output the only measure of  his character, and is the description of  his char-
acter the only measure of whether he was or was not a mystic? I doubt a
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 115

single of  the myriad readers of  the tale could ever have considered Daneri
a mystic – his character is too asinine, what Molloy (1994: 54) describes
as ‘an af fected middle-brow braggart’ – and thus one must assume that as
readers we have already made the basic assumption that a mystical experi-
ence does not necessarily make a mystic. This essential assumption forms
the basis of another tremendous debate that has dominated the scholarship
of mysticism since William James and which fuelled Underhill’s critique of 
James: the relationship between drugs (psychedelics) and mystical states
(see Huston Smith [2000], Rowlandson [2013]). Cohen (1973: 83) perhaps
alludes to this matter when suggesting that ‘“The Zahir” and “The Aleph”
describe false ways of inducing vision which, as Borges admits, produce false
or partial, and always terrible, experiences.’ Such a statement is reminiscent
of so much of  the literature (Underhill, Zaehner, Von Franz) in which psy-
chedelic experiences are described as ‘false’ pathways towards knowledge,
or the divine. Núñez-Faraco (2006: 47) is the only critic to my knowledge
to have likened the experience of  the Aleph to a drug-induced vision, sug-
gesting that the use of  the words ‘veneno’ and ‘narcótico’ ‘is particularly
interesting for its many literary associations, both ancient and modern’;
and whilst a case could be made that Borges may have been aware of, for
example, James’s description of  the state of nitrous oxide intoxication, this is
not my purpose here. It is pertinent, I would argue, simply to highlight the
basic postulation, related to Bossart’s ‘failed enlightenment’, that a mystic
is characterized as a mystic not for the experiences he has undergone, but
for some visible manifestation of  those experiences upon his character and
behaviour. Furthermore, such assumptions would not necessarily correlate
with the definitions of  William James, who, unlike Stace and Pahnke,
did not appraise the legacy of  the experience upon the individual beyond
the notion of  ‘noetic value’. Had Daneri composed splendid poetry, like
Dante, San Juan de la Cruz or William Blake, would the noetic value be
of greater worth here?
The Borges-narrator presents a phenomenological problem with
his description of  the Aleph which exposes the curious relationship
between Borges-author and the Borges-narrator-character. Both identify
the Jamesian ‘inef fable’ quality of a mystical experience, and express the
problem of inef fability as a linguistic problem based not on the lack of
116 Chapter Two

consensual understanding of a word, but of  the non-consensual nature of 


the experience. The Borges-narrator of  ‘El Aleph’ laments that he is unable
to describe fully the experience of  the Aleph because of  the singularity of 
the experience:

Todo lenguaje es un alfabeto de símbolos cuyo ejercicio presupone un pasado que los
interlocutores comparten; […] Los místicos, en análogo trance, prodigan los emble-
mas: para significar la divinidad, un persa habla de un pájaro que de algún modo es
todos los pájaros; Alanus de Insulis, de una esfera cuyo centro está en todas partes y
la circunferencia en ninguna; Ezequiel, de un ángel de cuatro caras que a un tiempo
se dirige al Oriente y al Occidente, al Norte y al Sur. (1974: 624–5)

[All language is a set of symbols whose use among its speakers assumes a shared
past. […] Mystics, faced with the same problem, fall back on symbols: to signify the
godhead, one Persian speaks of a bird that somehow is all birds; Alanus de Insulis,
of a sphere whose center is everywhere and circumference is nowhere; Ezekiel, of
a four-faced angel who at one and the same time moves east and west, north and
south.] (1971a: 26)

Borges (the Borges-author), meanwhile, many years later, would foreground


his exploration of  Swedenborg by identifying the very same phenomeno-
logical problem:

El empleo de cualquier vocablo presupone una experiencia compartida, de la que el


vocablo es el símbolo. Si nos hablan del sabor del café, es porque ya lo hemos probado;
si nos hablan del color amarillo, es porque ya hemos visto limones, oro, trigo y pues-
tas del sol. Para sugerir la inefable unión del alma del hombre con la divinidad, los
sufíes del Islam se vieron obligados a recurrir a alegorías prodigiosas, a imágenes de
rosas, de embriaguez o de amor carnal; Swedenborg pudo renunciar a tales artificios
retóricos, porque su tema no era el éxtasis del alma arrebatada y enajenada, sino la
puntual descripción de regiones ultraterrenas, pero precisas. (2005: 154)

[The use of any word whatsoever presupposes a shared experience, for which the
word is the symbol. If someone speaks to us about the f lavor of cof fee, it is because
we have already tasted it; if about the color yellow, because we have already seen
lemons, gold, wheat, and sunsets. To suggest the inef fable union of man’s soul with
the divine being, the Sufis of  Islam found themselves obliged to resort to prodigious
analogies, to images of roses, intoxication, or carnal love. Swedenborg was able to
abstain from this kind of rhetorical artifice because his subject matter was not the
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 117

ecstasy of a rapt and fainting soul but, rather, the accurate description of regions
that, though ultra-terrestrial, were clearly defined.] (1995: 7)13

Importantly, and as already examined, Borges implies here that Swedenborg


was unlike other mystics because his experiences were essentially ef fable.
Following the logic of  this argument, if  Swedenborg had no need to resort
to symbolic approximations to the experience, this would imply that his
language ‘presupposes a shared experience’; a problematic assertion, to
be sure, when the reader is confronted with discarnate souls and angels
discussing theology. It is apparent that the Borges-author of  ‘El Aleph’
speaks through the Borges-narrator with similar concerns about the tex-
tual inspiration behind the description of a mystical experience that we
analysed in Chapter One. As with Borges’ claims about Swedenborg’s
non-literary textual description of  his otherworld journeys, so the Borges-
narrator of  ‘El Aleph’ consciously chooses not to resort to the poetic sym-
bols employed by Alanus de Insulis (Alain de Lille) or Ezekiel so as to keep
his text somehow pure and ‘uncontaminated’ by the inf luence of  their texts.
‘Quizá los dioses no me negarían el hallazgo de una imagen equivalente,
pero este informe quedaría contaminado de literatura, de falsedad’ (1974:
625) [‘Perhaps the gods might grant me a similar metaphor, but then this
account would become contaminated by literature, by fiction’] (1971a: 26).

13 Borges argues this elsewhere, in another essay on Swedenborg from 1978: ‘Hay una
diferencia esencial entre Swedenborg y los otros místicos. En el caso de San Juan de
la Cruz, tenemos descripciones muy vividas del éxtasis. Tenemos el éxtasis referido en
términos de experiencias eróticas o con metáforas de vino. Por ejemplo, un hombre
que se encuentra con Dios, y Dios es igual a sí mismo. Hay un sistema de metáforas.
En cambio, en la obra de Swedenborg no hay nada de eso. Es la obra de un viajero
que ha recorrido tierras desconocidas y que las describe tranquila y minuciosamente’
(2005: 200) [‘There is an essential dif ference between Swedenborg and the other
mystics. In the case of  St John of  the Cross, we have very vivid descriptions of ecstasy.
Ecstasy referred to in erotic terms or with metaphors of wine. For example, a man
encounters God, and God is the same as the man. There is a system of metaphors.
In the work of  Swedenborg, on the other hand, there is none of  this. It is the work
of a traveller who has explored unknown lands and who describes them in precise
detail’] (my translation).
118 Chapter Two

The Borges-narrator is thus making the same assumptions that we later find
in Borges’ many statements about Pascal, Dante, Luis de León, Juan de la
Cruz and Weatherhead; that their texts are somehow ‘non-mystical’ or even
‘false’ because they are literary – i.e. textually-inspired. As discussed in the
previous chapter, this is a perplexing conundrum, as it implies both the
possibility of a non-literary text and, more subtle yet equally Borgesian, the
possibility of a non-textual experience. Despite, therefore, his knowledge
of de Lille and Ezekiel, the Borges-narrator is suggesting not only that his
description of  the vision of  the Aleph in the basement of  Daneri’s house was
somehow free of prior textual inf luence, but that the experience itself was
somehow free of  this inf luence. As suggested earlier, this division between
experience and textual account of  the experience, which can constitute
a tremendous gulf, is scarcely addressed in the scholarship of mysticism.
It is abundantly clear that the ecstatic passage at the heart of  ‘El Aleph’,
‘[e]l inefable centro de mi relato’, is absurd, and, akin to the absurdity of 
Funes’ perpetual ecstasy, constitutes a parodic inversion of possible mys-
tical rapture. Whilst we may assert that Borges was employing a fictional
space in order to appraise his own prior experience, so may we justifiably
argue that the tale is merely an exquisitely crafted parody of mysticism; and
whilst Borges praised Estela Canto for appreciating that the text was mys-
tical, so Borges himself argued that it was nothing more than an invented
tale inspired by his reading material. Borges explains the artifice, or the
invention, of  this passage:

A man in Spain asked me whether the aleph actually existed. Of course it doesn’t. He
thought the whole thing was true. I gave him the name of  the street and the number
of  the house. He was taken in very easily. […] That piece gave me great trouble, yes.
I mean, I had to give a sensation of endless things in a single paragraph. Somehow,
I got away with it.
Q: Is that an invention, the aleph, or did you find it in some reference?
No. I’ll tell you, I was reading about time and eternity. Now eternity is supposed to
be timeless. I mean, God or a mystic perceives in one moment all of our yesterdays,
Shakespeare says, all the past, all the present, all the future. And I said, why not
apply that, well, that invention to another category, not to time, but to space? Why
not imagine a point in space wherein the observer may find all the rest. I mean, who
invented space? And that was the central idea. Then I had to invent all the other
things, to make it into a funny story, to make it into a pathetic story, that came
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 119

afterwards. My first aim was this: in the same way that many mystics have talked of
eternity … that’s a big word, an eternity, an everness. And also neverness; that’s an
awful word. Since we have an idea of eternity, of  foreverness in time, why not apply
the same idea to space, and think of a single point in space wherein the whole of
space may be found? I began with that abstract idea, and then, somehow, I came to
that quite enjoyable story. (Burgin 1998: 212)

Such is the power of  the fiction that the man in Spain failed to perceive
the artifice and sought the actual Aleph. One must assume, therefore, that
fact or fiction, genuine or imagined, the tale clearly is capable of delivering
a tremendous impact upon the reader. J. M. Cohen (1973: 81), meanwhile,
argued that Borges was attempting to mimic the ecstasies of  Böhme: ‘The
idea for the Aleph itself came, I believe, from a passage in the biography of 
Jakob Boehme which describes his first illumination in 1599. It is quoted
by William James in his Varieties of  Religious Experience.’ This is a power-
ful statement, as it implies not only a familiarity with the mystical text of 
Böhme, but also with James’ scholarship of mysticism, something we will
explore in the next chapter.
Likewise, whilst it has been suggested that Borges was searching for a
fictional text in which to explore his own ‘timeless’ moment (‘sentirse en
muerte’), the inef fable centre of  ‘El Aleph’ appears less a reaction to his
own personal experience than to the philosophical perplexity caused by the
gulf  between personal experience and textual accounts of mystical ecstasy.
Countless responses to ‘El Aleph’, from academic articles and book chapters,
to biographical accounts and reviews, describe the central episode as being
mystical. Canto and Kodama, as mentioned above, both identify a strong
mystical dimension to it; Alazraki calls the Aleph a ‘mystic symbol’ (1988:
49); Jason Wilson (2006: 16–17) considers it an extensive ‘Buddhist joke’
ridiculing the inability to capture Nirvana, and qualifying this perspective
by suggesting that this is the predicament that mystics encounter.

Buddhism also warns that language cannot communicate Nirvana, the void beyond
appearances. Truth is not found in words; Borges’s greatest fable, the fiction ‘The
Aleph’, is also a Buddhist joke. The vision granted to Borges under the staircase in the
story cannot be recreated in sequential words, despite Borges’s lists. Only a mystic
outside time can see everything at once, but then cannot communicate it.
120 Chapter Two

Yet is the text truly mystical? The ecstatic heart of  the tale evokes the vision-
ary raptures of  Meister Eckhart, Hildegard of  Bingen or Teresa de Ávila.
In particular, and ref lecting Borges’ familiarity with the poetry of  William
Blake, the tale may appear to suggest Blake’s ‘Auguries of  Innocence’: ‘To see
a world in a grain of sand, / And a heaven in a wild f lower, / Hold infinity
in the palm of your hand, / And eternity in an hour’. Despite these illus-
trious antecedents, the tale’s complex intertextuality and its metatextual
gameplaying with regards literary figures of  Argentine letters (Williamson
2004) provide a context in which the mystical rapture appears wantonly
parodic to the extent of ridicule. It is also the most extreme of images –
the vision of  totality. Amidst the mundane context of a basement in a
soon-to-be-demolished house belonging to a pompous poet, the narrator
appears to experience a vision of  totality that far exceeds even the most
sublime descriptions of visionary poets. Whereas Henry Vaughan’s cosmic
poem ‘A vision’ (1650) begins ‘I saw Eternity the other Night’, this poem
is generally considered a dream-like poetic image rather than the descrip-
tion of a genuine experience. The Borges-narrator, however, is attempting
not poetry (that is Daneri’s hapless task) but prosaic description. It is,
therefore, by Borges’ own standards, genuine. Borges presents something
beyond our most basic powers of cognition. What can it possibly mean to
see everything? ‘Everything’ as a word and as a concept becomes meaning-
less, as there can be no division between one ‘thing’ of totality and another.
The vision of  ‘El Aleph’ becomes as harrowingly impossible as Funes’ total
memory – it simply cannot be.14 Consequently, the enumeration of  the
things that the Borges-narrator does see is ridiculous, as it is like measuring
an inch in infinity. It is neither a portion of totality nor any approximation
of it. The vision of  the Aleph is a nominalist chaos, where ultimately all
we have is a random succession of words and no things in themselves. He
may just as well have listed twenty other things, or twenty further things,
ad infinitum. Or no things at all.

14 The hyperbolic nature of  the vision of  the Aleph is similar to Douglas Adams’ torture
device ‘the Total Perspective Vortex’ from The Hitchhiker’s Guide to the Galaxy, in
which the victim is annihilated through being forced to see himself in relation to
the enormity of  the cosmos.
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 121

Conclusion

As established, it is something of a mainstay in the scholarship of mysti-


cism to produce specific defining characteristics. What had scarcely been
addressed until Kripal (2001), however, is the inseparable relationship
between the scholar him/herself and the articulation of  the approach to
mysticism. Dean Inge’s perspectives on mysticism, for example, are inevi-
tably bound up with his adherence to Anglican orthodoxy.15 For example,
he rejects outright the ‘heresy’ of which Borges professed, that of  ‘God in
the making’:

The common assumption that God is so bound up with the world that it is as neces-
sary to Him as He is to it is incompatible with mysticism. The Supreme, whether we
call it God or with Plotinus the One or with Eckhart the Godhead, or with some
moderns the Absolute, is transcendent. The notion that God is evolving with His
universe, coming into His own, realizing Himself, or emerging, owes its popular-
ity to ‘the last Western heresy,’ the idea that the macrocosm is moving towards ‘one
far-of f divine event.’ There can be no process of  the Absolute, no progress, and no
change. Exhortations to take time seriously may be in place when we are dealing
with history; but to subordinate the Eternal to space and time is a fatal error in
metaphysics. (Inge 1947: 154)

William James cannot be separated from his upbringing amidst New


England Transcendentalism, Evelyn Underhill is in so many ways her-
self  the focus of  her whole system of investigation. This is not such an
obvious statement as it could appear, as in many cases the philosophical,
religious, political or even cultural assumptions and belief systems of  the
scholars feed into their scholarship in subtle ways. Sometimes, however,

15 Note that Russell (1961: 179) mocks Inge’s favouring of  Christian mysticism over
the mysticism of other faiths: ‘The chief argument in favour of  the mystics is their
agreement with each other. “I know nothing more remarkable,” says Dean Inge, “than
the unanimity of  the mystics, ancient, mediaeval, and modern, Protestant, Catholic,
and even Buddhist or Mohammedan, though the Christian mystics are the most
trustworthy.”’
122 Chapter Two

such positions are at once visible. Staal, for example, identifies this striking
feature of  Zaehner, arguing that his religious beliefs led him to a narrow
view of other beliefs and practices. ‘The main dif ficulty with this book as a
whole [Zaehner’s Hindu & Muslim Mysticism (1960)] is the author’s own
religious allegiance, which clearly prevents a fair and adequate description
and evaluation of dif fering points of view and which leads the author to
a classification which is nothing but a ref lection of  his own belief ’ (1975:
67). Zaehner similarly weighed into the debate on mysticism and psych-
edelics with a level of invective that revealed deep-seated moral concerns
with the proposal that mystical states are achievable through such means.
Zaehner criticized Huxley’s exuberant use of words from Catholic and
Hindu traditions, arguing that Huxley had no right to make these bold
declarations about ‘gratuitous grace’, ‘Beatic state’ or ‘one-ness’, as these
are matters of spiritual practice within established traditions of  faith. The
mescaline experience, he argued, aside from specific Native American tra-
ditions, lies outside established traditions of  faith. It is clear that Zaehner
is arguing not from a phenomenological position – i.e. is a mystical state
possible with mescaline – but a theological – is such a state permissible.
There is also the tendency present within the whole scholarship of
mysticism to reduce the mystical aspect of a text to mere textual markers,
and to correlate these textual instances against the check-list of  the scholar-
ship of mysticism, such as James, Underhill or Stace. Whilst this may be a
justifiable exercise in attempts to determine whether a text is, for example,
a good example of  Modernist or postcolonial literature, there is something
slightly disjointed when such textual scrutiny occurs with the study of
mysticism, in that the ceaseless attempts to pin it down to the salient char-
acteristics can seem contradictory to the very f luid and mysterious nature
that is, itself, mysticism. There is consequently something exasperating in
running through endless academic approaches to ‘deistic’ or ‘non-deistic’,
‘extravertive or intravertive’, ‘hot’ or ‘cool’, ‘perennialist’ or ‘essentialist’, as
these questions rarely confront actual and pressing ontological questions.
The questions, in my opinion, should not concern whether Emerson was
a ‘religious mystic’ or a ‘nature mystic’, nor whether Swedenborg’s experi-
ences were ‘hot’ or ‘cool’, ‘structured’ or ‘unstructured’ (Rawlinson 1998:
120), but what are we, as readers, to do with his texts? It occurred to me
Was Borges a mystic, and does it matter? 123

that Blake (regardless of whether he was or was not a mystic) would have
railed against so much scholastic inactivity. Swedenborg, likewise, was
highly critical of scholastic debates that served as mere displays of erudi-
tion rather than interrogating the nature of reality,16 and would have been
equally dismayed at seeing his moral theology ignored and his own status
pinned to a graph of  ‘hot unstructured’, or having his experiences forensi-
cally analysed according to whether they satisfy the requirements of  tran-
siency (no), inef fability (no), passivity (no), noetic quality (yes) and so
on. Kripal (2001) has bravely attempted to realign the scholars and their
scholarship with their own mystic-erotic experiences, but even his study
leaves many questions unaddressed concerning the nature of  the mystical
experience itself. The fact that James called the debate one of names is of 
key importance here, as there appears to be an endless circling above the
experience described in the text without the courage to plunge into the
very questions that mysticism itself raises.
Borges was manifestly astonished by his own experiences of  timeless-
ness, and, whilst he may not have engaged in theological discussions with
angels, as Swedenborg did, he nevertheless invested deeply in an aesthetic
and intellectual ef fort to understand the full significance of  his experi-
ences. It is consequently of  little importance whether Borges was or was
not a mystic. What is certain is that Borges experienced many matters that
habitually appear in the repertoire of mystical experiences: a sense of  the
numinous and the inef fable, noesis, ecstasy and a sense of moving outside of 
time, lucid dreams, possible communication with the dead, synchronicities,
awe at the mystery of existence, and other experiences of  ‘intersticios de
sinrazón’. These matters delighted and puzzled him, and his encyclopaedic
reading of other accounts of mystical and anomalous experience, especially

16 ‘If people have loved the academic disciplines only in order to sound learned, with-
out using them to develop their ability to reason, taking delight in their pride at
the contents of  their memories, they love sandy areas and prefer them to meadows
and gardens because sandy areas correspond to these kinds of study. People who are
wrapped up in knowing the doctrines of churches, their own and others’, without
applying them to life, love stony areas and live among rock piles. They avoid culti-
vated land because it is repulsive to them’ (Heaven & Hell §488).
124 Chapter Two

Swedenborg, assisted him in attempting to make sense of such matters.


The beauty of  Borges is that no sense is made at all. The mystic may receive
some sense of  the divine purpose, but as the experience, in Borges’ view, is
inherently inef fable, such revelation can never be transcribed. The universe,
Borges repeatedly maintained, is ultimately mysterious. The mystics seize
this mystery and, despite the inevitability that ultimate answers will not
be forthcoming, devote themselves to this intellectual and intuitive search.
Perhaps as the final word on the long scholarship of mysticism, we might,
like Underhill and Stace, of fer an explanation of precisely what a mystic
is not. It is not, as Borges describes, taking the universe for granted: non-
mystics: ‘take the universe for granted. They take things for granted. They
take themselves for granted. That’s true. They never wonder at anything,
no? They don’t think it’s strange that they should be living’ (1969: 6). This
touching aphorism could be taken as Borges’ poignant contribution to the
long and contradictory scholarship. From such a consideration, one could
suggest that for Borges the mystic is the one who is mystified; the one who
enters the mystery; the one who, at the final measure, is aware of  the mystery.
As I hope to have demonstrated, there is a tendency in the critical stud-
ies of  Borges to make assertions about the mystical or non-mystical nature
both of  himself and of  his texts. Such assertions assume a consensual under-
standing of  the term mystic. However, as I analyse above, not only is there
no consensus, but the term itself is immensely complicated. The most thor-
ough attempt to qualify such an assertion seems to be Howard Giskin, with
his correlation of  Borges texts with the four categories defined by William
James. An analysis as thorough as Giskin’s, though, leaves many questions
unanswered about the relationship between a ‘mystical’ text and the text’s
author, between the fictionality or potential parodic nature of  the text and
its ‘mystical’ attributes, between the wide variety of readers’ responses. It
becomes clear that we cannot rely on a simple set of co-ordinates in order
to establish whether Borges was or was not a mystic, as so many conf licting
avenues of enquiry need to be taken into consideration before any suitable
conclusion is reached. This chapter has attempted to consider certain texts
of  Borges in the light of a number of these variant enquiries into mysticism.
The conclusion is, consequently, notably inconclusive.
Chapter Three

In the shadow of  William James:


Borges as scholar of mysticism

In order to be able to decide if  the prophet is telling the truth or lying,
we shall have to investigate the mystical experience for ourselves. This can
be done in two ways: from the outside, by studying the biographies and
writings of  the saints; and from the inside, by following the instructions
they have given us.
— Christopher Isherwood, Vedanta for The Western World

Was Borges a theorist of mysticism? As established in the previous chapter,


it is characteristic of scholars of mysticism to define the terms ‘mystic’ and
‘mysticism’ by enumerating the salient features following analysis of  both
mystical texts and, in some cases, personal experience. William James’s
four principles are doubtless the best known. Borges is not a name gen-
erally associated with the long tradition of  the scholarship of mysticism,
for the same reason that he is not included, for example, in the Stanford
Encyclopaedia of  Philosophy. This is because he always eschewed defin-
ing a particular theory or method – whether philosophical, theological
or metaphysical – preferring to be considered ‘un mero hombre de letras
y no un investigador o de un teólogo’ (2005: 155) [‘a mere man of  letters
and not a researcher or theologian’] (1995: 8). He af firms this to Burgin
in interview: ‘I’m not sure whether I’m a Christian, but I’ve read a great
many books on theology for the sake of  their theological problems – free
will, punishment, and eternal happiness. All these problems have interested
me as food for my imagination’ (Burgin 1998: 57). Again, therefore, we are
presented with the problem that Borges himself would appear to distance
himself  from a critical appraisal of  the tradition of mysticism whilst, as
126 Chapter Three

discussed in Chapter One, making some forthright assertions about his


interpretation of certain mystical texts.
The question of separating mystic from scholar of mysticism is com-
plicated; and here we can perceive a thread developed by William James,
and running through Walter Stace to Frits Staal. How are we to establish a
suitable distinction between the mystic and the scholar of mysticism? This
may sound self-evident, but if we appraise the question in light of  Borges,
then we can perceive some problematic twists to the analysis. Stace (1960:
9), one of  the most prominent researchers into the variegated field of mys-
ticism, was outspoken in separating the mystic from the scholar.

By the word ‘mystic’ I shall always mean a person who himself  has had mystical
experience. Often the word is used in a much wider and looser way. Anyone who is
sympathetic to mysticism is apt to be labeled a mystic. But I shall use the word always
in a stricter sense. However sympathetic toward mysticism a man may be, however
deeply interested, involved, enthusiastic, or learned in the subject, he will not be
called a mystic unless he has, or has had, mystical experience.

Can we suitably distinguish between the mystical experiences and the


evaluation of  the experience? That is to say, can we distinguish so clearly
between the mystic and what Staal calls the ‘student of mysticism’ (1975:
135)? Firstly, it is unlikely that anyone experiencing a state of consciousness
wholly extraordinary would feel inclined not to evaluate the experience;
Teresa de Ávila, for example, dedicated many pages of  her autobiography
and El Castillo Interior [The Interior Castle] to an appraisal of  the spiritual
exercises that led to her states of ecstasy. Swedenborg described his specific
breathing and meditative techniques that prefaced his voyages to the heav-
ens. Teresa and Swedenborg are consequently as much students of mysticism
as they are mystics. Borges was as keen to evaluate his own two mystical
‘outside of  time’ experiences as he was to discuss Swedenborg, Silesius or
his friend Xul Solar. In a similar fashion, it would be remiss to assume
that students (scholars) of mysticism are not informed by experience, and
are only working at textual analysis. Emerson, for example, correlated his
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 127

reading of  Jakob Böhme and Swedenborg with his own ecstatic experience.1
William James, like Borges, denied his own mystical nature, yet nevertheless
emphasized that his mystical sensibilities predisposed him towards a study
of mysticism: ‘I have no mystical experiences of my own, but just enough of 
the germ of mysticism in me to recognize the region from which their voice
comes when I hear it’ ( James 2003: 210). Indeed, like Borges, he describes
in great detail four particular experiences ‘which could only be described
as very sudden and incomprehensible enlargements of  the conscious field,
bringing with them a curious sense of cognition of real fact’ ( James 1910:
87). It has been argued, indeed, that James was describing himself when
describing the ‘divided self ’ that an anonymous Frenchman suf fered, in
the chapter ‘The Sick Soul’ of  Varieties.2 Alicia Jurado, we recall from the
previous chapter, focuses on Estela Canto’s suggestion that Borges was
‘“one of  the greatest – and they are extremely rare – mystical thinkers of
our time”’, and reaf firms the idea of  Borges ‘as Mystical thinker, naturally,
not just mystic’ (1996: 98). Again, how are we to distinguish between the
terms ‘mystic’ and ‘mystical thinker’? Would we approach this laudatory
comment from a dif ferent angle if she had called Borges ‘one of  the great-
est mystics of our time?’ Does ‘mystical thinker’ permit the marriage of
intellect with spiritual sensibility, i.e. does it imply critical distance, even
scepticism, whilst ‘mystic’ would imply abandonment to irrationality or
to faith? The subtlety of distinction is important.
To pursue a study of mystical texts and scholarly analyses thereof, one
must already accept at least the possibility of certain postulates: that the
term ‘mysticism’ is worthy of investigation and that something useful may
be derived from this study. This would imply that the student of mysticism
would take seriously the claims made both by those known as mystics, and

1 ‘We return to reason and faith. There I feel that nothing can befall me in life, – no
disgrace, no calamity, (leaving me my eyes,) which nature cannot repair. Standing
on the bare ground, – my head bathed by the blithe air, and uplifted into infinite
spaces, – all mean egotism vanishes. I become a transparent eye-ball; I am nothing; I
see all; the currents of  the Universal Being circulate through me; I am part or particle
of  God’. (Emerson 2005: 12)
2 I am grateful to Jeremy Carrette for this information.
128 Chapter Three

the conclusions drawn by scholars. Ultimately, as with Borges’ defence of 


Swedenborg, the student of mysticism would likely be prepared to accept
the texts of mystics as not being the ramblings of  the insane or outright
lies; and if  they are not fantasy or lies, then there is the possibility that
Swedenborg’s accounts of conversations with angels and demons and his
voyages to heaven and hell are true. Therefore the student of mysticism
will likely be open to the possibility of a mystical state of consciousness
him/herself. The diligent student of mysticism is necessarily sympathetic
to mysticism, if, indeed only so as to attempt to refute it. This may sound
trite, but seeing as the field itself is of an order that can challenge certainties
about time, space, life and death, one can assume that in order to investi-
gate this curious area, and in order for the texts to inform the researcher
in some measure, the researcher must already be prepared to accept these
challenges to his/her ontological assumptions. Such an equation between
subject (mysticism) and observer (researcher) is succinctly encapsulated
by Kripal (2001), who argues that the scholarship has been driven by the
psychic energy bestowed upon the researchers by their own (secret and
erotic) experiences: ‘I would go so far as to argue that, without these subjec-
tive experiences and the creative energies they release in the psyches (and
bodies) of  the scholars who undergo them, there would be no study of
mysticism, at least as it has been practiced for the past one hundred years’
(27).3 Furthermore, Kripal argues:
It is not just that these experiences are methodologically important because they pro-
vide the historian of religions with the energy to carry through a particular project.
Second, and more important, they are methodologically significant because they
structure, inform, and even determine the hermeneutical choices of  the historians
who have undergone them. Which texts are studied, which passages ‘come alive’ and

3 ‘I hope to establish [that] the modern, and now postmodern, study of mysticism,
from its early beginnings to its contemporary practice, has been largely inspired,
sustained, and rhetorically formed by the unitive, ecstatic, visionary, and mystico-
hermeneutical experiences of  the scholars themselves. The mystical experiences of
scholars of mysticism – no archaeology of  the comparative study of mysticism can
justifiably ignore this weirdly beautiful, if ethically ambiguous, source of inspiration,
theory, and writing’ (Kripal 2001: 3).
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 129

so receive hermeneutical attention, which theoretical tool the hermeneut employs,


what interpretations are finally reached – all of  these are profoundly inf luenced by
the mystical experiences of  the historians themselves. (2001: 27)

Nevertheless, whilst acknowledging the interrelationship between


mysticism and the scholarship of mysticism, one should be careful not to
assume too close an interdependence. If we follow Stace’s judgment, then
we can assume that Borges was, indeed, a mystic, based upon his two related
‘timeless’ experiences; and we would assume that he was not a mystic if we
consider only his close and sympathetic reading of mystical texts. Likewise,
need we divide the Borges of  ‘Historia de la Eternidad’ into two – the
researcher of centuries of  theologians and mystics who have written about
eternity, and the narrator of a personal moment of  timelessness? Borges
was ‘desgraciadamente’ Borges, and consequently it seems disjointed to
separate one aspect from another, especially seeing that he was insistent
in claiming that a textual experience was as real as a non-textual one. We
recall the Swedenborgian Lawrence writing about the ‘Swedenborgian’
Borges, calling him ‘a kindred spirit to the Swedish mystic’ and suggesting
that he ‘shared with Swedenborg the same fundamental objectives; they
simply traversed the same terrain in somewhat dif ferent ways’ (1995: x). In
that respect a close and sympathetic reading of  Swedenborg becomes itself
a certain experience of  Swedenborg’s otherworld experiences.
Here we open another question in the thorny scholarship of mysti-
cism, ref lected in Kathleen Raine’s (1995) avowal that Blake’s poetry pro-
vides tangible experience of divine bliss rather than merely describing it.
This question is integral to the matter that preoccupied William James
and Bertrand Russell concerning the epistemology of experience: what is
the gulf  that separates knowledge-by-acquaintance from knowledge-by-
description? As discussed in Chapter One, Borges placed such experiential
value on the text that the reading of  the content constitutes an experience
of  that very content. In this sense, knowledge-by-description is knowl-
edge-by-acquaintance, and in this case, a dedicated student of mysticism
is capable of experiencing through the mediation of  the text some aspect
of  the mystical reality. Such a position would chime with James’s under-
standing that, as Eugene Taylor suggests, ‘[r]elations in experience also lie
130 Chapter Three

at the heart of  James’s epistemology. Since experience is all that exists and
all that exists is experience’ (Taylor 1996), and yet would jar with Russell’s
emphasis on distinguishing the two modes of  knowledge. Van Dusen
suggests that Swedenborg’s writings, beyond describing the otherworld
realities, provide direct experience to the dedicated reader, and thus enact
a didactic method that can, if read properly, make a mystic of  the reader:

If  I had to describe Swedenborg’s spiritual writings and their fundamental purpose
in one line, it would be this: the writings are a clear presentation meant to be used by
individuals to lead them into the life of  God – as an actual part of  their experience.
His writings are rational, but that is their style, not pre-eminently their nature. Their
nature and overwhelming purpose are to lead to God, which accounts for many aspects
of  their structure. So in this sense, not only are his writings the work of a mystic,
they are meant to help create mystics, that is, to lead others to the Divine. (1995: 134)

In this sense the writings of  Swedenborg become sacred texts – texts whose
oral transmission enacts a spiritual and numinous reaction in the readers or
listeners. This assertion is itself problematic if we follow the comments of 
Emerson, Henry James Sr., William James, Yeats, and Borges about how dry
and ‘insipid’ was the style of  Swedenborg. From Van Dusen’s perspective,
the text is not the narrative of an experience, it is the experience, and thus
the sympathetic reader (the student of mysticism) is the mystic. Van Dusen
takes this perspective to another level in the essay ‘Swedenborg’s Spiritual
Method’ (1991), where he cites his friend, a Swedenborgian scholar named
David St Amour, who derives great spiritual solace from Swedenborg’s
texts ‘even when he did not understand them’ (original emphasis). In this
sense the text is authoritative and somehow above the interaction of critical
scrutiny. Whilst Stace would balk at this muddying of  the waters of mystic,
text and researcher of mysticism, it is important for a study of  Borges to
acknowledge that the distinctions are not so radically distinct.
Staal (1975) approaches the question of  the researcher of mysticism
from another angle, and whilst recognising the necessary distinction
between mystic and scholar, suggests that the examination of  the mystical
state requires methodical and dispassionate (i.e. unmystical) approaches to
the phenomenon: He also suggests that mystics are probably not the best
to formulate theories of mysticism: ‘It is the students of mysticism whose
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 131

task it is to evolve a theory’ (63). This seems to imply that if  the mystic
were the intrepid explorer, then the scholar is the cartographer; the two
have a natural symbiosis where the mystic provides the raw data, and the
scholar assimilates, contrasts and analyses the material and prepares it for
the wider readership. This perspective is again not without its dif ficulties,
as evinced by James and Borges, in that the scholar himself may derive his
knowledge experientially (that is to say, non-textually, if such is possible)
as much as textually. With this distinction established, however, Staal was
also keen to emphasize that attempts by the scholar to detach him/herself
altogether from the field of study can lead to an impoverishment both
of  the scholarship and of  the possible experiences of  the researcher. It is
incumbent upon the researcher to have some working experience of  the
matters that are under investigation:

No linguist would refuse to study sentences because we cannot perceive how they
are internally produced. Nor would a physicist be content with mere speculation and
refuse to devise experiments to test some part of a hypothesis, on the grounds that
such experiments might be dif ficult to carry out, might be of uncertain outcome,
or might be time-consuming or expensive. And neither would a person interested
in reaching the South Pole, out of  fear that he might not be able to get there, stay
at home and refuse even to move in a southerly direction. Yet students of mysticism
have, in their field, left all such things undone. Content with mere speculation and
talking, they have not even considered the possibility of  traveling themselves that
part of  the road that appears to be within reach – even though not very well paved.
This can only be understood if it is the outcome of a deep-seated prejudice, for such
a negative attitude has in no domain of  knowledge been taken seriously or been
expected to lead to results. (Staal 1975: 127)

As established in the previous chapter, there is every indication to suggest


that Borges was familiar with many experiences that generally serve the
definition of  the mystic. However, like Jung he would have had no truck
with any suggestion that he himself was a mystic. Few scholars, despite their
personal experiences, would likely declare within their scholarly writing
that they themselves are mystics. There are many reasons for this. Firstly, as
Aniela Jaf fé describes about Jung, there is a tendency to assume that mysti-
cal experiences are non-rational, and that they consequently run contrary
to the academic pursuit of  truth.
132 Chapter Three

Jung did not like to be regarded as a mystic: he preferred to be recognized as an


empiricist, i.e., a scientist whose research is based on a careful observation of  facts.
In this sense, he thought of  himself as a natural scientist. One can understand why
Jung disliked being included in the ranks of mystics when one considers that in his
time, and essentially also today, to characterize a scientific author as ‘mystic’ casts a
doubt on the reliability or validity of  his ideas and his work. (1989: 1)4

This division between truth claims of  the ‘empiricist’ over those of  the
‘mystic’ is a central concern of  the scholarship of mysticism, and forms
the central area of concern for the conclusion of  William James’s chap-
ter on mysticism in Varieties, and the central focus of  Russell’s chapter
on mysticism in Religion and Science. James would argue that the mystic
is empowered with knowledge through the mystical experience, Russell
would argue that we have no way of  knowing, if such an experience and
such an account cannot be transmitted successfully. The essence of  both
arguments, though, as ref lected also in Jaf fé’s comments about Jung, is that
scholars are likely to be reticent in suggesting their own mystical nature
for fear of accusations of  ‘subjectivity’, ‘irrationality’, or even outright delu-
sion. In the case of  Borges, as discussed in the previous chapter, his desire
not to be considered a mystic appears less a fear of academic malpractice
than an eagerness not to be considered credulous, nor to have given him-
self over to statements of  faith. Whilst one may justifiably object to the
equation of mysticism with faith, one can perceive in Borges’ many com-
ments concerning the faculty of critical enquiry, and his other comments
about the faint and rapt outpourings of mystics, that he was keen to have
been seen, like Jung, as a sober and intellectual empiricist. So much value
is placed upon the term mystic that derives from the period, culture and
environment in which the term is used. As Jaf fé observed, the term had

4 Van Dusen (1995: 129) would reinforce the non-rational aspect of mysticism, though
more needs to be discussed in order to determine exactly what ‘non-rational’ means:
‘Mysticism is nonrational; this is again from the layperson’s definition. As a matter
of  fact, mystical writings vary across the whole spectrum of clarity and nonrational-
ity. Basically, mysticism, or the experience of  God, is irrational to those outside the
experience. It is rational, true, and clear to those in the experience. It informs reason
of  higher truths.’
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 133

implications of unreliability both in the time of  Jung and ‘today’ (1980s).
At the time of  Emerson, the term was employed ostensibly to designate a
vapid and over-emotional religiously-inclined personality (Hurth 2005).
In other times and cultures the term and its cognate expressions can have
notably divergent significations.5
This contradiction established between intellectual pursuit and mys-
tical experience is problematic for two reasons: firstly it implies that the
scholarly method can only be ef ficacious if all steps of rigorous analy-
sis are both expressed and expressible, and secondly, that epistemologi-
cal pathways that fall outside of such a scholarly method are somehow
inferior. Both assumptions are based on a dichotomy built up since the
Enlightenment but made more robust within academic scholarship
over the last century of prioritizing to an alarming degree one method
of enquiry over another. Borges himself alluded to this division within
modernity, arguing, as mentioned earlier, that Plato and Socrates con-
sidered reason and myth as similar epistemological pathways (Burgin
1998: 160), and that the Paris of  the Enlightenment worshipped ‘el culto
de la razón’ (1989: 235) [‘the cult of reason’]. Similarly, when discussing
Buddhism in Siete Noches, Borges dwells on the many binaries that char-
acterize modern western thought and that prevent a full engagement in
Buddhist spiritual practice: ‘Nosotros pensamos siempre en términos de
sujeto, objeto, causa, efecto, lógico, ilógico, algo y su contrario; tenemos
que rebasar esas categorías. Según los doctores de la zen, llegar a la verdad
por una intuición brusca, mediante una respuesta ilógica’ (1989: 252) [‘We
always think in terms of subject-object, cause-ef fect, logic-illogic, a thing
and its opposite. We must go beyond these categories. According to the
Zen masters, to reach truth through sudden intuition requires an illogi-
cal answer’] (1984: 73). Many scholars, such as Kripal (2001) and Ferrer
(2002, 2008), have attempted to redress this radical division, and, in the

