Sei sulla pagina 1di 110

Routledge Critical Studies in Discourse

E dited by M ichelle M. L a z a r, National University of Singapore

Metaphor, Nation
1. Framing Discourse on the
Environment and the Holocaust
A Critical Discourse Approach -
Richard J. Alexander The Concept of the Body Politic
2. Language and the Market Society
Critical Reflections on Discourse and
Dominance
Gerlinde Mautner

3. Metaphor, Nation and the


Holocaust
The Concept of the Body Politic
Andreas Musolff Andreas Musolff

Routledge
Taylor & Francis Group
New York London
\c 3 [p

Contents

First published 2010


by Routledge
270 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016

Simultaneously published in the UK


by Routledge List o f Tables vii
2 Park Square, M ilton Park, Abingdon, Oxon 0X 14-4RN Acknowledgments ix

Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business 1 Introduction: Deadly Metaphors That Won’t Die? Bodies and
Parasites as Concepts of Political Discourse 1

© 2010 Taylor & Francis


The right of Andreas Musolff to be identified as author of this w ork has been asserted
PA R TI
by him in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents .
Act 1988.
2 The Cognitive Import of Metaphor in Nazi Ideology 11
Typeset in Sabon by IBT Global.
Printed and bound in the United States of America on acid-free paper by IBT Global.
3 Body, Nature and Disease as Political Categories in Mein
All rights reserved. N o part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised Kam pf 23
in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereaf­
ter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or
retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. 4 The Public Presentation and Reception of Anti-Semitic Imagery
in Nazi Germany 43
Trademark Notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trade­
marks, and are used only for identification and explanation w ithout intent to infringe. 5 Methodological Reflection: Body and Illness Metaphors in the
Evolution of Western Political Thought and Discourse 69
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Musolff, Andreas.
Metaphor, nation and the holocaust: the concept of the body politic / by Andreas PART II
Musolff.
p. cm. — {Routledge critical studies in discourse ; 3)
Includes bibliographical references and index. 6'J Solidarity and Hierarchy: The Body-State Metaphor in the
1. Discourse analysis—Political aspects. 2. Metaphor. 3. Analogy. 4. Holocaust, Middle Ages _ 81
Jewish {1939-1945) I. Tide.
P302.77.M874 2010
320 .0 1 '4 -d c2 2 7 Concepts of Healing the Body Politic in the Renaissance 99
2010002457 I IjW lVFRSlTY
8 From Political Anatomy to Social Pathology: Modern Scenarios
ISBN13: 978-0-415-80119-5 {hbk) of the Body Politic and its Therapy 107
ISBN13: 978-0-203-84728-2 {ebk) 560 (3i|
<SoD-Vw\(xn
vi Contents
9 German Conceptual and Discursive Traditions of the Body
Politic Metaphor 221 Tables
10 Conclusion: Metaphor in Discourse History 137

Notes 247
Bibliography 279
Index 299

3.1 Body-Nation NLappings in Mein Kampf 26

3.2 Event Structure of Body-Nation Mappings 27


3.3 Basic Scenario Structure of Body-Nation Mappings in Mein
Kampf 35
3.4 Extended Scenario Structure of Body-Nation Mappings in
Mein Kampf 40
6.1 Body-State Correspondences in Policraticus 88
6.2 Body-State Scenarios in Policraticus 88
8.1 Political Body Parts/Fluids in 109
8.2 Political Life Functions in 110
8.3 Political Illnesses/Diseases in 114
Acknowledgments

So many friends, colleagues and students have contributed to this book that
it is impossible to acknowledge them all by name. However, without the help
of some it would have been impossible to finish this book. Saskia Daalder,
my partner, put up with years of discussions about Holocaust ideology
and kept me from losing faith in the project. My colleague Felicity Rash
offered expert advice and read the final manuscript, greatly improving its
content and ordering. David Baguley, Edward Budaev, Jonathan Charteris-
Black, Carlo Caruso, Paul Chilton, David Cowling, Roslyn Frank, Rudiger
Corner, Zoltan Kovecses, Fiona MacArthur Purdon, Barbara Rosenbaum,
Josephine Tudor, Arachne and Philip van der Eijk, M artin Wengeler, Bet-
tina Ziegler and Jorg Zinken gave generously of their time, experience and
advice to help me in assembling and interpreting the material, and provided
constructive criticism and comments on draft chapters. Research leave
from Durham University, support by the Arts and Humanities Research
Board, and a Visiting Fellowship at Queen Mary University of London
were instrumental in finalising the book.
1 Introduction
Deadly Metaphors That Won’t Die?
Bodies and Parasites as Concepts of
Political Discourse

1.1 THE BODY POLITIC AND THE HOLOCAUST

The phrase body politic belongs to a field of cliched metaphors in English


that refer to political entities and issues in terms of bodily organs and func­
tions, such as head o f state, head o f government, long arm o f the law,
organ (of a party), sclerosis or tumour (of the body politic), heart o f Brit-
ain/Europe} It is used by British and American media and politicians, e.g.
in formulations such as “Europe could cease to be the cyanide in the British
body politic”; “voices in the body politic”; “disembowelling the body poli­
tic”, “campaign culture metastasize[d] throughout the entire body politic”.^
The Conservative politician and mayor of London, Boris Johnson, even
described himself tongue-in-cheek as “a mere toenail in the body politic”.^
In German public discourse, by comparison, the idea of society and/or
the nation or state as a body is perceived as highly problematic. The term
Volkskdrper (“people’s body”, or “national body”), in particular, is stigma­
tized. In 1998, for instance, the conservative German politician J. Schon-
bohm was heavily criticised for having invoked the ideal of a homogeneous
German “people’s body” as opposed to the notion of a “multi-cultural”
society in the public debate about immigration. According to one of his
critics, the notion of bodily homogeneity for the nation was likely to “kin­
dle the fire” of inter-ethnic conflict.^ Eight yeajsJater, an.aftieie4n the daily
newspaper Die Welt discussed the low birtlyfate in Germany under the title
“A hurt soul in the sick nation’s body [Volkskorper]”.^ Again, the notion of
the nation’s or the people’s body was viewed as alluding to “the German
traumata of the twentieth century”. Those who discussed demographic
decline in terms of a threat to the national body’s health were suffering, the
author asserted, from a hysteria similar to that which had motivated previ­
ous “bio-political” attempts to cure the people’s body.^ Evidently, the term
Volkskdrper still reminds parts of the German public of statements such as
the following which were made by Adolf Hitler and his propaganda chief
Joseph Goebbels in the 1920s and 1940s: - ^
2 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Introduction 3
[the Jew] has always been a parasite in the body o f other peoplesJ political entity is usually not considered to belong in the category of biolog­
ical bodies, and a group of people in it is not an illness or parasite. Hence,
1914 witnessed the last flicker of the national instinct for self-preserva­ the semantic transfer of bodily expressions to political and social issues
tion in opposition to the progressive paralysis o f our people's body.^ would appear to qualify for “metaphor” status. However, in regard of the
Nazi use of body-illness-parasite imagery, we have to take into account the
. . .th e Jew represents an infectious illness . .. Germany has no inten- fact that they applied it in a horrifically “literal” sense by trying to physi­
- tion of giving in to this Jewish threat but intends to oppose it in time, cally destroy and eliminate Jewish people. Neil Gregor has aptly put this
if necessary by the means of its most complete and radical extermin-, problem in the form of a paradox: “it is not possible to see in Mein Kampf
eh, elimination.^ . . . a set of plans or a blueprint for mass murder in any specific way. . . .
But, equally, we should not regard Hitler’s metaphors merely as metaphors:
Statements such as these, which were taken from Mein Kampf and from for him, they described reality.”^’ We thus seem to be dealing with a form
Goebbels’s infamous “total war” speech of 1943, were not just meant as of (discourse that is non-literal and at the same time “literal” (in a poignant
insults of Jewish people. They implied a genocidal policy that ended in the historical and political sense). How can this contradiction be resolved?
Holocaust: the victims were treated as if they were agents o f disease and One way of dealing with this dilemma would be to assume that the meta­
parasites that threatened the German national body's health and therefore phor of the supposed Jewish “race” as an illness or parasite on the German
had to be annihilated. Goebbels’s false start, Ausrott[-ung] {“extermina­ nation's body was known to be just part of propagandistic jargon both by its
tion”) in the third example, gives away his knowledge about the ongoing users (i.e. the Nazis) and its receivers (i.e. the German public and everyone
genocide but also illustrates the effort to avoid unequivocal references to within the reach of Nazi propaganda), and really meant something else, i.e.
killing and mass murder. The vague notion of “getting rid” of the victims, genocide. In this case, the metaphor could be assigned the same semantic
which is implied in the term Ausschaltung (“elimination”, “removal”), was status as euphemisms or camouflage words, such as deportation {Deporta­
meant to leave room for a non-genocidal interpretation. However, the met­ tion, Umsiedlung), special treatment (Sonderbehandlung) or final solution
aphor of an infectious illness leaves little doubt that a complete destruction {Endlosung), which the Nazis used in administrative or legal documents
of the agent o f the illness was envisaged, or else the supposed infection when referring to their murderous practices. Such camouflage vocabulary
would not be eradicated. The “logic” of the illness-cure imagery based was not primarily intended to be persuasive; rather, it was meant to misin­
on the body-state metaphor thus gives the lie to the dissimulating talk of form those who were deemed outsiders or enemies, depending on the partic­
“elimination”. ular circumstances and the phase of policy implementation. The “insiders”
How could the conceptualization of a socio-political entity as a human would know what was meant and needed no persuasion: the camouflage
body acquire such sinister connotations? Is it a specific historical phenom­ language was just a ruse to cover their tracks (and, perhaps, to suppress the
enon of German political culture in the 20th century? Or is the metaphor -perpetrators’ own troubling emotions of empathy or guilt).
inherently racist, suggesting as it does a physical/physiological concreteness If the bodylparasite metaphor complex as used by the Nazis were on a
of politics, which perhaps “lends itself” to physical “solutions” of any per­ par with such terminology it would not in fact be metaphorical. On closer
ceived problems? Should anyone who employs body-ielated metaphors in inspection, however, this interpretation seems implausible. Camouflage
politics be viewed as a potential advocate of genocide? These are some of terms such as final solution or removal referring to genocide are deliber­
the questions that this book will engage with, with a view to determining ately abstract, vague and general: they are d e sig i^ t<^ide any concrete,
the function of metaphor in political communication, i.e. the basic issue vivid form of reference. But denouncing a^foup of people as a parasite
of how a metaphorical concept can impact on people’s political perception and describing one’s nation as a body that is in danger o f perishing are not
and behaviour, even turn them into genocide perpetrators (or at least, pas­ abstract or vague descriptions; on the contrary, they are striking and spec­
sive bystanders). tacular. The statements that included such metaphors were not confined to
The imagery used by the Nazis to legitimize their genocidal policies incidental, infrejquent forms of “background” propaganda; as we shall see
provides us with an extreme “test-case”, so to speak, of a metaphor that in detail later, they were carefully crafted and presented as “highlights” in
was turned into the horrendous reality of World War and Holocaust. We the Nazi leaders’ speeches. Anyone living under the Nazi regime or being
may ask, however, whether we are dealing with a “metaphor” at all. Stan­ aware of it could not help but notice them as key elements of their ideol­
dard definitions of “metaphor” describe it as the designation of a meaning ogy and propaganda. The metaphor was recognised as a core belief held by
unit by words taken from a different domain of meaning. This definition all the leading Nazis. That still does not mean that people mistook it for
can seemingly be applied without great difficulty to our case: a social or a literal description of political issues, or else it would have been regarded
4 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Introduction 5
simply as a grotesque category mistake. So, if it was neither that nor a lie, BC and was handed down by historians and philosophers as a political les­
how can we describe its meaning, both as a semantic category and as a son to avoid a rebellion.’^ The fable tells the story of a rebellion against the
pragmatic, political tool to advocate genocide.^ belly by other “members” of the body, which is motivated by their anger
Some of the confusion about the semantic status of the bodylparasite over the injustice that the seemingly idle belly/stomach takes all nourish­
“metaphor” can be avoided if we follow the insights of modern metaphor ment. The rebellion ends in disaster because without the belly first receiving
theories that have developed a notion of metaphor as a cognitive “fram- and then redistributing all the food, the other members get no nourishment
- ing” strategy to provide access to innovative perspectives for the concep­ either and so the whole body perishes.’* The standard political application
tualisation and the discursive negotiation of all kinds of experience. In of the fable is a vindication of the ruler’s right to receive all the revenues
the metaphorical frame, new concepts are integrated into familiar sets of of the state, so that he in turn can allocate them (justly) to all other organs
assumptions about classifications of entities, events and actions and their of the body politic. One of its most famous formulations can be found in
evaluations. With regard to Nazi metaphors, we have to investigate the Shakespeare’s Coriolanus, where the Roman senator Menenius uses it to
frames that enabled their users to believe in assumptions that made the qujell a Plebeian rebellion:
project of murdering all Jewish people in Europe seem possible, justifiable
and necessary. It is this inferential cognitive link between assumptions Menenius: There was a time when all the body’s members/ Rebell’d
embodied in the “source” concepts of bodies, illnesses and parasites and against the belly; thus accused it:/That only like a gulf it did remain/ T
the political conclusions at the “target” level of genocidal ideology {and the midst o’ the body, idle and unactive,/ Still cupboarding the viand,
practice) that is at the centre of the first part of this study. In the follow­ never bearing/Like labour with the rest, . . . / The belly answered .. .
ing chapters I shall propose a cognitive analysis of the mappings of body- ‘True is it, my incorporate friends’, quoth he,/ ‘That I receive the gen­
illness-parasite concepts onto politics as they appear in key texts produced eral food at first,/ Which you do live upon; and fit it is;/ Because I am
by the Nazis and in documented contemporary reactions and comments, the store-house and the shop/ Of the whole body: but if you do remem­
with a view to establishing the conceptual and argumentative framework in ber,/ I send it through the rivers of your blood,/ Even to the court, the
which the Holocaust would appear as a national healing exercise to the per­ heart, to the seat o’ the brain;.. . /The senators of Rome are this good
petrators and their audience.^^ However, an analysis based on the corpus belly,/ And you the mutinous members;’^
of texts from the Nazi period itself can only show its synchronic structure
and function in its respective historical period. As we saw from our initial After having stopped the unruly crowd in their tracks by telling the fable,
examples, the same metaphor complex is still being used in public discourse Menenius singles out the leader of the rebellion (the “First Citizen” in the
but it carries a kind of historical index of being related to the Nazi period. play) for humiliation. He calls him the “great toe of this assembly” on
We therefore also need to look at its diachronic development. account of his “being one o’ the lowest, basest, poorest, Of this most wise
'rebellion” and still having the nerve to “[go] foremost”.^®The literal and
figurative “forwardness” of the toelFirst Citizen is thus utilized by Mene­
1.2 A METAPHOR WITH A PAST nius to isolate and ridicule him. Perhaps B. Johnson’s above-quoted self­
description as the “toenail of the body politic” was owed to his knowledge
To depict societies, states and/or nations as a body is a metaphoric fram­ of Shakespeare (and even intended to demonstrate that). Another incidence
ing that has a long and famous pedigree in the history of ideas. Histori­ of erudite reference to the “fable of the belly” c a n ^ f o u ^ i n ^ e autobiog­
cal overviews’^ locate its origins in pre-Socratic thinking and highlight a raphy of the painter Oskar Kokoschka (1886-1980), who described the last
first flourishing of such-metaphors in the writings of Plato and Aristotle decades of the Habsburg Empire before World War I as a time of continu­
(with The Republic and Timaios, Politics and On the movement o f animals ous crisis dufing which the various nationalities “forgot the parable of the
being the respective key texts). They were followed by a series of Hellenistic Roman statesman that body members which are separated from the body
and Roman philosophers, the Stoics, Neoplatonists and mixed with Bibli­ are not capable of life”.^’
cal traditions {especially St. Paul’s Epistles to the Romans and Corinthi­ Such implicit or explicit “inter-textual” allusions are not essential, how­
ans), which were taken up by the “Church Fathers” and many political and ever, for the understanding of the metaphor. Any competent adult speaker
social theorists from the early Middle Ages onwards, continuing up to the of English and German can in principle make sense of Johnson’s and Koko­
twentieth century. schka’s statements or other uses of body imagery in politics without mak­
Closely connected is the tradition of the so-called “fable of the belly”, ing the connection to the tradition of the fable. After all, the knowledge
which has its beginnings in Aesopian texts dating back to the fifth century that body parts cannot normally exist if separated from the whole body.
6 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Introduction 1
and that toes or toenails are less important body members than, say, the understand allusions to the Nazi uses, which seems to indicate that some
head, belongs to our everyday “encyclopaedic” and practical knowledge of kind of a “discourse memory” relating to Nazi-typical metaphors still exists.
the world. Shakespearean scholars and conceptual historians will of course Right-wing and Neo-Nazi groups still make use of bodylparasite imagery as
recognise the image and reconstruct the links with ancient and modern if nothing had happened, so to speak,^^ but this lack of distance from Nazi
uses to further its understanding, but this happens at a secondary level of jargon has probably helped to bar them from having a significant influence
interpretation. It may add to the intellectual and aesthetic appreciation of on post-war German political culture. The public judgement that a person or
- the text in question but it is not needed for the basic understanding of the political group uses terminology and imagery comparable to that employed
metaphor. by the Nazis still serves as a powerful stigmatisation.^^ For German politi­
Clearly, the Nazis and their audience did not have to rely on a two- cians, to invoke body-parasite imagery when dealing with socio-political and
thousand-year-old philosophical tradition to motivate their wish to mur­ ethnic conflicts and to feign ignorance of the Nazi precedent is disingenu­
der all Jewish people in Europe. Like the interdependence and the relative ous and/or potentially self-defeating as long as they want to remain part of
importance of parts of the body, the dangers of illness and the benefits of the mainstream public political discourse.^^ So, why do body-illness-parasite
a cure are common knowledge, and racists of 'all times have employed that metaphors continue to be employed? By looking at the long-term history of
knowledge to denounce their enemies as agents o/'(political/social) disease. body-based political thought and discourse we hope to find answers to this
This does not, however, exclude the possibility that a special, vulgarised question; i.e. we not only try to understand the reasons for its historical “suc­
version of some of the theoretical and textual traditions mentioned earlier cess” in persuading a majority the German public to participate in or at least
was accessed around the turn of the last century by Hitler and other Nazi tolerate the Holocaust but also the role that body-based metaphors generally
ideologues, in a way similar to the pseudo-scientific theories on human play in current racist discourse and thought.
“races” that influenced Hitler during his formative years in Vienna and Given the vastness of the material, the selection of textual and concep­
Munich.^^ They co.uld in fact hardly have existed without the input from tual traditions presented here can only claim to be a sample of the huge field
an "authoritative” tradition that had already established the metaphorical of research (a cautious first estimate based on conceptual history research
concept of the body, its organs and functions and its state of health as a indicates the existence of at least 250 primary key texts ranging from antiq­
model for thinking and talking about politics. These beliefs would have uity to present-day texts in several European languages). The following
provided the semantic-ideological space in which Hitler’s political body chapters can thus not claim to be representative but only aim at providing
and parasite metaphors could resonate. insights into major continuities and discontinuities of the various strands
In order to substantiate this hypothesis, we have to investigate those of this metaphor leading up to {and beyond) its instrumentalisation by the
strands of the metaphor tradition that are most likely to have informed the Nazis. Some of these traditions were, as we shall see, explicitly connected
sedimented political assumptions in the early twentieth century, in par­ to Nazi ideology, others seem to have only implicit and fragmentary links,
ticular, conceptual and textual traditions of body politic theories and dis­ and further strands even point to the ideological opposite of racism-, i.e. an
cussions in German-speaking political culture. German traditions of this enlightened, tolerant vision of society and politics.
metaphor complex have been less well researched than, for instance, the The chapters are roughly ordered as follows. In the chapter introduc­
English- and French-speaking histories; it has even been claimed that Ger­ ing Part I we establish the methodological implications of the cognitively
man political literature lacked the equivalent of body politic imagery.^^ As oriented approach to metaphor analysis through its comparison with tradi­
we shall see later on, this assumption is unwarranted; in fact, the tradition tional analyses of Nazi imagery as a “mere” rhetorical trick that was inci­
of corporeal imagery in German political philosophy and discourse can be dental to Hitler’s ideology and actual policy. By c o h tra s ^ u r analysis tries
traced back to the early sixteenth century, i.e. to the same time when the to demonstrate that his body-illness-parasite metaphors provided not just
phrase body politic itself became established in England and when similar a propaganda ornament but were at the core of his racist ideology. Chapter
terminological and conceptual developments took place in other European 3 studies this conceptual core in detail by way of a close reading of Hitler’s
languages and political cultures. statements on race in Mein Kampf; Chapter 4 investigates how the Nazi
These long-standing metaphor traditions not only informed the popular ideologues and propagandists announced and presented the genocide as a
attitudes and opinions of the period until 1945; they still exert an influence therapy for the German national body while they were in power. Chapter
on current discourse, albeit as an undercurrent that is overlaid, as it were, by 5 provides a methodological reflection of the results of our analyses and
the -stigma-laden meniory of the use of illness/parasite imagery in Nazi ideol­ relates them to the second part, which investigates the body-state meta­
ogy. As we saw in the few examples from contemporary German discourse phor’s roots in Western cultural history. Chapters 6-9 proceed in a loosely
quoted earlier, journalists and politicians still expect the German public to chronological order from the Middle Ages through the Renaissance to the
8 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
twentieth century and provide cross-references to conceptual strands taken
up by the Nazis. The last chapter discusses the implications of this history
for the assessment of the -body-based political metaphors in creating and
shaping racist attitudes.
2 The Cognitive Import of
Metaphor in Nazi Ideology’

This chapter approaches the cognitive dimension of Nazi anti-Semitic


imagery by reviewing historical and linguistic research on Nazi discourse.
Much of post-war research treated the Nazis’ metaphors and other facets
of their political discourse either as “demagogic”, “manipulative” abuses
of language or as “literally” true expressions of racist ideology. Both these
approaches highlight important aspects but, apart from contradicting each
other, neither of them explains the extraordinary public appeal of the Nazi
anti-Semitic imagery, its seeming plausibility and conclusiveness, which
made the implementation of its genocidal implications in the Holocaust
possible. This aspect has been brought to the fore in recent cognitive studies
which have proposed various avenues of investigating the “mapping” and/
or “blending” mechanisms involved in constructing the Nazi image of “the
Jew” as a parasite; they provide a platform for the systematic analysis of
Hitler’s body-based imagery as a cognitive framework for genocide legiti­
mization in the subsequent chapters.

2.1 HITLER’S METAPHORS AS OBJECTS OF


HISTORICAL AND POLITICAL STUDY

Hitler and the Nazis’ use of imagery has been an object of comment and
analysis since the 1930s.^ One highlight of the early crr^al.anaiyses was
Kenneth Burke’s 1939 essay “The Rhetoric "of Hitler’s ‘Battle’”, which
focused on Hitler’s technique of “projecting” a religious category, i.e. the
devil, onto a “visible, point-to-able form of people with a certain kind of
‘blood’”.^ According to Burke, this transfer of religious categories onto the
socio-political level enabled Hitler to present his genocidal plans against
“the Jew” as a promise of purification.^ In the following chapter we shall
argue that the “religious” projection aspect is only a secondary part of
the system of metaphors that Hitler operated and, thus relativise Burke’s
conclusions to some extent. It is, however, important to recognize that, in
highlighting the “projection” strategy, Burke provided an early model for
an integrated analysis of content and style features of the “Rhetoric” of
12 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust The Cognitive Import o f Metaphor in Nazi Ideology 13
Mein Kampfth&t pointed to a deeper understanding of the Nazis’ cognitive technical devices of vermin extinction, such as poison gas. In his seminal
framing strategies. study of “Hitler’s world-view”, Eberhard Jackel concluded that Hitler, in his
Soon after the war, two studies of Nazi discourse appeared in the occu­ plans to eliminate the Jews, the "incurably ill” and all those he held respon­
pied zones of Germany: one was entitled “The Language of the Third sible for Germany’s defeat in WWI as laid out in Mein Kampf “indubitably
Reich” {LTI, short for Latin Lingua Tertii Imperii) by the Holocaust sur­ meant what he said quite literally”.’^Similarly, Hermann Greive, in his over­
vivor and Romance philologist Victor Klemperer;^ the other was a series view of the history of modern anti-Semitism, speaks of “bloody seriousness”
' of articles by the political scientists and journalists Gerhard Storz, Dolf {der blutige Ernst), which “cannot be argued away”.’*’
Sternberger and Walter E. Siiskind, which was later re-edited as the “Dic­ Such “literalness” can, however, be understood either as seriousness of
tionary of Inhumanity” {Worterbuch des Unmenschen).^ The main theo­ hateful intent or, in a more tenuous sense, as a weird “category mistake” that
retical paradigm of these and most of the following interpretations was the literally confused the domains of humans and of (non-human) animals,’^
conception of metaphor as a device of manipulative propaganda. In LTI, due to the fanatical ideology held by the Nazis. Such an extreme stance is
Klemperer cites Hitler’s bio-imagery in detail, including that of “the Jew” psychologically improbable and, as the following chapters will show, is far
as a maggot in the rotting corpse or as pestilence and he identifies as its too simplistic to account for the conceptual range and textual/argumentative
sources Hitler’s early political idols, the Austrian politicians Karl Lueger elaboration of Hitler’s metaphor system. However, in principle it is conceiv­
(1844-1910) and Georg von Schonerer (1842-1921).^ Their and his “sty­ able, and it seems that Daniel Jonah Goldhagen, in his bestselling book Hit­
listic device” [Stilform) of combining utmost “derision” and panic “ter­ ler's Willing Executioners: Ordinary Germans and the Holocaust, comes
ror” was, in Klemperer’s assessment, proof of their “primitive” xenophobic close to taking such a “category mistake” view when he labels the “organic
instincts; and its success in Nazi Germany depended on the affinity of these metaphors of decomposition” by which the Nazis referred to Jews a “set of
instincts with those of the “dumbest masses” in Germany.® As these masses cognitions”,’'^albeit ones that were “absolutely fantastical, the.sort of beliefs
were assumed to form the majority of the populace, no further explanation that ordinarily only madmen have of others”.”' He also maintains that the
of Hitler’s propagandistic success as such was needed; what remained to do product of this belief, i.e. “eliminationist” racial anti-Semitism, was shared
was to enlighten and educate the misguided populace, so that xenophobic by the vast majority of “ordinary Germans” of the day as an uncontested
rhetoric and imagery would never again have a chance of success.^ “cultural model”, which only had to be “channelled in a genocidal direction
Motivated by a broadly similar aim, Storz, Sternberger and Siiskind and activated” by the Nazis to be implemented in Holocaust.’®Goldhagen’s
analyse key words that indicate the inhuman spirit of Nazism and its legacy: methodology and his conclusions have been criticized by historians;’^ for our
the jargon of political management and administration that treats people purposes its most significant aspect is its assumption of a cognitive frame­
as objects rather than as agents. Metaphors play no prominent role in the work of “eliminatory anti-Semitism” that governed the thoughts and actions
dictionary-style word-explanations, but the authors give an in-depth analy­ of tens of millions of people. This constitutes the maximum position, as it
sis of the cynical assumptions underlying the terminology of “dealing with” were, of a stance that takes Hitler’s racist metaphor system literally and in
humans such as betreuen, behandeln, sonderbehandeln (“care for”, “treat”, addition assumes its cognitive domination over the whole of the German
“give special treatment”), which referred to acts of persecution and murder.’® nation up until 1945. By taking Nazi pronouncements at face value, Goldha­
The underlying semantic transfer from the domain of dealing with inanimate gen short-circuits the problem of determining the eliminationist “set of cogni­
and animate objects to that of engaging with humans can be viewed as a tions” that was expressed in Nazi imagery. He presupposes a “wild, ‘magical
“metaphorical” cognitive operation, but this aspect is not discussed in detail thinkir^’” on the part of the Nazi leadership and the Gerniau people and an
by the authors; they focus instead on its manipulative function and criticise “incapacity for ‘reality testing’” that “generally distinguishes them from the
its continued use after 1945, for instance, in administrative, advertising and perpetrators of other mass slaughters”.^®
media language. ” Further studies of Nazi discourse and vocabulary from the This presupposition is, however, by no means self-evident. After all,
following decades, which included racist metaphors, have further elucidated at least up until 1933, the German public did have access to competing
their historical origins and specific applications in detail, but did not tran­ media, political statements and ideological frameworks. “Eliminationist
scend significantly the “imagery-as-propaganda rhetoric” paradigm.’^ anti-Semitism” was one among many stances on racial and social issues,
It was therefore left mainly to historians to highlight the fact that, once in doubtless prominent among the Nazi movement, but not among the gen­
power, the Nazis tailored their “real” actions to Hitler’s illness/parasite met­ eral public. Even if we assume, for argument’s sake, that the Nazi view of
aphors by “literally” murdering millions of Jewish people and other groups the necessity to eliminate the Jewish “parasite” became consensus during
they deemed to be “not worthy to be alive”. They treated their victims as the Third Reich, this had to be achieved by a campaign of persuasion—
if they were indeed non-human “parasite” organisms, even using similar which brings us back to the manipulation/propaganda hypothesis. That
14 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust The Cognitive Import of Metaphor in Nazi Ideology 15
such a sustained propaganda campaign did in fact take place is not in any In his analysis, Hawkins focuses on Hitler’s characterisation of the Jews
way contentious;^’ what is in question is the issue of its cognitive impact as “black parasites” along three “iconographic frames of reference”—the
or “success”. light/colour spectrum, the Great Chain o f Being, and the Human Body. As
In order to investigate (rather than presume) a genocidal “set of cogni­ regards the first dimension, he highlights the perceptual-physiological and
tions” on the basis of Hitler’s imagery, we have to explain what we mean by cultural values that are associated with the colour contrast black-white:
characterising it as "cognition” in the first place. This problem has gener­ whiteness is causally linked to the experience of sunlight and with life (as
ated a substantial body of research over the past decades, which has spe­ its effect) and hence with positive emotions; its opposite, i.e. blackness, is
cifically focused on metaphors as cognitive phenomena. From the cognitive associated with death and negative emotions and experiences (as reflected
viewpoint, metaphors and other so-called “rhetorical” figures of speech in many idioms such as black sheep, blackmail, etc.).^* Goatly (2007) has
such as metonymy, simile, etc., are more than stylistic “ornaments” that pointed out a further link in regard to the conceptual metaphor goodness is
add some extra associative or emotional value to the “core meaning” of purity: a white surface is considered to be spoilt if there are black marks on
a proposition. Instead, they are seen as fundamental cognitive processes, it.j^ Any mixing of “pure” substances, including human “races”, can thus
i.e. as “mappings”^^ or “blendings”^^ of conceptual inputs from varying be conceptualized as an act of pollution and defilement.^''
domains, which provide new perspectives for categorizing and reasoning This metaphorical white-black opposition is routinely projected onto
about our experiences. stereotyped skin colours of humans by racists. However, this does not
As regards the critical analysis of political language use, this claim by explain the blackness of Jewish people in Hitler’s anti-Semitic metaphor
cognitivists to go beyond “rhetorical” analysis is of particular significance. system. Hitler, as a racist of his time, also held white supremacist views,
If metaphors structure our worldviews, they are clearly of fundamental but there is no indication in Mein Kampf t)i3X Jews are portrayed as being
importance in political ideology and their critical analysis can provide on the same racial level as African people. The latter, labelled “Negroes”
“particular insight into why the rhetoric of political leaders is successful”.^*' (German: Neger), were deemed to be inferior and only capable, as “cul­
Hitler’s imagery in Mein Kam pf has therefore been made the object of a ture-carriers” {Kulturtrdger), of assisting higher races (first and foremost
number of studies that claim to provide a specifically cognitive analysis, Aryans) in their “culture-building” {kulturschaffend) work.^’ The many
which goes beyond the earlier studies discussed earlier. disparaging remarks in Mein Kampf about “Negroes” clearly show that
they occupy the bottom rank of Hitler’s hierarchy of races.H ow ever, they
are not on the same level with the “Jews”. The “Negroes” appear as hapless
2.2 HITLER’S ANTI-SEMITIC ILLNESS/PAJRASITE IMAGERY AS beings, slavishly obeying whichever master is in charge.
A “COGNITIVE MODEL” OF DISCRIMINATORY IDEOLOGY The “Jews”, by contrast, are depicted not just as an inferior race but as
the Aryans’ irredeemable opposite, the “destroyer of culture” {Kulturzer-
Recent cognitively oriented publications often focus on Hitler’s anti-Semitic storer) in world h isto ry .T h ey are even blamed for cunningly “bringing
imagery as a kind of negative yardstick of racist or discriminatory ideology. the Negro to the Rhine” (during the allied occupation of the Rhineland),
Hawkins (2001), for instance, envisages a “cognitive sociolinguistics” that in order to precipitate the racial downfall of the Germans.^*’ Unlike the
“can help us understand how ca.tegorization is manipulated to establish supposedly “naive”, passive Negro races, the Jewish “race” was regarded
social dynamics which privilege certain groupings of experience and dis­ by Hitler as an active force of evil. No constructive relationship was con­
miss other such groupings”.^^ He views “iconographic reference”'as such a ceivable between Aryans and Jews, not even ^atof^ajlculm rerbuilding”
technique of manipulative categorization, i.e. the use of “simplistic images master race towards slaves. Furthermore, Jn contradiction to the colour
of our experiences” that are associated with “familiar values”, with the aim frame, non-Jewish people who were seen as enemies of the Nazi state could
of establishing “a powerful conceptual link between the referent and a par­ be denounced as “white Jews”, e.g. academics who had not distanced them­
ticular value judgment”.^^ Among the examples he discusses is a translated selves sufficiently from “Jewish” emigrant scientists such as Albert Einstein,
text passage from Mein Kampf, quoted after Bosmajian’s The Language o f as happened in an article published under the title “White Jews in Science”
Oppression (1983): {Weifle Juden in der Wissenschaft) in the SS journal “The Black Corps”
{Das schwarze Korps).^^ As the very title of this journal (and the uniform of
This contamination of our people is carried on systematically by the the SS) suggests, blackness was in certain contexts an attractive symbol for
Jew today. Systematically these black parasites of the nation defile o^r the Nazis themselves. These special aspects of what one might call “Nazi
inexperienced young blonde girls and thereby destroy something that aesthetics” do not invalidate Hawkins’s cognitive analysis of the standard
can no longer be replaced in this world. associations of colour-based “iconographic references” that inform racist
16 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust The Cognitive Import of Metaphor in Nazi Ideology 17
ideologies, but they do show that in the specific case of National Socialist US politicians’ rhetoric in the “war against terror” that portrayed terror­
im apry, citing a few “fitting” text passages is not sufficient evidence to ists as ‘“parasites’ in need of total elimination”."*"*Again, the Nazi example
motivate generalising conclusions that they have the same conceptual basis serves as a warning from history concerning the cognitive impact of racist
as other forms of racism. What is needed instead is a comprehensive survey imagery, with an implicit appeal to avoid its genocidal consequences that
of the metaphor system operated by Hitler and other leading Nazis, to pro­ were so starkly realized in the Holocaust. It is, of course, tempting to use
vide a basis on which their public reception can be assessed. the Nazis’ racist metaphor system, on account of its “literal” genocidal
Besides the colour frame, the Aryan-Jew contrast is integrated, accord­ application as an “example” of the worst possible outcome of denigrating,
ing to Hawkins, into two further iconographic frames: the Great Chain discriminating rhetoric and to highlight their alignment of various frames
o f Being and the human body. In referring to the Great Chain o f Being, of hierarchical social ordering as evidence of their extraordinarily vicious
Hawkins builds on Lakoff and Turner’s (1989) analysis of that concept racism. However, as indicated already in the discussion of blackness as a
complex as a cultural model that concerns kinds of beings and their prop­ racist category of denigration, the cognitive motivation of standard racist
erties and places them on a vertical scale”.^^ This cultural model, which associations is not sufficient to identify the specific character of Nazi imag­
has its roots in ancient philosophy, is still “indispensable to our under­ ery. Likewise, the claims that parasite status in the modern version of the
standing of ourselves, our world, and our language” to d a y .I n its “clas­ Great Chain o f Being defines “the Jew” in Nazi imagery is a proposition
sic versions, the Chain o f Being connected the various levels of creation, that has to be critically analysed rather than presumed.
ranging from heavenly “bodies” (stars etc.) to socio-political “bodies” (the
Christian Church, worldly kingdoms and social estates) to the sub-human
sphere of animals, plants and even inorganic matter. The different levels 2.3 HITLER’S MEINKAMPF AS A TWISTED
were graded in value but also continuous with each other, and each was VERSION OF THE GREAT CHAIN OF BEING}
indispensable for the balance and plenitude of the cosmos.^® The Chain
o j Being’s "continuity-within-discontinuity” allowed for correspondences By providing a searchable database and a systematic overview over the
“between macrocosm, body politic, and microcosm”,w h i c h in turn made whole range of metaphors in Hitler’s Mein Kam pf Felicity Rash (2005a, b,
it possible to explain events on one level (e.g. upheavals in society and poli­ 2006) has given a new empirical grounding to political metaphor research
tics) in terms of another level (e.g. extraordinary movements of the stars in general and the study of Hitler’s imagery in particular. By relating Hit­
or animal behaviour). Hawkins points out that in the Nazi version of the ler’s metaphors to idioms and further lexicographic and phraseological evi­
Chain o f Being as a hierarchy of human races, “Aryan Germans assiime the dence, and by contrasting the German original text with its main English
lofty status of superhumans”, whereas “the Jews are reduced iconographi- translations, as well as by indicating Hitler’s borrowings from Houston
cally to subhuman beings, ‘parasites’”, which makes them "at best . . . a Stuart Chamberlain and Richard Wagner’s writings. Rash provides an
lower animal”, "at w o rst. . . a plant of some kind”.'^'' This corresponds to excellent basis for all further in-depth discourse analysis of Hitler’s work.
the colour hierarchy with “pure” whiteness at the top and blackness at the First of all, she has convincingly shown that almost none of the metaphors
bottom.”*^ that Hitler employed were particularly original; on the contrary, they either
The third aspect of “body iconography” adds a further “measure of the consisted of well-worn phrases and idioms that were used in general parlance
negativity” to the lowly status of parasites in the Chain, because in popular or were prefigured in anti-Semitic and xenophobic hate speech well before
understanding parasites “maintain life within their own bodies by sucking Hitler’s time."*^ Relying on the Lakoff/Johnson model of cognitive metaphor
life-sustaining nutrients out of some other body”.''^ Hawkins thus identifies analysis. Rash groups the metaphor material oiMein main
the parasite-host body relationship as a further crucial source concept that groups: “Container Metaphors”, “Metaphoj-s of Location and Movement”,
motivated the Holocaust, for, from the Nazi point of view, the German host and the “Great Chain of Being”. Of these, it is the last group that she inves­
nation was perfectly entitled to defend itself against the dangerous "Jew­ tigates in most detail and observes that “^as we descend through the hierar­
ish” parasite. This extreme form of stigmatization can be found, according chy of THE GREAT CHAIN OF BEING we notice among the images used a higher
to Hawkins, not just in Nazi ideology but also in present-day media, and proportion of metaphors referring to Jews.”^®Rash states that “Hitler’s most
It IS with regard to such topical cases that “cognitive sociolinguistics” can repulsive metaphors are his most imaginative . . . and distinctive”, i.e. of Jews
enlighten the public about the dangers of racist iconographies."*^ as “slime, maggots, bacteria”, which- epitomizes Hitler’s depraved view of
In a similar vein, Charteris-Black (2005) regards “European fascist dis­ the world."*^ The main “creative” aspect in Hitler’s use of Chain o f Being
course of the twentieth century” and, specifically, the Nazi conceptualiza­ imagery to denigrate Jews thus lies in its intensity, underscored by repetition,
tion of “Jews” as parasitic animals as a prototype for more recent uses, e.g. hyperbole and combination with “personification”."** So, one might ask, is
18 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust The Cognitive Import o f Metaphor in Nazi Ideology 19
there anything at all that significantly distinguishes Hitler’s use of the Chain appear at first sight to tie in with it cannot be interpreted as evidence of
o f Being metaphor complex from other racist applications? any “straightforward” application of that notion. A “discontinuous chain”
Rash points to a specific aspect of Hitler’s Chain o f Being imagery that of races in a “complete” universe, which must nevertheless be rid of one
is overlooked if one only wants to find evidence of its general racist applica­ of these races—these implications of Hitler’s metaphor use are conceptu­
tions. His metaphors are based on an absolute contrast rather than a graded ally neither coherent in terms of their source concepts nor consistent with
difference between Germans and Jews: “The original great chain was any systematic version of the Chain o f Being notion.^^ This negative result
characterized by the principle of ‘continuity’ . .. each level in the chain is does not invalidate the identification of the Chain o f Being as a frame of
seamlessly connected with the next level. .. Hitler, on the other hand, pro­ reference in which to place Hitler’s anti-Semitism, but it serves as a warn­
claimed a discontinuity between Aryan and Jew: there was a gulf between ing against premature inferences from isolated text passages. Hitler picked
the two, one race being good and the otheT evil.”'*^ This finding confirms a and chose the source notions of animal and body hierarchies that suited
conclusion from our earlier discussion of the cognitive import of the black him to depict the target concepts of various human races. Within this ad
status of Jews: Hitler may have agreed with some kind of “continuity” of hoc framework, images of Jews as black parasites, agents o f illness or of
human races (starting at the top with the Aryan race, of which the German decomposition from the bottom ranks of the Chain o f Being metaphor
nation was supposed to have the largest stock, down to “primitive races” stock could be employed to arouse revulsion and hatred, but that did not
such as “Negroes”), but this hierarchy, which was racist enough in a gen­ commit him to assume continuity or plenitude of the universe as he wanted
eral sense, did not include the Jewish “race”. Jews were utterly disqualified to shape it in his mind. This is, after all, what the conceptual structure of
from being part of the Great Chain: they were outside/off any conceivable metaphor as a “perspective” makes possible: it is not a static notion or set
continuum that would connect them with the Aryans races. of notions that is blindly “copied” from one domain to another but a flex­
Thus, even if Hitler’s metaphorical characterisations of “the Jew” as ible cognitive “frame of reference” in which conceptual variation, innova­
lowly creatures resembled traditional Chain o f Being hierarchy, they were tion and reinterpretation are possible.
explicitly re-interpreted in Mein K am pf in such a way that they contra­
dicted the “continuity” principle of the Chain o f Being (and, implicitly,
the very notion of a Chain, as it is continuous by definition). In fact. 2.4 NAZI METAPHORS AS “VIRUSES OF THE MIND”
Hitler’s metaphors had little to do with the classic tradition of the Great
Chain o f Being idea as analysed by Arthur O. Lovejoy (1936). Lovejoy Variation phenomena in metaphorical and other cognitive structures have
had told the history of this idea as if it was the “life story” spanning been given special prominence in the Conceptual “Blending Theory”, a
almost two millennia, from its Platonist and Aristotelian beginnings, more recent version of cognitive metaphor theory that has been developed
through the reformulations in Neoplatonist, medieval and Renaissance by Gilles Fauconnier and Mark Turner.^^ Rather than assuming binary
philosophy up to the late eighteenth century and to early evolution theory. relationships of “source”-”target” mappings between perceptual and cpn-
At the core of the tradition lay, according to Lovejoy, a “conception of the ceptual domains, they operate a more flexible theory of “mental spaces”
universe” that was “composed of an immense . .. number of links rang­ that serve as “input” into the “conceptual integration” mechanisms that
ing in hierarchical order from the meagerest kind of existents . . . through characterize the workings of the human mind. The input spaces can be
‘every possible’ grade up to the e_ns perfectissimum''J^Loveioy identified more than two and, crucially, they are seen as giving rise not only to a
three basic principles that formed the conceptual core of this philosophi­ “generic” network that encompasses the shared concepttlal'sfructure of the
cal tradition; besides “continuity”- and “gradation”, it included also the input spaces but also to a “blended space”^"that contains new, “emergent”
principle of “plenitude”, i.e. the concept that all parts of the universe— structure when different or even contradictory input frames are merged:
from the “lowest” to the “highest”—were necessary, in a logical as well “[the input spaces and their] organizing frames make central contribu­
as ontological sense, to its being well-ordered and complete.^’ Compared tions to the blend, and their sharp differences offer the possibilities of rich
with this vision. Hitler’s hate-filled view of “the Jew” as the absolute clashes” which present “challenges to the imagination: indeed, the resulting
“Other” of the Aryans that had to be destroyed if they were to survive blends can be highly creative”.^**
not only violated the notion of continuity, as pointed out by Rash, but Paul Chilton (2005) makes use of this concept of conceptual blending in
also the principle of plenitude: for him, the universe was “complete” in a his analysis of the “race” chapter in Mein Kampf (Chapter 11 of volume
positive sense only without “the Jew”. 1). One key example of the emergence of an ideological blending in Hitler’s
In view of the violation of two out of three principles of the traditional text is the cumulative effect of equivocations between biological and social
Chain o f Being notion, the “iconographic references” in Mein Kampf thax categorizations of “the Jew”, as in the following passage:
20 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust The Cognitive Import o f Metaphor in Nazi Ideology 21
[The Jew] was never a nomad, but only and always a parasite in the the standard model of genetic mutation, and this likens concept evolution,
body of other peoples. That he sometimes left his previous living space in Sperber’s view, to that of viruses rather than to that of genes.D aw kins
has nothing to do with his own purpose, but results from the fact that and others have also adapted the virus analogy: viruses, as parasitic rep­
from time to time he was thrown out by the host nations he had mis­ licators at the genetic level, can be applied to the domains of technology
used. His spreading is a typical phenomenon for all parasites; he always and psychology, e.g. in the metaphors of “computer viruses” or of “mind
seeks a new feeding ground {Ndhrboden) for his race.^^ viruses” that infect whole human groups and populations driving them to
destructive behaviour.^^The example of Nazi ideology as such a mind virus
Chilton points out that “the first occurrence of he is associated not just with is again mentioned by Dawkins, alongside other instances of racism and
‘the Jew’, but with a blended concept: Jew-parasite, or some such”, and “the religious fanaticism.^'*
successive clauses predicate actions and properties that are metaphorically But like the gene-meme analogy, the virus metaphor has to be used with
isomorphic with the actions and properties of biological parasites”.^^ The care, as its meaning oscillates between scientific and colloquial registers
Jew-parasite blend is thus built up and reinforced grammatically within the and it suggests easy generalisations that gloss over important empirical dif­
text so that its chances of becoming a memorable notion are maximised. ferences. In common language, the term virus has negative connotations on
Once the blend is established, it can be filled in further within the “disease account of its connection with illness (and is therefore a favourite source
and medicine frames” and their specific “aetiologies”: it then “follows” concept for racist and xenophobic metaphors). In biological terms, how­
in the blend that the “host people” are in danger of dying out if they are ever, viruses are seen as types of non-cellular life forms that are “parasitic”
overrun by a parasite, and “that the fatal disease caused in the host can be in the sense that they depend for their reproduction on other organisms.
cured by removing it or destroying the parasite”.^^ Due to the continuous Inasmuch as ideologies depend on human brains to entertain and (re-)pro-
build-up of the socio-biological blending, the “parasite actually is the Jew duce them, they can be considered to be “parasitic” in this latter sense, but
in the blend, not ‘mere metaphor’ This analysis goes some way towards so are all other types of concepts, regardless of whether they are useful
resolving the “literally-understood” metaphor paradox mentioned in the or harmful.- Apart from the irony that Nazi racism may itself be labelled
preceding chapter. From the cognitive perspective, the blended concept a viruSf the analogy appears to be of limited explanatory value for the
Jew-parasite has an underlying metaphoric structure but at the same time analysis of their specific ideology and its propagandists success.
it is condensed sufficiently to be memorable as a seemingly substantive, It seems, for instance, doubtful whether the strong textual coherence in
“real” concept. Mein Kampf, which Chilton has so convincingly demonstrated in his close
Chilton builds on this analysis to explain why Hitler was so horren­ reading of Chapter 11, is conclusive evidence of its conceptual “meme”-or
dously successful in propagating his blended bio-social/political worldview. “virus”-status. In order to connect Hitler’s representation of the Jew/
He links the results of his close reading of the key passages from Mein parasite concept with the representations of the readers, Chilton assumes
Kampf with the “naturalist” approach to cultural history developed by that the notion of “parasites” (and connected aetiological and therapeu­
Richard Dawkins, Susan Blackmore, Dan Sperber and others.^^ In his 1976 tic aspects) was readily available for the recipients: “conceptual constructs
bestseller The Selfish Gene, Dawkins had proposed a view of cultural con­ become meme-like and ‘infect’ the mind (under the right social condi­
structs as “replicators” in analogy to genetic replication and had coined the tions) when they have complex blending potential that recruits fundamen­
neologism “meme” for this cultural gene equivalent.^° Dawkins’s analogy is tal knowledge domains along with the core mechanisms of metaphor.”^^
based on a complex metaphor: not only is the meme conceived of as a hypo­ The qualifying specification of the “right socialj:5nditions!lioirL.triggering
thetical cultural counterpart of the gene, but the latter is itself viewed meta­ an actual “mind-infection” reintroduces the'laistorical dimension that the
phorically as a “selfish” agent. In view of the tenuousness of the analogy, memetic/naturalist approach promised to bypass. If “mental” meme/virus
Dan Sperber (1996, 2000) has demanded a reorientation of the “memetic” status is dependent on social conditions, its cognitive framing and textual
approach, chiefly on the grounds that cultural constructs, including con­ pf-esentation by the speaker are at best pre-conditions for its success, but
ceptual representations, depend for their propagation on inter-personal not sufficient conditions in themselves.
communication. Unlike biological evolution, the evolution of concepts' is Moreover, it is also debatable whether medical “parasitological” knowl­
not determined just by the need to survive and propagate, but depends on edge, even in popularized form, constituted “fundamental knowledge” for
the continuous transformation from “mental” to “public representations” Hitler’s audience (or for modern audiences, for that matter). Viruses, para­
and vice versa, with a tendency towards the production of “contents that sites, bacilli, etc. are hardly ever directly “experienced”; any knowledge
require lesser mental effort and provide greater cognitive effects”. T h e about them as causes of illnesses has been acquired as part of socialization
rate of innovation in concept replication is therefore much higher than in processes that involve the reception of (popularized) scientific terminology
22 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
and its historical interpretations. In the case of Mein Kampf we know
that the extensive terminology from the fields of medicine and hygiene that 3 Body, Nature and Disease as Political
Hitler used was concocted from popular sources dating back to his Vienna
years/^ which were “updated” by specialized literature sent to him dur­ Categories in Mein Kampf
ing the writing ,and editing of the book by sympathizers {such as the pub­
lisher of medical and scientific books and supporter of eugenics, Julius F.
Lehmann).®^ The aetiology of parasites that Hitler transferred on to the
"target domain of “racial hygiene” was not “experientially” available to him
or to his readers; instead, it had been construed and explicated in a complex
textual tradition.
We can thus discern the limits of extrapolating from (supposedly, gen­
eral) domain knowledge to text-specific cognitive intentions and effects.
Doubtless, by the time that Hitler composed Mein Kampf, a host of “elimi- As'the most substantial public enunciation of Hitler’s “worldview” (Jackel
nationist” implications of the body-nation and parasite-Jew mappings had 1981), Mein Kampf prowided the benchmark, so to speak, for uses of the
already been propagated by the pseudo-scientific “experts” of race hygiene body-nation metaphor in Nazi propaganda up until 1945.^ Its thus provides
and eugenics whose ascent in German academia and popular culture in the us with a platform for investigating the cognitive import of his metaphor
latter half of the nineteenth and the first third of the twentieth century had system by studying the overall conceptual range of his source images and
been phenomenal, e.g. the “authoritative” books by Gunther (1922) and their target applications, the argumentative patterns in which they appear,
by Baur, Fischer and Lenz (1923).^^ Hitler was clearly influenced by popu­ and the explicit and implicit conclusions drawn by Hitler. This study does
larized versions of their speculations, though the multitude and obscurity, not in itself present new material or insights into the core ideological con­
of many of his sources make it difficult to reconstruct a precise lineage of tent of Mein Kampf, its main aim is to reconstruct the “ontology” underly­
influences.However, even if these details were fully known, they would ing his worldview in the form that Hitler was happy to admit to in public.
still only represent the material “input” into Hitler’s ideology: the system To even assume the existence of an “ontological” structure (and thus, a
in which they appear in Mein Kampf CAnnox be derived or predicted from certain rationality) may seem perverse and bordering on conveying some
them but has to be the object of an empirical text-based analysis that recon­ intellectual or even political legitimacy on Nazi anti-Semitism. However, to
structs the cognitive framework of the body-nation metaphor as used by deny any rationality or ontological order to the Nazi worldview for the sake
Hitler. of outraged “attitudinizing” (K. Burke) would be tantamount to giving up
As we have seen, the evidence of a few quotations is not sufficient for a analysing it at all. As Christopher Browning remarked in his seminal study
systematic cognitive analysis because it does not show the conceptual and of the “ordinary men” who actually carried out much of the Holocaust
argumentative patterns that the metaphor is part of. We therefore need a killing: “Explaining is not excusing, understanding is not forgiving. Not
substantially broader text basis. From a philological point of view, it would trying to understand the perpetrators in human terms would make impos­
be ideal to provide a complete account of all figuratively phrased anti-Semitic sible . . . any history of Holocaust perpetrators that sought to go beyond
statements made by Hitler between 1919 and 1945 on the basis of the exist­ one-dimensional caricature.”^
ing critical text collections,^^ Rash’s database, which is comprehensive for Hitler’s imagery rested, as we shall see shortly, on a complex system of
Mein Kampf, and philologically orientated special dictionaries. How­ analogies that showed a high degree of ontological-coherence-onee its basic
ever, as the aim here is analysis rather than documentation, we shall concen­ premises were granted. Such an evaluation cannot in any degree detract from
trate on exploring the conceptual range of the bio-political metaphor system the fundamental immorality and factual inaccuracy of those premises, but to
in Nazi key texts and, where available, evidence of their reception, starting comprehend the analogies’ attractiveness for so many followers it is essential
with Mein Kampf to take their argumentative value seriously.^ Our aim is to understand the
structural patterns that made it possible for Hitler’s imagery to be believable
to the point of quasi-literal acceptance by large pafts of the German public.
Whilst the textual manifestations and the historical implementation of Nazi
racism are a thing of the past, the underlying cognitive patterns that under­
pinned them can be assumed to be typical for many more extremist world­
views, including future ones, and thus of general relevance.
24 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Body, Nature and Disease in Mein Kampf 25
As a first step to generate a reliable corpus of bio-political imagery in It may almost be considered a good fortune for the German people
Mein Kampf, the original German text and its most accessible English that its period of creeping sickness [schleichende Erkrankung] was sud­
translation (by Manheim) were searched for biological, medical and physi­ denly cut short by so terrible a catastrophe, for otherwise the nation
ological terminology, most of which turned out to be used metaphorically, would have gone under more slowly perhaps, but all the more certainly.
i.e. referring to socio-political issues rather than to “real” bio-medical The disease [Krankheit] would have become chronic, while in the acute
topics. The resulting list of key-words includes 207 (93 German and 114 form of the collapse it at least became clearly and distinctly recognis­
English) expressions from five conceptual sub-domains, each with further able. . . . It was no accident that man mastered the plague more easily
sub-complexes of concepts, as indicated in the following list (the relevant than tuberculosis. . . . The same is true of diseases of the bodies of na­
German lexical items are given in the notes): tions [Erkrankungen von Volkskdrpern]. If the disease does not take
the form of catastrophe at the onset, man slowly begins to get accus­
a) general biological categories (e.g. nature^'^ {host-)organism,^ drive/ tomed to it and at length, though it may take some time, perishes all
instinct,^ species/ race/ birth, ^ generation/’^ breeding^^) the more certainly of it.^^
b) organs, functions and health of bodies {body,^^ h e a r t,v e in s /
arteries,blood,strength,^^ health^'^) This poison [Gift] [“of the press—mainly that of Jewish origin”] was
c) illnesses and other pathological phenomena {illness/disease,^^ able to penetrate the bloodstream of our people [Blutkreislauf unseres
blood(-race) mix,^^ monster,^° sclerosis,^^ paralysis,pestilence, Volkes] unhindered and to do its work, and the state was not strong
syphilis,^'* cancer,grow th/tum our,^^ impotence,^"^ death, enough to master the disease [Krankheit], Tfie threat of a decline [Ver-
decomposition^^) fall] of the Reich became obvious in the ridiculous half-measures that
d) illness-inducing agents {poison,^’^ viper,parasite-bloodsucker/ it usecFagainst that disease.'’^
vampire-leech-sponger,bacillus/germ (carrier),vermin^"-)
e) cure/therapy (medical treatment (pejorative),^^ prescription/ From these quotations we can already distil a preliminary schema of Hitler’s
medicine,regeneration^'^). view of-the Germ&n nation's body. Since before World War I, the nation was
suffering from a general disease that had been caused by Jewish blood poi­
Whilst this list gives us an overview of the terminological and conceptual soning. Pre-war politicians had failed to heal the body, due to their ignorance
range of “source” inputs for the body-state metaphor in Mein K am pf its of the cause', instead, they had been tinkering around [herumdokterten] on it,
cognitive patterns can only be identified from their conceptual and argu­ treating as they did only the symptoms but leaving the original agent [Erreger]
mentative “target” applications. In order to achieve this, we need to estab­ untouched.**^ By providing this superior “in-depth” diagnosis, Hitler implic­
lish the core mappings of the metaphor complex from key statements in the itly claims to be best qualified to heal the nation’s body, although he does not
text that demonstrate the main lines of argumentation that Hitler pursued style himself explicitly as the doctor operating on the body (as we shall see
to develop the body-nation analogy. soon, he reserves an even grander version than that of a national healer for
himself). The acute health crisis of the German nation's body is itself just
one symptom, one case of a universal disease that threatens all nations:
3.1 HITLER^S BIO-POLinCAL SCENARIO: HEALING
THE BODY OF THE GERMAN NATION [The Jew] was . . . always a parasite in the, bcidy'tjf other peoples [Parasit
im Korper anderer Yolker].. . . He is and remains the typical parasite, a
A first cluster of relevant quotations can be found in Hitler’s account of the sponger who like an infectious bacillus keeps spreading [der typische Par­
military and political collapse of the German Empire in 1918: asit, ein Schmarotzer, der wie ein schadlicher BazHlus sich immer mehr
ausbreitet] as soon as a favourable medium invites him. And the effect of
[This military defeat] was only the result of many manifestations of his existence is also similar to that of spongers: wherever he appears, the
disease [Krankheitserscheinungen] and their underlying causes, which host nation [das Wirtsvolk\ dies out after a shorter or longer period.**^
even in peacetime had disturbed the German nation. This was the first
consequence, catastrophic and visible to all, of an ethical and moral As the studies reviewed in the preceding chapter have shown, cognitive
poisoning [Yergiftung], of a diminution in the instinct of self-preser­ analysis can plausibly argue that what Hitler is doing in these passages is
vation and its preconditions, which had been undermining the founda­ more than merely using body imagery to liven up his racist rhetoric. Rather,
tions of the people and the Reich for many years. he invokes a whole conceptual domain as a frame of reference, namely that
26 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Body, Nature and Disease in Mein Kampf 27
of the human body which, as part of the natural world, is born, grows up, complex socio-political issue (Germany’s socio-political and economic cri­
can fall ill and die, as well as the sub-frames of an attack by a parasite that sis since 1918) to everyday world knowledge (i.e. diagnosis of an acute,
feeds on the body until it has destroyed it, and that of a cure, namely the potentially fatal illness that requires immediate medical intervention). This
radical, complete removal o f the parasite. To summarise these conceptual scenario structure fuses the source and target concepts so that they lead
relationships from our set of examples, we can draw up a schema of key the readers to a specific inference: national cure = elimination of “the Jew”.
mappings between source and target domains of body and nation concepts, The inference is not “automatic” in the sense of a tautological truth; rather,
-respectively, as seen in Table 3.1 it is suggestive of a seemingly plausible, analogical conclusion.
This table of metaphorical inter-domain mappings gives an overview of To capture this scenario dimension of biological/medical metaphors in
the basic conceptual correspondences, but it hardly conveys their argumen­ Mein Kampf, we need to amend the simple mapping schema of Table 3.1 by
tative and practical implications. The source cluster of body-illness-cure matching source and target concepts to their slots in the illness-cure nar­
concepts in Mein Kampf is not an arbitrary constellation of notional ele­ rative. For the “knowledge” that is presupposed in the source scenario and
ments but a complex, narrative/scenic schema or “scenario”^^ that tells a mapped onto the target is not restricted to a general ontology of disease/
mini-story, complete with causal explanations and with conclusions about illness; it also includes an anticipatory plan or “script” of cause-effect rela­
its outcome (here, the story of “a body suffering illness because of poison­ tionships and a resulting course of a c tio n ,i.e . an “event-structure” that is
ing and therefore needing a radical cure”). This scenario is mapped as a used to predict (and to promise) consequences. Table 3.2 aims to visualize
whole onto the target domain, leading the reader towards the expectation this narrative-predictive structure in Hitler’s bio-pblitical metaphors.
that a healer will appear who will cure the national illness. It includes, as Table 3.2 demonstrates how much Hitler’s political target-level argu­
a tacit assumption on the basis of “commonsense” human self-interest, an ment depends on the commonsense logic of the source scenario. The arrows
evaluation, i.e. the conviction that securing and/or restoring the health of in bold signify cause-effect relations; the empty arrows represent inferences
someone’s body is physically, emotionally, and ethically a good thing. The that are suggested by way of analogy. The only “hard” historical fact that
scenario serves as a justification for all the actions that are deemed to be Hitler is able to refer to is Germany’s post-World War I crisis. The meta­
necessary to achieve the overall therapeutic aim. phorical interpretation of this crisis as an illness, which is indicated by the
These commonsense assumptions imbue Hitler’s line, of argument with a symbol HI, sets off two argumentative moves, both of which are based on
seemingly indisputable conclusiveness. If one accepts his tacit premises that analogical conclusions (■=>). One move is the search for the cause o f the ill­
there is such a thing as a national body in the first place and that that body ness. The author chooses from the illness source scenario the aspect that
has fallen ill, then the need to find a cure appears to be uncontroversial, fits his purpose of depicting the target level match, “the Jew”, as negatively
and so does the necessity to destroy the parasite that has caused the illness. as possible; hence the choice of the extremely dangerous, potentially deadly
This analogical argument implied in the metaphor scenario links a highly
Table 3.2 Event Structure of Body-Nation M appings
Table 3.1 Body-Nation M appings in Mein Kampf Domains Underlying Cause Present Situation Action Needed
Source Domain Target Domain
Source Poisoning by a ^ Body suffering ^ The cure of the
parasitic ‘alien from a severe, illness consists in
Body (German) nation
body’ {bacillus, deadly illness____ ^ _..^he-f€m oval of its
virus, sponger) (Blood poisoning) cause by a com ­
Ulness/disease D im inution of the instinct of self-preservation petent healer