5 Hurth’s mention of  the historical variance of  the use of  the term ‘mysticism’ is of
crucial importance here, and we must also consider possible dif ferences between
English and Spanish when considering Borges. I have heard ‘él es un místico’ in Spain
to refer to a daydreamy man who regularly missed appointments.
134 Chapter Three

case of  Ferrer, propose a ‘participatory method’ in which the subject-


object division is surpassed. In this sense, a scholar may be more inclined
to describe and assimilate within his/her scholarship the life experiences
of a transpersonal, mystical or anomalous nature.
Yet the term mystic also has ethical implications that would dissuade
the scholar from expressing the experiential dimension in clear terms, for
fear of  being seen to assume a brazenly superior position. That is to say,
most of  the scholarship of mysticism highlights the ethical aspect of  the
mystical experience, whereby the mystic gains some moral insight into the
nature of  human af fairs. That being the case, to declare oneself a mystic may
equate to declaring oneself  ‘better’ than the non-mystic, or to declaring
oneself privileged above others, singled out by divine grace. Van Dusen is
the only scholar I have encountered to declare unabashedly his own mysti-
cal nature; indeed his contribution to Testimony to the Invisible is entitled
‘A mystic looks at Swedenborg’. Rigorous and informative as his chapter is,
there is an unsettling self-assurance in the opening pages when he recounts
‘when I first became aware that I was a mystic’ (1995: 106). Clearly he had
no intention of implying moral superiority, but it is dif ficult as a reader not
to respond with a certain misgiving. Where Borges describes Swedenborg
as ‘el elegido’ (2005: 154) [‘the chosen one’] (1995: 6), he implies the special
nature with which Swedenborg was endowed, and he pays close attention
to Swedenborg’s ethical and admirable nature. In tune with Borges’ widely
discussed modesty, therefore, and regardless of  his awareness that his own
experiences may have been termed mystical, it is highly unlikely that he
ever would have called himself a mystic for fear of presumption. Thus
there are many reasons that the scholarship of mysticism is replete with
subtle implications and allusions to personal experience with few outright
declarations, as the scholars may consider themselves risking the integrity
of  their scholarship by drawing too heavily on the personal, experiential
nature of mysticism.
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 135

Borges’ varieties of mystical experience

Although he never expressed a definitive theory of mysticism, Borges may


nevertheless be considered a scholar of mysticism in the tradition of  James,
Underhill, Stace and Zaehner. Despite his jocular insistence that he was
a man of  the nineteenth century, Borges was a man of  his times. As such,
in appraising his views on mystics, mysticism and mystical consciousness,
it is pertinent to see him not as a contemporary of  Blake, Coleridge and
de Quincey, nor of  Emerson, Thoreau, Melville and Whitman, but as an
inheritor of  the long shadow cast at the beginning of  the twentieth cen-
tury by William James. The manifest af finities between William James
and Borges have attracted surprisingly little critical research. The most
extensive investigation that I have encountered is the unpublished 2008
PhD thesis of  Marcel Fernandes: Borges and Pragmatism: Jorge Luis Borges,
William James, and the Destruction of  Philosophy. This exemplary piece of
scholarship coherently argues for a Jamesian reading of  Borges’ shifting
philosophies, aligned both to Pragmatism, Radical Empiricism, and the
religious-philosophical-psychological outlook of  Varieties. In particular,
Fernandes argues that whilst Borges himself locates James on the nominalist
side of  the historical realist-nominalist divide, as outlined in ‘El Ruiseñor
de Keats’ [‘The Nightingale of  Keats’] and ‘La Flor de Coleridge’ [‘The
Flower of  Coleridge’], Borges himself would occupy a position alongside
James. However, Fernandes proposes, both James and Borges share an
ironizing perspective – a pragmatic sensibility that truth is variable – that
grants them a more mobile position than that of an outright nominalist:
‘Borges is best described as a pragmatist rather than a nominalist since he
is self-ref lexive enough to be aware that such a division is after all itself a
Platonic construct, and that nominalism can itself  become a general dogma.
Instead, he makes aesthetic use of  the division’ (2008: 23). Fernandes’
insightful and close reading of  Borges’ tales reveals a strongly pragmatic
aspect to Borges which allows Borges to explore the aesthetic wonders of 
Platonic Idealism against the anarchic chaos of nominalism:
136 Chapter Three

Borges’ stories were to make more obvious use of philosophy than did any of  his pre-
vious writing [prior to his head injury], and in a way that pitted one type of  James’s
binary firmly against the other: the idealist or pantheistic aspects of  the history of
philosophy, from Plato to Plotinus to Schopenhauer, were to be set against the most
hard-headed nominalism of  Aristotle, Hume or James himself. Yet, instead of  the
agons of dialectic and argument, Borges was to allow realism (in the Platonic, idealist
sense) to inspire and structure and inform his short stories, relishing the aesthetic
potential of idealism while always holding it in abeyance, checking it with an irony
both recalcitrant and def lationary, ludic and nominalist. (2008: 22)

He also highlights the paucity of scholarship into the James–Borges con-


nection, focusing on Borges’ decision to omit from the 1975 Prólogo con un
prólogo de prólogos his own 1945 introduction to the Spanish translation of 
James’ Pragmatism. Following Nubiola (2000), Fernandes proposes that this
omission may derive firstly from Borges’ mistrust of his writings from thirty
years earlier. Secondly, and more audaciously, Fernandes proposes that:

Borges felt that this prologue to James’s book gave his game away, so to speak; it was
too close to the marrow of  his creative praxis. […] If  I am correct in arguing that
Borges utilizes a Jamesian pragmatism to engage the history of philosophy for aesthetic
ends, and makes pragmatic use of  the nominalist-realist controversy and empirical-
rationalist binary that was central to James’s own historiography of philosophy, then
it is unsurprising that he sought to avoid any obvious giveaways. Perhaps revealing
the intellectual engine of  his fictions was anathema to Borges; he may have viewed
such an admission as a kind of self-incrimination. (2008: 32)

Fernandes’ thesis maintains in essence that Borges’ repeated claims to ‘use


philosophy for aesthetic purposes’, itself disguises a pragmatic employment
of philosophical discourses in a manner that reveals the inf luence of  James.
This compelling hypothesis is fully borne out by his analysis of essays, fic-
tions and poems of  Borges.
The presence of William James in Borges forms the focus of an exchange
of articles in the James journal Streams of  William James. Nubiola (2000)
issued a call for further research into the Jamesian inf luence on Borges;
Stephens (2000: 1) responded with a suggestion that two of  James’ essays:
‘Does Consciousness Exist?’ and ‘A World of  Pure Experience’ are mani-
fest inf luence upon Borges’ ‘youthful essay entitled “The Nothingness of 
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 137

Personality”’. Nubiola (2001) responded with an insightful investigation


into the link between Borges and James provided by Macedonio Fernández,
a connection that he explored with great attention in a later article (2005).
The only other scholars I have encountered are Stephens (2000: 1), who
argues ‘that Borges’s literary style is built on, or presupposes, a foundation
of  Jamesian empiricism’, Almeida (2002), who explored the inf luence of 
James and Peirce upon Borges, and Bosteels (2007), whose analysis also
looks at the inf luence of  Pragmatism upon Borges. Were Fernandes’ thesis
to be published, then this would add great substance to this fascinating area.
The stream of inf luence in the arena of mysticism, however, has been
less analysed. Although Giskin pursues a Jamesian reading of  Borges’ fiction,
Báez-Rivera (2004) is the only scholar that I have identified to establish the
connection between Borges’ appraisal of  his own mystical experience and
his reading of  William James. ‘Borges, the meticulous reader of  William
James, did not hesitate to describe his two experiences as mystical whenever
urged to speak on it, either by his own initiative or for the insistence of  his
audience’ (2004: 85). Báez-Rivera draws on the notion of  Borges not as
agnostic but as ‘agnostótico’, which ‘has its root in the term agnostoteísmo,
coined by Julián Velarde to properly denote those who, starting from Kant,
af firm that God cannot be known, we can only believe in him’ (2004: 87).
This ‘agnostótico’ aspect of  Borges is worthy of  further exploration, as it
ties in with so much of  the Borges scholarship concerning the ‘imminence
of a revelation’, and it bears particular relevance to Flynn’s The Quest for
God in the work of  Borges.
William James has defined the landscape of scholarly approaches to
mysticism more than any other scholar, and his method of examining
the traditions of mysticism from an essentially psychological perspective
remains inf luential. His analysis of mysticism is found primarily the Varieties
of  Religious Experience (1902) and two little-known essays ‘A Suggestion
about Mysticism’ (1910) and ‘A Pluralistic Mystic’ (1910). As Fernandes,
Nubiola and Stephens argue, Borges inherited a fondness for William
James from his father and Macedonio Fernández, and references to James
are scattered amongst his work. He pays particular attention to Varieties,
stating to di Giovanni how James’ seminal volume inspired his own inter-
pretation of mysticism: ‘except for that one strange experience I had, really
138 Chapter Three

I can say very little about mysticism personally, though of course I have
studied, I have read my Varieties of  Religious Experience, and I have done
much reading in the mystics, especially Swedenborg, also Blake’ (Burgin
1998: 130). Cohen (1973: 81), we recall from the previous chapter, also
argues that Borges found the inspiration for the Aleph from a biography
of  Jakob Böhme, which he found reproduced in James’ Varieties.
James, as we also recall from the previous chapter, set a standard that
ensuing scholars would inevitably measure themselves against in the produc-
tion of discrete defining characteristics. In the absence of a list of  the salient
characteristics we can work through the Borges’ obra – tales, poems, essays,
lectures and interviews – and assemble from these varied texts a working
theory that Borges applied when considering mysticism. I will hereby list
these characteristics, and then, following James’ model in Varieties, examine
them in the light of  Borges’ work in greater detail. Mysticism, according
to Borges is:

1) pre-religious
2) original
3) spontaneous
4) revelatory
5) inef fable
6) outside of  time
7) transient
8) transformative

Whilst not all these aspects are necessarily articulated by William James, nev-
ertheless my hypothesis, as will now be examined, is that Borges’ understand-
ing of mysticism is inherently inf luenced by his reading of  William James.

Pre-religious

Borges, as analysed in Chapter One, prized Swedenborg’s critique of  the


institution of  the church, and felt that ‘cometió un incómodo error cuando
resolvió ajustar sus ideas al marco de los dos Testamentos’ (2005: 155)
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 139

[‘he made an awkward mistake when he decided to adapt his ideas to the
framework of  the two Testaments’] (1995: 9). I also argued that this is an
abiding perspective in the scholarship of  Swedenborg. What lies at the
heart of  Borges’ position is on the one hand an iconoclastic commenda-
tion of rebelliousness and heterodoxy, but on the other a declaration that
the experience of  the Swedish mystic could have somehow occurred in a
‘pure’ state that was coloured a posteriori by the embellishment of religious
authority.
Like his godfather, Emerson, and like his father, Henry James Sr.,
William James was a close reader of  Swedenborg. Although Swedenborg
is scarcely mentioned in Varieties, and whilst he did not write about him
in the same fashion as Emerson, nevertheless, as Eugene Taylor suggests,
James’ reading of  Swedenborg was essential to his discussion of metaphys-
ics, religious experience and mysticism. Taylor, indeed, suggests that the
‘Swedenborgian Doctrine of  the Rational and the Doctrine of  Use [were]
key inf luences on Charles Peirce as well as William James’ (2003: 4). Taylor
also af firms that: ‘the origin of  his philosophy is neither Cartesian, Kantian,
nor Hegelian, but rather Swedenborgian and transcendentalist’ (2003: 5).6
Emerson and William James critiqued the ecclesiastical or ‘church-bound’
manner of  Swedenborg, maintaining that the essence of  the mystical expe-
rience is transcultural, but that the transmission is both individually and
culturally determined.
James had said in the Varieties that religious experience could be understood both
in terms of what was generic to all human beings and what was idiosyncratic to the
individual. From the generic could be derived an understanding of psychological
processes common to all men and women insofar as phenomenological accounts of
spiritual experience was concerned. What was idiosyncratic to the individual was
an expression of  that person’s personal beliefs about the ultimate nature of reality,
which might or might not have relevance for anyone else except that one person.

6 This statement is challenged by James scholar Jeremy Carrette, who, having scru-
tinized the correspondence of  James in which he openly distances himself  both
from his father’s Swedenborgian perspective and from Swedenborg himself, argues
that Swedenborg may not have been such a significant inf luence on James as Taylor
indicates (personal discussion).
140 Chapter Three

These beliefs held by the individual over and above what was common to all human
beings regarding religious experience James called ‘overbeliefs’. (Taylor 2003: 3)

Borges follows the tradition particular to William James and his


Transcendentalist forefathers in concentrating not on traditional religion
but on the interior religious capacity. This is what Taylor calls ‘the cen-
tral point of  James’s work: namely, organized religion and personal spir-
itual experience are substantially dif ferent’ (2003: 2). This perspective, as
analysed in Chapter One, is fundamental to Borges’ reading not only of 
Swedenborg, but of other writers of  the mystical traditions. For example,
he suggests that Luis de León never experienced the poetic revelations that
he describes, but merely mimicked the Song of  Songs. He argues that Blake,
whom he describes as ‘el gran místico inglés’ (2005: 216) experienced some
tremendous revelations which he then awkwardly framed within his own
complex mythologies. In this respect Borges demonstrates the same perspec-
tive that he maintains for Swedenborg, not so much that the experience is
translated into the textual reproduction, which is inevitable, but that the
experience may be fundamentally dif ferent from the textual description,
as the text demands conformity to certain theological or poetic codes.
This would imply that in his readings of  Swedenborg and Blake, certain
passages shine through their doctrinal embellishments to represent some
pure, essential, experience.
I would argue, furthermore, that this position of  the pre-religious is
not to be considered perennialist, but should be seen as pragmatic in the
manner that Daniels (2003) describes below as the ‘third, middle, posi-
tion’. Daniels examines the critical position within the scholarship of  the
mystical experience that may be viewed as perennialist or essentialist; an
approach to mysticism that we already encountered with Schopenhauer’s
view that the mystical experience is the prime material of all subsequent
religious codes. This position opposes the more modern Constructivist
position, which, Daniels argues, sees the mystical experience as being only
the product of social and linguistic codes. This particular division is integral
to Borges’ understanding both of  the mystical texts that he read and of  his
own mystical experiences. Daniels writes:
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 141

All investigators recognise that there are many varieties of mystical experience. The
major debate centres on whether these many forms represent dif ferent interpreta-
tions or accounts of what is essentially the same experience (or a few basic types of
experience) or whether, on the other hand, the experiences themselves are funda-
mentally dif ferent. According to the first, perennialist, view (e.g., Forman, 1998;
Huxley, 1947; Smith, 1976; Stace, 1960; Underhill, 1911/1995) people everywhere
have the same basic experience(s) but they may interpret and describe them rather
dif ferently depending upon the personal, social, cultural and linguistic context. If 
this view is correct, it makes sense, as Wainwright (1981) has argued, to try to iden-
tify the essential cross-cultural characteristics and types of mystical experience (i.e.,
the characteristics and types that exist prior to any secondary interpretative dif fer-
ences). At the other extreme are the constructivists (e.g., Gimello, 1978, 1983; Katz,
1978) who argue that the experiences themselves (rather than simply their post-hoc
interpretations) are profoundly and irrevocably determined by predisposing personal,
social, and cultural factors, including religious doctrines and particular forms of
spiritual practice. Thus there are, according to Katz (1978), no pure or unmediated
experiences. For this reason there can be no true common experiential denomina-
tors in mysticism. The implication of  this second view is that there is, in principle,
an indefinite number of dif ferent mystical experiences, each one potentially unique
to the individual experiencer although there may be identifiable commonalities of
experience within particular mystical traditions. (2003 no pagination)

Whilst Daniels identifies this particular polarity in the debate, he recog-


nizes that there is a third avenue of enquiry that seeks the commonality
between these positions:
A third, middle, position (e.g., Hick, 1989; Zaehner, 1961) argues that while mystical
experiences themselves (rather than just their interpretations) are strongly inf luenced
by their personal, social and cultural contexts, it is possible to recognise certain cross-
cultural ‘family resemblances’ among them (Hick, 1989). For Hick, these family
resemblances result because the experiences represent various encounters with ‘the
Real’ (which Hick believes is an actual ontological reality). For this reason, mysti-
cal experiences must ref lect in an important way the qualities that are manifested in
human consciousness by the Real (e.g., they will express love, knowledge, understand-
ing and bliss rather than hatred, ignorance, bigotry and pain). (2003)

This is a pervasive division in the scholarship, and it becomes clear that


no assessment of mysticism can lie outside of one of  the three positions. I
would argue that Borges naturally swings between the twin pole positions
142 Chapter Three

in a manner that would resemble Daniels’ third way. As Fernandes (2008)


identifies, Borges examines nominalist and realist philosophical posi-
tions in his fictions, aesthetically evaluating the very dialectic between
the Aristotelian and the Platonic that he outlines in ‘Ruiseñor de Keats’
and ‘Flor de Coleridge’.7 This exploration of  both poles, Fernandes argues,
may best be described as pragmatic. The perennialist perspective is asso-
ciated with hermetic traditions, the Aurea Catena,8 Neoplatonism and
western esotericism, all of which were of great interest to Borges; whilst
the constructivist may be transcribed into the homonymous schools of 
thought of  the 1960s, linked to semiotics and structuralism, which would
uphold an ultimately linguistic construction of experience. Again, this
perspective is close to Borges’ views of  f luctuating linguistic systems and
nominalist language structures, and certainly has guaranteed his standing
in late twentieth century literary theory. Yet this third way would be the
one closest to James and to Borges, as it allows for some stable, empirical
experience whilst acknowledging the inf luence of social, literary, cultural,
even political systems upon the textual reproduction.

Original

The temptation is to include the characteristic of  ‘originality’ in the analysis


above about the pre-religious aspect of  the mystical experience. However,
there are subtle distinctions that demand a separate appraisal. Borges
wrote in numerous passages that one of  the most praiseworthy aspects of 
Swedenborg was his originality. Swedenborg’s radical theology, for exam-
ple, in which Man, and not God, is the arbiter and judge of whether the
dead soul will inhabit heaven or hell, was the most ‘original’ and ‘innova-
tive’ of all Swedenborg’s visions. He also described Swedenborg’s vision

7 Funes may be seen as a nominalist in extremis; Lonrot, as the realist.


8 ‘The Golden (or Homeric) Chain in alchemy is the series of great wise men, begin-
ning with Hermes Trismesgitos, which links earth with heaven’ (Aniela Jaf fé, in Jung
1989: 189).
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 143

of  heaven and hell as ‘su concepto originalísimo’ (2005: 155) [‘extremely
original concept’] (1995: 9). When describing Swedenborg’s vision of  the
hermit who through his own asceticism had denied himself  the company
of  the intellectually engaged angels in heaven, Borges employed the term
‘innovación’:

Ésta es una innovación de Swedenborg. Porque siempre se ha pensado que la salvación


es de carácter ético. Se entiende que si un hombre es justo, se salva. «El reino de los
cielos es de los pobres de espíritu», etcétera. Eso lo comunica Jesús. Pero Swedenborg
va más allá. Dice que eso no basta, que un hombre tiene que salvarse también inte-
lectualmente. Él se imagina el cielo, sobre todo, como una serie de conversaciones
teológicas entre los ángeles. Y si un hombre no puede seguir esas conversaciones es
indigno del cielo. Así, debe vivir solo. Y luego vendrá William Blake, que agrega una
tercera salvación. Dice que podemos – que tenemos – que salvarnos también por
medio del arte. Blake explica que Cristo también fue un artista, ya que no predicaba
por medio de palabras sino de parábolas. Y las parábolas son, desde luego, expresio-
nes estéticas. Es decir, que la salvación sería por la inteligencia, por la ética y por el
ejercicio del arte. (2005: 199)

[This is an innovation of  Swedenborg, because it has always been thought that salva-
tion is ethical in its nature. It is understood that if a man is just, he is saved. ‘Blessed
are the poor in spirit, for theirs is the Kingdom of  Heaven’, etc. Jesus proclaimed
this. But Swedenborg went further. He writes that this is not enough, that a man
must save himself intellectually also. He pictured heaven, above all, as a series of 
theological conversations amongst angels. And if a man is unable to follow these
conversations he is not worthy of  heaven, and he must live alone. He was followed
by William Blake, who added a third means of salvation. He says that we can – that
we must – save ourselves through Art. Blake explains that Christ was also an artist,
as he did not preach through words but through parables. And parables are, clearly,
an aesthetic expression. That is to say that salvation is through intelligence, ethics
and Art.] (My translation)

What is particularly striking is that Borges’ judgement itself is both aes-


thetic and ethical. It is aesthetic because Borges interprets Swedenborg’s
provocative and curious narrative as inventive and compelling. Just as with
any other literary concern of  Borges, derivative, imitative texts are of  lesser
appeal than innovative and original texts. And yet, as Borges was keen to
emphasize, mystical texts are no ordinary works of art, seeing that they place
curious interpretative demands upon the reader in relation to discerning
144 Chapter Three

between ‘authentic’ and ‘inauthentic’ (see Chapter One). It is ethical on two


levels: firstly because Swedenborg’s position, as Borges identifies, demands
of man a seizure of  his own destiny and an appeal to develop the critical
faculty governed by the intellect. Borges emphasized the moral aspect of 
this vision: ‘es innegable que la doctrina revelada por Swedenborg es más
moral y más razonable que la de un misterioso don que se obtiene, casi al
azar, a última hora. Nos lleva, por lo pronto, al ejercicio de una vida virtuosa’
(2005: 157) [‘we must recognize that the doctrine revealed by Swedenborg
is more moral and reasonable than one that postulates a mysterious gift
gotten, almost by chance, at the eleventh hour. To begin with, it leads us to
the practice of virtue in our lives’] (1995: 11). Secondly, it is ethical because
Borges perceived Swedenborg’s challenge to tradition and orthodoxy as
itself  being a moral declaration of intellectual will and philosophical free-
dom. Blake also, for Borges, was markedly original, though in Blake’s case
the originality implied a concomitant dif ficulty to provide a framework in
which to express the visions. Thus the textual reproduction, from an ethical
position, becomes the heterodox position of  the writer, and is thus integrally
related to power. In this sense, one would even argue that Borges’ view of
mysticism is political, in that the mystical authority constitutes a challenge
to the hegemony – what Staal (1975: 135) would call the ‘superstructure’
upon which the mystical experience and text are held. This is something
Jeremy Carrette pointed out to me in a private conversation in relation to
Foucault’s analysis of structures of power, and traditions of mystical writers
and the texts to which they may or may not have had access. It is ref lected
in the analysis of  Jantzen (1995: 12):

The idea of  ‘mysticism’ is a social construction and that it has been constructed in
dif ferent ways at dif ferent times. Although […] medieval mystics and ecclesiastics
did not work with a concept of  ‘mysticism’ they did have strong views about who
should count as a mystic, views which changed over the course of  time. Furthermore,
those changes were linked to changes in patterns of authority and gender relations.
[…] The current philosophical construction of mysticism is therefore only one in a
series of social constructions of mysticism.

It becomes clear through an analysis of  Borges’ many comments on mysti-


cal texts that part of  their impact for him lay with the challenge to dogma
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 145

– whether political, social, cultural or theological – present throughout


time and place. Here we may therefore agree with Báez-Rivera that Borges’
forthright dismissal of  Juan de la Cruz, Teresa de Ávila and Luis de León
as mystics could be considered ‘a joke’ (2004: 86), in order to rock the tra-
ditionalist and conservative boat. This is a reasonable assertion, as Borges
was ever keen to throw incendiary comments at his audience; yet even its
jocular dimension reveals a deep desire to locate the mystical experience
not only outside of orthodoxy, religious or otherwise, but, in the best of
cases, in opposition to it. Thus for Borges Swedenborg’s ‘innovación’ is an
aspect of  his rebelliousness and resistance to canonical authority.
However, the matter of originality and innovation is not as clear as it
may seem. In his desire to paint Swedenborg as a natural mystic endowed
with the innate gift of communicating with the spirit world, free from the
inf luence of ecclesiastical dogma, and conforming to Christian teachings
only, as it were, as an afterthought, Borges displayed a very selective reading
of  the Swedish seer. Not one biography of  Swedenborg fails to emphasize
that the boy was born into a notably religious and church-orientated family,
that, as Conan Doyle succinctly writes, Swedenborg ‘sucked in theology
with his mother’s milk’ (2005: 96). Whilst the matter of  Swedenborg’s
orthodoxy deserves far greater appraisal than is possible here, the point
must be made that the ‘church-bound’ nature of  his texts, something with
which Emerson, William James, Conan Doyle and Borges were uncom-
fortable, is indicative of  the religious milieu which he inhabited, at least in
his early years. In emphasizing the pre-religious, perennial, mystical aspect
of  Swedenborg, and in focusing on innovation and originality, Borges
appears keen to separate Swedenborg from the theological dimension
around which his texts are intimately entwined. Swedenborg’s Biblical
exegesis cannot be so easily divorced from his voyages to the heavens and
from his psychic abilities.
To confuse matters further, neither can we argue, as Borges also did,
that Swedenborg’s heterodox nature was so original and free from the
inf luence of  tradition and peers. Borges suggested that ‘La doctrina de las
correspondencias me ha llevado a la mención de la cábala. Que yo sepa o
recuerde, nadie ha investigado hasta ahora su íntima afinidad’ (2005: 159)
[‘The doctrine of correspondences has brought me to mention the Cabala.
146 Chapter Three

No one whom I know of or remember has yet investigated its intimate


af finity’] (1995: 14). There are two fundamental concerns of which Borges
appears unaware: firstly the Kabbalistic environment in which Swedenborg
himself moved and the abiding inf luence upon his thought such tradi-
tions imparted; and secondly the long tradition of interest in Swedenborg
amongst esoteric societies from his age up to the present. Whilst refer-
ences to Swedenborg’s esoteric and Kabbalistic practices are referred to
in many biographical studies, Schuchard (2006) investigates further than
any other scholar Swedenborg’s connection with the Moravian Chapel
in Fetter Lane, London, and his participation in their erotic spiritual
practices under the leadership of  the eccentric Count Zinzendorf. She
explores his association with Kabbalists, Rosicrucian and other esoteric
communities across Europe, and paints a picture of a man whose spiritual
experiences and religious texts owe much to the inf luence of such tradi-
tions. ‘In the early 1730s, while travelling in eastern Europe, Swedenborg
began to search in Neoplatonic, Hermetic and Kabbalistic literature for
the means of demonstrating scientifically the reality of  the soul. He stud-
ied the works of  Comenius, the spiritual father of  the Moravians, who
attempted to portray the soul in human form, using “a hieroglyphical
signification”’ (2006: 70).
Schuchard further explores Swedenborg’s alleged relationship with
Freemasonry. However, no biographical study fully bears out the supposi-
tion that Swedenborg paid more than a passing interest to the Freemasons
or any other esoteric community. By nature, rather like Borges, Swedenborg
does not seem to have been interested in joining the inner ranks of secre-
tive organizations, and a more reasonable line of analysis would be that
the similarity between his spiritual systems and Masonic and Moravian
ideas would be the Kabbalistic and Neoplatonic inf luence upon them
all. Although Schuchard paints a Swedenborg fully initiated into the
inner circles of  European Kabbalistic, Rosicrucian and Masonic groups,
it appears that this may be more of guilt by association. Talbot (2007)
published a stinging refutation of  Schuchard’s thesis, arguing that many
of  her claims are based upon Swedenborg’s geographical proximity to
such circles. Talbot cites numerous other scholars over the past two cen-
turies who have investigated the Kabbalistic claims, and suggests that
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 147

Swedenborg was either merely curious, or was even unsympathetic to


Kabbalistic thought. Citing Antón Pacheco (who also wrote about Borges’
reading of  Swedenborg), Talbot suggests that the similarities between
Swedenborg’s biblical exegesis and Kabbalistic biblical scholarship does
not necessarily mean that they are related: ‘The phenomenology of inter-
preting the Bible or the Quran according to visionary experiences might be
common to Swedenborg, Kabbalists, and Muslim mystics, but, as Pacheco
points out, it does not necessarily imply direct borrowing between any of 
them’ (Talbot 2007: 187).
What is particularly striking about Talbot’s critique of  Schuchard is
that amongst the many areas in which he feels she has misinterpreted the
biographies of  Swedenborg he feels in particular that she has misinterpreted
Swedenborg’s writings themselves. ‘Her biography of  Swedenborg is based
on selections from Toksvig’s and White’s biographies (sometimes misinter-
preted), each of which have their own prejudices and biases, and she rarely
discusses the firsthand sources behind their interpretations’ (2007: 204).
Herein lies the most splendid of misreadings that would have delighted
Borges: Talbot argues that Schuchard takes Swedenborg’s erotic texts to
be descriptions of  this world, when Talbot argues that they are descrip-
tions of  the next one:

On a positive note, Schuchard does seem to have documented contemporary accounts


of antinomian sexual practices on the part of some Moravians and Jews, which
could illustrate accounts in the Spiritual Diary or Spiritual Experiences. However,
unlike Schuchard, I think that the vast majority of  these, and probably all of  them,
occurred or were presented to Swedenborg in his travels in the next world, not this
one. (2007: 206)

Only in the Swedenborg scholarship could such confusion between mun-


dane and celestial descriptions occur!9

9 Continuing this extraordinary dichotomy whereby Swedenborg’s spiritual experi-


ences may be confused with his physical experiences, a similar confusion may also
be found in Emerson’s analysis of  Swedenborg. According to Emerson, Swedenborg
predicted the discovery of  Uranus: ‘It seems that he anticipated much science of  the
nineteenth century; anticipated, in astronomy, the discovery of  the seventh planet
148 Chapter Three

Of greater importance is the inf luence that Swedenborg’s writings had


on many streams of esoteric thought, from Freemasonry to Theosophy, after
his death. Of  this matter, Garrett (1984) recounts Swedenborg’s prominent
position amongst, in particular, Kabbalistic and Masonic sects:

On the continent, in places as diverse as Paris, Avignon, St. Petersburg, and Stockholm,
Swedenborg’s imagery was absorbed into the rituals of occultist freemasonry by indi-
viduals who recognized its af finity with alchemical and cabalistic conceptions of
spiritual reality. […] Throughout Europe, those who dabbled in alchemy, cabalism,
and Mesmerism found in Swedenborg’s spiritual experiences one more confirma-
tion of  the existence of  truths beyond the reach of  the five senses. Many of  them
were Freemasons, associated with the various occultist and mystical lodges that had
sprung up in the eighteenth century. (Garrett 1984: 70 & 74)

Bergquist (2002: 98) similarly acknowledges that the Kabbalistic aspect


of  Swedenborg was discussed amongst the ‘Eranos Circle, a group of exis-
tentially oriented philosophers, theologians, psychologists, linguists and
historians who regularly met in Ascona in Switzerland bringing scholars
like C G Jung, Henry Corbin, Mircea Eliade, Ernst Benz and Gershom
Scholem together.’ Borges stated on numerous occasions that his under-
standing of  the Kabbalah derived from Scholem, whom he once met on
a trip to Israel. Therefore it is possible that Borges was aware that other
scholars had pursued this angle. In sum, therefore, Borges presented a curi-
ously naïve position when suggesting that he was the first to pursue the
connection between Swedenborg’s doctrine of correspondence and the
Kabbalah. The scholarship in this area is large.

[Uranus], – but, unhappily, not also of  the eighth [Neptune]’ (2003: 10). I have
not found anyone aside from Emerson claim this, so it could be that Emerson was
mistaking Swedenborg’s scientific statements with a visionary one. Swedenborg,
after all, did communicate in visions with inhabitants of other planets. It would be
astonishing indeed if  Swedenborg described the planets Uranus and Neptune in a
manner that would tally with their descriptions by Herschel (Uranus) and Le Verrier
and Adams (Neptune).
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 149

Spontaneous

I have found no indication that Borges was familiar with the branch of  the
scholarship of mysticism concerning psychedelics and the supposed dangers
of electing what Indian guru Meher Baba (1966) condemned as ‘short-cuts
to the divine’, or what Huxley (1954: 59) called ‘gratuitous grace’. That he
was familiar with Huxley is certain from his reviews of  Huxley’s works;
that he engaged with the arguments put forth in The Doors of  Perception
(1954) and Heaven and Hell (1956) is less certain. Nevertheless this is an
integral aspect of  the scholarship of mysticism, originating a century before
James in both scientific and Romantic literature, and reaching its apogee in
the 1960s (see Jay 2000, Doblin 1991, Rowlandson 2013). Borges’ misgiv-
ings of subversive social movements in the 1960s and his self-proclaimed
conservatism in his later decades would imply a rejection of any proposals
that mystical consciousness may be experienced through the ingestion of
psychoactive substances. Yet without encountering any specific declaration
on the matter, we can nevertheless conclude that Borges would posit that
such activities cannot constitute genuine mystical experience, as he indi-
cated that the mystical state is spontaneous and unmediated. Describing
his ‘timeless’ moment, Borges often suggested that the experience was
some manner of divine gift: ‘I had that experience, and I had it twice over,
and maybe it will be granted me to have it one more time before I die’
(Barnstone 1982: 10–11). He made no suggestion that the experience was
in any way inspired by the subject matter of  his reading material, nor the
consequence of  his meditative, trance-inducing strolls; rather that the expe-
rience was somehow ‘granted’ to him. When he suggested that ‘el fin [de
‘El Congreso’] quiere elevarse, sin duda en vano, a los éxtasis de Chesterton
o de John Bunyan. No he merecido nunca semejante revelación, pero he
procurado soñarla’ (1989: 72) [‘its end tries, doubtless in vain, to match the
ecstasies of  Chesterton and John Bunyan. I have never been worthy of such
a revelation, but I managed to dream one up’] (1979: 93), this would imply
an extrinsic, perhaps divine, agency that judges whether an individual may
or may not experience mystical consciousness.
Borges likewise emphasized that the first profound mystical experience
of  Swedenborg came upon him utterly unbidden. Despite the fact that ‘Lo
150 Chapter Three

precedieron sueños, plegarias, períodos de incertidumbre y de ayuno y, lo


que es harto más singular, de aplicada labor científica y filosófica’ (2005:
154) [‘the experience was preceded by dreams, prayers, periods of  fasting,
and – much more surprisingly – by diligent scientific and philosophi-
cal work’] (1995: 6), the appearance of  the phantom being that bespoke
the initiation of  the ensuing decades of mystical encounters was wholly a
matter of divine grace, unwilled by Swedenborg. Indeed Borges referred
to Swedenborg during this episode as ‘el elegido’ (2005: 154) [‘the chosen
one’] (1995: 6), an image that suggests godly agency beyond Swedenborg.
He also referred to Swedenborg’s London as ‘la ciudad en que Dios le había
encomendado una noche la misión que lo haría único entre los hombres’
(2005: 160) [‘the city in which God had one night entrusted to him the
mission that would make him unique among men’] (1995: 15). Likewise,
when comparing Swedenborg with Dante, Borges emphasized that owing
to the length of  Dante’s vision, it must have been not the product of grace,
but of  his own ‘poetic faith’; it was, accordingly, self-willed: ‘I think that his
vision was voluntary. His vision was the result of  his poetic faith’ (Alifano
1984: 95).
Although Staal (1975) and Zaehner (1961) identify that there are many
complications in the correlation of western, Christian, mystical traditions
and eastern traditions, whether Hindu, Buddhist, Tao or Zen, nevertheless
many scholars have noted af finities in the experience of practitioners across
these traditions. Borges wrote extensively about Buddhism, and, like Suzuki,
perceived the similarities between the meditative, non-rational aspect of 
Zen and aspects of western mysticism. In particular, Borges indicated that
whilst the Zen practitioner may engage in many years of arduous training,
the moment of sudden enlightenment – satori – arrives unbidden and
unannounced: ‘En la zen se ha descubierto un procedimiento para llegar a
la iluminación. Sólo sirve después de años de meditación. Se llega brusca-
mente; no se trata de una serie de silogismos. Uno debe intuir de pronto
la verdad. El procedimiento se llama satori y consiste en un hecho brusco,
que está más allá de la lógica’ (1989: 251–2) [‘In Zen they have discovered
a procedure to reach illumination. It only works after years of meditation.
It arrives suddenly: it is not the product of a series of syllogisms. One must
suddenly intuit the truth. The process is called satori, and it consists of a
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 151

sudden event that is beyond logic’] (1984: 72). The mystical experience,
therefore, in its brief and rare occurrence for Borges, and in its repeated
and sustained occurrences for Swedenborg, is not to be considered the
result of will or conscious desire, but as grace of  the divine.

Revelatory

The matter of revelation is intimately associated with James’ category of 


‘noetic’, but there is a slight variance of meaning. The revelation that Borges
would suggest is possible in the mystical experience is not only noetic but
is a revelation of matters that are beyond the scope of our normal conscious
understanding. In this respect mystics, according to Borges, are privy to
matters that non-mystics (the vast majority of us) are only able to compre-
hend second-hand. This is thus the most important of  the many categories,
as it is intimately tied into philosophical, religious and spiritual specula-
tions about death. It is also intimately tied to the category outlined above
about divine grace.
To begin with, one must evaluate the state of unknowing in which, in
Borges’ universe, it is our lot to be imprisoned. The labyrinth, as analysed in
so many critical studies of  Borges’ work, is the abiding symbol for this state
of inhabiting a universe whose meaning we are forever in ignorance. ‘Mazes
are to be explained by the fact that I live in a wonderful world. I mean, I am
baf f led all the time by things. I am astonished at things’ (Barnstone 1982:
36).10 Perhaps one of  the closest af finities with Schopenhauer’s thought is
the absence of divine purpose – of any knowable telos. As such we are all
governed by the impulsive will which drives us ever onwards towards no
known place. Just as Schopenhauer rejected Schelling and Hegel’s hope
for eventual harmony and reconciliation, so we see in Borges the absence
of a knowable end, but the recognition of a will that drives us onwards.
During life, as exemplified by the rapt conclusion of  ‘Undr’, a moment of

10 ‘I think of  the world as a riddle. And the one beautiful thing about it is that it can’t
be solved’ (Barnstone 1982: 8).
152 Chapter Three

ecstatic revelation is in relation to the here and now, that ‘a mí también la


vida me dio todo’ (1989: 51) [‘life gave me everything as well’] (1979: 63).
This is no revelation of divine purpose but only that the mystery itself may
be a source of wonder and joy. However, those mystic few – Swedenborg,
the Kabbalists – may receive illumination that transcends the mundane
and through which they understand aspects both of  human purpose and
the future of  the soul after death. Di Giovanni thus struck at the core of 
the problem when he asked Borges ‘Do you see mysticism as a way out of 
the maze?’ Borges replied: ‘For all I know, mysticism is the only way; but
my gods, whoever they may be, have not allowed me that particular way’
(Burgin 1998: 129, emphasis added). It would appear to Borges that divine
grace reveals answers to these mysteries to the mystics. Those less fortunate,
like Borges, are trapped between disbelief and cynicism and a sense that
the mystical texts may be bearers of  truth.
However, seeing as the revelation occurred to the mystic and not to
the reader, the reader must go on trust if  he is to presume the text to be
truthful. As such, Borges read Plato, and consequently Socrates, in order to
appraise the condition of  the soul after death. ‘Anoche no salí después de
comer y releí, para comprender estas cosas, la última enseñanza que Platón
pone en boca de su maestro. Leí que el alma puede huir cuando muere la
carne’ (1974: 790) [‘Last night I stayed in after dinner and reread, in order
to understand these things, the last teaching Plato put in his master’s mouth.
I read that the soul may escape when the f lesh dies’] (1970: 32). Borges
similarly speaks to his dead friend not knowing if  his words will be heard:
‘No sé si todavía eres alguien, no sé si estás oyéndome’ (1989: 466) [‘I do
not know if you are still someone, if you are hearing me’] (my translation).
A 1940 review of  J. W. Dunne concludes with Borges’ sublime sharing of 
Dunne’s ultimate thesis on time. ‘[Dunne] nos asegura que después de
la muerte aprenderemos el manejo feliz de la eternidad. Recobraremos
todos los instantes de nuestra vida y los combinaremos como nos plazca.
Dios y nuestros amigos y Shakespeare colaborarán con nosotros’ (2005:
564) [‘Dunne assures us that in death we shall finally learn how to handle
eternity. We shall recover all the moments of our lives and combine them
as we please. God and our friends and Shakespeare will collaborate with
us’] (2000: 219). He cannot deny the possibility of  the immortality of  the
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 153

soul, something that appears in so many of  his poems, yet he cannot accept
it unconditionally.
Likewise, and especially in his later poetry, Borges presents death and
mystical revelation through a Platonic perspective as the possibility that
the true nature of  things will be revealed. In the poem ‘The Unending
Rose’ (from La Rosa Profunda) the blind, old, and desert-battered Attar
of  Nishapur caresses a rose and lovingly lists its qualities. He wistfully ima-
gines the eternal Rose ‘Que el Señor mostrará a mis ojos muertos’ (1993:
465) [‘the Lord will show my dead eyes’] (Alifano 1984: 137). The poem
‘Elogio de la sombra’ concludes with the poignant hope that the poet’s
forthcoming death will be the revelation of  his true identity: Llego a mi
centro, / a mi álgebra y mi clave, / a mi espejo. / Pronto sabré quién soy’
(1975a: 126) [‘I reach my center, / my algebra and my key, / my mirror. /
Soon I shall know who I am’] (1975a: 127).
Borges’ ceaseless search for meaning, though, compelled him to
acknowledge that textual descriptions of  the mystics cannot, despite the
best powers of imagination, constitute true knowledge or experience. As
such the lucid prose of  Swedenborg, in which he reveals his vision and expe-
rience of  the otherworld, cannot be construed as empirical proof. Indeed a
further aspect of  the Borges obra suggests that even in death, and even with
the possibility of  the soul’s survival, the solution to the riddle of existence
will not be forthcoming. Death may be neither oblivion and annihilation
nor revelation of divine purpose. It may be simply another area of igno-
rance, and consequently the dead may be no nearer illumination than the
living. Jung found the souls of  the dead to be keen for human contact as
their own knowledge was lacking, describing in the opening lines of  Seven
Sermons to the Dead how the dead came seeking him as they remained
frustrated by ignorance.11 Swedenborg found dead wandering aimlessly

11 Around five o’clock in the afternoon on Sunday the front doorbell began ringing
frantically. It was a bright summer day; the two maids were in the kitchen, from which
the open square outside the front door could be seen. Everyone immediately looked
to see who was there, but there was no one in sight. I was sitting near the doorbell,
and not only heard it but saw it moving. We all simply stared at one another. The
atmosphere was thick, believe me! Then I knew that something had to happen. The
154 Chapter Three

around unable to grasp anything. He also describes the angels as engaging


in constant debates and discussions. If death were revelation, then the dead
and the angels would have nothing to discuss in the theological disputes
that Swedenborg observed in heaven, unless it were simply to pass the time.
Many psychopomps throughout the ages have had precisely this role in
leading the confused dead into the further realms of  the afterlife; indeed
Borges himself writes in Atlas that he was wary of revealing to Haydée
Lange that she was dead for fear that it would be ‘rude’. Furthermore, if
death did constitute revelation, then the many channels of communication
between the living and the dead would, at some stage, have transmitted
this knowledge. This, Borges notes, has not happened. Hence we have this
predicament built up in the poem ‘Ajedrez’ [‘Chess’]. The chess pieces are
unaware that their fate is determined by the hands of  the players; yet even
so the players are unaware of  the hand of  God controlling them; yet even
so God is unaware of  the hand of a further god – and so on. This god,
therefore, could become aware of  the contingent nature of  his own exist-
ence, could begin to question the nature of  his reality, and could, indeed,
become burdened with existential angst, as could the further gods along
this endless trajectory. One reading of  this poem is that existential angst
might be an inherent characteristic in Swedenborg’s communities of  the
dead as much as it is amongst living humans.
This extensive analysis of  the notion of revelation of  Borges inevitably
ref lects the position that I identified in the Introduction between reason
and intuition, credulity and scepticism. Yet it also demonstrates the notion
of  the paradox that James identified in the arena of mysticism: something is
learned, yet that something is inef fable. Consequently, how can the mystic
transmit the true noetic nature of  the experience?

whole house was filled as if  there were a crowd present, crammed full of spirits. They
were packed deep right up to the door, and the air was so thick it was scarcely pos-
sible to breathe. As for myself, I was all a-quiver with the question: ‘For God’s sake,
what in the world is this? Then they cried out in chorus, “We have come back from
Jerusalem where we found not what we sought.” That is the beginning of  the Septem
Sermones’ ( Jung 1989: 190–1).
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 155

Inef fable

Inef fability, as already mentioned, is a thorny question. Borges repeatedly


discussed the ability of  language to operate through reference to a consen-
sual experience: ‘In my life I only had two mystical experiences and I can’t
tell them because what happened is not to be put in words, since words,
after all, stand for a shared experience. And if you have not had the experi-
ence you can’t share it – as if you were to talk about the taste of cof fee and
had never tried cof fee’ (Barnstone 1982: 10–11). It is noteworthy that the
Borges-narrator’s account of  the impossibility to articulate the experience
of  the Aleph, and Borges’ description of  the dif ficulty of expressing the
timeless moment of  ‘Sentirse en muerte’, are perfectly in tune with James’
explanation of  his defining characteristic ‘inef fability’:

The handiest of  the marks by which I classify a state of mind as mystical is negative.
The subject of it immediately says that it defies expression, that no adequate report
of its contents can be given in words. It follows from this that its quality must be
directly experienced; it cannot be imparted or transferred to others. In this peculiar-
ity mystical states are more like states of  feeling than like states of intellect. No one
can make clear to another who has never had a certain feeling, in what the quality or
worth of it consists. One must have musical ears to know the value of a symphony;
one must have been in love one’s self  to understand a lover’s state of mind. Lacking the
heart or ear, we cannot interpret the musician or the lover justly, and are even likely
to consider him weak-minded or absurd. The mystic finds that most of us accord to
his experiences an equally incompetent treatment. ( James 1913: 380)

The sense that Borges developed is that the mystical experience is described
only in terms that necessarily fail to describe it, and hence ‘Para sugerir la
inefable unión del alma del hombre con la divinidad, los sufíes del Islam se
vieron obligados a recurrir a alegorías prodigiosas, a imágenes de rosas, de
embriaguez o de amor carnal’ (2005: 154) [‘To suggest the inef fable union
of man’s soul with the divine being, the Sufis of  Islam found themselves
obliged to resort to prodigious analogies, to images of roses, intoxication,
or carnal love’] (1995: 7). Not so with Swedenborg, Borges argued, who
was fully able to capture the essence of  his experience through scholarly
Latin. Herein one finds the Jamesian angle of  Borges’ comments, as James
156 Chapter Three

argues that the inef fability of  the experience lies not so much with the
transmission from experience to text, but from text to reader: ‘The mystic
finds that most of us accord to his experiences an equally incompetent treat-
ment’ ( James 1913: 380 emphasis added). As such, unlike Borges’ Sufis, it
is the reader who is unable to grasp the text rather than the text unable
to grasp the mystical moment. As I also suggest earlier, if  Borges empha-
sized the inability of  the Sufi poets to represent their experience, this itself
implies not so much the inef fable nature of  the experience, but the limited
vocabulary of  the Sufi poets. As such, Swedenborg was unique amongst
mystics not for the radicality of  his visions, but for his dazzling command
of  Latin. Despite the best ef forts of  both James and Borges to present the
category of inef fability as definitive, it is clear that many questions remain.

Outside of  time

Time, for Borges, is the essential mystery. There is scarcely an essay, fiction
or poem in which Borges did not discuss or illustrate the anomaly that is
time; indeed for Borges an experience of  the f lexibility of  time is perhaps
the primary constituent of  the mystical experience. He described in great
detail in ‘Sentirse en muerte’ that the abiding sense was that of moving
outside of  time and experiencing eternity. He discussed this matter in
interview: ‘Somehow the feeling came over me that I was living beyond
time’ (Barnstone 1982: 10–11). Concerning mysticism he stated that ‘I’ve
had only two experiences of  timeless time in eighty years’ (Barnstone 1982:
73). Barnstone even cites Borges’ sense of  the mystery of  time as a chapter
heading in Borges at Eighty: ‘Time is the Essential Mystery’. This is the
chapter in which Borges refers to St Augustine’s legendary baf f lement at
the strangeness that is time:

I think that time is the one essential mystery. Other things may be mysterious. Space
is unimportant. You can think of a spaceless universe, for example, a universe made
of music. We are listeners of course. But as for time, you have the one problem of
definition. I remember what Saint Augustine said: ‘What is time? If nobody asks
me, I know what it is. If  I am asked, I am ignorant, I do not know.’ I think that the
problem of  time is the problem. (Barnstone 1982: 111)
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 157

We recall that the nature of  the vision of  the Aleph is both infinite space
and infinite time, and thus no distinction is to be made between the past,
present and future. He expressed to Biguenet and Whalen that ‘eternity
is supposed to be timeless. God or a mystic perceives in one moment all
of our yesterdays’ (Burgin 1998: 212). In this we can understand that the
vision of  the Aleph was an attempt – albeit ironic and parodic – to por-
tray such a mystical rapture. The dominant characteristic of  the mystical
experience was, for Borges, the transcending of mundane time. Writing
about Swedenborg’s angels in El Libro de los Seres Imaginarios Borges
declared that ‘En el Cielo no existe el tiempo’ (1967: 63) [‘In Heaven there
is no time’] (1974: 137). Ayora (1973: 595) identifies a strongly Gnostic
aspect to Borges’ treatment of  time, suggesting that Borges’ views of  the
circularity of  time over linearity constitute of a rejection of  the hegemonic
Christian worldview, and that ‘Any reader of  Borges’ works will agree that
Borges’ whole being rebels against the power of  time as a crucial dimen-
sion of reality.’ He discussed with Burgin ‘the idea of dif ferent times. Of
dif ferent time schemes’ (Burgin 1998: 39) which he had depicted in ‘New
Refutation of  Time’, and he discussed in the same interview ‘Psychological
time’, which implies the dimension in which the most synchronistic of 
Jung’s psychic phenomena can occur. This irregular pattern of  time, upon
consideration, can be considered the mainstay of  his entire fictional and
poetic work: Hladík experiences a year in a moment of  temporal stasis;
Menard becomes the seventeenth century Cervantes; the younger and
elder Borges bend time to meet each other both in ‘El Encuentro’ and
‘Veinticinco de agosto, 1983’; the players in the poem ‘Truco’ are plunged
into archetypal time through entering the ludic space; and so on. The
instances are too numerous to cover and would constitute a critical study
in its own right. In addition to other aspects of  the mystical experience,
therefore, the most profound and recurrent characteristic of  the descrip-
tions provided in mystical texts – from Plato and Plotinus through to
Blake and Xul Solar – is this sense of  transcending the regular linear
pattern of  time.
158 Chapter Three

Transient

There is a beautiful paradox exposed in this matter of time and the mystical
experience. The mystic, for both James and Borges, experiences a radically
altered perspective of  time, and yet this vision can only be transient, not
persistent. Eternity, in this sense, can only be experienced in an instant.
James describes the essence of  this transience:

Mystical states cannot be sustained for long. Except in rare instances, half an hour,
or at most an hour or two, seems to be the limit beyond which they fade into the
light of common day. Often, when faded, their quality can but imperfectly be repro-
duced in memory; but when they recur it is recognized; and from one recurrence to
another it is susceptible of continuous development in what is felt as inner richness
and importance. (1913: 381)

We recall Borges’ assertion that Dante’s vision could not have been truly
mystical: ‘I don’t believe that Dante was a visionary; a vision is something
more f leeting, something more ethereal. A vision as prolonged as The
Divine Comedy is impossible’ (Alifano 1984: 95). He also described his
own mystical experiences as mystical in part because of  their transiency: ‘It
may have been a minute or so, it may have been longer. […] Somehow the
feeling came over me that I was living beyond time, and I did my best to
capture it, but it came and went’ (Barnstone 1982: 11). Despite the regular-
ity of  Swedenborg’s visions, Borges likewise emphasized their transiency,
examining in ‘Testigo’ how dreams and daylight visions would occur to
Swedenborg in brief and illuminating spells, rarely of any duration. Whilst
one may pursue the lasting legacy of  the mystical vision – James’ category
of  ‘noetic’ – the vision itself in both James’ and Borges’ assessment is nec-
essarily of a transient nature.

Transformative

As established, it is clear that Borges’ own transient, timeless, mystical


moments were of such transformative power that they constituted the prime
motivation for his abiding fascination with mysticism, the anomalies of 
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 159

time, exploration of consciousness, studies of religious texts and anomalous


human experiences. It is thus particularly important to consider his desire
as an octogenarian to spend a sustained period in retreat in Japan in order,
precisely, to correlate his own experiences with those engraved in eastern
spiritual traditions. That the experience was transformative is one matter;
that it constituted a source of  knowledge of  the structure of reality is of  far
greater significance. In this respect, one can appraise what for Borges was
the epistemological value of mysticism, a perspective that may be aligned
closely with James’ category of noetic quality:

Although so similar to states of  feeling, mystical states seem to those who experi-
ence them to be also states of  knowledge. They are states of insight into depths of 
truth unplumbed by the discursive intellect. They are illuminations, revelations, full
of significance and importance, all inarticulate though they remain; and as a rule
they carry with them a curious sense of authority for after-time. ( James 1913: 380–1)

The central thesis of  James’ chapter on mysticism in Varieties is that the mys-
tical experience grants the mystic ‘authority’ in his understanding of reality
that stands beyond analytical scrutiny. This, clearly, is the chief rationalist
concern with the mystical experience, something present in Kant’s dis-
missal of  Swedenborg’s theological authority in his dense, bewildering and
under-studied Dreams of a Spirit-seer, and present in Russell’s critique of 
the alleged authority of  the mystic. In Borges’ analysis, Silesius, Swedenborg
and Blake gained true insight into the mysteries of existence through the
intuitive, experiential pathway of vision. This, he emphasized repeatedly
in discussion about Swedenborg, was neither falsehood, madness, delusion
nor hallucination, but a perspective on the real as epistemologically valid as
any rationalistic discourse. Indeed one senses that for Borges this mode of
enquiry into the nature of existence was of greater epistemological worth
than any other discourse because, in its pre-religious, perennial nature, it
transcends the limitations of orthodox structures of  thought, whether, as
discussed, philosophical, theological, cultural or political. James concludes
his exploration of mysticism with the strikingly pragmatic summary of  the
authority that the mystical experience confers:
160 Chapter Three

(1) Mystical states, when well developed, usually are, and have the right to be, abso-
lutely authoritative over the individuals to whom they come.
(2) No authority emanates from them which should make it a duty for those who
stand outside of  them to accept their revelations uncritically.
(3) They break down the authority of  the non-mystical or rationalistic conscious-
ness, based upon the understanding and the senses alone. They show it to be only
one kind of consciousness. They open out the possibility of other orders of  truth, in
which, so far as anything in us vitally responds to them, we may freely continue to
have faith. ( James 1913: 422–3)12

That Borges’ perspective is Jamesian is at once evident, although we cannot


at this level determine whether James was the prime inf luence upon Borges
in this matter. That James’ pragmatic conclusion is strikingly Borgesian
avant la lettre might also be argued.

12 ‘Once more, then, I repeat that non-mystics are under no obligation to acknowledge
in mystical states a superior authority conferred on them by their intrinsic nature.
Yet, I repeat once more, the existence of mystical states absolutely overthrows the
pretension of non-mystical states to be the sole and ultimate dictators of what we
may believe. As a rule, mystical states merely add a supersensuous meaning to the
ordinary outward data of consciousness. They are excitements like the emotions
of  love or ambition, gifts to our spirit by means of which facts already objectively
before us fall into a new expressiveness and make a new connection with our active
life. They do not contradict these facts as such, or deny anything that our senses have
immediately seized. It is the rationalistic critic rather who plays the part of denier
in the controversy, and his denials have no strength, for there never can be a state
of  facts to which new meaning may not truthfully be added, provided the mind
ascend to a more enveloping point of view. It must always remain an open question
whether mystical states may not possibly be such superior points of view, windows
through which the mind looks out upon a more extensive and inclusive world. The
dif ference of  the views seen from the dif ferent mystical windows need not prevent
us from entertaining this supposition. The wider world would in that case prove to
have a mixed constitution like that of  this world, that is all. It would have its celestial
and its infernal regions, its tempting and its saving moments, its valid experiences
and its counterfeit ones, just as our world has them; but it would be a wider world all
the same. We should have to use its experiences by selecting and subordinating and
substituting just as is our custom in this ordinary naturalistic world; we should be
liable to error just as we are now; yet the counting in of  that wider world of meanings,
and the serious dealing with it, might, in spite of all the perplexity, be indispensable
stages in our approach to the final fullness of  the truth’ ( James 1913: 427–8).
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 161

Conclusion

As established in the previous chapter, in addition to the articulation of 


the defining characteristics of mysticism, which I have now performed
for Borges, there is no way that the hierarchical judgement of value of  the
mystical experience can be divorced from the scholars’ own theological,
moral, ethical, assumptions. One might argue that if a scholar has tabulated
the defining criteria for mysticism, then, in order to determine whether a
particular figure was or was not a mystic, a simple cross-referencing of  the
texts/biography against the criteria would suf fice to determine the mystical
status of  that figure. Yet, as I have argued, we are not dealing with a scientific
matter of clear classificatory divisions – vertebrate/invertebrate, mammal/
reptile – but a deeply personal, f luid and mercurial set of determinants that
defy rigid categorisation. As such it is inevitable that the personal prefer-
ences of  the scholars should be immediately inf luential upon the scholarly
investigation, and it is to be expected that no two approaches to mysticism
will be in perfect accord. Furthermore, owing to the f luidity of  the whole
field, one scholar may be able to align a particular poet or religious figure
with the defining characteristics of, say, James, whilst another will deny
that this figure fits these criteria. This, as established, has been the case
in the scholarship of, amongst others, Blake, Emerson, Yeats and Borges.
In appraising Borges’ perspectives on mysticism and mystics, it becomes
clear that there is nothing objective – that is to say removed from the subject
and unbiased by personal will, desire or experience – in his views; and nei-
ther should there. As such, the evaluation of mysticism is in every sense an
evaluation of  Borgesian mysticism. Swedenborg, here, is not Swedenborg,
but Borges’ Swedenborg – Swedenborges. In his biographical studies of 
Swedenborg, Borges emphasized those characteristics that were closest
to his own philosophical perspectives: the prodigious intellect, choice of 
literature,13 studious and solitary existence, disdain for orthodoxy, interest

13 ‘Dejó buenos hexámetros latinos y la literatura inglesa –Spencer, Shakespeare, Cowley,


Milton y Dryden– le interesó por su poder imaginativo’ (2005: 153) [‘He wrote good
162 Chapter Three

in original texts over translations, relationship with the Kabbalah, measured


and sober prose, etc. J. M. Cohen is the only critic I have encountered to
notice the kinship between the figure of  Swedenborg depicted in Borges’
poem ‘Emanuel Swedenborg’ and Borges himself, arguing that the poem
is in some respects ‘a self-portrait of  the private Borges, disguised under
the name of  Emanuel Swedenborg’ (1973: 95).
In the same way, one must suppose that Borges’ dismissal of  Pascal, Luis
de León, Juan de la Cruz and Teresa de Ávila has less to do with a full evalu-
ation of  their supposed mystical attributes, and more in relation to Borges’
desire to mock sacred cows, upset Catholic traditionalists, and choose his
cultural heroes from the northern climes. Thus his love for Swedenborg
cannot be separated from his love of  Icelandic sagas, Anglo-Saxon poetry
and his own Northumberland ancestry. He contrasted Swedenborg both
with those mystics one may consider apart from ‘las circunstancias y urgen-
cias que llamamos, nunca sabré por qué, la realidad’ (2005: 152) [‘removed
from the circumstances and urgencies we call […] reality’] (1995: 3), and
those characterized by ‘el éxtasis del alma arrebatada y enajenada’ (2005:
153) [‘the ecstasy of a rapt and fainting soul’] (1995: 7). As such, in his few
comments about Teresa and the Spaniards, one may suggest that Borges
would judge Teresa to be pious, orthodox, ecstatic and removed from
worldly concerns. Whilst she may have been both pious and ecstatic, one
cannot judge her to be either docile or obedient to church authority, nor
anything other than deeply involved in the political ecclesiastical machi-
nations of  her time. Thus it would seem that Borges conducted a fairly
selective reading of  those mystics he contrasted with Swedenborg owing
to his own personal af finities and inclinations.
A selective reading, though, is inevitable. Borges constructed a nar-
rative in which Swedenborg was only Christian by default – i.e. not by
intellectual choice – whose very experiences were of an order both beyond
and superior to the orthodox teachings of  his day. This, as discussed, is a
familiar feature in the Swedenborg scholarship, as each critic or biographer

Latin hexameters and was interested in English literature – Spenser, Shakespeare,


Cowley, Milton, and Dryden – because of its imaginative power’ [1995: 5]).
In the shadow of  William James: Borges as scholar of mysticism 163

concentrates on those biographical matters most dear to him/herself.


Conan Doyle, for example, eschews Swedenborg’s theological works
in favour of  his spirit mediumship. James, like Borges, emphasized the
dialectic apparent in Swedenborg between orthopraxy and heteropraxy.
Schuchard pays great attention to the erotic and esoteric world in which
she portrays Swedenborg as inseparably enmeshed. Her critical reviewer,
Talbot, a dedicated Swedenborgian, refutes such erotic claims both with
substantial evidence and, it appears, with personal moralistic disgust, and
proposes that Swedenborg’s piety would have prevented him being drawn
into such dubious occult practices.
In sum, therefore, it is clear that Borges paid great attention not only to
the aesthetic and imaginative nature of mystical texts, but to the ontologi-
cal and epistemological challenges that the texts engendered. Like James
he correlated his own experiences (though not induced by nitrous oxide)
with his profound reading of  the wide and varied literature, and from this
twin reading synthesized a series of defining characteristics of  the mystical
experience. However, unlike James, Borges claimed to be no theorist or
philosopher, and consequently he never articulated these defining charac-
teristics in a simple enumeration. From a reading of  his many essays, tales,
reviews and interviews, it is possible to establish the theoretical platform
from which he based his interpretation of  the mystical texts. As I hope to
have demonstrated, the figure of  William James and his work in Varieties
is manifestly present.
Chapter Four

Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges

The Arabians say, that Abul Khair, the mystic, and Abu Ali Seena, the
philosopher, conferred together; and, on parting, the philosopher said,
‘All that he sees, I know’; and the mystic said, ‘All that he knows, I see’.
— Ralph Waldo Emerson, Representative Men

Why was he gazing upwards from the steps of  the porch, hearing their
shrill twofold cry, watching their f light? For an augury of good or evil?
A phrase of  Cornelius Agrippa f lew through his mind and then there
f lew hither and thither shapeless thoughts from Swedenborg on the cor-
respondence of  birds to things of  the intellect and of  how the creatures of 
the air have their knowledge and know their times and seasons because
they, unlike man, are in the order of  their life and have not perverted
that order by reason.
— James Joyce, A Portrait of  the Artist As a Young Man

Ralph Waldo Emerson is a powerful presence in Borges. He is referred to in


many essays, interviews, tales and poems. Borges dedicated a sonnet to him
and listed him amongst his enumeration of  treasures in the poem ‘Elogio de
la sombra’. He also translated Emerson’s Representative Men into Spanish.
Far too many to list here, the many references to Emerson in Borges’ works
are invariably employed as herald for an exploration of a particular literary
or philosophical theme.1 Most importantly and most frequently, Borges

1 ‘Emerson, lector de los hindúes y de Attar, deja el poema Brahma’ (1974: 251)
[‘Emerson, reader of  the Hindus and of  Attar, left us the poem Attar’] (my transla-
tion); ‘Esa misma intuición de que el universo es una proyección de nuestra alma y
de que la historia universal está en cada hombre, hizo escribir a Emerson el poema
166 Chapter Four

refers to Emerson’s notion of  the One Book in which all books are written,
citing (and translating) Emerson in ‘La Flor de Coleridge’: ‘“Diríase que
una sola persona ha redactado cuantos libros hay en el mundo; tal unidad
central hay en ellos que es innegable que son obra de un solo caballero
omnisciente”’ (1974: 639) [‘“I am very much struck in literature by the
appearance that one person wrote all the books”’] (1964: 9). It is signifi-
cant that Borges quotes from this particular essay of  Emerson ‘Nominalist
and Realist’ in the very essay in which he presents the historical polarity
of nominalists and realists; indeed one can see ‘La Flor de Coleridge’ in
many respects as a condensed edition of  Emerson’s essay.2
Borges was ef fusive about his own admiration of and debt to Emerson,
stating: ‘I like to be indebted to Emerson, one of my heroes’ (Barnstone
1982: 67), and ‘I greatly admired Emerson’ (1975b: 717), calling Emerson
‘un caballero y un clásico’ (2005: 44) [‘a gentleman and a classic’] (my

que se titula History’ (1974: 679) [‘That same intuition that the universo is a projec-
tion of our soul and that universal history is within every man, compeled Emerson
to write the poem entitled History’] (my translation). ‘Emerson dijo que una bib-
lioteca es un gabinete mágico en el que hay muchos espíritus hechizados’ (1989:
254) [‘Emerson said that a library is a magic cabinet full of  bewitched spirits’] (my
translation). ‘Emerson dijo que el lenguaje es poesía fósil’ (1989: 440) [‘Emerson
said that language is fossil poetry’] (my translation). We find this in Borges at Eighty:
‘I remember what Emerson said: language is fossil poetry. He said every word is a
metaphor. You can verify that by looking a word up in the dictionary. All words are
metaphors – or fossil poetry, a fine metaphor itself ’ (Barnstone 1982: 165). ‘Emerson
wrote that “arguments convince nobody” and that it is suf ficient to state a truth for it
to be accepted’ (1971b: 26). This line also appears in Borges’ essay on Swedenborg: ‘A
la manera de Emerson y de Walt Whitman, creía que los argumentos no persuaden a
nadie y que basta enunciar una verdad para que los interlocutores la acepten’ (2005:
155) [‘Like Emerson and Walt Whitman he [Swedenborg] believed that arguments
persuade no one and that stating a truth is suf ficient for its acceptance by those who
hear it’ (1995: 8)].
2 In the essay that Borges cites, ‘Nominalist and Realist’, Emerson writes: ‘I am very
much struck in literature by the appearance, that one person wrote all the books; as
if  the editor of a journal planted his body of reporters in dif ferent parts of  the field
of action, and relieved some by others from time to time; but there is such equality
and identity both of judgment and point of view in the narrative, that it is plainly
the work of one all-seeing, all-hearing gentleman’ (2005: 270).
Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges 167

translation), and praising his intellectual poetry: ‘I love Emerson and I


am very fond of  his poetry. He is to me the one intellectual poet – in any
case, the one intellectual poet who has ideas. The others are merely intel-
lectual with no ideas at all. In the case of  Emerson he had ideas and was
thoroughly a poet’ (Barnstone 1982: 5). There are many ways of assessing
this debt that Borges owes Emerson. To begin with, one can start from the
outside and acknowledge the innumerable occasions Borges praises the
large body of nineteenth century writers from the East Coast of  the US:
‘Literature would not be what it is today had there been no Edgar Allan
Poe, no Walt Whitman […] no Herman Melville, no Thoreau, and no
Emerson’ (Barnstone 1982: 5); to whom one would add other of  Borges’
prized authors: Longfellow, Hawthorne, Emily Dickinson (‘perhaps the
greatest lady writer and the greatest poet that America – I’m thinking of
our America also – has yet produced’ (Barnstone 1982: 5)), and, though of
a younger generation, William and Henry James.3 All these writers were to
a greater or lesser degree inf luenced by Emerson as the leading figure in a
literary, philosophical and social movement known as Transcendentalism.
The af finity between Borges and this movement is visible in Borges’ own
description of its history and genesis:

The roots of  transcendentalism were multiple: Hindu pantheism, Neoplatonic specu-
lations, the Persian mystics, the visionary theology of Swedenborg, German idealism,
and the writings of  Coleridge and Carlyle. It also inherited the ethical preoccupa-
tions of  the Puritans. Edwards had taught that God can infuse the soul of the chosen
with a supernatural light; Swedenborg and the cabalists, that the external world is a
mirror of  the spiritual. Such ideas inf luenced both the poets and the prose writers
of  Concord. The immanence of  God in the universe was perhaps the central doc-
trine. Emerson reiterated that there is no being who is not a microcosm, a minuscule
universe. The soul of  the individual is identified with the soul of  the world; physical
laws are mingled with moral laws. If  God is in every soul, all external authority disap-
pears. All that each man needs is his own profound and secret divinity. Emerson and
Thoreau are now the most prominent names in the movement, which also inf luenced
Longfellow, Melville, and Whitman. The most illustrious individual example of  the
movement was Emerson (1803–1882). (Borges 1971b: 24–5)

3 Mark Twain must also be mentioned, though he was from Missouri.


168 Chapter Four

Quite clearly, noting these inf luences upon Emerson and his group, and
noting the inf luence of these dif fering streams of philosophical and religious
thought upon Borges, one must readily conjecture that Borges’ member-
ship in the Transcendentalists was only prevented by time and geography.4
Barnstone identifies the Emersonian aspect of  Borges, employing a pecu-
liarly problematic judgment of  ‘secular mystic’:

So, along with the mathematician of  time and the cerebral master, intensely passion-
ate and despondent, there is the exquisitely calm and wise man who is reconciled to
human limitations, and to a godless world that will forever suggest yet disguise its
mystery. There is the Borges of  Emersonian transcendence, the secular mystic, and
[…] there is the man waiting in the ghetto of  his earthly blindness, free from the
tyranny of metaphor and myth. (Barnstone 2000: 47)

There are many similarities between Borges and Emerson at the level of 
literary taste, style, poetics, secular religiosity, af finity to mysticism, and
a philosophical outlook coloured by Stoicism, Idealism, Puritanism and
Americanism.5 The debt that Borges owes to Emerson’s particular style can

4 That is, despite the assertion of  Holditch: ‘Any attempt to make a case for Borges as
a Transcendentalist in the Emersonian sense would be foolish and futile, but what
is apparent from the evidence of fered above, incomplete as it may be, is the fact that
Borges feels for that “tall gentleman” of  Concord both an admiration and an af finity.
The value of  finding and analyzing such a relationship is the evidence it of fers for
the value of  tradition and the relationship of  that tradition to poets and poetry,
and the insight which such a study can af ford readers to the writings of  two great
“intellectual” poets, one of  the nineteenth century, one of  the present; of  two – as
Borges himself might express it – “amanuenses” of  the one great Spirit that connects
all literature of  the past and present and – if  human beings continue to read – of  the
future’ (1986: 206).
5 Borges also attributes his dislike of newspapers to Emerson: ‘Borges: La crucifixión
de Cristo fue importante después, no cuando ocurrió. Por eso yo jamás he leído un
diario, siguiendo el consejo de Emerson. Sábato: ¿Quién? Borges: Emerson, que
recomendaba leer libros, no diarios’ (Borges & Sábato 2002: 18). [‘Borges: The cru-
cifixion of  Christ was important afterwards, not when it occurred. That’s why I have
never read a newspaper, following the advice of  Emerson. Sábato: Who? Borges:
Emerson, who recommended reading books, not newspapers’] (my translation).
Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges 169

be appraised by a comparison of  these two passages, the first from Emerson’s
1841 essay ‘The Transcendentalist’, the second from Borges’ essay on Keats:

What is popularly called Transcendentalism among us, is Idealism. […] As thinkers,


mankind have ever divided into two sects, Materialists and Idealists; the first class
founding on experience, the second on consciousness; the first class beginning to
think from the data of  the senses, the second class perceive that the senses are not
final, and say, the senses gives us representations of  things, but what are the things
themselves, they cannot tell. The materialist insists on facts, on history, on the force
of circumstances, and the animal wants of man; the idealist on the power of  Thought
and of  Will, on inspiration, on miracle, on individual culture. (Emerson 2005: 98)

Coleridge observes that all men are born Aristotelians or Platonists. The latter feel
that classes, orders, and genres are realities; the former, that they are generalizations.
For the latter, language is nothing but an approximative set of symbols; for the former,
it is the map of  the universe. The Platonist knows that the universe is somehow a
cosmos, an order; that order, for the Aristotelian, can be an error or a fiction of our
partial knowledge. Across the latitudes and the epochs, the two immortal antagonists
change their name and language: one is Parmenides, Plato, Spinoza, Kant, Francis
Bradley; the other, Heraclitus, Aristotle, Locke, Hume, William James. In the ardu-
ous schools of  the Middle Ages they all invoke Aristotle, the master of  human reason
(Convivio, IV, 2), but the nominalists are Aristotle; the realists, Plato. The English
nominalism of  the fourteenth century reappears in the scrupulous English idealism
of  the eighteenth century; the economy of  Occam’ formula, entia sunt multiplicanda
praetor necessitatem, permits or prefigures the no less precise esse est percipi. Men, said
Coleridge, are born Aristotelians or Platonists; one can state of  the English mind
that it as born Aristotelian. For that mind, not abstract concepts but individual
ones are real; not the generic nightingale, but concrete nightingales. It is natural, it
is perhaps inevitable, that in England the ‘Ode to a Nightingale’ is not understood
correctly. (Borges 1964: 129)6

6 For ease of comparison I have placed the translation first. Herewith the original:
‘Observa Coleridge que todos los hombres nacen aristotélicos o platónicos. Los
últimos sienten que las clases, los órdenes y los géneros son realidades; los primeros,
que son generalizaciones; para éstos, el lenguaje no es otra cosa que un aproxima-
tivo juego de símbolos; para aquellos es el mapa del universo. El platónico sabe que
el universo es de algún modo un cosmos, un orden; ese orden, para el aristotélico,
puede ser un error o una ficción de nuestro conocimiento parcial. A través de las
latitudes y de las épocas, los dos antagonistas inmortales cambian de dialecto y de
170 Chapter Four

For further and more detailed appraisal of this inf luence, see, Christ (1969),
Coleman (1972), Golobof f (1977), Holditch (1986). It is Emerson, indeed,
whom Coleman refers to as ‘at the heart of  Borges’ Aesthetics’ (1972: 359).
The avenue of enquiry that is of interest to us here, though, is the particu-
lar relationship to mysticism, and in particular to Swedenborg, that links
Emerson to Borges. Borges suggests further that it was thanks to Emerson
that he, as a young man in Geneva, first encountered Swedenborg:

Lo conocí por Emerson. Porque Emerson tiene un libro: ‘Representative Men’. Ese
libro está escrito un poco a la manera de ‘On Heroes Heroworship and the Heroic
In History’, de Carlyle, que fue de algún modo su maestro; entonces, él toma dis-
tintos tipos humanos. Recuerdo que son: Montaigne o el escéptico, Swedenborg o
el místico, Shakespeare o el poeta, Napoleón o el hombre del mundo y Goethe o
el escritor. Yo comencé leyendo ese libro. Ese libro lo leí en Ginebra en el año 14 ó
5; y luego, mi padre tenía un ejemplar de ‘Heaven and Hell’, ‘Caelo et Inferno’; él
lo tenía en una edición de la Everyman’s Library. Bien, yo leí ese libro y encargué a
Inglaterra los otros tres publicados por la misma editorial. Publicaron cuatro libros de
Swedenborg de acuerdo con la Sociedad Swedenborg de Londres. Y luego en francés
conozco solamente una versión de Caelo et lnferno’. Swedenborg fue a Inglaterra
porque quería conocer a Newton, y finalmente no pudo lograrlo, qué raro, eh? Yo he
hablado mucho sobre Swedenborg con el pintor y místico argentino Xul Solar, yo era
muy amigo de Xul, iba a casa de él en la calle Laprida 1214, y leíamos a Swedenborg,
leíamos a Blake, leíamos a los poetas alemanes, leíamos al poeta inglés Swinburne y
muchos otros textos. (Wildner 1991)

nombre: uno es Parménides, Platón, Spinoza, Kant, Francis Bradley; el otro, Heráclito,
Aristóteles, Locke, Hume, William James. En las arduas escuelas de la Edad Media,
todos invocan a Aristóteles, maestro de la humana razón (Convivio IV 2), pero los
nominalistas son Aristóteles; los realistas Platón. El nominalismo inglés del siglo xiv
resurge en el escrupuloso idealismo inglés del siglo xvii; la economía de la fórmula
de Occam, entia non sunt multiplicanda, praeter necessitatem permite o prefigura el
no menos taxativo esse est percipi. Los hombres, dijo Coleridge, nacen aristotélicos o
platónicos; de la mente inglesa cabe afirmar que nació aristotélica. Lo real, para esa
mente, no son los conceptos abstractos, sino los individuos; no el ruiseñor genérico,
sino los ruiseñores concretos. Es natural, es acaso inevitable, que en Inglaterra no sea
comprendida rectamente la Oda a un ruiseñor’ (1974: 718–19).
Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges 171

[I encountered Swedenborg through Emerson, through his ‘Representative men’, a


book written somewhat in the style of  On Heroes and Hero Worship and the Heroic
in History by Carlyle, who was in some sense his master. Emerson, as such, used the
model of distinct human types. I remember who they were: Montaigne or the Sceptic,
Swedenborg or the Mystic, Shakespeare or the Poet, Napoleon or the Man of  the
World, and Goethe or the Writer. I began to read this book in Geneva in 1914 or
15. Later my father had a copy of  Heaven and Hell (Caelo et Inferno) in the edition
of  Everyman’s Library. Well, I read this book and ordered from England the other
three of  his works published by the same publisher. They published four Swedenborg
works in collaboration with the Swedenborg Society in London. In French I know
of only one edition of  Caelo et Inferno. Swedenborg went to England because he
wanted to meet Newton, and yet in the end he never did meet him. Strange, eh? I
have spoken on many occasions about Swedenborg with the Argentine painter and
mystic Xul Solar, who was a good friend of mine. I would go to his house on Calle
Laprida 1214 and we would read Swedenborg, we would read Blake, we would read
the German poets, we would read the English poet Swinburne and many other
texts.] (My translation)

McNeilly, in the introduction to Emerson on Swedenborg: introducing


the mystic, perceived the legacy of  Emerson’s essay on Borges: ‘Jorge Luis
Borges, some 50 years later, indicated its continued importance by uti-
lising its premise as a counterpoint for his own essay on Swedenborg’
(Emerson 2003: viii). McNeilly refers to Emerson’s Representative Men,
which Borges translated and whose centrepiece, for Borges, was the essay
on Swedenborg. The particular ‘premise’ is not specified, but as we shall
now analyse, Emerson’s essay served as something of a blueprint for Borges’
biographical essay of  Swedenborg, ‘Testigo de lo invisible’; indeed Borges
pays respects to Emerson’s essay in the opening lines: ‘En su admirable
conferencia de 1845 Ralph Waldo Emerson eligió a Emanuel Swedenborg
como prototipo del místico’ (2005: 152) [‘In his famous lecture of 1845,
Ralph Waldo Emerson cited Emanuel Swedenborg as a classic example of 
the mystic’] (1995: 3). Borges also referred elsewhere to Emerson’s essay as
‘aquella espléndida conferencia que dio Emerson’ (2005: 201) [‘that splen-
did address that Emerson delivered’] (my translation). What is of crucial
concern in charting the trajectory of inf luence is that both Emerson and
Borges based much of  their overall principles of mysticism and mystics on
their reading of Swedenborg, and thus their respective essays constitute their
172 Chapter Four

essential theoretical model of  the enigmatic phenomenon. The inf luence of 
Emerson on Borges thus becomes a determining factor in Borges’ under-
standing of mysticism.

Emerson and Borges on Swedenborg

It is important to stress the impact that Swedenborg had on Emerson and


his companions, many of whom as we have seen, were favourite authors of 
Borges. Colin Wilson (1995: 90) considers the reasons behind this, exam-
ining the dif ficulty of  those nineteenth century writers who were sceptical
of  the church yet profoundly religious:

Swedenborg belonged to an age of  faith, when the majority of people believed in
angels and devils; now, the new German critics insisted that the Bible was merely a
piece of imaginative fiction, and that Jesus never existed. Intellectual men began to
look back on the ‘age of  faith’ with nostalgia. Many of  them – like Carlyle, Tennyson,
Emerson, Melville – were men of religious feelings who were totally unable to accept
traditional Christianity; they felt stranded in an emotional wasteland.