Sympton of illness N ational downfall (especially, the m ilitary col­ HI


lapse o f 1918) and its consequences
Target Destructive force ^ N ational crisis of ^ Germany m ust
Cause of illnees: poisoning Jewish press of the Jewish G erm any (visible em power a
press and the since 1918) politician w ho is
Agent of illness: bacillus, virus, “T he Jew ” general influence able to effect the
sponger, parasite of Jews on Ger­ rem oval of Jews
m an society from German
Cure of illness Removal of all Jews from Germany society
28 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Body, Nature and Disease in Mein Kampf 29
blood-poisoning agent as the source equivalent of the target concept. oversimplified account of heredity in the animal kingdom, rather than a
Unless readers reject it out of hand, this choice activates their everyday political treatise. The opening paragraph starts with a childish-sounding
“knowledge” about illnesses in general and blood poisoning in particular. introduction to the fact that sexual reproduction among the “higher” ani­
This knowledge in turn yields the analogical warrant: “just as every illness mals is usually confined to members of the same species:
(including blood poisoning) must have an underlying cause and, thus, some
illness-causing agent, so the national crisis must have a cause and a culprit There are some truths that are so obvious that for this very reason they
who can be held responsible.” are not seen or at least not recognized by ordinary people... . [people]
The other argumentative move for Hitler, after having determined the wander about in the garden of Nature; they imagine that they know
cause o f the illness, is the practical conclusion, i.e. the necessity/urgency practically everything and yet, with few exceptions, they pass blindly
of medical treatment. Again, experience-based source-domain knowledge, by one of the most patent principles of Nature’s rule: the inner segrega­
i.e. that an illness normally requires a cure by a competent doctor. Is used tion of the species of all living beings on this earth. . .. Blue tit seeks
by Hitler to suggest himself as the healer o f the suffering patient, the Ger­ blue tit, finch goes to finch, stork to stork, field mouse to field mouse,
man nation. This suggested conclusion carries with it a host of further dormouse to dormouse, he-wolf to she-wolf, etc.**^
presuppositions, e.g. that the illness is in principle curable, that the therapy
is worth the effort, that the healer has been rightly identified, etc. These Even a very naive reader might wonder why Hitler would assume that this
assumptions are “straightforward” only at the source level (of a benevolent truth is not at all known to “ordinary people” who “wander about in the
medical science and practice), whereas they are extremely problematic at garden of Nature”—after all, his insights into the life of blue tits and finches
the target level and would normally require extensive argumentative back­ are not that original. Within a couple of pages, however, after dealing per­
ing for each step in the argument. However, within the analogical argu­ functorily with the most glaring exceptions to that “most patent principle”.
mentation context of the metaphor scenario, these presuppositions can be Hitler gets to his main point: just like animals, he alleges, humans of differ­
taken for granted as a whole. The nation thus becomes the patient that ent races are not supposed to mate with each other:
urgently needs the cure; the healer is present, the diagnosis is clear: the
treatment is without alternative. Historical experience . .. shows with terrifying clarity that in every
We can connect this basic illness-cure scenario that Hitler used to justify mingling of Aryan blood [Blutsvertfiengung des Ariers] with that of
his hatred of Jews to its characterisation as a distinctively radical “redemp­ lower peoples the result was the end of the cultured people.. . . Briefly,
tive”, “exterminatory” or “eliminationist” version of anti-Semitism, as pro­ the result of all racial crossing is therefore always the following:
posed by Holocaust researchers such as .Yehuda Bauer, Christopher Browning, (a) Lowering of the level of the higher race;
Saul Friedlander and Daniel J. Goldhagen.*^^ These explanations all refer to (b) Physical and intellectual regression and hence the beginning of a
the outcome of the cure that Hitler planned for the German national body. slowly but surely progressing sickness [eines, wenn auch langsam, so
Whilst the categorisation as “exterminatory”/“eliminationist” is mainly based doch sicher fortschreitenden Siechtums],
on the hindsight knowledge about the genocidal result of that cure, the term To bring about such a development is therefore nothing else but to sin
“redemptive” seems more apt as a characterization of how Hitler presented against the will of the eternal creator [Sunde treiben wider den Willen
his policies to his contemporaries in Mein Kampf It also points to a further des ewigen Schopfers].'^^
conceptual dimension of his metaphor system. “Redemption” presupposes
not just a national crisis but rather a universal catastrophe that demands a Hitler’s crude equivocation between animal “species” and hurnan “races”
universal healing process. has baffled even readers who tried to take, his worldview as seriously as
possible. Eberhard Jackel considered this notion of race beneath con­
tempt: “There is no need to comment on the nonsensicality of this kind
3.2 NATURE’S GARDEN AND HITLER’S of argument.”**^ Others, such as Alan Bullock, Ian Kershaw and Richard
UNDERSTANDING OF THE CREATOR’S DESIGN J. Evans, have spoken of “enter[ing] the world of the insane”, an “over­
riding and all-embracing obsession” or a “paranoid conviction”.T h e s e
Hitler’s most elaborate attempt to give such a universalist underpinning to psycho-pathological characterisations of Hitler’s racist beliefs are certainly
the illness-cure scenario can be found in Chapter .11 of Mein Kampf, enti­ appropriate as regards the “target” content of these beliefs but help little
tled “Nation and Race” {‘^Volk und Rasse”). A first glance at the introduc­ to explain their appeal for Hitler’s followers and the catastrophic conse­
tion to the chapter, however, may well impress the reader as a grotesquely quences. By focusing on their function as metaphorical mappings, however,
30 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Body, Nature and Disease itj Mein Kampf 31
we can analyse their (analogical) conclusiveness. We thus need to inves­ favoured by extreme racists) only to underline that its proponents were
tigate the source domain inputs that these metaphors activate as well as engaged in an irrational enterprise: “Those who do not admit the principle
the emerging “blended” mental spaces on their own terms (i.e. suspending of evolution, must look at species as separate creations . . . ; and they must
for the sake of the analysis our knowledge about'their “nonsensicality” in decide what forms of man they will consider as species by the analogy of the
target logic). method commonly pursued in ranking other organic beings as species. But
The first input domain to consider here is that of popularized biological it is a hopeless endeavour to decide this point, until some definition of the
^nd medical knowledge that can be assumed to have been available to Hitlef. term ‘species’ is generally accepted; and the definition must not include an
In their attempts to explain the appeal of Hitler’s especially extreme “racism”, indeterminate element such as an act of creation. .. . Those naturalists, on
historians have pointed to the links between his pronouncements on “race” the other hand, who admit the principle of evolution . .. will feel no doubt
and the contemporary “eugenics” movement as well as to the larger intel- that all the races of man are descended from a single primitive stock.”^®The
lectual/political tendencies of “social Darwinism” that had become estab­ whole question of whether the different varieties of humans constituted
lished in Western culture ahd especially in Germany since the latter decades species or races was therefore only of secondary importance to Darwin. For
of the nineteenth century. In view of Hitler’s well-documented acquaintance him, this was a question of more or less emphasis on differences between
with vulgarized versions of social Darwinism in his Vienna years, his contact existing varieties; in his model, all species had been at a previous point in
with and support for academic representatives of “racial hygiene” and of the time “sub-varieties” (or “so-called races”) of earlier species.
involvement of German biological and medical scientists in the Nazis’ eugen- In terminology that would count today as highly “politically incorrect”,
icist and genocidal programmes, Nazi racism has even been interpreted as a Darwin even asserted that some human races, for instance, “the Negro and
special, vicious variant of “social Darwinism”.^^ Hitler repeatedly claimed European, are so distinct that, if specimens had been brought to a natural­
that his racially defined anti-Semitism was based on “rational”, scientific ist without further information, they would undoubtedly have been consid­
insights rather than on “mere emotions”,^^ and polemicised against “old- ered by him as good and true species.”^^ On the other hand, he stressed that
fashioned” non-racially motivated forms of anti-Semitism.^^ “all the races agree in so many unimportant details of structure and in so
However, that “scientific” basis turns out to be fictitious as regards even many mental peculiarities, that these can be accounted for only by inheri­
the most basic categories, i.e. “species and “races”. Whilst Hitler regarded tance from a common progenitor.” In a similar dialectical argument, he
these categories as self-evident, even modern evolutionists concede that the claims that “American aborigines, Negroes and Europeans are as different
emergence of distinct species from sub-varieties/races of any one originator from each other in mind as any three races that can be named”,^' only to
species is far from obvious; instead, it presents a “fundamental problem”, then highlight their similarities: “yet I was incessantly struck, whilst living
for the “division of living organisms intro discrefe species is . . . not an with the Fuegians . . . , with the many little traits of character, shewing [sic]
obviously necessary state of affairs” and in principle it would be “easy to how similar their minds were to ours; and so it was with a full-blooded
imagine a world without such sharp differences”.^"*This problem also lies at Negro with whom I once happened to be intiraate”.^^
the heart of Charles Darwin’s The Origin o f Species, which we shall briefly For Hitler, to assert kinship (or friendship) with “Fuegians” or “full-
discuss to highlight its implications for racist ideologies, without suggesting blooded Negroes” would have been anathema. His interest in blurring the
that Hitler knew Darwin’s work from his own study. lines between race and species was not motivated by a wish to emphasise
Darwin himself drew no sharp dividing line between a species and any evolutionary continuity but, on the contrary, to make contrasts between
sub-varieties that evolved from it: if “species are only strongly marked and human “races” appear as discontinuous as possible. Despite his preten­
permanent varieties, and . . . each species first existed as a variety”, then sion to “rational”, scientific standards, Hi;ler’s-notion-©f-^face” was
“no line of demarcation can be drawn between species, commonly supposed based on the supposed “culture-building!’' abilities of the human races
to have been produced by special acts of creation, and varieties which are as “founders”, “bearers” and “destroyers of culture” [Kulturbegriinder,
acknowledged to have been produced by secondary laws.”^^ In The Descent -trdger, -zerstorer).^^ This tripartite distinction comes down to a simple
o f Man, he applied this notion of the continuum of varieties and species to opposition in one dimension: of all human races in the world, only one
“differences between the so-called races of man” ^^and stated that in prin­ qualifies as the founder of culture, i.e. the Aryan race, and again only one
ciple it was “almost a matter of indifference whether the so-called races of bears the stigma of the destroyer of culture, “the Jew”. All other races
man are thus designated, or are ranked as species or sub-species”; still, “the and peoples are just intermediates, i.e. mere bearers of the founders’ cul­
latter term” appeared to him to be “the more appropriate”.^^ ture to a higher or lesser degree.
Darwin even went to considerable length to deal with the “polygen- The concept of the fundamental “racial” opposition “Aryan”- “Jew” (and
ist” theory of a creation of several “species” of humans (which would be of the Jew-exclusive hierarchy of “creator”-and “bearer”-races) has no basis
32 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Body, Nature and Disease in Mein Kampf 33
in any biological source knowledge, however biased and popularized,^** but politico-religious framework. Even Barsch comes up with only about two
amounts to no more than an assemblage of arbitrary and contradictory dozen brief quotations from both volumes of Hitler’s book, which does
assertions on cultural differences. In this respect, its (dis-)qualification as not seem to indicate a high degree of “religious content”.’^ The much more
“nonsensical” is justified, but this only shows that further inputs have to extensive and systematically developed references to Bible texts in Rosen­
be taken into consideration. The second main input domain, which has to berg and Eckart’s writings and Goebbels’s religious family and education
make up, so to speak, for the deficiency of the pseudo-biological notion of backgrounds^ make them more likely candidates for advancing politico-
-“race” difference, is the notion of an absolute contrast between Devil and religious versions of Nazi-ideology than Hitler, who is reported to have
God, as derived from the Judeo-Christian tradition of religious eschato­ stated that Rosenberg’s The Myth o f the Twentieth Century was too arcane
logical thought.^^ In this framework, the notion of any “crossing” between to be of much propagandistic value.s®
Aryans and Jews was a cosmic abomination, a monstrous violation against For Hitler, ideological-propagandistic effectiveness was the main
the design of “the eternal creator”. In fact, any racial mixing was not quality criterion that mattered, and it was in this technical sense that
meant to be and it was the duty of anyone who tried to help the wprk o f the he wanted his followers to emulate the intensity of religious convictions
Lord to eliminate its “mongrel” offspring*^^ and help “Nature” in her work and that he praised what he saw as propagandistic feats of the Catholic
of “higher breeding”.^® Church.^^ The echoes of biblical textual traditions in Mein Kampf thus
The outlines of the biblical account of man's fall and redemption pro­ have to be interpreted with a view to their propagandistic function. The
vided a familiar metaphysical event-structure for Hitler’s scenario of the religious term redemption (Erldsung), for instance, changes its mean­
fight between the elite race of Aryans as men made in the Lord's image, ing radically if, instead of a metaphysical figure, the leader of a political
endowed with a god-like genius,^^ against the devil [Teufel] race of “the party ascribes to himself the role of its agent and if it is furthermore
Jew” that tried to prevent the Aryan’s work by fostering racial mixing and integrated into a scenario that has as its central principle not an ethical
world revolution.^® The danger allegedly posed by the Devil-Jew was so or theological imperative but the “struggle for self-preservation” or for
grave that a redeemer was called for in order to save not just the German “existence on this earth” {Kampf fur Selbsterhaltung/um das Dasein auf
people but the Aryan race and even human life on earth: this was the role dieser We/i).®®
that Hitler explicitly claimed for himself: The concept of the struggle for existence takes us back to the pseudo-
biological aspect of “social Darwinism” in Hitler’s anti-Semitism. As in
If, with the help of his Marxist creed, the Jew is victorious over the the case of race, Hitler also bent the biological concept of the struggle for
other nations of the world, his crown will be the funeral wreath of existence to suit his own purposes. Darwin had used the phrase struggle
humanity and this planet will, as it did thousands of years ago, move for existence in The Origin o f Species and had endorsed Herbert Spen­
through the ether devoid of men. Therefore, today I believe that I cer’s concept of the “survival of the fittest”.®’ He was, however, aware of
am acting in accordance with the will o f the Almighty Creator: by the possibility of misunderstandings of these notions and emphasized that
defending myself against the Jew, I am fighting for the work o f the he employed the phrase struggle for existence “in a large and metaphori­
Lord?'" cal sense including dependence of one being to another, and including
(which is more important) not only the life of the individual, but success
It is on account of this metaphysical dimension of Hitler’s bio-political sce­ in leaving progeny”,®^ i.e. in an essentially statistical sense.®®
nario that Burke (1939) characterises the anti-Semitism of Mein Kampfas Hitler’s view of struggle for existence, on the other hand, was based
the “materialization of a religious pattern”,^^ that Friedlander (1998) speaks exclusively on the notion of “fighting” (RfJwp/jrFTifler'useR Kampfas the
of the “redemptive” aspect of Nazi anti-Semitism,^® and that Barsch (2002) central expression for his own political biography and it was for him a
views the National Socialist ideology as a “political religion”.^**Barsch puts source of pride: all masters, geniuses and heroes, he assumed, had had to
Hitler’s references to biblical and religious topics in the context of writ­ conquer “weaker” beings, and would always have to prove themselves in
ings by other National Socialist ideologues such as Dietrich Eckart, Joseph fighting.®** He, too, had been able to lay the “granite foundation” of his
Goebbels and Alfred Rosenberg, and he concludes that the “religious con­ worldview only through suffering and fighting in his Viennese years,®®
tent” was a central feature of Nazi anti-Semitism and a decisive factor in and this fight would continue.®^ Similarly, Aryans, when “liberated” from
securing support for it.^® It is, however, debatable to what degree Hitler’s “the Jew”, would have to go on conquering other races to give “them a
rather unspecific and sporadic use of religious terms {devilish Jews, god­ fate that was better than their previous so-called ‘freedom’ Those
like or divine Aryans, the Lord's work, God's will, creator, omnipotent, who did not acknowledge this “iron law” of eternal fighting were weak­
paradise, providence, our creed, sin) in Mein Kampf constitutes a coherent lings and/or liars and their existence was useless:
34 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Body, Nature and Disease in Mein Kampf 35
The stronger must dominate and not blend with the weaker, thus sacri­ Table 3.3 Basic Scenario Structure of Body-Nation M appings in Mein Kampf
ficing his own greatness. Only the born weakling can view this as cruel, Event Structure
but he after all is only a weak and limited man; for if this law did not
prevail, any conceivable higher development of organic beings would Domains Underlying Cause Present Situation Action Needed
be unthinkable.®®
Source Poisoning by Body suffering Cure of the illness
an ‘alien body’ from a severe, through removal
. . . to preserve a certain culture, the man who creates it must be pre­ (bacillus, virus, deadly illness of its cause
served. This preservation is bound up with the iron law of necessity sponger)
and the right to victory of the best and stronger in this world. Those
who want to live, let them fight, and those who do not want to fight in -0- a-
this world of eternal struggle do not deserve to live.®^ Target I Destructive influ­ G erm any’s Em pow erm ent of
(Germany) ence of Jews on national crisis a m an able to
Cultural “improvement”, the great prerogative of the Aryans, was o'nly pos­ German society following the remove “the Jew ”
sible as a result of continuous fighting against other races, but there was no defeat in 1918 from the G erm an
coherent notion of evolutionary development in this conception: neither as nation
regards the races, which had been there since the beginning of the world, nor ■0-
as regards individual existences. In this eternal fight, the winner “took all”,
the loser could only hope to survive as the victor’s slave, and if he was lucky Target II Devilish forces Threat to creator’s A redeemer is
enough to have Aryans as his masters, he might participate in their culture (Universe) foster unnatural plans of continu­ needed to enforce
mixing of hum an ous improvement the creator’s uni­
provided he never tried to join the master race. Catastrophe ensued if the species/races of species/races versal design
Aryan—too nice for his own good, as it were—lowered the race/blood barri­
ers and mingled with the lower race: by committing this fateful error, he “lost
his right to stay in the paradise that he had created for himself”.^® By comparison with the already tenuous analogical inferences between
The German people provided a special case of this general picture. The the primary source and target levels, the mappings underlying target level
Germans were not a uniform racial group but contained the most ancient II are based on sheer speculative extrapolation from the national crisis to a
“Aryan” traits.^^ They had forfeited their chance of “putting the world into universal drama (symbolised by the empty “down” and “across” arrows).
the service of a higher culture” by indulging in racial mixing and there­ Nevertheless, in the “analogical logic” of the metaphor scenario, even these
fore losing the First "World War, suffering as they did then from the lack of a speculations retain a vestige of conclusiveness. Target level II “inherits”, as
proper “herd instinct based on unity of the blood”.^®However, all hop? was it were, from level I the grounding in the illness-cure scenario. As the source
not lost, for although inter-racial mixing had damaged the nation’s body, level is further removed than from level I, the derived event structure of level
there were still “great unmixed stocks of Nordic-Germanic people whom II may appear less plausible, but it is still present. The pseudo-religious nar­
we may consider the most precious treasure for our future”.^'^ The earthly rative of mankind’s fall (= "sin” of racial mixing), followed by suffering and
paradise of Aryan world power and “culture-building” could therefore still repentance (= post-WWI crisis) and redemption (= elimination of “the Jew”)
be regained if only racial mingling could be stopped and healed by way is broadly compatible with the primary scenario levels, infection-illness-cure
of removing its agent, “the Jew”, for good. This promise of final redemp­ (source), and Jewish influence on German socie^, (Q\\oYip3hY-national cri­
tion contradicted, strictly speaking, the even more cynical notion of eternal sis, followed by liberation-through-elimination o f Jewry (target level I). The
fighting; but again, as in the case of Hitler’s reinterpretation of biological strict parallelisation suggests coherence and comprehensiveness of the overall
concepts, we must not search for an internal logical consistency in his argu­ scenario and imbues its core mappings with a global dynamic.
mentation. For his purposes, it was sufficient that the two “universalist”
domains of race theory and religion were combined to add a global, even
cosmic dimension to his scenario, even if they were incoherent on their own 3.3 GENOCIDE AS THE ONLY THERAPY
terms and contradicted each other. What mattered was that their combi­ FOR RACIAL BLOOD POISONING
nation, however crude, mirrored the event structure of the first, national-
political target level and thus provided a further general level, which is Overblown and menacing as it was. Hitler’s diagnosis of a disease threat­
visualized in Table 3.3 as follows: ening the body politic still did not warrant a complete annihilation of the
36 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Body, Nature and Disease in Mein Kampf 37
supposed agent o f disease. After all, even a life-threatening illness (in the together to suggest the imminent danger of a deadly, disgusting, univer­
literal sense) can be treated without necessarily eliminating all of its agents, sal disease. Even where the scenarios contradict each other (e.g. infectious
and the same might be assumed to hold for illnesses that threaten the body disease v. acute poisoning v. decomposition), the role slot for “the Jew”
politic. According to Susan Sontag (1978), in “classical” political theory remains the same: he only changes his metaphoric appearance. Whether he
up to the Enlightenment, disease metaphors served mainly the purpose of is depicted as a viper, a bacillus, a leech, a fungus or a rat, he is in every case
“encourag[ing] rulers to pursue a more rational policy” and were not nor­ the parasitical driving force. This role was, according to Hitler, unchange­
mally used to suggest the complete destruction of social groups, nations or able: it could not be affected by any change of circumstances other than
- races.^^ We shall examine Sontag’s historical claims in detail in subsequent complete destruction either through a “politico-medical” intervention,
chapters and critique it with regard to specific historical examples, but gen­ such as the one Hitler himself hoped to bring about, or in an apocalyptic
erally she is right that socio-political illness imagery does not necessarily scenario, as the inadvertent result of “the Jew’s” final victory:
entail genocidal therapy solutions.
Hitler, however, clearly aimed to draw the most drastic conclusions from . . the blood-Jew [Blutjude] tries to exterminate the national intel­
the worst possible illness scenario; in his view, the entirety of Jewish peo­ ligentsia and, by robbing the peoples of their natural intellectual lead­
ple were puppets of a worldwide conspiracy, as outlined in the infamous ership, makes them ripe for the slave’s lot of permanent subjugation.
forgery of the “Protocols of the Elders of Zion”.^^ To integrate the notion .. . The end, however, is not only the end of the liberty of the peoples
of eliminating all Jews into his metaphor scenario. Hitler needed to rely oppressed by the Jew, but also the end of this parasite upon the nations
on source concepts that had an irredeemably negative value and could be [Volkerparasit] itself. After the death of his victim, the vampire sooner
projected onto “the Jew” as a collective entity. The illness-cure scenario or later dies too.^°^
provided a slot for suggesting a radical cure by identifying blood poisoning
as the cause of the disease,-which enabled him to conceptualize “the Jew” Within this complex of parasitological, pathological and medical scenarios,
as the blood poisoning agent. the notion of blgod is of special importance. It is, in the first place, the
This metaphorical characterisation had the advantage of functioning at immediate source of the blood-poisoning metaphor, which appears in two
various levels of the scenario structure. In the most basic version, Hitler lik­ forms: a) as the bite of a poisonous snake, and b) as a by-product of para­
ened “the Jew” to a viper, or an adder whose bite directly induced venom into sitical activity, e.g. a bloodsucker’s bite, which introduces toxic substances
the bloodstream of the victim.^® At a second level, “the Jew” was depicted as into the bloodstream. At a second, symbolic level, blood was for Hitler the
a bloodsucker, leech and generally as a parasite {Parasit, Schmarotzer).^^ The carrier of heredity and racial identity. Procreation among members of dif­
bloodsucker-parasite metaphor in particular fused the two aspects of (1) an ferent races always resulted in a mingling o f blood, and such racial crossing
organism that takes advantage o f or lives at the expense of another organism led to “physical and intellectual regression” and was “the beginning of a
(the sense in which parasite/parasitic is still used today as a routine figure of slowly but surely progressing sickness”.
abuse)’°° and (2) poisoning as a potentially fatal threat. In this scenario ver­ This belief in the hereditary importance of blood was not an idiosyn­
sion, the host organism is deprived of some of its own blood by the parasite; cratic superstition on the part of Hitler but was in line with traditional folk-
through the contact with it the remaining blood is at the same time infected: theoretical assumptions that an offspring’s blood was a mix of the parents’
the alleged damage is thus multiplied.^°^ blood, and with it their inheritance. The remnants of this tradition can be
At a third, more abstract level, “the Jew” was depicted as the bacillus or germ seen in idioms such as being o f or sharing the same blood, blood relations,
carrier or agent o f disease {Bazillus, BazUlentrdger, Erreger).^°^ This general of blood being thicker than water, or of noble blood, which are in use to
qualification linked to the scenario of decomposition [Zersetzung, Fdulnis), in this day.^°^ These phrases are remnants of pre^modern eoflceptrof blood as
which “the Jew” had the role of the decomposing agent {Zersetzer, Ferment a “life force” and one of the “four humour^” and the belief that a person’s
der Zersetzung), for instance, as a bacterium {Spaltpilz) or maggot {Made), character was a mix of his or her parents’ blood. It was only at the turn
or figured as a multiplying agent, i.e. vermin, especially rats {Ungeziefer, Rat­ of the twentieth century that the “blood myth” of heredity was experi­
ten) that spread the products of decomposition [Leichengift).^^^ The infection mentally falsified by Charles Darwin’s cousin Francis Galton (1822-1911),
scenario was also compatible with that of an epidemic (Seuche), which Hitler ironically, as it were, for Galton was also the founder of the eugenics move-
used to describe Jewish influence in society, e.g. pestilence [Pest, Pestilenz, ment.’°^ But despite experiments such as Gabon’s and despite the growing
Verpestung) and syphilis (Syphilis, Versyphilitisierung).^^'^ public awareness of Gregor Mendel’s (1822—1884) theory of genetics, the
These varying scenarios do not form a taxonomically consistent source conceptual linkage of blood with heredity persisted into the twentieth cen-
domain, but they do invoke an ensemble of causeslagents o f illness that fit tury.“ ° In writing Mein Kampf, Hitler could rely on his readers to accept
38 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Body, Nature and Disease in Mein Kampf 39
the blood = heredity equation as a conventional way of speaking about With Satanic, joy in his face, the black-haired Jewish youth lurks for
individual and racial heredity. hours in wait for the unsuspecting girl whom he defiles with his blood
As a corollary of this equation, the notion of poisoned blood entailed [mit seinem Blute schdndet], thus stealing her from her people. With
that of poisoned heredity. The supposed blood-poisoning agent of the • every means he tries to destroy the racial foundations of the people he
German nation’s body (as well as of the Aryan race and, ultimately, the has set out to subjugate. Just as he himself systematically ruins women
world), i.e. “the Jew”, was a danger not just for one generation but forever. and girls, he does not shrink back from pulling down the blood barri­
This long-term threat made the elimination of all forms of the supposed ers )^lutschranken] for others, even on a large scale.” '*
■Jewish poisoning agent, i.e. of all the bacilli, vipers, leeches, parasites and
vermin, even more urgent. However, in terms of Hitler’s analogical argu­ Hitler introduces this scene in the context of discussing the penultimate stage
ment, a crucial element in the illness-cure scenario was still missing that of his pseudo-history of German-Jewish relations in Chapter 11 of Mein
would make cure-by-elimination an absolutely binding imperative. The Kampf. The conceit of historical specificity is, of course, vacuous: it could be
missing element is the aspect of ethical or moral responsibility. Actual located at any “stage” of his narrative and Hitler makes no attempt to give
bacilli, vipers, leeches, parasites and vermin may be called agents of dis­ any kind of documented, empirical reference for such a scene. The factual
ease and their effects evil or even cruel when viewed with a conscious, veracity of the account is clearly irrelevant for Hitler: he is enunciating a
anthropocentric interest. However, as organisms without consciousness “prototypical” scene of German-Jewish relations as imagined by anti-Sem­
or conscience, they are, of course, not held literally responsible for the ites, irrespective of any evidence.”' The essence of this horror-version of the
results of their “behaviour”. But when Hitler applied these moral cat­ blood poisoning scenario is the contrast between the deliberate, predatory
egories to racial parasites, he meant their anthropomorphic assessments aggression on the part of the “black-haired Jewish youth” and the innocence
in earnest. The argument that “allowed” him to treat the Jews as if they of the “unsuspecting girl”. The defilement ofnon-Jewish blood by “the Jew”
were blood-poisoning agents that caused death and decomposition on is thus presented as a totally one-sided attack, which morally justifies any
purpose was his particular “explanation” of how such a poisonous racial defence, either by the victim herself or any saviour who comes to her rescue.
mix had come about. Again, the interplay between a supposedly descriptive account, racist
Hitler explained the supposedly “unnatural” fact of such a mix by imagery and the text-specific scenario system of Mein Kampf is crucial. In
enriching his basic scenario with accounts of actual inter-racial Jewish- isolation, the phrases defilement o f blood or defilement of race [Blut-, Ras-
German/Aryan contacts, both in the form of allegedly self-witnessed senschande) were at the time conventional labels for undesirable forms of
scenes in pre-World War I 'Vienna and Munich, and during the war, inter-racial sexual contact” ^ and, as metaphors, not even particularly vivid,
and in a historical overview spanning a millennium, which occupies large but they had a special appeal when they were applied to the scene depicted
parts of Chapter 11 of Mein Kampfa.nd is divided in twelve phases,^’^ His in the preceding quotation. Hitler construes here an exact parallel to the
general “explanation” of Jewish-German marriages and sexual contacts biological source scenario at the target level of his metaphor, but with an
came down to the allegation that “the Jew” had a cunning stratagem to added moral dimension. The scene is that of an act of “blood poisoning”;
ensure maximum hereditary racial advantage by keeping his own male however, not a “simple” poisoning as the result of a metaphorical viper or
bloodline pure whilst poisoning other races through intermarriage in the bloodsucker’s bite. Rather, the conventional metaphor is underwritten and
female line: “The Jew almost never marries a Christian woman; it is the reinvigorated by the account of a supposedly real sexual attack.
Christian who marries a Jewess. Yet, the bastards'take after the Jewish This prototypical scenario of Jewish aggression against non-Jewish victim,
side.”’' ' together with its implicit appeal for rescue, formed_a com presupposition in
This combination of racist suspicion, sexism and factual errors as Hitler’s concept of bloodirace defilement. The.parallelisation of the biological/
regards Jewish heredity laws was typically dismissive but still conven­ medical concept of blood poisoning and the ethical concept blood defilement
tional. “The Jew” was the agent but the “Aryan” partners were viewed as matched and complemented the notion of race defilement both at the national
collaborators: moral responsibility thus lay with both parties. In order to and the universal levels. It thus allowed Hitler to pass between source and
demonstrate the necessity of destroying “the Jew” as an evil force threat­ target domain levels without further argumentation. The boundaries between
ening the Aryan race and the German people. Hitler had to come up with biological, ethical, socio-political and metaphysical concepts were effectively
a more specific scenario of inter-racial blood poisoning as a one-sided eliminated. Whenever Hitler called “the Jew” a poisonous parasite, he uttered
act of aggression. This he did in the passages cited in the last chapter what was for him a truthful characterization that fitted the scenario versions
and analysed by Bosmajian (1983), Hawkins (2001) and Chilton (2005) at all domain levels. This conceptual addition requires, as a last amendment
but furthermore in an even more “concrete” and possibly more repulsive of our scenario schema, the introduction of an intermediate layer between the
version: main source and target levels, as shown in Table 3.4.