Wilson’s comments are strangely reminiscent of so many of  the descrip-


tions of  Borges: mistrustful of orthodoxy – whether religious, political
or even literary – yet invested with an intense respect for the numinous.
Emerson’s essay on Swedenborg was delivered as a series of public lectures;
he only submitted the manuscript for publication a number of years later.
This also is reminiscent of  Borges, who delivered a series of  lectures on
Swedenborg, most famously at the University of  Belgrano, Buenos Aires.
In both cases, furthermore, their essays are biographical sketches with
interpolated philosophical commentaries.
Both Emerson and Borges wrote short poems on Swedenborg which
were included alongside the essays in later publications. There are striking
similarities in the poems, not least their peculiarly bombastic and unemo-
tive style, what Borges would praise in Emerson as ‘intellectual’. Note, for
example, Emerson’s line: ‘In spirit-worlds he trod alone, / But walked the
Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges 173

earth unmarked, unknown’, and Borges’: ‘Más alto que los otros, caminaba /
Aquel hombre lejano entre los hombres’ [‘Taller than the others, this man /
Walked among them, at a distance’]. Or Emerson’s line: ‘Through snows
above, mines underground, / The inks of  Erebus he found’, and Borges’:
‘Lo que no ven los otros terrenales: / La ardiente geometría, el cristalino /
Laberinto de Dios y el remolino / Sórdido de los goces infernales.’ [‘That
which earthly eyes do not see: / The fierce geometry, the crystal / Labyrinth
of  God and the sordid / Milling of infernal delights’]. That Borges found
inspiration for his laudatory sonnet in Emerson’s verse is at once evident.
There is much to compare between the two essays, and there are many
identifiable hooks that link the two. Borges, for example, mimics Emerson
in the equation of  Swedenborg’s voyages to the otherworld with his Viking
heritage and the legacy of epic voyages. Emerson writes that Swedenborg
laboured ‘with the heart and strength of  the rudest Viking that his rough
Sweden ever sent to battle’ (2003: 15). Borges writes: ‘No one was less like a
monk than that sanguine Scandinavian who went much farther than Erik
the Red’ (1995: 3).7 Emerson writes: ‘This man, who appeared to his con-
temporaries a visionary, and elixir of moonbeams, no doubt led the most
real life of any man then in the world’ (2003: 7).8 Borges writes: ‘The word
[mystic] runs the risk of suggesting a man apart […] No one is less like that
image than Emanuel Swedenborg. […] No one accepted life more fully, no
one investigated it with such passion, with the same intellectual love, or
with such impatience to understand it’ (1995: 3).9 Emerson writes: ‘Having
adopted the belief  that certain books of  the Old and New Testaments were

7 ‘Nadie más distinto de un monje que ese escandinavo sanguíneo, que fue mucho más
lejos que Enrico el Rojo’ (2005: 152).
8 Borges repeats this line of  Emerson’s in the lecture ‘Emanuel Swedenborg’ (2005:
195).
9 ‘Esta palabra, aunque justísima, corre el albur de sugerir un hombre lateral, un
hombre que instintivamente se aparta de las circunstancias y urgencias que llamamos,
nunca sabré por qué, la realidad. Nadie menos parecido a esa imagen que Emanuel
Swedenborg, que recorrió este mundo y los otros, lúcido y laborioso. Nadie aceptó
la vida con mayor plenitud, nadie la investigó con igual pasión, con idéntico amor
intelectual y con tanta impaciencia de conocerla’ (2005: 152).
174 Chapter Four

exact allegories, or written in the angelic and ecstatic mode, he employed


his remaining years in extricating from the literal, the universal sense’ (2003:
29). Borges writes: ‘it was thought that the lord had written two books, one
of which we call the Bible and the other of which we call the universe. […]
Swedenborg began with the exegesis of  the first’ (1995: 14).10
Whilst we may suggest that Borges owes much of  his essay to Emerson,
it is of greater importance to scrutinize the essential concepts of mysticism
that derived from their studies of  Swedenborg and which they presented
in their essays. Both Emerson and Borges recognized that the Doctrine
of  Correspondences was at the heart of  Swedenborg’s mystical theology.
However, neither was comfortable either with the dazzling complexity of
such a system, nor with the implicit reduction of human existence into mere
functional modules of a divine matrix. Emerson, in particular, criticized
this doctrine as being arbitrary yet harrowingly deterministic and at odds
with the inherent f luidity of nature:

This design of exhibiting such correspondences, which, if adequately executed, would


be the poem of  the world, in which all history and science would play an essential
part, was narrowed and defeated by the exclusively theologic direction which his
inquiries took. His perception of nature is not human and universal, but is mystical
and Hebraic. He fastens each natural object to a theologic notion: – a horse signifies
carnal understanding; a tree, perception; the moon, faith; a cat means this; an ostrich,
that; an artichoke, this other; and poorly tethers every symbol to a several ecclesiastic
sense. The slippery Proteus is not so easily caught. In nature, each individual symbol
plays innumerable parts, as each particle of matter circulates in turn through every
system. The central identity enables any one symbol to express successively all the
qualities and shades of  the real being. In the transmission of  the heavenly waters,
every hose fits every hydrant. Nature avenges herself speedily on the hard pedantry
that would chain her waves. She is no literalist. Everything must be taken genially,
and we must be at the top of our condition to understand anything rightly. His theo-
logical bias thus fatally narrowed his interpretation of nature, and the dictionary of
symbols is yet to be written. But the interpreter, whom mankind must still expect,
will find no predecessor who has approached so near to the true problem. (2003: 30)

10 ‘Se pensó que el Señor había escrito dos libros, el que denominamos la Biblia y el que
denominamos el universo. Interpretarlos era nuestro deber. Swedenborg, lo sospecho,
empezó por la exégesis del primero’ (2005: 159).
Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges 175

Emerson’s ecstatic and romantic vision of nature would clearly dif fer from
Swedenborg’s meticulous cataloguing of all aspects of material and spiritual
reality, an approach cognate with the Enlightenment spirit of  his intellec-
tual powers. Eugene Taylor pays attention to Emerson’s misgivings on this
matter: ‘Emerson rejected as too absolute the so-called Swedenborgian dic-
tionary of correspondences, which required the reader to accept as gospel
the exact spiritual meaning Swedenborg himself  had placed on each object
in nature’ (1995: 153). Borges, like Emerson, was uneasy with this notion of
correspondence, and, like Emerson, his description of it bears something
of  the absurdity of  taxonomy that we famously encounter in ‘El idioma
analítico de John Wilkens.’ Borges continues in ‘Testigo’:

Swedenborg […] llegó a elaborar un vasto sistema de significaciones ocultas. Las pie-
dras, por ejemplo, representan las verdades naturales; las piedras preciosas, las verdades
espirituales; los astros, el conocimiento divino; el caballo, la recta comprensión de
la Escritura, pero también su tergiversación por obra de sofismas; la Abominación
de la Desolación, la Trinidad; el abismo, Dios o el Infierno; etcétera. […] no hay
un solo ser en la tierra que no perdure sino por el inf lujo constante de la divinidad.
[…] Esa perturbadora sospecha de que somos cifras y símbolos de una criptografía
divina, cuyo sentido verdadero ignoramos, abunda en los volúmenes de Léon Bloy,
y los cabalistas la conocieron. (2005: 159)

[Swedenborg […] prepared a vast system of  hidden meanings. Stones, for example,
represent natural truths; precious stones, spiritual truths; stars, divine knowledge;
the horse, a correct understanding of  Scripture but also its distortion through soph-
istry; the abomination of desolation, the Trinity; the abyss, God or hell; etc. […]
There is not a single creature on earth that does not owe its continued existence to
the constant inf luence of  the Divine Being. […] The disturbing suspicion that we are
ciphers and symbols in a divine cryptography whose true meaning we do not know
abounds in the volumes of  Leon Bloy, and the Jewish Cabalists knew of it.] (1995: 14)

Borges appears to derive from this aspect of correspondences the uncanny


notion of predetermination, as this ‘disturbing suspicion’ might relate to
the interplay between divine will and free will, where humans are led to
believe that they have free agency in choices, all the while ignorant that
176 Chapter Four

these choices are predetermined by divine plan.11 This is a theme we encoun-


ter in many of  Borges’ tales and poems. One might see ‘El muerto’ [‘The
Dead Man’] as allegorising this predicament: ‘Otálora comprende, antes
de morir, que desde el principio lo han traicionado, que ha sido condenado
a muerte, que le han permitido el amor, el mando y el triunfo, porque ya
lo daban por muerto, porque para Bandeira ya estaba muerto’ (1974: 549)
[‘Otálora realizes, before dying, that he has been betrayed from the start,
that he has been sentenced to death – that love and command and tri-
umph have been accorded him because his companions already thought
of  him as a dead man, because to Bandeira he already was a dead man’]
(1971a: 99). The protagonist only understands at the point of death that
his imagined freedom to choose had been an illusion carefully orchestrated
by his omniscient chief, Bandeira. In ‘La Biblioteca de Babel’, chaos and
order are unnervingly harmonized in an infinite, labyrinthine, library in
which one book must contain all books. In the oppressive atmosphere of 
this tale there is infinite choice but all choices are limited by the vertigi-
nous infinite order of  the library. Borges comments that in Swedenborg’s
visionary world the soul is free (unlike in Dante’s) but that all souls are
nevertheless within the gravitational orbit of  God: ‘En la Divina Comedia
de Dante – esa obra tan hermosa literariamente – el libre albedrío cesa en
el momento de la muerte. Los muertos son condenados por un tribunal y
merecen el cielo o el infierno. En cambio, en la obra de Swedenborg nada
de eso ocurre. Nos dice que cuando un hombre muere no se da cuenta
de que ha muerto, ya que todo lo que lo rodea es igual’ (2005: 196) [‘In

11 Need Swedenborg’s doctrine of correspondence necessarily equate to predestina-


tion? Kathleen Raine would argue that this is cognate with the Hermetic tradition
of interrelationship between the heavens and the earth, the subtle paths of com-
munication that connect the spirit world to the material, and not stern paragraphs
in the book of destiny: ‘It is the poets’ and painters’ task to perfect a language of
correspondences – the word is Swedenborg’s but the concept is Plato’s and goes back
to the famous saying in the Timaeus that the world is “a moving image of eternity.”
Correspondence is the secret of all poetic imagery’ (2007: 25). José Lezama Lima,
in his discussion of metaphor, likewise assumed that the poets and painters need to
seek this subtle language in order to harmonize the material and spirit forms (see
Rowlandson 2007).
Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges 177

Dante’s Divine Comedy – that beautiful literary work – free will ceases upon
death. The dead are tried by a tribunal and deserve heaven or hell. None
of  this occurs in Swedenborg’s work. He tells us that when a man dies he
is not aware that he has died because everything that surrounds him is the
same as before’] (my translation). This dimension of  free will was another
of  the significant heterodox claims of  Swedenborg, and was one of  the
litany of accusations (alongside his rejection of  the Trinity, his belief  that
Christ was God on earth, not the son of  God, his critique of  St Paul, his
belief  that direct experience of  the divine could be achieved without the
medium of clergy) that led to his censorship and publication prohibition
in his native Sweden: ‘Swedenborg radically departed from the orthodox
Christian belief in an individual and final judgment. The spirit, not God,
ultimately decided where to spend eternity’ (McDannell & Lang: 189. See
also Bald 2006: 16–18).

‘The excess of inf luence’ (Emerson 46)

Emerson, like Borges, perceived in Swedenborg a disquieting yearning to


accord his experience of interconnection with these doctrinal traditions:
‘Swedenborg and Behmen [Böhme] both failed by attaching themselves
to the Christian symbol, instead of  to the moral sentiment, which carries
innumerable christianities, humanities, divinities, in its bosom’ (Emerson:
45). Hurth (2005) examines the degree to which Emerson rejected such
schematized visions of nature in both Swedenborg and Böhme: ‘Emerson
did not accept the too literal and rapt approach to allegorical truth by
mystics like Swedenborg and Böhme, and he incisively criticized that the
literary presentations of  their mystical visions were too narrow and their
symbols too schematic and rigid. They thus established a fixed formula of
symbols to render human experience’ (2005: 335). As discussed in previous
chapters, it was Swedenborg’s heterodoxy, to the point of  heresy, married to
his accounts of direct experience of otherworld realities, that particularly
178 Chapter Four

appealed Borges: ‘Swedenborg, como Spinoza o Francis Bacon, fue un pen-


sador por cuenta propia y que cometió un incómodo error cuando resolvió
ajustar sus ideas al marco de los dos Testamentos’ (2005: 155) [‘Swedenborg,
like Spinoza or Francis Bacon, was a thinker in his own right who made
an awkward mistake when he decided to adapt his ideas to the framework
of  the two Testaments’] (1995: 9). The full impact of  both Emerson and
Borges’ reference to the Viking ancestry is, consequently, striking, as despite
Swedenborg’s lengthy tomes of scriptural hermeneutics, they considered
him the opposite of a theologian. He was an intrepid explorer of other
worlds, not a purveyor of  ‘scholastic frivolity’ (‘Duración del Infierno’).
Borges was explicit about this matter, explaining in interview: ‘los místicos,
tienden a escribir de un modo vago; él no. La obra de él es …, yo no diré
prosaica, pero sí precisa. Es un poco …, como si él hubiera ido a la China, o
hubiera ido a la India y describiera lo que ha visto’ (Wildner 1991) [‘Mystics
tend to write in a vague way. Not Swedenborg. His work is … well I won’t
say prosaic, but I will say precise. It is as if  he had gone to China or India,
and had described what he had seen’] (my translation). His religious argu-
ments, Borges writes, were based upon experience and from a system of
morality derived from that experience. Crucially, in Borges’ judgment, that
experience was not mediated by ecclesiastical authority and neither did all
of  Swedenborg’s proclamations conform to orthodoxy.
It is, though, a problematic point that both Emerson and Borges raise
here, and concerns the boundary between experience and textual reproduc-
tion. Where Emerson suggests that Swedenborg was ‘narrowed and defeated
by the exclusively theologic direction which his inquiries took’, it is unclear
whether these ‘inquiries’ refer to the specific mystical experience (the voyage
to heaven and hell), or to the subsequent ref lection, interpretation and
textual composition of  the experience. This is to say, it is unclear whether
Emerson is implying that Swedenborg’s direct experiences were theologi-
cally compromised a priori, which would suggest that he was interpreting
his surroundings with adherence to doctrine at the point of experience;
or whether his outlandish and ‘original’ (Borges 1995: 9) experiences were
later ‘narrowed’ and distorted by Swedenborg’s conscious desire at the point
of ref lecting and writing. This is a question that we will find ref lected in
many dif ferent contexts in our study of  Borges. The tale is tangled further,
Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges 179

however, when we appreciate that Emerson detects a fictional dimension


to Swedenborg’s angelic landscapes, based upon Swedenborg’s own idea
that we project our own will upon the heavenly realm. Emerson, it would
appear, criticizes Swedenborg’s inability to create interesting, individual,
characters. This would appear a purely aesthetic judgment of no ontological
import, as Emerson is making a firm assumption about the literary inven-
tion that is Swedenborg’s account:

The universe, in his poem, suf fers under a magnetic sleep, and only ref lects the
mind of  the magnetizer. Every thought comes into each mind by inf luence from
a society of spirits that surround it, and into these from a higher society, and so
on. All his types mean the same few things. All his figures speak one speech. All
his interlocutors Swedenborgize. […] Only when Cicero comes by, our gentle seer
sticks a little at saying he talked with Cicero, and, with a touch of  human relent-
ing, remarks, ‘one whom it was given me to believe was Cicero;’ and when the soi
disant Roman opens his mouth, Rome and eloquence have ebbed away, – it is plain
theologic Swedenborg, like the rest. His heavens and hells are dull; fault of want of
individualism. (Emerson 2003: 44)

The ontological implications of  this statement are profound when we cor-
relate it with other statements of  Emerson and Borges about the ‘reality’
of  Swedenborg’s visions. If  Emerson detects a distinctly Swedenborgian
language of  the characters then the author of such visions is not God but
Swedenborg. Consequently his angels inhabit the same fictional space as
H. G. Wells’ Morlocks, Shakespeare’s Hamlet or Tolkien’s Hobbits. This is
the question that concerned us in Chapter One, in which Borges repeatedly
separated mystics (‘When I talk of mystics, I think of  Swedenborg, Angelus
Silesius, and the Persians also’) from non-mystics (‘Not the Spaniards. I
don’t think they had any mystical experiences’ [Barnstone 1982: 11]) based
upon, precisely, the non-fictional quality of  the mystics’ texts. We recall that
he opined that Dante could not have experienced his vision in verse. This
is of crucial concern. Borges argued that Dante, in his letter to Cangrande
Della Scala, proposed an allegorical reading of The Divine Comedy: ‘Nothing
is further from the ultraterrestrial destinations of  Swedenborg’ (1995: 9);
they are real, not fictions. Emerson appears to share Borges’ view about
Dante, but here applies the notion to Swedenborg, further emphasising
180 Chapter Four

the a priori nature of  Swedenborg’s visions and making a brief equation
with Dante:

The parish disputes, in the Swedish church, between the friends and foes of  Luther
and Melancthon, concerning ‘faith alone,’ and ‘works alone,’ intrude themselves into
his speculations upon the economy of  the universe, and of  the celestial societies […]
He is like Michaelangelo, who, in his frescoes, put the cardinal who had of fended
him to roast under a mountain of devils; or, like Dante, who avenged, in vindictive
melodies, all his private wrongs. (Emerson 2003: 46–7)

Emerson’s essay on Swedenborg is significantly longer than Borges’. As


such, we can perhaps consider Borges’ brief comment that Swedenborg
‘cometió un incómodo error cuando resolvió ajustar sus ideas al marco
de los dos Testamentos’ (2005: 155) [‘made an awkward mistake when he
decided to adapt his ideas to the framework of  the two Testaments’] (1995:
9) a synoptic, concise, response to Emerson’s lengthy diatribe. Emerson,
indeed, dwells to a significant degree on a critique of  Swedenborg’s dense
theologisation: ‘The vice of  Swedenborg’s mind is its theologic determina-
tion. Nothing with him has the liberality of universal wisdom, but we are
always in a church’ (2003: 45), a sentiment that is perhaps best summed up
by Borges: ‘Los incalculables cielos de Swedenborg están llenos de amor y
de teología’ (2005: 158) [‘The incalculable heavens of  Swedenborg are full
of  love and theology’] (1995: 13). Emerson’s invective culminates in his
oft-proclaimed dislike of  Swedenborg’s passionless tone:

These angels that Swedenborg paints give us no very high idea of  their discipline and
culture: they are all country parsons; their heaven is a fête champêtre, and evangeli-
cal picnic, or French distribution of prizes to virtuous peasants. Strange, scholastic,
didactic, passionless, bloodless man, who denotes classes of souls as a botanist disposes
of a carex, and visits doleful hells as a stratum of chalk or hornblende!12 He has no

12 This is the aspect of  Swedenborg that Yeats (1920: 299) famously equated to his work
as a mineralogist: ‘He considered heaven and hell and God, the angels, the whole
destiny of man, as if  he were sitting before a large table in a Government of fice put-
ting little pieces of mineral ore into small square boxes for an assistant to pack away
in drawers’, and that Garrett (1984: 68) describes as: ‘an odd, dry precision to his
descriptions of  Heaven that suggests the engineer far more than the mystic’.
Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges 181

sympathy. He goes up and down the world of men, a modern Rhadamanthus in gold-
headed cane and peruke, and with nonchalance, and the air of a referee, distributes
souls. […] Behmen is healthily and beautifully wise, notwithstanding the mystical
narrowness and incommunicableness. Swedenborg is disagreeably wise, and, with
all his accumulated gifts, paralyzes and repels. (2003: 53)

Borges, however, of fers a slightly more sympathetic appraisal of  the persis-
tent biblical, theological tone of  Swedenborg’s many volumes, suggesting
that, despite the ‘unfortunate mistake’ of adapting his visions to doctrine,
Swedenborg would inevitably have experienced such an ecclesiastical vision
of  the otherworld reality, as this was his vision of  the mundane reality also.
‘[…] el padre de él era obispo, obispo evangélico, luterano. El tiene que
haberse criado en un ambiente muy piadoso. […] él pensaba naturalmente
en el espíritu de la Biblia’ (Wildner 1991) [‘His father was an evangelical
Lutheran bishop. He must have been brought up in a very pious environ-
ment. […] He must have considered the spirit of the Bible quite naturally’]
(my translation).13 In this respect, Borges would appear more forgiving
of  Swedenborg’s ecclesiastical tone than Emerson; and just as Emerson
and Borges were troubled by the presence of orthodoxy in Swedenborg,
Emerson was greater troubled by the translation of  Swedenborg’s visions
into doctrine: ‘These books should be used with caution. It is dangerous
to sculpture these evanescing images of  thought. True in transition, they
become false if  fixed. It requires, for his just apprehension, almost a genius
equal to his own. But when his visions become the stereotyped language of
multitudes of persons, of all degrees of age and capacity, they are perverted’
(2003: 43). Emerson railed against the perversion of  Swedenborg’s ‘evanesc-
ing images of thought’ into something quotidian and mundane, arguing that
this would remove the mystery and the moral truth of  Swedenborg’s texts.
This again is a sentiment fully visible with Borges, who paid close attention
to the ‘original’ experiences and unorthodox theology of  Swedenborg, but
was at no stage prepared to accept the constellation of such accounts into
doctrine or articles of faith. For both Emerson and Borges, this predicament

13 This is similar to Conan Doyle’s comment that Swedenborg ‘sucked in theology with
his mother’s milk’ (2005: 96).
182 Chapter Four

was at the heart of  their strained relationships with orthodox religion:
mystery lies at the heart of  the religious experience, and yet the conversion
of such mystery into matters of  faith is the erection of a rigid belief system
bereft of  the transformative power of mystery.

Intelligence over piety

As Quinn (1950) identifies, Emerson placed the intellect in high esteem,


and was vexed by ‘“a very good woman with much light in her heart but
no equal light in her mind. Well I weary presently of  these quiet souls if 
they cannot rouse me with a thought”’ (in Quinn 1950: 402). In another
letter, Emerson writes: ‘“Strange strange it seems that I should nowhere
find that goodly marriage which everywhere I seek of  holiness & genius in
one mind, which shall be majesty. Goodness will always be suspicious to
me & only half goodness until it attains to become sight, and apprehends
Chemistry, for example”’ (in Quinn 1950: 403). Such a position would
chime immediately with Borges, who enthused at Swedenborg and Blake’s
praise of  the intellect above simple uncritical piety. We recall that Borges
writes that for Swedenborg, intelligence is of more worth in heaven than
righteousness. ‘Al requisito de ser justo, Swedenborg añade otro, antes no
mencionado por ningún teólogo: el de ser inteligente’ (2005: 158) [‘To the
requirement of righteousness, Swedenborg adds another, never before men-
tioned by any theologian: intelligence’] (1995: 13). Emerson likewise prized
Swedenborg’s dazzling intellect above all righteousness, communion with
God or religious fervour. As Quinn suggests, for Emerson, Swedenborg
was ‘a kind of inspired scientist. […] Nowhere in this essay does Emerson
dwell on Swedenborg’s holiness or estimate the degree to which he realized
spiritual perfection’ (1950: 406–7). Quinn then concludes that Emerson’s
judgment of mysticism was essentially that of magic, associated not with the
striving to perfection (‘mysticism’, in Quinn’s terms), but with ‘the pursuit
of power which this supernatural reality is thought to contain. It is the art
Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges 183

of getting at that power so as to make use of it in the natural world’ (1950:


401). The mystic, in Quinn’s analysis, does not crave this power: ‘He is not
interested in wielding supernatural force. In his transaction with the super-
natural he is seeking only for union with God. It is his instinct to adore
what the magician would use’ (1950: 401). Borges repeatedly emphasized
the intellectual aspect of  Swedenborg as the very quality that made possible
his intrepid exploration and cataloguing of  the angelic worlds, indeed he
praised Swedenborg as the epitome of intellectual potency:

Yo escribí un prólogo a un libro sobre Swedenborg a instancias del Sr. Spiers, de la


Fundación Swedenborg. Y tengo en proyecto (claro que a mi edad los proyectos son
un tanto aleatorios) un libro sobre las tres salvaciones; la primera es la de Cristo,
que es de carácter ético; la segunda es la de Swedenborg, que es ética e intelectual;
y la tercera es la de Blake, discípulo rebelde de Swedenborg, que es ética, intelectual
y estética, que se basa en las parábolas de Cristo, que él dice que son obras de arte.
(Wildner 1991)

[I wrote a prologue for a book about Swedenborg upon the request of  the Swedenborg
Foundation. I have a project in mind about a book of  the three salvations: the first is
that of  Christ, which is ethical in its nature; the second is that of  Swedenborg, which
is ethical and intellectual; and the third is that of Blake, rebel disciple of  Swedenborg,
which is ethical, intellectual and aesthetic, and which is based in Christ’s parables,
which he calls works of art.] (My translation)

There are aspects of  the language of  Borges’ essay on Swedenborg that reveal
profound admiration for Swedenborg’s mighty intellect; indeed his intel-
lect in many respects supersedes his heavenly visions in Borges’ esteem. ‘No
le bastaron las versiones latinas; investigó los textos originales en hebreo y
en griego’ (2005: 153) [‘He always preferred the study of sacred scripture
to that of dogmatic theology. Latin translations were not good enough
for him; he studied the original texts in Hebrew and Greek’] (1995: 5).
Borges, as we recall, likewise ‘preferred the study of sacred scripture to that
of dogmatic theology’, and in many places describes reading Schopenhauer
and Kant in the original German so as to appreciate their authentic style.
One might conclude, therefore, that on matters of  the intellect, Borges
indeed, as Lawrence suggests, felt himself  ‘a kindred spirit to the Swedish
mystic’ (1995: x).
184 Chapter Four

Emerson and Borges mystics manqués

Emerson is commonly considered a literary critic, poet, philosopher and


religious thinker. He is also known – sometimes polemically – as a mystic.
‘But despite their notorious imprecision, mystic and its related words are
often used by the commentators on Emerson. Indeed it may be said that
references to Emerson as a mystic are as common in studies of  Emerson as they
are rare in studies of mysticism’ (Quinn 1950: 397, original italics). As with
the assessment of  Borges’ mystical attributes, the label ‘mystic’ is applied to
Emerson based often on only a scant understanding of  the complexity of 
the term and the disagreements within the scholarship. Similarly, as with
Borges and William James, the term may have dif ferent tones depending
on how it is applied: Emerson the mystic and Emerson the scholar of mysti-
cism. Quinn coherently argues that Emerson’s use of  the term ‘mysticism’
is itself problematic due to his casual and conf licting use of  the term. In
particular, Quinn looks at the celebrated passage in Nature – almost too
well known to need quoting – which reads: ‘“Standing on the bare ground
– my head bathed by the blithe air, and uplifted into infinite space – all
mean egotism vanishes. I become a transparent eyeball; I am nothing; I see
all; the currents of  the Universal Being circulate through me; I am part or
parcel of  God.” On the face of it, this would appear to demand interpreta-
tion as a mystical document’ (in Quinn 1950: 408). Quinn argues, however,
that Emerson’s ease of expression, his ‘almost glib’ attitude concerning the
mystical state, makes Emerson’s ‘mysticism, if  this be mysticism, sound[s]
suspiciously easy here’ (409), and he questions Emerson’s relationship with
God prior to this description as a means of demonstrating that he had not
fulfilled the requisite steps along the spiritual path. Quinn ref lects a cen-
tury of scholarship and biographical studies which scrutinize the poetic
and critical works of  Emerson and, as with the Borges scholarship, which
assert that Emerson was or was not a mystic. Hurth (2005) suggests that
the term that was employed to describe Emerson best by his contemporar-
ies was the ‘Yankee Mystic’ a term which allowed for his radical departure
from Christian orthodoxy, and his assimilation of  the democratic new
Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges 185

principles of  his county at that period in history; a spirit that later informed
his godson William James in his depiction of pragmatism: ‘As a “Yankee
mystic” Emerson was a pragmatic mystic to the core’ (Hurth 2005: 336).
Hurth also concisely addresses the central arguments of  this contro-
versy over Emerson’s mystical credentials.

In 1942 Henry B. Parkes launched an aggressive attack on the allegedly ‘mystical’


features of  Emerson’s thought. According to Parkes, Emerson’s epiphanies and vision-
ary moments had no biographical basis. He was only a ‘pseudo-mystic’ who had ‘no
true mystical experience. His mysticism was founded on those moments of exhilara-
tion, caused by a feeling of  harmony between oneself and the external world, which
everyone occasionally experiences’. Emerson’s contemporary critics were ready to
label Emerson a ‘mystic,’ but to them ‘mysticism’ was mostly a term of reproach and
equivalent to ‘misty’ or ‘occult’. (2005: 333)

Parkes’ essay is vitriolic against both Emerson and any critic foolhardy
enough to call him a mystic. This is familiar in the scholarship of mysti-
cism, for example in Zaehner’s refutation of  Huxley, and demonstrates, as I
mentioned in Chapter Two, the degree of reliance that many scholars place
on one or other of  the defining categories of  the term ‘mystic’ and ‘mysti-
cism’. In Parkes’s case mysticism cannot be a common-or-garden sensation
of  harmony, but is something far more closely aligned to religious ortho-
doxy. What is visible in Quinn’s firm assertion is a bias of  the work ethic
that we encounter with Zaehner’s rejection of  Huxley’s ‘gratuitous grace’
and Meher Baba’s God in a Pill? Apotheosis does not come cheaply. One
cannot take a shortcut to the divine. It is the perennial argument concern-
ing ‘dif ficult’ or ‘easy’ spiritual paths, characterized (and satirized) by Alan
Watts’ division of  the easy approach to satori: ‘Beat Zen’ and the dif ficult
approach: ‘Square Zen’ (Watts 2006). Quinn qualifies his assertion with
a definition of what the ‘true’ mystic is: ‘For the mystics we know of, in
the East as in the West, dedicated years to the spiritual exercises by which
they might become united with God. Emerson would have this rare phe-
nomenon take place almost instantaneously. It is obvious that whatever
we may call this theory of  Emerson’s, it will hardly do to call it mysticism’
(1950: 411). Quinn would doubtless reject Watts’ ‘Beat Zen’.
186 Chapter Four

Both Quinn and Hurth evaluate the many scholars who have assessed
Emerson’s works, in particular the famed passage from Nature, and argue
that most scholars agree not only on the literary quality of  Emerson’s text,
but that the text was inspired by other texts, in particular Böhme: ‘Emerson
welcomed Böhme as someone who was taught directly by God through his
own intuitions, not by book learning – a mystic in the most exact sense’
(Hurth 2005: 337). Emerson’s theoretical position concerning mysticism,
therefore, is strikingly close to that of  Borges’ in the emphasis on the unme-
diated mystical vision. Hurth also points out that ‘since Emerson did read
the Aurora shortly before the publication of  Nature, one may guardedly
assume that Böhme’s work was a possible inf luence for his most famous
passage. Emerson may also have noticed that Böhme often used the physi-
cal eye as a symbol for the communion between soul and God’ (2005:
339). Whilst this is a position taken by many of  the scholars she mentions,
Hurth does allow for the originality of experience which was later framed
in a style inf luenced by Böhme: ‘But while on the surface Böhme’s descrip-
tions of mystical experience are largely in accord with the mysticism of the
“transparent eye-ball” passage, the underlying beliefs and assumptions are
quite dif ferent, and the Aurora is thus a source for Emerson only in the
sense that it provided him with a vocabulary for his own ideas’ (2005: 339).
Quinn, meanwhile, suggests the Jamesian principle of inef fability: ‘As
a rule, most mystics find it exceedingly dif ficult to describe their mystical
experiences. Words fail them. But words do not fail Emerson. He, indeed,
is almost glib’ (1950: 409). Quinn goes on to suggest that Emerson’s lan-
guage may be borrowed from Plotinus. This needs emphasising, as it is
related to the views of  Borges concerning Swedenborg and Dante’s mystical
texts. What emerges, quite ironically, is that an unliterary description of 
the experience would testify to a failure of  language to accommodate the
experience, and would thus testify to the experience’s inef fability, which
would thus testify to its genuine mystical aspect. In brief, therefore, the
better the poet, the worse the mystic.
As we assessed in Chapter Three, Borges is also polemically described
as a mystic, a ‘mystical thinker’, an almost-mystic, a non-mystic, etc., and as
discussed the term can only have meaningful value if determined according
to one or other of  the theoretical positions that define mysticism. What is
Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges 187

interesting to note, nevertheless, is that both Emerson and Borges approach


Swedenborg with the assumption that his prime mystical experiences may
be somehow divorced from his church-bound experiences or from the
church-bound textual recounting. As such they both assume a phenom-
enological experience somehow unculturated and thus antecedent to the
cultural-religious embellishments. But this approach to Swedenborg is
derived from their own experiences of mystical consciousness which they
would both propose as unmediated by doctrine – religious, cultural, aes-
thetic or otherwise. Thus one can perceive with Emerson and Borges a desire
to correlate their misgivings of  the church with their enthusiasm for the
radical experiences of  Swedenborg, set against personal unitive experiences.
It would appear, furthermore, that this unease of church-bound mys-
ticism also prevented both Emerson and Borges from a more profound
reading of  the texts of mystical traditions. Quinn describes how Emerson,
in truth, knew precious little of  the canon of western mysticism: ‘To read
Emerson […] is to be struck by the fact that he seems to have known very
few of  them [mystics], even by repute. He does not refer to such stand-
ard instances as those represented by Dionysius the Areopagite, Meister
Eckhart, John of  Ruysbroek, St Teresa of  Avila, St John of  the Cross, or
Catherine of  Siena’ (1950: 408). It is likewise interesting to note that Borges
invests in Swedenborg with a zeal as powerful as Emerson’s, and yet rarely
discusses other canonical mystics, aside from brief mentions of  Angelus
Silesius and Jakob Böhme, and dismisses Pascal and ‘the Spaniards’ as not
even being mystics. Again, the mark of  Emerson is visible on Borges. We
can perceive how both Emerson and Borges were keen to evaluate their
own ‘mystical’ experiences (‘timeless’ for Borges, ‘transparent eyeball’ for
Emerson) in light of  their reading of  Swedenborg. Again, the tension vis-
ible in Emerson’s Nature and in Borges’ ‘Sentirse en muerte’ is between the
experience and the cognitive powers that attempt to seize, conceptualize
and recount the experience.
188 Chapter Four

Conclusion

Analysing the cross-currents and intersections of readers of  Swedenborg


shows a true web of encounters, friendships, correspondences, inf luences,
antagonisms. Delightfully, one can perceive a direct line of  figures which
links Borges with Swedenborg, and it runs through William James and
his godfather, Ralph Waldo Emerson. Emerson, indeed, is a vital link in
this chain.
Borges was a close and admiring reader of  William James, whose
psychological works Borges’ father taught. Macedonio Fernández, Jorge
Guillermo Borges’ friend, and friend and ‘mentor’ to Georgie, corresponded
with William James.14 William and his brother Henry the novelist were
deeply inf luenced by their father, Henry James Sr. and his fascination with
Swedenborg. James père was close friends with J. J. Garth Wilkinson (after
whom he named his third son), chief  translator of Swedenborg and friend of 
Carlyle, who first introduced Emerson to Swedenborg’s works. Wilkinson
was friend of  C. A. Tulk (Deck 1977: 217). Tulk was friend and corre-
spondent with S. T. Coleridge. Coleridge was friends with De Quincey,
who read Swedenborg owing to his friendship with John Clowes.15 Tulk
met William Blake in an early congregation of  the London New Church,

14 Borges discusses this in ‘Autobiographical Essay’. Nubiola (2005) explores the verac-
ity of  this claim and locates the correspondence.
15 ‘an Anglican clergy [sic] and Swedenborgian preacher who was a good friend and
a frequent visitor in the De Quincey household. […] Clowes even lent copies of 
Swedenborg’s works to De Quincey [who] is known to have given Coleridge the
works of  Boehme years later’ (García 2007: 64) ‘In his translation of  Immanuel
Kant’s Abstract of  Swedenborgianism, De Quincey found the Kantian framework
for interpreting mystical dreams and divine states compelling enough to translate and
publish. Kant argues that Swedenborg’s prophecies are a product of a disorder in the
faculty of sensibility; and that in communicating with spirits, Swedenborg is simply
echoing his inner ideas within himself, projecting what is in the mind outward. For
Kant, these mystical visions are therefore a form of madness’ (García 2007: 65).
Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges 189

a Swedenborgian sectarian church in Eastcheap.16 Tulk also introduced the


elderly Blake to Coleridge.17 Blake was born into a family deeply versed
in Swedenborg, and Blake remained a close and often antagonistic reader
of  Swedenborg throughout his life.18 It is delightful to imagine the young
Blake meeting the elderly Swedenborg, and indeed this legend appears in
poetic form in H. N. Morris’ Flaxman, Blake, Coleridge, and other men
of genius inf luenced by Swedenborg (1915: 76): ‘During the first year of  his
apprenticeship it is probable that on his [Blake’s] way to and from work
he often met or walked beside the great Emanuel Swedenborg, then an
old man of eighty-four.’ This legend is coherently refuted, however, by
David V. Erdman (1953). Blake’s mother became interested in Swedenborg
initially through the exposure of  Swedenborg’s works in the at the Fetter
Lane Moravian congregation, an Episcopalian denomination active in
London in the eighteenth century which she and her first husband (Thomas
Armitage) and second husband ( James Blake) attended.19 Swedenborg
was for a while a registered attendee. It is possible, therefore, that there
was personal contact between Blake’s mother and Swedenborg himself.

16 ‘Toward the end of  this decade, Blake began to read Swedenborg’s works, and in 1789
he attended the First General Conference of  the New Church, which was held at
Eastcheap from April 13 to 17, 1789. Here we might speculate on a “first meeting” of 
Tulk and Blake’ (Deck 1977: 218). See also Rix 2007.
17 ‘We can then combine this evidence with Crabb Robinson’s statement about Blake
and Coleridge to conclude that this meeting occurred in 1825 or very early in 1826’
(Deck 1977: 224).
18 ‘Blake must early have been acquainted, inasmuch as his father was a dissenter inter-
ested in Swedenborg and sympathetic to his teachings if not, like William’s brother
Robert, actively associated with a Community’ (Schorer 1938: 157).
19 ‘From May 1744, Swedenborg lodged with his Moravian friend John Paul Brockmer.
Together they attended Moravian services, and Swedenborg became so attracted to
Fetter Lane Chapel (to which Blake’s mother was later connected) that he considered
formal af filiation’ (Rix 2007: 51). Ankarsjö (2009: 32) is more forthcoming in suggest-
ing a personal connection between Blake’s mother and Swedenborg: ‘Swedenborg’s
af filiation with the Moravians […] coincided with the period when Blake’s mother
Catherine and her first husband Thomas Armitage and Blake’s possible uncle John
had their most active years in the church. Particularly, Catherine seems to have been
a devoted Moravian member at the time.’
190 Chapter Four

Should Catherine Blake and Swedenborg not have met, then a path can be
traced from Blake to Robert Hindmarsh, one of  the original founders of 
Swedenborgianism and friend of  Tulk’s father, John Augustus Tulk, whose
gatherings Blake attended with his friend and supporter John Flaxman
(Rix 2007: 53–5). Hindmarsh’s father, James Hindmarsh, was one of  John
Wesley’s preachers, and was trained by Wesley in London. Swedenborg cor-
responded with Wesley in 1772, inviting the Methodist minister to visit him
in London (Synnestvedt 1977: 33).20 John Wesley and his brother Charles
were also members of  the Fetter Lane Moravian Church at the same time
as Swedenborg (Ankarsjö 2009: 37). As such, and allowing any number of
variant trajectories and alternative figures, there is direct person-to-person
contact that links Swedenborg to Borges via Emerson.
As established in the previous chapter, Borges adopted a curiously
contradictory stance in his evaluation of  Swedenborg. His repeated empha-
sis on the heterodox aspect of  the Swedish seer resulted in a judgment
about originality of experience that is problematic. It is striking to note,
as scholars such as Quinn and Hurth have done so, that Emerson presents
an equally problematic and at times inconsistent approach to his evalua-
tion of  Swedenborg and Böhme. It is therefore of concern for this study
to appraise the strong kinship that Borges felt for Emerson, to note the
similarities and the dif ferences in their outlook, and to chart the visible
marks of inf luence.
As indicated, both Emerson and Borges delivered lectures on
Swedenborg which they later published, in which they presented bio-
graphical material alongside a critical evaluation of  his work. Emerson and
Borges paid particular attention to the magnitude of  Swedenborg’s intel-
lect. This is of great importance to both, and, as discussed, it becomes clear

20 A word of caution for the scholar approaching Swedenborg for the first time; these
three names can be confusing: Toksvig, Signe (1948) Emanuel Swedenborg: Scientist
and Mystic (New Haven: Yale University Press). Sigstedt, Cyriel (1952) The Swedenborg
Epic: The Life and Works of  Emanuel Swedenborg (New York: Bookman Associates,)
Synnestvedt, Sig (1970) The Essential Swedenborg. Boston: Houghton Mif f lin Co.
(The Spanish-language edition of  this latter volume is what Borges was invited to
contribute to).
Two lectures on Swedenborg: Emerson and Borges 191

from appreciating Borges’ close attention to Swedenborg’s scholastic and


linguistic achievements that he felt personal admiration of  the skills that
were also present in himself. The emphasis on the intellectual dynamic of 
Swedenborg ref lects both Emerson and Borges’ particular critical focus on
the curious relationship between spontaneous, unconscious, mystical expe-
rience and the sharp, sceptical, analytical approach to the mystical experi-
ence that accompanies the intellect. Swedenborg, Borges suggested, would
have been equally prominent in history as a scientist and inventor had he
never embarked on his voyages to the otherworld; and yet, Borges stressed
he was no retiring monk, nor fainting saint, nor ecstatic holy man. Borges
seized on Swedenborg’s intellect – and not his faith – as the vehicle that
bore him to these fantastic locations. Hurth charts the evolving relationship
that Emerson maintained with the texts of  Böhme and Swedenborg, and
remarks that he was increasingly troubled by the contradictions thrown
up between faith and intellect, and how they are reconciled (though not
always) in the two mystical writers. In particular, as Emerson grew older, he
came to view the critical apparatus as an impediment to genuine mystical
insight, and as a result he viewed Böhme’s experiences as increasingly unat-
tainable, and Swedenborg’s as a unique and challenging harmony between
the forces of  faith and reason:

Mystical experience was of fset by the sudden inf lux of skepticism. Böhme’s mysti-
cism appeared to Emerson to leave no room for such doubt and skepticism. Emerson
acutely sensed the simple sincerity and piety of  Böhme and was sure that with this
‘sentiment of piety’ Böhme experienced ultimate reality as indubitably present. Böhme
was aware of  this reality with a vividness and vitality that the aging Emerson could
only long for. (Hurth 2005: 349)

This touching account of  Emerson evokes Williamson’s description of 


Borges’ eagerness to gain some tangible understanding whilst in Japan of 
his own previous experiences (Williamson 2004: 444). It similarly relates
to the mood that typifies so much of Borges’ work and that forms the focus
for the study of  Flynn (2009) concerning the absence of a revelation, or, as
in the final words of  Pedro Salvadores: ‘Como todas las cosas, el destino
de Pedro Salvadores nos parece un símbolo de algo que estamos a punto
de comprender’ (1975a: 64) [‘As with so many things, the fate of  Pedro
192 Chapter Four

Salvadores strikes us as a symbol of something we are about to understand,


but never quite do’] (1975a: 65).
It is therefore with similar critical eyes that Emerson and Borges
appraised the doctrinal, religious, aspect of  Swedenborg’s works. This is
a strong link between them and accords with their understanding of  the
relationship between intellect, faith and religion, a tension manifest in
Emerson’s 1842 lecture ‘The Transcendentalist’. Borges inherited from
Emerson this profound awe and respect for religious-inspired texts cou-
pled with a critical and at times cynical regard for religious doctrine and
dogma. As such Borges ref lected Emerson’s stern critique of  Swedenborg’s
adherence to certain orthodox codes, although Borges granted him far
more freedom from orthodoxy than did Emerson. A brief comment made
by Barnstone can now take greater prominence than Barnstone perhaps
anticipated: ‘There is the Borges of  Emersonian transcendence, the secu-
lar mystic’ (Barnstone 2000: 47). This comment, whilst not without its
dif ficulties in relation to the recurrent ambiguity of  the term ‘mystic’, is
wholly appropriate in this context not only for describing Emerson and
Borges, but, importantly, for describing their approach to Swedenborg. If we
were to contrast the term ‘secular mystic’ with ‘religious mystic’ (again, not
without its problems), then we can perceive that what fascinated Emerson
and Borges about Swedenborg was precisely the secular, perennial, universal,
ancient quality of  his recorded experiences; and in this respect Swedenborg
belongs to a noble lineage stretching back to pre-Christian epochs. Where
they both stumble in their reading of  Swedenborg is in his adherence to
Scripture and the adaptation of  ‘his ideas to the framework of  the two
Testaments’ (Borges 1995: 9). This reading of  Swedenborg, however, may
not be appropriate, whose entire theological/mystical project was deeply
religious. What lies at heart of  Emerson and Borges’ reckoning is not so
much the ‘secular’ quality but, as established in the previous chapter, the
relationship between institutional religion and personal transcendence.
Chapter Five

The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges

No pasa un día en que no estamos, un instante, en el paraíso.