I
40 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Body, Nature and Disease in Mein Kampf 41
Table 3.4 Extended Scenario Structure of Body-Nation M appings in Mein Kampf could be dismissed as the product of cunning deception practised by “the
Jew” as “the great master of lying”.^^®
Event Structure By following up the implications of the politico-medical metaphor sce­
nario in Mein Kampf, we have reached the core, or in Hitler’s words, the
Domains Underlying Cause Present Situation Action N eeded
“granite foundations”, of his specific, vicious anti-Semitism.” ^ They centred
Source Poisoning by Body suffering Cure by w ay of a on the notion of an irreconcilable antagonism between Aryans/Germans
an ‘alien body’ from a severe, complete removal and “the Jew”, the responsibility for which lay wholly with “the Jew”. It
(bacillus, virus, deadly illness, i.e. of the cause of was he and he alone who had launched a deadly attack in the form of blood
sponger) blood poisoning the illness poisoning against the German nation’s body at least at three levels: a) as a
supposedly real act of blood defilement, i.e. rape or seduction, b) as cause
of the German nation’s illness, and c) as a devilish conspiracy against the
Target Race defilement i=D> D estruction of The girl m ust be creator’s design. “The Jew” was portrayed as an eternal agent of destruc­
Level la of innocent girl hereditary foun­ saved from the
tion, which, unlike an unconsciously “acting” bio-parasite (a virus or bacil­
by Jewish rapist dations of the rapist
girl’s race/people lus), would deliberately invade as many host populations as possible.
The apparent conclusiveness of this conceptual framework suggestive of
■0 -Q-1 f}r genocide derived not so much from the individual “content” of Hitler’s meta-
phorization of Jews as parasites but from its integration in scenarios that
Target Destructive influ­ ■=> Germany’s dow n­ =J> Elim ination of
Level lb ence of Jews on fall following the Jews from Ger­ had their own internal event-structure logic. The basic mapping (see Tables
German society defeat in World m an society/ 3.1, 3.2) allowed inferences from the domain of popular biological, medical
W ar I Europe and hygienic knowledge (“necessity to remove a parasitic agent of disease”)
to be transferred to the target level of politics (“necessity to fight against the
alleged Jewish influence”). This mapping and its implications did not as such
Target Devilish forces T he'natural A redeemer has traTnscend the conventional cliches of anti-Semitic discourse 'at the time (as
Level 2 foster unnatural course of to enforce the we shall see later, the parasite image had become established in German body
mixing of hum an im provem ent of creator’s cosmic politic conceptualisations much earlier and had gained central importance
species/races species-races is design
p u t in jeopardy
by the end of thee nineteenth century).” ®Hitler, however, did not stop at
exploiting the standard implications of this analogy. By including a second­
ary target level, of cosmic-metaphysical “redemption-through-annihilation”
In terms of this'last scenario version, “the Jew” was seen as an essen­ and an intermediate pseudo-realistic level between source and target sce­
tially a«t/-human parasitic species, which, unlike an unconsciously acting narios (see Tables 3.3, 3.4), he managed to insinuate that the alleged crime of
bio-parasite, deliberately tried to invade as many host populations as pos­ blood poisoning was “literally” true as well as being the overarching concep­
sible. As the infection was lethal for all its hosts, its own victory would also tual frame for the Jewish role in humanity at large.
be its own nemesis: it would perish together with the last host it had con­ The analysis of this multilayered conceptual structure of the chief causal
quered. “The Jew” thus became a kind of universal super-parasite that event in the illness-cure scenario helps to explain the peculiar “metaphori­
not only had the will to destroy other races but would do this, as it were, on cal” status of Nazi anti-Semitism as far as it appesrrin Mi^it Kampf, whilst
principle, i.e. even risking its own destruction in the process. In this cosmic fully recognising its function as a real policy model for what the Nazis
scenario framework, all conceptual boundaries between source and target would later call the “Final Solution”. The blood-poisoning scenario was
domains were erased: for Hitler, any German-Jewish contact was blood considered to be truthful both at the level of experienced reality and in the
mix, hence blood defilement and blood poisoning. The conceptual and metaphorical/allegorical applications of that concept. This alleged act of
epistemological difference of source and target levels was short-circuited deliberate parasitic aggression justified in the eyes of Hitler and his follow­
and the result was a closed belief system of extreme apparent coherence, ers any inhuman behaviour towards “the Jew” as an altruistic act of life­
as the different scenario levels could be used to corroborate each other. saving help for his supposed victims, i.e. any innocent Aryan girl, which at
Any claims that might seem problematic at target level were thus “proven” the same time symbolized the German national body, the whole o f human­
at source level—and vice versa. Outside facts that did not fit the scenario ity and even the cosmic order.
42 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
These results cast a new light on several central topics of Holocaust
research that have been discussed among historians and in the wider pub­ 4 The Public Presentation and
lic. First, in the context of the long-standing debates between ‘intentional- '
ist’ and ‘functionalist’ explanations of the origins of the H o lo c a u s t,th e
Reception of Anti-Semitic Imagery in
cognitive study of the inner coherence of Hitler’s ideology reinforces the Nazi Germany
view that Hitler favoured a genocidal “solution” of “the Jewish question”
- already by the time of writing Mein Kampf, for in this book he explained
the solution in terms of extermination scenarios that were meant in earnest,
and not just fanciful rhetoric. The implementation of his genocidal plans
would thus have been for him more a matter of timing and opportunity,
rather than merely one possible option among many. At the time of publica­
tion, i.e. the mid-1920s and for some years to come, this conceptual frame­
work was taken by many as the ranting of a failed putschist that might Wliat role did the body-parasite metaphor complex play during the rule of
inspire a few individual acts of racist violence but was without a chance of National Socialism in Germany? Was it only a rehash of the imagery used
influencing the wider public, let alone lead to a real genocide. In order to in Mein Kampf or did it undergo changes that can be related to political
better understand how it was transformed Into a public consensus we need developments over the period 1933-1945.? What discernible impact did it
to show a) that this metaphor system was actually operated by Hitler to have on the public: was it just a sinister accompaniment of the Holocaust
prepare the implementation of his “redemptive” anti-Semitism once he had or was it instrumental in indoctrinating Germans to participate in or at
full access to the public and b) how it was received by the public in such least tolerate the unfolding genocide? Physically, the Holocaust could have
a way as to allow the Nazis to implement the desired genocidal outcome happened without any propaganda (metaphorical or otherwise), but such a
and to convince ordinary Germans to support or at least tolerate it. These “mute” genocide is extremely implausible given that the regime needed the
issues, which were crucial for the execution of the genocide, will be studied active participation of hundreds of thousands and the support, or at least
in the following chapter. tacit toleration, of millions of Germans in their execution of the genocidal
programme. Research into the primary evidence, i.e. the secret intelligence
reports of popular opinion compiled by the GESTAPO and the SS’s spe­
cial “security service” [Sicherheitsdienst, short SD) as well as those by the
exiled Social Democrats [Sopade) until 1940,^ and from diaries, letters, etc.,
has established beyond doubt that the supposition of ignorance about the
Nazis’ anti-Jewish policy among a majority of Germany’s adult population
is a.myth.^ Even though these primary sources cannot be used uncritically,
due^ to the respective political bias of exaggerating the perceived political
consensus or dissent, depending on institutional and personal interests and
the limited knowledge of the authors,^ they reveal widespread awareness
of the Nazis’ anti-Jewish propaganda campaign and repressive/genocidal
policies, including numerous reports about mass-shootmgs“.
Crucially, tliey also contain evidence that the regime’s official “justi­
fication” of their anti-Semitic policies by way of framing their policy
announcements in the body-parasite scenario was taken up in the popu­
lation. Although Nazi propaganda has generally been well researched,'^
this role of body-related metaphors has largely been left unexplored. The
purpose of the following discussion is to establish to what degree these
metaphors were present in the public domain and how they were received.
As regards the first aspect, we shall focus on Hitler’s speeches and also on
some by his propaganda minister, Joseph Goebbels. Their use of body, ill­
ness and parasite imagery when referring to the relationship between the
44 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Presentation and Reception o f Anti-Semitic Imagery 45
German nation and “the Jew” was relayed endlessly by the controlled mass against Jews (exclusion from the civil service including the whole of the
media and was therefore sure to find a wide national and international education system), continuous harassment, arbitrary arrests and a barrage
audience. Regarding the reception, we shall take the aforementioned secret of radical, if vague, insults, it helped to drive 37,000 Jews out of Germany
reports into consideration, as well as the secret diaries of Victor Klemperer, within a year.^^
a professor at Dresden University until 1935, who was considered to be As regards public perception, it is difficult to gauge the salience of the
racially Jewish by the Nazis but survived the Nazi period thanks to being specifically anti-Semitic measures vis-a-vis the repression of other groups
married to a non-Jewish wife who stood by him. His secret diary, published such as Communists, Social Democrats and other political enemies of the
posthumously,^ provided the material for his 1945 analysis of the Language Nazis (who accounted for the vast majority of arrests, beatings and killings
o f the Third Reich.^ The period covered is that between 1930, when the in the “wild” torture chambers and camps and the circa 100,000 incarcera­
NSDAP won a significant share of votes in the general election of 17 Sep­ tions in concentrations camps over the course of 1933).*^ Among the politi­
tember (18.3%, compared with 2.6% previously) and the end of World War cal poisons and illnesses that Hitler vowed to fight at the Nuremberg party
II in May 1945. conference in September 1933,^® he named “Bolshevism” as the most dan­
gerous one. In Hitler’s belief system, Bolshevism was, of course, invented
by “the Jew”; hence Jews were the implicit target. They formed the core,
4.1 PREPARING THE PUBLIC FOR THE GENOCIDE: so to speak, of the vast group of targets/victims who stood in the way of
THE BODY-PARASrrE SCENARIO IN NAZI the Nazis’ vision of a homogeneous society. These groups also included the
ANTI-SEMITIC PROPAGANDA, 1933-1939 physically and mentally disabled, the further supposed “race” of “gypsies”,
the Nazis’ “official” political adversaries (mainly socialists and commu­
The extreme socio-economic crisis in Germany that ensued as part of the nists but also members of other parties as well as clerics who refused to
worldwide recession following the bank crash of 1929 lent itself, so to speak, acknowledge the supreme authority of the Nazi state), socially marginal
to the use of illness imagery. Even the plain-talking conservative chancel­ groups (“work-shy” people, beggars, vagrants, prostitutes), criminals and
lor of the Centre Party, Heinrich Bruning, spoke of the urgent heed for a the sexually “deviant” (mainly male homosexuals). All of them were stig­
political and social recovery {Gesundung) of the nation as a precondition for matized and persecuted as parasites or pests- {Volksschadlinge) that dam­
regaining the ability to engage in reform policies.^ It was he, however, who aged the nation’s body^^
was the main target of Hitler and Goebbels’s accusations that the govern­ Zygmunt Baumann (2000) has described this forcible “re-formation” of
ment treated the “wounds on the German people’s body” by just “putting on the German body politic as an “exercise in social engineering on a gran­
sticking plaster”,®instead of ridding the nation’s body of parasites.^ In a par­ diose scale”. T h e lead metaphor of his analysis is that of “gardening” as
liamentary speech in 1932, Goebbels attacked Briining’s austerity measures a characteristic of modern culture, intent as it is on creating an artificial
as the equivalent of a “scientifically correct operation” that had “left the order: “The order, first conceived of as a design, determines what is a
patient dead”.^“ In the summer of that year, during the last general election tool, .what is a raw material, what is useless, what is irrelevant, what is
campaign of the Weimar Republic, he depicted the Reichstag parliament as harmful, what is a weed or pest. It classifies all elements of the universe
a “carcass” (Parlamentskadaver) whose “carrion stench” {Aasgestank) was by their relation to itself... . Modern genocide . . . is a gardener’s job. It is
polluting the people and had to (be made to) disappear.^’ just one of the many chores that people who treat society as a garden need
When he was finally appointed chancellor in January 1933, Hitler, to undertake.” This characterisation emphasises-the-^eomple^nentary”
swiftly followed by Goebbels, proclaimed his government’s determination nature of repressive and genocidal policies that corresponds to the “con­
to restore the nation’s body through a “reform of head and limbs [Refottn structive” aspects of the Nazis’ “perfectionist” design of an ideal society.
an Haupt und Gliedern), echoing the famous formula from the time of A^such, the gardening metaphor is compatible with the hygienic-medical
the Church Reformation in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries.’^ Three parasite-as-illness-agent metaphors: “Gardening and medicine are func­
months later, after a first nationwide boycott of Jewish businesses, Goeb­ tionally distinct forms of the same activity of separating and setting apart
bels declared German Jewry to be an “alien, separate nation with parasitic useful elements destined to live and thrive, from harmful and morbid
characteristics” [artfremdes, streng abgeschlossenes Volk mit parasitdren ones, which ought to be exterminated. However, whilst the “gardening”
Eigenschaften), intent on sabotaging the national reform/healing process.^^ imagery aims to justify repressive and genocidal measures as “necessary
The boycott appears to have met with widespread indifference in the general evils” of an overarching endeavour to achieve a perfect society, the special
population and was called off after just one day^'* but was terrifying to Jew- function of body-based bio-medical imagery lies in the urgency
' ish people.i^ combination with the legal and professional discrimination of radical exterminatory intervention. The danger posed by a parasite on
46 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Presentation and Reception of Anti-Semitic Imagery 47
one's own body that is about to poison one’s bloodstream is of a different even if it meant sacrificing his own comrades. He had acted as a heroic
order of intensity than that of a garden weed. The defensive reaction by the healer who did not shy away from, eliminating parts of his own party’s
host organism is also different: it is instinctive, immediate, involves terror, body to save the nation’s greater body. In this perspective, the Night of the
revulsion and righteous aggression, and will not rest until the last vestiges Long Knives needed no legal justification: it was an act of self-defence.
of the parasite are eliminated. If in 1934 the National Socialist government had demonstrated its abil­
Baumann is, however, fight to stress that the genocidal “cleansing” ide­ ity to cleanse itself, the Nuremberg Party rally of the following year pro­
ology, whether botanical or zoological in its source input, was not reserved ceeded to lay the legal foundation for, disposing of all alien bodies in the
for Jewish targets alone but for all supposed forms of life “unworthy to nation. The party and in its wake the Reichstag passed the race laws “for
live” in the Nazi state. In the second year of his rule. Hitler even made an the Protection of German Blood and Honour” and a newly defined citizen­
example of his own comrades falling under the cleansing-as-extermination ship, which excluded Jews from German citizenship and from marriage
maxim. In the so-called “Night of Long Knives” (30 June 1934) almost all or sexual relations with Germans; associated deprees stigmatized “less
the leaders of the “storm troopers” [Sturmabteilung, SA), as well as a num­ valuable” handicapped people as well as “Gypsies, Negroes, and their
ber of alleged co-conspirators (including Hitler’s immediate predecessor as bastards”.^^ According to Hitler’s proclamation, “Jewish Marxism” was
Re/c^s-Chancellor, General von Schleicher and his wife), were murdered the core “enemy within” which was now to'be fought relentlessly,^® whereas
on the pretence of an alleged plot to overthrow his government. In the other countries (“when we look around us”) still contained the “ferments
Reichstag, Hitler presented the executions, which had taken place on his of decomposition” and the “elements of destruction”, on account of the
orders but without any formal legal authority, as the “burning out, down activities of Jewish emigrants.
to the raw flesh” of “ulcers” [Geschwure) that had been caused to grow by In technical legal terms, the Nuremberg laws may have been over­
“poisoning”, specifically, “well-poisoning” {Brunnenvergiftung), echoing complicated as the supposed racial Jewish heredity was solely defined in
the age-old anti-Jewish alleg atio n .T h e ambitious SA leadership under terms of ancestors’ religion. The resulting calculations of degrees of blood
Ernst Rohm may have indeed formed a threat to his own rule, but accord­ admixture for anyone but a “full” Jew were the subject of endless debates
ing to Hitler it was the nation’s life that was in danger: among Nazi jurists and administrators (up to the “Wannsee conference”
of 20 January 1942, which coordinated the already ongoing genocide).®^
The nation must know that no one can threaten her existence . . . A na­ Notwithstanding these technical problems, the laws sufficed to ensure that
tion only has itself to blame if she does not find the strength to defend “proof that one was not of Jewish origin or did not belong to any ‘less valu­
herself against such parasites [Schddlinge].”'^"' able’ group became essential for a normal existence in the Third Reich”.
Any connection with Jews now carried the threat of criminalisation. For
If Hitler was ready to sacrifice his own comrades as well as incur the oppro­ Jews were not just being segregated from German society; they were now
brium attendant on ordering the killing of members of the top ranks of the systematically linked to crime and deviancy under the parasite/pest label
traditional military and political establishment on account of their being in police reports, party speeches and the Nazi press.®^ Particular emphasis
Schadlinge, then it was plain to all that inclusion in the parasite category was laid on the link to sex crimes. The “prototypical” blood-poisoning sce­
amounted to nothing less than a latent death warrant. The German pub­ nario of the rape and/or seduction of non-Jewish victims by Jews, which, as
lic, presented with the tale of an attempted coup d’etat (as well as with we-saw, occupied a central place in Hitler’s imagination was continuously
lurid hints of “unspeakable” scenes in which SA leaders had been found reinforced by the “popular” outlets of anti-Semitic Nazi propaganda, such
on arrest), showed for the most part relief as to the ensuing restriction of as Julius Streicher’s Der StMrwen”
the SA’s “rowdy” violence and admiration for the Fiihrer’s decisiveness in With the Nuremberg laws, the Reich’s highest legal experts went to great
cleansing {Sduberung, Reinigung) his own movement of Schadlinge, accord­ lengths to describe precisely all sexual activities that might be subsumed
ing to underground rep o rts.V icto r Klemperer noted that the lack of legal uif^der the label of Rassenschande.^^ With such official backing, party mem­
grounds for the executions was accepted as irrelevant on account of Hit­ bers as well as “ordinary” citizens now engaged in the business of denun­
ler’s authority as Fiihrer. He also reported that Goebbels attempted to link ciations.®^ The pornographic racist “male fantasies” (Theweleit 1980) that
the attempted coup d’etat to Jews.^^ A more tenuous connection—between had always been a central part of anti-Semites’ obsessions were made legal
Jewish emigrants and the leadership of the SA, of all people—could hardly and social reality. In order to fit “real” experiences to the stereotype of
be imagined. Most importantly, however, Hitler came out of the affair as “the Jew” as a sexual parasite and predator, the Nazis did not shy away
being resolute and “consistent”: he was regarded as having proven himself from provoking or enacting the supposedly “typical” behaviour. Sopade
firm enough to destroy any illnesses and parasites on the nation’s body, reports mention, for instance, the “coincidental” public kissing of a Jewish
Presentation and Reception o f Anti-Semitic Imagery 49
48 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
approach to public opinion management as regards the “Jewish question”.
doctor by two female patients to effect his arrest as a race defiler^ and
Goebbels uses the insider knowledge of his audience of party propaganda
the case of two teenage sweethearts being chased by Nazis into a dark
experts about anti-Jewish policies to instruct them to (mis-)inform the Ger­
alleyway to justify their arrest of the Jewish boy on a charge of attempted
man and international public on a cynically applied “need-to-know” basis.
rape.^^ The “Jewish question” was now inextricably tied to the taboo area
He lays the main emphasis on deceiving Jews who are still living in Nazi
of criminal(ised) sexuality; Jewish people and anyone who might befriend
Germany, but underlying this trick is a differentiation of the general public
them were constantly threatened with public humiliation, conviction for
into groups of distinct degrees of political understanding. Going from the
- race defilement and subsequent transportation to a concentration camp.^^
centre to the periphery, these groups would include: 1) the innermost circle
The multiple source-target blend of the blood-poisoning-parasite scenario
of the party and SS leaders who were agreed on eliminating Jews from
had become a self-fulfilling stigmatization technique: the (metaphorical)
the German nation, 2) the colluding members of the old elites (in military,
Jewish parasite identity was linked to supposedly real criminal behaviour
administrative, legal, and economic functions, who were needed—and gen­
and this in turn was portrayed as particularly abhorrent due to its alleged
erally willing—to “work towards the Fuhret”), 3) various circles of party
link with the “Jewish” core parasite group.
officials and members who were relatively well-informed as regards Nazi
At the same time, despite the maximally stigmatizing rhetoric and the
policy aims but had to be kept under discipline until violent action would
legally binding force of the Nuremberg decrees. Hitler was careful not to
become opportune, 4) the general, non-committed German and interna­
spell out all the genocidal consequences of the body-parasite scenario just
tional public, 5) resistance and victim groups who should be kept in the
yet. No less a propaganda expert than Goebbels provides us with an expla­
dark until it was too late for them to take counter-measures.**®
nation of this aspect in a special, non-public speech to party functionaries
Goebbels’s praise for Hitler’s 1935 speech at Nuremberg as a model of
at the Nuremberg rally of 1935. He hailed Hitler’s speech as exemplary
how to present measures against the Jewish parasite appears to have been
because it introduced the most stringent and menacing anti-Jewish mea­
proven right by the public reaction. The Nuremberg race laws were seen as
sures by way of a drip-feed tactic designed to address at the same time
reining in the “rowdy” violence of local party groups, which though ideo­
several audiences (including the victims!) and satisfy their needs to know
logically “on the right lines”, proved embarrassing for the Nazi leadership
and to hope: due to their ostentatious, savage violence. Both the SD and the resistance
reports note tacit approval among large parts of the public as the legisla­
[You have to always leave the ending open] just as the FUhrer did in
tion was expected “to restore calm to the street”. Even people who were
his masterly speech yesterday: ‘We hope that the laws concerning the
neutral to or critical of the Nazi regime were taken in by the Nazi leaders’
Jews have opened the chance for a tolerable relationship between the
assurances that reports about state terror, torture and race hatred against
German and the Jewish peoples and . . . ’ [laughter]. That’s what I call
the Jews were “atrocity propaganda” and that the Nazi “revolution” was
skill'. That works'. But if one had said immediately afterwards: Well,
these are today’s laws for the Jews; don’t think that’s everything; next the “least bloody” in world history.**^
month . . . there’ll be new ones so that in the end you’ll be back to be­ The control that Hitler and Goebbels had over the mass media meant
ing beggars in the ghetto—then it’s no surprise the Jews mobilize the that Nazi anti-Semitic propaganda could be turned on and off according to
whole world against us. But if you leave a little chance open to them, the need of differentially addressing the diverse layers of public opinion in
Germany and the world. In 1936, for instance, during the Olympic Games,
then the Jews will say, ‘Hey, if we start atrocity propaganda from out­
copies of Der Sturmer disappeared from display in Berlin, as a gesture
side, it’ll be worse, so let’s keep quiet, and maybe we can go on after
to placate international opinion. Even the assassinatipju>f--th&.Nazi rep­
air [laughter, applause].^®
resentative Wilhelm Gustloff by a Jewish student in Switzerland in Febru­
ary 1936 did not trigger anti-Jewish actions, on express orders.**^ One year
As their reactions show, no-one in Goebbels’s audience of party function­
later, however, the rabidly racist touring pseudo-documentary exhibition
aries was in any doubt that the destruction of the Jews’ social existence in
The Eternal Jew {Der ewige Jude) started to be shown throughout Ger­
Germany at the very least was the goal of the decrees proclaimed the day
many until 1939.*’“' At local and regional level, the terror against Jews and
before by the FUhrer. Spelling out their final outcome was, however, coun­
other groups defined as Schadlinge continued unabated.**^
ter-productive, according to Goebbels’s advice: it would be a premature
The overall success of this flexible strategy can be observed at the cli­
warning for the Jews inside Germany and alienate world opinion, which
max of pre-war public anti-Jewish policies in Nazi Germany, the so-called
could damage the still fragile German economic recovery. We have here
“Crystal Night” pogrom of 9-10 November 1938, which was staged as a
an instance not only of the general technique of tailoring propaganda and
“spontaneous” outbreak of popular fury over the assassination of Ernst
information policies to popular o p in io n ,b u t also of the differentiated
50 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Presentation and Reception of Anti-Semitic Imagery 51
vom Rath, a German Embassy official in Paris, by the seventeen-year-old if Germany should be “dragged into a w ar” (which had only narrowly
Pole Herschel Grynspan (whose family had been among 16,000 people been avoided in the Sudetenland crisis in the preceding year). For such an
forcibly deported to Poland in October, as part of the Third Reich’s mea­ eventuality, he had a “prophecy” that would be fulfilled as precisely as all
sures to expel Jews)/^ To keep up the pretence of spontaneity, Hitler did his other predictions always had been:
not issue official orders in his capacity as Chancellor of the Reich and it was
not the ordinary “order police” but SA, SS and GESTAPO who carried out I have very often in my lifetime been a prophet and have been mostly
the burning of synagogues and Jewish shops in cities, towns and villages derided. At the time of my struggle for power it was in the first instance
-up and down the country, the ransacking of homes and violence that cost the Jews who only greeted with laughter my prophecies that I would
hundreds of lives and led to the arrest of about 30,000 Jewish men, as well some day take over the leadership of the state and of the entire people of
as 300-500 suicides."*^ The violence had been as ostentatious as possible Germany and then, among other things, also bring the Jewish problem
in order to “intimidate as many Jews as possible into leaving Germany”/® to its solution. I believe that this hollow laughter of Jewry in Germany
Reactions in the German public, as recorded by the SD and GESTAPO has already stuck in its throat. I want today to be a prophet again: if
and in the Social Democrat resistance reports, ranged from isolated offers international finance Jewry inside and outside Europe should succeed
of help and protests over displays of shame and embarrassed silence to in'plunging the nations once more into a world war, the result will be
expressions of fear of negative foreign reactions and anger at the wanton not the Bolshevization of the earth and thereby the victory of Europe,
destruction of property and, from the Nazi faithful, wholehearted endorse­ but the annihilation [Vernichtung] of the Jewish race in Europe!^^
ment of utmost brutality/^ Still, the chief Nazi (and by then, national) daily
newspaper, Volkischer Beobachter, claimed that “not a single hair had This threat of extermination has often been quoted as the definite announce­
been touched on a Jewish head”/° Such brazen denial can hardly count ment of Hitler’s genocidal intentions against the European Jews,^^ and it
as an efficient attempt at covering up the extreme violence vis-a-vis either is not just with the benefit of hindsight that such an interpretation seems
the German or the world public/^ Rather, it turned the victims and their correct. After all, at the start of 1939 the “outbreak” of a war was not
treatment, in the words of the historian Marion A. Kaplan, “into the object exactly unlikely, as Hitler’s annexations in 1938 had only been achieved on
of a general, hateful taboo’V^ k®- ^ very special kind of “open secret” that the basis of massive threats of military aggression. It was also well known
was commonly known but unspeakable and thus, not truly “open”—in that Hitler regarded Jews at the very least as a liability for Germany at
fact, even its status as a secret was, officially, secret/^ Less paradoxically, war, given their supposed track record of treason in World War I.^® The
Kershaw (2008) speaks of the “exceptional sphere of politics” to which “prophecy” was the climax of an extended passage in Hitler’s speech that
the whole “Jewish question” belonged (together with the Fiihrer myth as dealt almost exclusively with the “Jewish question”. Starting with a sar­
its opposite), as distinct from “everyday” culture in Nazi Germany, which castic allusion to the hypocrisy of “democratic states” that “shed crocodile
allowed for a relatively high degree of conflict, dissent and complaint/** By tears for the poor, oppressed Jewish people” but were so “hard-hearted
contrast, the “exceptional sphere” comprised core topics and attitudes that as to eschew their duty to help them”,^^ Hitler portrayed Germany as a
were focused on “distant utopian goals” and in relation to which “rejection nation that over the centuries had allowed the Jews, who “had nothing
of National Socialism and opposition to its policies played as good as no of their own, except for political and sanitary diseases”, to infiltrate and
role whatsoever”/^ From the Nazi propaganda viewpoint, the Kristallnacht sponge off it until they had turned the Germans into beggars in their own
pogrom would then have been problematic insofar as it brought the perse­ country. Hitler paid lip service to the principle that the earth might “have
cution of Jews back into the sphere of “everyday” experience and made its roqm enough to accommodate the Jews”, but he insisted that the condi­
brutality visible to too many people who were still outsiders. tion for a satisfactory solution of the “Jewish '^estldfi’n iad to be the end
It was the Fiihrer himself who, true to Goebbels’s praise back in 1935, of the misconception “that the good Lord had meant the Jewish nation to
would provide an example of how to reveal parts of the “open taboo” spqnge off a certain percentage of the body and productive work of other
whilst still keeping it safely in the “exceptional sphere” of the nation’s nations” {Nutzniefler am Korper und an der produktiven Arbeit anderer
“highest” concerns. And again, it was his use of the body-parasite sce­ Volker zu sein)A^ If Jewry would not join the “constructive work of other
nario that was instrumental in achieving this effect. A little more than peoples”, however, it would “succumb to a crisis of unimaginable sever­
two months after the Kristallnacht pogrom, on 30 January 1939, Hitler ity” {Krise von unvorstellbarem Ausma(^e)A^ This prediction was followed
addressed the Reichstag on the occasion of the sixth anniversary of his by the “prophecy”; and it, in turn, was reiterated with the slight variation
accession to power, listing for more than two hours his seemingly trium­ that in case of a new “senseless” war “that only served Jewish interests”,
phant achievements. For the future, he promised more of the same, even the world would see the same result of an “enlightenment” about their
52 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Presentation and Reception o f Anti-Semitic Imagery 53
true aims as had been effected in Germany within a few years, i.e. Jewry’s -were warned to leave this non-negotiable core concern of Nazi ideology to
“complete demise”/^ those in power; and those who considered opposing the Nazi regime were
With the historical hindsight of what happened after 1939, it is almost left in no doubt as to the fateful consequences for themselves were they to -
impossible not to read Hitler’s "prophecy” as a kind of precis of the geno­ hinder the regime in carrying out its genocidal intentions.
cide to come, phrased, of course, with his own ideological “spin” of blaming
the Jews in advance for what he wanted to do to them later. In the context
of the speech and the historical situation, however, the prophecy is based 4.2 FULFILLING THE PROPHECY OF PARASITE ANNIHILATION:
on the metaphoric scenario of Hitler’s anti-Semitic core ideology that had VICTORY AS RACIAL THERAPY, 1939-1943
been established since the 1920s, complete with the body-parasite source,
its political application, its metaphysical extrapolation to God’s plan for the The 1939 prophecy must have been an object of considerable pride for
peoples of the earth, and the apocalyptic goal of a “purifying” catastrophe, Hitler, for he referred to it later several times, especially in the anniver­
i.e. the complete destruction of the parasite. The prophecy is thus almost sary speeches of 30 January 1941 and 1942. Hitler consistently misdated
tautological in view of the preceding prediction of a “crisis of unimaginable the prophecy to 1 September 1939, i.e. the day of the attack on Poland,
severity” for Jewry; it only specifies one precise further condition, i.e. the which started the Second World War.^^ His error was telling, if not delib­
outbreak of a world war. The main difference to the scenario exposition in erate: by 1941/42, Hitler considered his prophecy’s premise—of the out­
Mein Kampf was thus not the content of the prophecy but its topicality in break of a new world war that had been started by the Jews—as fulfilled
view of the impending world war. and therefore saw himself as legitimised to carry out its conclusion, i.e.
By leaving a minimal room of conditionality and the need to “trans­ the therapy of Europe’s illness by way of genocide. In January 1941, in a
late” the figurative into literal “annihilation”, the 1939 prophecy still con­ speech predominantly devoted to attacking Britain for its unwillingness
formed to the tactics that Goebbels had praised so highly in '1935. Even to accept his various “peace offers”, Hitler used a slightly vaguer formula­
Victor Klemperer appears to have attached no special ominous significance tion than “annihilation”: now, he spoke of his “hint” {Hinweis) of 1939
to it, although he noted the speech in his diary as an instance of Hitler’s that “the whole of Jewry will have ceased to play a role in Europe” {das
trick “to make all his enemies into Jews”.^** The prime audience who were gesamte Judentum [wird] seine Rolle in Europa ausgespielt haben).^^ The
intended to embrace the “disingenuous” but logically still possible reading “evidence” he cited for the prediction coming true is the assertion that one
of a last hope for avoiding an “annihilation” outcome were, however, no nation after another was accepting the German “understanding of raCce”
longer Jews in Germany but the general populace, who did not want to (Rassenerkenntnis)-, only British politicians, due to “softening of the brain”
believe that a world war was close. Foreign reporters such as the American caused by Jewish emigrants, were unable to see this “truth”, but he hoped
William Shirer as well as the secret reports of the exiled Social Democrats that even “those who were still enemies at present” would one day recog­
and the SS Sicherheitsdienst all indicate widespread anxiety at the prospect nize their true “inner enemy”.^^
of war in September 1938 during the Sudetenland crisis and massive relief This 1941 version of the prophecy fits in with the ongoing relentless pro­
and hope for a lasting peace after its seeming “resolution” in the Treaty of paganda effort of reinforcing the two key tenets of supposedly corroborat­
Munich.^^ In the run-up to the following “crises” over the fate of the remain­ ing evidence for the Nazi interpretation of the war at that stage: 1) German
ing Czechoslovakian state and the Danzig/“corridor” conflict with Poland, superiority, as “demonstrated” by the successful military campaigns in
the pretence of striving for a peaceful resolution was kept up.^^ Those who Poland, Benelux, France, Denmark, Norway dj^n g 1939:::4D,Z£.and 2) the
wanted to believe in the Nazi leadership’s “peaceful” intentions—even if depravity of Jewish parasite that waa close to meeting its deserved come­
only out of sheer despair—could still dismiss the prophecy as exaggerated uppance at the hands of the victorious German forces. This triumphant
propaganda oratory. On the other hand, the predictions of annihilation/ confirmation -of the Fuhrer’s prophecy probably found its most explicit
demise/crisis of unimaginable severity were strong enough to indicate to articulation in the film The eternal Jew {Der ewige Jude), which together
anyone that engaging with the “Jewish question” was “exceptional”, a mat­ with The Rothschilds {Die Rothschilds) and Jew Siiss {Jud Siiss) formed the
ter of the highest importance. The status of the Jews as a “hateful taboo” infamous mini-series of three films commissioned by Goebbels in 1939 to
was thus reinforced for various audiences at the same time: fervent Nazis bolster anti-Semitism.^^
(and anyone with the ambition to make a career in the state apparatus) were By late autumn 1940, when The Eternal Jew appeared in the cinemas,
encouraged in redoubling their efforts to join in anti-Semitic actions; mod­ “ordinary” Germans had witnessed an extraordinary year. The country had
erate supporters and non-committed citizens were reassured that the state been at war since September 1939, and had witnessed a series of Blitzkrieg-
would find a “solution” for the “Jewish question”; sceptics and doubters triumphs that were without precedent and put most of continental Europe
54 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Presentation and Reception of Anti-Semitic Imagery 55
between the Atlantic and the borderline with Soviet Russia under direct sponging, decay, decomposition and illness are continued throughout the
German control. By autumn 1940, the only enemy nation that had entered film and applied to religious, artistic, economic and political issues.
the war in 1939 that was left was the United Kingdom, which according The myth of the “Wandering Jew” (Ahasverus) is not dwelt on as such,
to Nazi propaganda was isolated and certain to surrender at some point. but the theme of Jewish migration forms a central motif of the film. It is
Relations with the USSR were officially amicable, with foreign affairs com­ conceptually reinforced at three levels:
missary Molotov visiting Berlin in November. Secretly, the Nazi leadership
was making plans for the invasion of the USSR but these were obviously a) Jewish ethnic migration over the past 4,000 years, starting from
not publicised. In terms of the general strategic situation, the Reich thus Mesopotamia, via Egypt, Canaan and later advancing through the
seemed secure, almost unassailable. Greek and Roman empires to all of Europe and, after reconsoli­
As regards the Jewish population, the Altreich had seen the first mass dation in Eastern Europe (following the “defensive” anti-Jewish
deportations in February 1940 from Pomerania to the Lublin ghetto in medieval pogroms in Western Europe), across the world.
occupied Poland, and in October from Baden and the Palatinate to occu­ b) The “exemplary” case of the famous Rothschild family, whose
pied F ra n c e ,a s well as a series of anti-Jewish laws and administrative banking empire has migrated and spread from one banking house
regulations that furthered their systematic isolation from the non-Jewish in Frankfurt first over Europe and then the whole world; they
population. They included the introduction of the “Jewish” names “Israel” represent the prototype of the alleged global influence of finance
and “Sara” on identification documents and the forced removal to the Jewry, whose catastrophic consequences for all nations are illus­
so-called JudenhduserJ^ Whilst real Jewish people were forced to retreat trated by the banking crises of the 1920s.
and disappear from actual public life, their supposed collective identity c) In direct analogy and supported by inter-cutting and commentary
was reinvented according to the Nazi ideological model in the three assertions, Jewish migration patterns are identified with the migra­
above-mentioned anti-Semitic propaganda filrns.^^ The three films were tion patterns of parasitizing vermin, specifically rats that spread
accorded massive resources as well as careful planning, with detailed input diseases such as “plague, leprosy, typhoid, cholera, dysentery”.
from both Goebbels and Hitler.^®
Whilst the most successful of the three films, Jud Suss, concentrated on The analogy of Jews-as-race/nation and Jews-as-a-clan/class with illness­
the biography of one individual, i.e. the negative hero Joseph Suss-Oppen- spreading rats formed a concentrated filmic visualisation of the body-par­
heimer, and the much less successful (and subsequently rewritten and re-re- asite scenario that lay at the core narrative of the Nazi ’’solution” of the
leased) Die Rothschildts provided a historical sketch of the bankii^ family’s "Jewish problem”.’^ The only possible inference from this analogy was that
rise to financial world domination at the time of the Napoleonic Wars, The the recipe for success in combating epidemic-spreading vermin had to be
Eternal Jew was presented as a documentary, as its sub-title asserts: “A film applied to their supposed human counterparts, i.e. annihilation. Whilst
contribution to the problem of world Jewry” {Ein Filmbeitrag zum Problem the images of rats may have been “topped” in terms of sheer gore by the
des Weltjudentums). The film promised to reveal the “true” identity of “the reconstruction scenes of ritual cattle slaughter (which were advertised as
Jew”, which was not easily visible from the “civilised” West and Central such through special captions warning the “sensitive” parts of the audience
European, including German, Jewry due to their clever camouflage. to look away and were omitted from screenings for youths), the illness­
This revelation of the “true” Jewish national/racial character had been spreading migration o f parasites formed the conceptual basis for charac­
made possible by the German victory over Poland: only now could the Jews terising Jewry as a mortal danger: it identified the featuresj)£.an, “eternal
be seen, according to the voice-over, at their “nesting site” (Niststdtte). parasitic existence” as the features of the ,‘^Eternal Jew” (Die Ziige des
The film introduces Jews as the “origin of plague in humanity” [Pestherd ewigen Schmarotzertums— die Ziige des Ewigen Juden).
der Menschheit). In the first place, this is visualised by pictures of “dirty The end of the film, in the words of the contemporary review magazine
and neglected” Jewish living quarters—schmutzig und verwahrlost, as the u e r deutsche Film, provided “a return to the light” for the audience. “Ger­
speaker states. Soon afterwards, the “systematic” categorisation follows: man people and German life surround us once more. It is as if we have
Jews are proclaimed to be a “people of parasites” (ein Volk von Parasiten), travelled to distant parts and we feel the difference that separates us from
followed by the “explanation” (referenced to a quotation from Richard the Jew with a horrifying shudder.”^^ The Fiihrer’s measures to deal with
Wagner’s anti-Semitic writings) that “wherever a sore has opened on a the parasite are recalled: prohibition of kosher slaughtering in 1933, the
nation’s body, they will settle and feed on the decaying organism” (Immer Nuremberg laws of 1935 and as the climax, the clip of his 1939 prophecy,
dort wo sich am Volkskorper eine Wunde zeigt, setzen sie sich fest und announcing the annihilation of the Jewish race in Europe. After that, the
ziehen aus dem verfallenden Organismus ihre Nahrung). The motifs of film wallows in pictures of Aryan boys and girls, banners, marching music
56 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Presentation and Reception o f Anti-Semitic Imagery 57
and marching troops that take the German viewers back into the present However, as Saul Friedlander has emphasized, “the commercial success
of autumn 1940.
of Jud Siiss and the limited commercial appeal of Der Ewige Jude should
Was The Eternal Jew just a filmic repeat, then, of Hitler’s previous state­ not be viewed as contrary results in terms of Goebbels’s intentions . . . both
ments, or did it make a new contribution to the propagandistic preparation films can be considered two different facets of an endlessly renewed stream
of the Holocaust? Generally, its themes would have been familiar to anyone of anti-Jewish horror stories, images, and arguments”.®^ Where Jud Siiss
in Germany who had been exposed to Nazi propaganda in the years before. told an engaging human story, Der Ewige Jude purported to be informa­
The scenes from Polish ghettos, supposedly giving an objective impression tive, objective, scientific. It could not be expected to become a blockbuster
of Jewish life there, had been shown in many a Wochenschau reel as well but was still a perfect blueprint for genocide propaganda “in the age of
as in the campaign “documentary” Feldzug in Polen, which was directed
technical reproduction” (Walter Benjamin): its images reappeared in count­
by the same director as The Eternal Jew, Fritz Hippier.®*^ The equation of less posters and pamphlets. Prior to and during the onslaught on the Soviet
Jews and illness-carrying parasites could not have come as a surprise to Union in 1941 the film was shown to the Wehrmacht and police units that
anyone who had lived consciously through the preceding years. But the were directly involved in the mass murders of Jewish civilians; it even found
film’s “innovative” contribution to the campaign of familiarising Germans its way into the killers’ training journals and manuals:
with the plan for genocide lay in the direct link it constructed between the
body-parasite scenario and Hitler’s prophecy.
The word of the Fiihrer that a new war, instigated by Jewry, will not
This link had been included already in his 1939 speech itself but was bring about the destruction of anti-Semitic Germany but rather the
implicit in the extended passage vilifying the Jews, which as a whole was end of Jewry is now being carried out. The gigantic spaces of the east,
“par for the course” of Nazi anti-Semitic rhetoric.®^ Crucially, at that time which Germany and Europe have now at their disposition for coloniza­
the possibility of war was a threat, not reality. Since then, the antecedent tion, also facilitate the definitive solution of the Jewish problem in the
of his conditional statement had become true: war had broken out. In this near future. This means not only removing the race of parasites from
context, Hitler’s misdating of the speech to 1 September 1939 is significant: power, but its elimination from the family of European peoples.®^
apparently, he wanted the prophecy to have been made on the occasion of
the outbreak of war, so that the consequence—annihilation of all Jewish For the perpetrators, then, the combination of parasite scenario and Fiihrer
people in Europe—would be more noticeable. The film, corrected, as it prophecy was a succinct and stimulating affirmation of what they were
were, the mis-timed announcement by re-contextualising both the scenario engaging in, i.e. the genocidal killing of all Jewish persons they could get
and the prophecy of the situation in the new time frame of autumn 1940. hold of. However, what did "ordinary” bystanders, in Raul Hilberg’s
Now the parasite race was exposed for what it was: its trail of migration words,®^ or in the case of cinema audiences, spectators, make of this film
and devastation throughout the world could be “scientifically” proven, and version of the parasite-annihilation scenario? The reports on popular opin­
the prophecy could be corroborated by evidence. What remained to do was ion compiled by the SS Sicherheitsdienst as well as by police divisions and
to -draw the practical conclusion from it and make the Eiihrer’s prediction local or regional Nazi Party organizations give us a detailed, though not
come true completely.
necessarily objective or representative, picture. In January 1941, the SD
The film opened on 28 November 1940 in thirty-six cinemas in Berlin drew a first resume from the reports that had come in from all over the
alone®^ and on the same day in film theatres all over Germany, accompa­
Reich. Singled out for praise were the “proofs” that Eastern and Western
nied by a huge advertising campaign in -the form of posters, promotional
Jews were of the same race “deep down”, despite their differing outward
material and newspaper reviews. Following on from Die Rothschilds appearances, and that vermin and Jewish mi^mtion patterns and effects
{released in July) and Jud Siiss (released in September), it was doubtless were congruent. Hitler’s announcement of the “Jewish question’s” solu­
intended to put the finishing touches to the anti-Semitic indoctrination of tion was said to have elicited “relieved and enthusiastic” applause.®® On
the general populace. However, the ticket sales soon fell off, as the film
the other hand, the report conceded that the film attracted mainly the
followed too soon after the popular success of JudSuss.^^ The Eternal Jew
“politically active” part of the population, whereas “the typical cinema-
had been released into an already partly saturated market and it made less
goer”,- who had liked Jud Siiss, did not attend in greater numbers and was
easy viewing than Jud Siiss’ with its engrossing plot and the vivid, engaging
indeed scared off by rumours about the disgusting slaughter scenes. The
performances by popular actors such as Ferdinand Marian, Werner Krauss
demonstration of such “Jewish filth” was deemed unnecessary.®^ A local
and Kristina Soderbaum. Hence, the audiences for The Eternal Jew were
report from rural Westphalia, where slaughter scenes would not have been
from the start smaller than those for Jud Siiss and fell away after the initial
particularly shocking to the largely farming population, even came up with
performances.®*’
the assessment that the film contents were all “well and good” but the form
Presentation and Reception o f Anti-Semitic Imagery 59
58 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
of presentation rather “boring” {Das Dargestellte sei alles gut und richtig, or text based on the analogy, still demanded a minimum of inferential
operation on the part of the audience in order to be fully “understood”. The
aber in der gebrachten Form etwas langweilig gewesen)?^
What is conspicuous by its absence is any hint of political comment, public were led to the intended conclusion but had to make the crucial infer­
let alone dissent. Of course, it is debatable to which degree such criticism ence (i.e. from the body-parasite scenario to the annihilation outcome) for
would have found entry into the SD reports. Any serious opponents or dis­ themselves. This inference from analogy demanded more cognitive effort
sidents would have been unlikely to attend such a film in the first place; if than the reception of a non-literal statement about the genocide (which was
they did, they would have been on their guard with regard to voicing their never officially made) would have demanded.^^ The film thus left no doubt
true feelings to anyone beyond a small circle of friends, given the high levels about what the Nazis were planning for the Jews but the responsibility for
of surveillance, oppression and denunciation in Nazi public life/Neverthe­ accepting this knowledge was left with the audience, thus making them
less, the SD reports do contain reports of popular distancing behaviour accomplices of the genocide.
on other occasions, for instance, during the November 1938 pogroms and After the invasion of the USSR on 22 June 1941, which was to deliver an
additional 2.5 million Jews into his h a n d s,H itle r repeated his trick from
also later during the war, when Goebbels’s attempts to denounce the Allied
1939 of blaming the whole conflict on “world Jewry”;^*^ but now he could
bombing campaign or to exploit Soviet war atrocities as evidence of Jewish-
set in motion a truly Europe-wide campaign of destruction against the par­
Bolshevik cruelty were not only met with scepticism but even relativised by
asite race. Accordingly, during the summer and autumn of 1941, SS Ein-
damning comparisons between these crimes and German treatment of the
satzgruppen, police reserve battalions, and Wehrmacht troops started mass
Jews as well as of Polish and Russian civilians.^^ After all, the reports were
killings that quickly developed into the wholesale annihilation of local and
not intended in the first place to serve as evidence in the active prosecution
regional communities.^^ During the campaign, Hitler’s 1939 “prophecy”
of opponents and dissidents but to “feel the pulse” of the populace. The
about the annihilation of Jewry, linked to references to Jews as parasites,
covert elicitation and evaluation of the reports was designed to circumvent
appeared time and again in the letters of perpetrators and training journals
the caution that would prevent people from voicing dissent publicly.
Although it is notoriously difficult to draw conclusions from negative for Order Police units.^^
After-the defeat of the German offensive outside Moscow and the United
evidence, the absence of any major dissenting voices from the film audiences
States’ entry into the war in December 1941, however, the context of the
of 1940/41 can be interpreted at the very least as evidence that the message
genocidal campaign and its propagandist^ support changed. The suppos­
of the Jew-as-parasite concept in The Eternal Jew did not strike the view­
edly Jewish-controlled USSR had shown its ability to fight back, which
ers as exceptional. Fervent Nazis (and anyone with the ambition to make a
even Hitler had to acknowledge in p u b lic ,a n d the Western war coalition
career in the state and party apparatus) could feel encouraged in redoubling
had strengthened immeasurably. The threat to eliminate the European Jews
their efforts to cleanse Germany of "the Jew”. Moderate supporters and
non-committed citizens were at least reassured that the Fiihrer had found had no further use as a means of blackmailing or intimidating other states,
and was now implementing the final “solution” of the “Jewish question”; nor could the mass murder be postponed so as to provide an “addendum”
for uncertain or wavering spectators, the combination of parasite imagery to a quickly completed military victory, for it was evident that the war
and Fiihrer’s prophecy was at least sufficiently unambiguous to know in would last for a considerably longer period.^®
general terms that the treatment of the parasitic Jews lay at the core of Nazi Hitler implicitly admitted as much in his speech to a popular rally in
rule and was therefore not to be interfered with. The sceptics and doubters Berlin on 30 January 1942 when he presented the alternative that the war
were warned to leave this non-negotiable part of Nazi ideology to those in could only end “either with the obliteration.©f'th'e'rAry^peoples or the
power. Anyone who contemplated opposing the Nazi regime’s core project disappearance of Jewry from Europe” {dafS'entweder die arischen Volker
or thwart the Fiihrer was left in no doubt as to the fateful consequences for ausgerottet werden oder dafl das Judentum aus Europa verschwindet).
themselves and their family and friends. The combination of the prophecy His response to the rhetorical question—’’which outcome .would it be?”—
and the body-parasite scenario thus still fulfilled the remit set by Hitler and was to recite his prophecy of “annihilation”, this time embellishing it with
Goebbels: whilst being unambiguously encouraging for their followers, it the reference to the “truly ancient Jewish law ‘An eye for an eye, and a
also catered for the different audiences across the whole spectrum of Ger­ tooth for a tooth’”, which he promised to apply “for the first time” to the
Jews themselves. All of this was topped up with a further prediction that
man popular opinion.
The Eternal Jew spelt out the necessity of genocide in “graphic” detail— the hour would come “when the most evil world enemy of all times will
have ended his role for a thousand years”.A c c o r d in g to Sicherheitsdienst
but still only in the form of an analogy. Following the analogical argument,
reports, the broadcasted speech was praised and the accusations against
everyone could know what the “real” application of the racial parasite ther­
. the Jews with the specific emphasis on the ‘Eye for an eye . . . ’ phrase were
apy implied, i.e. genocide, but on the other hand, the film, just as a speech
60 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Presentation and Reception of Anti-Semitic Imagery 61
interpreted as an indication that the Fiihrer’s “fight against the Jew was can now be acknowledged. For Hitler, the Jewish parasite was now reap­
being conducted with utmost consequence to its end and that soon the last ing the just rewards for starting the new world war, and it would perish
Jew would be deported {vertrieben) from the European continent”.^'^^ By together with its host nation. Germany’s war effort, led by its redeemer-
this time, the public evidence of the “utmost consequences” was unavoid­ Fiihrer, was the surgical intervention that brought to fruition what was
able: since autumn 1941, the remaining German Jews had to wear the open in any case inevitable. This was Hitler’s own “truth” about the unfolding
stigma of the yellow star and their numbers dwindled due to the ever-ac­ Holocaust at the height of its implementation: still couched in parasite-
celerating deportations to the East. From October 1941 onwards, any ’’metaphoric” language but ostentatiously murderous.
public show of friendly relations or pity towards Jews by non-Jewish Ger­ Victor Klemperer saw in Hitler’s speech of April “intensification of
mans was deemed an offence worthy of arrest and, in “serious cases”, of hatred to the highest degree of madness”, brought about by the method
imprisonment in a concentration camp.’°^ of “combining secrecy and open threat”.^®’ He read it as a sign that the
Hitler’s repeated public references to the “fulfilment” of the annihilation “end” was imminent, not “five minutes before twelve” but “11.59 o’clock”
prophecy against European Jewry as a therapy of Germany and Europe’s and whether Jews “would still live to the end of the day” was dubious.'
illness in 1941-42, which were recycled time and again by Goebbels,^®** left After he heard an older worker shouting at him “You Jewish swine” {Du
no doubt that he regarded the now ongoing genocide as the realization of Judenluder), he concluded that for Jews perhaps even “11.59 o’clock” was
his greatest ambition and as “doing the Lord’s work”. The annihilation of no longer the correct time.’°^ Nazis were evidently reassured by the speech,
the Jewish parasite race was now made public to anybody who wished to as it “blamed the Jews for the military losses and the devastation inflicted
listen to it. In his Reichstag speech of 26 April 1942, Hitler reconfirmed by the Allied bombing campaign”^® and thus confirmed the overall cogni­
his redemptive-therapeutic scenario of what he saw as “world history in the tive frame in which the war against the Jewish world enemy was just and
making” in such an emphatic manner that it left little room for any non- successful. Caught in the middle, “ordinary Germans” were on the one
genocidal interpretation: hand “no longer impressed by the propaganda” but unable to voice opposi­
tion, which would invariably elicit immediate prosecution; instead, tacit
Politically, this war is no longer about the interests of individual na­ opposition was visible from large-scale apathy and growing fears that the
tions but a conflict between those nations that want to assure their genocide of the Jews would lead to Allied retaliation.” ^
members’ right to exist on this earth and those that have become the However, during the summer of 1942, with both the systematic mass mur­
will-less instruments of an international world-parasite [Weltparasit]. der of Jews and the new offensives in southern Russia advancing relentlessly,” ^
The true character of this Jewish international war-mongering has now Hitler was still sufficiently confident to continue boasting of his prophecy
been revealed to the German soldiers and their allies in that country and to publicly emphasize its consequences with sadistic pleasure. At the end
where Jewry exerts its exclusive dictatorship .. . We know the theo­ of September, with the 6th Army seemingly poised to conquer Stalingrad, he
retical principles and the cruel truth underlying the aims of this world harked back to the alleged “mockery” of his prophecy by the Jews before he
pestilence [Weltpest], Its name is “dictatorship of the proletariat” but came to power, a topic that had figured also in his 1939 and 1941 speech­
its reality is the dictatorship of the JewE°^ es.”!^ He facetiously wondered about “whether by now there were any left
who were still laughing at him” and promised that they would soon stop:
Even if Bolshevik Russia is at the moment the tangible product of this not just in Germany but “everywhere”.” ** Friedlander calls the prophecy’s
Jewish infection, we must not forget that it is democratic capitalism that function by this time that of a “mantra announcing to all and sundry that
provides the conditions for such an outcome. . . . In the first phase of the fate of the Jews was sealed and soon none ^^uld^J:emaH^:44^^served as
this process [the Jews] debase the masses of millions of people to help­ a quasi-magical incantation to reassert Hitler’s double strategy of war and
less slaves . . . Later, this is followed by the extermination of the people’s genocide. In the anti-Semitic scenario as applied to the war situation, victory
national intelligentsia . . . What remains [of the people] is the beast in on the battlefield ensured annihilation of the Jews by making their deporta-
man plus a Jewish class that, once it has taken over, will eventually, as tion/mass murder physically possible; the genocide, on the other hand, was
parasites [als Parasit], destroy the own host on which it has grown.^®^ thought necessary to secure military success because it guaranteed, suppos­
edly, that there would be no resistance or “stabbing-in-the-back”.
These words echo the passages of Mein Kampf that we analysed earlier. In However, with the catastrophic turnaround in Germany’s military for­
contrast to its use in Mein Kam pf however, the body-parasite scenario is tunes at the battles of El Alamein and Stalingrad in late 1942/early 1943,
presented here no longer as a general law or a prediction but as a fact that the strategic context changed irredeemably, whilst eyewitness reports and
62 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Presentation and Reception of Anti-Semitic Imagery 63
rumours about the mass killings of Jews in occupied Poland and Russia necessary to stop the “Jewish infection” and the sacrifices that the nation
spread ever more widely in Germany.” ^ From this time onwards, Hitler’s would have to make would amount to a “surgical intervention” [operativen
references to his 1939 prophecy seem to have ceased. Its propagandistic Schnitt] that might feel and look gruesome but that was absolutely necessary
usefulness had ended. With military victory over the Allies becoming less if the redeemer-healer were to save the patient.^^^
likely if not impossible, the nexus between the prophecy’s two aspects— Goebbels’s speech was meant to “defeat defeatism” inside Germany
military victory and “annihilation” of the European Jews—was broken. and convince the enemies that any hope of a German surrender or immi­
As a consequence, the scenario started to be used on its own: no longer nent collapse was futile.^^° Klemperer, who read it in a Dresden newspaper
a fulfilled promise of victory, it was now being presented as an insurance (to which he had only access through a sympathising lawyer), noted the
against total defeat. implicit double threat against the remaining Jews and all Germans who
might stand in the way of a “total war”.^^’ For all the emphasis on the “cer­
tainty” of a final therapy, the very urgency of Goebbels’s “appeal-by-way-
4.3 RACIAL THERAPY THROUGH GENOCIDE AS of-threat” underlined the probability of the apocalyptic scenario-outcome,
AN END IN ITSELF: BODY-PARASITE IMAGERY i.e. total defeat. There is evidence that such disingenuous reception of Nazi
FOR THE “FINAL SOLUTION”, 1943-1945 propaganda was not confined to special, particularly sensitive readers such
as Klemperer but became more widespread over the course of 1943. Goeb­
On 30 January 1943, when the anniversary of the Nazi “power seizure” bels’s attempt later that year to utilize the discovery of the remains of several
effectively coincided with the final capitulation of the 6th Army at Stalin­ thousand Polish officers in Katyn as “proof” of Bolshevik-Jewish atrocities,
grad, Hitler’s ritual anniversary speech, read over the radio by Goebbels, for instance, appears to have largely backfired. The huge publicity given to
stated that only the National Socialist idea could put an end to “the Jew’s” the finds created genuine fear of Soviet-Jewish revenge atrocities following
warmongering and its effects of “tearing apart” [zerfleischen] and “decom­ a defeat of Germany and led to comparisons between the murder of the
posing” {zersetzen) humanity.” ^ The same imagery was used by Goebbels Polish officers and the German “treatment” of Jews, and even to suspicions
in his infamous “total war” speech of 18 February 1943, in which he inter­ that the mass graves had been made for Jews.’^^ For such a comparison to
preted the loss of the 6th Army as a “sacrifice” that could only be honoured be made, knowledge of the Jewish holocaust and of its ethical status as an
if the rest of the nation fought on with “total” commitment, lest a truly atrocity had to be presupposed. The chief implementers of the genocide
apocalyptic alternative to a German victory should become reality (which acknowledged as much when they emphasised the need to maintain secrecy
uncannily resembled the actual devastation wrought by Nazi Germany on about the actual (“literal”) killings. In the summer of 1943, M artin Bor-
Europe at the time): mann, chief of the “party chancellory”, gave orders to ensure that NSDAP
officials only referred to the “conscription” of Jews for “deployment of
Behind the advancing Soviet divisions we can already see the Jewish exe­ labour” in the East,^^^ and in October of that year, the Keichsfiihrer SS,
cution commandos and behind them we see the terror, the spectre of mil­ Heinrich Himmler, told the top brass of the SS that the extermination of
lions starving and complete anarchy in Europe. International Jewry thus the Jews would was a “page of glory” in their history that had to remain
proves itself to be the devilish ferment of decomposition [das teuflische publicly unmentionable forever.’^'’
Ferment der Dekomposition], feeling as it does an outright cynical plea­ At the same time, the regime redoubled its efforts to inculcate,in the
sure in plunging the world into the deepest chaos and causing the demise German public opinion the absolute necessity of the annihilation of the
of age-old civilizations, which it never had a part in.“ ® Jewish parasite, e.g. by way of “information” gampaigns-such-as-one enti­
tled “The Jew as World Parasite” [Der Jude als Weltparasit). Even these
With breathtaking rhetorical and ideological audacity, Goebbels transformed campaigns, however, elicited ambivalent, or at best “politically correct”,
the Soviet victory, which had just resulted in the loss of 300,000 men and a responses, according to the secret party and SD reports.^^^ Again it was not
major retreat of the German forces, into a negative “proof” of the truth of the the scenario as such that was doubted but the specific outcome: victory for
body-parasite scenario: it showed what a complete defeat of German forces Germany or victory for “the Jew”. One report from Franconia in August
would result in, i.e. the destruction of European/German civilization by the 1944 went so far as to spell out the “negative” outcome as a summary of
ferment of decomposition. This confirmation of the real possibility of a cata­ general opinion:
strophic outcome was, of course, still linked to the reassurance that Germany
had a chance to avoid it: if only the whole nation followed the Fiihrer and The people are convinced that in case of a victory of the others \in-
intensified her war effort, she would still win through. The radical measures folge eines nicht unserigen Sieges], Jewry will pounce on the German
64 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Presentation and Reception o f Anti-Semitic Imagery 65
people’s body [sich . .. auf den deutschen Volkskorper stiirzen] and by submitting to them (literally, “stroking them”: . .. man [glaubt] .. . ,
will make all its devilish and bestial plans, which have been publicized durch untertdniges Streicheln die selbstgezuchteten jiidischen Bakterien
by our press, reality. Therefore, our motto [must be]: death and annihi­ vielleicht entgiften zu konnen)}^^ Thanks to his own leadership, Germany,
lation to the Jew; for us, the future and life.’^^ on the other hand, was able to take decisive measures against the bacte-
riaP'^ Whilst the target-level reference of this metaphor application can be
The report asserts that the view of “the Jew” as a threat to the German assumed to be the parts of European Jewry who had survived the German
nation’s body had finally found resonance in the population by 1944, but onslaught, including people freed by the Allies in their advance over previ­
only to lead them to the fatalistic expectation of a grim fate. The party had ously German-held te rrito rie s,th e absurd source notion of “stroking bac­
little else to offer in response than the ritual reiteration of its “motto” with­ teria” betrays the disintegration of Hitler’s bio-political scenario. Stroking
out outlining any strategy other than the murder of the Jews. If the report one’s own bacteria would have been implausible at any scenario level, even
could be taken as representative, it would indicate that the “annihilation” within the conceptual metaphor system as outlined in Mein Kampf
of the Jews at the hands of the Germans was now seen as the initial part of Hitler’s broadcasted speech on the last anniversary of the 1933 “power
a total confrontation that was likely to bring down an apocalyptic revenge seizure” in January 1945 also lacked internal consistency, although he
upon the Germans (and which had already partly materialized in the Allied no longer claimed that the enemies were stroking their bacteria. Instead,
bombing campaign).’^^ On the one hand, this conclusion might be called a he asserted that Britain as well as all European continental nations that
“success” of the sustained propaganda effort in favour of the annihilation surrendered to the Allies would eventually suffer the fate of progressive
scenario; on the other hand, the fatalistic conclusion was the opposite of destruction and subsequent annihilation on account of the destructive (lit­
the intended effect. erally, decomposing) illness (auflosende Krankheit) of Bolshevism spread
Even Goebbels and Hitler’s own use of body-illness/parasite scenario by the “Kremlin’s Jews”.^^^ So far, the original scenario remained intact,
seems to have been affected by the lack of a plausible victorious scenario as a reiteration of the standard anti-Semitic illness narrative, with a cata­
outcome from 1943 onwards. Goebbels favoured metaphors and similes strophic outcome. However, Hitler could not admit that this was truly the
of Germany at this stage of the war as a sportsman (e.g. a long-distance end; he had to maintain that Germany would be exempt from the dire fate
runner or boxer) whose body was totally exhausted and covered in injuries of the other European nations and that the desperate urgency of its crisis
but who could still win if only he managed to endure one minute lon­ was at the same time the sign of Germany’s recovery.^^'^ This double target
ger than the opponents; the alternative would be the nation’s “biological application split the outcome of the body-parasite scenario into two mutu­
annihilation”.^^®Not only was the source concept of roughly equal bodily ally incompatible versions: annihilation of Europe that was surrendering to
strength between competitors misleading in view of the Allies’ vast superi­ “the Jew” and at the same time, the rescue of Germany (and following its
ority over Germany in man- and firepower but the whole scenario was con­ recovery that of Europe).
tradictory. A contest of sheer endurance, which everyone can still survive, Hitler’s other recorded statements in the time up to his suicide on 30
is fundamentally different from a fight to the death in which only one of April 1945, e.g. his proclamations to the party on 24 February, to the sol­
the combatants survives at the expense of the other’s life. In the latter case, diers on the Eastern front on 13 April (by then some twenty miles from Ber­
injuries and exhaustion signal impending collapse and defeat. In the con­ lin) and his “political testament” of 29 April 1945 still condemned the Jews
text of German retreats on all fronts, Goebbels’s emphasis on the exhaus­ as a “pestilence”, or “world poisoner” {Weltvergifter) but failed to give
tion aspects and his warning of Germany’s own biological annihilation at any plausible narrative of how the desperate crisis of the illness that they
the hand of “the Jew” as parasite/enemy would most likely have triggered had allegedly caused would end; the speeches^Rly-containednhe manic
despondency and fatalism rather than a renewal of the will to fight for the invocations of his will to avoid defeat.^^^ Xbe idea of rescuing Germany,
Nazi cause. The basic scenario of a physical struggle o f the nation’s body Europe and ultimately the whole world through annihilating the Jewish
was thus still maintained but the prospect of its “inevitable” outcome was parasite had turned into a reiteration of insults. Meanwhile, during the
certainly disheartening from the Nazi viewpoint. last months and weeks of the war, SS and Gestapo, aided in some cases
The imagery of Hitler’s last speeches also suffered from inconsistencies by the Wehrmacht and police troops, completed as much of the originally
that exposed the appeal to pursue the survival/therapy-by-extinction as the envisaged scenario implementation as possible by murdering as many of the
ravings of a “madman” (Klemperer),^^? ^hich made no attempt to sound remaining Jewish prisoners as they could.^^^
plausible. In the anniversary speech of 30 January 1944, Hitler included Right up to the unconditional surrender on 8 May 1945, some people
an ironically intended depiction of enemy nations as slaves of interna­ still accepted fragments of the scenario narrative, e.g. that the German
tional Jewry who tried to “detoxify” their “home-grown Jewish bacteria” defeat was a “victory of Bolshevism and international Jewry”,^®^ as noted
66 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Presentation and Reception o f Anti-Semitic Imagery 67

during the last months of the war by Victor Klemperer (who, together with Jew left no doubt about the desired outcome of the German-Jewish rela­
his wife, survived the bombing of Dresden on 13-14 Februaryand man­ tionship as envisaged by the Fiihrer, but official government statements and
aged to escape to Bavaria). As Klemperer noted, it was only the actual the state-controlled media claimed that “not a hair had been touched” on a
experience of foreign occupation that generated retrospective sympathies Jew’s head and that arrests were only made to protect Jews from “popular”
for resistance against Hitler’s regime (as well as a widespread sudden amne­ wrath.
sia about Nazi persecution of Jews).^^® Having devoted, perforce, the past All this changed with the imminence of the world war, to which Hitler,
twelve years under persecution to studying the language of his persecu­ referred at the earliest opportunity, i.e. in the speech of 30 January 1939,
tors, Klemperer had little hope that Nazi terminology and the ideology with the promulgation of his prophecy that linked the body-parasite sce­
contained in it would disappear overnight. When publishing his analysis of nario to the prediction of the complete annihilation of European Jewry.
“The Language of the Third Reich” in 1946-47, he noted that his young Its reiteration and boastful referencing in speeches up to autumn 1942
post-war students continued to use Nazi jargon, seemingly unaware of its marks the second phase of an ostentatious, uninhibited announcement of
murderous implications.^®^ Similar findings motivated Sternberger, Storz the genocide-in-progress as the victorious elimination of the world pesti­
and Siiskind to publish their articles on the “Lexicon of Inhumanity”.^“° lence or world parasite (see Hitler in April and September 1942, as quoted
Research in the US occupation zone in 1946 documented anti-Semitic atti­ earlier). From the SD reports and Klemperer’s notes it is evident that such
tudes among three fifths of the German population. Are such findings speeches and their incessant reinforcement by the party-controlled mass
proof that the Nazi “worldview” of the nation fighting for its life against media were received by an audience who through rumours, soldier’s reports
the Jewish parasite, as outlined in Mein Katnpf had remained unchanged or listening to forejgn broadcasts gradually learnt of the genocide unfolding
over the whole period of Nazi rule? in Eastern Europe and who began to associate the ever-increasing impact
of the Allied war effort, especially the bombing raids, with the persecution
of the Jews. The target level meaning of the body-parasite scenario, i.e. the
implementation of racial therapy by way of mass murder, was clearly no
4.4 CONCLUSION
longer the “insider knowledge” of some dedicated perpetrators but slowly
The evidence presented in this chapter indicates that whilst the core con­ became accessible to large sections of the general population.
cept of Jews as parasites on the body o f the nation remained unchanged Whilst the “metaphoric” status of the scenario was still upheld in official
for the Nazi leadership throughout their rule, its public presentation as rhetoric, its target application had become transparent, so that a simple
part of the illness-therapy narrative changed in relation to the needs and “camouflage” effect can hardly be assumed to pertain to its reception by
opportunities of its reception in the German populace. We can distinguish the majority of Germans during this phase. At the same time, however, the
three main phases in the “discourse career” of the body-parasite scenario continued use of the body-parasite scenario and its gruesome “outcome”
in-Nazi rhetoric. During the years 1933-1939, we find continued use of the descriptions {annihilation, destruction, extermination o f the parasite) sig­
scenario in its “canonical”, fully fledged form, ranging over all source and nalled the Holocaust’s political taboo status: it served as a warning to anyone
target levels from pseudo-metaphysical visions of fulfilling the “Creator s who wanted to engage with the “Jewish question” without acknowledging
will” by “removing” the Jew/parasite through associations with repulsive the Nazis’ authority in defining and treating that question that they were
physical illnesses and diseases to specific target-level allegations of criminal playing with fire. The metaphoric reference could thus also be understood
acts, including “race- defilement”. This constant invocation of the body- as an invitation to disengage and turn a blind'eye~to its'actual~genocidai
parasite scenario was coupled with ever more detailed legal, political and target level implementation.
socio-econpmic measures designed to destroy Jewish civil existence in Ger­ After the defeat at Stalingrad and the further military setbacks from
many. At the same time, however, given.the overall political context of 1943 onward. Hitler’s boastful references to the double fulfilment of the
international appeasement policy, the Nazi leaders kept on denying and prophecy, i.e. military victory plus annihilation of the Jew/parasite in
camouflaging their anti-Semitic campaigns. As Goebbels stated in his unof­ Europe, ceased. Strategic developments were from now on conceptualized
ficial 1935 lecture on anti-Semitic propaganda tricks, the aim was to lull the in “defence” rhetoric. The main remaining link between the military situ­
German populace, foreign states and even the Jews who were living inside ation and the “Jewish question” was the abstract notion that “the Jew”
Germany into a false sense of security whilst preparing the onslaught. was the secret power behind all enemy forces. The anti-Semitic parasite-
' This pretence was still kept up even on the occasion of the “Crystal pestilence-poisoner imagery continued to be employed, but now against
Night” pogrom: the outright violence of the SS and GESTAPO and the the background of fears of an impending military collapse. The propagan-
hate-filled rhetoric of Nazi speeches and campaigns such as The Eternal distic and political function of the body-parasite scenario was thus turned
68 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
on its head: in its former manifestation since the 1920s, it had triumphantly
announced the imminent completion of victory in the race war; now it epit­ 5 Methodological Reflection
omized the concentration of Germany’s war effort to continue the destruc­
tion of “the Jew” for as long as possible until its military power was spent. Body and Illness Metaphors in the
Now, given the ever-increasing knowledge about the genocide both inside
Germany and among its enemies and the signs of a military collapse, the
Evolution of Western Political Thought
_ “alternative” outcome of the scenario, i.e. the annihilation of Germany, and Discourse
began to dominate popular opinion. The regime’s assertions that it would
continue its fight against the Jewish parasite to the end turned the German
populace into accomplices of the genocide and at the same time into hos­
tages of their own national catastrophe.

Having studied several crucial phases in the development and reception


of the body-parasite metaphor scenario in Nazi Germany over the period
1930-1945, we can return to the question of how to explicate its cognitive
import, i.e. the way in which it was understood by its users and hearers as
a meaningful depiction of politics that could even motivate them to engage
in specific actions. In view of the historical consequences, the answer to
this question is far from trivial; however, at first glance, those text passages
from Nazi discourse (whether from Mein Kampf or from later speeches)
that contain relevant metaphor uses seem so absurd that it is difficult to
take them seriously. The descriptions of social and national groups in terms
of animal organisms and the practical conclusions that the Nazis drew
from them are so obsessive and grotesque that their rational discussion
seems impossible. Hence, historians have described their content as “enter­
ing the world of the insane” or sheer “nonsensicality”. Indeed, when analy­
sed stringently for logical consistency at either the source level of biology
and medicine or at the target level of politics, the metaphor scenario of the
German nation’s fight for its life against the Jewish parasite race is riddled
with contradictions and non sequiturs. However, when analysed as a meta­
phoric blend that “created” its own meaning system, the scenario did show
a high degree of internal coherence and also an enormous scope that ranged
from accounts of alleged crimes over socio-political analyses and overviews
of German national history to eschatological and cosmic visions (see Chap­
ter 3). Hitler used it as a conceptually closed^^niversallrame of reference
to perform his political speech acts of warning, threatening and promising/
prophesying. At the time of writing Mein Kampf, he could do no more than
perform these speech acts in theory, as he was imprisoned. But the “action
points” of his metaphorical scenario spelt out what would be carried out
if and when he acquired the political power to fulfil his “vision”, as was
demonstrated in all its.genocidal consequences during 1933-45.
With the hindsight knowledge about these consequences, some histori­
ans have treated the body-parasite scenario and its eliminatory outcome as
not being metaphoric at all, i.e. either as a “literal” blueprint or as camou­
flage phraseology that was meant to hide the intended target result of the
I

70 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Methodological Reflection 71

Holocaust. However, neither of these solutions is truly plausible. As we extermination against “the Jewish race in Europe” that was implied in the
saw from the history of the Nazis’ anti-Semitic discourse during the period promise of national/racial therapy and redemption was understood.
when they were in power, Hitler and Goebbels were clearly aware of dealing If we therefore reject “literalness”, “camouflage” or “misunderstanding”
with human victims who had to be deceived by way of sophisticated propa- as categories to characterise the cognitive import for Nsizi parasite imagery,
gandistic exercises before they could be murdered, even up to the point of we have to search for other explanations of its politico-discursive “suc­
“soliciting the co-operation of the victims” (Baumann 2000)—if they had cess”. Some researchers have pointed to the historical precursors of Nazi
“literally” mistaken them for “mere” animals they need not have bothered anti-Semitism, i.e. the development of “racially” motivated anti-Semitism
to attempt such a deceit. Furthermore, the notion of morally responsible siilce the second half of the nineteenth century, which is supposed to have
“parasite” organisms, which was the basis for the Nazis’ wish to kill them provided the precondition of Nazi success. Goldhagen (2003) suggested
all (see Section 3.3), is a contradiction in terms, and whilst it is clear that that it generated a predisposition for the acceptance of an “eliminationist”
the Nazis made use of such an implausible notion, its literal interpretation anti-Semitism in the general public, so that by the outbreak of World War
is simply impossible. I, “k stable framework with widely accepted reference points, images, and
The opposite evaluation of the metaphor scenario as a lie or camouflage, explicit elaborations—had for over thirty years been in place with regard to
on a par with terms such as final solution, special treatment^ etc., is not the Jews.”^ In the context of the post-World War I crisis of Germany, this
satisfactory either. At first, i.e. during the 1920s and even during the first radical anti-Semitic “framework” is assumed to have become mass consen­
years of the Nazi regime, many people, including even future victims, may sus.^ Goldhagen’s critics have pointed out that this hypothesis glosses over
have misunderstood and underestimated the body-illness-parasite imag­ crucial developments of anti-Semitism in Germany between the 1860s and
ery as “wild talk”. However, after the “Crystal Night” pogroms and at the 1930s in such a sweeping manner as to invalidate his generalizations.^
the latest after war had started. Hitler’s reiterated statements about the That a violent, racially motivated anti-Semitism was on the rise in Germany
fulfilment of his prophecy concerning the annihilation of European Jewry since the latter half of the nineteenth century is uncontroversial since Han­
left no doubt that the premise for the prophecy had come into effect and nah Arendt’s studies on the Origins of Totalitarianism from the 1950s, but
that its completion was therefore imminent. Whilst the precise scale of the it is also undisputed that this was not a special German phenomenon.'* The
genocide and the details of extermination camps were concealed by the question of whether the Germans at some point became “eliminationist”
regime, ordinary Germans became increasingly aware of mass killings of anti-Semitic racists revisits some of the controversies about the search for
Jews in Eastern Europe during the war; they also could not help but notice “the man” (or several men) “who gave Hitler his ideas” (Daim 1958), which
the “disappearance” of all Jews from the Reich, and they are on record for occupied early researchers of Nazi ideology. The answers provided then, i.e.
associating military setbacks as well as the allied bombing campaign with interpretations of Hitler’s references in Mein Kampf to nineteenth-century
national responsibility for what “happened to the Jews”. In the latter part anti-Semitism in Austria, to Richard Wagner, Dietrich Eckart and Houston
of the war, the genocidal outcome scenario of the body-parasite fight was Stewart Chamberlain, as well as to social Darwinist theories and apocalyp­
so emphatically highlighted by Hitler and Goebbels (speeches after Stalin­ tic religious traditions, are pertinent and backed up by evidence but still not
grad, complete extermination as the alternative to “stroking one’s bacte­ conclusive. They hardly explain the strength and ubiquity of the genocidal
ria”, etc.) that its “misunderstanding” as mere rhetoric is highly improbable impulse among the contemporary German public. Any attempt at an expla­
(even if it was claimed after 1945 by many Germans for obvious reasons). nation has to take into account the disturbing unresolved issue at the cen­
Even where such a misunderstanding occurred genuinely, its causes would tre of Holocaust ideology: how could a worldvrewijased^iTaiT Analogical
have to be sought in psychological and sociological conditions of non-belief mapping of bio-medical onto socio-politicarconcepts become so powerful
in a genocide being perpetrated by one’s own people rather than as a con­ and be taken so seriously that it actually turned into the reality of genocide
sequence of the metaphoricity of Nazi anti-Semitism. and world war? Clearly, historical “conditioning” of the German public has
This body-parasite scenario as sustained in Hitler’s speeches up to the to play a role in the explanation of the ideological-propagandistic success
end of the war did not hide or cover up the genocidal implications but of Nazi anti-Semitism; but to restrict the search for “precursor concepts”
instead highlighted and foregrounded them. If anyone was uncertain about to the pre-twentieth-century “race” theories or anti-Semitic tendencies in
the fate of the Jews in German-controlled Europe (on ac.count of only par­ German history amounts to an artificial exclusion of the main conceptual
tial experience of general disbelief), Hitler’s announcements and proud complex that the Nazis themselves used and that, as we have argued earlier,
assertions of the “annihilation” outcome right up to the end of the war was understood by the German populace, i.e. the complex of biologically
left no doubt as to what was happening to the Jews. The evidence from the and medically based metaphors referring.to political issues in general and
secret SD reports and Klemperer’s diary demonstrates that the threat of national identity in particular. We therefore have to consider the possibility
72 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Methodological Reflection 73
of explaining some of the cognitive import and forcefulness of Nazi imag­ if combined, they could underpin a perspective, in which the turn from
ery by reflecting on the history of this metaphor complex. the Renaissance to the early Enlightenment appears as a watershed that
separated the traditional focus of political body- and illness-based imagery
on maintaining or restoring a balance in society from “modern” uses that
5.1 POLITICAL BODY IMAGERY IN THE “HISTORY OF IDEAS” articulate radical, even “exterminatory” verdicts on whether a given socio­
political entity deserves to exist at all.
"The mapping between the source domain of the body and the target It might appear tempting to integrate the Nazi version of the body-na­
domain of politics and the nation-state was by no means an original idea tion metaphor in such a long-term perspective: either as a perverse twist
of Hitler’s. As mentioned earlier, it has a long history in Western politi­ at the end of the history of a once great idea, in the tradition of Lovejoy
cal thought that is closely connected to the Great Chain o f Being con­ and Tillyard, or, following Sontag, as the “totalitarian” version of “mas­
cept, whose origins have been traced back by Arthur O. Lovejoy (1936) ter illness” metaphors in modern political thought. However, an uncritical
and other historians of thought to Neoplatonist philosophy in antiquity application of early history-of-ideas models c i political theory develop­
and its reformulations and re-interpretations during the Middle Ages and ment would be methodologically highly problematic. In the first place,
the Renaissance, and reaching into the nineteenth and twentieth centu­ traditional history-of-ideas approaches concentrated on texts from the top
ries. Within the paradigm of the “History of Ideas”, Lovejoy retraced layer of philosophical, poetic and scientific formulations of a set canon of
step by step, as it were, the permutations of the Great Chain o f Being famous concepts. However, as Quentin Skinner (1978), followed by other
idea, whilst E. M. W. Tillyard (1982) proposed the .general hypothesis critics, has pointed out, it is hard to see how we can hope to reach an
that the system of correspondences between all levels of the Great Chain understanding of a historical period if we “focus our main attention on
o f Being, i.e. those of human, social, and heavenly bodies, was believed those who discussed the problems of political life at a level of abstraction
in in a quasi-literal sense as representing the God-given order of the and intelligence unmatched by any of their contemporaries”.^ In later stud­
world up to and during the Middle Ages. In the course of the Renais­ ies, this problem has been tackled by including further texts from popular
sance, however, it was transformed into an inventory of rhetorical/poetic political culture, such as pamphlets and other popular media genres and
metaphors: “the correspondence between macrocosm, body politic, and registers, but its application to long-term developments such as that of the
microcosm” still “served, as in medieval times, to express the idea of a body-nation metaphor complex in Western political thought has its own
cosmic order, but [Elizabethans] no longer allowed the details to take the practical problems connected with the sheer volume of the relevant text
form of minute mathematical equivalences . . . equivalences shaded off material, its heterogeneity in terms of registers, diversification through bor­
into resemblances”.^ Viewed from this perspective, modern versions of rowing across different languages, etc.
body-state metaphors, including their twentieth-century versions, have a Secondly, the relationship of Hitler and Goebbels’s political body-par­
conceptually different status from those of pre-modern times. asite scenario and the famous tradition of body-politic theories, as pro­
A further major hypothesis concerning a hiatus in long-term conceptual posed by John of Salisbury and Thomas Aquinas, Machiavelli and Hobbes,
history with special reference to body politic imagery was formulated by Rousseau, Kant, Herder and many others, is clearly not a straightforward
Susan Sontag, in her celebrated essay Illness as Metaphor, first published one. Even if we take into consideration the effects of “sedimentation” and
in 1978. Sontag claimed that there was a qualitative difference between “vulgarization” of political theory “down” to the level of folk theories and
“classical”, i.e. pre-Enlightenment, and “modern” uses of political health- popular pamphlet and brochure culture, the notion of Na^ijr^gigery as a
illness imagery: “classical formulations which analogize a political disorder direct “descendant” of the body-politic traditjon'Ts absurd, for it would beg
to an illness—from Plato to, say, Hobbes—presuppose the classical medical the crucial question of its reception (and “implementation”) by the Ger­
(and political) idea of balance. . . . The prognosis is always, in principle, man public of the first half of the twentieth century. If the implications
optimistic. Society, by definition, never catches a fatal disease.”^ From the of the body-parasite scenario had been always available, why were they
Enlightenment onward, however, “the use of disease imagery in political so singularly “successful” then and not before.’ As we shall consider later
rhetoric [implied] other, less lenient assumptions”, and the modern idea of on (Chapter 9), even the most ambitious attempt to match Hitler’s view of
revolution “shattered the old, optimistic use of disease metaphors”.^ During the nation’s body defending itself against the Jewish poison to the history
the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, “master illnesses” such as tubercu­ of political theories based on body imagery, undertaken in 1938 by the
losis and cancer, which required matching radical cures, became the sta­ Nazi jurist Carl Schmitt, had to short-circuit three centuries in order to
ple of revolutionary, authoritarian and ultimately totalitarian discourse.® “reclaim” a heavily biased version of Hobbes’s Leviathan concept for the
Sontag’s account can be read as a specification of Tillyard’s hypothesis: Nazis, only to end in failure.
74 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Methodological Reflection 75
To draw any direct link between the historical metaphor tradition and Over the past decade or so, however, a renewed interest in the dia­
its use by the Nazis would amount to attempting to convey an aura of chronic dimension of cognitive phenomena has emerged. On the one hand,
respectability to the latter, which might seem desirable from a neo-Nazi the early focus on universal conceptual structures has led to investigations
propagandistic viewpoint but evidently has got nothing to do with any seri­ into cross-cultural distribution—and variation—of metaphor systems. The
ous endeavour to reconstruct and understand the conceptual and discursive conceptual metaphor Emotions Are Fluids in a Container, which has been
history of this metaphor complex. On the other hand, to deny any link found in many European languages, for instance, appears to be linked to
'between the tradition and its manifestations in Nazi ideology is akin to the concept of four bodily “humors” that dominated Western culture for
cherry-picking supposedly “respectable” parts of the body-illness metaphor more than a millennium and whose terminological traces can still be found
complex and excluding its unsavoury aspects, thus truncating the analysis in the vocabulary of the “temperaments”.^^ By contrast, Chinese idioms
of its semantic and political range of implications. Acknowledging that the seem to rely on the metaphor Anger Is Gas in a Heated Container, which
Nazis and their audiences are not likely to have consciously followed in the is related to traditional Chinese philosophy and medicine.*'* Other meta­
footsteps of philosophical discussions does not preclude the investigation phors, e.g. Quality Is Wealth, or Politics Is War, have also been linked to
of their dependence on aspects of these conceptual and cultural traditions. specific theories or ideologies that were developed in the West-.*^ Further­
Our guiding principle for the following chapters is therefore to look for more, even in a predominantly synchronic analysis, conceptual metaphors,
conceptual and discursive traditions in the use of the metaphor to which especially body-based ones, are not “determined” by a fixed, universal
the Nazis could attach their notions of a racial therapy for the German “primary” experience but vary across cultures, national languages and
nation’s body. discourse formations and registers.*^ Kovecses (2009) aptly concludes that
“cultural models can be both created by metaphors and at the same time
can determine (or select) the metaphors we use in discourse”.*^ It follows
5:2 AN EVOLUTIONARY ACCOUNT OF that the cognitive analysis cannot dismiss the culture-specific implications
POLITICAL BODY METAPHORS df metaphors as extras that can be separated from their “core meaning”.
Instead, these implications, together with their socio-historical indexical-
One central challenge for providing a cognitive account of the histori­ ity, have to be treated as integral aspects of the semantics of the metaphor
cal development of the conceptual metaphor complex surrounding the in question.
notion of the state or nation as a body lies in the problem of formulating If even general conceptual metaphors can only be understood as embed­
a perspective for the conceptualization of long-term semantic change. ded in culture-specific historical traditions, such specificity can be assumed
Cognitive metaphor analysis in its early phase did not make historical a fortiori for a more concrete metaphor scenario such as Hitler’s genocidal
investigations its foremost concern. Even if the historicity of conceptual concept of a therapy o f the body politic through annihilation o f a supposed
metaphor systems such as the Great Chain o f Being was acknowledged, parasite race. As we have seen (Chapters 2, 3), this scenario was in fact a
as in Lakoff and Turner (1989),’*’ the main emphasis was on the syn­ complex and quite elaborate combination of folk-theoretical, historical and
chronic investigation of the metaphor’s “basic version” that is “largely ideological propositions that were built on various, partially contradictory
unconscious and so fundamental to our thinking that we barely notice traditions of religious, scientific and neo-mythical thought. Hitler did not
it” and that “occurs throughout a wide range of the world’s cultures”. claim to have “researched” these “insights” all alone by himself, but he cer­
In the context of cognitive “embodiment” theory, the role of the body as tainly claimed possessing the genius to fit them into a convincing, system­
the experiential and physiological basis of perception and conceptualiza­ atic framework (whidi we reconstructed in the-^t^de'd's^nario structure
tion has been explored further, with special regard to neurophysiological in Table 3.4), which formed the “granite foundation” of his political vision
structures and to primary experiential scenes in ontogenesis.^^ On this and which would motivate the German people to act accordingly. But if the
basis, we can,de-construct the body-nation metaphor as the complexion implications of political body-parasite metaph6rs had always been “auto­
of the general concept of complex (social) systems as bodies and the matically” present to everyone, there would have been no need for Hitler
metonymy of bodies-persons. In an ahistorical approach, it might then (or any other political propagandist) to explicate them, and they would
be argued that all uses of a metaphor mapping, such as that between be fundamentally identical across all ages. There is, however, no histori­
nation and body, are mere re-occurrences of a universal conceptual unit cal evidence to support the contention that each and every use of political
that as such has no history other than a chronological series of mani­ body-parasite imagery is automatically genocidal; it is therefore incumbent
festations, which would be produced automatically, unconsciously and on an analysis intent on explaining the cognitive import of Nazi imagery to
spontaneously. identify and analyse those cultural traditions that specifically informed it.
76 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Methodological Reflection 77
In order to combine cultural-historical and cognitive perspectives in historical data bear out the neat distinction of innovation and propagation
our analysis, we can make use of a modified version of the “naturalist” in metaphor evolution.
approach to conceptual history that builds on analyses of cultural develop­ Together with this distinction, Croft and Cruse’s approach has inher­
ment as an evolutionary phenomenon, some of which we briefly reviewed in ited from the “memetic” approach a degree of reification of linguemes as
Chapter 2. We have already noticed that the gene- or virus-based analogies entities that remain somehow “the same” whilst occasionally undergo­
-for cultural phenomena that underpin such approaches may iji fact beg cru­ ing mutations and being subjected to the selection pressures of different
cial questions about differences between conceptual and biological forms socio-discursive environments. They thus speak of the “life history of a
of “reproduction” and about the relationship between the experiential basis metaphor”, a s if they were dealing with a living organism: “at the begin­
of a metaphor and its historically situated application. Croft (2000) takes ning of its life, even if it is being laid down as an item in the mental lexi­
some of these concerns into consideration and proposes a refinement of the con, speakers are very conscious of its status as a metaphor. . . . As time
naturalist approach for the purpose of a cognitive explanation of language passes, however, the sense of the expression’s metaphorical nature fades
change. Building on Hull’s (1988) application of the “memetic” approach and eventually disappears. . .. Once that happens, the expression is no
to the history of science, Croft develops a “two-step” model of innova­ different from a literal expression, and only etymologists and historians of
tion (“altered replication”) and selection (“differential replication”).'® In language can recreate the path of derivation. At some point along this path
this perspective, the smallest meaningful elements of utterances, dubbed of change, the expression acquires a capability to act as a literal basis for
linguemeSy are the cognitive replicators whose “reproduction”, instead of further metaphorical extensions
being the equivalent of a simple replication, has to be modelled in every This account of a long-term semantic development of metaphors as
case as a function of both innovation and “entrenchment” in the socio- a “life story” from “cradle to grave” covers only the “genetic” side, as
communicative context.’^ it were, and has to be complemented by the socio-historical selection/
The methodological consequence of this distinction, i.e. the differentiation dissemination account, lest we run the risk of falling back into a linear
between the investigation of the emergence of new linguemes and their vari­ narrative that would repeat in naturalist terminology the reifications of
ants, on the one hand, and the investigation of their entrenchment in discourse early history-of-ideas accounts. As it is only in socio-culturally embed­
and social dissemination, on the other, is applied to metaphor in Croft and ded utterances that new lingueme variants are coined and that they are
Cruse’s (2004) overview of Cognitive Linguistics. When a metaphor “is first accepted or rejected, almost every replication of an utterance is in itself
coined . . . the only way to interpret it is to employ one’s innate metaphorical a re-creation, and thus a subtle innovation, of concepts. The discursive
strategy, which is subject to a wide range of contextual and communicative history of political body imagery is therefore unlikely to follow a con­
constraints”.^*^But once it “takes hold in a speech community. . . its meaning tinuous path of change; rather, it constitutes a collage of re-interpreted
becomes circumscribed relative to the freshly coined metaphor,. . . it begins facets of diverse strands in the conceptual and discursive traditions of this
. . . a process of semantic drift, which can weaken or obscure its metaphori­ metaphor complex. Older traditions of the body-state metaphor did not
cal origins”.^' In contrast to a simple “linear” model, this two-step model of suddenly disappear but only gradually gave way to newer versions, so that
innovation and selection-propagation can help to differentiate between the various versions co-existed for ce n tu rie s.T h e resultant historical narra­
investigation of the creation and change of the metaphor and its scenario ver­ tive is not one of cumulative conceptual growth or steady decline, nor a
sions, and the study of the socio-historical conditions of its diffusion in spe­ Hegeliah dialectic from “thesis” to “antithesis” to “s y n ^ s i i ^ rather
cific discourse communities, such as those in German political public under the sketch of a “complex adaptive system”, “ where meaning changes are
Nazi rule.Tt is one thing to motivate the anti-Semitic body-parasite imagery neither completely random nor teleological but express shifts in dominant
by recourse to general cognitive strategies such as the mapping or blending of distribution patterns.
certain conceptual inputs to achieve a semantic innovation in the form of key In the following second part of our study we shall focus on several
scenarios. It is a different rnethodical approach to study these metaphors as important stages in the discourse tradition of political body metaphors
“discourse metaphors”-(Zinken 2007; Zinken et al. 2008) to explicate the pat­ in European political thought since the Middle Ages. The aim is not to
terns of their propagation in specific situational and socio-cultural contexts. give a comprehensive overview of the metaphor’s conceptual “career”, but
The preceding chapters have included our proposals for such a “two-step” rather to provide case studies of primary texts and their interpretation,
account of a) Hitler’s body-parasite scenario as political-semantic innovation in order to sketch the contours of the conceptual background on which
and b) its micro-development during the Third Reich. The following chapters National Socialist anti-Semitism could build its genocidal body-parasite
aim to retrace European and, specifically, German traditions of the body- scenario. Of course, the ancient, medieval, Renaissance or Enlightenment
state metaphor that the Nazis built on. It remains to be seen whether these authors who-employed political body metaphors could not foresee later
78 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
(ab-)uses of that metaphor, and there are significant contrasts that allow
us to highlight the characteristics of Nazi use. It is in order to be able
to identify such contrasts, as well as some significant parallels, that we
engage in the diachronic analysis.
6 Solidarity and Hierarchy
The Body-State Metaphor in the
Middle Ages

When Arthur O. Lovejoy set out to describe the “life history” of the Great
Chain o f Being concept, he saw it as a complexion of “ideas which have,
throughout the greater part of the history of the West, been so closely and
constantly associated that they have often operated as a unit”,' and he
located the origins of that combination in Neoplatonic thought.^ For the
reasons mentioned in the last chapter, retelling conceptual history as the
“life and adventures” of ideas is no longer feasible, and irrelevant for the
metaphor of the state as a body. Even the assumption of a distinct starting •
point in the work of one author (or group of authors) would be fallacious.
The beginnings of the body-state metaphor in Western culture have been
traced back to early ancient Greek political philosophy, but even earlier
sources can be identified in the Indo-European foundation myths of tribes
and nations (as well as of royal and caste lineages as descendants of the
body parts of mythical founder figures)^^owever, as our concern is spe­
cifically with the metaphor versions that may have been relevant for Nazi
ideology, we shall confine our study to Western traditions that are most
likely to have served as inputs to political theory and discourse in Germany
in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries.
Among Platonic texts, it is the Republic, Crito, Timaios and The Laws
that articulated a concern for the state’s health and showed a critical focus
on the rulership systems of specific Greek city-states as types of political dis­
eases.^ Aristotle explained the polis as a “thing that exists by nature”, which
motivated his definition of man as a political animaP and the proposition
that the origins of political rule can be found irfnatufe,"nScSar as the soul
governs the movements of animal bodies (including those of the “political
animals”}.^ It follows that every polis can be compared to a body and its
growth, which determines its state of health: “A'body is composed of parts,
and must grow proportionately if symmetry is to be maintained. . . . The
same is true of a city. It, too, is composed of parts; and one of the parts may
often grow imperceptibly out of proportion.”^ Through the continuation of
these analogies in the works of the Stoics, Neoplatonism, and boosted by the
rediscovery of Platonic and Aristotelian texts, the conceptualisation of poli­
tics in terms of anatomy and medicine became an integral part of political
thought in medieval and early modern Europe.®
82 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Solidarity and Hierarchy 83
A second major strand of the body-nationistate metaphor tradition was It would, however, be misleading to posit a fusion of these three con­
— formed by the narrative of the “fable of the belly”, which first appeared in ceptual traditions—that of a state or society.’s health and illness, the fable
texts attributed to Aesop and was retold in varying forms by Livy, Dio­ of the belly, and the concept of Christendom as a body—in a similar
nysius of Halicarnassus, Plutarch and o th e rs ^ ts vindication of the only way as Lovejoy sees a merger of the principles of gradation, continuity
seemingly idle belly’s right to receive all food first because it is the organ and plenitude merging in the Great Chain o f Being concept in Neopla­
that makes the food available to all the other part's of the body seems to tonism.^® The various strands of mappings between corporeal-medical
“ have an inherently conservative bias. It denounces any.rebellion against the source and socio-political target domains did influence each other but
central organ’s authority in order to maintain balance and harmony. This had different textual and ideological functions. Apart from its Christo­
conservative sense is certainly conveyed in Shakespeare’s Coriolanus by logical complications, the source concept of th^ body could apply to the
the representative of the senate, Menenius (see Chapter 1). However, as we church (in which case Christ was the head, represented by the pope), the
shall see later on, even the Middle Ages knew other, less one-sidedly argu­ worldly empire or state (with the emperor or king as the head), or other
ing versions of the fable. public “corporations”^such as universities.^^ Some authors even operated t
The third major strand that fed into the conceptual complex of political different aspects of these traditions in one. and the same text and used the
body concepts originated in patristic interpretations of biblical texts, in par­ different traditions for varying, sometimes contradictory, purposes. In
ticular, Paul’s Epistles to the Romans and Corinthians, which defined the view of this wealth of conceptual variation, any streamlined account of
Church as Christ’s Body as a binding reason for demanding unity,'mutual the metaphor’s “life history” would clearly be inappropriate; any remain­
care and discipline among church members of all ranks.^° This image had to ing “biographical” Conceit in the historical narrative can therefore only
be reconciled with other corporeal concepts in the Bible, e.g. that of Adam be that of the “picaresque” progress. ' ^
having been made in God’s “image” and after his “likeness” (in Genesis
1:26-27), and that of Christ as the head (therefore, strictly speaking, just
one, albeit the most important, body part) of the church (1 Corinthians 6.1 POLITICAL p h y s io l o g y IN THE TWELFTH CENTURY:
11:3, 23-29 and,15:44; Ephesians 4:15-16; Colossians 2:19) and the dis­ JOHN OF SALISBURY’S POUCRATICUS
tinction between Christ’s human, i.e. natural body, which was sacrificed at
crucifixion (and, symbolically, at the Last Supper and the church’s Eucha­ In medieval European political thought, the conceptualisation of state and
rist in the form of bread and wine) on the one hand, and Christ’s separate society in terms of the human anatomy appears to have found its first elab­
spiritual body on the other.^^ orated version in the Latin treatise Policraticus sive De nugis Curialium et
Besides the theological and Christological implications, the image also pro­ vestigiis philosophorum {Policraticus. O f the Frivolities o f Courtiers and
vided the basis of a re-conceptualisation of the political sphere as part of the the Footprints ofPhilosophers)^^niten at around 1159-1160 by the Ang­
Christian universe. In the fifth century, St. Augustine of Hippo, in The City of lo-Norman cleric, diplomat and philosopher John of Salisbury (c. 1115-
God {De Civitate Dei), presented a system of rational order that encompassed 1180). As secretary to the successive archbishops of Canterbury, Theobald
body, soul, the human and the heavenly polis in one cosmic hierarchy, created and Thomas Becket, John was involved in the conflict between the English
arid overseen by God. Within that system, the human body and the human king and the church, which led to him being exiled in France (and which
cit^ were defined as corresponding systems of order: “the peace of the body is later would lead to the assassination of Becket).*^ During his exile he wrote,
the'balanced ordering of its parts . . . the peace of the city is an ordered con- and dedicated to Becket, the Policraticus, conttastingy^s-the-subtitle states,
I cord, with' respect to command and obedience, of the citizens’XlD
This concept of the Christian state as a body comprising members of
the “frivolities of courtiers” (to be avoided)-with the “footprints of phi­
losophers” (to be follow ed).In Books V and VI of<the Policraticus, John
develops the notion of the state {res publica) in its medieval feudal form in
different status and function and striving to emulate the “perfectly ordered
and perfectly harmonious fellowship in the enjoyment of God and one terms of the analogy with the human body, on the supposed authority of an
another in God” in the Heavenly City^^ provided the frame of reference for “instruction” to the Roman emperor Trajan by Plutarch.^’
medieval political philosophers who attempted to accommodate in it the We can analyse this use of the analogy from around the middle of the
new social and political entities that had arisen in Europe since the fall of twelfth century as a kind of “test case” for the degree of its integration into
the ancient Roman- Empire.^*’ The debates and conflicts over spiritual and a supposedly stable, literal worldview, as claimed by Tillyard (1982), and
worldly headship of that “mystical body” {corpus mysticum) of Christen­ also for the optimistic bias in favour of restoring balance in a state, which
dom shaped the course of history for centuries and prepared the ground for has been deemed to be typical of “pre-modern” thought by Sontag (1978).
the emergence of the modern understanding of politics.*^ After introducing the pseudo-Plutarchian letter in a quasi-philological
84 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Solidarity and Hierarchy 85
manner by citing its supposed address to Trajan, John incorporates its con­ can be said that the Policraticus explicitly and repeatedly emphasises one
tent into his treatise in Chapter 2 of Book V; “lesson” to be drawn from the body-state analogy, i.e. that notwithstand­
ing their hierarchical relationships, all members depend on each other and
For a republic is, as Plutarch declares, a sort of body which is animated must “work” together in order to enable the whole body of the res publica
by the grant of divine reward . .. The position of the head of the repub- to stay healthy and function properly:
" lie is occupied . . . by a prince subject only to God and to those who
act in His place on earth, inasmuch as in the human body the head is The health of the whole republic will only be secure and splendid if the
stimulated and ruled by the soul. The place of the heart is occupied by superior members devote themselves to the inferiors and the inferiors
the senate, from which proceeds the beginning of good and bad works. respond likewise to the legal rights of their superiors, so that each in­
The duties of the ears, eyes and mouth are claimed by the judges and dividual may be likened to a part of the others reciprocally and each
governors of the provinces. The hands coincide with officials and sol­ believes what is to his own advantage to be determined by that which
diers. Those who always assist the prince are comparable to the flanks. he recognises to be most useful to others.
Treasurers and record keepers . .. resemble the shape of the stomach
and intestines; these, if they accumulate with great avidity and tena­ Thus far, the body-state metaphor in Policraticus seems to fit well into
ciously preserve their accumulation, engender innumerable and incur­ the schema of a “medieval-as-pre-modern” view of socio-political entities
able diseases so that their infection threatens to ruin the whole body. as integral parts of the Great Chain o f Being. For this reason, Tillyard
Furthermore, the feet coincide with peasants perpetually bound to the regarded John’s treatise as “one of the most elaborate medieval statements”
soil, for whom it is all the more necessary that the head take precau­ of the body-state analogy within the context of microcosm-macrocosm
tions, in that they more often meet with accidents while they walk correspondences.” However, there are some ways in which the analogy is
on the earth in bodily subservience; and those who erect, sustain and elaborated in Policraticus that are not consistent with such an harmony-
move forward the mass of the whole body are justly owed shelter and oriented interpretation. One first complication is caused by an apparently
support. Remove from the fittest body the aid of the feet; it does not competing version of the analogy to the head-to-feet model in the form
proceed under its own power, but either crawls shamefully, uselessly of the “fable of the belly”, which appears in the Policraticus as a “les­
and offensively on its hands or else is moved with the assistance of son” taught to the author by none less than the then reigning pope, Adrian
brute animals. IV, in a purported conversation with John. At the pope’s bidding, John
reports complaints against the church concerning corruption and simony
In this presentation of the body-state analogy, we find a succinct and well- and goes on to challenge the (deputy) head and father of the mystical body
explained hierarchical perspective from the lyead “down” to the feet, com­ of the church: " . . . why do you accept presents and payments from your
bined with commonsense advice to the prince to avoid a malfunctioning of children?”” The pope responds by telling the fable in'its traditional ver­
the sromflcWtreasurers and to look after the /cef/peasants. The specifica­ sion, in which the organs rebel against the stomach and end up enduring
tions that the headlpnxict is ruled by the so«//church and is assisted by the a severe health crisis: “This was suffered on the first day; on the following
heartlstnaxt show that his position is not that of an “absolute” monarch day it was more annoying. On the third day it was so pernicious that nearly
in a modern sense but is instead viewed, unsurprisingly for the historical all showed signs of faintness.” After drawing out the analogy in graphic
context, in a church-oriented perspective. This latter point has drawn the detail and also invoking the classical authority of Quintus Serenus Sam-
attention of historians interested in the conflicts between monarchical and monicus, the pope deduces the “obvious” conclusronr^^MeasurTfieither our
church power, especially in connection with John’s condemnation of tyr­ harshness nor that of secular princes, but atfend to the utility of all.””
anny” as opposed to lawful kingship and his involvement in the conflict The fact that the most important organ in the fable, as retold by John, is
between Kings Stephen and Henry II and the church as represented by the the belly or stomach, instead of the head, has been noted as a discrepancy
archbishops of Canterbury.” A further focus of historical interest has been by some researchers.Viewed from a discourse-oriented perspective, how­
John’s attention to the problems caused by the stomach and the concern for ever, this variation hardly causes a conflict of meaning. In the first place,
the feet. In this respect, the influence of John’s teachers in Paris and at the the purported contexts for the two metaphor versions are different: one is
School of Chartres, notably Robertus Pullus (1080-1154) and Guillaume a quotation from (pseudo)-Plutarch, the other a report of an alleged con­
de Conches (c. 1080-1154), has been cited; some historians see John even versation with the pope. John uses the fable as a separate “example”, which
as part of the reformist movement of “medieval humanism” that challenged he could assume to be known to his learned readers:^^ it thus “amplifies”
the established feudal concepts of state and society.” At the very least it rather than contradicts the head-to-feet analogy. Secondly, the respective
86 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Solidarity and Hierarchy 87
target referents are not the same: one is the (secular) prince; the other is the out, broken off and thrown far away, if they give offence to the faith or
pope, who as we have seen in the first quotation from Policraticus is viewed public security, but they are to be destroyed utterly so that the security
as deputising for the soul (God) that “rules” the head/prince. John is thus of the corporate community may be procured by the extermination of
talking about two distinct, though related, institutions. the one member. Who will be spared, I say, by him who is commanded
There is, however, a more fundamental tension between the two meta­ to do violence against even his own eyes? Indeed, neither the ears nor
phor versions of head-to-feet and belly-v.-organs. The presentation of the the tongue nor whatever else subsists within the body of the republic
body anatomy in the pseudo-Plutarch stresses the ideal of co-operation and is safe if it revolts against the soul for whose sake the eyes themselves
interdependence among all members, whereas the fable of the belly thema- are gouged out.^^
tises a near-fatal crisis, which only the pope can cure (and by somewhat
dubious means!). At the source domain level, the difference seems not to The reason that John provides for his zealous plea in favour of amputation
be dramatic, because even the main head-to-feet analogy quoted earlier is the fact that the injury of rebellion directly concerns the soul, as a case
includes a hint of an illness scenario with reference to the stomach and “when God is offended . . . or the Church is spurned”.^^ An attack on the
intestines, i.e. roughly the same source concept as in the f a b l e . I n both church is not merely a danger for a particular organ of the state. The enor­
cases— stomachHntestines keeping all food for themselves (in the head-to- mity of the therapy can hardly be surpassed and its description certainly
foot analogy) or starving (in the fable)—the malfunctioning of digestive shows little sign of optimism or concern for balanced disease management.
organs “engender[s] innumerable and incurable diseases so that their infec­ The epitome of this darker, more pessimistic vision can be found in Book
tion threatens to ruin the whole body”.^^ The need for a properly func­ 8, Chapter 17, of the Policraticus, where John depicts the counter-image of
tioning stomach is therefore a special case of the general principle that a proper political body, namely the “republic of the impious”:
cooperation among all memberslorgans is essential for the whole body’s
survival. Its tyrannical head, therefore, is the image of the devil; its soul is formed
In terms of narrative and argumentative emphasis, however, the discrep­ of heretical, schismatic and sacrilegious priests and, to use the words of
ancy between the anatomical analogy and the illness-cure scenario of the Plutarch, prefects of religion, ^ssailing the laws of the Lord; the heart
fable is more significant. The former highlights the well-functioning, harmo­ of impious counsellors is like a senate of iniquity; its eyes, ears, tongue
nious state of a stable political body, thus confirming an optimistic viewpoint and unarmed hand are unjust officials, judges and laws; its armed hand
that includes the notion of malfunction only as a possibility that should be is violent soldiers, whom Cicero labels mercenaries; its feet are those
avoided. The latter, however, sees that body as a fundamentally instable, among the more humble occupations who oppose the precepts of the
insecure entity. The fable in Policraticus, focusing as it does on the Pope’s Lord and legitimate institutions.^*
remedy for Christendom, still envisages an almost automatic cure, but the
text also contains quite drastic illness-cure scenarios for the worldly state. In this quotation, the body-state analogy is as complete as the “proper”
John gives the example of an oppressive magistrate being equal to a “swollen body model in the “pseudo-Plutarch” version, but it conveys the opposite of
head” that makes it "impossible for the members of the body to endure it” any optimistic evaluation. From the head down to the feet, the devil’s anti-
and even leads them to suicide, for “if the affliction would be incurable, it state forms a body mirroring that of the proper state but now the function
is more miserable to live than to die”.^'’ Later on in the text of Policraticus, of every body part is unhealthy and destructive. Thus, the same source sce­
^ he asserts the dangers of injury to the whole body if the supreme head is nario as that of the healthy res publica is employed by John a l ^ to depict
NtDOH? wounded: “a blow to the head, as we have already said, is carried back to all the opposite target notion of a tyrannical staterTabte'6Tl'’summarizes the
the members and a wound unjustly afflicted upon any member whomsoever conceptual elements of the analogy. Table 6.^ its scenario implications.
tends to the injury of the head”jS iu t if the life o f the organism as d whole is Tables 6.1 and 6.2 show the immense differences of John of Salisbury’s
at stake due to a rebellion, all members are dispensable, and it is the prince’s conception from the therapy/redemption scenario that we derived from
duty to amputate and eliminate them. Invoking biblical authority (Matthew Mein Kampf (see Chapter 3). This finding is, of course, to be expected
18:9), John insists on the most radical form of therapy: but by no means trivial, for in terms of the basic mappings, there is not
that much of a difference: in both cases concepts of the body, its health
That the members are likewise to be removed is clear from that which and therapy are applied to a worldly state and the universal, even mystical
is written: ‘If your eye or your foot offend you, root it out and cast it whole of creation under God’s rule. Even the role-slot for a “devil” figure
away from you.’ I think this is fo be observed by the prince in regard (and the implication that he must be combated at all cost) is present in both
to all of the members to the extent that not only are they to be rooted scenarios.
eta o ation and oloca st Solidarity and Hierarchy 89
Table od fate Correspondences in olic atic s instead, he assumes their existence as a matter of course {within his reli­
gious worldview) and concentrates on showing what must be done to check
Source Target Counter-Target them in principle. Within this rather rigid overall scenario, however, he is
Soul (holding supreme G od/C hurch (Principle of Devil/Heretics/Rebels ready to consider the possibility of every part of the body being liable to
responsibility for body) Universal Order) (causing Universal Dis­ fall ill and deserve amputation, even the head (i.e. a tyrannical ruler). The
order) devil is not identifiable as a particular group of people, a race, or a nation;
he can be represented by any member of society, even clerics.T he supreme
— Head/Belly (Command Prince/Pope (Political and Tyranny
spiritual authority on
authority of the soul lies ultimately with God, represented by the pope
over other body mem­
bers) earth (who is, however, not beyond suspicion, even for John); any assumption
of this role by the worldly head or ruler, comparable to Hitler’s assump­
H eart Senate Senate of iniquity tion to do “the work of the Lord”, would have been a blasphemy for the
Judges, governors U njust officials, judges
medieval cleric. Thus, quite apart from the lack of an explicit anti-Semitic
Eyes, ears, tongue
and laws bias, the whole “ontology” and value system attached to John of Salisbury’s
body-state analogy is fundamentally different in terms of its argumentation
H ands Soldiers M ercenaries structure from Hitler’s. This discrepancy underlines the necessity for the
State officials C orrupt State officials
cognitive analysis of metaphor to go beyond a mere comparison of source-
Sides
target mappings and relate their implications by way of scenario analysis to
Stomach/intestines Financial officers C orrupt Financial officers the historically and socially situated presuppositions.
With regard to Tillyard’s (1982) characterisation of medieval and Renais­
Feet Farmers Rebellious people
sance thought as a system of micro- and macrocosrnic correspondences, the
Folicraticus proves to be “a case in point” only to a certain degree. John’s
Table od tate Scenarios in olic atic $ pseudo-Plutarchian vision of the head-to-feet hierarchy indeed confirms
Tillyard’s description, but the existence of a parallel devil’s counter-uni-
• Source Target Counter-Target verse, with its diseased bodies, tyrannical or rebellious societies and gen­
Bodily H ealth based on Peaceful es blica, ' Tyrannical state o r civil eral chaos, puts the vision of human society matching the harmony of God’s
co-ordination of all based on m utual help w ar rule into question. Obviously, there is not the slightest hint of its endorse­
body members by head/ of all p arts of society ment by John, but still, to admit and describe in detail its existence, must
soul under just ruler: duty of have been deeply disturbing to him and his contemporaries. The devil’s
obedience on the p art of
counter-world is only there, of course, as a “worst-case scenario”, depicted
all subjects
in all its horror to warn against rebellion or lax government that plight fail
Medical care to avoid or D uty of care on the p art Neglect of society and to fqlfil its duty of care and therapy of the body politic.
combat diseases (swollen of ruler to prevent/cor- state; corruption Such a warning partly fits Sontag’s hypothesis that “classical” formula­
head, infection, injury, rect any dysfunctional tions aim to “encourage rulers to pursue a more rational policy”,'*®as the
affliction) social o r political devel­
opments
analogy in Folicraticus clearly serves to advise the leadership of state and
Church on how to avoid and manage political d i^A ^s. Npnetheless, John’s
Amputation of any body Removal of tyrant Tyrannical rule Vr emphasis on the ruler’s duty to amputate rebellious members and the sub­
part, even of parts of the ject’s duty to remove a swollen head and even destroy a tyrant*^ are remind­
head, if offensive to soul ers that for John the devil’s tyranny was not a just a theoretical possibility
but aj:eal danger.
However, these similarities are undermined by wholly different sets of In terms of its discursive presentation, John’s vivid, occasionally crass,
underlying presuppositions. In the first place, the target levels that Hitler depiction of political illnesses, injuries and therapies in Folicraticus shows
construed as mutually confirming sets of data are conflated in the olic ati that he was keen to use every rhetorical trick to twist and turn the core con­
c s into one rigid category, which makes no distinction between empirical- cept of this metaphor to drive home his message. Nor did he shy away from
factual and mystical-metaphysical arguments. John of Salisbury makes no employing different source aspects (e.g. head v. belly) for similar argumen­
pretence of “proving” empirically (i.e. by reference to supposed social facts) tative purposes or from mixing his body-state analogy with other meta­
that devilish forces are at work and must be destroyed at a given moment; phors, such as those of rulers as fathers,'*^ of the king as an image o f equity
90 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Solidarity and Hierarchy 91
or justice*^ or of the state as a beehive^* He even acknowledged the limits these texts had been translated, partly from Arabic sources, into Latin from
of some analogies: in order to capture all of the “lower” ranks of society the 1240s onwards.”*®Leading theologians at the University of Paris, such
he extended the concept of the feet beyond farmers (who had a transparent as Albert the Great (c. 1200-1280) and his disciple Thomas Aquinas (c.
tertium comparationis with the feet, i.e. walking the soil) and applied it 1225-1274), made the integration of Aristotle’s thought into the existing
to all “who exercise the humbler duties”, including, for instance, weavers, Christian philosophical traditions the centre of what was to become the
artisans, servants, procurers of food and managers of private households “scholastic” synthesis of theological and secular thought.”*^Aristotle’s com­
-As a result, the source concept becomes grotesquely distorted, which gives parison of the polis with a body that comprises different parts which form
John a chance to poke fun at his own metaphor: “there are so many of these a self-contained whole inspired the scholastics to redefine the state as
occupations that the number of feet in the republic surpasses not only the a “corporation” alongside the church, whose own “mystical” body-status
eight-footed crab, but even the centipede.”'*^ was well established on the authority of Paul’s epistles and Augustine’s De
John’s own thematisation of the absurdity of counting all the feet of the Civitate Dei.^^ Aristotle’s body-state analogy was thus integrated with the
republic can be seen as evidence, that even for him the body-state analogy Pauline-Augustinian-patristic tradition: its emphasis now lay on the obliga­
was not at all a matter of minute “equivalences” that had to be believed tion of all members of the state body to help each other so as to achieve
literally, but a rhetorical figure that served its purpose up to a certain point the common good [bonum commune).^^ In the treatise “On Kingship” [De
and could be turned into a joke. John was also clearly aware of the con­ Regno ad Regem Cyprii), which was posthumously ascribed to Thomas
ceptual and literary traditions, as illustrated by the use of the fable of the Aquinas and integrated into Ptolemy of Lucca’s De Regimine Principium,^^
belly and a host of further biblical and classical references. He probably the king’s command over the political body neatly fitted into a system
even invented a classical authority for his main analogy, i.e. the pseudo- of corresponding layers of a rational world order that did indeed match
Plutarchian “Instruction to Trajan”, to create a tradition where there had Tillyard’s schema of a universe in harmony under God:,
been none. John never uses the body-state analogy as a rigid classificatory
schema but as an argumentative warrant for socio-political conditions for But the particular rulership, which is found in humans, is in fact most
the well-being of the commonweal. It thus seems difficult to subsume his like the divine rulership; on account of this, the human being is called
use of the body-state analogy under the stereotyping notion of a medi­ a smaller w orld... . For just as the universe of corporeal creatures and
eval belief system, which, as Tillyard claimed, continued to be “taken for all spiritual powers are contained under the divine government, so in
j granted” even by the Elizabethans.'*^Instead, John’s flexible, inventive, and this way are the members of the body and other powers of the soul
I in places playful, variations on the traditional metaphor topos of the state ruled by reason; . .. But because human beings are by nature social
I as a body in Policraticus are testimony to the medieval humanism that pre- animals living in a multitude, . . . a likeness to the divine rulership is
. ceded the rigid systems of scholastic philosophy in the following centuries. found among human beings not only insofar as one person is ruled
John of Salisbury was neither a heretic nor a revolutionary (even though by reason, but also inasmuch as a multitude is governed through the
he was forced into exile), and he probably shared many Neoplatonic pre­ reason of a single person . . . the king ought to recognize that . . . he
suppositions of the Great Chain o f Being and of Pauline Christology as exists in his kingdom just the same way as the soul exists in his body
passed on by the church fathers, i.e. the concept of .Christ as the head of and God exists in the world. If he carefully reflects upon this, from one
the mystical body of the church and its manifestation in medieval empires. side, a zeal for justice will be kindled in him .. . and from another, he
But these presuppositions, and the metaphorical arguments based on them, will acquire the gentleness of mildness and clemency, when he consid­
were not static or uncontested and could hardly be taken for granted, for ers those individuals who are subject to his'governme^nf'Eo"be like his
they were at the centre of conflicts between the highest authorities on earth own members.^”*
at that time, i.e. the kings/emperors of the emerging medieval states and
the pope. John’s use of the body-state analogy was but a foretaste of the The socio-political body of a Christian state was thought to function
conceptual battles that were to follow. in harmony with the church, which was the “body of Christ”.^^ In less
theologically orientated works, such as Brunetto Latini’s Book of Trea­
sure (1260-1266), the head-body relationship was praised for being mutu­
6.2 THE “COMMON GOOD” OF THE POLITICAL ally beneficial and this practical/functional evaluation was also explicitly
BODY'. SCHOLASTIC ARGUMENTS applied to elected rulers of medieval city-republics.^® In the further devel­
opment of scholasticism, however, the implications of the analogy started
A new impetus for the corporeal analogy during the Middle Ages was the to.be examined critically. The part-whole relationship as a central tertium
reception of Aristotle’s Politics, together with his Ethics and Rhetoric, after comparationis between members of a body and members of a political
92 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Solidarity and Hierarchy 93
community was in need of further explication, on account of the incongru­ authority was “concerned with heavenly things and the soul” whilst “the
ence between the way in which a limb automatically “follows” the will of authority of temporal rulers [was] concerned with earthly things and the
the soul and the obedience that a Christian owed to the ruler. To solve this body”; hence, “the latter should be ordered towards the former as it would
problem, Giles of Rome (c. 1247-1316) and Henry of Ghent (c. 1217-1293) be towards something superior”.'^®
endeavoured to define more precisely the “common good” as the basis on The corporeal analogy could cut both ways in the debates about the
which socio-political obedience to the worldly ruler could be justified. His “common good” and “the two kingdoms” between the scholastic advisers
-right to command and tax everyone was derived from his function to ben­ of kings and popes. In contrast to the creative exploitation of the full range
efit the whole of the political body, even if this diminished the personal of source concepts by John of Salisbury, however, the scholastics used the
good(s) of the individual. metaphor in a more schematic way and restricted it largely to the head/
This principle was, however, put in question as a result of the conflicts soul-body relationship, which was only varied in terms of the target notion
between the French King, Philip IV (“the Fair”), and the church over inves­ (worldly ruler vs. pope/church). The illness-cure event structure, too, was
titure and taxation, which developed towards the end of the thirteenth alluded to only as an abstract threat, with barely a mention of drastic cures
century. Who was to be in command of the body of Christianity (and its such as a m p u ta tio n .A further contrast to John’s Policraticus are the ref­
national sub-units)? In 1302, Pope Boniface VIII reasserted the church’s erences to the Aristotle’s Politics as a well-established “authority” on a par
claim to ultimate power {plenitudo potestatis) in his bull Unam sanctam. with the Bible and Augustine’s De Civitate (not to mention a fictitious text
According to the bull, the church represented “one mystical body” [unum such as Plutarch’s letter to Trajan). The discourse tradition of the body-
corpus mysticum), “whose head was Christ” {cuius caput Christus): he had state metaphor was thus newly cross-referenced with regard to canonical
delegated his authority to St. Peter and to each of his successors, respec­ predecessor texts to strengthen the analogical arguments derived from it.
tively, as the sole head of Christendom, without allowing for any compet­
ing second head.^* The pope’s “spiritual” authority was therefore superior
to the “worldly” authority of any prince. This proposition was backed up 6.3 CHALLENGES TO THE POLITICAL BODY
by references to the traditional body-church analogy, e.g. in the writings of HIERARCHY IN THE LATE MIDDLE AGES
Giles of Rome {De Ecclestastica Potestate, 1302) and of James of Viterbo
(c. 1255-1308; P)e Regimine Christiano, 1302).^^ Reasserting some of John With the waning of both the papal and imperial powers after the thirteenth
of Salisbury’s views, they emphasized the obligation for all members of the century, the focus of political body theory gradually shifted away from
body of the church, including worldly rulers, to obey the commands of its the competition between rival heads (pope v. emperor/king) towards the-
soul, i.e. the pope.^° relationship between the head and the rest o f the body.’Yh.e change waSj
The corporeal analogy was, however, also employed to argue for the by no means abrupt; papal arid imperial claims to headship still occupied,
opposite solution in favour of ultimate authority lying with the Christian for instance, William of Ockham (c. 1285-1347) and Bartolus of Saxo-
worldly ruler. Using Godfrey of Fontaines’s (c. 1250-1309) argument that ferrato (1314-1357). They still made use of scholastic formulations about
a.ruler’s taxes, if used “for the good of the community”, are the sustenance the “regular” working of a Christian monarchy in terms of the body-state
of the state’s body/^ John of Paris (c. 1255-1306) asserted that any human analogy but now applied them to decide “irregular” questions, such as the
body, whether individual or collective, “would pass away unless there systematic theory of the right to resist or depose rulers. In his Eight Ques­
were some common force within the body which directed it towards the tions on the Power o f the Pope, William of Ocjd^m ^ g ued that as “in
common good of all the members” and identified the king as that force.^^ a natural body, when one limb beconies defe^ive, tlie rest make up the
An even more radical stance was taken by Marsilius of Padua (c. 1275-c. deficiency if they are able”, so in a worldfy universitas-''wh^n one part
1342), who in his “Defender of the Peace” {Defensor Pads, 1324) turned becomes defective, the other parts, if they have the natural power, ought to
the “papalist argument on its head”.^^ With reference to Books I and V make up the deficiency”.^^[He concludes that in the desperate emergency of
of Aristotle’s Politics, Marsilius used the analogy between the health o f a the supreme head of the empire behaving as a tyrant, he may be removed
body and the “tranquillity” of a state^^' to draw the conclusion that only a “by those who Represent the peoples subject to the Roman Imperium”, in
worldly authority could act as “Defender of the Peace”, and that the pope’s particular “by the elector-princes” as the “chief ‘limbs’ or ‘members’ of the
claim to this role represented a “pernicious plague”.'^^ In a further twist to body of the EmpJre”.^^^artolus asserted that any “right of judgment” held
the argument about the st^tdbody’s “tranquillity”, however, Remigio dei by elected rulers “was only delegated to them {concessum est) by the sov­
Girolami (c. 1235-1319), with reference to Augustine’s De Civitate Dei, ereign body of the populace”.^®By the mid-fourteenth century, such limita­
put the sublime peace of the spiritual kingdom above worldly peace: papal tions of the imperial head’s supreme command even found their way into
Solidarity and Hierarchy 95
94 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
to return to the public good, as will be better explained later. Just as
the formulations of the Holy Roman Empire’s constitution as laid down the legs and feet sustain the human body, so, too, the laborers sustain
in the “Golden Bull” of 1356. Here, the “prince-electors” of the empire
all the other estates.'^^
were depicted metaphorically as being "the chief columns” that “sustain”
the empire and at the same time “the chief members of its mystical body”, Although this exposition of the head-to-feet hierarchy at first sight appears
whose consensus was essential “if ‘Imperial honour’ as well as Imperial to be quite similar to John of Salisbury’s, two crucial elements are missing;
unity were to be preserved”.^^ the soullchurch and the heart/senate analogies are left out and they do not
It was not just the head-kukrship of Christendom or the “Holy Roman appear in later chapters. Thus, a little more than a century after the papal
Empire” that was subjected to critical scrutiny through the applications claim of supreme headship over the mystical body of Christendom and in .
of body imagery (though the respective debates continued long into the particular over worldly emperors and kings, little was left of the hierocratic
fifteenth century, e.g. in the context of the conciliarist movement).^^ The application of the corporeal analogy, even if the Livre de Corps de Policte
national monarchies of France and England, engaged as they were in The still contained references to the canonical text tradition (i.e. Paul s epis­
Hundred Years War” as well as in internal dynastic conflicts, were chal­
tles Aristotle’s Ethics, Politics and Rhetoric and Augustine’s
lenged in two famous reformulations of the body-state analogy. In 1406, Dei) Christine combines the head/body-im^gery with that of the ‘ good
during the reign of King Charles VI of France, who faced challenges from shepherd”, taken from the New Testament.^^|The princelhead is first and
\ successive English kings as well as from powerful French dukes, Christine foremost obliged to stay healthy, “that is, virtuous”, by following Christ s
de Pizan (c. 1364-c. 1430) wrote the Book o f the Body Politic [hivre de model as a good shepherd, for if the head “is ill, the whole body will feel
Corps de Folicie), dedicated to the king and the princes, with particular it’w C hristine admits that the good prince “should be feared” on account
benefit for the Dauphin, Louis of GuyenneF%ome sixty-five years later, Sir of his “virtue” and “justice”, i.e. his determination to give “the same right
John Fortescue (c. 1395-c. 1477), attending the exiled English Queen Mar­ to everyone”,®’ but she insists that this authority must be coupled with kind­
garet of Anjou and her son Edward, whose father. King Henry VI, had been ness and mercy.®2 The good prince must therefore not aim to rule by him­
taken prisoner by the (Yorkist) King Edward composed in Latin a trea­ self i e tyrannically, but in consultation and continuous discussion with
tise in “Praise of the Laws of England” (De laudibus legum Anglie). Here, his advisors and nobles, thus also supporting and practicing eloquence and
the body-state analogy was used as a frame for lessons by the “Chancellor
learnedness as key skills of politics.®^
(the mouthpiece of Fortescue) to the Prince of Wales on the constitution of What happens to a prince who does not care about achieving consensus
his nation as a “political and royal dominion”.^^ Both Pizan and Fortescue’s and who has an over-suspicious or hostile attitude towards his s^t>jects is
texts adapted the metaphor concept of the Christian state as a body to the made abundantly clear in Christine’s version of the “fable of the belly ,
changing political context of their age and in the process changed the meta­ which is notably different from the previous medieval uses that took only
phor’s cognitive import in significant ways.
Christine de Pizan’s Livre de Corps de Bolide is construed, as its title the side of prince:
suggests, as an explication of the body-state analogy and introduces it right Once upon a time there was a great disagreement between the belly of
at the start in Chapter 1. Without naming John of Salisbury,^^ she takes a human body and its limbs. The belly complained loudly about the
over his conceit of Plutarch’s letter to Trajan, in which he compared the limbs and said that they thought badly of it and that they did take
polity to a body having life”: care of it and feed as well as they should. On t_hejDtherJiand,3e limbs
said they were all exhausted from work, ^ndyet despite all their labor,
There the prince and princes hold the place of the head in as much as coming and going and working, the belly wanted to have everything
they are or should be sovereign and from them ought to come par­ ^nd was never satisfied. The limbs then decided that they would no
ticular institutions just as from the mind of a person spring forth the longer suffer such pain and labor, since nothing they did satisfied the
external deeds that the limbs achieve. The knights and nobles take the belly. So they would stop their work and let the belly get along as best
place of the hands and arms. Just as a person’s arms have to be strong it might. The limbs stopped their work and the belly was no longer
in order to endure labor, so they have the burden of defending the law nourished. So it began to get thinner, and the limbs began to fail and
of the prince and the polity. They are also the hands, because just as weaken, and so, to spite one another, the whole body died.®"*
the hands push aside harmful things, so they ought push all harmful
and useless things aside. The other kinds of people are like the belly, In this version of the fable, it is the belly that initiates the conflict by,-com-
the feet and the legs. Just as the belly receives all that the head and the plaining about the alleged laziness of the limbs and thus provokes the
limbs prepare for it, so, too, the activity of the prince and nobles ought
Solidarity and Hierarchy 97
96 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
is accorded functional precedence. It is not the head/pnnce's autonomous
conflict.” The limbs' counter-complaint carries at least as much plausi­
will that directs the political body but he is dependent on the supply of the,
bility as his. Their ensuing rebellion is ultimately self-destructive; here
blood of “political provision for the interest of the people” in order to be y
Christine’s version conforms to the tradition. But the responsibility for the
able to govern in the proper way. This limitation of the head/prince's role is
catastrophe is shared between limbs and belly. Christine explicitly draws
further reinforced in the paragraph that follows the previous passage:
the conclusion that just as in the fable “when a prince requires more than a
people can bear, then the people complain against the prince and rebel by
The law . .. resembles the sinews of the physical body, for just as the
disobedience”, with the outcome that “they all perish together”, whereas
body is held together by the sinews, so this body mystical [of the people]
“agreement preserves the whole body politic”.®^ This is a far cry from John
is bound together and preserved as one by law . . . and the members
of Salisbury’s vivid description of the head's duty to implement therapy-
and bones of this body, which signify the solid basis of truth by which
by-amputation or the tacit obedience requested by the pope’s version of the
the community is sustained, preserve their rights through' the laws, as
fable in the purported conversation with John.” The head/belly of the body
the body natural does through the sinews. And just as the head of the
politic that Christine described was doubtless in a position of authority, but
physical body is unable to change its sinews, or to deny its members
not of autocracy or godlike rulership; the Livre de Corps de PoUde thus
proper strength and due nourishment of blood, so a king who is head
marks an important step in the secularisation of the concept of political
of the body politic is unable to change the laws of that body, or to
headship. deprive that same people of their'own substance uninvited or against
Our second key text to illustrate the range of conceptual shifts in. the
body-state analogy during the late medieval period, John Fortescue’s Praise their wills.^'*
o f the Laws o f England, is a didactic dialogue in which the “Chancellor”
Not only is the head/prince not autonomous but he is depicted as being even
convinces the “Prince” to immerse himself in the study of the customary
unable to change the smew^s/laws substantially because they are integral
English laws in addition to the universal, God-given laws.” Such knowl­
parts of his own body. Furthermore, Fortescue also emphasises their lon­
edge of the national laws founded on traditional customs and statutes should
gevity and anteriority to any dynasty by asserting their existence since the
enable the Prince to rule “politically”, i.e. in consensus with his nation, rather
nation’s legendary foundation by exiled Trojans, through British, Roman,
than “only royally” {i.e. by sheer royal power).^^ The central justification for
Saxon, Danish and Norman rule.” This “argument from antiquity” invokes
this approach is spelt out in the Chancellor’s'explanation of “how kingdoms
the historical track record of the nation’s “own” laws as an argument for
ruled politically first began”.^“ Fortescue starts with a rather crude demon­
their authority.^^ At the same time, it reinforces the conclusiveness of the
stration of the necessity of a political head for the political body, because
corporeal analogy: if the nation is a political, “mystical” body, it must
“just as in natural things, what is left over after decapitation is not a body,
have come into life, with the heart!ptop\t's intention being its “first living
but what we call a trunk, so p o litic a l things, a community without a head
thing”, nourishing the body’s sinews. Their longevity is evidence of the
is not by any means a b o d y . ^ o far, the analogy is explicated in the tradi­
body’s.general health; hence, if the head/pr'mce wishes to care for the body
tional manner and backed up by references to Aristotle and A ugustine,but
of the nation, he had better learn and observe the customs that have kept it
it soon serves as a platform for innovative explorations:
in good health for so long.^^.
Christine de Pizan and John Fortescue’s conceptualisations of the state
Just as . . . the physical body grows out of the embryo, regulated by one
as a body are perhaps the most “balanced” acco.untS'^rtenrls'ofThsrrela­
head, so the kingdom issues from the people, and exists as a body mys­
tionship between the roX^t-organ {head/belly) and the other members that
tical, governed by one man as head. And just as in the body natural, as
we have come across so far. The limbs’ duty to obey the authority of the
the Philosopher [i.e. Aristotle] said, the heart is the first living thing,
head/belly is still maintained but the whole body’s health is of paramount
having in itself the blood, which it sends forth to all the members,
whereby they are quickened and live, so in the body politic the inten­ importance and overrides any ambitions or prerogatives that the head^may
. claim. In this regard they come close to Susan Sontag’s notion of the "clas­
tion of the people is the first living thing, having in it the blood, namely
political provision for the interest of the people, which it transmits to sical” tradition of corporeal and medical metaphors for the state being
premised on the assumption that the “prognosis” for the body politic is
the head and all the members of the body, by which the body is nour­
always, in principle, optimistic” and is primarily intended “to encourage
ished and quickened.^^
rulers to pursue a more rational policy”.^® According to Sontag’s model,
these late medieval versions of the body-state analogy would thus be
The head's principal ruler-authority is acknowledged but the heart, as “the
grouped together with earlier medieval versions, e.g. by John of Salisbury
first living thing” in the body and representing the people’s “intention”.
98 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
and the scholastics. This generalization is, however, not borne out by the
texts. Despite referring to John of Salisbury and other medieval thinkers (as 7 Concepts of Healing the Body
well as to the classical authorities of Aristotle, Augustine, etc.), Christine
de Pizan and John Fortescue changed the discourse about the body politic
Politic in the Renaissance
significantly by retelling the “fable of the belly” in a more evenly weighted
account of responsibility for the body politicos health or lack of it (Pizan),
and by affirming the functional precedence of the nation’s heart over its
head (Fortescue). The latter version might be regarded as being reminiscent
of John of Salisbury’s limitation of the head's rulership by the heart-as-
senate, were it not for the fact that the Anglo-Norman bishop gave absolute
priority to the so«//church over both the headlprxnzt and the heartlsen-
ate.^^ These differences show that there was in fact no fixed pre-modern or
“classical” model that mapped roughly the same corporeal concepts onto By the early sixteenth century, the notion of the ruler, whether Pope,
roughly the same target notions of state/society. Rather, the whole concep­ Emperor, King or other worldly prince, as the head of ‘his’ political entity
tual complex, involving both source and target levels, exhibits a consider­ was a well-established commonplace that co-existed alongside the older
able range of synchronic and diachronic variation. This variation was by hierocratic and legal notions. The commonsense implication was that the
no means random but reflected the changing socio-political contexts for the ruler was an integral part of the body and therefore dependent on its gen­
application of the metaphor, from an early focus on the Christian Empire eral health. If the body died, the head (or, in the “fable” tradition, the belly)
as a “mystical body” to justifications over competing claims to supreme would perish with it. In the following two centuries this assumption was
headship between pope and emperor or dynastic prince to political theories to change drastically. The assumption of the interdependence of all body
for worldly states, in which the head's rule over the other members had politic members including the head o f state gave way to new concepts that
to be re-conceptualised and re-legitimised in terms of the whole national served the ideological needs of rulers who were able to make a bid for more
body's needs. absolute power. The metaphorical framing of these changes forms the topic
of this chapter.^

7.1 SHAKESPEARE’S UBIQUITOUS BODY POLITIC

During the “Autumn of the Middle Ages” (Huizinga), the internal conflicts
of church and empire, the reformation and the discoveries in all fields of
the arts, geography and the (proto-)sciences had put the notion of a stable
Great Chain o f Being system in question. Its socio-political application by
way of interpreting the state as a body that corresponded to human physical
bodies as well as to celestial cosmic bodies had been adapted to all manner
of pragmatic-rhetorical and political interests.JSIey£rtheles&5-aa“^(flexible)
frame of reference for rhetorical and poetic ;rietaphors, the system was still
functional and experienced its own special “renaissance” in the sixteenth
an,d seventeenth centuries.
In English literature, Shakespeare’s dramas are the classic locus for many
political applications of the Great Chain o f Being system. In Coriolanus,
the character of Menenius, who tells of the “fable of the belly”,^ is by no
means the only one using body politic imagery. Just when he is about to
giVe voice to the belly's reply to the mutinous members, the First Citizen,
who depicts another vision of a body politic, in which the belly's answer
would have little or no significance, interrupts him: ^
100 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Concepts o/^Healing the Body Politic in the Renaissance 101
Your belly’s answer—what? / The kingly crown’d head, the vigilant this centre / Observe degree, priority and place”)^^, only to then depict in
eye, / The counsellor heart, the arm our soldier, / Our steed the leg, the detail the disasters that befall the body politic in correspondence with the
tongue our trum peter,. . . if that they— . .. / Should by the cormorant macrocosm:
belly be restrain’d, / Who is the sink o’ the body,— . .. / The former
agents, if they did complain, / What could the belly answer?'* . . . when the planets / In evil mixture to disorder wander, / What
plagues and what portents, what mutiny, .. . / Divert and crack, rend
-The First Citizen’s rhetorical question implies that the “cormorant” (ever- and deracinate / The unity and married calm of states / Quite from
hungry) belly, the “sink o’ the body” would have no right to speak at all their fixture. . .. / Take but degree away, untune that string, / And
in the illustrious company of the previously mentioned “higher” organs of hark! What discord follows.*^
state. Menenius’s reply seems to disabuse him of this assumption only to
confirm the traditional hierarchy (the authority of the senate) by validat­ Ulysses’ speech, together with the wealth of references to the Great Chain
ing the belly as “the store-house and the shop / Of the whole body”, i.e. as system in Shakespeare and his contemporaries’ works (e.g. Spenser’s works,
being indispensable for the well-being of the whole organism, and later by Raleigh’s History o f the World, Elyot’s The Book Named the Governor and
humiliating the First Citizen as “the great toe”. ^ The potential plebeian the Laws o f Ecclesiastical Polity), served Tillyard as evidence that the prin­
complaint about being discriminated against by the belly-a.na\ogy is thus ciple of degree in the Chain o f Being was “taken for granted” by “all Eliza­
averted. Later in the drama, the pro-plebeian Tribunes develop an illness- bethans of even modest intelligence-”*'* and was still defended against all
amputation scenario to justify the banishment of the patrician Coriolanus misgivings of impending destabilization.*^ Quentin Skinner, however, reads
by likening him to a “disease that must be cut away”, a “gangren’d foot”, Ulysses’ speech on degree “more as a reflection of the resulting confusions
and an “infection” that, “being of a catching nature”, endangers the whole than a straightforward restatement of the old commonplaces”.*^ Skinner’s
body politic.^ critique of the over-generalizations of the older history-of-ideas tradition is
The ruler’s role is further thematised in other Shakespearean plays: in justified at the methodological level, insofar as Tillyard’s selection of quo­
Hamlet, he is conceived of as the “head” (i.e. integral part of the body) tations from the top layer of literary and philosophical works can hardly
when Laertes warns Ophelia that the prince’s decisions cannot be only be regarded as representative for the state of a whole national culture in a
for his own person, “for on his choice depends / The sanity and health of particular period. With regard to the body-politic metaphor tradition, an
this whole state; / And therefore must his choice be circumscrib’d / Unto even more radical critique seems to be called for: from the Middle Ages
the voice and yielding of that body / Whereof he is the head”.^ Richard II onwards, this metaphor complex was never fixated on or dominated by one
has been interpreted by Kantorowicz as the “tragedy of the King’s Two meaning alone but lent itself, so to speak, to being used and exploited by
Bodies”,®on account of the piecemeal self-degradation of Richard: with his all sides of topical political conflicts. In the Renaissance, this susceptibility
own hands, he undoes his transcendental body politic, including the sym­ to semantic flexibility and variation led to a truly innovative emphasis on
bols of his dignity, and thus reduces himself to his own body natural, which healing the body politic.
then can be easily disposed of by Bolingbroke, the future king, Henry IV. ^
In Richard III, the Duke of Gloucester is entreated by his supporter Buck­
ingham to take up the kingship, in order to “recure” the state of England: 7.2 HEAD AND HEALER: NEW ROLES FOR
“The noble isle doth want her proper limbs; / Her face defac’d with scars THE RULER OF THE BODY POLITIC ______ _
of infamy, / Her royal stock graft with ignoble plants”.^°The imagery here
invokes the traditional commonplace assumptions, but the character that When King Henry VIII of England asserted his own status as “supreme
employs it not only does so fraudulently but is himself deceived by Richard, Head” of the English body politic in the 1530s,*^ he also assumed reli­
who later has him executed. For the audience, it is imagery used by a liar, gious headship. *®This claim was different from that of earlier debates,
not a truthful representation of a valid, stable belief system. e.g. Marsilius of Padua’s arguments in defence of the emperor (as head
This fundamental ambivalence of both the body politic and Chain of and “Defensor Pacis” of Christendom) or the French King Philip the Fair’s
Being concepts is also exploited in Ulysses’ speech on “degree” in Troilus challenge to papal supremacy, even if the body-head imagery was remi­
and Cressida, which Tillyard read as an exemplary declaration expound­ niscent of medieval debates. Where the earlier debates had focused on the
ing a “conception of order” that was “part of the collective mind of the question of the prince’s right to rule as the head of his worldly imperium
people” in Shakespeare’s time.^^ The speech indeed begins with the solemn without interference from the pope, Henry VIII and Thomas Cromwell’s
invocation of universal order (“The heavens themselves, the planets and legislation redefined the national body politic belonging to the royal head
102 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Concepts o/" Healing the Body Politic in the Renaissance 103
as being a religious body. The king was therefore head of a national state Starkey also allowed for that heart to be made up of “many” persons, either
and church; hence, the “fusion of bodies politic and spiritual was absolute a council of wise men or the whole people.^^ He then had the dialogue part­
and complete”2^ ners agree on a “tempered” monarchical rule combining king, constable,
Whilst the target level implications of this change of head/hody imagery council and parliament as providing the best cure for the body politic.^^
affected first and foremost the conceptualisation of relations between state Starkey’s Pole portrayed the competent healer as helping nature: it suffices
and church, the newly enhanced royal headship of the body politic could for the physician to remove the main cause of illness: then the body can
also include a healing function. Healing, as a form of divine empowerment, recover by itself. Starkey’s conceptualisation of the body politic hovered
“associated with the anointing as part of the coronation ceremonies, had midway between the older notion of the king as integral part of that body
long been part of the King’s “mystical” n a t u r e . B u t this healing tradi­ and that of him as part of a team of healers, which must have been rather
tionally concerned the natural bodies of the King’s subjects from diseases risque in view of Henry VIITs autocratic tendencies. The meticulous refer­
such as scrofula and epilepsy. What was in question now was the power ence to the “four humours” theory tradition as the framework for a system
of healing the body politic. Whilst defenders of the traditional political of political “illnesses” and “cures” may have been intended to tone down
body-head concept {and of the traditional state-church relationship), such (or possibly, disguise) its revolutionary implications for the understanding
as Sir Thomas More, Sir Thomas Elyot, Cardinal Reginald Pole and Bishop of the powers of the ruler.
John Fisher (and indeed Henry VIII himself in his proclamations before the The first theory that appears systematically to ascribe the power of heal­
break with Rome), spoke of royal headship as included in the whole body,^’ ing the body politic to the ruler was the one developed by Starkey’s Italian
the King’s chaplain, Thomas Starkey (1495-1537), introduced—cautious- contemporary, Niccolo Machiavelli (1469-1527). In the last chapter of The
■ly—a new perspective on the relationship of king and body politic in his Prince {II Principe, composed in 1513, published posthumously in 1532),
Dialogue between Pole and Lupset (written c. 1529-1532, later dedicated after diagnosing that Italy had “great virtue in the limbs, were it not for
to Henry VIII).^^ the lack of virtue in the heads”, Machiavelli voiced his fervent longing for
Starkey had his one dialogue partner, Cardinal Reginald Pole, invoke the advent of a national healer figure, who might heal Italy’s “wounds . . .
Pauline and Platonic references and the humoral theory as his frame and who can cure her of those sores that have been festering for so long”.^®
of reference for eight chief political maladies:^^ meagreness—lack of Earlier on, he had analogised “consumptive illnesses” with dangers to the
populace,^** dropsy—negligent or lazy p o p u la c e ,palsy—social unrest, state: just as the former are in the beginning “easy to cure but difficult to
pestilence—political d i s c o r d , deformity—imbalances in society,^® diagnose”, but if not recognised or treated at the outset, become “easy to
weakness—inability of a nation to defend itself,^^ frenzy—irrational diagnose but difficult to cure”, so also political “evils” that are foreseen “in
go ver nme nt , an d gout—bad conditions for farmers and workers who advance (a gift granted only to the prudent ruler),.. . can be cured quickly;
sustain the basis of soci et y. Thi s list of socio-political was clearly but when they are .. . left to grow to such an extent that everyone recogn­
based on traditional notions of an ideal balance and proportion of bodies ises them, there is no longer any remedy”.
natural and politic. Sontag reads this use of the illness metaphor as being “not so. much
The state’s head, i.e. “offycerys Sc rularys” could fall ill from frenzy— about society as about statecraft (conceived as a therapeutic art): as pru­
but even that was curable. Starkey thus appears to fulfil Sontag’s (1978) dence is needed to control serious diseases, so foresight is needed to control
concept of political illnesses as imbalances in the body politic that can all social crises”; hence she counts Machiavelli amongst the “optimistic”,
in principle be remedied. His reformist proposals—i.e. equitable taxation, classical thinkers: “the presumption is that the disease can be cured.”
measures to increase the population, banishment of malcontents, improved However, it is surprising that Machiavelli’s call for foresight in The Prince
education and, in particular, the prevention of sedition^^—all betrayed a leaves out any concrete description of the thernpy~^ndTln p^ticulai, any
pragmatic orientation. specification of how drastic it may have to be. The Prince does not explain
Whilst Starkey’s political illness metaphors were perfectly traditional in ' the precise nature of the envisaged “therapeutic art” in politics; instead, it
applying the “humoral” system and were compatible with the notion of a giifes a rather general (and almost tautological) calculation of the chances
powerful ruler-healer in principle, they did not chime with the principle of of success: these are good, if the illness is diagnosed early enough; if the
renewed, emphatic spiritual-cum-political headship, which, as we saw, was diagnosis is left too late, “there is no longer any remedy”.
non-negotiable for King Henry VIII. Starkey therefore had to be extremely In order to understand more clearly what Machiavelli had in mind as
careful: he left the king out of the list of parts-of the body politic that political cures, we have to consult his Discourses on the First Ten Books
attracted the aforementioned chief political illnesses: the king was not the of Livy {Discorsi, first published in 1531), where he discusses remedies for
head (which might fall ill from frenzy) but the heart of the state’s body.^^ maladies of the state in detail. These remedies, exemplified by events from
104 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Concepts o/" Healing the Body Politic in the Renaissance 105
Roman history, include draconian measures such as “judicial sentence of by scruples is to betray your chosen cause. To be a physician is to be a
death on a whole legion at a time, or on a city”, mass banishments and deci­ professional, ready to burn, to cauterize, to amputate; if that is what the
mation, as well as prudent constitutional changes that prevent “corruption” disease requires, then to stop halfway because of personal qualms, or
of the body politic.^^ The former cures are obviously far from benign; in some rule unrelated to your art and its technique, is a sign of muddle and
fact, they are deliberately intended to be “terrifying”/^ Other references to weakness, and will always give you the worst of both worlds”.®'^ Skinner
political diseases in the Discourses reiterate the need for immediate action, likewise views Machiavelli as demanding from “men of the highest virtu”
once political illness symptoms have been identified,for instance, with that they must “be capable, when the situation requires it, of behaving in
regard to the potential of ambition to grow into a disease that can cause a completely vicious way”.®®
the destruction o f a state,^^ or the unwillingness to prepare for war as a Such an emphasis on Machiavelli’s supposed endorsement of complete
malady that can be cured only by a strong government,^® Machiavelli also ruthlessness and “viciousness” in applying political therapy may, however,
compares republican and princely maladies and their respective therapies: be just as much an exaggeration of its pessimistic, or cynical, aspects as
“a licentious and turbulent populace, when a good man can obtain a hear­ Sontag’s reading of it as an example of “classical” optimism. Overall, pol­
ing, can easily be brought to behave itself; but there is no one to talk to a itics is conceived by Machiavelli as the art of gaining, maintaining and
bad prince, nor is there any remedy except the sword”/^ The inference that perfecting government against the contingency of Fortune by combating,
Machiavelli draws in the Discorsi is “that the greater the cure, the greater through renewed virtii, the maladies that befall every state over time.®®
the fault’V® hence, a diseased form of princely rule is worse for the body In the context of this argument, the body-illness-cure scenario serves to
politic and requires the ultimate remedy of “the sword”, in contrast to the explain politicians’ ability to effect the renewal of virtue and foresee, pre­
more easily manageable diseases caused by popular unrest. vent and, if needs be, diagnose and cure political maladies; it is neither a
Machiavelli clearly did envisage life‘threatening and incurable diseases guarantee for the success of the cure nor a fatalistic endorsement of radical
of the state and the respective radical counter-measures. In his reflections policies that must be carried through “no matter at what cost”.
on the transition from a tyranny to a republic, in Chapters 16-18 of the This pragmatic line of argument is taken up'(with explicit reference to
Discourses, he proposes a kind of inverse relationship between the gravity Machiavelli) by Francis Bacon (1561-1626) in his Essays, in particular
and the curability of political corruption in princely and republican states. Essay XV: O f Seditions and Troubles.^'^ Bacon distinguishes between two
Princely corruption is most dangerous and can lead to the destruction of kinds of seditions, the first one being caused by “much poverty” (“rebel­
the state but it is curable, albeit by radical, violent means {the sword). On lions of the belly”—a neat metonymical inversion of the rebellion against
the other hand, if the people themselves have become corrupt, “neither in the belly fable) and the second by “discontentments”.®®The latter are lik­
Rome nor anywhere else would remedies adequate for its existence have ened, in accordance with the traditional imagery, “to humours in the natu­
been found”.'*^ A populace that has become a republic but “has been accus­ ral [body], which are apt to gather a preternatural heat and to inflame”.®^
tomed to live under a prince” (and hence, corrupted) will therefore “return However, Bacon makes no attempt to invoke a symmetrical system of bio­
to the yoke” at the next opportunity.®'^ Therefore, the republic, whilst being medical concepts comparable, for instance, to Starkey’s account (nor to
in principle a healthier state than a principality (due to its capability to “modern” scientific accounts, either).®'* What matters most for Bacon, as
listen to sober criticism and advice and effect reforms),®^ is doomed if cor­ for Machiavelli, is the distinction between proper healers of the body poli­
ruption has spread to all or most of her members and even “penetrated to tic and quacks: “as there are mountebanks for the natural body, so there
the bowels”.®^ are mountebanks for the politic body; men that undertake great cures, and
The systematic classification of political maladies according to dif­ perhaps have been lucky in two or three experiments^burWanttKe grounds
ferent criteria—primary victim (prince or people), form of government, of science, and therefore cannot hold out.”®'
gravity of corruption—and the explicit specification of some illnesses that In Machiavelli’s and Bacon’s (and implicitly perhaps also in Starkey’s)
are only curable “by the sword” put into question the interpretation of perspective, it was no longer sufficient for the ruler to be a healthy part
Machiavelli’s political theory as an example of the “classical” concept of o f the body politic, whether as head or as belly. His new essential quality
political concepts, as suggested by Sontag. ®®For this reason, other was that he functioned as a competent healer, as a benign authority that
commentators have stressed the ruthlessness of Machiavelli’s proposals could identify the right medicine and effect the right treatment when
for political and social therapies. Isaiah Berlin interpreted Machiavelli’s threatened. Machiavelli’s and Bacon’s innovations vis-a-vis the traditional
“secular, humanistic, naturalistic morality” as implying that “Once you body-state analogy lay not so much in the repudiation or denial of the
embark on a plan for the transformation of a society you must carry it “humoral” understanding of the body politic—as we have seen, this sys­
through no matter at what cost: to fumble, to retreat, to be overcome tem had already lost some of its rigidity and validity earlier on—but in the
106 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
emphasis on the healer role. In the following chapter we will discuss how
this healer concept was further developed in the analysis of political lead­ 8 From Political Anatomy to Social
ership put forward by Bacon’s friend and temporary amanuensis, Thomas
Hobbes, in Leviathan. Pathology
Modern Scenarios of the Body Politic and
Its Therapy

Thomas Hobbes’s (1588-1679) version of the body politic metaphor in


Leviathan (1651) has been described variously as marking the final phase
of the classical commonplace metaphor of the state as a human body or as
the start of a new tradition in the history of thought, reflecting as it does the
change from the ancient humoral model of disease to a more “modern” one
that was inspired by new mechanistic and scientific re-conceptualisations
of both physical and social bodies.^ Whilst these periodizing perspectives
articulate important insights into a major discontinuity between traditional
and modern versions of the metaphor in terms of its conceptual elements,
they tend to gloss over the argumentative implications that follow from the
main argumentative scenarios in which the metaphor is employed. In this
chapter, these implications will be highlighted and characterised as laying
the stress on a pathological view of the staxt-body, with view to linking
them to metaphor versions that were formulated later during the Enlight­
enment and in the run-up to the French Revolution. The claim is not that
Hobbes’s concept of the body politic in Leviathan directly informed or
inspired the implicitly or explicitly regicide applications of the metaphor
but that it opened the way for a thoroughly sceptical attitude towards the
traditional head (= Prince)’s competence to effect necessary cures o f the
body politic once the latter had seriously fallen ill.