[Not a day passes in which we are not, in an instant, in Paradise.]
— Borges, Los Conjurados

oathiose infernals to Booth Salvation, arcane celestials to Sweatenburgs


Welhell!!
— James Joyce, Finnegans Wake

Durante los últimos veinticinco años de su estudiosa vida, el eminente


hombre de ciencia y filósofo Emanuel Swedenborg (1688–1772) fijó su
residencia en Londres. Como los ingleses son taciturnos, dio en el hábito
cotidiano de conversar con demonios y ángeles.
— Jorge Luis Borges and Margarita Guerrero,
Libro de los seres imaginarios
[For the last twenty-five years of  his studious life, the eminent philoso-
pher and man of science Emanuel Swedenborg (1688–1772) resided in
London. But as the English are not very talkative, he fell into the habit
of conversing with devils and angels.]
— Book of imaginary beings

As discussed in Chapter One, Swedenborg constitutes a far richer pres-


ence in Borges’ work than the scholarship has hitherto acknowledged.
Rodríguez Risquete (2005) enumerates 95 references to Dante in Borges’
work, dividing his bibliography into five sections. For my own part, I have
identified the following appearances of  Swedenborg in Borges, some as
critical assessments or biographical studies, others as mere references. The
list is doubtless incomplete: ‘Testigo a lo invisible’, the poem ‘Emmanuel
Swedenborg’ (El otro, el mismo), the poem ‘Doomsday’ (Los Conjurados),
194 Chapter Five

the poem ‘Otro poema de los dones’ (El otro, el mismo), ‘El espejo de
los enigmas’ (Otras Inquisiciones), ‘Nueva refutación del tiempo’ (Otras
Inquisiciones), four tales of  El libro de los seres imaginarios: ‘El Devorador
de las Sombras’, ‘El Monstruo Aqueronte’, ‘Los Demonios de Swedenborg’
and ‘Los Ángeles de Swedenborg’, ‘La duración del infierno’ (Discusión),
‘Historia de la Eternidad’ (Historia de la Eternidad), ‘La memoria de
Shakespeare’ (La Memoria de Shakespeare), ‘Veinticinco de agosto, 1983’
(La Memoria de Shakespeare), ‘Laprida 1214’ (Atlas), ‘Sobre Oscar Wilde’
(Otras Inquisiciones), ‘Pascal’ (Otras Inquisiciones), ‘Nota sobre (hacia)
Bernard Shaw’ (Otras Inquisiciones), ‘Sobre el Vathek de William Beckford’
(Otras Inquisiciones), ‘Prólogo de prólogos’ (2005: 13), ‘Dos interpretaciones
de Arthur Rimbaud’ (2005: 315), ‘Emanuel Swedenborg: Mystical Works
(2005: 152), ‘Personality survives death, de Sir William Barrett’ (2005: 361),1
‘William Blake. Poesía completa’ (2005: 554),2 ‘Leon Bloy: La salvación
por los judíos. La sangre del pobre. En las tinieblas’ (2005: 544),3 ‘Leslie
Weatherhead: After Death’ (Discusión), Prologue to Xul Solar, Catálogo de
obras del Museo (Borges 1990). He also reproduces a number of Swedenborg
texts: ‘Un teólogo en la muerte’ (Historia universal de la infamia and
Antología de la literatura fantástica), ‘Un doble de Mahoma’ (Historia
universal de la infamia), two passages of  El libro de los seres imaginarios:
‘Los Demonios de Swedenborg’ and ‘Los Ángeles de Swedenborg’, seven
passages of  El Libro del cielo y del infierno: ‘Correspondencias arcanas’, ‘El
hombre elige su eternidad’, ‘Las formas del infierno’, ‘Infiernos ruinosos’, ‘Los
ricos en el cielo’, ‘Un réprobo en el cielo’, ‘Camino de perfección’ [although
this latter piece is authored by El Falso Swedenborg]. For the following
interviews in which he discusses Swedenborg, please consult bibliography
for full details. Salas (1976), Bourne (1980), Enguídanos (Barnstone 1982),

1 This is a fascinating brief review, as he recounts Barrett’s communications from


the other side, and remarks that Barrett’s post-mortem experiences corroborate
Swedenborg’s. The implications of  this are the reinforcement through consensus of 
Swedenborg’s heavenly theology.
2 ‘recorrió, como Swedenborg, las regiones de los muertos y de los ángeles’ (554). He
also talks of  Blake’s homemade mythologies.
3 He calls Bloy ‘profeta y visionario’ (544) and he likens him to Swedenborg.
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 195

Hughes et al. (Cortínez 1986), Sábato (2002), Barili (Burgin 1998), Christ
(Burgin 1998), Yates (Burgin 1998), Enguídanos (Burgin 1998). He tells
Miguel Enguídanos at Indiana University in March 1976 that ‘I also intend
to write a book on Swedenborg’ (Barnstone 1982: 97); he tells Barnstone: ‘I
would like to write a book on Swedenborg’ (Barnstone 1982: 109); and he
says to Hughes et al. ‘I’m writing a book on him [Swedenborg]’ (Cortínez
1986: 16). The book was never written, or at least never published.
This volume of references cannot indicate by deduction neces-
sary inf luence, but it certainly demonstrates the perpetual presence of 
Swedenborg in Borges’ mind whilst he composed tales or poems, reviewed
the works of others, or analysed a particular field in a critical essay. In par-
ticular, Borges appraised accounts of  life after death, heavenly voyages,
communication with the dead or with angels, anomalous experiences with
time and heterodox theologies with reference to Swedenborg. It becomes
quite clear that for Borges Swedenborg is the yardstick of such mysterious
matters against which other accounts are judged. This is most manifest
by the proportion of  Swedenborg passages that fill the pages of  Borges’
and Bioy’s Libro del cielo y del infierno. Not only are there seven texts of 
Swedenborg, but the authors make specific reference to Swedenborg in
the prologue. It is clear that on matters eschatological and of  the afterlife,
Swedenborg constituted the greatest authority for Borges.
When did Borges first write about Swedenborg? How did he initially
come across his works? Borges relates his introduction to lecturing on
Swedenborg in his ‘Autobiographical Essay’:

So, at forty-seven, I found a new and exciting life opening up for me. I traveled up
and down Argentina and Uruguay, lecturing on Swedenborg, Blake, the Persian
and Chinese mystics, Buddhism, gauchesco poetry, Martin Buber, the Kabbalah,
the Arabian Nights, T. E. Lawrence, medieval Germanic poetry, the Icelandic sagas,
Heine, Dante, expressionism and Cervantes […]. Not only did I end up making far
more money than at the library, but I enjoyed the work and felt that it justified me.
(1971a: 245)

This question of where and when he first encountered Swedenborg, how-


ever, is not easily answered, as one must evaluate the profound impact that
Swedenborg had on so many of  the writers that Borges read with af fection:
196 Chapter Five

Goethe,4 Blake, Coleridge,5 De Quincey, Carlyle, Emerson, Thoreau,


Whitman, Melville, Hawthorne, Longfellow, Emily Dickinson, Robert
Frost, Swinburne, Dante Gabriel Rossetti, Strindberg, von Schelling,6
Tennyson, William James, Henry James, C. S. Peirce, W. B. Yeats,7 E. A.
Poe, Victor Hugo, Flaubert, Balzac,8 Baudelaire, Valéry, George Sand,
Robert Browning, Elizabeth Barrett Browning, G. K. Chesterton,9 Conan
Doyle, Schopenhauer, Kant,10 Jung, Henry Corbin, Rudolf Steiner, Tolstoy,
Dostoevsky,11 Carl Sandburg, Kierkegaard, Jaspers, Bertrand Russell,12
C. S. Lewis, Joyce, H. P. Lovecraft. Of other writers who were favourites of 
Borges, I am unable to determine whether they were readers of  Swedenborg:
Wilde, Kipling, Stevenson, Conrad, G. B. Shaw,13 Dr Johnson, Wordsworth,

4 ‘Goethe once said that only by reading Swedenborg’s Heaven and Hell was he enabled
to finish his masterpiece, Faustus, which he had put aside in frustration for a decade’
(Lawrence 1999).
5 See Lawrence 1999.
6 As a reader of  Schopenhauer, Borges would likely have been aware of  Schelling.
7 ‘Of course I delight in Yeats’ (Barnstone 1982: 87).
8 His novel Serafita, is an exposition of  Swedenborgian spiritual theology.
9 There are only brief mentions of  Swedenborg in Chesterton, yet the fact that he
wrote a book on Blake indicates his knowledge of  him.
10 Borges makes no mention that I can find of  Kant’s Dreams of a Spirit Seer, in which
Kant investigates Swedenborg, but he discusses in Autobiographical Essay reading
Kant as a young man. He also declares to Christ (1967): ‘I tried my hand at Kant’s
Critique of  Pure Reason. Of course, I got bogged down as most people do – as most
Germans do’.
11 ‘Like the discovery of  love, like the discovery of  the sea, the discovery of  Dostoevsky
marks an important date in one’s life’ (Borges 2000: 517).
12 Russell wrote about Kant’s Dreams of a Spirit Seer. Borges declared that Russell’s
History of  Western Philosophy would have chosen as his desert-island book (Sorrentino
2001: 230).
13 ‘Shaw, que yo sepa, no habló nunca de Swedenborg; cabe suponer que escribió bajo
el estímulo de Blake, a quien menciona con frecuencia y respecto, o, lo que no es
inverosímil, que arribó a las mismas ideas por cuenta propia’ (2005: 155–6) [‘Shaw
never, so far as I know, spoke of  Swedenborg; it might be supposed that he wrote
under the stimulus of  Blake, whom he mentions frequently and with respect’] (Borges
1995: 9).
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 197

Mark Twain, Unamuno, Lewis Carroll, T. S. Eliot, Frost, Ezra Pound,
Faulkner, Stephen Crane, Ambrose Bierce, Keats, H. G. Wells, Kafka.
Swedenborgian scholars, such as Eugene Taylor, Wilson Van Dusen
and James Lawrence have attempted to demonstrate that Swedenborg is
a far greater inf luence upon streams of intellectual, artistic and spiritual
thought – principally in the West but also, viz Suzuki, in the East – than
has hitherto been acknowledged. It would appear that Swedenborg con-
stitutes a far less pervasive presence in Hispanic artistic traditions than
in the English-speaking world. There are many reason for this, the most
immediately apparent being the twofold nature of  Swedenborg’s relation-
ship to the Enlightenment at a time when the Catholic authorities in Spain
were resistant to such secular inf luences; and secondly his Protestant,
non-conformist, anti-ecclesiastical and heterodox religious dimension.
Chadwick (2003: 2–3), Swedenborgian scholar and translator, is the only
scholar I have encountered to address the issue of  Swedenborg’s impact
(or lack of ) in the Catholic world:

The Vatican maintained an Index of prohibited books, and I had always assumed
that Swedenborg’s theological books appeared on it. […] The Vatican Library, which
includes the library of  the Inquisition, has no copies of  the original editions, other
than Volume I of  the Principia. Similarly the Library of  the Institut de France in
Paris reports only The Apocalypse Revealed among the major works of which it has
first editions. From this I deduce that the educated public of  Catholic countries
were almost totally unaware of  these books when they were published in London
and Amsterdam.

As discussed, it is precisely his innovative and anti-ecclesiastical qualities


which endeared Borges to Swedenborg. In searching through the extensive
articles in Swedenborgian denomination church publications, one finds
many references to Borges as a close and sympathetic reader of Swedenborg
– we recall Lawrence describing Borges as ‘Swedenborgian’. This fact alone
stands as testimony to the fact that Borges’ admiration for Swedenborg
outshone his anti-ecclesiastical critical bias in general. Indeed the dis-
senting, sceptical, critical and yet generously accommodating nature of so
many of  the published articles by Swedenborgian scholars demonstrates
198 Chapter Five

the spirit of  free enquiry typified by such denominations; a far cry from
the Argentine Catholicism of which Borges was so critical.
However, beyond the many references, and beyond the employment
of  Swedenborg in his ref lections on mysticism, to what extent was Borges’
poetic and fictional aesthetic inf luenced by Swedenborg? In this chapter
I concentrate on the narrative space of  the tales and poems in order to
investigate the abiding presence of  Swedenborgian ideas of  heavens and
hells, the persistence of  the soul after death, the landscape of  the visionary
world and the symbolic aspect of dreams. Importantly, and surprisingly
given Borges’ seeming disdain for the moral aspect of  theological works,
I intuit in Borges’ work a strong ethical dimension that bears visible hall-
marks of  the heavenly ethos of  Swedenborg. Rarely does the question
of ethics in Borges’ work appear in the scholarship, but I propose that a
ethical dimension present in his many interviews and essays demonstrates
the inf luence of  Swedenborg. An example of  this is his description of a
‘moral law’ to Amelia Barili: ‘I feel that we all know when we act well or
badly. I feel ethics is beyond discussion. For example, I have acted badly
many times, but when I do it, I know that it is wrong. It is not because of 
the consequences. In the long run, consequences even up, don’t you think?
It is the fact itself of doing good or doing bad’ (Burgin 1998: 245). As we
will explore in this chapter, such a statement reveals the Swedenborgian
perspective that heavens and hells are states of  the soul that surround us
even in life, and that the ethical instinct within us encourages us to choose
those pathways most appropriate to our moral state. Borges also discussed
the natural ethical nature of man in the preface to Elogio de la Sombra,
exclaiming somewhat provocatively, that the Protestant mentality privi-
leges this ethos more than the Catholic: ‘Una de las virtudes por las cuales
prefiero las naciones protestantes a las de tradición católica es su, cuidado
de la ética’ (1974: 975) [‘One of  the virtues for which I prefer Protestant
countries to Catholic is their regard for ethics’] (1975a: 10). This Protestant/
Catholic aspect with regards Swedenborg is discussed later in this chapter.
The earliest mention of  Swedenborg that I have encountered in
Borges’ work is the 1929 essay ‘La Duración del Infierno.’ What is curious
about this piece is that whilst he refers to Swedenborg only in a footnote,
never­theless the whole trajectory of  his analysis leads to a conclusion of
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 199

a uniquely Swedenborgian perspective. With an anti-ecclesiastical vision


that is characteristic of  Borges’ entire critical work, the essay considers the
theological implications of  the notion of  hell’s eternity, suggesting that
the ultimate aim of  the church in proposing the eternal nature of  hell was
that of enforcing obedience, and he appraises the various contradictions
inherent in the theological arguments. ‘Ahora se levanta sobre mí el tercero
de los argumentos, el único. Se escribe así, tal vez: Hay eternidad de cielo y
de infierno porque la dignidad del libre albedrío así lo precisa; o tenemos la
facultad de obrar para siempre o es una delusión este yo’ (1974: 237–8) [‘Now
the third argument looms over me. It may, perhaps, be written thus: Heaven
and Hell are eternal because the dignity of  free will requires them to be so;
either our deeds transcend time, or the “I” is a delusion’] (2000: 51, original
italics). This powerful statement demonstrates firstly the similar considera-
tion for the transiency of  the state of  ‘I’ that is developed in the essay of
1922 ‘La nadería de la personalidad’, and secondly, a Swedenborgian vision
of  the states of  heaven and hell as being selected not by divine judgement
but by the human soul. Indeed, without mentioning Swedenborg, Borges
presents the argument so heretically maintained by Swedenborg that ‘nos
concede el atroz derecho de perdernos, de insistir en el mal, de rechazar
las operaciones de la gracia, de ser alimento del fuego que no se acaba, de
hacer fracasar a Dios en nuestro destino, del cuerpo sin claridad en lo eterno’
(1974: 238) [‘we given the terrifying right to perdition, to persist in evil,
to reject all access to grace, to fuel the eternal f lames, to make God fail in
our destiny, to be forever a shadow’] (2000: 51). Swedenborg’s Heaven and
Hell contains ample descriptions of  this state of choice that human souls
are given over whether to reside in heaven or in hell: ‘even while we are
living in our bodies, each one of us is in a community with spirits as to our
own spirits even though we are unaware of it. Good people are in angelic
communities by means of [their spirits] and evil people are in hellish com-
munities. Further, we come into those same communities when we die’
(§438). Importantly, Swedenborg suggests that such conditions are states
of  the soul that are already present in our daily lives: every day we project
around us our own heavens and hells, love being the guiding principle of 
200 Chapter Five

heaven.14 Borges’ ethical position can be demonstrated as deriving from


his reading of  Swedenborg, as he articulates this perspective in the essay
on Swedenborg ‘Testigo de lo invisible’:

El Infierno es la otra cara del Cielo. Su reverso preciso es necesario para el equilibrio
de la Creación. El Señor lo rige, como a los cielos. El equilibrio de las dos esferas es
requerido para el libre albedrío, que sin tregua debe elegir entre el bien, que mana del
Cielo, y el mal, que mana del Infierno. Cada día, cada instante de cada día, el hombre
labra su perdición eterna o su salvación. Seremos lo que somos. Los terrores o alarmas
de la agonía, que suelen darse cuando el moribundo está acobardado y confuso, no
tienen mayor importancia. Creamos o no en la inmortalidad personal, es innegable
que la doctrina revelada por Swedenborg es más moral y más razonable que la de un
misterioso don que se obtiene, casi al azar, a última hora. Nos lleva, por lo pronto,
al ejercicio de una vida virtuosa. (2005: 157)

[Hell is the other face of  heaven. Its exact opposite is necessary for the balance of
creation. The Lord rules over it as he does over heaven. Balance between the two
spheres is required for free will, which must unceasingly choose between good,
which emanates from heaven, and evil, which emanates from hell. Every day, every
instant of every day, man is shaping his eternal damnation or his salvation. We will
be what we are. The terrors or anxieties of agony, which usually occur when a dying
person is frightened and confused, are of  little importance. Whether we believe in
the immortality of  the soul or not, we must recognize that the doctrine revealed by
Swedenborg is more moral and reasonable than one that postulates a mysterious
gift gotten, almost by chance, at the eleventh hour. To begin with, it leads us to the
practice of virtue in our lives.] (1995: 11)

This is a theological and ethical thread that runs throughout Borges’


works. In this early essay he evokes Shaw’s Man and Superman alongside

14 ‘There is infernal freedom and there is heavenly freedom. It is from infernal free-
dom to think and to will evil, and so far as civil and moral laws do not hinder, to
speak and to do it. On the other hand, it is from heavenly freedom to think and to
will good, and so far as opportunity is granted, to speak and to do it. Whatever a
man thinks, wills, speaks and does from freedom he perceives as his own; for all the
freedom which everyone has is from his love. Therefore those who are in the love of
evil perceive only that infernal freedom is freedom itself, while those who are in the
love of good perceive that heavenly freedom is freedom itself and consequently the
evil and the good perceive the opposite to be slavery’ (Divine Providence, §43).
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 201

Swedenborg’s works as one of  the more compelling aesthetic and ethical
depictions of  hell. In repeated interviews of  his later decades, he continues
to draw on these two writers as portraying hell in a manner that champi-
ons the human seizure of destiny over either the reward of  faith or the
arbitrariness of divine will. Importantly, Borges draws from Swedenborg’s
vision of elected afterlife locations an ethical position that emphasizes the
state of rapture at the mystery of existence, and the fulfilment gained from
following one’s own particular destiny. He returns to these two positions
repeatedly in the interviews compiled in Borges at Eighty:

I think that one is dying all the time. Every time we are not feeling something, dis-
covering something, when we are merely repeating something mechanically. At that
moment you are dead. Life may come at any moment also. If you take a single day,
therein you find many deaths, I suppose, and many births also. But I try not to be
dead. I try to be curious concerning things, and now I am receiving experiences all
the time, and those experiences will be changed into poems, into short stories, into
fables. I am receiving them all the time, although I know that many of  the things I
do and things I say are mechanical, that is to say, they belong to death rather than
to life. (Barnstone 1982: 13)

The ethical instinct, he argues, lies in understanding that right and


wrong are aspects of  following or not following one’s appropriate life path-
way. Consequently, the states of  heaven or hell are neither for Borges nor
Swedenborg exclusively states of the soul after death, but are present around
us throughout our life: ‘At the very moment of our lives we know whether
we’re acting the right way or the wrong way. We might say that doomsday is
going on all the time, that every moment of our lives we’re acting wrongly
or rightly. Doomsday is not something that comes at the end. It’s going
on all the time. And we know, through some instinct, when we have acted
rightly or wrongly’ (Barnstone 1982: 19). Note how this statement echoes
Borges’ description of  the states of  the soul that are Swedenborg’s heavens
and hells: ‘El cielo y el infierno de su doctrina no son lugares, aunque las
almas de los muertos que los habitan, y de alguna manera los crean, los
ven como situados en el espacio. Son condiciones de las almas, determi-
nadas por su vida anterior. A nadie le está vedado el paraíso, a nadie le está
impuesto el infierno. Las puertas, por decirlo así, están abiertas’ (2005:
202 Chapter Five

156) [‘The heaven and hell of  his doctrine are not places, even though the
souls of  the dead who inhabit and, in a way, create them perceive them as
being situated in space. They are conditions of  the soul, determined by its
former life. Heaven is forbidden to no one; hell, imposed on no one. The
doors, so to speak, are open’] (1995: 10). Borges’ statements thus chime with
Swedenborg, and consequently one can allow greater room for manoeu-
ver within Lawrence’s claim that Borges was himself  Swedenborgian. It is
also a position that informs Borges’ reading of  Dante. As discussed, whilst
Borges’ praises the Divine Comedy as being the pinnacle of poetic vision,
he rejects outright the theological basis of reward and punishment that he
perceives in the structure of  the poetic cycle. He repeats his gnostic and
Swedenborgian credentials in recognising that hell is a state in the present,
not a future punishment:

You know, Dante was wrong about hell, wrong about the meaning of  that inscrip-
tion on the gate of  the Inferno in the first lines of  Canto 3: Lasciate ogni speranza,
voi ch’entrate (Abandon every hope, you who enter). Hell doesn’t begin down there.
There is no entry to the afterlife. Hell begins here, and here is where we should
abandon all hope. Then we have the possibility, the hope, of some momentary hap-
piness. (Barnstone 2000: 31)

As I hope to have demonstrated, there is an ethical attitude present in


Borges that clearly derives from his reading of  Swedenborg and which
informs his reading of  Dante, Shaw and other writers. Swedenborg, it
must be emphasized, inscribed a strong ethical dimension to his writings
– indeed an ethos of portraying divine love against demonic vice purveys
his works. He explains this repeatedly in Heaven and Hell: ‘All this has
been presented to encourage people to examine themselves and to iden-
tify their dominant love on the basis of  their pleasures, so that according
to their grasp of  the knowledge of correspondences, they may know their
state of  life after death’ (§487). I would argue that such an ethical position
is visible in Borges, and that it is a position that he defends in interview
on many occasions and that, as we shall now see, is presented in many of 
his poems and fictions.
The work of  Swedenborg that appears to have been of greatest impact
upon Borges is Heaven and Hell, which he cites on numerous occasions, and
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 203

which he describes as ‘el más conocido y hermoso de sus tratados’ (2005:


155) [‘the best known and most beautiful of  his treatises’] (1995: 9). This
work is commonly considered the most accessible of  Swedenborg’s many
spiritual volumes, being his most articulate and unambiguous account of 
his journeys to the angelic realms and his many conversations with angels
and the dead. Borges considered this book particularly noteworthy pre-
cisely because Swedenborg’s clear and lucid descriptions of an otherworld
reality are such that this reality appears normal and commonplace, rather
than fantastic or fictional. Upon this basis, as discussed in Chapter One,
rests so much of  Borges’ confusing hermeneutics of mystical texts.

‘Los ángeles de Swedenborg’

As is to be expected with Swedenborg’s extensive and thorough volumes,


there is no easy way to summarize the vision of this other world, nor its com-
plex structure of  hierarchies of angels. Whilst Borges’ essay on Swedenborg,
which we have appraised earlier, is of great synoptic value, one of  the most
concise précises of  this perplexing landscape is a brief  Borges text in Libro
de seres imaginarios (with Margarita Guerrero), called ‘Los ángeles de
Swedenborg’. Borges also includes other passages from Swedenborg in
the same work and in Antología de la literatura fantástica (with Silvina
Ocampo and Bioy Casares).15 Of particular importance here, is the selec-
tion of a passage from Swedenborg’s Arcana Cœlestia, which Borges entitles
‘Un teólogo en la muerte’ and which he includes in Historia universal de
la infamia and Antología de la literatura fantástica. This brief  tale serves
as a blueprint both for Borges’ fictional depiction of otherworld realities,
which we will explore below, and as the clearest exposition of  the tension

15 Antología de la literatura fantástica (1940) was originally translated by Anthony


Kerrigan as Extraordinary Tales (Herder & Herder 1971c). It was then republished
with no translator identified by Viking (1988) with a foreword by Ursula K. Le Guin.
204 Chapter Five

between faith and experience, orthodoxy and heterodoxy, pride and humil-
ity, that we find throughout Borges’ critical work.
I have been unable to ascertain whether Borges transcribed the passage
from Swedenborg’s Arcana Cœlestia directly from a Spanish translation, or
whether he translated it himself  from an English (or perhaps other) trans-
lation. Borges’ self-confessed poor Latin would indicate that it is unlikely
he translated it directly from Swedenborg himself.16 The passage itself, as
one would expect in a piece that Borges chose to incorporate in two of  his
many anthologies, is arrestingly Borgesian. To begin with, as with so many
tales of  Borges, whether from the period of  Ficciones or the later Brodie,
the text is itself second-hand, as Swedenborg remarks that his account
had been told him by the angels. Regardless of  the ontological question
of angels, as a narrative strategy this provides layers of  fictionality over
the account, inviting the reader into the textual space. This is reinforced
by the rendition of  the passage in a collection of  Borges in which fiction
and historical legend are juxtaposed.
‘I have been allowed to talk with some people who lived more than
two thousand years ago, people whose lives are described in history books
and are therefore familiar’ (§480). Swedenborg recounts the activities of 
the theologian Melanchthon (who, I conjecture, is Philipp Melanchthon,
the German reformer and collaborator with Martin Luther), who upon
dying is unable or unwilling to acknowledge that he is dead and contin-
ues with his theological entreaties concerning faith as of greater value
in heaven than charity. Over a period of  time (though as Borges indi-
cates elsewhere, there is no time in Swedenborg’s heaven) he becomes
entrenched in his dogmatic doctrine of  faith, and distances himself ever

16 One can only conjecture whether Borges was really familiar with all the eight vol-
umes of  Swedenborg’s Arcana Cœlestia (or more, depending on the edition; Borges
refers to the nine volumes of  Arcana Cœlestia in ‘Testigo’). Judging by his review of 
Hesse’s Glass Bead Game, for example, which is merely a biographical sketch about
Hesse, with one empty brief paragraph about the novel, and which thus suggests that
he did not read the novel (2005: 512), and by his confession that he could not finish
Joyce’s Ulysses, it is perfectly likely that he skimmed Arcana Cœlestia (as I confess to
have done), selecting the passages relating to the situation of  the souls of  the dead,
the angels and the demons, and hurrying over the extensive biblical exegesis.
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 205

more from divine love and wisdom. His pride and obstinacy eventually
drive him into consort with magicians and demons and exclude him for-
ever from heaven. This passage demonstrates the severe critique – to the
point of  heresy – that Swedenborg maintained concerning doctrines of 
faith, perfectly encapsulated in Swedenborg’s damning sentence in Heaven
and Hell: ‘I can bear witness from all my experiences of what happens in
heaven and in hell that people who have confessed faith alone as a matter
of doctrine and have engaged in evil as regards their lives are all in hell’
(§482). Repeatedly in Arcana Cœlestia and in Heaven and Hell he depicts
the astonishment of newly-dead upon realising that faith alone serves
them no purpose if not justified by love and charity – a position resonant
of  St Paul. Faith, Swedenborg argues, must be borne out by manifestation
of  love, and whilst a cruel heart may be disguised on earth, there is no
hypocrisy possible in heaven, as the individual’s true nature is visible.17
Furthermore, writes Swedenborg, believers and non-believers alike share
the afterlife with no distinction. As I argued in the Introduction, whilst
Swedenborg was demonstrably a man of  faith, this heterodox theological
position would chime at once with Borges’ intellectual dif ficulty with the
exhortation to treat matters theological or metaphysical as matters of  faith.
Experience and imagination, not adherence to faith, are the epistemologi-
cal bases of  Borges’ philosophical outlook, and thus he would have found
great accommodation within Swedenborg’s vision.

‘Diálogo de muertos’

The extract ‘Los ángeles de Swedenborg’ also provides the substance


for a strikingly Swedenborgian tale, ‘Diálogo de muertos’ [‘Dead Men’s
Dialogue’], a brief  tale from El Hacedor, which, like many of  Borges’ more

17 ‘In heaven no one can conceal his interiors by his expression, or feign, or really deceive
and mislead by craft or hypocrisy’ (§48).
206 Chapter Five

enigmatic shorter pieces, has generated scarcely any critical response. As


with Swedenborg’s account of  Melanchthon, in Borges’ tale, the two cen-
tral characters of  the tale, former caudillo Rosas and the general Quiroga,
are both initially unaware that they are dead, and are both made aware,
over the course of  the text, of  their predicament and of  the need to adapt
to the new circumstances. The narrative concerns the return of  Rosas to
Argentina from his burial place of Southampton in 1877, where he is greeted
by a crowd of soldiers and by his former comrade-in-arms Quiroga. Borges
revisits two historical characters who figure largely in his work, granting
them thus a post-mortem arena in which to reconcile themselves both to
their prior lives and to their current existence in death. Both Rosas and
Quiroga constitute important aspects of  Borges’ ancestral history (see
Williamson 2004), and both are subjects of early poems: ‘Rosas’ (Fervor
de Buenos Aires [1923]), and ‘El General Quiroga va en coche al muere’
(Luna de enfrente [1925]).
A sense of squalor and putrefaction pervades the tale, and, like a con-
densed version of  Pedro Páramo, the reader is only made aware that the
characters are dead once the narrative is truly established.18 Rosas may be
seen as embodying aspects of  Swedenborg’s Melanchthon, in that his pride
and haughtiness whilst alive dominate his character whilst dead; whilst
Quiroga, who died a hero’s death at the hands of  the treacherous Rosas
forty years earlier, allows himself  to learn and develop in the realm of  the

18 It needs emphasising that Borges paid particular attention to the squalid landscape
of  hell depicted by Swedenborg. ‘Ahora, ¿qué son los infiernos? Los infiernos, según
Swedenborg, tienen varios aspectos. El aspecto que tendrían para nosotros o para los
ángeles. Son zonas pantanosas, zonas en las que hay ciudades que parecen destruidas
por los incendios; pero ahí los réprobos se sienten felices. Se sienten felices a su modo,
es decir, están llenos de odio y no hay un monarca de ese reino; continuamente están
conspirando unos contra otros. Es un mundo de baja política, de conspiración. Eso
es el infierno.’ (2005: 198) [‘So, what are these hells? Hells, for Swedenborg, have
various aspects: one for us and one for the angels. They are swampy places in which
there are cities that seem destroyed by fire. But the damned feel happy there. They
feel happy in their particular way, that’s to say, they are filled with hatred, there is no
monarch, and they are continually plotting against each other. It is a world of  lowly
politics, of conspiracy. This is hell’] (my translation).
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 207

dead. This putrid landscape is at once resonant of  the landscapes of  hell
described by Swedenborg:

In some hells you can see what look like the ruins of houses and cities after a fire, where
hellish spirits live and hide out. In the milder hells you can see crude huts, sometimes
grouped in something like a city, with alleyways and streets. There are hellish spirits
in these homes, with constant quarrels, hostility, beating, and violence. The streets
and alleys are full of  thieves and robbers. In some hells there are nothing but brothels,
foul to look at and full of all kinds of  filth and excrement. (Heaven and Hell: §586)

Borges writes about Swedenborg’s works that ‘Quienes mueren no saben


que están muertos; durante un tiempo indefinido proyectan una imagen
ilusoria de su ámbito habitual y de las personas que los rodeaban’ (2005:
156) [‘People who have died but fail to realize they are dead project, for an
indefinite period of  time, an illusory image of  their customary ambiance
and of  the people who surrounded them’] (1995: 10). From the imagery
of  this tale, he presents the characters Quiroga and Rosas as inhabiting a
world of projection, and consequently they are recently arrived in the world
of  the dead. In Swedenborg’s account of  Melanchthon, as the theologian
persists in his drive for authority and in his adamant refusal to accept
his own death, his surroundings slowly begin to evanesce: ‘los muebles
empezaron a afantasmarse hasta ser invisibles’ (1974: 335) [‘the furnishings
in his room began to fade away and disappear’] (1988: 258), and a group
of obsequious admirers gravitate towards him, ‘pero como alguna de esas
personas no tenía cara y otros parecían muertos, acabó por aborrecerlos y
desconfiar’ (1974: 336) [‘but since some of  the visitors were faceless and
others seemed dead he ended up hating and distrusting them’] (1988: 258).
Swedenborg writes in other passages both of  Heaven and Hell and Arcana
Cœlestia that like f lock to like both in heaven and in hell, and thus souls
filled with divine love are attracted towards the angelic realms, and may
eventually become angels, whilst hateful and proud souls gravitate towards
the demonic realms, and may eventually become demons. One can imme-
diately perceive how Borges’ reading of  Swedenborg informed his concep-
tion of  the historical re-enactment of  Rosas and Quiroga. He writes, for
example, that in Swedenborg’s accounts ‘Los réprobos no tienen cara o
tienen caras mutiladas y atroces’ (2005: 156) [‘the damned are faceless or
208 Chapter Five

their features are mutilated, atrocious’] (1995: 10). In the tale ‘Diálogo’, these
faceless or ghoulishly disfigured souls gravitate towards Rosas clearly drawn
to his still manifest mundane power. Rosas, like Swedenborg’s theologian,
likewise seems gravely resistant to abandoning the power and authority
that had been his during life. Swedenborg writes in Heaven and Hell that
souls filled with hatred and malice naturally are attracted to the regions
of  hell rather than heaven:

There is no way that people who are engaged in carnal love can live in heaven’s warmth,
because heaven’s warmth is heavenly love. They can live in hell’s warmth, though,
which is a love of cruelty toward people who do not support them. The pleasures of 
this love are contempt for others, hostility, hatred, and vengefulness. When they are
absorbed in these they are in their very life, with no knowledge whatever of what it
means to do good for others out of sheer goodness and for the sake of  the good itself.
All they know is how to do good out of malice and for the sake of malice. (§481)

Borges, perhaps referring to this passage or any of  the many similar pas-
sages in Heaven and Hell and Arcana Cœlestia, writes of  ‘los réprobos’ [‘the
damned’] that ‘El ejercicio del poder y el odio recíproco son su felicidad.
Viven entregados a la política, en el sentido más sudamericano de la palabra;
es decir, viven para conspirar, mentir e imponerse’ (2005: 156) [‘for them,
happiness lies in the exercise of power and in mutual hatred. They devote
their lives to politics, in the most South American sense of  the word: that
is, they live to scheme, to lie, and to impose their will on others’] (1995:
10). It is clear that his depiction of  Rosas is of a soul defiantly unwill-
ing to relinquish such political power, and who is consequently guiding
himself  towards the demonic regions of  hell. Emerson, in his chapter on
Swedenborg, concisely describes this desperate nature depicted by Borges
in Rosas: ‘The ghosts are tormented with the fear of death, and cannot
remember that they have died’ (2003: 34). Quiroga appears like the broth-
ers Cain and Abel in ‘Leyenda’ (Elogio de la sombra), Borges’ brief and
Swedenborgian account of  the dead brothers meeting in the next world,
in that, like Cain, he has forgiven Rosas through his oblivion. Quiroga is
consequently fully cognizant of  his status, and fully prepared to move on
into the further regions of  the dead, whereas Rosas, puf fed up with pride
for his life achievements, wishes to remain Rosas even in death, believing
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 209