8.1 THE BODY POLITIC AND ITS DISEASES IN HOBJBESiR^


LEVIATHAN: “ARTIFICIALL MAN” OR JWO-HEADED MONSTER

Hobbes’s treatise has as its very introduction a drawn-out metaphor-cum-


allegory of the state as a human body, which may at first sight look like an
extended version of John of Salisbury’s pseudo-PIutarchian body analogy,
albeit not ordered from “head to toe” but biographically from “the cradle
to the grave”:

. . . by Art is created that great L eviathan called a C ommon -wealth ,


or State, . . . which is but an Artificial! Man; though of greater stature
\

108 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust From Political Anatomy to Social Pathology 109
and strength than the Naturall, . . . ; and in which the Soveraignty is with the modern usage of the term.^ Hobbes indeed criticises “metaphor”
an Artificial! Soul, as giving life and motion to the whole body; The but endorses explicitly what he calls “similitude”—i.e. in modern termi­
Magistrates, and other Officers of Judicature and Execution, artificial! nology, simile (which counts in cognitive theory as a conceptual mapping
Joynts; Reward and Punishment (by which fastned to the seate of the just as a metaphor). He sees in “similitudes” not an abuse but, on the con­
Soveraignty, every joynt and member is moved to performe his duty) trary, a helpful tool to “open up” the understanding in “Demonstration,
are the Nerves, that do the same in the Body Naturall; The Wealth and in Councell, and all rigourous search of Truth”.^° Similitudes show good
Riches of all the particular members, are the Strength', Salus Populi wit, and “rarity of . .. invention”.” Modern criticism of Hobbes as being
(the peoples safety) its Businesse; Counsellors, by whom all things “anti-metaphor” thus rests on an anachronistic confusion of his special use
needfull for it to know, are suggested unto it, are the Memory; Equity of the term metaphor in the sense as an “abuse” of speech and, the cogni­
and Lawes, an artificial! Reason and Will; Concord,- Health; Sedition, tive meaning of “metaphor” as a conceptual operation that would have
Sicknesse; and Civill war. Death. Lastly, the Pacts and Covenants, by included what he endorsed as “similitude”.
which the parts of this Body Politique were at first made, set together, Besides the above-quoted introduction. Leviathan contains one fur­
and united, resemble that Fiat, or the Let us make man, pronounced ther passage that depicts the state as a human body in Chapter 23, which
by God in the Creation. ^ treats “O/"the publique ministers o f Soveraign Power”. A few other refer­
ences to organs and functions of the body politic are scattered through­
The body-state metaphor pervades the remainder of Leviathan, to the out the book. Tables 8.1 and 8.2 give an overview over these conceptual
extent that without it the whole treatise would, in the words of Prokhovnik mappings.
(1991), “consist of a set of doctrines without a cohering philosophy, and Some salient body parts, e.g. head, heart and feet, which had hitherto
its rhetoric would lack its central feature”.^ Overall, as Johnston (1986) always been included in traditional versions of the body-state analogy,
observes, Leviathan is “rhetorical in character throughout”, and “simile are missing, and there is one minor discrepancy: the source concept of
and metaphor are in constant use”.*’ Besides the body politic, Skinner (1996) nerves is used to depict both a political function and the functionaries
counts five further major metaphorical themes: reading (of Man’s charac­ {Publique ministers) themselves. Furthermore, the second list contains
ter), physical movement, use o f arms in combat, building-architecture, and as many psychological and social qualities of human beings as physi­
enslavement-physical constraint.^ Not only are metaphors in abundance; cal ones. It is therefore evident that there is no systematic anatomical
the latter parts of the treatise (III and IV) also abound in comments on
whether specific biblical passages should or should not be read metaphori­
cally, with Hobbes’s argumentation again exploiting the whole range of Table 8.1 Political Body Parts/Fluids in Leviathan
rhetorical tropes. Source Concepts Target Concepts
Far from earning him a reputation as a sophisticated rhetorician, Hob­
bes’s abundant use of imagery has led to accusations of methodological Body Common-W ealth
inconsistency, in view of his own explicit denunciation of “metaphor” in Soul Soveraignty
Leviathan (and elsewhere) as an “abuse” of words, which, like “senslesse
and ambiguous words”, functions as intellectual “/gwes fatui” (i.e. will- Joynts M agistrates
o’-the-wisps): “reasoning upon them is wandering amongst innumerable Nerves rew ard, p u n i s l ^ ^ t
absurdities”; whoever follows them ends in “contention and sedition, or
contempt”.^ Some cognitive metaphor researchers have seen in Hobbes’s Publique Ministers: Protectors, Vice-Roys, and
apparent “anti-metaphor” stance “the most complete and clear exam­ Governors
ple of the epistemological basis for the empiricist attack on metaphor”,^
Hands Publique M inisters: executioners etc.
whilst others view him as a metaphor critic who did not follow his own
recipe.® Eyes Publique M inisters: Governm ent Spies
On closer inspection, though, the contradiction between Hobbes’s con­
demnation of “metaphor” and his own frequent use of it reveals itself to Fare Publique M inisters: Receivers of petitions
be something of a myth. Basically, the term metaphor in Leviathan has Blood mony, gold and silver
a special meaning that was based on the classic rhetorical and humanist
tradition of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries and had got little to do Muscles lawful Systemes, and Assemblyes of People
110 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust From Political Anatomy to Social Pathology 111
Table 8.2 Political Life Functions in Leviathan Oliver Cromwell’s “Common-Wealth”, to the fact that the previous Head
Source Concepts o f State, King Charles I, had literally been decapitated two years earlier,
Target Concepts
and jump to the conclusion “that the metaphor of the body politic died
Strength w ealth, riches with the king at Whitehall”.'^ However, even during the English civil war,
Safety the head of the King as the ‘King body politic’ (in contrast to the actual
businesse
bodily King), was still retained by Parliment as a symbol on the great
Memory counsellors seal and coins, as Kantorowicz has ponted out: “the king body natural in
Oxford had become a nuisance to Parliament; but the King body politic
Reason and will equity and laws was still useful: he was still present in Parliament, though only in his seal
Health concord
image”. N e i t h e r was a head required for the “Soveraign” of Hobbes’s
Leviathan—what mattered was the “constructedness” of the “Artificial!
Death civill w ar Man'’— head and all—as is highlighted in the exposition of the whole
God's Fiat (Genesis) analogy, which precedes the above-quoted body politic passage:
pacts, covenants
Voice judges N ature (the Art whereby God hath made and governes the World) is by
the Art of man, as in many other things, so in this also imitated, that it
Nutritive faculty Power of levying mony can make an Artificial Animal. For seeing life is but a motion of Limbs,
Motive faculty Power of conduct and com m and
the beginning whereof is in some principall part within; why may we
not say, that all Automata (Engines that move themselves by springs
Rationall faculty Power of m aking Lawes and wheeles as doth a watch) have an artificial! life?'^
Procreation, children colonies
The “Artificial Animal” of the body politic is a human imitation of the nat­
ural body, which itself is an artifice made by God. Where God only needed
account of the body politic in terms of a 1:1 correspondence in Levi­ to utter his command to create a human being, man is forced to put together
athan— a. fact that motivated David Hale in particular to list Hobbes laboriously a socio-political construction though covenants.'* Much has
among those who put "an end to sustained or serious use of organic been made of Hobbes’s acknowledgment of contemporary machine concep­
imagery in political discussion”.'^ But then Hobbes nowhere pretended tions of the body, as promoted by Rene Descartes (1596-1650) and Wil­
to aim for comprehensiveness in this respect: his considerable interest in liam Harvey (1578-1657).'^ But the application of the latest physiological
(natural) sciences centred on mathematics and physics, not biology or insights onto politics was surely not the main concern for Hobbes. What
medicine.'^ To decide whether nerves were factually “parts organicall” recommended the mechanical perspective of contemporary medicine and
was not his concern: all that he needed for his argument in Leviathan science to him was rather the fact that it suited his argument. Hobbes’s
were source concepts that fitted the intended target concept of the state theory of the “Common-wealth” as being based on an artificial covenant
in its structural complexity. contradicted any attempt to derive'it from the “state of nature”. The cov­
Even if some prominent body parts are missing at the source level, the enant would relieve men from that state of nature, which was viewed by
body politic depicted in Leviathan is as complex as that on the famous Hobbes famously as continuous warfare, in whix:h-Iife-was^olitafy, poore,
frontispiece of the book, which shows (against varying emblematic back­ nasty, brutish, and short”.^° ''
grounds, depending on the year of the imprint) a crowned figure of a The correspondences between anatomic and functional aspects of the
man from the waist upwards, holding a sword and a crosier in his hands, human body and the state that we have sketched so far are neither sys­
with arms and the trunk consisting of a multitude of miniature heads tematic nor innovative as regards the source concepts: Hobbes picks and
that represent the people.'** If we assume that the frontispiece figure was chooses from the metaphor tradition what is suitable for his analysis of
meant to complement the textual metaphor, we can interpret the crowned the state as a hierarchical and functional whole. However, his analogies
head as containing the state’s soul that is mentioned in the introduc­ are not exhausted by these general references. Leviathan also includes a
tion and represents the sovereign’s will. We should thus be cautious to vivid account of the body politic’s illnesses, which we need to take into
read too much into the “headlessness” of the body politic in Leviathan, consideration in order to assess the overall argumentative import of the
even though it may be tempting to link its publication in 1651, i.e. under metaphor.
112 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Prom Political Anatomy to Social Pathology 113
Hobbes devotes a whole chapter of Leviathan to "things that Weaken, employed illness metaphors mainly to encourage “rulers to pursue a more
or tend to the DissoimiON o f a Common-wealth” The chapter is rational policy”.^^ By comparing his ideological adversaries to mad dogs
roughly structured by the stages of the life cycle and the degree of dan­ that can bite a state to the quick and kill it, Hobbes comes close to suggest­
ger of illnesses in the body politic. First, Hobbes discusses Defectuous ing that such dangerous beasts must be put down, lest they ruin the body
Procreation, i.e. “Imperfect Institution” of states, which he equates with politic.
the lack of power and resources of the sovereign.Secondly, he con­ Hobbes’s discussion of the third type of serious political diseases harks
siders “Diseases of a Common-wealth, that proceed from the poyson back to medico-philosophical speculation: as there “have been Doctors,
of seditious doctrines”. A f t e r refuting six such doctrines, which put that hold there be three Soules in a man: so there be also that think there
the sovereign’s ultimate authority into question, Hobbes analyses the may be more Soules (that is, more Soveraigns,) than one, in a Common­
underlying causes of sedition. Here, illness imagery plays a central role. wealth”.^^ The import of this comparison is an attack on the church’s
The first cause that he highlights is the “Example of different Govern­ claims to “Supremacy against the Soveraignty”, which Hobbes sees as
ment” in other n a tio n s,w h ic h is so seductive that people cannot leave bne of the causes of fanaticism that leads to civil war. In his view,
it be “though they be grieved with the continuance of disorder; like hot “this is a Disease which not unfitly may be compared to the Epilepsie,
blouds, that having gotten the itch, tear themselves with their own nay- or Falling-sicknesse”: an “unnaturall spirit” causes “violent, and irregu­
les, till they can endure the smart no longer.”^^ The reference to hot lar motions” of the members, which puts the victim (person or state) in
blouds appears to be an allusion to the theory of the four humours, danger of falling either into fire/water or into “the Fire of Civill warre”.^"*
which surfaces in Leviathan in a few other instances, e.g. when unlawful The implication is that the sovereign must remain the sole soul of the
assemblies are described as “Wens, Biles, and Apostemes, engendered state; any other rival authority is seen as a mortal danger to'the health of
by the unnaturall conflux of evill humours”. T h e hot blouds passage, the body politic. Lastly among the major challenges to the state’s health,
however, evidently achieves its rhetorical effect less through the reference Hobbes considers the idea of dividing government between two or thrfee
to humoral medicine than the graphic account of scratching an itching constitutional powers, which are loosely likened to life functions, i.e. the
wound. powers of “levying mony, (which is the Nutritive faculty)”, “of conduct
This focus on the graphic depiction of illness symptoms is also promi­ and command, (which is the Motive faculty)” and “of making Lawes,
nent in the discussion of the second cause of political poisoning, i.e. “the (which is the Rational! Faculty)”. A s with the “State v. Church” rivalry
Reading of the books of Policy, and Histories of the antient Greeks, and for the soul of the body politic, Hobbes dismisses any such arrangement
Romans” that incite “young men and all others that are unprovided of as an “irregularity of Common-wealth”.^^
the Antidote of solid Reason” to emulate their reb ellio n s.In particular, After having discussed defective procreation, poisoning and rivalry
ancient republicanism appears poisonous to Hobbes, justifying as it does of souls in one body politic as diseases “of the greatest and most present
regicide: this “Venime” he “will not doubt to compare to the biting of a danger”, Hobbes goes on to describe less dangerous but still important
mad Dogge, which is a disease the Physicians call Hydrophobia, or fear anomalous conditions, which “are not unfit to be o b serv ed ".O f these
o f Water”. Hobbes parallelises the symptoms of this political illness in a he notes seven: 1) “difficulty of raising Mony” (“Ague caused by con­
strictly analogical and at the same time fanciful way: gested arteries obstructing the passage for the Bloud”); 2) monopolies
that hoard “the treasure of the Common-wealth” (“pleurisie”, i.e. intru­
For as he that is so bitten, has a continuall torment of thirst, and yet sion of blood into the lungs); 3) “Popularity of a potent Subject” that
abhorreth water; and is in such an estate, as if the poison endeavoureth tempts him to become leader of a rebellion (“effects of Witchcraft”); 4)
to convert him into a Dogge: So when a Monarchy is once bitten to immoderate growth of towns, corporations aiTd concblmtant^^iberty of
the quick, by those Democraticall writers, that continually snarle at Disputing” (“wormes in the entryles”); 5)'expansionist policies (“Buli­
that estate; it wanteth nothing more than a strong Monarch, which mia”), which in their consequence, lead to “Wounds . . . received from
neverthelesse out of a certain Tyrannophobia, or fear of being strongly the enemy; and the Wens, of ununited conquests”; 6) excessive “Ease”
governed, when they have him, they abhorre. (“Lethargy”) and 7) “Riot and Vain Expense” (“Consumption”).^®Hob­
bes rounds off the discussion of detrimental and destructive develop­
This horror scenario of snarling “Democraticall writers” that can bite a ments in political bodies with a description of a defeat in war as the
state to the quick calls into question not only Hale’s assertion that in Levia­ state’s dissolution, because the sovereign, its soul, loses command of its
than the body-state “comparisons are not insisted upon”,^"^but also Sontag’s members and only leaves the “carcasse” of the s ta te .( s e e overview in
inclusion of Hobbes in the list of pre-modern thinkers who optimistically Table 8.3).
114 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
From Political Anatomy to Social Pathology 115
Table 8.3 Political Illnesses/Diseases in Leviathan. It is evident from the overlaps between different categories and the
Source Concepts Target Concepts mix of concepts from various medical theories {humours, blood circula­
tion, witchcraft, bulimia etc.) that, as in the case of anatomical and func­
Disease, infirmities Things that weaken the Common-wealth tional aspects, there is no pretence of a systematic medical or pathological
Sicknesse account at the source level. Whereas Starkey, in the 1530s, had made sys­
Sedition ■
tematic use of humoral principles, Hobbes, like Bacon, pays little attention
~Unlawfull conflux of evill unlawful assemblies in common-wealth to a consistent analysis of political illnesses as disturbances of the humoral
humours equilibrium, even if he occasionally slips in references to “humours”. The
Hot blouds main contemporary “scientific” alternative to humoral medicine, i.e. Har­
desire of novelty vey’s theory of blood circularion, is also referred to in Leviathan, i.e. in the
Defectuous Procreation Imperfect Institution depiction of the state’s strength as the '‘Wealth and Riches” of money
circulation (“Sanguification of the Common-wealth”),'” and of its impedi­
Biting of Mad Dogge, Tyrannophobia ment by ague or pleurisy.^^ However, it would be a gross misrepresenta­
Hydrophobia tion to claim that this one aspect structures the whole account of political
Epilepsie, or Falling-sicknesse illnesses in Leviathan. It is just one of several source frames of reference,
Belief in Ghostly Kingdome
which, strictly speaking, are incompatible with each other in terms of their
Conjoined twins mixt government medical source notions.
Hobbes’s lack of commitment to a systematic medical underpinning for
Ague (obstructed Heart difficulty of raising Mony his body-state analogies has irritated some modern critics. Hale (1971) found
arteries)
his list of diseases o f the body politic “heterogeneous” and unspecific;'’^H ar­
Pleurisie Monopolies ris (1998) contends that Hobbes did “not have a live humoral vocabulary
with which he might image the commonwealth’s ‘internal diseases’” and
Witchcraft Rebellion by charismatic army leaders that this “predicament” was notable from his inability to find the equiva­
Wormes in entryles lent of the defect of the division of the powers of levying money, of (execu­
liberties of great towns, corporations, liberty tive) command and of making laws.'*'’ To prove the point, Harris quotes
to Dispute
Hobbes’s “admission”; “To what Disease of the Naturall Body of man I
Bulimia appetite of enlarging Dominion may exactly compare this irregularity of a Common-iyealth [i.e. three-way
division of powers], I know not”.'’^ However, Harris omits Hobbes’s further
Wens conquests explanation, which does in fact provide an approximate source equivalent
of the target notion:
unlawfull systemes in the Common-wealth
Biles unlawfull systemes in the Common-wealth But I have seen a man, that had another man growing out of his side,
with an head, armes, breast, and stomach, of his own. If he had had
Apostemes unlawfull systemes in the Common-wealth another man growing out of his other side, th^compa risorumight then
Lethargy have been exact.'*®
Ease
Consumption Riot and Vain Expense In this “admission” of his supposed “predicament” of humoral ignorance,
Hobbes compared what he saw as an unworkable political organisation,
Poyson, venime seditious doctrines i.e. a three-way division of powers in a state, to a condition that would be
- contagion Greek dsemonology met in source terms by conjoined triplets: only they apparently did not exist
in his experience. The next best image was therefore the existing metaphor
■antidote Reason of conjoined twins.*'^ As source input for his simile, this indication was
sufficient to convey what mattered to Hobbes, i.e. the disqualification of
Dissolution, Carcasse Destruction of state through war divided sovereignty as an apparently unworkable (and “unlivable”) mon­
strous body. Instead of “failing” to match source and target inputs, Hobbes
116 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust From Political Anatomy to Social Pathology 117
achieved his aim by “blending” the closest source approximation with the 8.2 HOBBES’S HERITAGE IN THE ENLIGHTENMENT
target referent of different political powers to explicate in his view that AND AFTER: THE DEMISE OF THE HEAD OF THE BODY
these powers should always be united in one sovereign, at least as far as POLITIC AND THE RADICALISATION OF HEALERSHIP
worldly rulership was concerned: “In the Kingdome of God, there may be
three Persons independent, without breach of unity in God that Reigneth; Despite many fundamental differences to Hobbes’s concept of the “Artifi­
but where men Reigne, that be subject to diversity of opinions, it cannot cial! M an”, Jean Jacques Rousseau’s {1712-1778) re-configuration of the
be so”/® contract-based theory of the state, in his Social Contract of 1762,^° puts
Any competition of political powers within one body politic consti­ similar emphasis on the principle of sovereignty being created through oblig­
tutes, in Hobbes’s view, a fundamental defect and monstrosity that shows ing all citizens to put their person and power “under the supreme direction
the limits of what is politically manageable. Whatever the official nomen­ of the general will”, so that all members “as a body [en corps] receive each
clature and titular terminology may say: “if the King bear the person of member as an indivisible part of the whole”. A s in Leviathan, there is no
the People, and another Assembly bear the person of a Part of the people, systematic anatomy of the body politic {corps politique). Its main organs
they are not one Person, nor one Soveraign, but three Persons, and three are identified as the mindibrain (i.e., the executive power) and the heart
Soveraigns”. The outcome of such competing sovereignty can only be (i.e., the legislative power), and of these it is the latter that matters most:
the dissolution of the political “person” of the “Common-wealth” as an
identifiable body. The mind may be unable to function yet the individual can still be
Hobbes’s supposed “failure” to account for mixed government in terms alive. A man can be mindless and live, but as soon as the heart ceases
of medical imagery is thus not motivated by any insufficiency of the source to work the animal is dead. It is not by its laws that the state subsists
domain vocabulary but by the fact that such conditions reach and possibly but by the legislative power . .. wherever the laws are weakened by age
transcend the limits of political science. Any fundamentally heterogeneous it is a proof that the legislative power has gone, and that the state is
body politic has the status of a chaotic, irregular phenomenon, the very without life.^^
opposite of rational political order. What is beyond the limits of conceiv-
ability is, a fortiori, also beyond the'limits of political government and Rousseau also follows Hobbes in stressing the artificial character of
even redemption. The prudent healer figure that is implicitly omnipresent the body politic without seeing this as a contradiction to the corporeal
in Hobbes’s account (but not depicted in action) would waste his^efforts on im ag ery ,b u t he applies this characterization also to the government: it is
such a monstrous state that was doomed to perish. The only constructive a political “body” on a small scale,^^ contained within the national body
solution for the monstrous body politic lies in its destruction and the con­ politic and created by it artificially, just as the body politic is itself an arti­
stitution of a completely new “Commonwealth”. ficial body,^^ designed to unite the primary social entity, i.e. the “body of
Even such a radical scenario might still be fitted into Sontag’s concept of society” {corps social) , “body of the nation” {corps de la nation)^^ or
“classical” political thought that can foresee and forestall any political ill- “body of the people” {corps du peuple).^^
ness, i.e. as a “worst-case scenario”. Such an interpretation would, however, This emphasis on the people/nation/society as the entity that is consti­
run counter to the main line-of argument and emphasis in Hobbes’s treat­ tuted as a body politic marks Rousseau’s break with the traditional (includ­
ment of Things that weaken or tend to the dissolution o f a commonwealth. ing Hobbes’s) reference to the state as the “target” of 6ody-based political
Hobbes does of course acknowledge that there are manageable and curable imagery. It changes the status of the head or the brain (which was still
illnesses o f the state that can be regulated by the political equivalent of conceivable as being represented by a prince or Jjingl-back-tcrtlrarDf an inte­
rebalancing the humours in the body natural or, in the physio-mechanistic gral part of the body that lives and dies with the rest of the organism: the
paradigm, of restoring a proper blood circulation. However, the chief infir­ ambivalence of the head/king also being the (external) healer o f the body
mities that he identifies—mixed government, fanatical sedition and divided is thus revoked. Whatever and whoever is part of the body politic is part of
sovereignty or power—are compared to diseases that could only conceiv­ the nation and is defined by its function in it. Like a natural human body,
ably be prevented by a miraculously prescient rultr-healer but which are the nation’s body politic “begins to die as soon as it is born”, but through
in fact incurable once the body politic has contracted them. In extreme prudent planning its life can be extended “for the longest time possible by
manifestations, as in the case of a three-way split of political powers, they endowing it with the best constitution that it can have”.^®
transcend the limits of conceivable political illnesses and instead indicate The schema of the life cycle also informs Rousseau’s discussion of ill­
the “Other” of rational politic theory and practice—the monstrous body nesses o f the body politic', when relatively young, nations are amenable to
politic that defies the best efforts of any political healer. reforms, but once any dysfunctional “customs” have become established,
118 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
From Political Anatomy to Social Pathology 119
"the people cannot bear to have the disease treated, like those stupid and This inter-personal, discursive operation of the legislative heart of the
fearful patients who tremble at the sight of the physician’’/^ Even the out­
body politic distinguishes Rousseau’s concepts from the conceptualisa­
break of a serious illness in the body politic can, however, still lead to a
tions of the state as the object of revolutionary therapy that became dom­
recovery as a rebirth: in revolution and “the flames of civil war”, the state
inant in the 1780s and 1790s, even though these were claimed by some
recovers Its youthful strength”.^ This image of revolution as a medical
to be based on his “naturalist” understanding of society and the political
crisis, which can turn either into the death o f the body politic or into its sal­
p r o c e s s .In the context of these revolutionary discourses, the purge of
vation, allows in principle for a healing of the nation’s body, though not on
the body politic became the focus of naturalist imagery, and it is here
account of a restoration by an able healer figure (e.g. in previous accounts,
that we find early uses of the parasite metaphor. According to Abbe Sie-
by the rationally acting prince); rather, it is presented as the product of a
yes (1748-1836), the whole system of feudal privileges formed “parasitic
desperate crisis, which if unchecked can destroy the whole body. Rousseau’s
growths that cannot live except on the sap of plants that they exhaust and
insistence on the real possibility of the catastrophic outcome of a political
deplete”.^®Whilst Sieyes’s analogy was originally drawn from botanical
illness would have met with Hobbes’s approval but the conceptualization
concepts, its parasite-privilege equation was soon combined with corpo­
of a revolution as a possibly salutary crisis certainly would not: Hobbes’s
real bloodsucker and vampire imagery. Its targets were all those linked
head/healer-soverdgn could hardly be expected to endorse his own demise
and bring back the “state of nature”. to the system of privileges, i.e. in the first place the king and queen (who
had been stripped of any head or healer status by way of denunciation
In Rousseau’s system, on the other hand, the healer role is fully externa-
for impotence, sexual illness and perversity) and the nobility, but also
h s e d -it now falls to the political philosopher, whose competence is deter­
the “farmers-general” and tax collectors.^^ During the reign of terror
mined by his capability of conceiving the state properly, i.e. as the nation’s
(1792-94), the parasite stigma for “enemies of the people” implied a de
body. Rousseau criticizes traditional political theorists as being nowhere
facto death sentence. A t the international level, supporters of the Revo­
dose to achieving even this basic task, due to their misguided attempts to
lution, such as Thomas Paine in Britain and Georg Forster in Germany,
divide the sovereign body o f the people: “The sovereign is made into a fan­
borrowed it in order to explain excesses of revolutionary violence and
tastic patchwork: it is as if they had made a man composed of more than
warfare,^° whereas its detractors, such as Edmund Burke, denounced it as
^ e body, one having eyes, another arms, another feet, and nothing else”.^^
“a medicine of the state corrupted into its poison”.^^ In the following cen­
He likens such theories to the feats of Japanese magicians who seem to “dis­
turies, the denunciation of social/political parasites by the Jacobins would
member a child before the audience’s eyes, and then throwing all its limbs serve as a model for condemnations of whole social classes by revolution­
one after another mto the air, . . . bring it down alive again”; similarly, the
aries such as Karl M arx (1818-1883), who depicted the bourgeois bureau­
conjuring tricks of traditional political theory consist in “chopplingl up cracy as a “parasite body” [Parasitenkorper],'^^ and Lenin (1870-1924),
the body social by a sleight of hand worthy of a fairground showman”.« By who portrayed the bourgeois state as a “parasitic organism” that fed on
contrast, a new, properly conceived political science has to (re)conceptualise the people.^® In the Soviet Union, the category of social parasite even
the social-national body as an indivisible natural entity. In doing so Rous- became a legally defined term to designate alleged enemies of socialism/
seau naturalises” not only the concepts of state, society and nation but also communism who had to be isolated and imprisoned or expelled.^*^
political theory itself: it cannot fulfil its task, i.e. help the of the
Having reviewed some of the self-conscious “modern”, even “revolution­
pei^le s body, as long as it does not understand its natural working
ary”, theories of state and politics with regard to i//«ess-imagery, Sontag’s
To understand the functioning of the body social, the political physician
(1978) verdict that it assumes “in modern political_^sco_mse._.^^_punitive
has to focus on the assembly of voters as “a moral and collective body
notion: of the disease not as a punishment b^t'*^ a sign of evil, something
which . . . is endowed with its unity, its common self, its life, and its will.”«
to be punished” seems to be broadly confirmed, even if we have to pre­
n practice, this ideal assembly of the whole body politic has to be enacted
date its emergence to Hobbes’s political pathology (which Sontag had still
by an assembly of deputies who should, however, be considered not so
included in the classical tradition). The emphasis in modern uses is on an
much as the people’s “representatives” but as their “agents”.^^ Rousseau
imminent, fundamental crisis of the whole political-social body, caused by
admits that such agency is difficult to realize in larger nations and he leaves
constitutional deficiencies, poisoning or parasitic organisms, which need to
the solution of this problem to a future work containing the theory of fed-
be treated by a competent healer with ruthless consequence. Although the
eratmn But whatever the formal arrangements, the lawgiving assembly,
imagery of purging, amputation or radical therapy was by no means spe­
as the heart of the body politic, must provide a room for free debate and
cifically “modern”, insofar as we have found it being used in graphic detail
equa voting rights; only in this way, i.e. as the result of a discourse among
equals, does the body politic truly come to life. in medieval and Renaissance texts, it appears to become more predominant
and systematically elaborated.
120 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
We might be tempted to draw a direct link from this imagery to Nazi
rhetoric: the basic scenario of parasite-induced disease and its cure through 9 German Conceptual and Discursive
parasite-elimination would remain the same, but the target referents would
change from the “privileged” estates of the Ancien Regime to the “racial
Traditions of the Body Politic
misfits” of Nazi ideology. Hitler’s adaptation of this scenario in Mein Metaphor
Kam pf as explicated in Chapter 3, would then constitute merely an ideo-
-logically elaborated version, which on account of particularly unfortunate
historical circumstances was given a chance to be implemented in the form
of genocide. However, apart from the general methodological problems
which we have considered {see Chapter 5), it is prima facie improbable that
the Nazis took as their model Hobbes’s or Rousseau’s body politic imagery >
or even the parasite terminology of French revolutionaries, let alone that of
communist ideologues. It is much more plausible that any conceptual and At the beginning of this book we referred to recent debates in Germany
discursive traditions they based their own use on (and which they could rely about the term Volkskdrper (literally, the people's or nation's body), and
on to be understood by their audience) would have been those developed its associations with racist discourse and Nazi jargon. This stigma of a
in German political history. The following chapter will therefore concen­ “Nazi jargon” echo attaches, to be sure, only to the specific expression
trate on body-illness-parasite metaphor use in the development of German Volkskdrper (as well as to further Nazi-characteristic applications of the
political culture, with the twofold aim of explicating its links with the body-nation metaphor such as talk about social groups as parasites or
“common” European heritage of this metaphor complex, as sketched in the vermin) but not to other expressions from that lexical field, let alone the
preceding chapters, and of tracing the crucial development from politico- underlying general conceptual metaphor, which could be paraphrased as A
social to racial definitions of the body politic. political entity is a body. Thus, we can find uses of the body-statelnation
metaphor that are not “tainted” by any Nazi stigma and are used as politi­
cally unproblematic, even neutral ways of referring to political entities, as
in the following examples:

A jury of critics discusses the ten most significant theatre productions


of this season. They speak of the ‘body of the stage’ and the ‘body of
the nation’ [vom "nationalen JCdrper”]—society has become the giant
body that theatre dissects^ (article on unification of East and West Ger­
man theatre cultures).

Around 450 AD Germanic power-centres had become established in


the vast [Roman] Empire. They were effectively ulcers in the body
politic [Staatskorper] of Rome. During the fourth and Wth centuries,
Germanic tribes invaded the Roman Empire.^Soonthey fomied inde­
pendent uncontrollable centres of power—the germs of the Empire’s
dow nfall (article on an exhibition of Germanic cultural artefacts).

In the same way as the body politic [Korper des Staates] needed reform­
ing in the long term, it was necessary to conquer one’s own body natu­
ral, with its many enormous deficiencies^ (characterisation of Friedrich
Schiller’s attitudes).

Unlike the idiomatically fixed English expression body politic, the match­
ing German terminology is thus characterised by a degree of heterogeneity:
122 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust German Conceptual and Discursive Traditions 123
Volkskorper competes with terms such as nationaler Korper (“national/the guilt or emergency demand, irrespective of whether it concerns a pope,
nation’s body”), Staatskorper (“state’s body”) and politischer Korper (“polit­ a bishop or priest—they may threaten or interdict it as much as they
ical body”) and further morphological variants (e.g. “possessive” construc­ like.®
tions of the type Korper + genitive noun phrase such as Korper des Staates).
Whilst the general mapping of the source concept of the body onto the target Luther took up the long-standing conflict between the spiritual and worldly
concept of the “(nation) state” can be assumed to be the same, the qualifying “swords” again, only to resolve it by completely handing over “the indepen­
morphemes, i.e. Volk-, Staat-, national and politisch, respectively, not only dent jurisdictions of the sacerdotium . . . to the secular authorities”.^ His
provide different lexical meaning nuances but, at least in the case of Volk-, reasoning was that all Christians, whatever their social rank, were mem­
also distinct ideological and historical associations. The diachronic analysis bers (“mitglid”) of the same body (“corper”), of which Christ is the only
has to take these various semantic strands into consideration if it wants to head.^ For him, as for previous critics of papal claims to supreme ruler-head
chart the development of the metaphor, or else it would be reduced to giving power, such as William of Ockham and Marsilius of Padua, Christ’s repre­
only the history of an isolated lexical item.'* (This is, of course, not a special­ sentative in the body of the Holy Roman Empire was the emperor, not the
ity of the German language but can be found in other language histories pope.^ Adherents of the pope’s authority over the emperor and other “her­
too; French examples in preceding chapters, for instance, showed variation etics”, in particular Jews as the “enemies of Christ”, were for Luther ill­
between corps de policie, corps politique, corps social.) In the following sec­ nesses on the Christian people’s body, akin to plague and pestilence, which
tions we will therefore look at both the lexical and semantic history of the needed to be eradicated.
metaphor to sketch some of the major developments and turning points of In contrast to the emerging national monarchies that had adopted
the discourse traditions that can be compared to the Nazi use of that meta­ Protestantism, e.g. England, Denmark and Sweden,^^ however, the hope
phor. of resolving the headship for state and church bodies remained elusive in
the “Holy Roman Empire of German Nation”, for the Catholic Habsburg
emperors would not accept the Lutheran re-definition of their role. More­
9.1 THE GERMAN BODY POLITIC, 1500-1806: FROM over, the emperor’s rule was already limited by the empire’s constitution
CHRISTIAN IMPERIAL BODY TO HEADLESS RVMP as an elective monarchy, with relative autonomy of the territorial princes
(as laid down in the “Golden Bull” of T365). The political and religious
During the Middle Ages, philosophers of German origin, such as Albertus compromises that the emperor and the Protestant princes of the empire
Magnus and Nicolas of Cusa had participated in the late Latin traditions entered into after the “Schmalkaldian war” (1546-1547) and in the “Peace
of European political philosophy, including the tradition of conceptual­ of Augsburg” of 1555 showed that neither side could gain supremacy and
ising the relations between spiritual and worldly powers in terms of the that the notion of the empire as a unitary imperial body ruled by a single
body-state metaphor (see Chapters 6, 7). When public debates began to be worldly (let alone, spiritual) head/ruler had become highly problematic.
conducted in the vernacular languages during the Renaissance and Refor­ Assertions of the bodily unity of the empire thus acquired normative
mation, the Latin terminology of corpus mysticum and corpus politicum status. In their supplications to the imperial courts regarding the emper­
was accordingly translated. In Germany it appears to have been Martin or’s infringements of their rights, for instance, Protestant German estates
Luther (1483-1546) who was, among other things, the first to employ regularly invoked the body image to demand that all its parts, including
German corporeal vocabulary to express his vision of a reformed church the emperor, ought to lend each other a hand (“die Hand bieten”) as so
and state, in his “Address to the Christian Nobility of German Nation, closely related members o f one body (“als so nafiewerwandtCGlteder eines
about the reformation of the Christian Estate” [An den christlichen Adel Leibes”).^^ A few years before the outbreak of the Thirty Years War (1618-
deutscher Nation von des christlichen Standes Besserung, 1520).^ On the 1648), Christian Werner Friedtlieb, in his book Prudentia Politica Chris­
basis of St. Paul’s and St. Peter’s Epistles (whose translation into German tiana, based the ideal Christian state on the body-state mapping, stressing
he published two years later), Luther emphasized a Christian ruler’s duty the usefulness of the metaphoric model as a means of popularising political
to exercise his power in the worldly realm without interference from the theory:
church authorities:
Just as the excellent and famous old philosopher Aristotle likens man
for worldly government has become a member of the Christian body, to the world and calls him a small 'world, so we can compare a good
. . . its work shall be carried out freely and without hindrance in all Christian Commonwealth to a human body and its main members,
members of the whole body, to punish or to prosecute people, as far as and that is the best way to explain it to the common man or layman.^^
124 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust German Conceptual and Discursive Traditions 125
Friedtlieb places the emphasis in his body description on a well-ordered, to this day. Hofmann (1976b), for instance, attacks Pufendorf for alleg­
harmonious state under one prince and regent (“just as any human body edly not being able to grasp the “living imperial organism” {lebendiger
has only one head, which holds the brain, the seat of the mind and the eyes, Reichsorganismus) inherited from the Middle Ages,^^ whereas Schilling
which see everything”), in which all limbs are content to fulfil their pre-or­ (1994) relates the monstrosity verdict to the inflexibility of the consti­
dained function.^'^ Other publications using body imagery in the early seven­ tutional arrangements in the empire that preserved medieval structures
teenth century include Paul Negelein’s Vom Burgerlichen Stand (1616) and when confronted with the necessity of rapid modernisation.” Berschin
Georg Engelhard Lohneyss’s Aulico Politica (1622), which concentrated on (2002), on the other hand, argues that the “monstro simile” formula was
the eye. With reference to King Salomon’s wisdom, Lohneyss compared the only meant to stress the singularity of the Reich as fulfilment of the bib­
all-seeing eye, the “finest and noblest part of the body”, to state author­ lical “Fourth Eschatological Empire”, which had been predicted in the
ity (“Obrigkeit”), while the subject (“Unterthan”) was represented by the vision of Daniel and was unlike the preceding,empires; he therefore reads
receptive ear.'^^ In Daniel Casper von Lohenstein’s patriotic novel Gross- the empire-monster comparison as a mere resemblance between the state
miithiger Feldherr Arminius (1689), eyes and ears both belonged to the and a fabulous creature (“Fabelwesen”).”
prince, informing him of future developments and dangers so that his heart However, whether it was seen as monstrous in the senses of an ill-shaped
could make the right decisions.^^ The moralising novels and rhetorical trea­ and doomed body or as a fabulous creature^ the Holy Roman Empire
tises of Christian Weise (1642-1708) thematised political illnesses at court continued to exist and to be referred to as a “state body” [Staatskorper]
as well as their treatment by competent doctors and warn against politi­ throughout the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. In the wars between
cal quacks [Quacksalber). By the end of the century, the metaphor was Prussia and Austria under the Habsburg dynasty, for instance, the fic­
so commonplace that Stieler’s dictionary of 1691 included the synonyms tion of the imperial body and head was used by the Frederick II of Prussia
Staatskorper and Staatsleib.'^^ to gain propagandistic advantage. Eager to justify his military offensive
The most famous (to some, infamous) seventeenth-century German against Austria in the Second Silesian War (1744-45), Frederick presented
application of the body-state metaphor, however, was Samuel von Pufen- his own actions as the altruistic defence of the then head of the empire,
dorf’s comparison of the empire in its state after the Thirty Years War as a the Bavarian Emperor Charles VII, after the latter’s defeat by the Aus­
monstrous body in his treatise “On the State of the German Empire” [De trian army: “neither I nor any other Prince in the Empire would ever toler­
Statu Imperii Germanici), which he published in Latin in 1667 (German ate an attack on the head of the German body politic [das H a u p t. . . des
and French translations in 1669): teutschen Staatskorpers]”.^^ From Frederick’s point of view, his own attack
on Austria was only one body member doing its duty to preserve the head
There is now nothing left for us to say, but that Germany is an Irregu­ (which did not hinder him from attacking Austria again later, despite the
lar Body, and like some mis-shapen Monster [irregulare aliquod corpus Habsburgs having regained head-empeior status in the meantime).
et monstro simile] if . . . it be measured by the common Rules of Poli­ When the German (“Holy Roman”) Empire finally collapsed in the wake
ticks and Civil Prudence, and that nothing similar to it, in my opinion, of repeated military defeats at the hands of Napoleon’s French Empire,
exists anywhere else on the whole globe. the last emperor, Francis II, declared his status and obligations as Head of
the empire [reichsoberhauptliche A m t und Wiirde) as null and void.^^ He
In Pufendorf’s view, the empire was no longer one coherent, centralised accused those smaller West German states that had formed the “Rhenish
national state nor was it (yet) a confederation of independent states. The Confederation” [Rheinbund] under French protection of having broken the
emperor was head o f state but could not interfere in the other body mem­ bonds that had once united the Siijafs^orper.iirtheir-owirdectaration of
bers’ internal affairs; they in turn were obliged in principle to come to the secession, the Rheinbund confederates had4ndeed stated that the empire
head’s assistance when it called for help but in fact they had the power to as one body was effectively dissolved. They explained that the preceding
enter allegiances and even engage in war against that same head o f state. wars, all of which had been won by their new protector, Napoleon, had
This fundamental “irregularity” in the Empire’s constitution caused “an demonstrated this “truth” so clearly that there was no point in prolonging
inextricable and incurable Disease”, for “whilst the Emperon [was] alwaies the agony:
labouring to reduce it to the condition of a Regular Empire, Kingdom,
or Monarchy . .. the States on the other side [were] restlesly acquiring to The past three wars, which have disturbed Germany almost without
themselves a full and perfect Liberty”. interruption, have exposed the tragic truth that the bond that was sup­
Pufendorf’s critical analysis of the empire, which scandalised contem­ posed to unite the different members of the German body politic [Glie-
porary political debate in Germany,^^ continues to exercise historians der des deutschen Staatskorpers] was no longer sufficient or, rather.
126 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust German Conceptual and Discursive Traditions 127
was indeed already broken-----It was futile to look for Germany any­ Gottfried Herder (1744-1803) put forward the idea of “a physiology of the
where in the body of the Empire [Reichskorper].^^ whole national body [Physiologie des ganzen NationalkorpersT' instead
of the outdated descriptions of the medieval Holy Roman Empire that
The abdication of Francis II provided a kind of death certificate for the body dealt mostly with the “pathology of the head, i.e. the Emperor and some
politic of the “Holy Roman Empire”, which has entered German public mem- Estates”.^^
ory.2® At the 200th anniversary of its demise in 2006, the magazine Der Spie­ Herder developed and established an interest in all nations—and their
gel quoted the nostalgic interpretation of the imperial abdication by Goethe’s languages and cultures—as organic wholes and, consequently, in their
mother in a letter to her son: “it felt as if you have received a message that physiological explanation. As Isaiah Berlin (1976) has pointed out, there
an old friend who the doctors had already given up on has finally died: you was “no Pavoritvolk" for Herder; his “use of ‘organic’ and ‘organism’ [was]
know he was dying but you are still shaken by the news of his death”.^^' still wholly metaphorical and not, as in later, more metaphysical thinkers,
only half metaphorical”.” However, it was also Herder who first described
the Jews as a parasitical plant or growth on other nations:
9.2 COSMOPOLITAN VS. NATIONALIST
CONCEPTS OF THE BODY POLITIC IN THE God’s own people who were once given their fatherland as a divine
GERMAN ENLIGHTENMENT AND AFTER present have been, almost since their inception, a parasitic plant on
the stems of other nations [eine parasitische Pflanze auf den Stdmmen
Whilst the term Reichskbrper lost its specific topical relevance with the anderer Nationen].^*
j ! Holy Roman Empire’s” dissolution, the more general term Staatskorper
seems to have become the main lexicalised expression for the abstract con­ When comparing such a formulation with later anti-Semitic texts, it is
cept of the state as a body since the end of the seventeenth century. We important to bear in mind that Herder did not connect the parasite plant
thus find Staatskorper in the writings of the philosopher Immanuel Kant with the idea of a human or animal body: the host of the “Jewish parasite”,
(1724-1804) and the poet and publicist Christoph Martin Wieland (1733- as he saw it, was another plant, e.g. a tree. The source domain for the
1813), not just as descriptive terms for any form of state but in the context parasite image was still botany (as in the case of Sieyes’s accusation against
of enlightened designs for world peace and a cosmopolitan culture: the privileged classes),” not human physiology. It would therefore be mis­
leading, as well as anachronistic, to'blame Herder for later versions of the
Finally war becomes . . . such an uncertain . . . and disturbing enter­ body-parasite scenario.
prise for all states that they . . . make preparations for a future great Soon, however, the combination of the metaphor of the nation’s body
united state body [einem kiinftigen grofien Staatskorper]. Even though and the scenario of a parasite-induced illness was to become a more potent
at the moment such a state body exists only as a blueprint, a feeling of and dangerous conceptual mixture in the context of “naturalized” con­
concern for the preservation of the whole [Erhaltung des Ganzen] is cepts of society and history. The new term Volkskorper began to replace
stirring in its members [in alien Gliedern].^^ Nationalkorper, emphasizing the physical presence of the people.^'^ Once
the parasite concept was remapped into the source frame of human physi­
It is in the interest of humanity and every single nation, every single ology, the focus shifted to the parasite’s allegedly destructive, poisonous
state body and every individual human being that as many of such trea­ effect on the host, as statements from the middle of the nineteenth century
tises [on the knowledge of humanity] as possible are being deposited in onwards show. In the run-up to the revolutioi^of- 184S^he-naHonalistic
the inventory of general knowledge.^* publicist Ernst Moritz Arndt (1769-1860) depicted “Jews and their fellows-
in-arms” as working incessantly “towards the decomposition and destruc­
Kant and Wieland both used Staatskorper as denoting the generic, abstract tion [Zersetzung und Auflosung] of . . . the love for the fatherland and the
form of a state; the bodily source aspect played little if any role in their fear of God”.” The Prussian court preacher Adolf Stocker (1835-1909)
conceptualisations of existing or ideal states. At about the same time when denounced "modern Jewry” as an “alien drop of blood in our national
they formulated their utopias of an enlightened global state and culture, body [ein fremder Blutstropfen in unserem Volkskorper] . . . a destruc­
however, a radically new interpretation of the political body metaphor tive, wholly destructive force”.^®In his 1881 book On the Jewish Question,
was introduced in German thought that would prove to be historically Eugen Karl Diihring (1833-1921) declared that “the Jew comes into his
more influential—and more ambivalent: the idea of the nation as an ethnic own” when he can “act as a parasite in an existing or impending process
body. Building on Rousseau’s concept of a "national physiology” Johann of corruption”. He concluded that “wherever [the Jew] has made his home

I
128 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust German Conceptual and Discursive Traditions 129
in the nations’ flesh [im Fleische der Yolker], one needs to looks closely “revival” of Hobbes’s political theory with regard to Nazi politics, which
whether it is still healthy”.^^ Strauss and Schmitt had begun. What was it that made two obscure mon­
Towards the end of the nineteenth century, uses of the body metaphor ster symbols from the book of Job, in their Hobbesian version, attractive
in German political discourse were increasingly informed by an ethnicised for analyses of Nazi Germany?
notion of the body politic as a Volkskdrper that had to guard itself against In his 1936 book, Leo Strauss discussed the corporeal imagery of Levia­
alien bodies from both inside and outside. In 1918, then, the diagnosis o f a than in the context of his argument that, contrary to traditional assess­
life-threatening crisis o f national health caused by parasites seemed to be ments, “the real basis of [Hobbes’s] political philosophy [was] not modern
confirmed by the “evidence” of Imperial Germany’s defeat. But how could science”, but was instead a strong “moral basis” deriving from his human­
this largely theoretical metaphor tradition be linked to concrete, suggestive ist roots, which was partly obscured in the famous treatise of 1651.^°
scenarios, such as those in Hitler’s Mein Kampf which were to incite its This conclusion is important to our discussion not so much as an exegetical
genocidal implementation? In the following section we shall analyse the hypothesis, but insofar as it is based on Strauss’s reading of the body-state
attempt by Carl Schmitt to provide a theoretically “respectable” reading of allegory: the main tertium comparationis between Leviathan and the State
the body-politic tradition to fit the requirements of the “total state” under was, according to Strauss, not “mighty power as such . . . but the mighty
H itle r ,a s well as counter-readings of that tradition by emigrants from power which subdues the proud”.^^ Later in his book, Strauss built an intri­
Nazi Germany. cate argument about the apparent lack of the traditional head = sovereign
analogy in Hobbes’s body politic concept:^^ “The holder of the sovereign
power is not the ‘head’, that is the capacity to deliberate and plan, but the
9.3 HOBBES REVISITED: THE BODIES OF ‘soul’, that is the capacity to command, in the State.”^^ He regarded this
LEVIATHAN AND BEHEMOTH AS CONCEPTUAL distinction as indicative of Hobbes’s “break with rationalism”, which fore­
MODELS OF THE “THIRD REICH” shadowed “Rousseau’s theory that the origin and seat of sovereignty is la
volonte generale”.^'^ Later Strauss retracted the assessment of Hobbes “as
In 1936 and 1938, two reassessments of Hobbes’s theory of the state-as-a- the originator of modern political philosophy”, for which the distinction
body by German political theorists appeared, both written with view to an .between the sovereign = head v. sovereign =soul analogies was supposed to
application to the contemporary existence of a “total” political system, i.e. be evidence,but his reading became important for the strongly metaphor-
Nazi Germany. The earlier book, which gave a general account of the Polit­ and symbol-focused interpretation in Carl Schmitt’s 1938 book. We need
ical Philosophy o f Hobbes: Its Basis and Genesis, was authored by Leo to look briefly at the link between the two thinkers’ biographies in order to
' Strauss (1899-1973), at that time a refugee from Nazi Germany in Britain.**^ gauge the seemingly paradoxical common interest in Hobbes’s Leviathan,
The latter, under the programmatic title The Leviathan in the State Theory shared by an emigrant from Nazi Germany on the one hand and its “crown
o f Thomas Hobbes: Meaning and Failure o f a Political Symbol (Der Levia­ jurist” on the other, a connection that has exercised Strauss’s and Schmitt’s
than in der Staatslehre des Thomas Hobbes: Sinn und Fehlschlag eines disciples and opponents to this day.^^
politischen SymbolsY^ was published by Carl Schmitt (1888-1985), profes­ Strauss’s research on Hobbes, which resulted in his 1936 book, was
sor of law in Berlin and a member of the Nazi party, who, on account of his based on a project that had been co-refereed in 1932 by Schmitt (together
contribution to the constitutional dismantling of the Weimar Republic and with Strauss’s PhD supervisor, and later fellow emigrant, the philosopher
his subsequent praise of Hitler’s dictatorship, has been dubbed the “crown Ernst Cassirer, 1874-1945) for a grant from th^RGGkefellerFotmdation.^^
jurist” of the “Third Reich”.'*^ It was this grant that allowed Strauss to liv6 and work outside Germany
Four years later, with the Second World War raging, another emigrant, from 1932 onwards, first in France and then in Britain, and to prepare
Franz Neumann (1900-1954), published a sociological analysis of Nazi the/publication of the 1936 book.^® Strauss, for his part, had written a
Germany under the title Behemoth, the other monster besides Leviathan detailed review of Schmitt’s seminal treatise “The Concept of the Politi­
mentioned in the book of Job, whose name Hobbes had used'as a title for cal” (Der Begriff des Politischen), first published in 1927 and reissued
his account of the English Civil War, Behemoth, or the Long Parliament. in revised form in 1932. In this treatise, Schmitt set out to redefine the
Like Leviathan, but operating on land rather than a't sea (“it eats grass like political sphere “in its own right” on the basis of the distinction of friend
an ox”)'*^, the Behemoth is of super-human strength'*^ and he, too, is used to and foe, in opposition to liberal political theory that defined politics indi­
demonstrate the absolute superiority of God’s power over man.'’^ Neumann rectly and derived it from social categ o ries.T h e friend-foe relationship
explicitly referred to Hobbes’s use of the Behemoth imagery of terrifying does not necessarily include hatred or hostility,^® but always implies that
destructive power in the preface to his 1942 book,‘^^ thus continuing the the foe is “in a particularly intensive sense an existentially other and
130 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
German Conceptual and Discursive Traditions 131
stranger”, so that the conflict with him is not soluble or reconcilable by
liquidation of the “Rohm-Putsch”^^ and praised the 1935 Nuremberg race
recourse to shared norms or to an impartial arbiter.^' Schmitt connected
laws as advancing a “constitution of liberty”. A t the zenith of his career,
this fundamental conflict with Hobbes’s theory of the “state of nature”
in 1936, acting as a Prussian “State councillor” and leader of the university
where “every one is at war with every one else”,^^ in order to be able to
section of the National Socialist lawyers’ federation, Schmitt organised a
invoke Hobbes as a witness against what he saw as the “facile optimism”
conference on Jewry in the Study of Law” in Berlin. The meeting took its
of both the revolutionary-utopian and the liberal definitions of politics
motto from Hitler’s statement that the fight “against the Jew” was “doing
_Agamst this optimistic bias, Schmitt set a “realistic” pessimistic view of the Lord’s work”.^^
humanity that took the possibility of war into account and he insisted on
However, Schmitt’s seemingly impeccable Nazi credentials proved to
the interdependence of protection and obedience as the source of all sov­
be dubious, after all. Since 1933, emigrants, such as Schmitt’s former dis­
ereignty. Viewed from this perspective, the history of political thought
ciple Waldemar Gurian, had attacked and exposed him as an opportunist
smce the enlightenment was—with few exceptions^**—one of continuous
who before 1933 had supported parts of the anti-Weimar political right
neutralization” and “de-politicization”, an erosion of the political to the
advantage of the social.^^ other than the National Socialists.These attacks provided ammunition to
Schmitt’s rivals in the Nazi legal establishment and in the SS. They saw in
In his review, Strauss explicitly acknowledged the importance of
him not just a less-than-fully committed “fellow-traveller” but a potentially
Schmitt’s critique of liberalism for an “appropriate understanding of
dangerous conservative double-dealer who might change sides again.^^
Hobbes this latter task was for him a pre-condition to gaining a “per­
Shortly after the seeming triumph of the 1936 Berlin conference, the SS
spective beyond liberalism”.^^ So far, both thinkers seem to have been in
organ The Black Corps (“Das schwarze Korps”) denounced Schmitt; this
agreement; however, there was a fundamental difference in their aims of
and pressure from the head of the Sicherheitsdienst (SD), Reinhard Hey-
using Hobbes’s theories. Whereas Strauss hoped to recover the “human­
drich (1904-1942) were sufficient to force his resignation from all offices
istic” aspects of Hobbes’s system in order to reach beyond liberalism
within party-affiliated legal institutions.^® Behind-the-scenes protection
Schmitt aimed to re-found political theory on the friend-foe distinction
from other Nazi leaders such as justice minister Hans Frank (1900-1946)
and reclaim” Hobbes for such a stance. Schmitt had based his reading of
and Hermann Goring (1893-1946) saved him from further persecution: he
. Hobbes s concept of war as a fundamental political category on the idea
could remain a National Socialist party member and Prussian state coun­
of a nation-state asserting its identity by distinguishing friend and foe;
cillor and kept his chair at the University of Berlin but played no further
the foe could be another state, or a section of the community, or an indi­ active role in shaping Nazi legal policy.^^
vidual. Strauss, however, highlighted the fact that Hobbes’s definition of
It was in this situation, i.e. after having been sidelined and under pres­
war was first and foremost that of a condition holding between individu­
sure to prove his Nazi credentials, that Schmitt published the Leviathan
als. Hobbes’s own conclusion was, according to Strauss, the opposite to
book. Immediately in the first paragraph of the introduction, he announced
the one drawn by Schmitt: “the characterization of the state of nature as
his interest in the concept of “Leviathan” as something “more than just
the war of everyone against everyone is meant to motivate the relinquish-
an illustration of a thought or a comparison”; instead, he invoked it as
ment of the state of nature”,®^ i.e. not to perpetuate it as the basis of the
political, as Schmitt would have it. “a mythic symbol”. H i s first chapter recounted parts of the conceptual
history of the symbol before its use by Hobbes, with special emphasis on
Despite this difference, Strauss’s recognition of Schmitt as the pioneer
Christian and Jewish theological interpretations in the Middle Ages.®*
of a critique of liberalism that would prepare the ground for a redefinition
According to Schmitt, the “Jewish-cabbalistic”jxadition-viewecH:eviathan
of pohti^cal theory^s was sufficient for Schmitt to write a positive Rocke-
and Behemoth as representing the gentile peoples (which could be sepa­
M e r reference.65 However, by the time Schmitt published his own book on
rated in sea- and land-based powers); he then linked this tradition with the
Hobbes s Leviathan, any understanding that had existed between the two
Talmudic story that the flesh of the Leviathan would serve as a dish at a
thinkers before 1933 had become, at best, a “hidden dialogue”.^®Whilst
feast for the “just” (Jews) in paradise,®^ in order to demonstrate “the totally
Strauss went into academic and political exile to Britain and then to the
singular, incomparable .. . and abnormal situation and attitude of the Jew­
United States, Schmitt experienced the highs and the lows of ansacademic ish people to all other nations”:®®
and (temporarily) public career in Nazi Germany.^* Following the acces­
sion of Hitler to the Reic/^s-chancellorship at the end of January 1933 he
The Jews stand and watch how the nations of the earth kill each other;
immediately supported in articles the "purge” of Jewish academics,’the
and for them this mutual “ritual killing and slaughtering” is lawful and
empowerment” law and the "right” of the Nazi revolution.^^ He became
“kosher”. For this reason, they eat the flesh of the slaughtered nations
a member of the NSDAP, hailed the Fuhrer^s “defence of the right” in the and live from it.®**
132 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust German Conceptual and Discursive Traditions 133
From the start, Schmitt’s associations showed a radically anti-Semitic bent: king, the nobility and the protestant church from within”.’^ The Prussian
Behemoth and Leviathan, as politico-theological symbols, were supposed State-Leviathan, which was still “full of life”, was “castrated” by “Stahl-
to be “Jewish myths of combat, of the highest order”.®^ Arbitrarily, Hebrew Jolson”.’^ Following on after this main “breach” of Hobbes’s “authentic”
and Jewish(-German) literary traditions®^ were reinterpreted to fit a conclu­ idea of the state, a host of Jewish intellectuals (i.e. the Rothschilds, etc., see
sion that could have sprung from the pages of Mein Kampf, i.e. a projection earlier) “[broke] into the European nations”; each one occupied a “zone of
of the “reconstructed” Jewish myth “onto the allegedly real influence of operation in the economy, in journalism, in the arts and in the sciences”.’®
Jews on the history of the Christian peoples”.®^ Following this expository The institutions of individual freedom that these “liberals” created were
depiction of the Leviathan story as a Jewish “combat myth”, Schmitt asked the “knives with which anti-individualistic powers cut up the body of the
what bearing Hobbes’s choice of the Leviathan as a symbol of pure state Leviathan and divided his flesh between them. Thus, the mortal God died
power had on the distinction of friend versus /be.®® The answer was only a second death”.” In his denunciation of the supposed liberal-Jewish plot
partially positive: Hobbes succeeded in defining the contemporary Roman to castrate, kill and devour the state-Leviathan, Schmitt provided a high­
papacy as the foe of an ideal “Commonwealth” that would unite state and brow version of Nazi-typical historiographies of “the Jew” as the decom­
church; his use of the Leviathan symbol, however, had made that very the­ posing agent in European culture. There were no explicit endorsements of
ory vulnerable to a “Judeo-Christian” separation of political sovereignty Nazi policy in Schmitt’s Leviathan, but his consistent use of scenarios of
and religion by the “Jewish thinker” Baruch de Spinoza.®’ decomposition and parasitic destruction as the subtext for his conceptual
This alleged vulnerability of Hobbes’s theory to a Jewish symbol tradi­ history strongly resembled Hitler’s scenario of an illness o f the body politic
tion, of which Spinoza represents the beginning, has no basis in the text of caused by “the Jew” that necessitated a radical therapy. It also fitted into
the 1651 Leviathan.^^ For Schmitt, however, it was the key to the history of Schmitt’s professed admiration of Hitler’s Fiihrer-competence on account
a gradual “de-construction” of the theory of the state at the hands of “Jew­ of his proven ability “to distinguish who is friend and who is foe”.^°®
ish thinkers”: Spinoza, Moses Mendelssohn, Friedrich Julius Stahl (whom In his theory of the homo sacer, which is informed by a detailed cri­
Schmitt insisted on calling Stahl-Jolson),’^ and a group of further suspects tique of Schmitt, Giorgio Agamben has shown that the sovereign’s power
united supposedly by their Jewishness: “the young Rothschilds, Karl Marx, to stigmatize a subject as a homo sacer, i.e. as someone “who may be killed
Borne, Heine, Meyerbeer and many others”.’^ Hobbes’s Leviathan imagery but not sacrificed”, is even “more original”, more basic “than the Schmit-
was thus supposedly “revealed” by Schmitt as an unfortunate choice of tian opposition between friend and enemy, fellow citizen and foreigner”.^®*
symbol that made the unitary concept of the state the victim of subversive This stigmatizing and destructive use of power to deprive subjects of all
“Jewish thought”.’® rights, was, needless to say, characteristic of Nazi Germany: its victims
The anti-Semitic bias—and, significantly, its expression in terms of were no mere “foes” in the sense of strangers or “honourable” adversaries
the pathological bio-imagery of decomposition—is the only aspect that (as Schmitt would pretend) but instead “bare”, dispensable life that could
provides a modicum of coherence for Schmitt’s selective history of state- be extinguished without guilt, life “that did not deserve to live” {lebensun-
as-Leviathan theories. Spinoza’s relation to Hobbes, for instance, was wertes Leben).^°^
not analysed in any detail but just presented as the story of the “Jewish Agamben criticizes Schmitt not so much for being too radical or cyni­
thinker” taking advantage of a vulnerable point in Hobbes’s theory, i.e. the cal but for not being radical enough in conceptualising the structure and
difference between a subject’s inner commitment and outward obeisance effects of unrestricted state power. Unlike the “heroic” Schmittian sover­
to the sovereign, and bringing this “germ” of decomposition to full frui­ eign who defined friend and foe to assert his own id ^ it y J n j h e ensu­
tion until, in contrast to Hobbes’s supposedly “authentic” idea, the state/ ing fight, Agamben’s sovereign (as well as ^'Kat of Hobbes in Agamben’s
Leviathan has been destroyed, “deprived of his soul from within”.’**In the reading)^®® is defined by his self-decreed fight to declare a total ban on
eighteenth centufy, Moses Mendelssohn, though allegedly a “much inferior the homo sacer that allows him “to kill without comrpitting homicide and
intellect” compared to Spinoza, “instinctively” continued his destructive vyithout celebrating a sacrifice”.^®**As a consequence, Agamben gives a fur­
work by widening the gap between religious belief and state sovereignty, ther twist to the interpretation of the figure in the frontispiece of Leviathan:
so as “to undermine and hollow out the state’s power and to strengthen his the “Common-wealth’s” artificial body politic that is formed of the “bare
own [Jewish] people’s status”.” The coup de grace for the concept of the life” of individual persons signifies nothing but “the absolute capacity of
state was delivered, according to Schmitt, by the nineteenth-century politi­ the subjects’ bodies to be killed”.®°’ The utterly defenceless existence of the
cal theorist Julius Friedrich Stahl. He “alienated” subjects and sovereigns prisoner in a Nazi concentration or extermination camp is the manifesta­
through his theory of “constitutional monarchy” and, in particular, “con­ tion of this “new political body”, and this concept is complemented by that
fused” and “paralysed spiritually” the “inner core of the Prussian State, the of the Fiihrer, who, unlike princes, kings and emperors of old, is “neither
134 M.etaphof, Nation and Holocaust
German Conceptual and Discursive Traditions 135
private nor public and whose life is in itself supremely political” and is monstrous body politic that was beyond the control of even the most pru­
m fact identified with the very biological life of the German people” dent political healers}^'^
The Fuhrer represents the new unity of body politic and race/nation and is In its “revival” after almost three centuries at the time of the Nazi dicta­
therefore perfectly entitled to those meta-constitutional powers that Hitler torship, this political monster scenario was open to contradictory readings.
did, in fact, assume: immediate executive, legislative and judicial command Leo Strauss, in some way pre-figuring Susan Sontag’s stance, put the main
without recourse to mediating procedures or institutions. The Fiihrer's emphasis- on the cautionary lesson for rational politics. From this perspec­
_identihcation of agents o f illness, parasites or alien bodies, which we find tive, Hobbes’s depiction of incurable diseases of the body politic was meant
m M em Kampf instantaneously transformed their bearers into “bare life” to warn rulers and their advisors never to, let the'state’s health deteriorate
that had to be eliminated if the nation’s body was to survive.
that far: instead, at the first recognition of any symptoms, they had to
/r monster that “makes the deep to boil like a pot” combat the illness by all means available to the Leviathan-state. Strauss
{Job 41:31) provided the central point of reference for Schmitt’s attempts claimed this “humanistic” Hobbes for the project of a new political theory
to vindicate his anti-liberal and anti-Semitic reading of Hobbes, the second that would empower a rational state order to go beyond the mere mediation
mythical fi^ re that Hobbes borrowed from the Bible, Behemoth, was the of different socio-economic interests, as envisaged by classical liberalism.
symbol of Nazi Germany as viewed by the emigrant lawyer and sociolo­ Schmitt’s interpretation, on the other hand, was informed by a markedly
gist Franz L. Neumann; “a non-state, a chaos, a rule of lawlessness and different, “anti-liberal” vision: he admired Hobbes’s Leviathan for its unity
anarchy, which has swallowed’ the rights and dignity of man, and is out to and strength, which needed to be reasserted against the efforts to divide,
transform the world into a chaos”.^07 Neumann was well aware of Schmitt’s weaken and castrate it that had allegedly been perpetrated by generations
writings, but insisted that the “National Socialist state [was] no Levia­ of “Jewish thinkers”. Schmitt abandoned the traditional source domain of
than in Hobbes’s sense, for his “Leviathan, although it swallows society human physiology for the body politic imagery and concentrated on the
does not swallow all of it”.^<’^ In Hobbes’s vision, the power of the sover­ unity o f the animal body of the Leviathan. In doing so, he surrendered the
eign was enormous but was still “merely a part of the bargain in which last vestiges of a humanistic vision of the body politic. In the end, however,
the sovereign has to fulfil his obligations, that is preserve order and secu- it was his own forced “re-construction” of the Leviathan against the sup­
rity. . . . If the sovereign cannot fulfil his side of the bargain he forfeits his posed Jewish conspiracy, not Hobbes’s original one, that “failed to restore
sovereignty. In comparison with such a rational, if pessimistic, concept the natural unity of the state”."^ Lastly, Neumann, in order to achieve a
of the state as a Leviathan, National Socialism was wholly unprincipled- its similar effect from the opposite. Nazi-critical perspective, chose the sym­
coMections with traditional ideologies were “mere arcana dominationis bol of Behemoth to denounce the destructive strength of National Social­
techniques of domination”^!’ that could be discarded if they became incon­ ism. For him, the monstrous aspect of the Nazi body, as personified in the
venient. As evidence, Neumann pointed to the unrestricted power of the Fuhrer, lay in the utter lack of any constructive vision of politics: for the
FM^rer as the personification of Germany’s national body, which destroyed same reason, the Nazi-Behemoth, though formidable, was doomed to per­
even the last vestiges of a rational form of state: Nazi Germany’s power ish eventually.
rested solely “in the Leader, who [was] not the organ of the state but . . . These opposing re-applications of Hobbes’s body-state' metaphor to
t e community, not acting as its organ but as its personification”."^ The Nazi Germany are of course not representative of any popular conceptu­
FuFrer-embodied Nazi state, as Behemoth, had no further purpose than alisations among the German public at the time: Strauss’s and Neumann’s
acting out Its own destructive power; in terms of body politic imagery analyses were restricted to a reception in acadejnically orientated-emigrant
the only remaining quality it had was its sheer terror-inspiring strength. circles and political scientists; Schmitt’s laboured re-appropriation of Hob­
The emergence of competing reinterpretations of Hobbes’s monster bes was not even attractive to the Nazi elites that it was meant to placate.
symbols for the body politic in the historical context of National Socialist The references to the arcane biblical monsters Leviathan and Behemoth
rule in Germany was no accident. Hobbes’s theory of the “war of every­ were esoteric and. speculative and their i?ody-metaphorical characterisa­
one a p in st everyone” as the (negative) motivation for men to surrender tion remained highly abstract: all that was left of their “nature” was sheer
their natural ’ freedom to a protector-sovereign was an important point strength or force, which was viewed by Schmitt with nostalgic fascina­
of reference for any analysis of dictatorship, and its combination with bib­ tion, by Neumann with horror, and in Strauss “humanistic” interpretation
lical symbolism and body politic imagery provided a conceptual space of was being relativised as much as philologically possible. Nevertheless, in
enormous historical, literary and political depth. It had enabled Hobbes their focus on the dehumanised Fiihrer-state the three opposing readings
to explore the boundaries of conceivable political theory by constructing “shared” an interest in redefining the nature of the body politic that was
imaginative notions of the absolute Other of rational political order- the uncannily topical in the context of a regime that specialised in defining its
136 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust
foes and reducing them to bare, i.e. destroyable, life. And by linking or at
east referencing their interpretations to Hobbes’s version of the h o ly poli- 10 Conclusion
d is m u T ^ T ’ temporal and concepmal
distance between the seventeenth century and their own historical con- Metaphor in Discourse History
text, a connection could be made between the corporeal theories of Euro-
ideology of a new
National s t k t e ’' by the
Their acknowledgment of such a link between the past and contemno-
mry metaphor scenarios did not entail a material endorsement of its target
meaning as envisaged by the Nazis—on the contrary! For Strauss and Nra-
mann, the Nazi version of body imagery was a manifestation of the mon-
strous state-feody which Hobhes had warned against. Even Schmittfeh The body-state metaphor and its illness and parasite scenarios have been
unable to declare the idea of a unitary, all-powerful “total” state an unmiti­ declared “dead”, “moribund” or at least deserving to be extinct in several
gated success; in fact, he called it a “failure” but tried to shift the blame for schools of conceptual history. Its anti-Semitic associations have made it
1 fe’’ h u m r ' “bare suspect on account of the memory of its use by the Nazis.^ Its semantic
life humans escaped him; instead, he harked back to the romanticised coherence has been seen as being weakened in the modern era due to the
notion of a heroic confrontation with an honourable foe demise of the humoral source knowledge system and its replacement by
of the “total’’ s ? 7 ' m e t a p h o r for the theory new, mechanically orientated scientific paradigms.^ Some historians have
of the total state was, of course, in addition to its racist bias, also flawed claimed that body-state imagery was developed from a semantically flex­
as a historical account, due of the uncritical assumption of an immanent ible metaphor complex to an institutional and scientific (especially, socio­
eaae^nThTf metaphor’s history (i.e. its supposed Jewish-cabbalistic bag- logical) terminology during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.^ In this
ft ^ Levtathan symbol). This bias is so transparent thft view, the metaphor has lost most of its iconicity and suffered what Croft
may b^e easily avoided today, but the damage it did to Schmitt’s con- and Cruise (2004) have called a “semantic drift” to a point where it is "no
“S r h assumption of immanence in the different from a literal expression, and only etymologists and historians of
life history of conceptual metaphors. An alternative reification could for language can recreate the path of derivation”.**
I ^ 'b e notion that political body-parasite-therapy scenarios Such “obituaries” of the metaphor have concentrated on changes to
N r z f H d o l u s r s h“ ’’iustification”, as demonstrated in the its corporeal-medical source-level aspects. By comparison, target-related
Nazi Holocaust. Such a perspective would just exchange one flawed teleol- criticisms on account of changes in state and society are rare but can also
ogy of the metaphor’s semantic drift for another. The concluding chapter b?en found. In 1987, the German writer and critic Hans-Magnus Enzens-
™ll discuss the implications of our findings for the prospect of a non-tele- berger provided an example of target-related criticism of the metaphor
ological perspective in discourse history. when he declared the body-state metaphor “dead” because it assumed
the existence of an identifiable head/brain (= central control organ) of the
state, which no longer applied to modern politics.^ Among the^uthors we
have cited earlier, Susan Sontag did acknowle^e^and'anatyse fKTpromi-
nence of the body politic metaphor’s illness ejttensions in the modern era
but assumed a kind of ethical decline after the seventeenth century. Her
hypothesis that since then, and especially in the nineteenth and twentieth
centuries, pathological and medical imagery in political discourse had
assumed “a punitive notion; of the disease not as a punishment but as
a sign of evil, something to be punished”^ is certainly borne out by the
use of illness and parasite metaphors in Nazi ideology and propaganda,
which we studied in Part I of this book. In National Socialist ideology, the
foody-based metaphor scenario of therapy-through-elimination became a
self-asserting ideology that reduced its targets to mere "bare life”, which
138 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Conclusion 139
had to be eliminated so as to preserve the body politic of the Nazi Behe­ associate it with Shakespeare’s texts.® In US American English, body politic
moth (in Neumann’s reading). has its own characteristic connotations that invoke an inclusive view of
However, as the texts from the Middle Ages, Renaissance and Enlight­ society (as in President Obama’s appeal to overcome “racial and religious
enment have shown, uses of pathological and radical surgical.metaphors tensions within the body politic”).^ In political science and philosophy, the
can be traced to a time long before the advent of modern medicine and metaphor has also been employed to denote notions of inclusiveness, e.g.
parasitology or “master illnesses”. Thus, one-dimensional accounts, either in debates about globalisation and the phenomenological critique of the
of the linear increase or decrease of specific manifestations of the meta­ theory of sovereignty.^® In France, Rousseau’s notions of the social body of
phor, of de- or re-metaphorisation, are not borne out by the historical find­ the people are still being invoked to promote patriotic solidarity, e.g. in an
ings. Neither, as we have seen in the last chapter, would it be justified to article by Michel Guenaire welcoming the election of Nicolas Sarkozy as
posit a special national path, e.g. in German political culture: though the president in 2007 as an opportunity to put “le vieux corps social fran^ais”
development of expressions for the body-state analogy is different from the in order and to rediscover “son propre genie”.”
conceptual history of the body politic phrase in British and American Eng­ Not only do such allusions demonstrate a degree of popular memorising
lish, the contrast is by no means a straightforward one of, say, a tendency of famous and infamous historical formulations of the metaphor but, more
towards or a preponderance of “racial” versus “social” definitions (except importantly, they derive their very pragmatic and political import from this
for the official discourse during the twelve years of Nazi rule in Germany). historical “resonance”. To invoke the body politic today would probably be
The history of uses of the body-state analogy in German political thought viewed as a laboured effort to use archaic language, were it not for the fact
and discourse reaches back to the early sixteenth century and shows just as that speakers and writers know that they will be understood as referring
much diachronic variation since then as other vernacular traditions of its to a conceptual-discursive tradition that is still relevant for their audience.
use in European languages and political cultures. The historicity of the body-state metaphor, however vaguely remembered
In view of this result, we need to take up once again the general question by members of the public, is part of its attractiveness for continued uses,
of what we mean if we speak of the “history” of the metaphor complex. To interpretations and reinterpretations in public discourse. For this reason,
answer this question, we need to distinguish several levels of analysis. The the historical indexicality of the metaphor cannot be excluded from its cog­
basic conceptual mapping that matches the outward appearance and main nitive analysis. If the grounding of the body-state mapping in experientially
functional aspects of the human body to the socio-political entities appears based schemas is the necessary condition for its successful use in all kinds
to be near universal: it is certainly attested beyond Western culture^ and is of expressions and scenarios, its historicity and discursive “situatedness”
as accessible today as it was in the Middle Ages and before. However, this (Frank 2008) provide the necessary complement to reach a sufficient expla­
general perspective does not justify the conclusion that the metaphor has no nation of its variation patterns. In the remainder of this chapter we will dis­
history at all, or that its history is a mere chronological series of instantia­ cuss the implications of this programmatic statement for the further study
tions of one and the same mapping, for its continued use has been shown to of the body-state metaphor and of political metaphor in general.
be based upon and indeed manifested by its conceptual-discursive develop­ In the first place, our overview of the various manifestations and sce­
ment. Without at least some—more or less conscious—awareness of that narios of the body-state metaphor has shown that cognitive analysis has
tradition on the part of its users, the body-state image should have faded to take into account the full range of its semantic variation as regards the
after the demise of humoral medicine and would only be manifest in a few source domain. It is evident that there are vast differences in the anatomi­
lexicalised “dead” metaphoric expressions such as head o f state. But if our cal, functional and medical understanding of even the most basic source
analyses have demonstrated anything, it is the emphatic, creative exploita­ concepts of body-related metaphors (e.g. anatoffiicahpa'fts, main organs
tion of its conceptual potential that characterizes its function in philosophi­ and their functions) in antiquity, the Middle Ages, the Renaissance, the
cal arguments, political theory and polemics to this day. Enlightenment and modern science. As for specialised notions, such as
In its use by the Nazis, the metaphor helped to advance a genocidal parasites, cancer, AIDS, viruses, etc., they could serve as source input for
ideology in its most brutal form, which is still remembered. As a result, metaphorical use only after these concepts had entered popular knowledge.
parasitological scenarios have become stigmatised in German and, to some The “paths” of their semantic development and entry into public conscious­
extent, international public debates on politics and societ. But the “Ger­ ness can be very complicated and are by no means only unidirectional (in
man case” is not unique: Native speakers of British English who employ the sense of body knowledge being “first” and its socio-political application
the phrase body politic may not be aware of all the'historical details from coming “afterwards”). In the case of English parasite and German Para-
the metaphor’s heyday during the Tudor Renaissance, but they will recog­ sit, for instance, etymological studies have shown that their Greek source
nise it as a special phrase (if only due to its archaic morphology) and may term parasitos denoted "a person allowed to share in the food provided
140 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Conclusion 141
for a public official, or in the feast after a sacrifice”; i.e. the human social in the various layers of popular knowledge frameworks.^^ Such simultane­
domain seems to have been the earlier domain of usage, and bio-medical ous use of source inputs with diachronically diverse origins provides the
applications are only recorded since the eighteenth century.’^ Whilst such basis of semantic metaphor variation that constitutes a vast field for further
detailed etymological knowledge can be assumed to be largely irrelevant research.
for modern users, it demonstrates that the physical or physiological domain A second main question we have raised concerns the “cognitive import”
is npt necessarily the historically primary or original source of metaphor of the body-state metaphor when we consider its central role in Nazi anti-
. mappings and that source-target directions are reversible, at least from a Semitic ideology. In Part I we explicated the various layers of source and
diachronic viewpoint. target inputs in detail to show the internal systematicity and range of Hit­
The parasite metaphor even appears to have changed its mapping direc­ ler’s imagery as a basis for an elaborate argument-by-analogy, which per­
tion twice: in the eighteenth century, the social category of a person who vaded both Mein Kampf and his later rhetoric up to the end of the “Third
lives at the expense of another person' (which was based on the historical Reich”. It is obvious and. has never been contentious that the body-parasite
notion of a person allowed to share in the food of another, as inherited scenario is present in these texts; what has been contentious is its cognitive
from ancient Greek culture)’^ was applied to the newly conceptualised rela­ and pragmatic function: was it a “mere” propaganda slogan to accompany,
tions between organisms in the natural world, especially to plants. By the and perhaps camouflage, the “real” Nazi policies of genocide and war, or
end of that century, however, it was re-applied from that botanic source to was it an integral part of the ideology that was necessary to make the Holo­
the concept of peoples as organisms, as we saw, for instance, in Herder’s caust happen? We considered (Chapter 2) diverse hypotheses that assumed
statements from the 1770s-80s quoted in the preceding chapter. The fur­ the latter case with view to the following question: How were the recipi­
ther development of this “re-mapped” metaphor in social Darwinist and ents, i.e. in the first place, the German public, supposed to have understood
racist discourses of the nineteenth century was informed by the then topical the meaning of the metaphor? The initial answers—that the metaphor was
hygienic, virological and bacteriological insights, so that the notions about understood as a “literal” blueprint for genocide, or as a “code” to hide its
the relative danger that parasites pose for their host organisms and about true nature—turned out to be disappointing. As a literally true descrip­
the methods of medical intervention were substantially different from those tion the body-parasite scenario makes no sense; as a camouflage “code” it
of earlier parasite metaphors. As we saw in Part I, it was these “modern” would have had to be more terminologically fixed and abstract (like, e.g.,
implications that were transferred in Hitler’s scenario of a supposed Jew­ “special treatment” or “deportation”) to be functional. Instead, the sce­
ish parasite attack on the German body politic, rather than the older, less nario appeared in the Fuhrer’s speeches and speeches by other party “lead­
dramatic connotations.^'* ers” of all ranks as well as newspapers, books, pamphlets, radio and film
In one sense, therefore, the history of body and illness metaphors can be propaganda as a vivid and emphatic announcement of genocidal intentions.
written as a story of medical and scientific advances, insofar as they have This publicity was, however, counteracted by the policy of strict secrecy
been popularised in a given discourse community. Popular “knowledge” practised by the agencies of perpetrators (SS, SD, Gestapo etc.). There are
concerning body and health issues varies through the centuries depending statements by Goebbels and Himmler to the effect that the German peo­
on received scientific consensus, and, as we have already observed, even ple were not (yet) ready for the full knowledge of what “happened to the
officially discarded conceptual traditions such as humoral medicine and Jews”, and we have detailed data from diaries and secret reports about the
the notion of a hierarchy of parts of the body can have a long “afterlife” popular rumours of mass killings, which fell short of providing detailed
in common language use, with varying degrees of semantic and etymo­ information especially about the extermination camps but which do show
logical transparency. The impact of scientific “breakthroughs” for popular a general awareness of the enormous dimensi<3n~oFthe genocide. On the
metaphorical conceptualisations of the body and its state of health must basis of these data, we can conclude that the'raetaphor scenario supporting
therefore not be exaggerated. Whilst the Great Chain o f Being system that the genocide was integrated into a systematically distorted discourse that
surrounded the humoral.medical philosophy of the Middle Ages has largely treated the murder of European Jewry (as well as of other groups) as an
disappeared by now, some of its conceptual and terminological elements “open secret”.
have remained in use. The notion of blood as a substance that defines a per­ In this discourse the metaphor of parasite annihilation played the central
son or a group’s inheritance and identity, for instance, has survived in folk role of naming, explaining (and supposedly justifying) the core content of
theories, idioms and in public discourse until today. Usage patterns of body Nazi policy against Jews, which was “taboo” for identification in literal
and health-illness metaphors are thus not only wide-ranging in terms of the terminology (apart from some cases of internal communication among the
conceptual source input but are made more complex by the simultaneous perpetrators). Depending on situational context, social identity and per­
co-existence of several metaphor versions from different periods of origin sonal interests, members of the general public could, as it were, choose from
142 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Conclusion 143
an array of interpretative “versions” that ranged from dismissive attitudes Carl Schmitt’s biased reconstruction of Hobbes’s Leviathan showed that
towards it as mere “wild” or “ugly” rhetoric over semi-informed suspicion the attempt was made to connect the “respectable” philosophical body
of its “true” meaning to knowing complicity with (or, in incomparably politic tradition with the notion of a “total” state that gained its identity
fewer cases, resistance against) its “practical” genocidal implications. In only through combating an existential foe. The permanent crisis of such a
the latter cases, the official insistence on continuing the “annihilation of the state founded pn conflict, which classical thinkers considered mainly as a
Jewish parasite race” as a means to “save the German nation’s body" (and, limiting concept for a situation that had to be avoided, was for Schmitt the
for good measure, also the wider European body politic) must be assumed pre-condition of all political activity. So it was for Hitler and the Nazis,
to have been easily comprehensible as a paraphrase for a statement that the but they drew from it the ultimate conclusion which Schmitt himself did
genocide was ongoing (even after the chances of military victory, for which not (dare to?) consider: the absolute necessity for the national body politic
it was supposedly a precondition, were disappearing). to destroy the foe as a parasite life form that was “unworthy to live”. The
Whilst the Nazi leaders and their audience did not need to have detailed basis for such a conclusion was of course not Schmitt’s attempted recon­
knowledge of the long history of political body imagery in Western political struction of Hobbes’s theory but the popularized “sedimented” tradition of
philosophy and public discourse in order to “understand” the genocide they body-state analogies.
were perpetrating and/or witnessing, the famous traditions of conceptualis­ Our historical analyses in Part II have revealed that whilst a relatively
ing state, society or nation as a body certainly had a reinforcing and famil­ wide range of conceptual/lexical source elements can be found in the rel­
iarising effect on their use. Our sketches of the discursive and conceptual evant texts, only a handful of thematic clusters appear repeatedly and
changes of body-state imagery in the preceding chapters have shown that prominently: the hierarchically ordered anatomy o f parts o f the body,
this history is not amenable to a one-dimensional interpretation in the sense their mutual interdependence, the life cycle o f the whole organism and
of a linear development, but that does not mean it is un-interpretable. The the illness-diagnosis-cure scenario. These key themes and scenarios carry
main contrast between the political therapy scenarios employed by John of evaluative and emotive associations with them, as well as assumptions
Salisbury and Christine de Pizan, Starkey and Machiavelli, and Hobbes, about preferred and feared consequences and courses of action, which
Rousseau, Kant and Herder and those used by Hitler and his acolytes does are understood as evaluations of solutions of political crises. Whilst
not lie in the source knowledge or in the supposedly more “optimistic” they may appear to be nothing but commonsense concepts grounded in
view of the severity of political illness, but in the degree of commitment bodily experience and pre- or folk-theoretical assumptions, we can in fact
that they impose on speakers and hearers. trace them back to philosophically and even theologically oriented tradi­
In what Sontag called the “classical” tradition, the scenario of a maxi­ tions reaching back to concepts of Christ’s/God’s body and its manifold
mally invasive and aggressive therapy (e.g. amputation, radical surgery) worldly manifestations (e.g. as the “mystical body” of the church with
was present, but it did not figure as the only possible “solution”; rather, it the pope as its head, or as the emperor, or as the king in his “body poli­
was the means of last resort. It was conceivable, but it was certainly not tic”, or as the “sovereign” as the principle of the state, the people’s body,
considered to be desirable or necessary except in desperate, “monstrous” etc.). Long after the ancient cosmological and theological frameworks
circumstances that were themselves to be avoided at all cost. For this rea­ that sustained these notions have disappeared or have been relativised to
son, classical scenarios of the body-state metaphor used to be couched in the point where they can no longer be considered belief systems that mem­
hedging formulations; e.g. similes, exemplary stories (e.g. the “fable of bers of a particular national or religious culture adhere to uncritically, the
the belly”), referenced quotatipns from ancient and famous authors and “holiness” of the collective (social and/or political) body remains. It was
explicitly argued analogies that stressed a relational rather than substantive and still is this holiness of the body politic that-has-had-terbe-defended at
similarity between the body and the state. Hitler and the Nazi’s scenario all costs, against devilish inspired heretics Jti the Middle Ages, humoral
of national and cosmic therapy^ by contrast, knew only one outcome, one imbalances in the Renaissance, rabid dogs that can bite a state “to the
therapy and one course of action for the healer, in order to solve the alleged quick” for Hobbes, or racial vermin and agents o f decomposition, in the
extreme crisis of the body politic, i.e. its cure-through-elimination of the Nazi worldview.
parasite. This therapy was understood by Hitler and his followers in the Hitler’s “diagnosis” of Germany’s post-World War I crisis thus
sense of an elimination of all individuals of the supposed parasite organ­ sounded plausible not despite but because o f its metaphoric character
ism. As the scenario analysis in Chapter 3 showed, the source and target and history. This apparent plausibility was grounded in its familiarity as
levels in Mein Kampf were so intricately fused that the distinction of literal an age-old, tried and tested commonsense analogy. It provided the Ger­
and figurative meanings of the bodylnation-v.-parasiteljew mapping was man public with a conceptual and argumentative space to reason about
rendered meaningless. the socio-economic and political hardships they were experiencing and
144 Metaphor, Nation and Holocaust Conclusion 145
to trust Hitler with applying the therapy that would end those hardships However, as the examples of Rousseau’s corps de la nation concept in its
and prevent them in future. As a means to achieve the common good application during the French Revolution, Herder’s idea of parasite nations
tor the nation, these measures could be interpreted as ethically accept- in its later distortions and Hobbes’s theory of the sta.te-SiS-Leviathan in
able, even if they included hardships and sacrifices (hence Himmler and Schmitt’s biased re-interpretation have shown, not even truly rationally
other SS-leaders’ self-stylisation as carrying out an unpleasant, almost oriented versions of the body-state metaphor are immune to being recon­
sacrificial task m perpetrating the genocide). The function of the body- figured as closed scenarios that legitimise murderous policies. The body-
parastte scenario as employed by the Nazi elite was to make the geno­ state metaphor complex is neither a superficial rhetorical ornament nor just
cide appear as the inevitable “solution” for Germany’s crisis. They stuck an ahistoric, universal conceptual structure: in all its uses it provides an
with this scenario through the changing fortunes of war. As the secretly opportunity and a challenge for the respective body politic and its public
recorded statements of popular opinion show, its genocidal agenda was “voices” to reflect on the ethical implications of their self-presentation and
understood by the majority German populace sufficiently to at least “tol­ -interpretation. The metaphors by which nations define their destiny have
erate”, if not participate, in that final solution. This astonishing persua­ the potential to shape that destiny.
siveness of the cure-by-elimination scenario remains inexplicable if we
dismiss It as a propagandistic extra to Hitler’s “real” policies or view it as
the re-manifestation of a “mind virus” (in an accidental, tragic ■historical
context). Our findings show that Hitler’s metaphorical presentation of
parasite annihilation as a natural, self-evident and necessary therapy for
the existential problems of the German body politic convinced the public
of his genocidal agenda.
The comparison of Hitler’s scenarios with those promoted by medieval
theologians, humanists and enlightened thinkers would seem at first sight to
be almost an “open and shut” case of contrasting a conceptually incoherent
and ethically depraved use with a highly respectable philosophical tradition
of political thought. However, we have seen that not only the range of source
domain concepts and scenarios can be shown to be similar but also that even
respectable” authors often come dangerously close to suggesting radical and
potentially genocidal cures for perceived political illnesses.
It is only through the explicit comparison and historical reconstruction
that the differences between their uses of the metaphor and Hitler’s version
become visible;

• Where Hitler’s metaphor system is a closed set of “self-fulfilling”


mutually reinforcing scenarios and “prophecies”, classical and also
many modern uses are embedded in textual structures that highlight
their figurative status (e.g. simile, quotation, “exemplum”).
• Where the Nazis depicted the worst-possible scenario outcome
{destruction and decomposition o f the body politic) as an imminent
and inevitable danger, most other uses portray it as a potential, but
not inevitable, worst-case scenario that can and should be avoided.
• The therapy “offered” by the Nazi body-parasite scenario is a precise
match of the supposed extreme danger to the body, i.e. complete anni­
hilation of the supposed illness-inducing agent as a “final solution”,
whereas in classical and enlightened scenario applications, extreme
therapies are mentioned mainly as deterrents to underline the neces­
sity to avoid such a negative outcome.
Notes

NOTES TO CHAPTER 1
1 For dictionary entries on body politic and fu rth er political body imagery see
* D eignan 1995, p. 2; Brewer’s Dictionary of Phrase and Fable 1999, pp. 149,
713- for analyses see Pauwels an d Vandenbergen 1995; M usolff 2 0 0 4 a, b.
2. The Guardian, 18 January 1996; The Observer, 13 N ovem ber 2005; The Times
Higher Education Supplement, 2 2 N ovember 1996; O bam a 2007, p. 16.
3 Independent on Sunday, 20 N ovem ber 2005 an d again on the BBC p ro ­
gram m e Newsnight (5 O ctober 2009: “ . . . he said ‘as a mere M ayor of
L ondon, as a mere toenail in the body politic, it m ay be difficult to have a
referendum ’”. ,7 n i
4. DieZeit, IS Ju n e 1998: “Wer d ieH o m o g en itatern es‘deutschenV olkskorpers
ins Feld fu h rt, der gieSt O l ins Feuer der G h etto s”.
5. Die Welt, 26 M arch 2006: “ Im kran k en V olkskorper steckt eine verletzte