‘Será que no estoy hecho a estar muerto’ (1974: 792) [‘It must be that I am
not made to be a dead man’] (1970: 35).
In the poem ‘Rosas’, the youthful Borges considers the tremendous
presence of  Rosas upon contemporary Argentine society. Again, ref lect-
ing his abiding interest in the dialectic of memory and oblivion (‘olvido’),
Borges concludes the poem with the ref lection that to maintain hatred
for Rosas is to keep him alive ‘Ya Dios lo habrá olvidado / y es menos una
injuria que una piedad / demorar su infinita disolución / con limosnas de
odio’ (1972: 16) [‘Even God has forgotten him, / and to delay his eternal
extinction / for a pittance of  hatred / is to turn our contempt into charity
now’] (1972: 17). The poem ‘El General Quiroga va en coche al muere’,
meanwhile, presents a proud Quiroga defiantly rejecting his forthcoming
death, proclaiming his integral power and importance with the world and
the living: ‘Ya muerto, ya de pie, ya inmortal, ya fantasma, / se presentó al
infierno que Dios le había marcado, / y a sus órdenes iban, rotas y desan-
gradas, / las ánimas en pena de hombres y de caballos’ (1972: 40) [‘Now
dead, now on his feet, now immortal, now a ghost, / he reported to the
Hell marked out for him by God, / and under his command there marched,
broken and bloodless, / the souls in purgatory of  his soldiers and his horses’]
(1972: 41). These early poetic musings on the deaths of  Rosas and Quiroga
also present a Swedenborgian vision of  the complex web of relationships
between the souls of  the dead, the people they had been when alive, and
their persistent presence in the memory of  the living. Rosas, it would seem
both from the poem and the tale, is prevented from any development of 
his soul in the realm of  the dead partly because of  his towering pride, but
partly because of  the sustaining force of  hatred that the living (Borges, for
example) thrust upon him. Quiroga, perhaps as a result of  his premature
death four decades previously, appears to have overcome the pride that char-
acterized his death, indicated in the poem, and would seem keen to find a
passage away from these infernal regions: ‘Yo pensaba como usted cuando
entré en la muerte, pero aquí aprendí muchas cosas’ (1974: 792) [‘I thought
as you do when I entered death, but I learned many things here’] (1970:
35). In the case of  both figures, the thoroughly Swedenborgian approach
to the conscious choices that the souls of  the dead have is developed; and
consequently the hell which the figures inhabit is not one of punishment,
210 Chapter Five

such as depicted by the mediaeval theologians that Borges discusses in


‘Duración del Infierno’, but one of  the ongoing squabbles and battles that
characterized the lives of  these figures.
As is typical of  Borges, even with such a brief and seemingly simple
piece as this, an intriguing narrative device is delivered at the end of  the
tale – a seemingly innocuous statement that strikes at the heart of complex
aesthetics of  Swedenborg. As discussed throughout this book, the fictional/
poetic space for Borges constitutes far more than mere fiction or mere
poetry, as it can be considered of an epistemological order akin to Blake’s
‘Imagination’ or Corbin’s mundus imaginalis – the imaginal. Whilst this is
a dominant aspect of  his philosophy of aesthetics, nevertheless Borges mud-
dies the hermeneutic waters by emphasising the ‘reality’ of  Swedenborg’s
visions against the ‘poetic unreality’ of  Dante’s (see Chapter One). Borges
anticipates the expected reader reaction to the works of  Swedenborg when
he defends him against charges of madness. This is because when we read
certain passages in Swedenborg’s Heaven and Hell, the voice of our educa-
tion tells us that he must be delusional because the alternative is so hard to
conceptualize: ‘When I have been allowed to be in the company of angels,
I have seen what was there exactly the way I see things in our world, so
perceptibly that I did not know I was not in our world and in the court of
some king here. I have also talked with angels just as one person here talks
to another’ (§174). The alternative to delusion, hallucination or poetic
fancy is that Swedenborg’s angelic realm is of an order equivalent to an
undiscovered island in the Pacific, or a tribal community hidden in the
rain forest – de carne y hueso. Borges, synthesizing numerous passages from
Arcana Cœlestia and Heaven and Hell, assures us that this is not so, and
that ‘El cielo y el infierno de su doctrina no son lugares, aunque las almas
de los muertos que los habitan, y de alguna manera los crean, los ven como
situados en el espacio. Son condiciones de las almas, determinadas por su
vida anterior’ (2005: 156) [‘The heaven and hell of  his doctrine are not
places, even though the souls of  the dead who inhabit and, in a way, create
them perceive them as being situated in space. They are conditions of  the
soul, determined by its former life’] (1995: 10). The location (for want of a
better word), therefore, of  Swedenborg’s heavens and hells is neither ‘real’,
as the New World was for Columbus, nor ‘merely fictional’, as Mordor or
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 211

The Shire were for Tolkien and his readers. They are, as Borges suggests
‘conditions of  the soul’ and thus correspond to the Imagination of  Blake
and Coleridge, to Corbin’s imaginal, to Jung’s dreamworld, as liminal spaces
neither one nor the other. Kathleen Raine lucidly describes this liminal
state: ‘For the landscapes of poetry, the landscapes of  the great painters are
not to be found in nature at all. […] They are landscapes of  the soul, and
the imagery is not an end but a means – a language for discoursing upon
realities of  the intelligible world, not of  the physical world. The theme
of imaginative art is not physical but metaphysical’ (2007: 25). It must
be emphasized that Swedenborg did not walk out of  his door and into a
parallel universe populated with angels and demons, but neither was he
‘making it up’ in the sense that a novelist might create a fiction.19 This is a
dif ficult idea to conceive of, let alone describe, and yet Corbin succeeds in
defining the imaginal as, precisely, this liminal landscape that has charac-
terized religious and mystical experience (both in Christianity and Islam),
poetry and art, across time and cultures; and Swedenborg was for Corbin
of supreme importance, in the same way that he was for Borges, as ‘recorrió
este mundo y los otros, lúcido y laborioso. […] ese escandinavo sanguíneo,
que fue mucho más lejos que Erico el Rojo’ (2005: 152) [‘(he) journeyed,
lucid and laborious, through this and all other worlds […] that sanguine
Scandinavian who went much further than Eric the Red’] (1995: 3). This

19 Perhaps, however, his voyages were of such a physical order. Swedenborg writes in
Heaven and Hell: ‘As to being carried away by the spirit to another place, I have
been shown by living experience what it is, and how it is done, but only two or three
times. I will relate a single instance. Walking through the streets of a city and through
fields, talking at the same time with spirits, I knew no otherwise than that I was fully
awake, and in possession of my usual sight. Thus I walked on without going astray,
and all the while with clear vision, seeing groves, rivers, palaces, houses, men, and
other objects. But after walking thus for some hours, suddenly I saw with my bodily
eyes, and noted that I was in another place. Being greatly astonished I perceived
that I had been in the same state as those who were said to have been led away by
the spirit into another place. For in this state the distance, even though it be many
miles, and the time, though it be many hours or days, are not thought of; neither
is there any feeling of  fatigue; and one is led unerringly through ways of which he
himself is ignorant, even to the destined place’ (§441).
212 Chapter Five

whole dimension of  the imaginal is dif ficult to apprehend cognitively, as


it can only be described in terms that create a sense of contradiction – nei-
ther real nor fantasy yet both real and fantasy. Czeslaw Milosz, another
contributor to Lawrence’s Testimony to the Invisible examines the complex
nature of  the imaginal with regards Dante, Blake and Swedenborg:

Blake’s The Marriage of  Heaven and Hell is modeled on Swedenborg, and he would
have been amused by an inquiry into whether he had ‘really’ seen the devils and angels
he describes. The crux of  the problem – and a serious challenge to the mind – is
Blake’s respect for both the imagination of  Dante, who was a poet, and the imagina-
tion of  Swedenborg, whose works are written in quite pedestrian Latin prose. Dante
was regarded by his contemporaries as a man who had visited the other world. Yet
Jaspers would not have called him a schizophrenic, because the right of  the poet to
invent – that is, to lie – was recognized in Jaspers’s lifetime as something obvious. It
is not easy to grasp the consequences of  the aesthetic theories which have emerged
as the f lotsam and jetsam of  the scientific and technological revolution. The pres-
sure of  habit still forces us to exclaim: ‘Well then, Swedenborg wrote fiction and he
was aware it was no more than fiction!’ But, tempting as it is, the statement would
be false. Neither Swedenborg nor Blake were aestheticians; they did not enclose the
spiritual within the domain of art and poetry and oppose it to the material. At the
risk of simplifying the issue by using a definition, let us say rather that they both were
primarily concerned with the energy that reveals itself in a constant interaction of 
Imagination with the things perceived by our five senses. (1995: 25–6)

Swedenborg’s first profound experience in such altered states of con-


sciousness occurred as a result of dreams and visions, and waking trances
brought on by breath control and meditation. His journeys were thus
likewise ‘conditions of  the soul’ in the manner in which Borges considered
dreams to be, and in the manner in which Jung describes the ‘Transcendental
Function’.20 There is therefore a relationship between the landscape of 
Swedenborg’s visions and visionary or numinous dreams; indeed Robert
Moss (1998), author of many books about dreaming and lucid dreaming,
writes that Swedenborg’s were dreams of  the most ecstatic and potent form.

20 He later renamed this ‘Active Imagination’, an aesthetic, contemplative exercise that


he pursued in his own visionary quests that led to the composition of  the Red Book
(see Jung 1997).
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 213

Swedenborg’s visions have also been appraised as correlating with NDEs


(near death experiences) and OBEs (out of  body experiences). Raymond
Moody, researcher into such experiences, writes in the foreword to Van
Dusen’s Presence of  Other Worlds (2004: xi): ‘Swedenborg’s reports of  his
out-of-body experiences resonate well with the legions of contemporary
reports of people who find themselves out of  their bodies and who are per-
plexed about the situation.’ Swedenborg himself describes this distinction
between the solid, concrete world of reality, and the visionary dreamworld
of  the spirits: ‘But it must be remembered that a man cannot see angels with
his bodily eyes, but only with the eyes of  the spirit within him, because his
spirit is in the spiritual world, and all things of  the body are in the natural
world’ (Heaven and Hell: §76).
With this in mind, we return to the tale. Quiroga explains to Rosas
that nothing can persist forever, not even in death, and that even as they
speak, ‘Fíjese bien, ya estamos cambiando los dos’ (1974: 792) [‘Just look,
we are both changing already’] (1970: 35). The response of Rosas is curious:
‘Será que no estoy hecho a estar muerto, pero estos lugares y esta discusión
me parecen un sueño, y no un sueño soñado por mí sino por otro, que
está por nacer todavía’ (1974: 792) [‘It must be that I am not made to be a
dead man, but these places and this discussion seem like a dream, and not
a dream dreamed by me but by someone else still to be born’] (1970: 35).
The tale then concludes with the equally mysterious commentary of  the
anonymous narrator: ‘No hablaron más, porque en ese momento Alguien
los llamó’ (1974: 792) [‘They spoke no more, for at that moment Someone
called them’] (1970: 35). The tale is set in 1877. Borges was born in 1899.
The tale was published in 1960. Following the argument of  the parallels
between dreams, visions and poetic imagination, one might suggest that
there is no dif ference between Swedenborg’s account of  Melanchthon
and Borges’ account of  Rosas and Quiroga. Why would we assume one to
have genuinely (i.e. non-poetically) experienced such an account (although
recounted via angels) and the other to have merely invented it? These are
the wrong questions. Rosas and Quiroga did engage in this dialogue of  the
dead, as we have testimony of it in the tale, and they were themselves wit-
ness to the dream crafting of  the poet – Borges – who was yet to be born
and yet to witness them. Who, consequently, is this ‘Alguien’? Could it be
214 Chapter Five

Borges, summoning the dead warriors into his dream/fiction, or could it


be the reader, engaging in the poetic act of  textual dialogue with these war-
riors? Or could it be God or an angel, drawing them onwards, as Quiroga
declares, towards ‘otra cara y otro destino’ (792) [‘another face and another
destiny’]? No answer is to be expected, and neither should it. As Corbin
argues, we tend to approach these imaginal matters with the wrong epis-
temological tools, seeking concrete answers to mercurial concerns. Borges
appears to intuit the same liminal question, and consequently challenges
our already challenged critical faculty by provoking this most labyrinthine
relationship between fiction and reality, the living and the dead, dream
and waking, madness and sanity. ‘Diálogo de muertos’, reading like a page
from Swedenborg although in a Latin American climate, challenges our
most essential ontological certainties and raises questions about the nature
of  the real.

‘Fragmentos de un evangelio apócrifo’


[‘From an apocryphal gospel’]

As I have suggested above, the theological, visionary, works of Swedenborg


constituted a powerful presence within Borges’ works. I have also argued
that Borges’ inclusion of  the passage entitled ‘un teólogo en la muerte’ is
significant as numerous Swedenborgian elements in the brief extract are
present in Borges’ later tale ‘Diálogo de muertos.’ There are further works
of  Borges that deserve consideration, even if it may be less thorough than
the analysis of  ‘Diálogo’. As I have also suggested, the briefer pieces of 
Borges’ later works tend to receive lesser critical attention than his earlier
fictions. In Elogio de la sombra, Borges confronts much of  his contempla-
tion about the nature of death and the dead that his reading of  Swedenborg
and other mystics would have fuelled. There is scarcely any critical atten-
tion given, for example, to a peculiar and oddly-numbered list of  thirty-
seven proverbs entitled ‘Fragmentos de un evangelio apócrifo’ [‘From an
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 215

apocryphal gospel’]. Whilst it would be rash to ascribe all or even most of 
these proverbs to a Swedenborgian source, nevertheless, these proverbs are
a clear articulation of  the central ethical position, inf luenced strongly by
Swedenborg, that we find Borges discussing in his many later interviews.
That they have been so overlooked is a shame, as they truly embody all
that is most Borgesian: iconoclastic, ironic, humble, wise, ethical, humor-
ous, whimsical and, importantly, practical. Borges would balk at being
called a spiritual teacher, but a perusal of  these proverbs reveals a deeply
measured and insightful counsel; some proverbs barbed like a Zen kōan,
others revealing the presence of  Swedenborg. Without the space to discuss
each one, for the purposes of  this study I will appraise the Swedenborgian
aspect of a brief selection.
‘3. Desdichado el pobre en espíritu, porque bajo la tierra será lo que
ahora es en la tierra’ (1975a: 106) [‘Wretched are the poor in spirit: for
what they were on earth, so shall they be in their graves’].21 Recounting it
in his biographical sketch on Swedenborg, Borges took obvious relish in
Swedenborg’s account of  the hermit who had renounced all worldly goods
and activities, who then found himself woefully unfit for heaven. This first
proverb appears as a direct allusion to this matter, indicating the position
that Swedenborg maintained that full engagement with life and with the
world are the essential drives of  the living that can only be denied at a price.
Swedenborg explains this in detail in Heaven and Hell.
I have spoken with some after death who, while they lived in the world, renounced the
world and gave themselves up to an almost solitary life, in order that by an abstraction
of  the thoughts from worldly things they might have opportunity for pious medita-
tions, believing that thus they might enter the way to heaven. But these in the other
life are of a sad disposition; they despise others who are not like themselves; they are
indignant that they do not have a happier lot than others, believing that they have
merited it; they have no interest in others, and turn away from the duties of charity
by which there is conjunction with heaven. They desire heaven more than others;
but when they are taken up among the angels they induce anxieties that disturb the

21 In this chapter and the ensuing Conclusion, all translations of  texts of  Elogio de la
sombra are by Di Giovanni and are from the bilingual edition entitled In Praise of 
Darkness (1975a).
216 Chapter Five

happiness of  the angels; and in consequence they are sent away; and when sent away
they betake themselves to desert places, where they lead a life like that which they
lived in the world. (§360)

‘11. Bienaventurados los misericordiosos, porque su dicha está en el


ejercicio de la misericordia y no en la esperanza de un premio’ (1975a: 106)
[‘Blessed are the merciful: for their happiness is in showing mercy, not in
obtaining reward’]. ‘12 Bienaventurados los de limpio corazón, porque
ven a Dios’ (1975a: 106) [‘Blessed are the pure in heart: for they already
see God’]. Countless passages in Heaven and Hell testify to the nature of
mercy being a natural attribute of divine love, and that to perform acts
of mercy or charity for the aggrandizement of  the constitute selfish acts:

[…] the angels refuse all thanks for the good they do, and are displeased and withdraw
if any one attributes good to them. They wonder how any one can believe that he is
wise from himself or does anything good from himself. Doing good for one’s own
sake they do not call good, because it is done from self. But doing good for the sake
of good they call good from the Divine; and this they say is the good that makes
heaven, because this good is the Lord. (§9)

‘28. Hacer el bien a tu enemigo puede ser obra de justicia y no es


arduo; amarlo, tarea de ángeles y no de hombres’ (1975a: 108) [‘To bless
thine enemy may be righteous and is not dif ficult: but to love him is a
task for angels, not for men’]. Many passages from Heaven and Hell testify
to the biblical entreaty to love thy neighbour, and that this, as with the
matter of mercy detailed above, is commonly misapprehended as a means
of garnering heavenly favour. The reader may consult paragraphs 13–20 for
Swedenborg’s lengthy account of  how true love of  the neighbour is an act
of such self lessness that, as Borges encapsulates in his brief maxim, only
the angels are truly capable of performing.
‘30. No acumules oro en la tierra, porque el oro es padre del ocio, y
éste, de la tristeza y el tedio’ (1975a: 108) [‘Lay not up for thyself  treasures
upon earth: for treasure is the father of idleness, and idleness of  boredom
and woe’]. Again this resonates strongly with Swedenborg’s highly unor-
thodox perspective on the church teaching that the rich man will not enter
heaven. The danger, as Swedenborg writes, is that the riches may constitute
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 217

a distraction from the true purpose, and that the rich man may become
tempted by the temptations of  the money system and so neglect his true
self. Borges writes in ‘Testigo’ that wealth is no obstacle for entrance into
heaven in Swedenborg’s theology, unless it is the cause of greed or sloth.
Wealth per se is unimportant. The full exposition of  this highly unorthodox
revelation appears throughout a series of paragraphs of  Heaven and Hell:

Out of a great deal of conversation and living with angels, I have been granted sure
knowledge that rich people enter heaven just as easily as poor people do, and that no
one is shut out of  heaven for having abundant possessions or accepted into heaven
because of poverty. There are both rich and poor people there, and many of  the rich
are in greater splendor and happiness than the poor. (§357)22 […] One person can
live like another in outward form. As long as there is an inward acknowledgment of 
the Deity and an intent to serve our neighbor, we can become rich, dine sumptu-
ously, live and dress as elegantly as befits our station and of fice, enjoy pleasures and
amusement, and meet our worldly obligations for the sake of our position and of our
business and of  the life of  both mind and body. So we can see that it is not as hard to
follow the path to heaven as many people believe. The only dif ficulty is finding the
power to resist love for ourselves and love of  the world and preventing those loves
from taking control, since they are the source of all our evils. (§359)

This sentiment is also ref lected in Borges’ maxim number 47: ‘Feliz el pobre
sin amargura o el rico sin soberbia’ (1975a: 110) [‘Happy is the poor man
without bitterness, and the rich man without arrogance’].
Whilst there are further proverbs that echo a Swedenborgian senti-
ment, it is perhaps of greatest worth to consider the final two proverbs
which, in their simplicity, evoke Swedenborg’s works with greatest power:
‘50. Felices los amados y los amantes y los que pueden prescindir del amor’
[‘Happy are the lovers and the loved, and they that can do without love’]. ‘51.
Felices los felices’ (1975a: 110) [‘Happy are the happy’]. Not only in Arcana
Cœlestia and Heaven and Hell, but importantly his work Conjugal Love,
Swedenborg goes to tremendous lengths to describe the nature of conjugal
love as being the terrestrial portion of divine love, and that true lovers may

22 This is the very passage that Borges and Bioy reproduce as ‘Los ricos en el cielo’ in
Libro del cielo y del infierno. Their brief passage is a composite of sentences from §357
and §361.
218 Chapter Five

remain together in the next world, a matter to which Borges pays atten-
tion in his essay ‘Testigo’. Beyond the matter of  lovers, Swedenborg’s entire
heavenly opus is dominated by a perpetual return to the idea of  happiness
as the ultimate state of divine love. Again, as with other matters described
above, there are innumerable passages in Heaven and Hell that describe the
happiness of the angels, the happiness of those souls that dwell in the angelic
realms, and the absence of  happiness for those who reside in the hellish
regions. Amidst detailed descriptions of  heavenly joy, Swedenborg writes
that ‘the angels have everything that is blessed, delightful, and happy, or that
which is called heavenly joy’ (§286); ‘Those that are in heaven are continu-
ally advancing towards the spring of  life, with a greater advance towards a
more joyful and happy spring the more thousands of years they live’ (§414).
We recall Borges in the poem ‘El remordimiento’: ‘He cometido el peor
de los pecados / que un hombre puede cometer. No he sido / feliz’ [‘I have
committed the worse sin of all / That a man can commit. I have not been /
happy’] (Burgin 1998: 140), and that in his many interviews he writes that
whilst sadness, loneliness and suf fering are the source of art, happiness is a
good in and of itself, and requires neither cause nor objective. Whilst we
would be exaggerating to claim that such a sentiment springs directly from
his reading of  Swedenborg, we can nevertheless determine that amidst so
many references to Swedenborg, so many allusions to his heavenly land-
scape, and so many ethical considerations that echo Swedenborg’s ethics,
we may determine a respectful thread concerning happiness that Borges
identifies in Swedenborg.
Such a presence of  Swedenborg is not limited to these two texts. Elogio
de la sombra contains another brief and wholly under-studied tale titled
‘His end and his beginning’ (the original title is in English), which relates
the activities of a man who has recently died and, in a manner reminis-
cent of many narratives in Heaven and Hell, begins a process of  learning
the nature of death. Following the Swedenborgian dimension, one must
first identify the curious relationship within the anonymous protagonist
between sleep and death. The tale begins: ‘Cumplida la agonía, ya solo, ya
solo y desgarrado y rechazado, se hundió en el sueño’ (1975a: 116) [‘After
death, after the wrench and the stark loneliness, he dropped into a deep
sleep’]. Swedenborg recounts in numerous passages of  Heaven and Hell
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 219

that discarnate spirits, like living people, wake and sleep and even dream
whilst asleep. Indeed, as with the living (as with Swedenborg himself ) the
dream of  the dead can constitute a journey of discovery into the realms
of  further mystery. ‘Some spirits who were not evil settled down into a
peaceful state, rather like sleep, and in this way were taken into heaven in
respect to the deeper levels of  their minds’ (§411).23 Whilst Swedenborg’s
narrative of  Melanchthon which Borges reproduced concerns a man whose
pride prevents his admission into heaven, in the brief  tale ‘His end and his
beginning’ the man is destined to heaven, yet is simply unable to compre-
hend this most cognitively challenging of matters. Now dead, he returns
to work and attempts to maintain the life that he had. Like Melanchthon,
however, the material objects surrounding him begin to evanesce and dis-
appear, whilst his former colleagues fail to perceive him.
One of  the most important matters of  this tale for our present analysis
is the matter of  the protagonist’s dreams. He is made aware that he is dead
through the sudden realisation ‘que no podía recordar las formas, los sonidos
y los colores de los sueños’ (1975a: 116) [‘that he was unable to recall the
shapes or sounds or colours of  his dreams’]. He is made suddenly aware that
his reality is now a dream. This immediately brings us back to the discussion
above about the nature of dream, vision and death. Swedenborg, again in
Heaven and Hell, recounts in many passages that whilst alive he has been
granted entry into the land of  the dead through dreams and visions, and
that the soul of  the dead, upon death, moves into the same dream landscape
that he may have experienced once alive. Indeed Swedenborg recounts in
§449 that his visions into the land of  the dead were of great profundity
precisely because his material body was capable of such inactivity (mini-
mal heartbeat and breath) that he ef fectively was both dead and dreaming.
Whilst on the one hand this evokes the metaphor that so intrigued Borges,
and which he identified in poets throughout the ages including, obviously,

23 Conan Doyle writes of  Swedenborg’s works: ‘Death was made easy by the presence
of celestial beings who helped the newcomer into his fresh existence. Such newcom-
ers had an immediate period of complete rest. They regained consciousness in a few
days of our time’ (2005: 100).
220 Chapter Five

Shakespeare and Calderón, that life is a dream,24 in this Swedenborgian


tale we may perceive an accompanying metaphor: that death is a dream.
The nature of  this dream/death world in which Borges’ protagonist finds
himself is further reinforced by the similarly Swedenborgian motif, also
present in ‘Un teólogo en la muerte’, that the narrator has been, during
this immediately post-death period, creating the world that surrounds
him: the of fice, the people, their faces. He understands, like Quiroga and
unlike Rosas, that he must move on: ‘De algún modo sintió que su deber
era dejar atrás esas cosas, ahora pertenecía a este nuevo mundo, ajeno de
pasado, de presente y de porvenir’ (1975a: 116) [‘Still, he somehow felt it his
duty to be rid of everything. He belonged to another world now, detached
from past, present, or future’]. This is a painful process, as it demands of 
him an abandonment of all that had constituted his identity once alive.
Again we recall how Rosas is wholly unable to relinquish being Rosas, as
Melanchthon cannot abandon being Melanchthon. Both are denied heaven.
Swedenborg describes in Heaven and Hell with numerous examples how
the angels, acting as psychopomps, assist the dead in adjusting to their new
environment and state, and that if  the individual resists with suf ficient force,
then eventually the angels will abandon this soul to his own demonic fate.
Angelic identity, in a manner that strangely evokes some of  Borges’ con-
cerns for the status of  the ‘I’ developed in ‘La nadería de la personalidad’,
‘Borges y yo’ and his lectures on Buddhism, is universal, not particular. At
the end of  the brief  tale, the man, having relinquished his past and his self,
has attained divine grace: ‘desde su muerte había estado siempre en el cielo’

24 ‘Cuando Shakespeare, por ejemplo, equipara la vida con un sueño, él, en lo que
insiste, es en la irrealidad de la vida, en el hecho de que es difícil fijar una diferencia
entre lo que soñamos y lo que vivimos. En cambio, en el caso de Calderón, creo que
la frase tiene un sentido teológico: la vida es sueño, en el sentido de que nuestra vida,
nuestra vigilia, no corresponden a la realidad, sino a una breve parte de la realidad, el
sentido de que lo verdadero son el cielo y el infierno’ (Sorrentino 2001: 133). [‘When
Shakespeare, for example, equates life with a dream, he refers to the unreality of  life,
in the fact that it is dif ficult to establish a division between what we dream and what
we live. With Calderón, on the other hand, I feel that the phrase Life is a dream has a
theological sense, in that our waking life does not correspond to reality, but to a brief
part of reality, the sense that heaven and hell are the true reality’] (My translation).
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 221

(1975a: 118) [‘from the moment of death he had been in heaven’]. ‘Diálogo
de muertos’ and ‘His end and his beginning’, therefore, can both be consid-
ered remarkably Swedenborgian, and published in the same volume, may
be considered synoptic treatments of  Swedenborg’s heterodox theological
perspective on the soul’s ability to choose his angelic or demonic environ-
ment. Rosas, like Melanchthon, chooses hell; the anonymous man of  the
other tale chooses heaven.

Conclusion

What I have hoped to demonstrate in this study of certain Borges texts is


the pervasive presence of  Swedenborg that informs the many narrative of
death and the afterlife. Whilst it would be remiss to af firm that these texts
are conscious reworkings or even respectful parodies of  Swedenborg’s text, it
can be established that Borges’ close and af fectionate reading of Swedenborg
provided essential substance for his own fictional world. Neither are such
matters limited to the few texts outlined above; throughout Borges’ works,
from the early essays to the Ficciones of  the 1940s, through to the later
essays, poems, fictions and interviews, Swedenborgian imagery, landscape
and, importantly, ethics, pervades Borges’ work. For example, few critical
studies have considered the curious academy of  heavenly students from
which the magician of  ‘Las ruinas circulares’ initially attempts to select his
future son. This perplexing image of concentric levels of studious discarnate
souls eager to be incarnated resembles the many perplexing descriptions
of communities of angels and spirits in Swedenborg’s Heaven and Hell.
The magician in this case clearly has the ability, like Swedenborg, to enter
this spiritual landscape through dreams and meditation in his quest for
progeny. In his later (and also under-studied) work Atlas, Borges presents
an uncanny episode in which he enters into dialogue with the dead soul
of  Haydée Lange through a dream vision, and decides not to reveal to
her that she is dead. In this case, the Borges narrator chooses not to act as
222 Chapter Five

psychopomp – that is to say he decides not to help her move further into
the heavenly realm – resolving, one would assume, that angelic guides
would perform that function.
One final text may be selected to draw to a close this chapter. The
text, entitled ‘Abramowicz’, from Borges’ final published volume before
his death, Los Conjurados, bears the hallmarks of  Swedenborg’s visions of 
the afterlife with which Borges was so familiar. I deem this text to be of
great importance for an understanding of  the whole of  Borges’ work, as
it can be seen to constitute a state of genuine revelation about the myster-
ies of death that do not stem from books but from immediate experience.
Through a Jamesian Radical Empiricist method, Borges, it would appear,
received confirmation about the persistence of  the soul after death that he
had read with such attention and for so many years in Swedenborg. Maurice
Abramowicz (1901–1981) was Borges’ friend from his youth in Geneva
with whom he maintained correspondence. In this brief piece (which he
describes to Amelia Barili)25 Borges becomes suddenly and delightedly
aware that his dead friend is still, in some way, present: ‘Esta noche, no
lejos de la cumbre de la colina de Saint Pierre, una valerosa y venturosa
música griega nos acaba de revelar que la muerte es más inverosímil que
la vida y que, por consiguiente, el alma perdura cuando su cuerpo es caos’
(1989: 467) [‘Tonight, not far from the top of  the hill of  Saint Pierre, a
courageous and happy Greek music has just revealed to us that death is
more implausible than life and that, therefore, the soul survives when its
body is chaos’].26 Borges intuits not only that his dead friend is still pre-
sent, but, like Swedenborg’s depiction of  the communities of discarnate
souls, he is surrounded by the souls of  the departed: ‘Contigo estaban las

25 ‘It was a beautiful night. María Kodama, Maurice Abramowicz’s widow and I were
at a Greek tavern in Paris, listening to Greek music, which is so full of courage. I
remembered the lyrics: “While this music lasts, we will deserve Helen of  Troy’s love.
While the music lasts, we will know that Ulysses will come back to Ithaca.” And I
felt that Maurice was not dead, that he was there with us, that nobody really dies,
for they all still project their shadow’ (Burgin 1998: 241).
26 Translation Frank Thomas Smith <http://www.southerncrossreview.org/47/abramo-
wicz.htm>.
The Inf luence of  Swedenborg on Borges 223

muchedumbres de las sombras que bebieron en la fosa ante Ulises y también


Ulises y también todos los que fueron o imaginaron los que fueron’ (1989:
467) [‘With you were the throngs of shadows who drank before Ulysses
in the grave and also Ulysses and also all who were and all those imagined
by those who were’] (trans. Smith). In tune with much of what we have
discussed in this chapter about the relationship between mystical vision
and imagination, it is important that neither Borges nor his companions
see Abramowicz as a fully present ghost, as some material entity on the
same plane of existence as them, but simply imagine him witness to their
gathering. This is thus further exploration of  the liminal space defined by
Corbin as imaginal, neither mere fantasy nor material reality, but a third
way in which imagination and reality are in some curious interrelation-
ship. Borges published this volume only months before his own death,
and it is therefore of great poetic beauty to read of  this wisdom that he
gains through his dead friend concerning the future joyous realm of death:
‘Esta noche me has dicho sin palabras, Abramowicz, que debemos entrar
en la muerte como quien entra en una fiesta’ (1989: 467) [‘Tonight you
have told me without words, Abramowicz, that we must enter death like
one who enters a party’] (trans. Smith). Again and again Borges would
have read in his beloved Swedenborg of  the persistence of  the soul, and
of  the joyous aspect of  the angelic communities. It would appear that sit-
ting at dinner with friends and good wine and evoking the memory of  his
dead friend, the words of  Swedenborg suddenly and rapturously rang true.
‘Estabas ahí, silencioso y sin duda sonriente, al percibir que nos asombraba
y maravillaba ese hecho tan notorio de que nadie puede morir’ (1989: 467)
[‘You were there, silent and no doubt smiling when you perceived that
we were amazed and marveled at the notorious fact that no one can die’]
(trans. Smith). If  this moment did, indeed, constitute an epiphanic reali-
zation of  Swedenborg’s teachings, then, as readers of  Swedenborg and of 
Borges, we may justifiably intuit that Borges and his friend Abramowicz
are now sitting together, conversing, as Borges decribes in ‘Elegía’, about
‘los dos sueños que se llamaron Laforgue y Baudelaire’ (1989: 466) [‘those
two dreams called Laforgue and Baudelaire’] (my translation) and merrily
engaging the angels in theological debates.
Conclusion – Confronting the shadow:
The hero’s journey in ‘El Etnógrafo’1

Artists are magical helpers. Evoking symbols and motifs that connect
us to our deeper selves, they can help us along the heroic journey of our
own lives.
— Joseph Campbell, Pathways to Bliss

An art that does not heal is not an art.


— Alejandro Jodorowsky, The Way of  the Tarot

I’ve always been a great reader of  Jung.


— Borges, Conversations with Jorge Luis Borges

Borges’ later fictions have received far less critical attention than his well-
known publications of  Ficciones (1944) and El Aleph (1949). Bell-Villada
(1999: 260), for example, dismisses El Informe de Brodie as ‘rather slight’,
suggesting that: ‘Because none of  the material in Dr. Brodie’s Report even
approaches the level of  the Ficciones or the stories in El Aleph, there is little
reason to discuss any one piece in detail’. The prose pieces of  Elogio de la
sombra and the tales of  El libro de arena and La Memoria de Shakespeare
are, with notable exceptions, often overlooked. This can be explained partly
by the enigmatic and at times pseudo-realist character of  these later fic-
tions, which may fail to evoke the labyrinthine complexity and literary
puzzles of  his earlier pieces. This to me is a scholarly oversight, as I feel that

1 An earlier version of  this conclusion was published as an article in Journal for Romance
Studies: ‘Confronting the Shadow: The Hero’s Journey in Borges’ “El Etnógrafo”’,
12/2 (summer 2012), 17–32. Many thanks to the journal editors for kind permission
to reproduce the text here.
226 Chapter Five

Borges’ later works – poetry, fiction, essays and interviews – demonstrate


a creative mind grappling with equal intensity with the philosophical and
metaphysical questions as his earlier work, only with a style that employs
fewer devices and strategies to catalyse the particular puzzle-solving detec-
tive faculty in the reader. An example of  this is the brief (just over 600
words) and deceptively simple tale ‘El Etnógrafo’ of  Elogio de la sombra,
which has received curiously little scholarly attention. Brevity in Borges
generally betrays deep currents, and a close reading of  this tale opens many
avenues implicit in the text. In particular, the tale embodies crucial elements
of  the hero’s journey as extensively examined by C. G. Jung, a journey that
analogizes the process of psychic healing expressed by Jung as Individuation.
In this final conclusive chapter I appraise ‘El Etnógrafo’ alongside other
fictions of  Borges that represent aspects of  the hero’s journey. In particular,
I evaluate the particular dynamics ref lected in the tale of  the stages of  the
journey as articulated by Jung scholar Joseph Campbell as the ‘Monomyth’,
which he observed in mythological tales across time and cultures: the sum-
mons away from home, the confrontation with the shadow, the dialogue
with the senex (wise old man) figure, the death and resurrection, the magi-
cal knowledge and the return home. Psychopathology, Jung argued, arises
commonly through an individual’s inability or unwillingness to assess the
distinction between ego and persona and to explore the ego’s relationship
with unconscious complexes and archetypal figures. The hero’s journey
thus expresses the ego’s inner journey into the unconscious to acknowledge
and integrate these areas which, through being ignored, block psychic
energy (libido), and being contemplated, release this energy. In this sense,
Murdock, the protagonist of  ‘El Etnógrafo’, can be analysed as engaging
in this process of psychic healing, gaining wisdom and a deeper under-
standing of  his own psyche. He can also be seen as embodying a collective
psyche that confronts a collective shadow and gains deeper understanding
of unconscious processes. This analysis corresponds to a larger project in
which I evaluate the shifting oeuvre of  Borges in the light of  Jung’s process
of individuation – the journey towards the self, often depicted in literature
and mythology as the hero’s journey. This is not, however, a psychoanalytical
appraisal of  the tale, rather it follows the amplification analysis customary
to Jung’s depth psychology which reveals an archetypal mythic pattern
Conclusion – Confronting the shadow: The hero’s journey in ‘El Etnógrafo’ 227

apparent within both ‘El Etnógrafo’ and other tales of  Borges. By such an
evaluation I hope to depict within the tale an implicit search for psychic
wholeness – the voyage into the unconscious and the confrontation with
the shadow – analogized by the hero’s journey.
There is a rich tradition in the Borges scholarship of  binding his work
to his biography through a psychoanalytical perspective, most notably
Freudian, but also, in the case of  Rodríguez Monegal (1978), through a
Lacanian and Kleinian lens. Characteristic of  the psychoanalytical reading
are the Oedipal, Narcissicistic and parricidal elements of  his life and work,
described by Rodríguez Monegal (1990: 129) in a later article: ‘Educated
by his father in the writer’s calling, he had practiced it as a son; in so doing
he avoided parricide. But on the death of  his father in 1938, and after an
accident on Christmas Eve of  the same year, Borges committed symbolic
suicide in order to conceal the parricide and to be free to begin writing his
most important fictions.’2 This interpretation, which Woodall described
as ‘an obsessively psychoanalytical view of  the man’ (1997: xxi), remains
inf luential, with parallel arguments concerning the failed writer-father, the
overbearing mother, the consequent troubled relationships with women
and the clues of  this dynamic implicit in the literary works, forming the
central narrative of  Williamson’s Borges: A life (2004). There are limita-
tions, however, to the psychoanalytical reading of  Borges, as it can limit
the artistic creation to a mere cipher of this dominant Freudian dynamic of
psychological trauma. This is highlighted by Earle (2000: 100) in his review
of  the starkly Freudian analysis by Woscoboinik (1998): ‘In this psycho-
portrait our model is cornered by the ghosts of  Oedipus and Narcissus –
the mother-obsession and the self-obsession, that is – and never escapes.’
Furthermore, Borges himself was critical of  Freudian psychoanalytical

2 Molloy (1994: 78) questions whether Borges was consciously alluding to Freud
in his examination of das unheimlich – the uncanny – in his review of  Beckford’s
Vathek. Tcherepashenets (2008) approaches Borges’ interest in dreams in relation to
Freud’s dream analysis. de Costa (2000: 47) appraises the humour in ‘Death and the
Compass’ in light of  Freud’s Jokes and their Relation to the Unconscious. A number
of articles, such as Portugal M. Saliba (2001), also appraise Borges through a variety
of psychoanalytical perspectives.
228 Chapter Five

analyses establishing too rigid a bond between artistic creativity and child-
hood, family and sexuality. His scathing comments to Burgin about Freud’s
obsession are well known:

I think of [Freud] as a kind of madman, no? A man laboring over a sexual obsession.
Well, perhaps he didn’t take it to heart. Perhaps he was just doing it as a kind of game.
I tried to read him, and I thought of  him either as a charlatan or as a madman, in a
sense. After all, the world is far too complex to be boiled down to that all-too-simple
scheme. (Burgin 1969: 109)3

His views of  Freud chime closely with those that Jung expressed later in
his life concerning Freud’s obsessive desire to maintain his theories of
sexuality,4 and, indeed, in the same interview Borges expressed his respect
for Jung: ‘Jung I have read far more widely than Freud, but in Jung you feel
a wide and hospitable mind’ (Burgin 1969: 109). Borges was an engaged
reader of  Jung, citing his work on numerous occasions.5 However, his

3 Borges jokingly called Freud ‘not my favourite fiction writer’ (Barnstone 2000: 111),
and Jason Wilson reminds us that Borges was ‘as anti-Marxism or anti-pyschoanalysis
(merely gossip) as he was anti-Hitler’ (2006: 119). Kristal remarks on the irony that
Borges presented a lecture on Spinoza 1981 at the Freudian School of  Buenos Aires,
‘given his skepticism about Freud, and his sometimes disparaging remarks about
psychoanalysis’ (2002: 144).
4 ‘There was no mistaking the fact that Freud was emotionally involved in his sexual
theory to an extraordinary degree. When he spoke of it, his tone became urgent,
almost anxious, and all signs of  his normally critical and skeptical manner vanished.
A strange, deeply moved expression came over his face, the cause of which I was
at a loss to understand. I had a strong intuition that for him sexuality was a sort
of numinosum’ ( Jung 1989: 150). ‘When, then, Freud announced his intention of
identifying theory and method and making them into some kind of dogma, I could
no longer collaborate with him; there remained no choice for me but to withdraw’
( Jung 1989: 167).
5 Some notable examples of  his references to Jung, in particular to Psychologie und
Alchemie, are: ‘Nota sobre Walt Whitman’ (1974: 249–53), ‘Nathaniel Hawthorne’
(1974: 670–85), ‘Kafka y sus Precursores’ (1974: 710–12), ‘El Verdugo Piadoso’, of 
Nueve Ensayos Dantescos (1989: 357–9), ‘Los Conjurados’, of  Los Conjurados (1989:
501), ‘William Beckford. Vathek’ (2005: 533), and El Libro de los Seres Imaginarios.
He also refers to Jung in many interviews.
Conclusion – Confronting the shadow: The hero’s journey in ‘El Etnógrafo’ 229

familiarity with Jung’s works should not be considered here as grounds for
perceiving a necessary Jungian inf luence on his writings, such as one might
find, for example, a conscious inf luence of  Freud upon certain Dadaist art-
ists. Rather I hope to demonstrate that the archetypal narrative of  the Hero,
as indicated by Jung and illustrated by Campbell, is apparent in Borges’ art
as it is apparent in dreams, myths and art across time and culture.

‘El Etnógrafo’6

In a customary fashion, Borges author and Borges narrator are conf lated


in the opening lines of  the tale: ‘El caso me lo refieron’ (1975a: 46) [‘This
story was told me’], and the narrative is located in the temporal and spatial
distance. In this way, as with many of  the tales of  El Informe de Brodie, it is
given a mythological, timeless dimension by the implication of anecdote,
suggesting that the narrator Borges is not author but mere storyteller
recounting a tale that he was told some time ago, the events of which took
place even further ago. This is an important aspect of  this and other tales,
as the narrative assumes a collective nature, becoming the creation not
of a lone artist, but of  tradition. Pursuing this avenue, one can perceive
the protagonist of  the tale as everyman, embodying aspects of a collec-
tive psyche in addition to that of  the author. This is at once visible in ‘El
Etnógrafo’ both in the fact that Murdock is also the thousands of charac-
ters ‘visibles e invisibles, vivos y muertos’ (1975a: 46) [‘seen and unseen,
living and dead’], and by the fact that Murdock is depicted with only the
barest of defining characteristics. He is credulous and naïve, unquestion-
ing of authority, harbouring an underdeveloped critical faculty which
would prohibit him from engaging in any philosophical, metaphysical
or psychological exploration. Murdock’s ingenuous character dramatizes
the radicality of  his transformation during the narrative, positioning the

6 Di Giovanni translates the tale as ‘The Anthropologist’.


230 Chapter Five

initial lack of consciousness against the later position of  heightened con-
sciousness. Jung depicts this character type as in ignorance of  the uncon-
scious and consequently living in peril of neurotic fear of  the unknown:
‘A man who is unconscious of  himself acts in a blind, instinctive way and
is in addition fooled by all the illusions that arise when he sees everything
that he is not conscious of in himself coming to meet him from outside as
projections’ (1983: 335). This state of passivity sets the scene for the devel-
opment of ego-consciousness in relation to the unconscious, a process
analogized in the journey of  the hero. Whilst numerous passages of  Jung’s
extensive work elucidate this psychic process, it is summarized cogently by
Joseph Campbell as the prototypical sequence of steps pursued by mythic
heroes across time and cultures, illustrated dramatically in The Hero with
a Thousand Faces (1949). Campbell borrowed the term ‘monomyth’ from
Joyce’s Finnegans Wake to describe this process: ‘A hero ventures forth from
the world of common day into a region of supernatural wonder: fabulous
forces are there encountered and a decisive victory is won: the hero comes
back from this mysterious adventure with the power to bestow boons on
his fellow man’ (1949: 30). Importantly, through his passivity, Murdock
embodies a collective ego that is likewise not in tune with the deeper
dimensions of  the unconscious. This becomes apparent when Murdock
leaves the security of  home and its nurturing environment and plunges
into the unknown represented by the prairie.
The narrator reveals that one of  Murdock’s ancestors had died in hos-
tility with the Indians and that ‘esa antigua discordia de sus estirpes era un
vínculo ahora’ (1975a: 46) [‘this old family bloodshed was now a link’]. A
link to what? The relationship here is immediately apparent with Borges
and his ancestral heritage (Williamson 2004: 24), and as such Murdock
confronts a personal shadow in the guise of ancestral strife, and his trip
to the prairie could indicate a step towards redemption or vindication of 
this historical enmity. Murdock certainly prepares himself  for such an
encounter, aware that in order to learn the language of  ‘los hombres rojos’
(1975a: 46) [‘the red men’] he would need to be accepted by them: ‘Previó,
sin duda, las dificultades que lo aguardaban; tenía que lograr que los hom-
bres rojos lo aceptaran como unos de los suyos’ (1975a: 46) [‘No doubt he
foresaw the dif ficulties that were in store for him; he would have to do his
Conclusion – Confronting the shadow: The hero’s journey in ‘El Etnógrafo’ 231

best to get the red men to accept him as one of  them’]. Murdock is also
symbolically bound to the Indians by the curious facial description of  ‘de
perfil de hacha’ (1975a: 46) [‘hatchet face’], which evokes the mythologized
Native American hatchet.
Amplifying Murdock to the embodiment of collective psyche, how-
ever, his experience expresses a collective confrontation with the traditional
‘other’ represented by the Indians. Campbell describes this archetypal
encounter and its significance:

There’s a lot in you that’s neither being carried into this persona system nor into
your ego, as part of what you perceive as ‘you.’ Just opposite to the ego, buried in
the unconscious, is what Jung calls the shadow. […] The nature of your shadow is a
function of  the nature of your ego. It is the backside of your light side. In the myths,
the shadow is represented as the monster that has to be overcome, the dragon. It is
the dark thing that comes up from the abyss and confronts you the minute you begin
moving down into the unconscious. It is the thing that scares you so that you don’t
want to go down there. (2004: 73)

Two streams are developing together, therefore: Murdock as individual con-


fronting his personal shadow tied to his ancestry; and Murdock as westerner
confronting the shadow of  the Indian. Jung wrote plentifully about the
conf lict between westerners and indigenous Americans as a projection of 
the European shadow content upon the radical ‘other’. Projection implies
lack of conscious awareness of such a process, and thus the Indian who
is labelled savage and barbarous ref lects the savage and barbarous nature
of  the European/American: ‘I have frequently observed in the analysis
of  Americans that the inferior side of  the personality, the “shadow”, is
represented by a Negro or Indian’ (1956: 183). Jung perceives in individual
psyches the centuries-old conf lict across the Americas concerning civili-
zation and barbarism, a debate repeatedly ref lected in Borges’ writing. It
is important to note that I am not embarking on a fresh evaluation of  the
matter of civilization and barbarism in Borges, primarily because such a
complex issue requires a deep assessment of  Borges’ relationship with his
soldier ancestors, his depiction of  the caudillo Rosas, his interpretation
of  Martín Fierro, gauchos, Indians, knife-fighters and hoodlums, Perón
and Evita, the Third Reich, communism, hippies (see Guibert in Burgin
232 Chapter Five

1998: 51), and the military junta of  the Dirty War. The conf licting polari-
ties of civilization and barbarism are ref lected in his appreciation or dis-
like of novelists and poets, philosophies, theologies and cosmologies, and
in his interpretation of such philosophical dialectics as William James’
‘tough-minded’ or ‘tender-minded’, Jung’s shadow complex, or Nietzsche’s
articulation of  the cosmopolitan Apollonian and the barbarian Dionysian.
The debate is central to the Argentine national character and is central to
Borges and his readership. For wider analysis see: Balderston (1993), Ulla
(2002), Williamson (2004), and Orrego Arismendi (2007).
Importantly for Borges, however, the time-worn debate evoked in
the sixteenth century by Las Casas and Sepúlveda and rearticulated by
Sarmiento cannot be reduced to a simple binary. As indicated by the enu-
meration above, barbarism is visible in Borges’ work in many guises beyond
the mythical Indian, and indeed constitutes an essential characteristic of 
the individual psyche. In this way one can see Dahlmann’s journey into the
unconscious in the tale ‘El Sur’ [‘The South’] leading him to confrontation
with his shadow projection, the gauchos. In this tale the gaucho represents
the brutish opposite of  Dahlmann – uncultured, instinctive, dealing not
with abstraction but tangible reality – but also, conversely, what Dahlmann
most desires. Such an interpretation is reinforced by the idea that Borges
himself supported, that Dahlmann’s whole adventure into the pampa was
a dream, and hence a compensatory vision of unconscious desire.7 The
integration of  the shadow, in this case through the ritual death with the
assistance of  the senex figure who throws him the knife, is one of compen-

7 ‘It [“The South”] can be read in two ways. You may read it in a straightforward way
and you may think that those things happen to a hero. Then, you may think there’s
a kind of moral behind it – the idea that he loved the south and in the end the south
destroyed him. But there’s another possibility, the possibility of  the second half of 
the story which is hallucination. When the man is killed, he’s not really killed. He
died in the hospital, and though that was a dream, a kind of wishful thinking, that
was the kind of death he would have liked to have – in the pampas with a knife in
his hand being stabbed to death. That was what he was looking forward to all the
time. So I’ve written that story in order that it would be read both ways’ (in Burgin
1998: 8).
Conclusion – Confronting the shadow: The hero’s journey in ‘El Etnógrafo’ 233

sation, and brings about symbolic psychic wholeness. Similarly, in the tale
of  Brodie ‘El evangelio según Marcos’ [‘The Gospel according to Mark’],
the protagonist Espinosa and the rustic Gutre family (who themselves are
of  ‘civilized’ Scottish ancestry) enact a symbolic union of compensation –
the civilized embodying the barbarous and vice versa – through Espinosa’s
ritual crucifixion. The ‘indio de ojos celestes’ [‘Indian with blue eyes’] of ‘El
cautivo’ [‘The Captive’] is both barbarous and civilized, unable to remain
rooted to one polarity. Lastly, as Bell-Villada (1999: 158–9) discusses, the
tale of  ‘Historia del guerrero y de la cautiva’ [‘Story of  the Warrior and the
Captive’] concerns the double characterization of  the Lombard barbarian
warrior who becomes civilized and the civilized Englishwoman who turns
savage, but also the pairing of  the cautivas – the Englishwoman and Borges’
grandmother, one civilized one savage, both captive; and consequently the
double guerrero – Droctulf and Colonel Borges. These multiple and subtle
pairings in Borges’ fiction evoke a strongly Jungian alchemical vision of 
the twin polarities within each individual psyche: light and dark, civilized
and barbarous, ego and shadow.
It is interesting to note that both Jung and Borges were fascinated by
Stevenson’s tale Strange Case of  Dr Jekyll and Mr Hyde (1886), Jung equat-
ing Mr Hyde with our shadow (Fordman 1953: 49), Borges acknowledging
that his tales ‘Borges y yo’, and ‘El otro’ were adaptations of  Stevenson’s tale
(Borges 1982: 166), and that ‘Las ruinas circulares’ was a retelling of  his tale
‘El Golem’, which itself  follows Wilde’s Picture of  Dorian Gray, which itself
was a retelling of  Jekyll and Hyde (Barnstone 1982: 82). In brief, therefore,
Borges repeatedly evokes the confrontation with the barbarous other,
often depicted as fetch, doppelgänger, gaucho, Indian or knife-fighter,
who evokes a powerful psychic drive within the ‘civilized’ protagonists and
whose integration is often evoked by a ritual death. Borges’ position is strik-
ingly akin to Jung’s in this perspective, and importantly can be understood
within a framework of  the process of individuation, the journey towards
psychic wholeness. Just as Dahlmann integrates the shadow of  the barba-
rous in his journey south, so Jung writes of  the ‘savage’ or the ‘primitive’
within us whose integration likewise propels the individual or the collec-
tive towards wholeness: ‘Indeed, for a wide-awake person, the primitive
contents may often prove to be a source of renewal’ (1993: 195). And just
234 Chapter Five

as Borges recognized the cult of violence that lay within his psyche hidden
beneath layers of  language, literature and culture, so Jung recounts in his
memoirs a ‘primitive’ figure who appeared in a dream and who led him to
conclude that: ‘The small, brown-skinned savage who accompanied me
[…] was an embodiment of  the primitive shadow’ (1989: 181).
Murdock endures the arduous separation from home, friends, family,
customs and even his language over his two-year encampment on the
plains. He confronts a deeper aspect of  the ‘barbarous’ shadow, both on
a personal and collective level, with the great challenge to the deep-set
epistemological certainties that his culture had instilled in him: ‘llegó a
pensar de una manera que su lógica rechazaba’ (1975a: 48) [‘he came to see
things in a way his reason rejected’]. This is the result of  his many months
of apprenticeship, his dialogue with the tribal ‘sacerdote’ [‘medicine man’],
his rigorous moral and physical exercises and his awakening understanding
of  the language of dreams. It is at this level that the most profound trans-
formation occurs with Murdock, discernible in his realization that ‘en las
noches de luna llena soñaba con bisontes’ (1975a: 48) [‘on nights when the
moon was full he dreamed of  bison’].8 This insight, which he relays to the
medicine man, signifies the conclusion of  his sojourn on the prairie and he
returns home. Importantly, Murdock has engaged on the hero’s journey – a
narrative encountered in countless myths (Campbell) and dreams ( Jung)
– allegorizing the journey inward into the unconscious (Campbell 2004:
111–33). Having heeded the herald (his professor) and headed out to the
prairie, having undergone trials and training, he encounters in his dreams
the tribe’s totem animal, the bison. The bison represents another shadow
projection of  Western history, as they were slaughtered en masse during
the final decades of  the nineteenth century in order to drive the nomadic
tribes into the reservations and make way for cattle. Campbell explored the
importance of  the buf falo in Native American myths, discussing the impact
of  the slaughter in depth with Bill Moyers: ‘That was a sacramental viola-
tion. […] The frontiersmen shot down whole herds, taking only the skins

8 Di Giovanni mistakenly translates ‘bisontes’ as ‘mustang’. I am unable to determine


how that mistake arose.
Conclusion – Confronting the shadow: The hero’s journey in ‘El Etnógrafo’ 235

to sell and leaving the bodies there to rot. That was a sacrilege. It turned
the buf falo from a “thou” to an “it”’ (Campbell 1988: 78).9 The slaughter
of  the bison was not simply a strategy to assist ethnic translocation; it was
also, as Campbell observes, an attempt to erase the animal nature from
within the Euro-American psyche, concomitant with a refusal to acknowl-
edge the shadow. Jung intuited that such acts of extreme aggression arose
from a fear of  the unconscious content: ‘When I see a man in a savage rage
with something outside himself, I know that he is, in reality, wanting to
be savage toward his own unconscious self ’ (1993: 16). Murdock has thus
passed through a threshold from one mythic order represented by ‘razón’
[‘reason’] and ‘ciencia’ [‘science’] into another represented by dreams, the
full moon and the totem animal.
Everything has changed for Murdock. He had set out on the adventure
at the behest of  the professor in order to study indigenous languages and
later to present the thesis. After radical separation from home and a new
vision of reality, he returns home and, like the captive of  the eponymous
tale, he feels homesick for the prairie. He returns to the professor and
informs him that he will not present the thesis. What has changed? There
are many aspects to this question. Firstly, on an individual basis, Murdock
has atoned for his ancestor who died in a skirmish with the Indians. This
family lineage is symbolic of a collective need to atone for the brutality of
colonialism. However, the tale is not a discourse in postcolonialism, and
atonement for colonialism is a loose interpretation. Murdock has learned
to harken to his dreams. Here the aesthetics of  Borges and the psychol-
ogy of  Jung come together in harmony. A central pillar of  Jung’s entire
life’s work rests on the importance of dreams, in brief, as messages from
the unconscious:

9 Campbell also quotes the famous 1852 letter Chief  Seattle wrote to the US President:
‘Your destiny is a mystery to us. What will happen when the buf falo are all slaugh-
tered? The wild horses tamed? What will happen when the secret corners of  the
forest are heavy with the scent of many men and the view of  the ripe hills is blotted
by talking wires? Where will the thicket be? Gone! Where will the eagle be? Gone!
And what is it to say goodbye to the swift pony and the hunt? The end of  living and
the beginning of survival’ (1988: 34).
236 Chapter Five

In the end, we have to ask what the aim of  the dream is from a teleological point of
view. Why does this person’s unconscious wish to show him an image like that? […]
The dream is a product of  the imagination, a gallery of images, images of protection
from some blow that is threatening; the function of  the dream is to compensate the
conscious attitude. I believe that what dreams show us in vivid and impressive images
are our vulnerable points. (1993: 143)

Dreams are cognate with the epistemological value of active imagination


and are the fundamental portal for an exploration of  the unconscious;
they manifest archetypal images and mythic narratives; are habitual fac-
tors of synchronicity and as such can operate outside of ego-consciousness,
time and space; are pertinent to the psychic and physiological state of  the
individual; and consequently are of absolute importance for the process
of psychic healing.

It is in our dreams that the body makes itself aware to our mind. The dream is in large
part a warning of something to come. The dream is the body’s best expression, in the
best possible symbol it can express, that something is going wrong. The dream calls
our mind’s attention to the body’s instinctive feeling. If man doesn’t pay attention
to these symbolic warnings of  his body he pays in other ways. A neurosis is merely
the body’s taking control, regardless of  the conscious mind. (1993: 49)

Borges, as I argued in Chapter Two, likewise pays attention to dreams, rec-


ognizing their importance in his own literary production, observing their
perennial importance in artistic creativity across cultures, puzzling over their
oblique relationship with linear time, and acknowledging that they reveal
much of  the psychic state of  the individual. Borges refers to Jung’s deep
analysis into dream symbolism, suggesting in ‘El verdugo piadoso’ [‘The
Pitying Torturer’] (one of  the Nueve Ensayos Dantescos) that ‘La segunda
[conjetura] equipara, según la doctrina de Jung, las invenciones literarias
a las invenciones oníricas’ (1989: 357) [‘The second conjecture, following
the doctrine of  Jung, equates literary and oneiric inventions’] (2000: 284).
This equation of  literary and dream creativity is a constant throughout
Borges’ work, and indeed, like Jung, attention to dreams and nightmares
Conclusion – Confronting the shadow: The hero’s journey in ‘El Etnógrafo’ 237

forms a mainstay of  his philosophical discourse.10 ‘Los sueños son una obra
estética, quizá la expresión estética más antigua. Toma una forma extraña-
mente dramática’ (1989: 231) [‘Dreams are an aesthetic work, perhaps the
most ancient aesthetic expression. They take a strangely dramatic form’]
(1984: 40). Borges places a strong epistemological value on the dreamworld
and the aesthetic, and innumerable passages testify to the power of dreams
to grant the dreamer knowledge of deeper aspects of  the self and further
panoramas of  landscapes and times. Dreams are crucial, both for Borges
and for Jung, in pursuing the path towards psychic well-being.
Murdock has thus travelled deep into the unknown, and has released
the powerful psychic energy represented by the dream of  the bison. This
is the energy of  healing, the vital force that is essential to the shaman in
tribal societies and was essential for Jung. The medicine man himself would
have had to walk the similar path of physical and psychological separation,
arduous training and attention to dreams prior to gaining the power to
heal. Such a process of  trauma is documented in the literature concern-
ing shamanism (Eliade 1972, Halifax 1982, McKenna 1991), encapsulated
by Campbell: ‘In primal societies, the shaman provides a living conduit
between the local and the transcendent. The shaman is one who has actu-
ally gone through a psychological crack-up and recovery’ (2004: xviii). In
this respect, the medicine man acts as psychoanalyst for Murdock, guiding
him on his exploration of  the unconscious, supporting him in the darkness.
So strong is that association between shaman and doctor that Campbell’s
explanation of it deserves quoting in full:

Psychoanalysis, the modern science of reading dreams, has taught us to take heed
of  these unsubstantial images. Also it has found a way to let them do their work.
The dangerous crises of self-development are permitted to come to pass under the
protecting eye of an experienced initiate in the lore and language of dreams, who
then enacts the role and character of  the ancient mystagogue, or guide of souls, the
initiating medicine man of  the primitive forest sanctuaries of  trial and initiation.

10 Borges, whilst recognizing the importance of dreams in psychology, is critical of what


he feels is scant attention to nightmares: ‘I have read many books on dreams, volumes
of psychology, but I never found anything interesting on nightmares’ (Barnstone
1982: 7).
238 Chapter Five

The doctor is the modern master of  the mythological realm, the knower of all the
secret ways and words of potency. His role is precisely that of  the Wise Old Man of 
the myths and fairy tales whose words assist the hero through the trials and terrors
of  the weird adventure. He is the one who appears and points to the magic shining
sword that will kill the dragon-terror, tells of  the waiting bride and the castle of many
treasures, applies healing balm to the almost fatal wounds, and finally dismisses the
conqueror, back into the world of normal life, following the great adventure into
the enchanted night. (1949: 9–10)

Murdock returns home radically transformed from the naïve and uncriti-
cal student that he was prior to his voyage of discovery, and informs his
professor that he intends not to publish. This interchange – also a symbolic
confrontation – is of particular importance for an understanding of  the
psychological processes of  the narrative. Murdock has changed but the acad-
emy has not. He has activated a powerful force of psychic energy through
his journey, and yet the wisdom gained lies beyond the strict measures of
academic discourse. His professor is visibly displeased with this judgement
and snidely alludes to the fact that Murdock has abandoned his culture
and language, that he has gone native. But Murdock does not intend to
return to the prairie; he has integrated the psychic force represented by
the shadow figures of  the Indian and the bison, and has returned to his
cultural home. The westerner, Jung argued, cannot pretend that his roots
lie elsewhere and that his psychic constitution is other than its particular
cultural formation. Jung, perhaps problematically from our twenty-first
century outlook, perceived certain people, such as the Taos Pueblo Indians
or the eastern Africans, operating with a more direct, unconscious and
less ego-orientated psychic structure than the Europeans ( Jung 1989). He
consequently advised against an abandonment of  the ‘storm-lantern of 
the ego’ (Von Franz 1975: 41), not allowing it to be engulfed in the dark
seas of  the unconscious. For this reason, as documented in his memoirs,
he broke up a festive nocturnal drum and dance ceremony in the Sudan
as he felt threatened by the overwhelming forces of unconscious energy:
‘At that time I was obviously all too close to “going black”’ (1989: 271);11

11 ‘I was not to recognize the real nature of this disturbance until some years later, when
I stayed in tropical Africa. It had been, in fact, the first hint of  “going black under
Conclusion – Confronting the shadow: The hero’s journey in ‘El Etnógrafo’ 239

and, as Schlamm (2010) discusses, he was unwilling to meet Hindu gurus


whilst on his trip to India in 1938, erroneously believing them to advocate
ego abandonment. This also explains his fears over the use of psychedelic
drugs (Von Franz 1971: 41). Murdock has not turned his back on his cul-
ture, nor has he abandoned ego-consciousness, but has chosen to return
with the shadow energy fully integrated. The hero must always return.
Here a further dynamic is established between Murdock’s journey and
the process of individuation. Borges, as established, was a close reader of 
William James (as was his father and Macedonio Fernández). In particular,
Borges’ evaluation of mysticism owes much to the four characteristics of
mystical states articulated by James in Varieties (1902: 380): inef fability,
noetic quality, transiency and passivity. Borges’ reading of  Angelus Silesius,
Meister Eckhart, Emmanuel Swedenborg and Blake (all of whom Jung
also read) demonstrates his employment of  these four terms in navigating
the ontologically challenging texts. His own two mystical experiences, as
I analysed in Chapter Two, furthermore, conform to these characteristics.
The noetic and the inef fable are of crucial importance in our evalua-
tion of  Murdock’s experience, as he has acquired wisdom, yet is unable to
express it in arid academic prose that lacks the vocabulary of  the experi-
ence. Murdock, like Borges, experienced something mystical, noetic yet
inef fable, instructive yet beyond language. This has a further relationship
with Jung, for whom the process of individuation – the hero’s journey –
will constellate archetypal images which are endowed with numinosity. In
a 1945 letter, Jung accredits his work as a medical doctor as healing through
the numinous – a potent statement that binds him with the shamans and
medicine men of  tribal cultures:

I know it is exceedingly dif ficult to write anything definite or descriptive about the


progression of psychological states. It always seemed to me as if  the real milestones
were certain symbolic events characterized by a strong emotional tone. You are quite
right, the main interest of my work is not concerned with the treatment of neuroses
but rather with the approach to the numinous. But the fact that the approach to the

the skin,” a spiritual peril which threatens the uprooted European in Africa to an
extent not fully appreciated’ ( Jung 1989: 245).
240 Chapter Five

numinous is the real therapy and inasmuch as you attain to the numinous experi-
ences you are released from the curse of pathology. Even the very disease takes on a
numinous character. ( Jung, in Hollis and Rosen 2003: 120)

Within Jung’s dynamic process, therefore, one cannot separate healing


from the numinous, or, as Campbell expresses it, healing is made possible
by becoming ‘transparent to the transcendent’ (2004: xvii). Thus Murdock’s
journey and the revelation it af fords him is a voyage of  healing. But what
was Murdock’s (psycho)pathology prior to his journey? Here, as described
above, it is important to consider Murdock embodying a collective psyche.
In response to his professor, Murdock declares that ‘la ciencia, nuestra
ciencia, me parece una mera frivolidad’ (1975a: 48) [‘science – our science
– seems not much more than a trif le’]. Whilst on the prairie, ‘llegó a pensar
de una manera que su lógica rechazaba’ (1975a: 48) [‘he came to see things
in a way his reason rejected’]. Logic and science, the quintessence of  the
western dream of civilization, led Murdock’s ancestor to die fighting the
Indians, and led his collective ancestors to slaughter the buf falo and herd
the Indians into reservations. Logic and science deny the epistemological
value and validity of  fantasy, imagination, mythology and the dreamworld,
the very lifeblood of  the Indian community with whom Murdock resides
and the very source of  Borges’ and Jung’s aesthetic and psychological pro-
ject. The numinous is taboo, and nowhere more than the university; and
the professor is the stalwart representative of  his institution.
Murdock’s professor advised him to head out to the prairie and to
observe the rites and ‘que descubriera el secreto que los brujos revelan al
iniciado’ (1975a: 46) [‘to uncover the medicine man’s secret’],12 an eccen-
tric research proposal for one studying ‘lenguas indígenas’ [‘aboriginal
languages’]. He is then irked by Murdock’s later decision not to publish.
Orrego Arismendi, one of the few scholars to have scrutinized ‘El Etnógrafo’,
suggests that the professor is a likely analogue of  Borges, ‘ansioso por saber
lo que pasa por la mente nativa como solo podría estarlo el mismo Borges’
(2007: 49) [‘eager, like Borges himself, to know what goes through the
native mind’] (my translation), owing primarily to his thirst to know these

12 Di Giovanni’s translation is here also imprecise.


Conclusion – Confronting the shadow: The hero’s journey in ‘El Etnógrafo’ 241

hidden secrets. This is a possible interpretation, if, for example, we correlate


it to Borges’ desire whilst in Japan to examine his own mystical experi-
ences with Shinto monks. However, another angle would be to view the
professor, ‘un hombre entrado en años’ (1975a: 46) [‘a man getting along
in years’], as one who has failed to engage in the process of individuation,
nevertheless knowing that something is missing that he wishes to recover.
Like the bride-snatcher depicted by Campbell (2004: 118), he is unwilling
to venture on the journey himself; or, like the mythical King Mark, who
entrusts Tristan to bring back his bride Iseult, unconsciously willing that
Tristan does fall in love with her; or King Arthur, who unwittingly invites
Lancelot and Guinevere to love, the professor seeks to seize the treasure
by proxy, all the while unconsciously resigned to the understanding that
the journey is the treasure. Murdock tells him as much: ‘El secreto, por
lo demás, no vale lo que valen los caminos que me condujeron a él. Esos
caminos hay que andarlos’ (1975a: 48) [‘The secret, I should tell you, is
not as valuable as the steps that brought me to it. Those steps have to be
taken, not told’]. Murdock here acts the same role as Bjarni Thorkelsson in
Borges’ tale ‘Undr’, who, when exhorted by the narrator to reveal the secret
word, declines, stating that: ‘He jurado no revelarla. Además, nadie puede
enseñar nada. Debes buscarla solo’ (1989: 50) [‘I have sworn not to divulge
it. Besides, nobody can teach anything. You must find it out for yourself ’]
(1979: 61). The professor’s psychic state corresponds to that described by
Jung as exhibiting critical conf lation of ego and persona and a pathological
denial of unconscious content (see, for example, his essay ‘Does the World
Stand on the Verge of a Spiritual Rebirth?’ [1993: 67–76]). The professor
represents the state of psychic disharmony that would be harmonized by
the journey of  the hero – the process of individuation – and as such his
character is crucial for an understanding of  the development of  the tale.
Murdock is empowered by his experience. He has undergone a physi-
cal and spiritual adventure, has encountered the shadow, has learned from
the senex, has experienced the numinous, and has returned enriched. And
his adventure does not end there; the final words of  the tale can be inter-
preted as his experience of  the anima (for explanation of animus/a see Kast
2006) in the figure of  his wife; and, as with the shadow figure, he assimi-
lates rather than becomes this figure, symbolized by divorce. He then finds
242 Chapter Five

work in the library, a location depicted symbolically by Borges as the vault


of  human memory and knowledge, and thus Murdock inhabits a psychic
state representing perennial wisdom.
Murdock’s journey thus constitutes an archetypal voyage of  the hero,
illustrated in its perennial stages by Campbell’s Monomyth. In this way this
tale and other tales of  Borges reveal an unconscious prevailing force towards
psychic wholeness, towards the self. It is at this level that Borges as poet/
author can be traced along the pathway of individuation, seeking the elusive
centre of  the mandala-labyrinth. Importantly for this book, however, is the
evocation both by Jung as psychologist and Borges as artist of a dynamic
process that underscores an individual’s search for selfhood and knowledge,
described by Jung as individuation, and depicted by Borges as the search
for God, the ‘god in the making’ (Burgin 1998: 209, 241; Barnstone 1982:
109), his poem ‘Elogio de la sombra’: ‘Llego a mi centro, / a mi algebra y mi
clave, / a mi espejo’ (1975a: 126) [‘I reach my center, / my algebra and my
key, / my mirror’], or his perennial search for the true identity of  ‘Borges’.
Such a process is portrayed in numerous tales and poems and is ref lected
in his reading matter, such as Sufi mystics, Swedenborg and Dante. ‘El
Etnógrafo’, an understudied tale, exhibits characteristics germane to the
hero’s journey, a quest for knowledge integral to a process of  healing. What
Murdock learns out in the desert heals his soul. And what does he learn?
We must go to the desert to find out.
Bibliography

Borges, Jorge Luis,


——Silvina Ocampo & Adolfo Bioy Casares, eds, Antologia de la Literatura Fantástica
(Buenos Aires, Sudamericana, 1940).
—— Other Inquisitions, 1937–1952 (New York: Washington Square Press, 1964).
—— and Margarita Guerrero, El libro de los seres imaginarios (Buenos Aires: Emecé,
1967).
——Dreamtigers, Mildred Boyer and Harold Morland, trans. (New York: E. P. Dutton,
1970).
—— The Aleph and Other Stories, 1933–1969, Norman Thomas di Giovanni, ed. and
trans. (New York: Dutton, 1971a).
——An Introduction to American Literature (Lexington: University Press of  Kentucky,
1971b).
—— Silvina Ocampo & Adolfo Bioy Casares, eds, Extraordinary Tales, Anthony
Kerrigan, trans. (New York: Herder & Herder 1971c).
—— Jorge Luis Borges Selected Poems 1923–1967, Norman Thomas di Giovanni, ed.
(London: Allen Lane, The Penguin Press, 1972).
—— and Adolfo Bioy Casares, eds, Cuentos breves y extraordinarios (Buenos Aires:
Losada, 1973).
——Extraordinary Tales, Anthony Kerrigan, trans. (New York: Souvenir Press, 1973).
—— Obras Completas: 1923–1972 (Buenos Aires: Alianza Emecé Editores, 1974).
—— In Praise of  Darkness, Norman Thomas di Giovanni, trans. (London: Allen
Lane, 1975).
—— ‘Walt Whitman: Man and Myth’, Critical Inquiry 1/4 ( Jun., 1975b), 707–18.
—— Labyrinths, Donald A. Yates and James E. Irby, eds, various trans. (London:
Penguin, 1976).
——The Book of Sand, Norman Thomas di Giovanni and Alastair Reid, trans. (London:
Penguin, 1979).
——and Adolfo Bioy Casares, eds, Libro del cielo y del infierno (Buenos Aires: Sur, 1983).
——Seven Nights, trans. Eliot Weinberger (University of  Michigan: New Directions,
1984).
—— Atlas, trans. Anthony Kerrigan (New York: E P Dutton, 1985).
—— and Margarita Guerrero, The Book of  Imaginary Beings, Norman Thomas di
Giovanni, trans. (London: Penguin, 1987).
244 Bibliography

—— Silvina Ocampo & Adolfo Bioy Casares, eds, The Book of  Fantasy (New York:
Viking, 1988).
—— Obras Completas: 1975–1985 (Buenos Aires: Emecé Editores, 1989).
—— ‘Prologue to Xul Solar, Catálogo de obras del Museo’ (Buenos Aires: Fundación
Pan Klub, 1990).
—— Historia universal de la infamia (Buenos Aires: Emecé, 1991).
—— Obra Poética 1923–1977 (Buenos Aires: Emecé, 1993).
—— ‘Testimony to the Invisible’, in Lawrence, ed., 1995, 3–16.
—— The Total Library: Non-fiction, 1922–1986, Esther Allen, Suzanne Jill Levine
& Eliot Weinberger, trans., Eliot Weinberger ed. (London: Allen Lane, The
Penguin Press, 2000).
——Borges Profesor, Martín Arias and Martín Hadis, eds (Buenos Aires: Emecé, 2002).
—— and Ernesto Sábato, Diálogos (Buenos Aires: Emecé, 2002).
—— Obra Completa IV: 1975–1988 (Buenos Aires: Emecé Editores, 2005).
—— Brodie’s Report, Andrew Hurley, ed. and trans. (London: Penguin, 2006).
—— On Mysticism, María Kodama, ed. (London: Penguin, 2010).

Alazraki, Jaime, Critical Essays on Jorge Luis Borges (Boston: G. K. Hall, 1987).
Alazraki, Jaime, Borges and the Kabbalah and Other Essays on His Fiction and Poetry
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).
Alifano, Roberto, ed., Twenty Four Conversations with Borges, N. S Araúz, W. Barnstone
& N. Escandell, trans. (Massachusetts: Lascaux Publishers, 1984).
Almeida, Iván, ‘Borges and Peirce, on abduction and maps’, Semiotica 140–1/4 (2002),
13–31.
Ankarsjö, Magnus, William Blake and religion: a new critical view ( Jef ferson, North
Carolina: McFarland, 2009).
Ayora, Jorge, ‘Gnosticism and Time in “El Inmortal”’ Hispania 56/3 (1973), 593–6.
Baba, Meher, God in a Pill? (California: Sufism Reoriented, 1966).
Báez-Rivera, Emilio R. ‘Swedenborg and Borges: from the Mystic of  the North to the
Mystic in puribus’, in McNeilly, ed., 2004, 71–91.
Bald, Margaret, Banned Books: Literature Suppressed on Religious Grounds (New York:
Facts on File Inc., 2006).
Balderston, Daniel, Out of context: historical reference and the representation of reality
in Borges (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1993).
Barili, Amelia, ‘Borges on Life and Death’, in Burgin, ed., 1998, 240–9.
Barili, Amelia, ‘Borges, Buddhism and Cognitive Science. A New Approach to Applied
Cognitive Science and Contemplative Studies across Disciplines’, Religion East
and West. Journal of  the Institute for World Religions (Berkeley, Institute for
World Religions, 9, 2009), 47–58.
Bibliography 245

Barnstone, Willis, ed., Borges at Eighty: Conversations (Indiana University Press, 1982).
Barnstone, Willis, With Borges on an ordinary evening in Buenos Aires: a memoir
(University of  Illinois Press, 2000).
Bell-Villada, Gene H., Borges and his fiction: a guide to his mind and art (Texas Pan
American series, 1999).
Bergquist, Lars, ‘Swedenborg and Heavenly Hermeneutics’, in McNeilly ed., 2002,
97–110.
Bioy Casares, Adolfo, Borges (Barcelona: Ediciones Destino, 2006).
Bossart, W. H., Borges and Philosophy: Self, Time and Metaphysics (New York: Peter
Lang, 2003).
Bosteels, Bruno, ‘Borges as Antiphilosopher’, Vanderbilt e-Journal of  Luso-Hispanic
Studies 3 (2006), 23–31.
Bosteels, Bruno, ‘The Truth Is In the Making: Borges and Pragmatism’, The Romanic
Review 98/ 2–3 (2007), 135–51.
Bourne, Daniel. ‘A Conversation with Jorge Luis Borges.’ Artful Dodge (College
of  Wooster, Ohio) April 25, 1980. < http://www3.wooster.edu/artfuldodge/
interviews/borges.htm>.
Brescia, Pablo, ‘A “Superior Magic”: Literary politics and the rise of  the fantastic
in Latin American fiction’, Forum for Modern Language Studies 44/4 (2008),
379–93.
Brown, Sir Thomas, Religio Medici (Kessinger Publishing, 2003).
Burgin, Richard, ed., Conversations with Jorge Luis Borges (Florida: Holt, Rinehart
& Winston, 1969).
Burgin, Richard, ed., Jorge Luis Borges: Conversations ( Jackson: University Press of 
Mississippi, 1998).
Campbell, Joseph, The Hero with a Thousand Faces (New York: Bollingen Foundation,
Pantheon Books, 1949).
Campbell, Joseph, The Power of  Myth, with Bill Moyers (New York: Doubleday, 1988).
Campbell, Joseph, Pathways to Bliss (California: New World Library, 2004).
Canto, Estela, Borges a Contraluz (Barcelona: Espasa Calpe, 1999).
Chadwick, John, Swedenborg and his readers – Selected Essays, Stephen McNeilly, ed.
(London: The Swedenborg Society 2003).
Christ, Ronald, ‘Jorge Luis Borges, The Art of  Fiction. Interview’, The Paris Review
40, Winter–Spring, 1967.
Christ, Ronald J., The Narrow Act (New York University Press, 1969).
Christ, Ronald, et al., ‘Borges at NYU’, in Burgin 1998, 118–38.
Cohen, J. M., Jorge Luis Borges (Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd, 1973).
Coleman, Alexander, ‘Notes on Borges and American Literature’, TriQuarterly 25
(1972), 356–77.
246 Bibliography

Conan Doyle, Arthur, ‘The Story of  Swedenborg’, in McNeilly, ed., 2005, 95–111.
Cortínez, Carlos, ed., Borges the Poet (Fayettevill: University of  Arkansas Press, 1986).
de Costa, René, Humor in Borges: Humor in Life and Letters (Detroit, MI: Wayne
State University Press, 2000).
Daniels, Michael, ‘Making Sense of  Mysticism’, Transpersonal Psychology Review 7/1
(2003), 39–55.
Deck, Raymond H. Jr., ‘New Light on C. A. Tulk’, Studies in Romanticism 16/2 (Spring,
1977), 217–36.
Doblin, Rick, ‘Pahnke’s “Good Friday Experiment” A Long-Term Follow-Up and
Methodological Critique’, The Journal of  Transpersonal Psychology 23/1 (1991),
1–28.
Dutton, Denis, ‘“Merely a Man of  Letters”: Jorge Luis Borges: an interview’, Philosophy
and Literature 1/3 (1977), 337–41.
Earle, Peter G., ‘Review: The Secret of  Borges. A Psychoanalytic Inquiry into His Work
by Julio Woscoboinik’, Hispanic Review 68.1 (2000), 99–101.
Eliade, Mircea, Shamanism: Archaic Techniques of  Ecstasy (New Jersey: Princeton
University Press, 1972).
Ellwood, Robert S., Mysticism and Religion (Seven Bridges Press, 1999).
Emerson, Ralph Waldo, Essays And Poems, Peter Norberg ed. (Spark Educational
Publishing, 2005).
Emerson, Ralph Waldo, Emerson on Swedenborg: Introducing the Mystic, Stephen
McNeilly ed. (London: The Swedenborg Society, 2003).
Enguídanos, Miguel, et al. ‘A writer is waiting for his own work’, in Barnstone 1982,
91–101.
Enguídanos, Miguel, et al. ‘Now I am more or less who I am,’ in Burgin 1998, 164–76.
Erdman, David V., ‘Blake’s Early Swedenborgianism: A Twentieth-Century Legend’,
Comparative Literature 5/3 (Summer, 1953), 247–57.
Fernandes, Marcel, Borges and Pragmatism: Borges, William James, and the Destruction
of  Philosophy, PhD Thesis (University of  Otago, Dunedin, New Zealand, March
2008).
Ferrer, Jorge, Revisioning Transpersonal Theory: A Participatory Vision of  Human
Spirituality (New York: Suny Press, 2002).
Flynn, Annette, The Quest for God in the Work of  Borges (London and New York:
Continuum International Publishing Group, 2009).
Fordman, Frieda, An Introduction to Jung’s Psychology (London: Penguin, 1953).
De Garayalde, Giovanna, Jorge Luis Borges sources and illumination (London: Octagon
Press, 1978).
Bibliography 247