6 . D ieWelt, 26 M arch 2006; “ Die D ebatte um den nationalen V olkskorper ist


Symptom einer H ysteric, die die deutsche Gesellschaft fallweise immer
w ieder erfafit.” , , ,
7 H itler 1933, p. 334 (comp. 1992, p. 276}: “ [der Jude] w ar . . . im m er nur
Parasit im K orper anderer V olker”. T he English translations here an d in the
follow ing examples are by the author; in th e case of quotations from Mein
Kampf they are for th e m ost p a rt based on th e tran slatio n by R alph M anheim
of 1943 b ut in some cases modified. T he page references give relevant pages
of the original G erm an tex t (23rd edition, of 1933) an d the 1992 reprint
of the M anheim translation. Em phasis th ro u g h italicization of m etaphoric
terms in the examples and the main text are b y ^ h e ^ t h o r r " ’
8 H itler 1933, p. 361 (1992, p. 298): “1914 . erfolgte . . . das letzte Aufflack-
ern des nationalen Selbsterhaltungstriebes gegenuber der fortschreitenden
. . . L ahm ung u nseres V olkskdrpers.” . f 1 ...
9. G oebbels 1971, vol. 2, pp. 182-188: “D as Judentum stellt eine mfektiose
E rkrankung dar, die ansteckend w irkt. . . . D eutschland h at jedenfalls nicht
die A bsicht, sich dieser jiidischen Bedrohung zu beugen, sondern vielmeht
die, ih t rechtzeitig, w enn notig unter vollkom m ener u n d radikalster Ausrott-,
A usschaltung des Judentum s, entgegenzutreten!”
10. See R aul H ilberg’s definitions of the categories of perpetrators and bystand­
ers in H ilberg 1992, pp. IX -X II.
11. G regor 2005, p. 67. • , m/ ■u
12. A ccording to Peter Longerich (2003), term s such as annihilation {Vermch-
tung), ‘ex tirp atio n ’ {Ausrottung), ‘final solution’ {Endlosung), ‘removal
148 Notes Notes 149
[Entfernung], ‘resettlem ent’ {Umsiedlung) or ‘evacuation’ {Evakuierung) and/or racists. T hus, the weekly new spaper Die Zeit w arned against N eo-
changed their m eanings several tim es: in the first phase, from the 1920s to N azis "penetrating the capillaries of society in some p arts of Saxony” {Die
the m id-1930s, the N azis “used the term s w ith reference to the Jews but Zeit, 24 February 2005: “ [es] ist den R echtsextrem en g elungen,. . . in bestim-
w ithout necessarily implying a program m e o f m ass m urder”; after th a t until m ten Gegenden [Sachsens] tief in die K apillaren der Gesellschaft einzudrin-
late 1941, their vocabulary “denoted the idea of a geographical relocation gen” ) an d the British daily The Independent ascribed to “ far rig h t” parties
of a m ass of people” and increasingly “incorporated the perspective of the in Europe the ability to act as “a virus w hich spreads th ro u g h the dem ocratic
physical end of the Jews in E urope”; in the last phase until 1945, these term s institutions th a t if abhors like some k in d of superbug, a political ‘M RSA’ ”
were “ increasingly used as synonyms for m ass m urder” (Longerich 2003, pp. {The Independent, 16 Jan u ary 2007).
2 4-25).
13. Longerich points out th a t even in H itler’s ow n circle, the H olocaust w as
referred to only in figurative o r abstract term s, probably so as to avoid
NOTES TO CHAPTER 2
“tak[ing] in the reality of the m urder of m illions of people” and “ [keeping]
the horror of it a t a distance” (Longerich 2 0 0 3 , p. 23).
14. T his em phasis on the “perspectivisation’^ function o f m etaphor has been 1. An earlier version of this chapter was published in the journal Critical
em phasized in cognitive approaches to m etaphor (Lakoff an d Johnson 1980;
Approaches to Discourse Analysis across Disciplines, vol. 2/2 (2008): 1-10,
Lakoff 1987; Kovecses 2002; Fauconnier an d Turner 2002), b ut is equally
under the title “What Can Critical Metaphor Analysis Add to the Under­
recognised in newer sem antic and pragm atic/discursive accounts (Stern standing of Racist Ideology?”
2000; Tendahl an d Gibbs 20 0 8 ; Z in k en an d M usolff 2009). 2. For early comments see Tucholsky [1930] 1960, vol. 8, pp. 129-133, Olden
15. O ur study does not deal w ith the issue of how the N ational Socialists pic­
1936, p. 140; Paechter 1944, Fischer 1945; Pechau 1935 provides a self-con­
tu red their ideal of a healthy n atural hu m an body, w hich is, of course, linked gratulatory Nazi comment. For the early post-war period, see Michael and
to their source concepts for the nation’s body politic. The N azi body ideal Doerr 2002; Niven 2002; Deissler 2003.
and its counter-im age of “the Jew ”, as depicted in literature and films as well 3. Burke 1984, p. 71.
as in all kinds of pictorial and sculptural m anifestations, has been studied in 4. Burke 1984, pp. 63-68.
detail (see, e.g., Theweleit 1980; G ilm an 1991; Alkemeyer 1996; W ildm ann 5. Klemperer 1975; English translation: 2000 (for a thorough critique, see Ind-
1998; Linke 1999). T he relationship betw een the individual an d the body sley 2004).
ideal and the collective body {Volkskdrper), however, is n o t one of identity 6. Sternberger, Storz and Siiskind 1989. These analyses were, like Klemperer’s,
but required its ow n argum entative buttressing. The study presented here based on pre-1945 studies; see Dodd 2003, 2007.
thus needs to be com plem ented by an exploration of th at relationship in N azi 7. Klemperer 1975, p. 185.
ideology and propaganda, so as to give a com plete picture of the literal and 8. Klemperer 1975, pp. 185-186.
m etaphorical applications of body concepts in N atio n al Socialism. 9. Klemperer 1975, pp. 7-14; 273-300.
16. See Coker 1910; A rcham bault 1967; H ale 1971; D h o rn van Rossum and 10. Sternberger, Storz and Siiskind 1989, pp. 33,135.
Bockenforde 1978; Sontag 1 9 7 8 ,1 9 9 1 ; Sawday 1995; K antorow icz 1997; De 11. Sternberger, Storz and Siiskind 1989, pp. 126-136; see also documents from
Baecque 1997; Peil 1983; H arris 1998; G uldin 2 0 0 0 ; M aitlan d 2003; N eder- the subsequent debate about their critique of Nazi- or Nazi-like language,
m an 2 0 0 4 ; Koschorke et al. 2007; M outon 2009. ibid., pp. 229-339.
17. See N estle 1927; H ale 1971, pp. 2 6 -2 9 ; Peil 1985, Patterson 1991; G uldin 12. See Seidel and Seidel-Slotty 1961; Bosmajian 1983; Volmert 1989; Schmitz-
2000, pp. 101-103; K oschorke et al. 2007, pp. 1 5 -26. Berning 2000.
18. Aesop 2 0 0 2 , p. 35 (fable no. 66). 13. Jackell981,p. 58.
19. Shakespeare, Coriolanus, Act I, Scene 1: 95-1 4 8 (quoted from .Shakespeare 14. Greive 1983, p. 128.
1976).-
15. For a theory of category mistakes in truth-value semantic terms, see Ryle
20. Shakespeare, Corioldnus, A ct I, Scene 1 :1 5 4 -1 5 7 . 1949.
21. See K okoschka 1971, quoted after H a m a n n 1996, p. 429.
16. Goldhagen 2003, p. 127. -------- —^
22. See H am an n 1996, pp. 2 8 5 -3 3 6 ; K ershaw 1999, pp. 71-106. 17. Goldhagen 2003, p. 412. /
23. See G anz 1957, p. 175. 18. Goldhagen 2003, p. 128.
24. See Levitas 1986; Linke 1999; Tow nsend 2005; K ienpointner 2005, pp.
19. See Schoeps 1996; Browning 2001, pp. 191-221; Browning 2004, pp.
226-227.
463-466.
25. Occasionally, such criticism has the pow er to ru in a politician’s career, as 20. Goldhagen 2003, p. 412.
in the case of the W est G erm an Parliam ent’s president, Philipp Jenninger,
21. See Bussemer 2000; Hachmeister and Kloft 2005; Herf 2006; Kallis 2008.
w ho had to resign after a com m em oration speech th a t w as deemed by many 22. See Lakoff and Johnson 1980.
to contain N azi vocabulary; see Ensink 1992; Krebs 1993; Siever 2001; for
23. See Fauconnier and Turner 2002.
overall assessments see Steiner 197 9 ,1 9 8 7 ; S t6 tze ri9 8 9 ; N iven 2 0 0 2 , 2006; 24. Charteris-Black 2005, p. 197.
Eitz and Stotzel 2007. 25. Hawkins 2001, p. 49.
26. T he use of such im agery for the purpose o f criticism (as in the above-m en­ 26. Hawkins 2001, p. 32.
tioned censure of the term Volkskdrper), is, of course, considered to be politi­
27. Hawkins 2001, p. 37; compare Hitler 1992 (Manheim translation), p. 512.
cally correct, as is, interestingly, its use to denounce right-w ing extrem ists 28. Hawkins 2001, pp. 36, 38-40.
150 Notes Notes 151
29. G oatly 2007, p. 47. 53. Fauconnier and Turner 1998, 2002; Turner and Fauconnier 2003; for a criti­
30. For the conceptual history o f the idea of supposedly hereditary “racial” cal comparison with the “conceptual metaphor theory” paradigm of Lakoff
purity, see Jones 2 000, pp. 10-11 , 3 8 -3 9 , 2 5 3 -2 6 4 . and Johnson, see Grady, Oakley and Coulson 1999.
31. See H itler 1933, pp. 313-319; 1992, pp. 2 6 0 -2 6 9 . 54. Fauconnier and Turner 2002,131.
32. See H itler 1933, pp. 76, 107, 307, 421, 428, 436, 4 4 6 , 478, 488, 704 711 55. Chilton 2005, 39; compare Hitler 1933, p. 334; 1992, p. 276.
730, 741; 1992, pp. 64, 254, 295, 353, 359, 3 6 6 -3 6 7 , 391, 399, 569, 574’ 56. Chilton 2005, p. 39. Chilton also highlights the apparent oddity of “he”
598. as a “masculine” anaphoric reference to the parasite in English (2005, pp.
33. H itler 1933, p. 332; 1992, pp. 273-274. 39-40). However, this is not an issue in the original German text, because
34. See H itler 1933, p. 357; 1992, p. 295. “der Parasit” has a grammatically binding masculine gender in German, just
35. See A nonym us 1937. Simon (2009) m akes the conjecture th a t the article as does “der Jude”—their formal congruence is grammatical not semantic.
w as probably penned by the editor in chief of Das schwarze Korps, G unter 57. Chilton 2005, p. 39.
d’Alquen. 58. Chilton 2005, p. 39.
36. L akoff and Turner 1989, p. 166. 59. See Dawkins 1989,1999, 2004; Blackmore 1999; Sperber 1996, 2000.
37. L akoff and Turner 1989, p. 167. 60. Dawkins 1989, p. 192.
38. Lovejoy 1936, pp. 2 5 -5 5 . 61. Sperber 1996,p. 53.
39. T illyard 1982, p. 107. 62. Sperber 1996, pp. 25,102-104.
40. H aw kins 2001, p. 45. 63. See Brodie 1996; Dawkins 2004.
41. H aw kins 2001, pp. 4 2 , 44. 64. See Dawkins 2004, pp. 166-171; 2005, p. 415.
42. H aw kins 2001, p. 46. 65. See Dawkins 1989, pp. 182, 192; Charlesworth and Charlesworth 2003, p.
43. H aw kins 2001, pp. 2 7 -2 9 19.
44. C harteris-Black 2005, pp. 182-184. T he body-parasite relation as the basis 66. Chilton 2005, p. 42.
of H itler’s racist ideology is again highlighted in several, m ainly Internet- 67. See Hamann 1996, pp. 285-336.
based publications by R ichard Koenigsberg (1986, 1992, 2 0 0 4 a, b, 2005a, 68. See Stark 1981; Kershaw 1999, p. 138; Weikart 2004, pp. 220-225.
b), w hich repeatedly h int a t a “cognitive” perspective. H is analyses are, how ­ 69. For historical overviews, see Proctor 1988; Weindling 1989; Weikart 2004.
ever, focused m am ly on a psychoanalytic investigation of H itler’s “paranoid 70. Hamann 1996, pp. 264-283, 333-336.
belief system , w hich according to Koenigsberg had its centre in the w ish “to 71. See Domarus 1965, Jackel and Kuhn 1980; Hitler 1992-1998; Weinberg
solve the problem of death by destroying Jew s, w ho symbolized the death-in­ 1961.
stinct— the reality th a t bodies eventually disintegrate” (2004a); the evidence 72. Rash 2005a.
for this psychological conclusion seems to be rath er thin. 73. See, for instance, Schmitz-Berning 2000; Michael and Doerr 2002.
45. See R ash 2 006, pp. 31-41.
46. R ash 2006,-p. 155.
47. R ash 2 0 0 6 , p. 174.
48. R ash 2 0 0 6 , pp. 169-172. NOTES TO CHAPTER 3
49. R ash 2006, p. 116. G oldhagen (2003, p. 411) highlights the sam e p o in t by
stating th a t on. the scale of hum an nations assum ed in N azi-ideology, Jews 1. The fact that the sales figures of Mein Kampf remained rather limited before
“w ere not even accorded a place on the continuum ”. 1933 and that estimates of readers’ numbers are still debated (Kershaw 1999,
50. Lovejoy,1936, p. 59. pp. 241-243; Rash 2006, p. 20) is of little concern here: its bio-political
51. Lovejoy 1936, p. 20. conceptualisations of the German nation and of Jews, which are the object
52. Lovejoy himself and another famous historian of ideas of his day, E. M . W. of our analysis, were indubitably in the public domain from the moment
Tillyard, did hint at a conceptual link between the Great Chain of Being that the first edition was distributed. Hitler’s so-called “Second Book” is, of
m etaphor and the racist ideology of N azi G erm any of which they were con­ course, essential for the comprehensive understanding ^ h is political ideol­
temporaries. Lovejoy saw the gradation principle of the Great Chain in nine­ ogy (Jackel 1981; Weinberg 1961), but as itx^ihaihed'unpublish^ it cannot
teenth-tw entieth century (German) rom antic thought perverted into a “kind of be regarded as having shaped the public consciousness and acceptance of his
collective vanity , the “tragic outcome” of w hich had “ been seen, and expe­ anti-Semitic bio-political metaphors.
rienced, by all of us in our ow n tim e” (1936, p. 313); and Tillyard noted, at 2. Browning 2001, p. xviii.
the end of The Elizabethan World Picture (first published in 1943), th at “ [the 3. For the classical topos of argumentation-by-analogy as a form of metaphori­
medieval/Renaissance habit of mind] resembles certain trends of thought in cal language use, see Aristotle Poef/cs, 57b (Aristotle 1996, p. 34). For mod­
central Europe, the ignoring of which by our scientifically m inded intellectuals ern theories of analogical reasoning that thematise its relation to metaphor,
has helped not a little to bring the w orld into its present conflicts and distresses” see Centner, Holyoak and Kokinov 2001; Steen 2009, pp. 26-30; Barnden
(1982, pp. 116-117). For both historians, N azi G erm any’s use of aspects of the 2009, p. 80); for its application in political discourse, see Musolff 2004a,
Great Chain tradition was a perverted, viciously tw isted version and a sad end­ pp. 173-177.
ing to a long conceptual career; Lovejoy explicitly concluded: “the history of the 4. Relevant German lexical items: Natur, Naturgesetz.
idea of the Chain of Being . . . is the history of a failure” (1936, p. 329). C om ­ 5. Organismus, organisch, Nahrboden, Wirtsvolk.
pare Spitzer 1944 for an early critique of such “linear” conceptual history. 6. Selbsterhaltungstrieb, Trieb zur Rassenreinheit, Instinkt.
152 Notes Notes 153
7. Art, Geschlecht. 45. For the relationship of m ental “ scripts” to conceptual schemas a n d scenarios,
a. Rasse, Rasseinstinkt, Rasseneinheit, Rassenunterschiede, Rassekern, ras- see S chank and Abelson 1977, pp. 3 6 -6 8 ; Taylor 1995, pp. 81-92.
senmdfiig, rasserein, Rassenkonglomerat, rassisch. 46. See Brow ning 1992, 2 004; G oldhagen 2003; Friedlander 1998, 2007; and
9. Wiedergeburt, Werden. Bauer 2001.
10. Geschlecht. 47. H itler 1933, p. 311; 1992, p. 258.
11. Hoherziichtung, Kreuzung, Mischprodukt. 48. H itler 1933, p. 313; 1992, p. 260. H itler’s “evidence” for this universal “ his­
12. Volkskdrper, staatliche Korper, wirtschaftliche Korper, Riesenkorper torical experience” w as an alleged difference in th e colonialist history of
13. Herz., South and N o rth A m erica. In South A m erica, the descendants of the colonial
~ 14. Lebensadern. invaders of “ R om anic” stock h ad fatefully m ixed w ith the aboriginal peoples
15. Blutlauf Blutopfer, blutsmd^ig, Blutseinheit, Blutsreinheit, to a large extent an d thus lost their cultural-racial advantage, w hilst in N o rth
Blutzufuhr, Herrenblut, Stimme des Blutes. A m erica th e E uropeans m aintained th eir “m aster”-status, due to racial seg­
16. Kraft. regation from indigenous peoples as well as im ported “N egro” slaves (ibid.).
17. Gesundheit, Volksgesundheit, gesund. From this, H itler drew the conclusion th a t “blood m ix tu re and the resultant
18. Erkrankung, Krankheit. (das) Krdnkliche, Seuche, Siechtum Verseuchung drop in the racial level” was “ the sole cause of th e demise of old cultures;
verseucht. for m en do n ot perish as a result of lost w ars, but by the loss of th a t force
19. Blutschande, Blutsumpf Blutsvermengung, Blutsvermischung, Rassenkreu- of resistance w hich is contained only in p ure blood” (1933, p. 324; 1992, p.
zung, Rassenschande, Bastard, Bastardisierung. 269).
20. Mifigeburt. 49. Jackel 1981, p. 89.
21. Erstarrung, Verknocherung. . 50. Bullock 1962, p. 40; Kershaw 1999, p. 244;.Evans 2003, p. 198.
22. Ldhmung. 51. See, e.g., Z m arzlik 1963; Baader and Schultz 1980; Kelly 1981; Wein-
23. Pest, Pestilenz, Verpestung. g art, K roll an d Bayertz 1988; P roctor 1988; W eindling 1989; Vogel 1992;
24. Syphilis, Versyphilitisierung. These terms can be interpreted both literally H am an n 1996, pp. 28 5 -3 1 9 ; Cornw ell 2 0 0 3 , pp. 7 1 -9 2 ; W eikart 2004. For
and metaphorically: in some passages of Mein Kampf they are linked to the a th o ro u g h critique of simplistic assum ptions ab o u t “d irect” links betw een
notion of an alleged Jewish-led rise of prostitution, but they are also used as social D arw inism and N ational Socialism, see Evans 1997.
general characterisations of the overall deplorable state of the nation’s body 52. S eeH itler’s l9 1 9 I e tte r to Adolf G em lich, in Jackel an d K uhn 1980, pp. 8 8 -9 0 ;
due to Jewish influence (see Hitler 1933, pp. 269, 271-274 278- 1992 d d for the context, Fest 1974, pp. 167-168; K ershaw 1999, pp. 1 2 4-125.
224,226-228,231-232). ’ 53. H itler 1933, pp. 130-132; 1992, pp. 109-110; compare also his account of “get­
25. Soziale Krebsschdden. ting to know ” Jews in Vienna, H itler 1933, pp. 59-70; 1992, pp. 5 3 -6 0 . Like
26. Polypen, Geschwulst. other apparently autobiographical aspects of Mein Kampf H itler’s account of
27. Impotenz. how his ow n opinions were formed in is a highly stylized legend rather th an a
28. Tod, Alterstod, Totenkranz der Menschheit, Vergehen Totengrdberarbeit, tru th fu l account (see Kershaw 1999, p. 11; H am an n 1996, pp. 500-502).
Verlust seines irdischen Daseins. 54. C harlesw orth and C harlesw orth 2003, p. 91. See also G ould 2 0 0 0 , pp.
29. (Fermente der) Zersetzung, Zersetzer, Spaltpilz, Fdulnis, Made im faulen- 4 9 -5 2 ; Rose 1998, pp. 33-47.
den Leibe. 55. D arw in 1901, p. 644.
30. Gift, giftig, Infizierung, Volkergift,(Bluts-)Vergiftung, Yolksvergifter. 56. D arw in 2 0 0 4 , p. 18.
31. Viper, Kreuzotter, Schlange, Schlangennest. 57. D arw in 2004, p. 210.
32. Parasit, Parasitentum, Schmarotzer, Schddling anfressen, Drohne, Bluiegel, 58. D arw in 2 0 0 4 , p. 205.
Blutjude, blutsaugerisch, Vampir. 59. D arw in 2 0 0 4 , p. 678
33. Bazillus, Bazillentrdger, Erreger. 60. D arw in 2 0 0 4 , p. 678
34. Ungeziefer. 61. D arw in 2 0 0 4 , p. 207.
35. herumdoktern. 62. D arw in 2 0 0 4 , p. 207. _
36. Rezept, Radikalmittel. 63. Hitler 1933, 317-337; 1992, pp. 263-279.
37. Regeneration, Heilung. 64. D uring the T h ird Reich, the absence o f ^ n y biological definition of race
38. See Hitler 1933, p. 252; 1992, p. 210. w ould lead to th e grotesque calculation of “full”, “ h alf” and “q u arte r” Jews
39. See Hitler 1933, pp. 253-254; 1992, pp. 211-212. based solely on th e religious affiliation of g randparents (as form ulated in the
40. See Hitler 1933, pp. 268; 1992, pp. 223. N urem berg race laws); see Friedlander 1997, pp. 144-170.
41. See Hitler 1933, p. 360; 1992, p. 298. 65. Obviously, the “Ju d ean ” aspect of this trad itio n w as absent in H itler’s and
42. Kershaw (1999, pp. 224-254) shows in detail that Hitler came to see himself any N azi version; the basis for such an anti-Sem itic “ interpretation” of the
as the one and only “leader” of Germany’s recovery only in the wake of the biblical source tex t h ad been laid by nineteenth-century and early tw entieth-
trial for the 1923 putsch attempt, i.e. during the time of his imprisonment cen tu ry w riters w ho alleged an “A ryan” background of the “historical Jesus”
and writing of Mein Kampf (see Fenske 2005 for the theological debates; fo r their reception by H itler, see
43. See Hitler 1933, p. 334; 1992, p. 111. H am a n n 1996, pp. 333-334).
. 44. For the semantic characteristics of “metaphor scenarios”, see Musolff 2006- 66. H itler 1933, p. 313; 1992, p. 260.
Semino 2008, pp. 218-222. 67. See H itler 1933, p. 70; 1992, p. 60.
154 Notes Notes 155
68. See H itler 1933, p. 313; 1992, p. 260. 100. See Shorter Oxford English Dictionary, 2002, vol. 2, p. 2096.
69. See H itler 1933, p. 318; 1992, p. 263; for the im plications of the depiction of 101. This doubly stigmatizing force of the bloodsucker metaphor probably
the A ryan as a “G od-child”, see Barsch 2 0 0 2 , pp. 3 0 8 -3 1 2 . accounts for its long tradition of use as a pejorative term; see Brewer’s Dic-
70. See H itler 1933, pp. 340, 351, 752; 1992, pp. 59, 282, 294, 605. • tionary of Phrase and Fable, 2000, p. 142; for German, see Grimm 1984,
71. See H itler 1933, p. 70; 1992, p. 60 (emphasis in the original). vol. 2 [1860], p. 190.
72. Burke 1982, p. 63. 102. See, e.g., Hitler 1933, pp. 62, 334, 360; 1992, pp. 54, 277, 298.
73. Friedlander 1998, p. 87. 103. See, e.g., Hitler 1933, pp. 135,186, 331, 361; 1992, pp. 113,155, 274, 298.
- 74. Barsch 2 0 0 2 , pp. 41-51, 1 38-142 , 3 6 8 -381. For the w ider debate, see also 104. See, e.g.. Hitler 1933, pp. 63,269,272; 1992, pp. 54, 224, 226. Tuberculosis,
Ach and Pentrop 2001; Fenske 2005. which figured in Hitler’s anti-Semitic metaphors in earlier writings, is men­
75. Barsch 2 002, p. 380. tioned only in “literally” medical contexts and explicit comparison in Mein
76. Barsch 2 002, pp. 271-319. For a com plete overview over all biblical allu­ Kampf\ see Hitler 1933, pp.-253, 269; 1992, pp. 211, 224.
sions in Mein Katnpf, see R ash 200 5 a, pp. 2 2 -2 7 ; on other general religious/ 105. Hitler 1933, p. 358; 1992, p. 296. The historical precedent of such an out­
m ythological term s, ibid., pp. 14-21 an d 2 8 -3 3 ; for discussion, see also come was, in Hitler’s view, Soviet Russia, where “the Jew”, once he had
G regor 2005, p. 77; and Greive 1983, pp. 1 2 6-128. gained power through the Bolshevik revolution, had “killed or starved about
77. See Barsch 2 002, pp. 6 0 -1 3 7 ,1 9 2 -2 7 1 . thirty million people with positively fanatical savagery, in part under inhu­
78. See Fest 1974, pp. 202, 732; Speer 1975, pp. 2 2 , 30; Picker 2003, pp. 3 0 0 - man tortures, in order to give a gang of Jewish journalists and stock exchange
301 (conversation note no. 74, o f 11 A pril 1942). bandits domination over a great people” (ibid.).
79. H itler 1933, pp. 481, 512-513; 1992, pp. 393, 417-418. 106. See Hitler 1933, p. 313; 1992, p. 260.
80. See H itler 1933, pp. 145,195, 324; 1992, pp. 1 2 2 ,1 6 2 , 269. 107. See Shorter Oxford English Dictionary 2001, vol. 1, pp. 250-251; Brewer's
81. D arw in 1901, p. 77 and passim. Dictionary of Phrase and Fable 1999, pp. 141-142.
82. D arw in 1901, p. 78. 108. See Jones 1996, pp. 3-15; 2000, pp. 19-36.
83. D arw in applied this notion of “struggle” as statistical com petition to hum an 109. See Jones 2000, p. 39.
history; in The Descent of Man he asserted th a t “the civilised races of man 110. See Jones 2000, pp. 38-40; Kevles 1985, pp. 3-19.
w ill certainly exterm inate, and replace, the savage races th ro u g h o u t the 111. See Hitler 1933, Chapters 2, 3, 4, 7; for their dubious quality as an autobio­
w orld” (2004, p. 183). This statem ent w as based on the evidence of h is­ graphical account, see Gregor 2005, pp. 18-21.
torical extinctions of ethnic com m unities, e.g. M elanesian an d A ustronesian 112. Hitler 1933, pp. 338-361. For differences in the list count in various edi­
populations after contact w ith E uropeans. D arw in attrib u ted such cases not tions, see Manheim’s footnote in Hitler 1992, p. 296.
just to defeat in m ilitary confrontations b u t proposed th a t, “if savages o f any 113. Hitler 1933, p. 346; 1992, p. 286.
race are induced to suddenly change th eir habits of life, they become m ore 114. Hitler 1933, p. 357; 1992, p. 295.
or less sterile, an d their young offspring suffer in health” (ibid., p. 220). 115. For the sources of the denunciation of Jews as sexual predators in racial anti-
The survival success of “civilised races” w as thus not due to any inherent Semitic literature available to Hitler, see Hamann 1996, pp. 472-487.
“higher” values but to accidentally improved resilience under changing living 116. Originally, the term Blutschande appears to have meant only “incest” but
conditions, w hich m ade D arw in com pare them to “dom esticated anim als, was then extended metonymically; see Grimm 1984, vol. 2, pp. 190-191.
for though the latter sometim es suffer in health . . . , they are rarely rendered 117. See Hitler 1933, p. 334; 1992, p. 277.
sterile” (ibid.). 118. Hitler 1933, pp. 253, 335; 1992, pp. 277, 289.
84. See the depiction of the emergence of the genius and the hero, w hich “can 119. Hitler 1933, pp. 22, 361; 1992, pp. 21, 299.
best be observed in w a r”; in H itler 1933, pp. 321-322; 1992, pp. 2 6 6 -267. 120. See Chapter 9 following.
85. H itler 1933, pp. 21, 361; 1992, pp. 21, 299. 121. For overviews of the intentionalist-v.-functionalist debate in Holocaust stud­
86. H itler 1933, p. 232; 1992, p. 193. ies, see Browning 1992, pp. 86-121; Cesarani 1996, pp. 1-29; Kershaw
87. H itler 1933, pp. 3 2 3 -3 2 4 ; 1992, p. 268. 2000, pp. 93-133; Friedlander 2000; Longerich 2005, pp. 11,14-17.
88. H itler 1933, p. 312; 1992, p. 259.
89. H itler 1933, pp. 316-317; 1992, p. 262.
90. H itler 1933, pp. 3 2 3 -3 2 4 ; 1992, pp. 2 6 8-269.
91. H itler 1933, pp. 4 3 6 -4 3 8 ; 1992, pp. 3 6 0 -3 6 2 . NOTES TO CHAPTER 4
92. H itler 1933, p. 437; 1992, p. 360.
93. H itler 1933, p. 437; 1992, p. 360. 1. See Behnken 1980; Boberach 1984; Kulka and Jackel 2004.
94. H itler 1933, p. 438; 1992, p. 361. 2. See Laqueur 1980; Kershaw 1983, 2008; Hilberg 1992, 2003; Gellately
95. Sontag 1978, pp. 71-76. 1990, 2001; Bankier 1992,1996; Friedlander 1998, 2007; Longerich 2005,
96. H itler 1933, p. 337; 1992, p. 279. 2006; Evans 2005, 2008.
97. See H itler 1933, pp. 2 6 6 -2 6 8 ; 1992, pp. 2 2 2 -2 2 3 . 3. For the methodological problems connected with use of SD and Sopade
98. See, e.g.. H itler 1933, pp. 268, 316, 346, 751; 1992, pp. 2 2 3 - 2 2 4 ,2 6 2 ,2 6 8 - reports, see Kulka and Jackel 2004, pp. 15-21; Longerich 2006, pp. 218-
269, 288, 605. 222; Kershaw 2008, pp. 121-123.
99. See, e.g.. H itler 1933, pp. 334, 335, 339, 3 40; 1992, pp. 276, 281, 282, 4. See Sington and Weidenfeld 1942; Diller 1980; Frei and Schmitz 1989; Abel
296. 1968; Longerich .1987; Balistier 1996; Bussemer 2000; Bytwerk 1996, 2001,
156 Notes Notes 157
■ 2004; Hachmeister and Kloft 2005; Herf 2006; Kallis 2008; Bachrach and 31. Friedlander 1998, p. 153.
Luckert 2009. 32. Gellately 2001, p. 49.
5. See Klemperer 1995. For its historical significance, see Friedlander 1998, pp. 33. O n Streicher an d Der Sturmer, see Bytwerk 2001.
58-59; for linguistic assessment, see Kamper 1996, 2001; Mieder 2000. 34. See Friedlander 1998, pp. 159-161; Przyrem bel 2003.
6. Klemperer 1975 (see earlier. Chapter 2). 35. See K ulka and Jackel 2004, pp. 1 1 2 ,1 2 9 ,1 4 8 -1 4 9 ,1 5 4 (complaints about race
7. Briining, Declaration (3. Sitzung, 16 October 1930), Verhandlungen des defilement hysteria [“Rassenschandepsychose”] by the GESTAPO), pp. 1 5 9 -
Reichstags, vol. 444, p. 19. 160; see also Gellately 2001, pp. 1 3 4 -141,145; Evans 2005, pp. 550-554.
8. Speech of 11 May 1930 in Goebbels 1933, p. 28. 36. See Behnken 1980, vol. 2 , pp. 1037,1042.
9. In the same speech of 11 May 1930, Goebbels alleged that the already weak­ 37. See published photographs of “race offenders”, in Schoenberner 1980, p. 35.
ened and badly treated nation was now under further attack from the Jewish In the w ake of the 1935 N urem berg rally, nationw ide cam paigns against
“tuberculosis bacillus” (Goebbels 1933, pp. 28-30). See also Hitler’s famous alleged Jew ish Rassenschande were stepped up on a massive scale, as the
speech at the Industrieklub in Dusseldorf on 17 January 1932 (Domarus reports of the social D em ocrat resistance groups show (Behnken 1980, vol. 2,
1965, pp. 88-89; for the historical context and Hitler’s (limited) success in pp. 1028-1042); see also G ellately 2001, p. 63; Evans 2005, pp. 551-553.
winning direct contributions from the industrialists, see Kershaw 1999, pp. 38. See G oebbels 1971, vol. 1, p. 249; em phasis m arked by italics and audi­
355-360. ence’s reactions (in square brackets) as in the G erm an tex t edition based on
10. Speech of 23 February 1932 in the Reichstag, in Goebbels 1933, p. 44; recordings.
reprinted (with minor modifications based on an audio recording) in Goeb­ 39. See Kershaw 1983; Bankier 1996; Evans 2005; Longerich 2006.
bels 1971, vol. 1, p. 7. 40. T his rough typology has sim ilarities to the classifications of G erm an atti­
11. Speech on 31 July 1932, in Goebbels 1933, pp. 92-96. tudes tow ards “the Jew ish Q uestion” th a t have been proposed by K ulka and
12. See Hitler’s proclamation of 1 February 1933, in Domarus 1965, p. 193; Rodrigue (1984) an d Kwiet an d Eschwege (1995, pp. 4 2 -4 4 ); for critical
Goebbels on 30 January 1933 (Goebbels 1933, p. 125) and on 21 February discussion, see Kershaw 2 0 0 8 , pp. 2 1 2-214. The degree of inform edness
1933 (Goebbels 1939, vol. 2, p. 365); for the history of the phrase Reform an obviously has a bearing on opinion building, but it is still im p o rtan t to dis­
Haupt und Gliedern, see Rohrich, 2001, vol. 2, p. 677. tinguish the tw o aspects. The m ain concern here is th e inform ation value of
13. See Goebbels’s speech to the press on 6 April 1933, quoted after Schmitz- N azi policy announcem ents on the “Jew ish question” in H itler’s speeches
Berning 2000, p. 463. insofar as they were fram ed by the body-parasite m etaphor scenario, an d the
14. See Friedlander 1998, pp. 22-23; Longerich 2006, pp. 65-66. public reception of this fram ing.
15. Victor Klemperer, for instance, felt as if he was experiencing “a pogrom in 41. See Bankier 1992, pp. 72 -7 5 , 77; Longerich 2 0 0 6 , pp. 7 5 -9 2 ; Gellately
the deepest Middle Ages or tsarist Russia” and being under “worse pressure 2001, pp. 1 2 2 -1 2 3 ; for a different em phasis on “ indifference an d passivity”,
than as a soldier during the war” (Klemperer 1995, vol. 1, pp. 15-19 (30 see Evans 2005, p. 548. For a firsthand account from th e Jewish perspective,
March-7 April 1933). see Klem perer 1995, vol. 1, pp. 2 0 8 -2 2 3 .
16. See Evans 2005, p. 15; see also Burleigh 2001, pp. 281-285; Gellately 2001, 42. Behnken 1980, vol. 3, pp. 9 -1 0 , 2 0 -4 2 .
pp. 26-28. 43. See Behnken 1980, vol. 3, pp. 28, 973, 982, 1648; Friedlander 1997, pp.
17. See Gellately 2001, pp. 9-59. 180-182; Evans 2005, pp. 5 7 0 -5 7 3 .
18. See Domarus 1965, p. 299: “Indem wir uns so der Pflege des uns vom Schick- 44. See K lem perer 1995, vol. 1, p. 467; Friedlander 1997, pp. 2 5 3 -2 5 4 ; Kallis
sal anvertrauten eigenen Blutes hingeben, helfen wir am besten mit, auch 2 0 0 8 , pp. 1 9 4 -1 9 5 ,1 9 9 .
andere Volker vor Krankheiten zu bewahren, die . . . von Volk auf Volk 45. See th e Sopade rep o rts, w hich from M arch 1935 on include special chapters
iiberspringen”. on the “te rro r” an d from July of th a t year extensive e x tra chapters dealing
19. See Gellately 2001, pp. 48-49, 67, 80-83, 184-188. w ith the “te rro r ag ain st Jew s” or “persecutions of Jew s” (Behnken 1980,
20. Baumann 2000, p. 66. vol. 2 , pp. 8 0 0 -8 1 3 , 9 2 0 -9 3 7 , 9 9 6 -9 9 7 , 1 0 2 6 -1 0 4 4 ; vol. 3, pp. 2 0 -4 1 ,
21. Baumann 2000, p. 92. 9 7 3 -9 9 3 ,1 6 4 8 -1 6 6 4 ; vol. 4, pp. 9 3 1 -9 4 7 ,1 5 6 3 -1 5 7 6 ; vol. 5, pp. 176-207,
22. Baumann 2000, p. 70 (emphasis in the original). 7 3 2 -7 7 1 , 1177-1210, 1329-1357; vol. 6, p p ._ 2 _ 0 1 -2 ^, ,89 8 - 9 4 0; vol. 7,
23. See Hitler’s declaration of 13 July 1934, in Domarus 1965, p. 421. pp. 2 5 6 -2 6 8 . -
24. See Domarus 1965, pp. 421-422. 46. See M airg u n th er 1987; O bst 1991; G ilbert 2007; Friedlander 1997, pp.
25. See Behnken 1980, vol. 1, pp. 197-203; Kershaw 1999, pp. 519-522; Evans 2 6 7 -2 6 8 .
2005, pp. 36-41. 47. See Gellately 2001, p. 128; Longerich 2005, pp. 6 0 -6 3 .
26. See Klemperer 1995, vol. 1, p. 121. 48. Evans 2005, p. 581. T he fu rth er m easures tak en by the N azi governm ent
27. See Kershaw 1999, pp. 568-573; Friedlander 1998, pp. 146-170; Longerich after “C rystal N ig h t” left no d oubt th a t it w anted to be seen to capitalize
2006, pp. 92-100. on the results in m ore th a n one sense. W hilst the arrested men were quickly
28. Hitler’s Proclamation on 11 September 1935, in Domarus 1965, p. 525. released on the condition th a t they em igrate, G erm an Jew ry as a whole was
29. Hitler’s Proclamation on 11 September 1935, in Domarus 1965, pp. fined one billion Reichsm ark and ordered to pay for all the dam age, which
525-526. largely destroyed their economic basis. Soon they were b anned from pub­
30. See Evans 2005, pp. 547-548; for the respective discussions at the Wannsee lic facilities, tran sp o rt, state education, social w elfare, and th eir businesses
conference, see Patzold and Schwarz 1992; Roseman 2002, pp. 55-107; were subjected to “A ryanization”, i.e. the forced sale at knockdow n prices
Friedlander 2007, pp. 349-353. (Friedlander 1997, pp. 2 5 7 -2 6 8 , 308-326).
158 Notes Notes 159
49. See Behnken 1980, vol. 5, pp. 1204-1211; vol. 6, pp. 211-226; Bankier 1992, 70. See, e.g., the newsreel-based film Campaign in Poland {Peldzug in Polen),
pp. 86-88; Friedlander 1997, pp. 295-298; Gellately 2001,' pp. 127-129; directed by Fritz H ippier; see http://w w w .im db.com /title/tt0199517/; for an
Kershaw 2005, pp. 587-592; 2008, pp. 173-182. overview over N azi w ar p ropaganda, see K allis 2008.
50. Volkischer Beobachter, 11 November 1938. 71. For overviews, see W ulf 1966; H ollstein 1971; M annes 1999; Tegel 2007;
51. The international public, of course, did not rely on the Nazi press’s version: Welch 2007; Vande W inkel and Welch 2007.
- foreign journalists, tourists and diplomatic staff had plenty of opportunities 72. See Evans 2 0 0 8 , p. 161.
to observe the main events and were relatively free to report these at home 73. See Brow ning 1992, pp. 1-27; K ulka and Jackel 2 0 0 4 , pp. 6 3 4 -6 3 6 .
even if the Nazis were unhappy about it. Still, the world public was arguably 74. See K ulka and Jackel 2 0 0 4 , pp. 6 2 6 -6 3 2 ; Friedlander 2007, pp. 53-127.
one of the-main addressees of the Nazi message of Kristallnacht, as a cyni­ 75. T h e m ini-series co n stitu tes an exception am o n g th e film p ro d u ctio n o f the
cal response to the “League of Nations” conference at Evian in July 1938, T h ird R eich, th e vast m ajo rity o f w hich w as devoted to the glorification
which had failed to offer any significant emigration route for Jews from Nazi of G erm an /A ry an heroism , co m radeship an d leadership on th e one h an d ,
Germany (see Friedlander 1997, pp. 248-250). an d escapist en tertain m en t films on th e o th e r (W elch 2007, pp. 2 6 6 -2 2 7 ;
52. Kaplan 1998, p. 44. V ande W inkel an d W elch 2007, p. 14).
53. See Laqueur 1980, pp. 17-40, for the discussion of the strange “secrecy” 76. See Welch 2007, pp. 2 2 2 -2 2 9 , 2 3 9 -2 5 7 ; Tegel 2007, pp. 151-153. A fter the
status of the Flolocaust in Germany. . w ar, Fritz H ippier, th e filmjs director an d chief of film production under the
54. Kershaw 2008, pp. 129-130. N azis from 1939 until 1943, w ho also directed the early Blitzkrieg docum en­
55. Kershaw 2008, p. 130. taries, used H itler an d G oebbels’ input to claim th a t he had had practically
56. Hitler on 30 January 1939, Domarus 1965, p. 105; translation after Herf no in p u t in The Eternal Jew an d w as “em barrassed to get the credit” fo r the
2006, p. 52. film (H ippier 1981, p. 207). T he scenes from the ghettos in occupied Poland
57. See, e.g., Friedlander 1997, p. 310; Kershaw 2000, pp. 152-153; Burleigh h ad , however, been filmed under his personal direction (ibid., pp. 187-189).
2001, p. 340; Longerich 2005, pp. 70-71; Evans 2005, pp. 604-605; Herf 77. See C hilton 2005; R ash 2 0 0 6 , pp. 172-181; M usolff 2007, pp. 3 4 -4 0 .
2006, pp. 5-6,52-53. 78. See Tegel 2007, p. 153.
58. See Evans 2003, pp. 60-76; Chickering 2004, pp. 189-192. 79. Der Deutsche Film, 6 Decem ber 1940, quoted after Welck 2007, p. 252.
59. Domarus 1965, p. 1056. , 80. See H ippier 1981, pp. 187-189; Welch 2007, pp. 16 6 ,1 7 3 .
60. Domarus 1965, pp. 1056-1057. 81. Longerich (2003, p. 71) accords a “new q u ality ” to the 1939 prophecy
61. Domarus 1965, p. 1057. because “it no longer was aim ed only a t p u ttin g fu rth er pressure on the Jews
62. Domarus 1965, p. 1057. for em igration” b u t threatened to use them “as hostages an d thereby prevent
63. Domarus 1965, p. 1058. an intervention by the W estern pow ers against his w ar policy”. T his is a
64. Klemperer 1995, vol. 1, p. 461 (entry of 5 February 1939). By this time, plausible interpretation o f the N azis’ short-term intentions in 1939 b ut the
Klemperer was under no illusions as to the general threat to his wife and explicit “an n ih ilatio n ” th rea t p o in ts to a com prehensive genocidal agenda.
himself and any Jews in Germany; since November 1938 he had been making 82. See Tegel 2007, pp. 166-167; Friedlander 2007, pp. 101-103. A ccording to
increasingly desperate efforts to emigrate (see ibid., pp. 436-460). N azi p ropaganda, the figure fo r Berlin cinem as in w hich the film opened was
65. See Shirer 1999, p. 25; Boberach 1984, vol. 2, pp. 367-390, and Behnken sixty-six (see W ulf 1966, p. 457).
1980; vol. 5, pp. 684-699, 809-841, 913-918 (for the disappointment of 83. Welch 2007, pp. 2 4 4 -2 4 5 ; Tegel 2007, p. 166.
German opposition groups over the Western powers’ retreat before Hitler’s 84. Welch 2007, pp. 2 5 2 -2 5 3 ; see also Evans 2 0 0 8 , pp. 5 7 1-572.
threats, see ibid., pp. 939-947). During the negotiations over the Sudeten- 85. Friedlander 2007, p. 102.
landy Hitler, to his chagrin, had been forced to accept an internationally 86. Mitteilungsbldtter fur die weltanschauliche Schulung der Ordnungspolizei,
guaranteed treaty and to pretend in public that he, too, wanted to preserve Folge 27; 1 D ecem ber 1941; quoted after M atth au s 2 0 0 4 , p. 3 00; see also
“peace in our time”, like the British, French and Italian politicians who co­ Brow ning 2001, p. 179.
signed the Munich Treaty (see Klemperer 1995, pp. 425-427; Kershaw 2000, 87. See H ilberg 1992.
pp. 122-123; Evans 2005, pp. 676-678). 88. See K ulka an d Jackel 2 0 0 4 , p. 4 4 0 ; B oberach-1984,-pp.-t917= 1^9.
66. See Domarus 1965, pp. 1307, 1312-1307; Shirer 1999, pp. 68-75; Kershaw 89. See K ulka an d Jackel 2004, p. 441.
2000, pp. 197-230. 90. SD Aufienstelle H oxter, 7^ February 1941, in K ulka an d Jackel 2 0 0 4 , p. 441.
67. See Domarus 1965, pp. 1163,1829; for interpretations, see Domarus 1965, 91. See, e.g., the reports in K ulka an d Jackel 2 0 0 4 , pp. 5 1 6 -5 2 0 , 525, 546.
p. 28; Kershaw 1999, pp. 152-153; 487,494; Friedlander 1998, p. 309; 2007, 92. T his difference is exploited, disingenuously, by H olocaust deniers still to this
pp. 132, 331-333; Longerich 2006, pp. 201-204. day (Lipstadt 1995; Longerich 2003, pp. 8-19): they insist on the pretence
68. Domarus 1965, p. 1663; Friedlander (2007, p. 132) emphasizes the (relative) th a t the ostentatious justification an d prophecy, o f the genocide in the term s
vagueness of the threat at this point but leaves it open whether the “change of a n analogical argum ent had “o nly” figurative m eaning, i.e. no “tru th -
of vocabulary was intentional or not”. The issue is not a change in Hitler’s value” in the sense of ethical or political com m itm ents.
genocidal intentions but rather the fact that before the attack on the USSR 93'. Friedlander 2007, pp. 2 0 8 -2 0 9 .
the fate of the Jews of continental Europe simply was not yet in Hitler’s 94. H itler speeches on 2 an d 3 O ctober; see D om arus 1965, pp. 1756,1760.
hands. 95. See Brow ning 1992, pp. 8 6 -1 2 1 ; 2 0 0 4 , pp. 3 0 9 -3 5 2 , M atth au s 2 0 0 4 , pp.
69. See Domarus 1965, pp. 1663-1664. 2 5 3 -3 0 8 . ^
Notes 161
160 Notes
112. See Friedlander 2007, pp. 330-447.
96. See Browning 2001, p. 179 and 2 0 0 4 , pp. 2 9 9 -3 0 0 . 113. Speech of 30 September 1942, see Domarus 1965, p. 1920; compare also
97. See his speech on “heroes’ rem em brance d ay ”, 15 M arch 1942, in w hich he
adm itted th a t for the p ast four m onths, i.e. since N ovem ber 1941, the adver­
ibid., pp. 1058,1163.
sary had been able to enforce a m ilitary “ tu rn a ro u n d ” {[Zeit fiir den Gegner]
114. Domarus 1965, p. 1920.
seinerseits die Wende in diesem . . . Ringen herbeizufuhren)-, th is change 115. Friedlander 2007, p. 402. j • c
116. See SD reports on and subsequent “rumours” of genocide in Germany trom
w ould be reversed in the com ing G erm an sum m er offensive (D om arus 1965, 1942 onwards in Kulka and Jackel 2004, pp. 489, 491, 510, 528-529, 531,
p. 1850). 533.
’9'8. T he significance of the 1941 setbacks in th e Russian cam paign an d the US’s
entry into the w ar for N azi propaganda an d public perception of it m ust n ot
117. See Domarus 1965, p. 1978.
be confused w ith the theory th a t the H olocaust w as only decided upon in
118. Goebbels 1971, vol. 2, pp. 178-179.
119. Goebbels 1971, vol. 2, pp. 182,188. • ^ , , qqo
Decem ber 1941; see Brow ning 1992, pp. 7 7 -8 5 ; for the dating of the final 120 See Goebbels’ diary entries from January to March 1943, in Goebbels lyyS
decision to put the com plete genocide of E uropean Jew ry into practice in the ' 2004, part II, vol. 7, pp. 368-374; for analyses of the public impact, see
context of the victory euphoria of Ju ly -early O ctober 1941, see Browning Moltmann 1964; Fetscher 1998, pp. 125-159; Hachmeister and Kloft 2005;
2 004, pp. 309-329. O n 22 July 1941, H itler is on record for explaining to
a visiting C roatian m arshal th e necessity of a pan-E uropean destruction of
Kallis 2005, pp. 130-137.
121. Klemperer 1995, vol. 2, pp. 332-333. , . ,
Jew ry in term s of the bacillus m etaphor: “ if even just one state . . . tolerates 122. See Kulka and Jackel 2004, pp. 516-520,525. For evidence of similarly scep­
one Jew ish fam ily in it, then this w ill become the bacillus for a new decom ­ tical reactions to the Nazi propaganda use of discoveries of Soviet atrocities
position” (ibid., p. 315). against Germans in Nemmersdorf, Eastern Prussia, in late 1944, see ibid., p.
99. See D om arus 1965, pp. 1828-1829.
100. See D om arus 1965, p. 1829. In his message of 24 February to the p arty faith ­ 546.
ful on the anniversary of the foundation of the NSDAP, H itler reiterated his
123. See Steinert 1970, p. 257. _
124. IMT (1948), vol. 29, pp. 145-146 (1919-PS); see also Friedlander 2007, pp.
m ix of annihilation prophecy and peace-through-victory prom ise, w hich he
542-544; Kershaw 2008, pp. 206-207.
then neatly rounded off in the clinical image o f “elim ination” (Beseitigung)
125. See Kulka and Jackel 2004, pp. 524-525, 535,537, 540, 547; Kershaw 2008,
of th e (ibid., p. 1844).
101. SD report of 2 February 1942, in Boberach 1984, pp. 3 2 3 3 -3 2 3 5 ; in K ulka
p. 202.
126. See Kulka and Jackel 2004, p. 543. •
and Jackel 2 004, p. 485. 127. See SD reports documenting popular opinions that the Allied bombing raids
102. See Friedlander 2007, pp. 2 5 1 -2 5 3 , 2 6 3 -2 6 4 , 3 0 6 -3 1 4 ; Bankier 1992, pp. were meant to revenge the German persecution of the Jews (Kulka and Jackel
124-138; Brow ning 2 004, pp. 111-151. 2004, pp. 526, 528, 540; also Bankier 1992, pp. 144-146).
103. See Gellately 2001, p. 142; Friedlander 2007, p. 289. 128 See Goebbels’ speeches on 5 November 1943, 3 October 1944, 28 Febru­
104. See Das Reich 16 N ovem ber 1941, “ It’s the Jew s’ fault” (Die Juden sind ary 1945 in Goebbels 1971, vol. 2, pp. 286-304, 405-446; on the function
schuld). The annihilation prophecy also appeared in G oebbels’ diaries, cul­ of sports imagery for Nazi propaganda, see Klemperer 1975, pp. 246-249;
m inating in the entry of 7 M arch 1942, w hen he recorded the adm inistrative on its use in Goebbels’ speech in February 1945, which he interprets as an
blueprint for the genocide agreed by the T h ird Reich’s top SS-and civilian expression of “sheer desperation” (vollige Verzweiflung), see Klemperer
jurists and adm inistrators a t the so-called “W annsee conference” on 20
January 1942 (i.e. system atic deportation of all E uropean Jews to the East,
1995, vol. 2, pp. 689-690.
their tem porary use as w orkers, eventual killing of all Jew ish persons). In his
129. Klemperer 1995, vol. 2, p. 251.
diary, he hailed it as the best possible outcom e of the “life-or-death struggle
T30. Domarus 1965, p. 2083.
betw een th e A ryan race and the Jewish bacillus” (see G oebbels 1 9 9 3 -2 0 0 4 ,
131. Domarus 1965, p. 2084. 1 • c.
132 Klemperer noted the well-publicized Nazi rage at Allied declarations after
p a rt II, vol. 1. p. 269; vol. 3, p. 561; for the "W annsee conference”, see the Normandy landings, which nullified all laws discriminating Jews (see
Friedlander 2007, pp. 339-3 4 3 ; Rosem an 2 0 0 2 , pp. 4 8 -5 4 , 68-107). entry for 20 July 1944, in Klemperer 1995, vol. 2, p. 5 4 7 ^ .
105. D om arus 1965, p. 1867. 133. Domarus 1965, pp. 2196-2197. '
106. D om arus 1965, pp. 1868-1869. 134. Domarus 1965, p. 2196.
107. Klem perer 1995, vol. 2, p. 74. 135. See Domarus 1965, pp. 2203-2207, 2223-2224, 2236-2239.
108. Klem perer 1995, vol. 2, p. 75. T he m ain topic of the diaries during this 136. See Gellately 2001, pp. 242-255; Friedlander 2007, pp. 648-656.
period is the massive increase of suicides of Jewish people fearing im m i­ 137. Klemperer 1995, vol. 2, pp. 721; see also ibid., pp. 704, 709, 732.
nent “d eportation” or reeling from the nightm arish experience of “house 138. See Klemperer 1995, vol. 2, pp. 755, 759, 761, 768-769, 773, 797.
searches”, w hich included n o t just the devastation of houses an d apartm ents
but beatings and open hum iliation of Jew s and their “A ryan” p artn ers, and
139. Klemperer 1975, pp. 8-14. , • 1 goo ^
140 See “Preface, 1945” in Sternberger, Storz and Suskind 1989, p. /.
often led to arrest, to rtu re, concentration cam p and “d ep o rtatio n ” (ibid., pp. 141. See Kershaw 2008, p. 206. In view of this devastating and relentless expo­
75-128). sure to the application of the genocidal scenario in the Nazi discourse during
109. Klem perer 1995, vol. 2 , p. 75. the last war years, the denial and suppression of Holocaust memories by
110. Bankier 1992, pp. 141-142. large sections of the population (Mitscherlich and Mitscherlich 1967; Niven
111. See Bankier 1992, pp. 140-145; Klem perer 1995, vol. 2, pp. 7 9 -8 0 , 122, 2002, 2006; Longerich 2006) becomes psychologically plausible: admission
153; K ulka and Jackel 2004, pp. 500, 503, 506.
162 Notes
Notes 163
of factual know ledge in com bination w ith th e (undeniable) aw areness of the the French Revolution, see H odson 2 0 0 7 (especially pp. 115-148) on the use
state leaders’- continuous prom ises of therapy-by-annihilation w ould have of m etaphors.
m ade it difficult to m aintain the stance th a t the general genocidal dim ensions 25. For the application of “adaptive com plex system s” theory to diachronic lin­
of the H olocaust w ere “inconceivable” for o rd in ary G erm ans. guistics and discourse history, see F rank 2 0 0 8 , 2009.

NOTES TO CHAPTER 5 NOTES TO CHAPTER 6


1. Goldhagen 2003, p. 80. 1. Lovejoy 1936, pp. 2 0 -2 1 .
2. Goldhagen 2003, pp. 81-87. 2. Lovejoy 1936, pp. 61 -6 6 .
3. See Evans 1997, pp. 149-180; Browning 2001, pp. 191-223; Friedlander 3. See Lincoln 1986; G uldin 2 0 0 0 . pp. 2 9 -3 2 . Such m yths are o f course not
2007, p . X X .
an Indo-E uropean specialism eitner b ut caiTbe found in m any cultures. For
4. See Arendt 1973; Poliakov 1974/75, vol. 3; Birnbaum 1992; Milfull 1993- body-based m yths of ancient M exico, for instance, see M iller an d Taube
Winock 1998; Lindemann 2001; Kertzer 2003. ’ 1993, pp. 4 5 -4 6 , 91-97.
5. Tillyard 1982, p. 107.
4. The Republic, 5 5 4 ', in Plato 1993, p. 278. For pre-Socratic notions o f the
6. Sontag 1978, p. 75.
7. Sontag 1978, p. 78. body of the state, e.g. in the Areopagiticus of Isocrates, see H ale 1971, pp.
1 9 -2 0 ; G uldin 2 0 0 0 , pp. 3 9 -4 8 .
8. Sontag 1978, pp. 71-72. Since the publication of Sontag’s essay, the ideo- 5. Politics, C hapter 1.2; 1253^2, in A ristotle 1995, p. 10.
^gically and ethically dubious status of bio-medical metaphors in public 6. Politics, C hapter 1.5; 1254'’2, in A ristotle 1995, p. 16; and On the Movement
discourse has become an object of intensive study in “Critical Discourse of Animals, quoted in H ale 1971, p. 24; com pare also G uldin 2 0 0 0 , p. 49.
Analysis”; see Charteris-Black 2005; Chilton 2005; Guldin 2000: Hawkins 7. Politics, C hapter 'V.3; 1302'’33, in A ristotle 1995, p. 184.
2001; Musolff 2003, 2004a, b, 2005; Niemeier 2000; Pauwels and Simon- ^ See Z avadil 2009, pp. 2 2 0 -2 2 3 .
Vandenbergen 1995; Peries 1991. ^ F o r the “fable of the belly” trad itio n , see Aesop 2 0 0 2 , p. 35. For its concep­
9. Skinner^1978, p. xi. For further methodological criticism of traditional “History tu al history see N estle 1927: Peil 1985: Schoenfeldt 1997; G uldin 2 0 0 0 , pp.
of Ideas” approaches, see also Hampsher-Monk, Tilmans and van Vree 1998. 101-103; K oschorke et al. 2007, pp. 32 -3 5 .
10. Lakoff and Turner 1989, pp. 166-167. 10. See the Bible (2001), Romans 1 2 :4 -5 ; 1 Corinthians 12:12-28; for analyses,
11. Lakoff and Turner 1989, p. 167. see H ale 1971, pp. 2 9 -3 2 ; Bass 1997, pp. 2 0 1 -2 0 2 ; K antorow icz 1997, pp.
12. See Johnson 1987; Lakoff and Johnson 1999; Grady and Johnson 2003- 7 1 -7 3 ,1 7 6 , 209.
Gibbs 2005. ’ 11. See H ale 1971, pp. 2 8 -3 2 ; C aird 1980, pp. 153, 187; Bass 1997, pp. 2 0 1 -
Kovecses 1995, 2005, 2006; Geeraerts and Grondelaers 1995; Gevaert 202; K antorow icz 1997, pp. 87-93.
12. A ugustine 1998, p. 938 {De Civitate Dei, X IX .13); see also Kempshall 1997,
14. See Yu 2008. pp. 3 2 4 -3 2 6 ; G uldin 2 0 0 0 , pp. 5 4 -5 5 ; Z avadil 2009, p. 229.
15. See Fabiszak 2007; Goatly 2007. 13. A ugustine 1998, p. 938.
16. See Kdvecses 2009; Shogimen 2008; Foolen 2008; Semino 2008; Musolff 14. See Skinner 1978, vol.T , pp. 3 -1 2 .
and Zinken 2009; Mouton 2009. 15. See K antorow icz 1997, pp. 4 9 6 -5 0 6 ; Skinner 1978, vol. 1, pp. 1 -6 5 ; Kemp­
17. Kovecses 2009, pp. 22-23. shall 1997, p. 3 4 8 -3 6 2 ; Struve 1978, passim.
18. Croft 2000, pp. 23-29. 16. Lovejoy 1936, p. 59.
19. Croft 2000, p. 38. See K antorow icz 1 9 y , pp. 1 3 9 -231, 2 7 3 -3 1 0 ; M a itla n d 2003, pp. 32-37.
20. Croft and Cruse 2004, p. 204.
21. Croft and Cruse 2004, pp-204-220.^ The methodological corollary of this
approach is a change of focus in metaphor studies: whereas “Lakoff argues
that It is precisely because metaphors . . . have become fixed in the lan­
t Jo h n of Salisbury 1990 (English translation), L atin edition by W ^ b : see John
of Salisbury 1965 (= reprint of 1909 edition).^ ---------- ' "
19. For Jo h n of S alisbury’s life an d career, see W ilks 1984; N ederm an 1990, pp.
xv i-x v iii; for the te x tu al history of Policraticus, see N ederm an 1990, pp.
guage (and because they are so widespread) that they'. .. reflect fundamen­ x v iii-x ix .
tal properties of the human mind”, Croft and Cruse point out that there is 20. Jo h n of Salisbury 1990, p. 230; ap a rt from T hom as Beckett, the Policraticus
a “separate and worthwhile study to be done on novel metaphors” (ibid., p. w ould presum ably have been accessible m ainly to high-ranking clerics and
206). ’ courtiers.
22. Croft and Cruse 2004, p. 204. 21. Liebeschutz (1950, pp. 2 3 -2 4 ) declared the “in stru ctio n ” to be a literary fic­
23. Croft and Cruse 2004, p. 205. tion designed “to disguise the personal character of his political criticism ”.
24. To assess the relative strength of the different metaphor versions in public K antorow icz (1997, p. 199); H ale (1971, pp. 39 -4 1 ); N ederm an (1990, p.
discourse would involve quantitative, statistical investigation, which would xxi); an d K oschorke et al. (2007, p. 78) accept this interpretation; for a dif­
be desirable but cannot be provided here. For an insightful exploration of fering view com pare Bass (1997, p. 206).
quantitative analysis with regard to British political discourse at the time of 22. Jo h n of Salisbury 1990, pp. 6 6 -6 7 .
164 Notes Notes 165
23. See K antotow icz 1997, pp. 9 4 -9 7 , 1 9 4 -2 0 0 ; H ale 1971, p. 4 0; N ederm an 56. See Latini, Li livre dou Tresor; quoted after Nederman and Forhan 1993, p.
1 9 8 8 ,1 9 9 0 . 73; for the politico-philosophical background of Latini, see Skinner 1978,
24. See H u izin g a 1933; L iebeschutz 1950, p. 2 2 - 2 4 ; S o u th ern 1970; N ed er- vol. l,pp. 36-41,44-48.
m an 1990, p. xvi; Bass 1997, pp. 2 0 3 -2 0 6 . For a stro n g em phasis on 57. See Kempshall 1997, pp. 130-203.
Jo h n ’s “rad ically inn o v atin g and com p assio n ate social visio n ”, see Bass 58. Boniface 1959, pp. 1245-1246.
(1997, pp. 2 0 7 -2 1 0 ). K antorow icz (1997, pp. 2 0 0 , 311), on th e oth er 59. See Kempshall 1997, p. 265.
h a n d , highlights Jo h n ’s dependence on th e P auline co n cep t of th e church 60. See Kempshall 1997, pp. 147-148, 267-271, 272-273,
~ as C h rist’s body; likew ise, Struve (1984, p. 309) an d H ale (1971, pp. 61. See Kempshall 1997, p. 249.
3 9 -4 0 ) underline Jo h n ’s unflinching belief in hierarchy an d lo y alty to 62. John of Paris, De Potestate Regia et Papali (1302/3), quoted after Nederman
church and state au th o rity ; G u ld in (2 0 0 0 , pp. 5 7 -5 8 ) specifically stresses and Forhan 1993, p. 162. See also Kempshall 1997, pp. 282-292.
th e “p a te rn a listic ” tenor. 63. Kempshall 1997, p. 355.
25. Jo h n of Salisbury 1990, p. 126. 64. Marsilius of Padua 2005, p. 12: “A city and its parts would . . . seem to be in
26. Tillyard 1982, p. 103. the same relation to tranquility as an animal and its parts is to health.. . . For
27. Jo h n o f Salisbury 1990, p. 135. . . . health is an animal’s optimal condition according to nature, and likewise
28. Jo h n o f Salisbury 1990, p. 135. . . . tranquility is the optimal condition of the city established according to
29. John o f Salisbury 1990, p. 136. reason.”
30. See H ale 1971, p. 4 0 , and G uldin 2 0 0 0 , pp. 57-58. 65. Marsilius of Padua 2005, p. 136; compare also Nederman and Forhan 1993,
31. See the use of the fable by Jo h n ’s contem porary M arie de France (1993, p. p. 198. For the political context see Skinner 1978,1, pp. 56-62.
25). 66. Remigio dei Girolami, De Bono Communi, De Bono Pads, Contra Falsos
32. In term s of target concepts, thb m ain m odel depicts the state’s “treasurers Ecclesie Professores, quoted after Kempshall 1997, p. 335.
and record-keepers”, w hilst the fable targets the p o p e’s adm in istratio n , but 67. See Albertus Magnus’s comments on Aristotle’s Ethics, Super Ethica, quoted
despite this difference, the im port of the tw o passages is fairly sim ilar; they in Kempshall 1997, p. 111.
explain the dangers th a t arise if the digestive system of the political body 68. William of Ockham, Eight Questions on the Power of the Pope, quoted after
does n o t function properly. Skinner 1978,1, p. 130.
33. Jo h n of Salisbury 1990, p. 67. William of Ockham, Eight Questions on the Power of the Pope, quoted after
34. Jo h n of Salisbury 1990, p. 63. ^ Skinner 1978,1, pp. 130-131.
John of Salisbury 1990, p. 137. For general w arnings about injuries to the 70. Bartolus of Saxoferrato, Commentaries on the Second Part of the New
body of the res publica see ibid., pp. 8 4 ,1 2 6 . Digest; quoted after Skinner 1978,1, p. 131.
36. John of Salisbury 1990, pp. 140-141. 71. The Golden Bull of the Emperor Charles IV, quoted after Skinner 1978,1, p.
37. John of Salisbury 1990, p. 141. 131.
38. John of Salisbury 1990, pp. 193-194. 72. See Dhorn van Rossum and Bockenforde 1978, pp. 546-548, 552-554;
39. See Jo h n ’s criticism of am bitious an d/or hypocritical clerics th a t £ause Koschorke et al. 2007, pp. 91-92) for the uses of body imagery on late-medi­
“calam ities in the H ouse of G od”: C hapters 17, 21 in Book VII of th e Poli- eval debates about the relationship between pope, empire and Christendom,
craticus (1990, pp. 162-175). especially in the writings of Juan de Torquemada (1388-1468) and Nicholas
40. Sontag 1978, p. 76. of Cusa (1401-1464).
41. See Jo h n ’s fam ous exhortation in favour of tyrannicide (under th e right cir­ ( f p Forhan 1994, pp. xvi-xvii.
cum stances) in Book V III of the Policraticus (1990, pp. 190-225). For biographical and political details, see Lockwood 1997, pp. xvi-xvii.
42. John o f Salisbury 1990, pp. 81,135 . 75. Fortescue 1997, pp. 20-21.
43. John of Salisbury 1990, pp. 2 8 -3 8 . 76. The Policraticus, however, is mentioned in the Livre de Corps de Policie
44. Jo h n of Salisbury 1990, pp. 127-132. (Christine de Pizan 1994, p. 27).
45. John of Salisbury 1990, p. 125. 77. Christine de Pizan 1994, p. 4. -----— ^
46. Jo h n of Salisbury 1990, p. 126. 78. See e.g., Christine de Pizan 1994, pp. 4-5, 15, 93, 105. In addition to her
47. T illyard 1982, p. 7. wide-ranging knowledge of the classical authors and John of Salisbury’s
48. See Skinner 1978, vol. 1, pp. 4 7-51 ; Kempshall 1997, pp. 2 7 -2 8 ,1 3 1 -1 3 3 . Policraticus, Christine de Pizan was also familiar with Giles of Rome and
49. See Kempshall 1978, pp. 2 6 -130. Brunetto Latini’s works, which were directly pertinent to the metaphor tradi­
50. A ristotle 1995, p. 184 {Politics, C hapter V.3; 1302'=33). tion; see Forhan 1994, p. xxi.
51. See Kempshall 1997, pp. 2 0 -2 1 , 257, Matthew 2:6, 26:31; John 10:11; Hebrews 13:20; 1 Peter 5:4.
52. See texts form A lbertus M agnus, Politicorum Libri Octo, Super Ethica com- ir'Ut-Jcri'n^. Pi75>n 1 Q'54 r> 4- for T . a r i n i . Nederman and Forhan 1993. D.
mentum et quaestiones\ T hom as A quinas, Summa contra Gentiles, Summa ^^73.
Theologica in N ederm an and Forhan 1993, pp. 97-148; see also Kempshall 81. Christine de Pizan 1994, p. 38.
1997, pp. 33, 41, 9 4 ,1 1 1 -1 1 2 ,1 2 2 ; K antorow icz 1997, p. 478. 82. Christine de Pizan 1994, p. 38.
53. See K em pshall 1997, pp. 132-133, especially footnote 13 ibid. v 83. Christine de Pizan 1994, Chapters 22-26, pp. 39-46.
54. N ederm an and Forhan 1993, p. 113. 84. Christine de Pizan 1994, p. 91. Note also the earlier reference to the gist of
55. T hom as A quinas, Summa Theologica, quoted after N ederm an and Forhan the fable of the belly in the initial prince-head analogy quoted earlier (1994,
1993, p. 135. p. 4)
166 Notes
Notes 167
85. Christine’s Book of the Body Politic inherits from John of Salisbury’s PoU T hom as N o rth ’s 1579 English translation of Plutarch’s Parallel Lives, see
craticus the inconsistency of using the belly as source input for two different Spurgeon 1935, pp. 34 7 -3 4 8 ; however, for its conceptual and literary inno­
vations com p. M otohashi 1994; Peltonen 2009.
e ruler (in the fable). As in the Poltcraticus, however, this inconsistencv 3. Peltonen (2009, pp. 251-252) points to sim ilarly pejorative references to the
^ substantive contradiction, for the source-target relationship is belly image in contem porary literature on versions of the fable.
^86. C h risd n eT p 7 zl'l9 9 t disambiguates any potential equivocation. 4. Coriolanus, 1 , 1 ,1 1 3 -1 2 4 .
87. John of Salisbury 1990, pp. 136, 140-141 5. Coriolanus, 1 ,1 ,1 3 2 ,1 5 5 .
6. Coriolanus, III, I, 2 9 2-307.
Deuteronomy 7. Hamlet, I, 3, 2 0 -2 4 (this an d the follow ing references to Shakespeare’s plays
generalizes them into “laws of nature’’ are quoted after Shakespeare 1983).
or. religions” (ibid., pp. 24-26) 8. K antorow icz 1997, p. 26.
89. Fortescue 1997, pp. 24-29. ^
Fortescue 1997, p. 20. 9. Richard II, IV, 1, 203 -2 1 1 ; see K antorow icz 1997, pp. 2 4 -4 0 .
(2 )J Fortescue 1997, p. 20. 10. Richard III, III, 7 ,1 2 4 -1 2 6 .
11. Tillyard 1982, p. 17. For Shakespeare’s use of th e body politic m etaphor in
l^rlTn^A references to Aristotle’s Politics and On the fu rth er plays, see H u n t 2 002; Spied 2007.
Animals and Augustine’s City of God 12. Troilus and Cressida, I, 3, 8 5 -8 6 .
93. Fortescue 1997, pp. 20-21.
94. Fortescue 1997, p. 21. 13. Troilus and Cressida, 1 ,3 ,9 4 -1 1 0 . An exam ple of such “discord” in the body
politic an d the whole Great Chain is provided by B rutus’s contem plation of
s^mrt1np7rom^A ^ t' inscribes himself in a tradition C aesar’s assassination in Julius Caesar, w hich he him self likens to the in te r­
k w -v i^ hrS ®"d continuing to Burke that links the idea of national nal conflict of a state: here the individual state o f m ind is likened to a politi­
noinfc n dy imagery to that of popular custom, which, as Pocock (2003) cal entity: “T he genius and the m o rtal instrum ents / Are then in council; and
points out, IS seen as the expression of “a particular judgment to which so the state of m an, / Like to a little kingdom , suffers then / The n atu re of an
many men’s experience testifies, that the probability of its conthiSng to give insurrection” {Julius Caesar, II, 1, 6 6 -6 9 ).
96. P o c S o a . 'p . " ! " ''' P- 14. T illyard 1982, pp. 17, 20.
15. T illyard 1982, pp. 2 3 -2 4 : “If the Elizabethans believed in an ideal order a n i­
97. In Fortescue’s didactic frame, the “argument from antiquity” serves to auell m ating earth ly order, they were terrified lest it should be upset, and appalled
counter-arguments: against the weight of collLtive experience by the visible tokens of disorder th a t suggested its upsetting. T hey were
that has been accumulated from the earliest times of the English body poli- obsessed by the fear of chaos an d the fact of m utability; and the obsession
th?r royal “apprentice” is forced to conceL w as pow erful in p ro portion as their faith in the cosm ic order w as strong”.
that he is persuaded to devote himself to the study of the laws as well as 16. Skinner 1 9 7 8 ,1, p. 239.
of leaving to his judges the detailed and definitive skill” of interpreting and 17. See H ale 1971, pp. 4 8 -5 0 ; com p, also Skinner 1978, II, pp. 85-89^ H ughes
applying the laws (Fortescue 1997, p 79) Hirerpreting and
98. Sontag 1978, pp. 75-76. 1988, p. 86; K antorow icz 1997, pp. 2 2 5 -2 3 1 ; M aitlan d 2003, p. 34.
18. We leave aside a fu rth e r “ex tern alisatio n ” aspect in early m odern concep­
99. Furthermore the Policraticus in itself was far from endorsing a simple onri- tu alisatio n s of th e body politic, i.e. th a t o f th e k ing as husband o f the body
emphasize the need for extreme, “unbLl- politic, as his wife. T his “gendered” version of the body-politic concept
^ e b e llin g S ? ’. "complete destruction” of any w as on th e one h an d com patible in principle w ith headship-, in the Pauline
trad itio n , th e h usband, .as head, w as also ruler of his w ife {Epistle to the
Ephesians 5 :2 3 -2 4 ); on the other h an d , th is ex tern alized , possessive stance
to w ard s th e head to its “fem inized” body politic w ould come to play a
NOTES TO CHAPTER 7 m ajor role in legitim ising absolutist ru le as in K ing Jam es I’s address to his
t p arliam en t tw o generations later: “I am th e H u sb an d , an d the w hole Isle is
1. With the exception of the discussion of Machiavelli’s innovation in concep­ my law full W ife; I am the head an d it is m y body” (M cHwacthTPlRjp. 272).
tualising the ruler as a healer this chapter concentrates on E^hsh sources For the gendered body politic trad itio n see'A x to n 1977; H arris 1998, pp.
This IS not intended to give the impression that English disco^se traditions 107-140.
represented or dominated all debates abopt the body politic in Renaissance 19. K antorow icz 1997, p. 229. T he blend of political and spiritual headship in
the new concept o f the King in tu rn m ade it possible to apply the much older
L'^indud^d®^’"' ^ ^“1 national strands would of course have to C hristological distinction betw een body natural an d body mystical directly
^ included, especially statements by thinkers such as, inter alia Bodin L d
to the King, w hich inspired the research in to the fam ous “Two Bodies”
w l5 7 6 metaphor (in Six livres de la Repub- trad itio n by M aitlan d , K antorow icz, Bertelli an d others. U nder the Tudor
C h l 1 9 7 0 -H a lfs 'S ■ international resonance (see m onarchs, it developed into an intricate legal system fo r distinguishing the
2007- Banks 2009 Koschorke et al. 2007, pp. 93-100; RobUs personal {body natural) an d political {body politic) obligations of the crown
2UU/, Banks 2009). For German contributions, see Chapter 9.
(see K antorow icz 1997, pp. 7 -2 5 ; 4 0 1 -4 0 9 ).
2. Coriolanusy 1,1,95-157; see also Chapter 1 above. For a reading ofShakfe-
speare s use of the body politic metaphor in Coriolanus as derivative of 20. See Bloch 1961; Bertelli 2001, pp. 2 6 -2 9 .
21. See H ale 1971, pp. 4 9 -5 1 ; Skinner 1978, II, p. 87.
168 Notes Notes 169