García, Humberto, ‘In the Name of  the “Incestuous Mother”: Islam and Excremental
Protestantism in De Quincey’s Infidel Book’, Journal for Early Modern Cultural
Studies 7/2 (Fall–Winter, 2007), 57–87.
Garrett, Clarke, ‘Swedenborg and the Mystical Enlightenment in Late Eighteenth-
Century England’, Journal of  the History of  Ideas 45/1 ( Jan–Mar., 1984), 67–81.
Giskin, Howard, ‘The Mystical Experience in Borges: A Problem of  Perception’,
Hispanófila 98/2 (1990), 71–85.
Golobof f, Gerardo Mario, ‘“Ser Hombre”: Exploración del Tema del “Otro” en un
Soneto de Jorge Luis Borges’, Revista Iberoamericana 43/100–101 (1977), 575–89.
Green, Celia Elizabeth, Lucid dreaming: the paradox of consciousness during sleep
(London; Routledge, 1994).
Grof, Stanislav, The Cosmic Game: Explorations in the Frontiers of  Human Consciousness
(Dublin: Newleaf, 1998).
Guibert, Rita, ‘Interview with Jorge Luis Borges’, in Burgin 1998, 42–76.
Halifax, Joan, Shaman: the wounded healer (London: Thames and Hudson, 1982).
Holditch, Kenneth, Borges and Emerson: The Poet as Intellectual, in Cortínez, ed.,
1986, 197–206.
Hollis, James and David Rosen, The Archetypal Imagination (Texas: A&M University
Press, 2003).
Hurth, Elisabeth, ‘The Poet and the Mystic: Ralph Waldo Emerson and Jakob Böhme’
ZAA (Zeitschrift für Anglistik und Amerikanistik) 53/4 (2005), 333–52.
Huxley, Aldous, The Doors of  Perception (Chatto and Windus, 1954).
Inge, William Ralph, Christian Mysticism (Methuen, 1913).
Inge, William Ralph, Mysticism in Religion (London: Hutchinson’s University Library
1947).
Jaf fé, Aniela, Was C.G. Jung a Mystic? And Other Essays (Einsiedeln: Daimon Verlag,
1989).
James, William, Varieties of  Religious Experience (London: Longmans, Green & Co.,
1913).
James, William, Letters of  William James, Henry James, ed. (Kessinger Publishing,
2003).
James, William, ‘A Suggestion about Mysticism’, The Journal of  Philosophy, Psychology
and Scientific Methods 7/4 (1910), 85–92.
Jantzen, Grace, Power, Gender and Christian Mysticism (Cambridge University Press,
1995).
Jay, Mike, Emperors of  Dreams: Drugs in the Nineteenth Century (Cambridgeshire:
Dedalus, 2000).
Johnson, Gregory R. ‘William James on Swedenborg: A Newly Discovered Letter’
Studia Swedenborgiana 13: 2 (2003) <http://www.baysidechurch.org/studia>.
248 Bibliography

Jung, C. G., Tipos psicológicos, Ramón de la Serna, trans. (Buenos Aires: Editorial
Sudamericana, 1945).
Jung, C. G., Symbols of  Transformation: An Analysis of  the Prelude to a Case of 
Schizophrenia (New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1956).
Jung, C. G., ‘Flying Saucers: A Modern Myth of  Things Seen in the Sky’ (Collected
Works 10: Civilization in Transition, 1958), 307–437.
Jung, C. G., Alchemical Studies, R. F. C. Hull, ed., Gerhard Adler, trans. (Collected
Works 13, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1983).
Jung, C. G., Memories, Dreams, Ref lections, Aniela Jaf fé, ed. (New York: Vintage
Books, 1989).
Jung, C. G., C. G. Jung Speaking: Interviews and Encounters, William McGuire and
R. F. C. Hull, eds (New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1993).
Jung, C. G., Jung on active imagination: key readings, Joan Chodorow, ed. (London:
Routledge, 1997).
Jung, C. G., The Red Book, Sonu Shamdasani, ed. (New York: W.W. Norton & Co.,
2009).
Jurado, Alicia, Genio y figura de Jorge Luis Borges (Editorial Universitaria de Buenos
Aires, 1996).
Kast, Verena, ‘Anima/animus’, in The Handbook of  Jungian Psychology: Theory, Practice
and Applications, Renos K. Papadopoulos, ed. (London: Routledge, 2006),
94–113.
Kripal, Jef frey, Roads of  Excess, Palaces of  Wisdom: Eroticism & Ref lexivity in the Study
of  Mysticism (University of  Chicago Press, 2001).
Kristal, Efraín, Invisible Work: Borges and Translation (Vanderbilt University Press,
2002).
Lachman, Gary, Swedenborg: An Introduction to His Life and Ideas (Penguin Group
US, 2012).
Lachman, Gary, Jung the Mystic: The Esoteric Dimensions of  Carl Jung’s Life and
Teachings (Tarcher, 2010).
Lawrence, James, ed., Testimony to the Invisible: Essays on Swedenborg (Pennsylvania:
Chrysalis Books, 1995).
Lawrence, James F., ‘Swedenborg’s Trail in the Coleridgean Landscape ’, Studia
Swedenborgiana 11/2 (1999): 55–66.
Lezama Lima, José, Diarios 1939–1949 / 1956–1958, Ciro Bianchi Ross, ed. (Havana:
UNEAC, 2001).
Main, Roderick, The Rupture of  Time: Synchronicity and Jung’s Critique of  Modern
Western Culture (Hove, East Sussex: Brunner-Routledge, 2004).
McDannell, Colleen and Bernhard Lang, Heaven: A History (London: Vintage 1990).
McKenna, Terence (1991) The Archaic Revival (San Francisco: Harper).
Bibliography 249

McNeilly, Stephen, ed., On the true philosopher and the true philosophy: essays on
Swedenborg (London: Swedenborg Society, 2002).
McNeilly, Stephen, ed., In Search of  the Absolute: Essays on Swedenborg and Literature
(London: Swedenborg Society, 2004).
McNeilly, Stephen, ed., Between Method and Madness: Essays on Swedenborg and
Literature (London: The Swedenborg Society, 2005).
Milosz, Czeslaw, ‘Dostoevsky and Swedenborg’, in Lawrence, ed., 1995, 19–51.
Molloy, Sylvia, Signs of  Borges (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1994).
Montaigne, Michel de, The Complete Essays of  Michel de Montaigne, 2 Vols (Forgotten
Books, 1910).
Moss, Robert. Dreamgates: an explorer’s guide to the worlds of soul, imagination, and
life beyond death (New York: Three Rivers Press, 1998).
Mualem, Shlomy, ‘The Imminence of  Revelation: Aesthetics and Poetic Expression in
Early Wittgenstein and Jorge Luis Borges’, Variaciones Borges 18 (2004), 197–217.
Nubiola, Jaime ‘Jorge Luis Borges and WJ’, Streams of  William James 1/3 (Winter
2000), 7.
Nubiola, Jaime, ‘WJ and Borges Again: The Riddle of  the Correspondence with
Macedonio Fernández’, Streams of  William James 3/2 (Fall 2001), 10–11.
Nubiola, Jaime Jorge Luis Borges y William James: Aproximaciones a la obra de
William James: la formulación del pragmatismo (Biblioteca Nueva, Universidad
Complutense de Madrid, 2005), 201–18.
Núñez-Faraco, Humberto, Borges and Dante: Echoes of a Literary Friendship (Oxford
and Bern: Peter Lang, 2006).
Orrego Arismendi, Juan Carlos, ‘Borges: sus cuentos sobre indios araucanos y el siglo
XIX’, Variaciones Borges 24 (2007), 35–55.
Pahnke, Walter, ‘Drugs and Mysticism’, The International Journal of  Parapsychology,
8/2 (Spring 1966), 295–313.
Portugal M. Saliba, Ana Maria, ‘Borges y Freud: Conjunciones’, Variaciones Borges
12 (2001) 179–92.
Quinn, Patrick, ‘Emerson and Mysticism’, American Literature 21/4 ( Jan 1950),
397–414.
Raine, Kathleen, ‘Poetry in relation to traditional wisdom’ Temenos Academy Review,
10 (2007), 21–36.
Raine, Kathleen, ‘The Human Face of  God’, in Lawrence, ed., 1995, 51–89.
Rawlinson, Andrew, The book of enlightened masters: western teachers in eastern tradi-
tions (Chicago: Open Court, 1998).
Rix, Robert, William Blake and the cultures of radical Christianity (London: Ashgate
Publishing, Ltd., 2007).
250 Bibliography

Rodríguez Monegal, Emir, Jorge Luis Borges: A literary Biography (New York: Dutton,
1978).
Rodríguez Monegal, Emir, ‘Borges and Derrida: Apothecaries’, in Borges and His
Successors: The Borgesian Impact on Literature and the Arts, ed. Edna Aizenberg
(Columbia, MO: University of  Missouri Press, 1990), 128–55.
Rodríguez Risquete, Francisco, ‘Borges: fervor de Dante’, Quaderns d’Italià 10 (2005),
195–218.
Romero, Oswaldo, ‘Dios en la Obra de Jorge L. Borges: Su Teología y su Teodicea’,
Revista Iberoamericana 43/100–101 (1977), 465–503.
Rowlandson, William ‘Borges’s Reading of  Dante and Swedenborg: Mysticism and
the Real’ Variaciones Borges 32 (2011), 59–87.
Rowlandson, William, ‘The Anaesthetic Revelation: Psychedelia and Mysticism’,
in Cameron Adams, Anna Waldstein, Ben Sessa, David Luke and David King
(eds) Breaking Convention: Essays on Psychedelic Consciousness (London: Strange
Attractor, 2013, in press) 234–42.
Rowlandson, William, Reading Lezama’s Paradiso (Oxford, Peter Lang, 2007).
Russell, Bertrand, ‘Mysticism’, in Religion and Science (Oxford University Press, 1961),
171–90.
Salas, Susana Chica, ‘Conversación con Borges’, Revista Iberoamericana 42/96–97
(1976), 585–91.
Schlamm, Leon, ‘Revisiting Jung’s dialogue with yoga: observations from transper-
sonal psychology’, International Journal of  Jungian Studies 2/1 (2010), 32–44.
Schopenhauer, Arthur, The World as Will and Representation, Vol. II (Courier Dover
Publications, 1966).
Schorer, Mark, ‘Blake and Swedenborg’, Modern Philology, 36 (1938), 157–78.
Schuchard, Marsha Keith, Why Mrs Blake Cried: William Blake and the Erotic
Imagination (Century First Edition, 2006).
Shenker, Israel, ‘Borges, a Blind Writer with Insight’, New York Times (6 April 1971).
Smith, Huston, Cleansing the Doors of  Perception: the religious significance of entheo-
genic plants and chemicals (Sentient Publications, 2000).
Sorrentino, Fernando, Siete conversaciones con Jorge Luis Borges (Buenos Aires: Editorial
El Ateneo, 2001).
Soud, Stephen E., ‘Borges the Golem-Maker: Intimations of  “Presence” in “The
Circular Ruins”’, MLN 110/4 (1995), 739–54.
Staal, Frits, Exploring Mysticism (Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: University of 
California Press, 1975).
Stace, W. T., The Teachings of  the Mystics (New York: Macmillan, 1960).
Stace, W. T., Mysticism and Philosophy (London: Macmillan, 1961).
Bibliography 251

Stephens, Matthew, ‘Borges and WJ Revisited’ Streams of  William James 2/3 (Fall
2000), 1–2.
Suzuki, D. T., Zen Buddhism: Selected Writings of  D. T. Suzuki (New York: Anchor
Books, 1956).
Swedenborg, Emanuel, Heaven and Hell (De Coelo et Ejus Mirabilibus, et de Inferno,
ex Auditis et Visis [London 1758]) George F. Dole, trans. (London: Swedenborg
Foundation New Century Edition), 2000.
Swedenborg, Emanuel, Arcana Coelestia [London 1749], John F. Potts, trans. (1910),
<www.sacred-texts.com/swd/ac/index.htm>.
Swedenborg, Emanuel, Divine Providence [London 1764], William Frederic Wunsch,
trans. (1851), <http://www.sacred-texts.com/swd/dpr/index.htm>.
Synnestvedt, Sig, ed., Swedenborg, testigo de lo invisible (Buenos Aires: Marymar, 1982).
Synnestvedt, Sig, ed., The Essential Swedenborg (New York, Swedenborg Foundation,
1977).
Talbot, Brian, ‘Schuchard’s Swedenborg’, The New Philosophy ( July–December 2007),
165–218.
Taylor, Eugene I. and Robert H. Wozniak, ‘Pure Experience, the Response to William
James: An Introduction’, in E. I. Taylor & R. H. Wozniak, eds, Pure Experience:
The Response to William James (Bristol: Thoemmes Press, 1996), ix–xxxii.
Taylor, Eugene, ‘Peirce and Swedenborg’ Studia Swedenborgiana, 6/1 (1986), 25–51.
Taylor, Eugene, ‘Have we engaged in a colossal misreading of  James’s Varieties?’ Streams
of  William James 5/1 (Spring 2003), 2–7.
Taylor, Eugene, ‘Emerson: The Swedenborgian and Transcendentalist Connection’,
in Lawrence, ed., 1995, 141–73.
Taylor, Eugene, A Psychology of  Spritual Healing (Chrysalis Books, the Swedenborg
Foundation, 1997).
Tcherepashenets, Nataly, Place and Displacement in the Narrative Worlds of  Jorge Luis
Borges and Julio Cortázar (New York: Peter Lang, 2008).
Ulla, Noemí, ‘Notas sobre “El cautivo” de Jorge Luis Borges’, Variaciones Borges 13
(2002), 227–33.
Underhill, Evelyn, Mysticism: A Study of  the Nature and Development of  Man’s Spiritual
Consciousness (New York: E. P. Dutton & Co., 1912).
Van Dusen, Wilson, ‘Swedenborg’s Spiritual Method’, Studia Swedenborgiana, 7/3
(1991), 3–19.
Van Dusen, Wilson, ‘A mystic looks at Swedenborg’, in Lawrence, ed., 1995, 105–41.
Van Dusen, Wilson, The Presence of  Other Worlds (Chrysalis Books, the Swedenborg
Foundation, 2004).
Vázquez, María Esther, Borges. Imágenes, memorias, diálogos (Caracas, Monte Ávila,
1977).
252 Bibliography

Von Franz, Marie-Louise, C.G. Jung: his Myth in our time (New York: G.P. Putnam’s
Sons, 1975).
Wallace, David Foster, ‘Borges on the Couch’, New York Times (7 November, 2004).
Warnes, Christopher, Magical Realism and the Postcolonial Novel: Between Faith and
Irreverence (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2009).
Watts, Alan, Eastern Wisdom, Modern Life: Collected Talks: 1960–1969 (Novato,
California: New World Library, 2006).
Watts, Alan, ‘Beat Zen Square Zen and Zen’, in The Portable Beat Reader, Ann Charters,
ed. (Penguin Classics, 2006), 607–15.
Webb, James, The Harmonious Circle: The Lives and Work of  G. I. Gurdjief f, P. D.
Ouspensky, and Their Followers (Boston: Shambhala, 1987).
Wellbeloved, Sophia, Gurdjief f : The Key Concepts (London: Routledge, 2003).
Wildner, Christian, ‘Entrevista realizada por Christian Wildner con Jorge Luis Borges
en prólogo a la traducción por él mismo realizada de Emanuel Swedenborg, El
Cielo y sus Maravillas y el Infierno (Buenos Aires, Editorial Kier, 1991) <http://
www.swedenborg.es/borges/borges_wildner.htm>.
Williamson, Edwin, Borges: A Life (London: Viking, 2004).
Wilson, Colin, ‘The Reality of  the Visionary World’, in Lawrence, ed., 1995, 89–105.
Wilson, Jason, Jorge Luis Borges, Critical Lives (London: Reaktion Books, 2006).
Woodall, James, Borges: A Life (New York: Basic Books, 1997).
Woolger, Roger, ‘Understanding C.G. Jung’s Red Book’ Network Review Journal of 
the Scientific and Medical Network Journal (Summer 2011), 3–8.
Woscoboinik, Julio, The Secret of  Borges: A Psychoanalytic Inquiry into His Work,
Dora Carlisky Pozzi trans. (Lanham, MD: University Press of  America 1998).
Wulf f, David, ‘Mystical Experience’, in Etzel Cardeña, Steven J. Lynn, and Stanley
Krippner, eds, Varieties of  Anomalous Experience (Washington: American
Psychological Association, 2000), 397–441.
Yates, Donald. ‘Borges: Philosopher? Poet? Revolutionary?’ in Burgin 1998, 192–9.
Yeats, W. B., ‘Swedenborg, Mediums, and the Desolate Places’, in W. B. Yeats and
Lady Gregory, Visions and Beliefs in the West of  Ireland (New York & London:
G. P. Putman, 1920), 295–339.
Yeats, W. B., ‘William Blake and the Imagination’, in W. B. Yeats, Ideas of  Good and
Evil (London: A. H. Bullen, 1903), 168–76.
Zaehner, R. C., Mysticism: Sacred and Profane (New York: Oxford University Press,
1961).
Index

Abramowicz, Maurice, 222–3 ‘Los ángeles de Swedenborg’, 194,


Alanus de Insulis (Alain de Lille), 117 203–5
anomalous human experience (para- Antología de la literatura fantástica
psychology, paraphenomena, [Extraordinary Tales], 59, 203
the occult, etc.), 6, 21–30, 91–4, Atlas, 1, 30, 104, 154, 194, 221
101–23, 134, 156–9, 195 ‘Autobiographical Essay’, 29
Aristotle, 136, 169 ‘La biblioteca de Babel’ [‘The Library
Augustine, St, 28, 110, 156 of Babel’], 7, 13, 176
‘Borges y yo’ [‘Borges and I’], 220, 233
Baba, Meher, 149, 185 ‘El ciervo blanco’, 105
Barili, Amelia, 15, 29, 39–43, 195, 198, 222 ‘El Congreso’ [‘The Congress’], 21,
Bioy Casares, Adolfo, 6, 23–8, 58–9, 76, 57, 149
195, 203, 217 Los Conjurados, 3, 21–2, 193, 222, 228
Blake, William, 4–5, 18, 22, 33, 43, 45, ‘Delia Elena San Marco’, 73
55–6, 63, 84, 98, 107, 115, 120, 123, ‘Diálogo de muertos’ [‘Dead men’s
129, 135, 138, 140, 143–4, 157–61, dialogue’], 22, 205–14, 221
170–1, 182–3, 188–196, 210–12, ‘Doomsday’, 22, 193
239 ‘Duración del Infierno’, 85, 178, 194,
Borges, Jorge Luis 198, 210
aesthetic value of philosophy, 6, 8–14 Elogio de la sombra [In Praise of
agnosticism, 7, 12–13, 23, 45, 74, 85–6 Darkness], 3, 12, 104, 153, 165, 198,
ethics, 198–203 209, 214–42
Hitler, Nazis, Third Reich, 24, 16, 228 ‘El Encuentro’ [‘The Meeting’], 113, 157
in Japan, 98–9, 108, 113, 159, 191, 241 ‘La escritura del dios’ [‘The God’s
psychoanalytical reading of, 227–9 Script’], 4, 8, 43, 83–4
teaching Borges, 6–7, 39–43 ‘El Etnógrafo’ [‘The Anthropologist’],
as Virgil, 43–6 225–42
Borges, Jorge Luis, texts discussed or Ficciones, 6, 13, 41, 104, 204, 221, 225
referred to: ‘Flor de Coleridge’, 142, 166
‘Abramowicz’ (Los Conjurados), ‘Fragmentos de un evangelio apócrifo’
222–3 [‘From an apocryphal gospel’],
‘Ajedrez’ [‘Chess’], 154 214–23
‘El Aleph’ [‘The Aleph’], 4, 8, 43, ‘El General Quiroga va en coche al
76–7, 80–4, 100, 108–20, 138, muere’ [General Quiroga rides to
155, 157 his death in a carriage’], 206–7
254 Index

Borges, Jorge Luis (cont.) ‘Pedro Salvadores’, 12, 191, 192


El Hacedor [Dreamtigers], 3, 9, 105, ‘Pierre Menard, autor del Quijote’
205 [‘Pierre Menard, author of the
‘His end and his beginning’, 218–21 The Quixote’], 7, 14
‘Historia de la eternidad’ [‘A History ‘Sentirse en muerte’ mystical experi-
of Eternity’], 21–2, 80, 109, 113, ence, 80, 94, 99–100, 108–20, 123,
129, 194 129, 149, 155–9, 187
‘Historia de los ángeles’ [‘History of Siete Noches [Seven Nights], 3, 31, 33,
Angels’], 15, 60 35, 41, 48, 69, 71, 99, 103, 105, 133
‘El idioma analítico de John Wilkens’ ¿Qué es el Budismo?, 41
[‘The Analytical Language of ‘Quevedo’, 34
John Wilkens’], 13, 15, 175 ‘El remordimiento’, 218
El Informe de Brodie [Dr Brodie’s ‘La Rosa de Paracelsus’, 21
Report], 3, 72, 204, 225, 229, 233 ‘Rosas’, 206–7
‘El jardín de senderos que se bifurcan’ ‘Las Ruinas circulares’ [‘The Circular
[‘The Garden of Forking Paths’], Ruins’], 21, 56, 72, 84, 104, 221,
7 233
‘Leyenda’ ‘Legend’, 208 ‘Ruiseñor de Keats’ [‘The Nightingale
El Libro de Arena [The Book of Sand], of Keats’], 135, 142, 169
3, 15, 57, 113, 225 ‘Swedenborg, testigo de lo invisible’
Libro del cielo y del infierno, 195 [‘Testimony to the Invisible’], 36,
Libro de los seres imaginarios [Book of 38, 50–5, 63, 75, 91–2, 110, 117, 125,
Imaginary Beings], 21, 46–7, 55, 134, 139, 143–6, 150, 155, 162, 166,
60–1, 73, 157, 193–4, 203, 228 171, 173–5, 178–80, 182–3, 192,
La Memoria de Shakespeare 196, 200, 202–3, 207–12
[Shakespeare’s Memory], 3, 113, ‘Un teólogo en la muerte’, 194, 204–7,
194 213, 219–21
‘El milagro secreto’ [‘The Secret ‘Tlön, Uqbar, Orbis Tertius’, 5, 7, 58
Miracle’], 22, 84, 105 ‘Tres versiones de Judas’ [‘Three
‘La muerte y la brújula’ [‘Death and Versions of Judas’], 22
the Compass’], 7, 13 ‘Two English Poems’, 30
‘El muerto’ [‘The Dead Man’], 176 ‘Undr’, 15–18, 151, 241
‘La muralla y los libros’ [‘The Wall & ‘Utopía de un hombre que está
the Books’], 12 cansado’ [‘Utopia of a Tired
‘La nadería de la personalidad’ [‘The Man’], 15–18
Nothingness of Personality’], 15, ‘Veinticinco de agosto, 1983’, 113, 157,
17, 37, 61, 109, 199, 220 194
‘Nueva refutación del tiempo’ [‘New ‘Una vindicación del falso Basílides’
Refutation of Time’], 80, 194 [‘A Vindication of the False
Nueve Ensayos Dantescos, 49, 66, Basilides’], 21
228, 236 Borges, Norah, 60
Index 255

Böhme, Jakob (Boehme or Behmen), 119, Fernández, Macedonio, 137, 188, 239
127, 138, 177, 186–7, 190–1 Ficino, Marsilio, 21
Bruno, Giordano, 21 Flaubert, Gustave, 52, 75, 196
Buddhism, 5, 15, 33, 39–43, 83, 99, 119, 133, Flynn, Annette, 36–9, 101, 109–10, 114,
150, 195, 220 137, 191
Zen, 98–9, 133, 150, 185, 215 Freud, Sigmund, 19, 227–9

Calderón de la Barca, Pedro, 105, 220 Grof, Stanislav, 42, 94


Campbell, Joseph, 94, 225–42 Gurdjieff, George Ivanovich, 22–3
Canto, Estela, 80–2, 85, 89, 118–19, 127
Castillejo, Cristóbal de, 27–8 Huxley, Aldous, 22, 94, 122, 141, 149, 185
Cohen, John Michael, 83, 115, 119, 138,
162 Inge, William Ralph (Dean Inge), 5,
Coleridge, Samuel Taylor, 105, 135, 142, 87–8, 95, 107, 121
167, 169–70, 188–9, 196, 211
Conan Doyle, Arthur, 54, 92, 94, 145, 163, James, Henry, 196
181, 196, 219 James, Henry, Sr, 52, 130, 139, 188
Corbin, Henry, 55–6, 107, 148, 196, James, William, 5, 8, 11, 18, 22, 24, 52, 79,
210–11, 214, 223 82–91, 95–102, 105–15, 119, 121–4,
125–63, 167, 169–70, 184–8, 196,
Daniels, Michael, 94–100, 140–2 222, 232, 239
Dante Alighieri, 4–5, 11, 18, 22, 36, 43–6, Varieties of Religious Experience, 79,
47–77, 105–18, 150, 158, 176–80, 88–91, 95, 119, 127, 132, 135–9, 159,
186, 193, 195–6, 202, 210, 212, 228, 163, 239
236, 242 Jodorowsky, Alejandro (Alexandro), 225
dreams, 4, 18, 29–38, 56, 62, 68, 74, Juan de la Cruz, San (St John of the
102–6, 123, 150, 158, 188, 198, 21–3, Cross), 5, 64–5, 72, 77, 84, 115,
219, 221, 223, 227, 229, 234–7 117–18, 145, 162, 187
lucid dreams, 91, 102–4, 123, 212 Jung, Carl Gustav
nightmares, 31, 34–5, 68, 103–6, Answer to Job, 15
346–7 the hero, 225–42
Dunne, John William, 22, 105, 152 individuation, 226, 233, 239, 241–2
Memories Dreams Reflections, 20, 29
Eckhart, Meister, 4–5, 8, 120–1, 187, 239 as mystic and guru, 20–1
Eliade, Mircea, 148, 237 The Red Book, 18, 20–1, 104, 212
Emerson, Ralph Waldo, 2, 4, 52, 54, 57, Septem Sermones ad Mortuos, 153–4
75, 86, 91, 106, 122, 126–7, 130–5, the shadow, 225–42
139, 145, 147–8, 161, 165–92, 196, synchronicity, 25–8, 236
208 transcendental function (active
Transcendentalism, 75, 121, 139–40, imagination), 212, 236
167–9, 192 UFOs, 18–19
256 Index

Jurado, Alicia, 82, 89, 127 Raine, Kathleen, 52, 56, 63, 176, 211
Reid, Alastair, 43, 45
Kabbalah (Cabala), 4–5, 17, 39, 64, 79, Rosas, Juan Manuel de, 206–14, 220
145, 148, 162, 195 Russell, Bertrand, 24, 87, 121, 129–30, 132,
Kant, Immanuel, 9, 11, 18, 59, 61, 93, 159, 196
137, 139, 159, 169, 170, 183, 188,
196 Scholem, Gershom, 17–18, 148
Kodama, María, 22, 83–5, 114, 119, 222 Schopenhauer, Arthur, 9, 18, 55, 88,
Kripal, Jeffrey, 6, 31, 39, 82, 113, 121, 123, 99–100, 136, 140, 151, 183,
128, 133 196
Schuchard, Marsha Keith, 146–7, 163
Lachman, Gary, 20, 31, 91 Scotus Erigena, 4–5, 59
Lange, Haydée, 30–1, 104, 154, 221 Shakespeare, William, 63, 76, 105, 118, 152,
Lezama Lima, José, 55–7, 176 161–2, 170–1, 179, 220
Luis de León, 5, 64, 77, 107, 118, 140, 145, Shamanism, 20–1, 94, 237, 239
162 Shaw, George Bernard, 15, 57, 101, 194,
196, 200, 202
McKenna, Terence, 94, 237 Silesius, Angelus, 4, 5, 18, 22, 43, 64, 126,
Milosz, Czeslaw, 212 159, 179, 187, 239
Montaigne, Michel de, 26–8, 170–1 Cherubinischer Wandersmann, 22
Myers, Frederic, 24 Socrates, 37, 133, 152
Staal, Frits, 42, 86, 88–9, 107, 122, 126,
Neoplatonism, 4, 21, 85, 142, 146, 167 130–1, 144, 150
Novalis, 4, 25 Stace, Walter, 5, 86, 90–1, 96–7, 101–2,
106–8, 115, 122, 124, 126, 129–30,
Ocampo, Victoria, 17–18 135, 141
Ocampo, Silvina, 203 Steiner, Rudolf, 22, 196
Ouspensky, Peter, 22–3 Stevenson, Robert Louis, 5, 7, 57, 196
‘Brownies’, 34–6, 46, 105
Pahnke, Walter, 97, 115 Strange Case of Dr Jekyll and Mr
Paracelsus, 18, 21 Hyde, 34–5, 233
Parmenides, 59, 169 Sufi mystical poetry, 4, 22, 44, 53, 83, 116,
Pascal, 5, 9, 65, 118, 162, 187, 194 155–6, 242
Pedro Páramo, 206 Suzuki, Daisetsu Teitaro, 94, 96, 99, 150,
Plato, 9, 13, 34, 37, 59, 73, 83, 90, 110, 133, 197
135–6, 142, 152–3, 157, 169, 176 Swedenborg, Emanuel
Poe, Edgar Allan, 48, 59, 167, 196 Arcana Coelestia, 2, 203–10, 217
postcolonialism, 6, 235 reception in Catholic countries,
psychedelic, 94, 115, 122, 149, 239 197–8
doctrine of correspondences, 94, 145,
Quiroga, Facundo, 206–14, 220 174–6, 188, 202
Index 257

Heaven and Hell, 1–2, 22, 45, 47, 54, Von Franz, Marie-Louise, 20, 115, 238–9
56, 59, 123, 128, 143, 170–1, 178,
180, 196, 199–221 Watts, Alan, 79, 86, 101, 107, 185
as heterodox or heretic, 63–6, 77, 94, Weatherhead, Leslie Dixon, 48, 59, 64–5,
106, 123, 178, 181, 187, 192, 199 72, 77, 108, 118, 194
Melanchthon, 204–7, 213, 219–21 Wellbeloved, Sophia, 22–3
Moravian Chapel, 146, 189–90 Wells, H. G., 5, 48, 59, 179, 197
psychic or extra-sensory powers, 91–4 Western esotericism, 5, 17, 24, 40, 142
as Viking or as Eric the Red, 2, 36, 51, Whitman, Walt, 54, 135, 166–7, 196,
173, 178, 211 228
Wilson, Colin, 63, 172
Teresa de Jesús (Teresa de Ávila, St Woolger, Roger, 20
Teresa), 5, 8, 62, 97, 120, 126, 145,
162, 187 Xul Solar (Oscar Agustín Alejandro
Thousand and One Nights, 6 Schulz Solari), 5, 77, 80, 126, 157,
170–1, 194
Underhill, Evelyn, 82, 86, 90–1, 95–6,
106–7, 113, 115, 121–4, 135, Yeats, W. B., 52, 54, 62–3, 81, 130, 161, 181,
141 196

Van Dusen, Wilson, 38, 92–4, 100, 102, Zaehner, R. C., 86, 96, 101, 106–7, 115,
130, 132, 134, 197, 213 122, 135, 141, 150
Hispanic Studies: Culture and Ideas
Edited by
Claudio Canaparo
This series aims to publish studies in the arts, humanities and social sciences,
the main focus of which is the Hispanic World. The series invites proposals
with interdisciplinary approaches to Hispanic culture in fields such as history
of concepts and ideas, sociology of culture, the evolution of visual arts, the
critique of literature, and uses of historiography. It is not confined to a
particular historical period.

Monographs as well as collected papers are welcome in English or Spanish.

Those interested in contributing to the series are invited to write with either
the synopsis of a subject already in typescript or with a detailed project outline
to either Professor Claudio Canaparo, Department of Iberian and Latin
American Studies, School of Arts, Birkbeck College, 43 Gordon Square,
London WC1H 0PD, UK, c.canaparo@sllc.bbk.ac.uk, or to Peter Lang Ltd,
oxford@peterlang.com.

Vol. 1 Antonio Sánchez


Postmodern Spain. A Cultural Analysis of 1980s–1990s Spanish
Culture. 220 pages. 2007.
ISBN 978-3-03910-914-2

Vol. 2 Geneviève Fabry y Claudio Canaparo (eds.)


El enigma de lo real. Las fronteras del realismo en la narrativa del
siglo XX. 275 pages. 2007.
ISBN 978-3-03910-893-0

Vol. 3 William Rowlandson


Reading Lezama’s Paradiso. 290 pages. 2007.
ISBN 978-3-03910-751-3
Vol. 4 Fernanda Peñaloza, Jason Wilson and Claudio Canaparo (eds)
Patagonia. Myths and Realities. 277 pages. 2010.
ISBN 978-3-03910-917-3

Vol. 5 Xon de Ros


Primitivismo y Modernismo. El legado de María Blanchard.
238 pages. 2007.
ISBN 978-3-03910-937-1

Vol. 6 Sergio Plata


Visions of Applied Mathematics. Strategy and Knowledge.
284 pages. 2007.
ISBN 978-3-03910-923-4

Vol. 7 Annick Louis


Borges ante el fascismo. 374 pages. 2007.
ISBN 978-3-03911-005-6

Vol. 8 Helen Oakley


From Revolution to Migration. A Study of Contemporary Cuban and
Cuban-American Crime Fiction. 200 pages. 2012.
ISBN 978-3-03911-021-6

Vol. 9 Thea Pitman


Mexican Travel Writing. 209 pages. 2008.
ISBN 978-3-03911-020-9

Vol. 10 Francisco J. Borge


A New World for a New Nation. The Promotion of America in Early
Modern England. 240 pages. 2007.
ISBN 978-3-03911-070-4

Vol. 11 Helena Buffery, Stuart Davis and Kirsty Hooper (eds)


Reading Iberia. Theory/History/Identity. 229 pages. 2007.
ISBN 978-3-03911-109-1

Vol. 12 Matías Bruera


Meditations on Flavour. Forthcoming.
ISBN 978-3-03911-345-3
Vol. 13 Angela Romero-Astvaldsson
La obra narrativa de David Viñas. La nueva inflexión de Prontuario
y Claudia Conversa. 300 pages. 2007.
ISBN 978-3-03911-100-8

Vol. 14 Aaron Kahn


The Ambivalence of Imperial Discourse. Cervantes’s La Numancia
within the ‘Lost Generation’ of Spanish Drama (1570–90).
243 pages. 2008.
ISBN 978-3-03911-098-8

Vol. 15 Turid Hagene


Negotiating Love in Post-Revolutionary Nicaragua. The role of love
in the reproduction of gender asymmetry. 341 pages. 2008.
ISBN 978-3-03911-011-7

Vol. 16 Yolanda Rodríguez Pérez


The Dutch Revolt through Spanish Eyes. Self and Other in historical
and literary texts of Golden Age Spain (c. 1548–1673). 346 pages. 2008.
ISBN 978-3-03911-136-7

Vol. 17 Stanley Black (ed.)


Juan Goytisolo. Territories of Life and Writing. 202 pages. 2007.
ISBN 978-3-03911-324-8

Vol. 18 María T. Sánchez


The Problems of Literary Translation. A Study of the Theory and
Practice of Translation from English into Spanish. 269 pages. 2009.
ISBN 978-3-03911-326-2

Vol. 19 Aino Linda Rinhaug


Fernando Pessoa. A Ludicrous Self. Forthcoming.
ISBN 978-3-03911-909-7

Vol. 20 Ana Cruz García


Re(de-)generando identidades. Locura, feminidad y liberalización en
Elena Garro, Susana Pagano, Ana Castillo y María Amparo Escandón.
259 pages. 2009.
ISBN 978-3-03911-524-2
Vol. 21 Idoya Puig (ed.)
Tradition and Modernity. Cervantes’s Presence in Spanish
Contemporary Literature. 221 pages. 2009.
ISBN 978-3-03911-526-6

Vol. 22 Charlotte Lange


Modos de parodia. Guillermo Cabrera Infante, Reinaldo Arenas,
Jorge Ibargüengoitia y José Agustín. 252 pages. 2008.
ISBN 978-3-03911-554-9

Vol. 23 Claudio Canaparo


Geo-epistemology. Latin America and the Location of Knowledge.
284 pages. 2009.
ISBN 978-3-03911-573-0

Vol. 24 Jesús López-Peláez Casellas


“Honourable Murderers”. El concepto del honor en Othello
de Shakespeare y en los “dramas de honor” de Calderón.
321 pages. 2009.
ISBN 978-3-03911-825-0

Vol. 25 Marian Womack and Jennifer Wood (eds)


Beyond the Back Room. New Perspectives on Carmen Martín Gaite.
336 pages. 2011.
ISBN 978-3-03911-827-4

Vol. 26 Manuela Palacios and Laura Lojo (eds)


Writing Bonds. Irish and Galician Contemporary Women Poets.
232 pages. 2009.
ISBN 978-3-03911-834-2

Vol. 27 Myriam Osorio


Agencia femenina, agencia narrativa. Una lectura feminista de la obra
en prosa de Albalucía Ángel. 180 pages. 2010.
ISBN 978-3-03911-893-3

Vol. 28 Forthcoming
Vol. 29 Soledad Pérez-Abadín Barro
Cortázar y Che Guevara. Lectura de Reunión. 182 pages. 2010.
ISBN 978-3-03911-919-6

Vol. 30 Gonzalo Pasamar


Apologia and Criticism. Historians and the History of Spain,
1500–2000. 301 pages. 2010.
ISBN 978-3-03911-920-2

Vol. 31 Victoria Carpenter (ed.)


(Re)Collecting the Past. History and Collective Memory in Latin
American Narrative. 315 pages. 2010.
ISBN 978-3-03911-928-8

Vol. 32 Geneviève Fabry, Ilse Logie y Pablo Decock (eds.)


Los imaginarios apocalípticos en la literatura hispanoamericana
contemporánea. 472 pages. 2010.
ISBN 978-3-03911-937-0

Vol. 33 Julian Vigo


Performative Bodies, Hybrid Tongues. Race, Gender, Sex and
Modernity in Latin America and the Maghreb. 391 pages. 2010.
ISBN 978-3-03911-951-6

Vol. 34 Heike Pintor Pirzkall


La cooperación alemana al desarrollo. Factores condicionantes de su
transformación en la década de los noventa y su impacto en América
Latina. 374 pages. 2010.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0107-7

Vol. 35 Arturo Casas and Ben Bollig (eds)


Resistance and Emancipation. Cultural and Poetic Practices.
419 pages. 2011.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0160-2

Vol. 36 Forthcoming
Vol. 37 Guillermo Olivera
Laboratorios de la mediatización. La experimentación con materiales
mediáticos, la teoría y la crítica cultural argentina, 1965–1978.
364 pages. 2011.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0201-2

Vol. 38 Guy Baron


Gender in Cuban Cinema. From the Modern to the Postmodern.
334 pages. 2011.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0229-6

Vol. 39 Claudio Canaparo


El imaginario Patagonia. Ensayo acerca de la evolución conceptual del
espacio. 576 pages. 2011.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0287-6

Vol. 40 Inmaculada Murcia Serrano


Agua y destino. Introducción a la estética de Ramón Gaya.
220 pages. 2011.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0251-7

Vol. 41 Bill Richardson


Borges and Space. 266 pages. 2012.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0246-3

Vol. 42 Forthcoming

Vol. 43 Ann Frost


The Galician Works of Ramón del Valle-Inclán. Patterns of Repetition
and Continuity. 241 pages. 2010.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0242-5

Vol. 44 Milagros López-Peláez Casellas


What About the Girls? Estrategias narrativas de resistencia en la primera
literatura chicana. 265 pages. 2012.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0264-7
Vol. 45 Bill Richardson and Lorraine Kelly (eds)
Power, Place and Representation. Contested Sites of Dependence and
Independence in Latin America. 268 pages. 2012.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0710-9

Vol. 46 Patricia D’Allemand


José María Samper. Nación y cultura en el siglo XIX colombiano.
177 pages. 2012.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0288-3

Vol. 47 Forthcoming

Vol. 48 Emilio Rosales


Baroja. La novela como laberinto. 163 pages. 2012.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0774-1

Vol. 49 Kristine Vanden Berghe


Las novelas de la rebelión zapatista. 171 pages. 2012.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0779-6

Vol. 50 William Rowlandson


Borges, Swedenborg and Mysticism. 267 pages. 2013.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0811-3

Vol. 51 Elena Rodríguez-Guridi


Exégesis del “error”. Una reinterpretación de la praxis de escritura en
Libro de la vida, Novelas ejemplares y Desengaños amorosos.
175 pages. 2013.
ISBN 978-3-0343-0817-5

Potrebbero piacerti anche