22. For the dating of text and dedication, see M ayer 1989a, pp. x -x ii; com pare possible to recover a free and ordered mode of life” (ibid., p. 157). Machia-
H errtage 1878, pp. Ixxi-lxxii.
velli’s notion of a headless but uncorrupted trunk that can survive and flour­
23. See H ale 1971, pp. 63, 6 7 -6 8 ; T illyard 1982, pp. 105-106; H arris 1998, pp.
ish successfully also puts paid to the idea that Renaissance writers were fully
35-36.
committed to humoral theory: in this instance, he clearly wasted no thought
24. Starkey 1989, p. 48: “sklendurnes . . . groundyd in the lake of pepul”.
on maintaining anatomical or medical source consistency. His one reference
25. Starkey 1989, p. 54: “for lyke . . . the body . . . w ith yl humorys lyth id u l. . .,
to “malignant humors” (ibid., p. 127) is unspecific and refers to a general
so ys a com m ynalty replenysched w ith neclygent 8c idul pepul”. human condition.
26. Starkey 1989, p. 55: “for lyke . . . some p arty s be ever movyng &C shakyng 51. Machiavelli 2003, pp. 254-257
. . ., so in ou r com m ynalty certain p arty s therbe, w ych ever be m ovyng 6c 52. Machiavelli 2003, p. 159.
sterryng”. 53. Sontag 1978, pp. 76-77.
27. Starkey 1989, p. 56: “dyscord &Cdebate in a com m ynalty”. 54. Berlin 1971, pp. 24-25.
28. Starkey 1989, pp. 56-57: “the p arty s of thys body be n ot proportyonabul one
55. See Skinner 1978,1, p. 138; comp, also Skinner 2000, pp. 63-66, and Pocock
to a nother”. 2003, pp. 204-311.
29. Starkey 1989, p. 57: “nother so abul to defend o u r selfe from injurys of ene- 56. Machiavelli 2005, pp. 21-30, 84-89; 2003, pp. 270-273; see also Skinner
mys, nother of other by featys of arm ys to recover our ryght agayn”. 2000, pp. 62-64.
30. Starkey 1989, p. 58: “for lyke . . . a m an consydereth n ot hymselfe nor can 57. Bacon 1972, p. 43.
tel w hat ys gud nother for hymselfe . . . so dow o u r offycerys & rularys, 58. Bacon 1972, p. 44.
. . ; apply them selfe to the fulfyllyng of theyr vayn pleasurys 6c folysch
59. Bacon 1972, p. 44. The overheated humours may be given “moderate lib­
fantasye”.
erty . . . to evaporate”, for holding them back “maketh the wound bleed
31. Starkey 1989, p. 58. “as hyt w ere, a com m yn disease for bothe the fete 6c
inwards” and thus “endangereth malign ulcers and pernicious impostuma-
they handys to w hom e I resemblyd plow m en 6c laburarys of the gro u n d ”. tions” (p. 46). For other references to the humours, see Essays III (p. 8) and
32. Starkey 1989, p. 48: “general fautys 6c m ysordurys 6c unyversal dekeys of XXXVI (p. 113).
the com m yn wele”.
60. Hale (1971, p. 108) claims that Bacon’s “materialism and rejection of the
33. See Starkey 1989, pp. 6 0 -1 2 2 .
Paracelsans destroy[ed] the philosophical underpinnings of the validity of
34. Starkey 1989, p. 33.
the [body-state] analogy”, but this interpretation is highly tenuous, as it begs
35. Starkey 1989, p. 33: “conseyl o f certayn w yse m en” o r “the hole pepul the question of consistency between Bacon’s epistemological theories of sci­
togyddur”. ence and his rhetorical practice. As Bacon’s (fragmentary) use of humoral
36. Starkey 1989, p. 123: “ thys is undow tydly tro th . . . yf thys <ground> were terminology in the Essays shows, he was far from using only scientific cat­
stablyschd 6c surely set, the cure of al other m ysordurys wych we notyd egories. For a thorough critique of attempts to neatly distinguish “pre-sci-
before w old by 6c by follow <6c easely insue>“. See also H errtag e 1878; entific” from “science”-iiispired foody-state analogies in the early modern
M ayer 1989a, 1989b, pp. 247-277. period, see Harris 1998, pp. 22-30.
37. Starkey 1989, p. 123: “th a t ys <troth> . . . for as physycyonys say, w hen they 61. Bacon 1972, p. 35.
have removyd the <chefe> cause of the m alady <6c disease in the body> by
lytyl 6c lytyl then nature hyrsulfe cu ry th the p aty en t”.
38. M achiavelli 2005, pp. 88-89.
39. M achiavelli 2005, p 12. See also his later reference to the quoted passage,
NOTES TO CHAPTER 8
w here he reinforces the im portance of the prince’s com petence to identify
early any “poison concealed u n dern eath ” th e body politic: “A nd thus anyone 1. For the former view, see, e.g., Strauss 1963; Hale 1971, pp. 128-130; Sontag
w ho does not diagnose the ills w hen they arise in a principality is n o t really 1978, pp. 77-78; for the latter, Harris 1998, pp. 141-143.
w ise, and this talent is given to few men” (2005, p. 49). 2. Hobbes 1996, pp. 9-10.
40. Sontag 1978, p. 76. 3. Prokhovnik 1991, p. 218; see also Baumgold 198§i_Mimz-1982;.Martinich
41. Sontag 1978, p. 75. 1992, pp. 48-49.
42. See M achiavelli 2003, pp. 5 2 6 -5 2 8 . 4. Johnston 1986, p. 67.
43. M achiavelli 2003, p. 527. 5. Skinner 1996, pp. 384-390.
44. M achiavelli 2003, pp. 157-15 9 ,1 9 3 . 6. Hobbes 1996, p. 36. For further criticisms of metaphor as deceptive and
45. M achiavelli 2003, p. 201. misleading in Leviathan, see ibid., pp. 26, 31, 35, 48, 52,177,180.
46. M achiavelli 2003, p. 208. 7. Johnson 1981, p. 11; see also Lakoff and Johnson 1980, pp. 11-12; Leezen-
47. M achiavelli 2003, p. 256. berg 2001, p. 1; Goatly 2007, p. 2.
48. M achiavelli 2003, p. 257.
8. See Cooper 1986, pp. 17-18; Bertau 1986, pp. 81-87; Muller-Richter 1998,
49. M achiavelli 2003, p. 157.
p. 11; for the rebuttal of earlier arguments in the same vein, see Prokhovnik
50. M achiavelli 2003, p. 153. A ccording to M achiavelli, the R om an republic was 1991, pp. 110-117; Skinner 1996, p. 363, notes 151-156.
only spared th at fate because, w hen it had liberated itself from the Tarquin-
9. See Johnston 1986, pp. 66-91; Skinner 1996, pp. 343-390, Feldman 2001;
ian kings after a relatively short tim e, it w as n o t yet corrupted by servitude,* Musolff 2004c, pp. 100-119.
so “since th e head w as lost w hile th e tru n k rem ained whole it w as easily 10. Hobbes 1996, p. 52.
170 Notes
Notes 171
11. H obbes 1996, pp. 50 -5 1 . T he distinction betw een misleading “m etaphor” 33. Hobbes 1996, pp. 226-227.
and helpful “sim ilitude” also reflects changes in H obbes’s ow n term inology. 34. Hobbes 1996, p. 228.
In his English version of A ristotle’s Rhetoric, published in 1637, H obbes 35. Hobbes 1996, p. 228.
treated similitude as differing from m etaphor only m inim ally, i.e. by the pro­ 36. Hobbes 1996, p. 228.
vision of “such Particles of Com parison, as these. As; Even as; So; Even so"; 37. Hobbes 1996, p. 228.
it is “a Metaphor dilated, and it does w ell in an O ration, so it be n ot too 38. Hobbes 1996, pp. 229-230.
frequent; fo r ’tis Poeticall” (H obbes 1986, p. 110; for the influence of A ris­ 39. Hobbes 1996, p. 230.
totle’s Rhetorics on H obbes, see Strauss 1963, pp. 3 5 -3 6 ; H arw o o d 1986, 40. Hobbes 1996, p. 9.
pp. 1 3 -3 2 ; Skinner 1996, pp. 239-242). By the tim e of w riting Leviathan, 41. Hobbes 1996, pp. 174-175.
he had, however, developed a m ore critical view of “m etap h o r” as serving to
42. In the case of the ague, the consequences of a blood blockage are “a cold
confuse, w ith the purpose of deception (H obbes 1996, pp. 26, 36), but his
contraction, and trembling of the limbes; and afterwards a hot, and strong
unchanged positive concept of similitude as a m eans to achieve argum enta­ endeavour of the Heart, to force a passage. . . till (if Nature be strong enough)
tive perspicuity still covered the non-deceptive uses of “m etaphor” in the
It break at last the contumacy of the parts obstructed, and dissipateth the
cognitive sense, i.e. any kind o f inter-dom ain m apping o r blending (comp.
H obbes 1986, p. 109 and 1996, p. 36).
venome into sweat; or (if Nature be too weak) the Patient dyeth”; in the case
12. H ale 1971, p. 130.
of pleurisy, the effects are less fatal but also very painful: the “Blood
getting into the Membrane of the breast, breedeth there an Inflammation,
13. See M artinich 1997, pp. 8 6 -9 8 ,1 0 0 -1 0 7 , Skinner 2 0 0 2 , pp. 5-37.
accompanied with a Fever, and painfull stitches” (Hobbes 1996. d 229)
14. For detailed analyses of the frontispiece, see B randt 1987; M in tz 1989; M al­ 43. Hale 1971, p. 128. ^
colm 2002. 44. Harris 1998, p. 143.
15. H ale 1971, p. 108.
16. See K antorow icz 1997, pp. 2 0 -2 3 .
45. Compare Hobbes (1996, p. 228) and Harris (1998, p. 143). Harris’s remark
17. H obbes 1996, p. 9. is part of an argument that reads Hobbes’s political pathology as indicative
18. H obbes 1996, pp. 9 ,1 1 7 -1 2 0 .
of an alleged gradual “breakdown not only of the logic of correspondence,
19. See H ale 1971, pp. 109, 129 -1 3 0 ; Jo h n sto n 1986, p. 124; G uldin 2 0 0 0 , pp.
but also to the endogenous pathological discourses which modelled disease
8 0 -8 9 ; G oatly 2007, pp. 3 62-363. C unningham (2004, pp. 176-177) has,
as an internal bodily state rather than as a determinate foreign body” (Har­
how ever, highlighted the problem s o f sim plistic notions of th e “m oderniza­
ris 1998, p. 143). However, Harris himself notes the “exception” of epilepsy
tio n ” of m edicine in the early seventeenth century. T his m odernization was
(1998, p. 175, note 4); Table 8.3 shows that, if anything, internal diseases
outweigh exogenous ones.
by no m eans a unitary enterprise: far fro m accepting D escartes’s m echanis­ 46. Hobbes 1996, p. 228.
tic views, H arvey, for instance, saw his ow n discovery o f blood circulation
47. Hobbes’s reference to conjoined siblings may have been influenced by Mon­
as a reassertion o f A ristotle’s understanding of the functions of the heart.
T he m echanistic interpretation w as th u s a later reassessm ent, w hich cannot
taigne’s interpretation of the case of such a “monstrous” child as a good
be projected retrospectively onto H arvey’s discovery, let alone attributed to
omen for the king’s supreme reign over diverse bodies in Essays (Montaiene
1965, II, pp. 480-481).
H obbes’s knowledge of it. T he fu rth er assum ption of a m etaphorical transfer 48. Hobbes 1996, p. 228.
of the presum ed new body concept o nto political th eo ry w ould appear to be 49. Hobbes 1996, p. 228.
even m ore speculative.
20. H obbes 1996, p. 89.
50. See Rousseau 1994a; for the French original, see Rousseau 1990. ‘
51. Rousseau 1994a, p. 55; see also ibid., p. 67.
21. H obbes 1996, C hapter 29 (pp. 221-230).
52. Rousseau 1994a, pp. 121-122 (1990, pp. 256-258). Rousseau’s essay on
22. H obbes 1996, p. 22 2 . Procreation here is equivalent to conception, whereas
in an earlier chapter H obbes used this term m etonym ically as a synonym for
Political Economy for Diderot and d’Alembert’s Encyclopedic contains a
more detailed list identifying the sovereign as the head, the laws as the brain,
the “Children of a Com m on-w ealth”, i.e. a t the targ et level, “Plantations, or
Colonies” (Hobbes 1996, p. 175). the working of the will as the nervous system, judges and public officers
23. H obbes 1996, p. 223.
as the organs, commerce, industry and agriculture as mouth Ar^_siom.ach,
public finances as the blood and the citizens as t^fTimbs', Butlte expli«tly
24. H obbes provides historical and contem porary examples (e.g. the Low C o u n ­
characterizes it as not particularly precise and being mainly of didactic value
tries as a m odel for English revolutionaries [H obbes 1996, pp. 2251). (see Rousseau 1994b, p. 6).
25. H obbes 1996, p. 225. 53. Rousseau 1994a, p. 76,104-105.
26. H obbes 1996, p. 165; see also H obbes’s reference to the link betw een the dif­ 54. Rousseau 1994a, p. 95.
ferent kinds of “M adnesse”, including “ m elancholy”, of individuals and an 55. Rousseau 1994a, p. 96.
“evill constitution of the organs of th e Body” (H obbes 1996, p. 54). 56. Rousseau 1994a, pp. 68, 75.
27. H obbes 1996, pp. 2 2 5 -2 2 6 . 57. Rousseau 1994a, p. 69.
28. H obbes 1996, p. 226. 58. Rousseau 1994a, p. 64.
29. H obbes 1996, p. 226. 59. Rousseau 1994a, p. 121.
30. H ale 1971, p. 128.
31. Sontag 1978, pp. 75-76.
60. Rousseau 1994a, p. 80; for Rousseau’s political illness imagery, see Starobin-
32. H obbes 1996, p. 226.
ski 1989, Ch. 5, and Harris 1998, pp. 144-145.
61. Rousseau 1994a, p. 80.
Notes 173
172 Notes
5. L uther 1917, vol. l , p p . 147-236. , . .... , ,
62. Rousseau 1994a, p. 64. 6 Luther 1917, vol. 1, p. 155: “w eltlich hirrschafft 1st em m itglid w orden des
63. Rousseau 1994a, p. 64. • il j - ■ i ’ christlichen corpers, d aru m b yhr w erck sol frey unvorhindert gehen in alle
64. Rousseau 1994a, p. 56; see also 1994b, p. 7: The political body . . . is also glidmaB des gantzen corpers, straffen und treyben, w o es die schuld vordienet
a moral being which has a will; and this general will, which tends always to odder n o t foddert, unangesehen Bapst, Bischoff, priester, sie drew en odder
the conservation and well-being of the whole and of each part of it . . . is, tor bannen, wie sie w ollen.”
all members of the state and in relation to it and them, the rule of what is just 7. Skinner 1978, II, p. 15.
8. L uther 1917, vol. 1, p. 153. tc 1 ^u.,*
65. - S ^ u 1994a, p. 127; see also p. 125: “On the instant that the people 9 The w orldly disenfranchisem ent of the church did n o t entail for Luther that
is lawfully assembled as the sovereign body, all governmental jurisdiction ' the em peror should assume also full spiritual authority, b ut “ his duty |w as]
ceases .. the executive power is suspended . . . because in the place where simply to foster the teaching of the gospel an d to uphold the tru e faith and
the body represented meets, there can be no representative.” he had “ the right to appoint and dism iss the officers, as well as to control and
66. Rousseau 1994a, p. 129. ,, , , .u u * dispose of the Church’s property” (Skinner 1 9 7 8 ,1, p. 15).
67 For the impact of Rousseau’s use of nature and body metaphors on the rhet- 10 See L uther’s notorious pam phlet O f the Jews and Their Lies ( V o n d en Juden
■oric and propaganda of the French Revolution and ' und iren Lugen”), of 1543; for its theologically, n ot racially m otivated, rad i­
fhoueht see laser 1971, pp. 12-47, 79-113; Koselleck 1973, pp. 133-142; cal anti-Sem itism , see H ilberg 2 0 0 3 ,1, pp. 13-14.
Arendt 1974, pp. 69-70; Kelly 1986; Blum 1986; Schama 1989, p. 770; Guil- 11. Skinner 1978, vol. 1, pp. 81-108. * * c* #
haumou 1989; Cooper 1999; Derathe 2000. ^ 12. See Lorenz 1991, pp. 65, 159 [Complaints from Protestant States, 1608),
68. Abbe Sieyes, Qu’est-ce que le Tiers Etatf, see Sieyes 1989, p. 30. 112 (Declaration of the Margrave of Brandenburg and the Palatine Duke).
69. See Flunt 1984,1991; Schama 1989, pp. 72-73; Desmet, Rooryck and Swig- 13. Friedtlieb 1614, p. 1, quoted in Friihsorge 1974, p. 63.
gers 1990, pp. 185-186; Walzer 1992, p. 191; de Baecque 1997, pp. 85, 14. Friedtlieb 1614, p. 12; quoted in Fruhsorge 1974, p. 65; see also Schulze
’ 1986, p. 601.
70. See Paine 1891, p. 19; Forster, Parisische Umrisse [1793], in Forster 1990, 15. Lohneyss 1622, p. 98, quoted in Fruhsorge 1974, p. 67.
16. Lohenstein 1689,1; Teil, 7; Buch 1102, quoted m Fruhsorge 1974, p. 118. For
71. Burke Reflectiom on the Revolution in France [1790] in Burke 1986, p. 126; the corporeal/sexual im agery in Lohenstein’s tragedies, see K oschorke et al.
see also ibid.,p. 158. • xx 2007, pp. 159-177.
72. Marx, The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte [1852], m Marx I960, 17. Weise 1686, p. 132-133 quoted in Fruhsorge 1974, p. 190.
18. See Stieler 1968, pp. 1 0 1 5 ,1132. , • . t- j a -d u \ 17^
73. Lenin, State and Revolution [1917], in Lenin 1963-69, vol. 25, Chap­ 19 Pufendorf 2 0 0 7 (reprint of the 1696 tran slatio n by E dm und Bohun), p. 1/t.
ters 2 and 3. For the L atin original and a m odern G erm an translation, see Pufendorf
74. See Beermann 1964; Gitelmann 2001, p. 168. . 1994.
20. Pufendorf 2007, p. 177. r -ji -mA-?
21. For the reception history, see Schilling 1994, pp. 9 4 -9 5 ; Seidler 2007, pp.
x ii-x x .
NOTES TO CHAPTER 9 22. H o fm an n 1976b, pp. x v i-ii.
23. Schilling 1994, pp. 95 -9 6 .
1. Die Zeit, 19. May 2005: “Fine Kritikerjury prasentiert die zehn 24 See Berschin 2 0 0 2 . For fu rth er interpretations of the monster com parison,
‘bemerkenswertesten Inszenierungen’ der Saison.. . . Sie sprechen vom Buh- ’ see Schnettger 2002; Stolleis 1988, 2 004; W ilson 2006.
nenkorper’ und vom ‘nationalen Korper’—Gesellschaft 1st der groKe Leib, 25. See Jessen 1965, pp. 192-193.
uber den sich das Theater beugt.” ., . . x 26. See H o fm an n 1976a, p. 395.
2. Der Spiegel 11/2007: “Urn 450 nach Christus hatten sich in dem weiten Impe- 27. See H o fm an n 1976a, p. 392. , • u j
rium germanische Machtzentren abgekapselt. Letztiich waren es Geschwure 28. A ttem pts to reaw aken the idea of a G erm an Reich'in -toe-m neteentn-ana
im Staatskbrper von Rom.. . . Im 4. und 5. Jahrhundert drangen germanische tw entieth centuries, including the N azis’ self-presentation of their regime
Stamme ins Romische Imperium ein. Sie bildeten eigenstandige und bald as the “T h ird Reich”, were th u s n ot m eant to resuscitate the corpse of the
nicht mehr kontrollierbare Machtzentren—Keimzellen des Untergangs. “H oly R om an Empire of G erm an N atio n ”; rath er, they were attem pts to
3. Die Zeit, Ze/t-Geschichte, November 2009: “So wie es den Korper des instrum entalise the “ m yth of the Reich” (Kettenaeker 1983) w ith its associa­
Staates a la longue zu bessern gait, gait es iiber den individuellen, mit semen tions of m edieval glory. From today’s perspective, the “ H oly R om an Empire
ungeheuren Unzulanglichkeiten zu triumphieren.” appears to be firmly historicised.
4 Peter F Ganz’s (1957, p. 175) statement that, apart from an isolated occur-
29. Der Spiegel, 32/2006. *u • u,»
' rence in a translation of Shaftesbury’s “Characteristicks”, no German loan 30. K ant, “Idee zu einer allgemeinen G eschichte in weltburgerlicher Absicht .
translation of body politic as politischer Korper is attested, thus oidy refers to Berlinische Monatsschrift [November 1784]. In K ant 1983, vol. 9, p. 47. K ant
that particular phrase; as we shall see, other loan items (e.g. Staatskorper) are also used Staatskorper to denote the nation state; see ibid., pp. 42, 48. In his
well attested. It is true, however, that no one term that would be comperable Critique of Judgement, published in l7 9 0 , K ant even gave the French revo­
to the phrase body politic, has dominated German political discourse over lutionaries the benefit of assum ing th a t their predilection for “orgttwismic”
centuries.
174 Notes
Notes 175
terminology in naming the institutions of their new state was indicative of any case, in the conceptual and tex tu al traditions since the M iddle Ages,
their interest in the participation of each member of the state body could head an d soul of the body politic w ere closely linked. ’
have “in creating the whole of the body” (1983, vol. 8, pp. 487-488. For the 53. Strauss 1963, p. 160.
influence of Kant’s concept of the state as an organic, autopoietic whole on 54. Strauss 1963, p. 160.
German idealism, see Ludemann 2007, pp. 178-179. 55. In the preface to the A m erican edition: Strauss 1963, p. xv.
31. See Wieland 1797, p. 143. 56. T he continuing debate about Strauss, Schm itt an d th eir biographical and
32. Herder, Deutsches Museum. Von der Ahnlichkeit der mittleren englischen intellectual connections rests to no sm all extent on th e perception th a t b oth
und deutschen Dichtkunst, nebst Verschiednem, das daraus folget (1777), thinkers were exceptionally influential in p o st-W W II Europe and the US.
quoted in Schmitz-Berning 2000, p. 667. In the case of Strauss, this aspect concerns in p articu la r his alleged influ­
33. Berlin 1976, p. 198.
ence on th e “neo-conservative” policies; in the case of Schm itt, his alleged
34. Herder, Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit (1784-91), hidden influence on W est G erm an and W est E uropean political thought; see
quoted in Schmitz-Berning 2000, p. 460. M eier 1998; G ross 2 0 0 0 ; B alakrishnan 2 0 0 0 , pp. 2 0 9 -2 1 6 ; N o rto n 2004
35. See Sieyes 1989, p. 30, and references quoted earlier. pp. 3 7 -4 2 ; M uller 2 003; Z uckert an d Z uckert 2 0 0 6 . *
36. Grimm (1984, vol. 26, p. 486) quotes the earliest source, a passage from F. 57. See M eier 1998, p. 17, note 11.
C. Dahlmann’s History of the French Revolution (1844-45), which speaks 58. See the 1936 preface in Strauss 1963, p. xiv, an d Strauss’s letters to Schm itt
of a “healthy principle of state” that “invigorates the blood circulation in the from M arch 1932, Septem ber 1932 an d 10 July 1933, in M eier 1998 dd
whole national body” {ein gesundes staatsprinzip . . . erfrischt zugleich den 131-135.
blutumlaufim ganzen volkskdrper). 59. See Schm itt 2 0 0 2 , p. 26 passim. I find the translation o f Schm itt’s term
37. See Arndt, Reden und Glossen. Leipzig 1848; quoted in Schmitz-Bernine “ Fem d” by foe preferable to enemy, because the form er highlights the “com ­
2000, p. 700. b at” aspect, w hich is centrally im p o rtan t for Schm itt; see his insistence on
38. See Stocker, speech on 4 February 1880, quoted in Schmitz-Bernine 2000, the “real possibility of physical killing” (2002, p. 33) an d his explication th at
pp. 667-668. he m eans Feind in the sense of L atin hostis, n ot the m ore general a n d abstract
39. See Diihring. Die Judenfrage als Racen-, Sitten- und Culturfrage (1881), inimicus (2002, p. 29).
quoted in: Schmitz-Berning 2000, p. 461; for the development of the body- 60. Schm itt 2 0 0 2 , p. 27.
parasite scenario as a pseudo-scientific justification in nineteenth-century 61. Schm itt 2 0 0 2 , p. 27.
anti-Semitic literature, see also Bein 1965, pp. 128-129. 62. Schm itt 2 0 0 2 , pp, 53, 6 4 - 6 6 , 82; comp, also Schm itt 2003, pp. 17-18, 34.
40. For the concept of the “total state” as a positively valued category in Schmitt’s In co n trast to H obbes, Schm itt’s notion of w ar w as, however, based on w ar
public statements from 1932 onwards, see Gross 2000, pp. 97-98. fought betw een nations as the paradigm atic form : civil w ar and the deadly
41. Strauss 1963. “ ban n in g ” of individuals are m entioned as special sub-cases (2002 dd 29
42. Schmitt 2003; English translation 2008. 3 2 ,4 7 ,5 3 ). ' .P P >
43. Gurian 1934; for historical assessments, see Koenen 1995, pp. 631-635; 63. Schm itt 2 0 0 2 , pp. 53, 66,
Gross 2000, pp. 158-163; and Stirk 2005. 64. As examples of such exceptions, Schm itt lists Bossuet, Fichte, de M aistre,
44. See Hobbes 1969. Hobbes finished the Behemoth book by 1668 but it was D onoso C ortes and H . Taine, and, w ith reservations, Hegel (Schmitt 2002
not licensed to be printed and appeared in an unauthorized version in 1679; p. 61)
see Hobbes’s letters 206, 208 in Hobbes 1994, II, pp. 771-773; see also Skin­ 65. Schm itt 2 0 0 2 , p. 94.
ner 2002, p. 29. 66. Strauss 1998, p. 125.
45. Bible 2001 Job 40:15. 67. Strauss 1998, p. 107; see also M eier 1998, pp. 3 9 -4 1 .
46. Bible 2001 Job 40:16-24. 68. See Strauss 1998, p. 125; for criticism o f am biguities in S chm itt’s treatise, in
47. For the mythological background and rabbinical, messianic and gnostic inter­ p articu lar in relation to H obbes, see ibid., pp. 121-123.
pretations of these biblical figures, see Brodye, Hirsch, Kohler and Schechter 69. See M eier 1998, pp. 16-17,
1904. 70. M eier 1998.
48. Neumann 1942, p. 5.
71. Schm itt 1936; for detailed historical analysis and-assesTm enCTee K oenen
49. Strauss 1963, pp. ix, 167-170. 1995; Gross 2 0 0 0 ; Blasius 2001.
50. Despite acknowledging Leviathan to be Hobbes’s “most mature” work, Strauss 72. Schm itt 1933a, b.
judged it to be “by no means an adequate source for an understanding of Hob­ 73. Schm itt 1934.
bes’s moral and political ideas” and that “in the earlier presentations the original 74. Schm itt 1935.
motives of Hobbes’s political philosophy [were] generally more clearly shown” 75. Schm itt 1936. T h e congress program m e has been deemed (Balakrishnan
(Strauss 1963, p. 170). For a recent interpretation that highlights humanistic 2000, p. 207) to be “ little m ore th a n a call fo r a w ell-organized intellectual
aspects of Leviathan in both early and later works of Hobbes’s development of pogrom ”; see also Behnken 1980, vol. 3, p. 1684; Koenen 1995, dp. 709-715-
a “civil science”, see Skinner 1996, pp. 327-375; 2002, pp. 66-86. G ross 2000, pp. 120-134.
51. Strauss 1963, p. 13. 76. See G u rian 1934, Koenen 1995, pp. 7 2 0 -7 2 3 , 7 3 2 -7 3 6 .
52. But see the argument put forward in Chapter 7 that the “head” imagery was 77. See B alakrishnan 2 0 0 0 , pp. 201-207.
not of central significance for Hobbes or, indeed, for the revolutionaries. In 78. Koenen 1995, pp. 714-746.
Notes 177
176 Notes
98. Schmitt 2003, p. 108.
79. Balakrishnan 2000, p. 207; Koenen 1995, pp. 752-764. 99. Schmitt 2003, p. 118.
80. Schmitt 2003, p. 9. 100. Schmitt 2003, p. 67 and Schmitt 1934.
101 . Agamben 1998, p. 110. , if c ,u
l l . Schmitt ?003,^p. 18. For the detailed analysis of Schmitt’s “cabbalistic” 102. See Agamben 1998, pp. 136-144. Schmitt himself was not unaware of the
sources and their varying presentation in Schmitt s works during the Third eenocidal tendencies of Nazi Germany (with the benefit of post-1945 hmd-
Reich and in the excised post-1945 versions, see Gross 2000, pp. 272 278. sieht), but he located the origin of the the transformation of the real into
83. Schmitt 2003, p. 16. an “absolute” concept of the foe in the “global civil war of revolutionary
84f Schmitt 2003, p. 18. class-hatred” resulting from World War I, i.e. not in Nazism (see Schmitt
2006, p. 96).
86 L e Heinrich Heine’s ironic poem Disputation, in which the Leviathan serves 103. See Agamben 1998, pp. 105-107,125.
as the name for a recipe promoted by the “Rabbi Juda to convert Goyim 104. Agamben 1998, p. 83.
(Heine 1976, vol. 11, pp. 167-168). In post-1945 editions of Schmitt s Land 105. Agamben 1998, p. 125.
und Meer, Heine is given even more prominence as an important source for 106. A gam ben 1998, p. 148. u uu ’ d i,
the myth (see Gross 2000, p. 274, note 30). 107 Neumann 1942, p. 5. The tertium comparatioms to Hobbess Behemoth
87 Gross 2000, p. 277; see also Muller 2003, p. 41. For contemporary reac ■was that in his account of the English civil war the English philosopher too
tions, such as the enthusiastic approval from the Nazi Institute for Race had concentrated on the breakdown of the body politic into a non-state, a
Theory, Anthropological Biology and Rural Sociology, see Gross 2000, pp. chaos, a situation of lawlessness, disorder, and anarchy” (ibid., P- •5)-^
277-279. 108. See his frequent references to Schmitt, especially the chapters on the Totali­
tarian State” (Neumann 1942, pp. 41-72), the Reich idea (pp. 110-153), and
89! Schmitt ^2^^^ 20-21. The distinction of “heathen-Chnstian” and “National Socialist Law and Terror” (pp. 359-347) as well as in the conclu­
“Tudeo-Christian” traditions occupies a central position in the development sion (p. 383).
of Schmitt’s'“political theology” as well as in his post-1945 attempts to dis­ 109. Neumann 1942, p. 375.
tance his “anti-Judaism” from Nazi-specific 110. Neumann 1942, p. 375.
Gross 2000, pp. 366-373, 378-382; apologetically: Maschke 2003, pp. 111. Neumann 1942, p. 381.
112. Neumann 1942, pp. 383-384.
90 E™^Schmitt had to admit that “the only authentic” references to Jewish 113. See Neumann 1942, pp. 359-374, 384-389.
traditions in Hobbes’s text were the quotations from Job, and that the mam 114. See above, chapter 8.
feature of the biblical Leviathan was its unsurpassable stren^h (Schmitt 115. Schmitt 2003, p. 130.
2003 D 35) To compensate for the lack of evidence of mythical or theologi­
cal perspectives on Leviathan in Hobbes’s text, he quoted contemporaries of
Hobbes who did refer to mythical aspects in varying degrees, e.g. in Bible
commentaries and in poetry (ibid., 36-45) and hinted mystifying y at a spe­ NOTES TO CHAPTER 10
cial significance” of the fact that Hobbes “as an Englishman of the seven­
teenth century” used Leviathan as a symbol of peace-giving political order, 1. See examples in Chapter 1. The memory of the Nazi associations of bio-
for “Leviathan, the ‘big whale’, was particularly close to the imagination of Dolitical imagery is of course not restricted to Germany. For instances ot
the English people” (ibid., pp. 34 and 43-45). international protest against its use, see the public outcry over President
91. See Schmitt 2003, pp. 86-110,126. • ■ u- f Ahmadinejad of Iran’s reported statement “that the tumour
92 Schmitt 2003, p. 108. For the inconsistencies and anti-Semitic bias ot this should be removed from Palestine {The Times, 9 December 2005) and
“history”, see Habermas 1982, pp, 72-74, Rumpf W72; Koenen 1995 pp, denunciations of xenophobic and racist propaganda that included the
808-816), Gross (2000, pp. 267-284), Balakrishnan (2000, pp. 209-220). description of Jews to “warts on a man’s body” {The Independent, 16 Janu-
Even the Schmitt-loyal Maschke (2003, pp: 207-209) calls the alleged Jewish - 2007)
conspiracy against Leviathan a “strangely heterogeneous group and con­ 2 See Hale 1971, p. 108; Dhorn van Rossum ,ahd Bockenforde 1978, pp.
cedes an anti-Judaistic bias, but he excuses Schmitt by speculating that he 549-552.
compensated for having used Jewish sources in the first place and that in his 3 See Coker 1910; Dhorn van Rossum and Bockenforde 1978, pp. 586-622;
post-1936 situation he had to protect himself by “token anti-Semitism. ■Koschorke et al. 2007, pp. 319-382. For a thorough critique and analysis of
93. Schmitt 2003, pp. 130-132. modern legal-sociological applications of the analogy, which demons^ates
94. Schmitt 2003, p. 87. i n ^,-rr their unbroken metaphoricity (and ideological bias), see Mouton 2009, pp.
95 Schmitt 2003, pp. 92-93. Mendelssohn’s contemporary, Johann Georg 274-353.
. Hamann (1730-1788), was hailed by Schmitt as the only German thinker 4. Croft and Cruse 2004, p. 205. iu j » •
who dared to oppose the “sophistries of the enlightened Jew , but apparently 5. See Der Spiegel 4/1987; “Die Gesellschaft isr keine Hammelherde , interview
to little avail (pp. 93-94). with Hans Magnus Enzensberger: “Im alten Europa hat man das Geman-
96. Schm itt 2003, p. 108. . , . , ••£,• „ t wesen immer nach dem Modell des menschlichen Korpers beschneben. Die
97. Schmitt 2003, p. 110; “.. . hat er .. . mitgewirkt, emen lebenskraftigen Levi­ Regierung war das Oberhaupt, der Kopf. Diese Metapher ist endgultig passe.
athan zu verschneiden”.
178 Notes
Ein Zentrum, das alles vorhersieht, steuert und entscheidet, ist nicht mehr
vorhanden.”
6. Sontag 1978, p. 78.
Bibliography
7. SeeShogimen2008.
8. See examples in Chapter 1; also Johnston 1998; Karwowsky 2004 and topi­
cal Internet Web sites such http://www.phrases.org.Uk/bulletin_board/5/
messages/1281.html (accessed 20 November 2009).
. 2^See Obama 2007, p. 10; comp, also Shields 2004; Internet sites such as http://
www.bodypolitic.com/ (accessed 20 November 2009).
10. See Falk 2008, p. 219 and Mensch 2009, especially pp. 69-71; 126.
11. Le Figaro, 7 May 2007.
12. See Shorter Oxford English Dictionary 2002, vol. 2, p. 2096.
13. For the use of the generalized concept of someone who lives off others and
profits from their patronage, see Ben Jonson’s play Volpone, of 1607 (Jonson
1966) with “Mosca, the Parasite” as one of its chief characters. Abel, Karl-Dietrich (1968). Fresselenkung im NS-Staat: Eine Studie zur Geschichte
14. The term Schmarotzer, which Hitler used interchangeably with Farasit, der Fublizistik in der nationalsozialistischen Zeit. Berlin: Colloquium Verlag.
appears to have retained (since its first recorded occurrences in the fifteenth Ach, Manfred and Clemens Pentrop (eds.) (2001). Hitlers ‘Religion’: Fseudoreligiose
century) a general social meaning but, through a parallel eighteenth-century Elemente im nationalsozialistischen Sprachgebrauch. Munich: Arbeitsgemein-
semantic extension to that of Farasit, the term has also became available schaft fur Religions- und Weltanschauungsfragen.
for botanical and zoological applications; see Grimm 1984, vol. 15, pp. ^A esop (2002). Aesop’s Fables. Trans. Laura Gibbs. Oxford: Oxford University
937-942. Press.
15. Depending on the period of origin of use, the various source inputs (and Agamben, Giorgio (1998). Homo Sacer. Sovereign Fower and Bare Life. Trans.
hence their mappings) may be wholly or partly incompatible in scientific Daniel Heller-Roazen. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
terms. For non-experts, however, such inconsistencies can be made to appear Alkemeyer, Thomas (1996). Korper, Kultur und Folitik. Von der “Muskelreligion”
compatible by rhetorical sleight-of-hand, which is of course, typical for polit­ Fierre de Coubertins zur Inszenierung von Macht in den Olympischen Spielen
ical demagoguery. von 1936. Frankfurt/Main: Campus-Verlag.
Anonymus (1937). Weifie Juden in der Wissenschaft. Das schwarze Korps, 25 July
1937.
Archambault, Paul (1967). The Analogy of the Body in Renaissance Political Lit­
erature. Bibliotheque d’Humanisme et Renaissance, 29: 21-63.
Arendt, Hannah (1973). The Origins of Totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt
Brace.
------- . (1974). Vber die Revolution. Munich: Piper.
Aristotle (1995). Politics. Ed. Ernest Barker, R. F. Stalley. Oxford: Oxford Univer­
sity Press.
------- .-(1996). Foetics. Ed. Malcolm Heath. London: Penguin.
Augustine (1998). The City of God against the Fagans. Ed. R. W. Dyson. Cam­
bridge: Cambridge University Press.
Axton, Marie (1977). The Queen’s Two Bodies: Drama and the Elizabethan Suc­
cession. London: Royal Historical Society.
Baader, Gerhard and Ulrich Schultz (eds.) (19S0). MedizijutndNatiefmkozialismus;
Tabuisierte Vergangenheit— Ungebrochene Tradition^ Special vol. 15, Forum
fur Medizin und Gesundheitspolitik. Berlin: Verlagsgesellschaft Gesundheit.
Bachrach, Susan and Steven Luckert (2009). State of Deception: The Fower of
Nazi Propaganda. New York: W.W. Norton & Co.
Bacon, Francis (1972). Essays. Introduction by Michael J. Hawkins. London:
Dent.
Balakrishnan, Gopal (2000). The Enemy: An Intellectual Portrait of Carl Schmitt.
London: Verso.
Balistier, Thomas (1996). Die Tatpropaganda der SA. Erfolg und Mythos. In:
Gerald Diesener und Rainer Gries (eds.). Propaganda in Deutschland. Zur
Geschichte der politischen Massenbeeinflussung im 20. Jahrhundert. Darm­
stadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 23-34.
180 Bibliography
Bibliography 181
Bankier, Dawi p 9 2 | The Germans and the Final Solution: Public Opinion under
Nazism. Oxford: Blackwell. Blasius, Dirk (2001). Carl Schmitt. Preuflischer Staatsrat in Hitlers Reich. Gottin­
gen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.
Awareness of the Final Solution. In: David Cesarani
(ed.). I he ttnal Solution; Origins and Implementation. London/New York- Bloch, Marc (1961). Les rois thaumaturges. Etudes sur le caractere surnaturel
Koutledge, 215-227. attribue a la puissance royale particulierement en France et en Angleterre.
Paris: Colin.
Banks Kathryn (2009). Interpretations of the Body Politic and of Natural
Bodies in Late Sixteenth Century France. In: Andreas Musolff and Torg Blum, Carol (1986). Rousseau and the Republic of Virtue: The Language of Poli­
tics in the French Revolution. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Discourse. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, Boberach, Heinz (Hrsg.) (1984). Meldungen aus dem Reich, 1938-194S: Die
Barnden, John p009). Metaphor and Context: A Perspective from Artificial Intel­ geheimen Lageberichte des Sicherheitsdienstes der SS. 17. vols. Herrsching-
Pawlak.
ligence. In: Andreas Musolff and Jorg Zinken (eds.). Metaphor and Discourse
Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 79-94. Boniface VIII (1959). Unam Sanctam . . .”. In: Corpus Juris Canonici, editio
(2002). Die politische Religion des Nationalsozialismus Lipsiensis secunda post Aemilii Ludovici Richteri curas ad librorum manu scrip-
M unich: rin k . torum et editionis Romanae fidem recognovit et adnotatione critica instruxit
Bass, Allen M. (1997). The Metaphor of the Human Body in the Political Theory of Aemilius Friedberg. Pars secunda Decretalium Collectiones. Titulus VIII: De
John of Salisbury: Context and Innovation. In: Bernhard Debatin, Timothy R. maioritate et obedientia. Graz: Friedberg, 1245-1246.
Jackson and Daniel Steuer (eds.). Metaphor and Rational Discourse. Tubingen- Bosmajian, Haig (1983). The Language of Oppression. Lanham, MD; University
Niemeyer, 201-213. ® ' Press of America.
Bauer, Yelmda (2001). Rethinking the Holocaust. New Haven/London- Yale Uni­ Brandt,Reinhart{1987).DasTitelbIattdesLeviathan.Zeirsc/7n/t/MrSozi(j/M'isse«sc/?a/t,
versity Press. 15: 164— 186.
Bai^ann, Zygmunt (2000). Modernity and the Holocaust (With a new afterword) Brewer’s Dictionary of Phrase and Fable (1999). Ed. Adrian Room. London:
Cambridge: Polity Press. ^ Cassell.
Brodie, Richard (1996). Virus of the Mind: The New Science of the Meme Seattle
PresT^ Cambridge: Cambridge WA: Integral Press. ’
Lrniz (1923). Grundriss der menschUchen Brodye, Isaac, Emil G. Hirsch, Kaufmann Kohler and Salomon Schechter (1904)
trblichkeitslehre und Rassenhygiene. Munich: J. F. Lehmanns. Leviathan and Behemoth. In: The Jewish Encyclopedia. Eds. Isidore Singer et
al. New York: Funk & Wagnalls, vol. 9, 37-38. http://www.jewishencyclope-
420-429^^^'^^' Russian Anti-Parasite Laws. Soviet Studies, 15 dia.com/view.jsp.>artid=2758detter=L (accessed: 30 January 2000).
Behnken Klaus (ed.) (1980). Deutschland-Berichte der Sozialdemokratischen Browning, Christopher (1992). The Path to Genocide. Essays on Launching the
Panel Deutschlands (Sopade) 1934-1940. 7 vols. Frankfurt/Main: Petra Net- Final Solution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
telbeck, Zweitausendeins. ------- . (2001). Ordinary Men: Reserve Battalion 101 and the Final Solution in
(1965). Der judische Parasit. Vierteljahreshefte fur Zeitgeschichte, Poland. London: Penguin. First published in 1992.
■ . (2004). The Origins of the Final Solution: The Evolution of Nazi Jewish
Berlin, Isamh (1971). The Question of Machiavelli. The New York Review of Policy, September 1939-March 1942. With contributions by Jurgen Matthaus.
Books, 17, 7 (November 4,1971: 20-32). • London: William Heinemann.
Enlightenment. In: Vico and Herder. London: The Bullock, Alan (1962). Hitler: A Study in Tyranny. Harmondsworth: Penguin. '
Hogarth Press, 143-216. Burke, Edmund (1986). Reflections on the Revolution in France. Ed. Conor Cruise
Berschm, Walter (2002). Neulateinische Utopien im Alten Reich (1555-1741). In: O’Brien. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Eckhard Kefiler, Heinrich C. Kuhn (eds.). Germania latina—Latinitas teu- Burke, Kenneth [1939] (1984). The Rhetoric of Hitler’s ‘Battle’. In: Michael Sha­
tonica. Pohtik, Wissenschaft, humanistische Kultur vom spdten Mittelalter bis piro (ed.). Language and Politics. Oxford: Blackwell, 6-1-80 (originally in: The
Southern Review, 5 (1939/40): 1-21).
inunsere Zeit. http://www.phil-hum-ren.uni.muenchen.de/GermLat/Acta/Ber- Burleigh, Michael (2001). The Third Reich: A New History. Ix)ndoin-Panr—
schin.htm (accessed 20 November 2009).
Bertau, Marie-Cecile (1996). Sprachspiel Metapher. Denkweisen und kommu- Bussemer, Thymian (2000). Propaganda und Populdrkultur: Konstruierte Erleb-
nikative Funktion etner rhetorischen Figur. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag. niswelten im Nationalsozialismus. Wiesbaden: Deutscher Universitats-Verlag.
Bertelh, Sergio (20 01). The King’s Body: Sacred Rituals of Power in Medieval and Bytwerk, Randall L. (1996). Die nationalsozialistische Versammlungspraxis. In:
tarly Modern Europe. Translated by R. Burr Litchfield. University Park: Penn­ Gerald Diesener und Rainer Gries (eds.). Propaganda in Deutschland. Zur
sylvania State University Press. Geschichte der politischen Massenbeeinflussung im 20. Jahrhundert. Darm­
Bible (2001). The New Oxford Annotated Bible. Third edition. With the Apocrv- stadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 35-50.
phal/Deuterocanonical Books. Ed. Michael D. Coogan. Oxford: Oxford Uni­ . (2001). Julius Streicher: Nazi editor of the Notorious Anti-Semitic News­
versity Press. paper Der Sturmer. New York: Cooper Square Press.
Birnbaum, Pierre (1992). Anti-Semitism in France: A Political History from Leon . (2004). Bending Spines: The Propagandas of Nazi Germany and
Blum to the Present. Oxford: Blackwell. the German Democratic Republic. Ann Arbor: Michigan State University
Press.
Bla^more, Susan (1999). The Meme Machine. Foreword by Richard Dawkins
Oxford: Oxford University Press. Caird, G. B. (1980). The Language and Imagery of the Bible. London:
Duckworth.
182 Bibliography ,Bibliography 183
Cesarani, David (1996). Introduction. In: The Final Solution. Origins and Imple­ Period. In: John E. Joseph and Talbot J. Taylor (eds.). Ideologies of Language.
mentation. London, New York: Routledge, 1-29. London: Routledge, 162-188.
Charlesworth, Brian and Deborah Charlesworth (2003). Evolution: A Very Short Dhorn-van-Rossum, Gerhard and Ernst-Wolfgang Bockenforde (1978). Organ,
Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Organismus, Organisation, Politischer Kbrper. In: Otto Brunner, Werner Conze
Charteris-Black, Jonathan (2005). Politicians and Rhetoric: The Persuasive Power and Reinhart Koselleck (eds.). Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe. Historisches
of Metaphor. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Worterbuch zur politisch-sozialen Sprache in Deutschland. Stuttgart: Klett-
Chickering, Roger (2004). Imperial Germany and the Great VJar, 1914-1918. Cotta, vol. 4, 519-622.
- Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Diller, Ansgar (1980). Rundfunkpolitik im Dritten Reich. Munich: Deutscher
Chilton, Paul (2005). Manipulation, Memes and Metaphors: The Case of Mein Taschenbuch Verlag.
Kampf In: Saussure, Louis de and Peter Schulz (eds.). Manipulation and Ideol­ Dodd, Bill (2003). Die Sprachglosse als Ort oppositionellen Diskurses im “Dritten
ogies m the Twentieth Century. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: Benjamins, 15-43. Reich”. Beispiele von Dolf Sternberger, Gerhard Storz und Wilhelm Sfiskind aus
Clark, Carol E. (1970). Montaigne and the Imagery of Political Discourse in Six­ den frfihen 1940er Jahren. Wirkendes Wort, 53: 241-251.
teenth-Century France. French Studies XXIV (4): 337-355. ------- . (2007). Jedes Wort wandelt die Welt: Dolf Sternbergers politische Sprach-
Coker, Francis W. (1910). Organismic Theories of the State: Nineteenth-Century kritik. Gottingen: Wallstein Verlag.
Interpretations of the State as Organism or Person (Studies in History Eco­ Domarus, Max (1965). Hitler: Reden und Proklamationen 1932-1945. Kom-
nomics and Public Law No. 101). New York: Columbia University mentiert von einem deutschen Zeitgenossen. 4 vols. Munich: Sfiddeutscher
Cooper, David E. (1986). Metaphor. Oxford: Blackwell. Verlag.
Cooper, Laurence (1999). Rousseau, Nature and the Problem of the Good Life. Ehlich, Konrad (ed.) (1989). Sprache im Faschismus. Frankfurt/Main:
University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press. Suhrkamp.
Cornwell, John (2003). Hitler’s Scientists: Science, V/ar and the Devil’s Pact Lon­ Eitz, Thorsten und Georg Stbtzel (2007). Worterbuch der "Vergangenheitsbewdl-
don: Penguin. tigung”: Die NS-Vergangenheit im dffentlichen Sprachgebrauch. Hildesheim:
Croft, William (2000). Explaining Language Change: An Evolutionary Approach. Olms.
London: Longman. Ensink, Titus (1992). Jenninger: De ontvangst van een Duits rede in Nederland:
Cr^t, William and D. Alan Cruse (2004). Cognitive Linguistics. Cambridge* een tekstwetenschappelijke en communicatiewetenschappelijke analyse. Met
Cambridge University Press. een bijdrage van Ali Oussaid. Amsterdam: Thesis Publishers.
Cunningham, Andrew (2004). William Harvey: The Discovery of the Circulation Evans, Richard J. (1997). In Search of German Social Darwinism. In: Reread­
of Blood. In: Peter Elmer and Ole Peter Grell (eds.). Health, Disease and Society ing German History, 1800-1996. From Unification to Reunification. London:
m Europe 1500-1800; A Source Book. Manchester and New York* Manchester Routledge, 119-144.
University Press, 173-178 (first published in 1987). ------- . (2003). The Coming of the Third Reich. London: Penguin.
Daim, Wiifried (1958). Der Mann, der Hitler die Ideen gab. Munich* Isar ------- . (2005). The Third Reich in Power, 1933-1939. London: Penguin.
Verlag. —;---- . (2008). The Third Reich at War, 1939—1945. London: Allen Lane.
Darwin, Charles (1901). The Origin of Species by Natural Selection or the Pres­ Fabiszak, Malgorzata (2007). A Conceptual Metaphor Approach to War Dis­
ervation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. (Sixth edition). London* course and Its Implications. Poznan: Adam Mickiewicz University.
John Murray. Falk, Richard (2008). Where Is ‘The Fork in the Road’? Over the Horizon! An
. (2004). The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex. With an Inquiry into the Failure of UN Reform. In: Markus Kornprobst, Vincent Pouliot,
Introduction by James Moore and Adrian Desmond. London: Penguin Nisha Shah and Ruben Zaiotti (eds.). Metaphors of Globalization: Mirrors,
Dawkins, Richard [1976] (1989). The Selfish Gene. Oxford and New York: Oxford Magicians and Mutinies. Basingstoke: Palgrave, 203-220.
University Press. Fauconnier, Gilles and Mark Turner (1998). Conceptual Integration Networks.
— . (1999). The Extended Phenotype: The Long Reach of the Gene, Oxford* Cognitive Science, 22 (2), 133-187.
Oxford University Press. ———. (2002). The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind^sJiidden
------- *. (2004). Viruses of the Mind. In: A Devil’s Chaplain: Selected Essays Ed Complexities. New York: Basic Books. ~ ^
Latha Menon. London: Phoenix, 151-172. Feldman, Karen S. (2001). Conscience and the Concealments of Metaphor in Hob-
de Baecque, Antoine (1997). The Body Politic: Corporeal Metaphor in Revolution­ bes’s Leviathan. Philosophy and Rhetoric, 34,1, 21-37.
ary France 1770-1800. Stanford, CA : Stanford University Press Fenske, Wolfgang (2005). Wie Jesus zum “Arier” wurde. Auswirkungen der Entju-
Deignan, Alice (1995). COBUILD English Guides. Vol. 7: Metaphor Dictionary daisierung Christi im 19. und zum- Beginn des 20. Jahrhunderts. Darmstadt:
London: HarperCollins. Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
Deissler, Dirk (2003). The Nazis May Almost Be Said to Have ‘Invented’ a new Fest, Joachim C. (1974). Hitler: Eine Biographie. Frankfurt/Main, Berlin, Vienna:
German Language. Der anglo-amerikanische Diskurs fiber nationalsozialis- Propylaen.
tischen Sprachgebrauch im Zweiten Weltkrieg und in der Besatzungszeit Ger- Fetscher, Iring (1998)./ose/Goebbels im Berliner Sportpalast 1943 "Wolltihr den
mamstische Linguistik, 169-170, 319-337. totalen Krieg?”. Ha^mburg: Europaische Verlagsanstalt.
Derathcj Robert (2000). Jean-Jacques Rousseau et la science politique de son Fischer, Heinrich (1945). Die deutsche Sprache im Dritten Reich. Ausblick, 1
temps. Paris: Vrin. (August 1945): 119-121.
Desmet, Pierre, Johan E. Rooryck and Pierre Swiggers (1990). What Are Words Foolen, Ad (2008). The Heart as a Source of Semiosis: The Case of Dutch. In:
Worth? Language and Ideology in French Dictionaries of the Revolutionary Farzad Sharifian et al. (eds.). Culture, Body, and Language: Conceptualizations
184 Bibliography
Bibliography 185
Internal Body Organs across Cultures and Languages. Berlin: Mouton de Gilbert, Martin (2007). Kristallnacht: Prelude to Destruction. London:
Gruyter, 373-394.
HarperCollins.
Forhan, Kate L. (1994). Introduction. In: Christine de Pizan. The Book of the Body Gilman, Sander L. (1991). The Jew’s Body. New York, London: Routledge.
Politic. Edited and translated by Kate Langdon Forhan. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, xiii-xxiv. Gitelman, Zvi Y (2001). A century of ambivalence: the Jews of Russia and the
Forster, Georg (1990). Revolutionsschriften 1792193. Ed. K.-G Pott (= vol 10 Soviet Union, 1881 to the Present. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
of Georg Forsters Werke. Sdmtliche Schriften, Tagebucher, Briefe) Berlin- Goatly, Andrew (2007). Washing the Brain: Metaphor and Hidden Ideology.
Akademie-Verlag. Amsterdam/New York: Benjamins.
Fortescue, Sir John (1997). On the Laws and Governance of England. Ed. Shelley Goebbels, Joseph (1933). Revolution der Deutschen: 14 Jahre Nationalsozialis-
Lockwood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. mus. Goebbelsreden mit einleitenden Zeitbildern von Hein Schlecht. Oldenburg
i. O.: Gerhard Stalling.
Frank, Roslyn M. (2008). The Language-Organism-Species Analogy: A Complex -------. (1939). Wetterleuchten: Aufsdtze aus der Kampfzeit. 3 vols. Ed. Georg-
Adaptive Systems Approach to Shifting Perspectives on “Language”. In: Roslyn Wilhelm Muller, Munich: Zentralverlag der NSDAP.
M. Frank, Rene Dirven, Tom Ziemke and Enrique Bernardez (eds.). Body — . (1971). Goebbels Reden. Ed. Helmut Heiber. 2 vols. Munich: Heyne.
Language and Mind. Vol. 2: Socio-Cultural Situatedness. Berlin- Mouton de ------- . (1993-2004). Tagebucher und Diktate. Ed. Elke Frohlich. 24 vols. Munich:
Gruyter, 215-262.
Institut fur Zeitgeschichte.
— . (2009). Metaphors of Discourse Evolution. Iii: Andreas Musolff and Jorg
Goldhagen, Daniel Jonah (2003). Hitler’s Willing Executioners: Ordinary Ger­
17^189^^^’ ' Discourse. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, mans and the Holocaust. London: Abacus (first ed. New York 1996: Knopf).
Frei, Norbert and Johannes Schmitz (1989). Journalismus im Dritten Reich Gould, Stephen Jay (2000). Wonderful Life: The Burgess Shale and the Nature of
Munich: C. H. Beck. History. London: Vintage.
Fnedlander, Saul (1998). Nazi Germany & the Jews. Vol. 1: The Years of Persecu­ Grady, Joseph and Christopher Johnson (2003). Converging evidence for the
tion, 1933-1939. London: Phoenix. notions of subscene and primary scene. In: Rene Dirven and Ralf Porings (eds.).
— . (2000). The Extermination of the European Jews in Historiography: Fiftv Metaphor and Metonymy in Comparison and Contrast. Berlin and New York:
De Gruyter, 533-554.
Years Later. In: Omer Bartov (ed.). The Holocaust: Origins, Implementation
Aftermath. London, New York: Routledge, 79-91. Grady, Joseph, Todd Oakley and Seana Coulson (1999). Blending and Metaphor.
In: Raymond W. Gibbs and Gerard Steen (eds.). Metaphor in Cognitive Linguis­
^ Vol. 2: The Years of Extermination, tics. Amsterdam: John Beniamins, 101-124.
1933-1939. New York: HarperCollins.
Fri^tlieb, Christian Werner (1614). Prudentia Politica Christiana, Das ist: Gregor, Neil (2005). How to Read Hitler. London: Granta.
Beschreibung einer Christlichen/NiitzUchen und guten Policey/wie dieselbe Greive, Hermann (1983). Geschichte des modernen Antisemitismus. Darmstadt:
beschaffen setn solle/auch mit Gottes hulffe in gutem Zustande erhalten werden Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
konne. Durch Vergleichung deren mit dem Menschlichen Korper und dessen Grimm, Jacob and Wilhelm (1984). Deutsches Worterbuch. 33 vols. Munich:
Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag.
vornembsten Ghedmassen und Eigenschafften. Goslar: Voigt.
Fruhsorge, Gotthardt (1974). Der politische Korper. Zum Begriff des Politischen Gross, Raphael (2000). Carl Schmitt und die Juden. Eine deutsche Rechtslehre.
Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp.
im 17. Jahrhundert und in den Romanen Christian Weises. Stuttgart: Metzler. Guilhaumou, Jacques (1989). La langue politique et la Revolution Frangaise. Paris:
Englischen aufden deutschen Wortschatz Meridiens Klincksieck.
1640-181S. Berlin: Erich Schmidt Verlag.
Geeraert^ Dirk and Stefan Grondelaers (1995). Looking Back at Anger- Cul­ ^Guldin, Rainer (2000). Korpermetaphern: Zum Verhdltnis von Politik und
Medizin. Wurzburg: Konigshausen & Neumann.
tural Traditions and Metaphorical Patterns. In: John R. Taylor and Robert E. Gunther, Hans F. K. (1922). Rassenkunde des deutschen Volkes. Munich: J. F.
MacLaury (eds.). Language and the Cognitive Construal of the World Berlin- Lehmanns.
de Gruyter, 153-179.
Gellately, Robert (1990). The Gestapo and German Society: Enforcing Racial Pol­ Gurian, Waldemar (under pseudonym “Paul Muller”) (1934). Entscheidung und
icy 1933—1945. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ordnung. Zu den Schriften von Carl Schmitt. Schjveizerische^Tirutttischau.
Monatsschrift fiir Geistesleben und Kultur, 34: 566-576.
— . (2001). Backing Hitler: Consent and Coercion in Nazi Germany. Oxford- Habermas, Jurgen (1982). Theorie und Praxis. Sozialphilosophische Studien (3rd
Oxtord University Press.
ed.). Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp.
Gentner Dedre, Keith Holyoak and Boicho N. Kokinov (eds.) (2001). The Analogi­
cal Mind: Perspectives from Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hachmeister, Lutz and Michael Kloft (eds.) (2005). Das Goebbels-Experiment:
Gevaert, Caroline (2005). The Anger Is Heat Question: Detecting Cultural Influ- Propaganda und Politik. Stuttgart: Deutsche Verlags-Anstalt.
ence on the Conceptualization of Anger through Diachronic Corpus Analysis Hale, David George (1971). The Body Politic. A Political Metaphor in Renaissance
In: Nicole Delbecque, Johan van der Auwera and Dirk Geeraerts (eds.). Perspec­ English Literature. The Hague/Paris: Mouton.
tives on Variation: Sociolinguistic, Historical, Comparative. Berlin: Mouton de Hamann, Brigitte (1996). Hitlers Wien: Lehrjahre eines Diktators. Munich:
Gruyter, 195-208. Piper.
Gil^s, Raymond W. Jr. (2005). Embodiment and Cognitive Science. Cambridee- Hampsher-Monk, Iain, Karin Tilmans and Frank van Vree (eds.) (1998). History
Cambridge University Press. of Concepts: Comparative Perspectives. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University
Press.
186 Bibliography
Bibliography 187
Harris, Jonathan Gil (1998). Foreign Bodies and the Body Politic- Discourses of
Socml Pathology m Early Modern England. Cambridge: Cambridge University "" ’O x 'C f B l ^ r e i r ^ ''^ ^ ofiBe English Vocabu-
Harwood, John T. (1986). Introduction: Thomas Hobbes's Briefe of the Art of ^^Esbury. Tiid-
r^Har'JooA' r ond Bernard'Lamy. Ed. John Hull, David L. (198^. Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social
r Harwood. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press,
and Conceptual Development of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hawkins, Bruce (2001) Ideology, Metaphor and Iconographic Reference In- Rene Hunt, Lynn (1984). Po/irics, Culture and Class in the French Revolution. Berkeley
CorneHa Ilie (eds.). Language and Ideology. Volume II- University of California Press. ^'
Descnptwe Cognitive Approaches. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: Beniamins 27-50 ^ t. Bodies of Marie Antoinette: Political Pornography and
Heme, Hemnch (1976). Sdmtliche Schriften. Ed. Klaus BrieglebSnTc^Hanser the Problem pf the Feminine in the French Revolution. In: Lynn Hunt (ed.). Eroti-
Herder Johann Gottfried [1777] (1893). Deutsches Museum Von Ahnifchkeirder cism and the Body Politic. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 108-130.
m ttleren englischen und deutschen Dichtkunst, nebst Verschiednem das daraus Hunt, Maurice (2002). Dismemberment, Corporeal Reconstitution, and the Body
Politic in Cymbehne . Studies in Philology, 99 (4): 401-431
__ ^ rm 4 9 T S 523-524.
T e-- ^ ^ Pf’flosophte der Geschichte der Menschheit (2000). The Language of the
In. Ed. B. Suphan, vol. 14, Berlin 1909. Third Reich. LTI Lingua Tertit Imperii. A Philologist’s Notebook. Henry
T’^e/ews^ Enemy: Nazi Propaganda During World War II Sweet Society Bulletin, 42 (2004): 36-39. ^
and the Holocaust. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press. International Military Tribunal (IMT) (ed.) (1948). Trial of the Major War Crimi­
nals. Nuremberg: Allied Control Authority for Germany
in the Reign
(King Henry the Eighth. Part I: Starkey’s Life and Letters. With an appen­ Jackel, Eberhard (1981). Hitler’s Worldview: A Blueprint for Power. Translated
dix, gtvmgan extract from Sir William Forrest’s Pleasant Poesye of pZceUe from the German by Herbert Arnold. Foreword by Franklin L. Ford. Cam­
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press
x S e r , iif-Ix iv h ^ N- Axel Kuhn (eds.) (1980). Hitler. Sdmtliche Aufzeichnungen
1905-1924. Stuttgart: Deutsche VerlagsAnstalt. ^
Jager, Hans-Wolf (1971). Politische Metaphorik im Jakobinismus und im Vormdrz.
Stuttgart: Metzlersche Verlagsbuchhandlung.
H a ;e n r d L J tn ° ? a “ e rlfp re 1 r" “ " ^ Jessen Hans {sd.) {1965). Friedrich der Grofle und Maria Theresia in
^ ‘’H M e T e ^ r n 'l '^h Einstellungen und Ruckblenden von Fritz Augenzeugenbertchten Berlin, Darmstadt, Vienna: Deutsche Buch-Gemeinschaft.
M Ar Wissen' unter Josef Goebhels. Diiss.eldotf: Verlag John of Salisbury (19«5). Pohcrattcus sive De nugis Curialium et vestigiis philos-
^horum. Ed. Clemens C. I. Webb. 2 vols. Reprint edition. Frankfurt/Main:
Hitler, Adolf (1933). Mein Kampf (23id ed.). Munich: Franz Eher Nachfolger. Minerva (Original edition: Oxford 1909).
(1990). Poltcraticus: Of the Frivolities of Courtiers and the Footprints of
by Philosophers. Edited and translated by Carl J. Nederman. Cambridge: Cam­
bridge University Press. ®
institiffSz\hg^;cS:.At^:ii G ® Johnson, Ben (1966). Three Comedies. Harmondsworth: Penguin
Johnson, Mark (1981) Introduction: Metaphor in the Philosophical Tradition. In-
" tK ^ e d T Ton- Mark Johnson (ed.). Philosophical Perspectives on Metaphor. Minnesota- Uni­
n of Rhetorique. In: The Rhetorics ofThbmas versity of Minnesota Press, 3-47.
Hobbes and Bernard Lamy. Ed. John T. Harwood. Carbondale and E d w aX -■ (1987). The Body in the Mind. The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination,
ville: Souther^IIlinois University Press, 33-128 and Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
^ c lw e lid fjp r™ ! Edited by Noel Malcolm. 2 vols. Oxford: Johnston David (1986). The Rhetoric of Leviathan: ThomasMobhes-and^he Poli-
tics of ^^^if^J^lJransformati^^^^ Princeton, NJ: Princ'kon University Press.
Johnston, Paul (1998). Body Politic. London: New English Library Ltd.
” l^ ;« s k y Cambridge: Cambridge Jones, Steve (1996). In the Blood; God, Genes and Destiny. London: piaminpo.
- {2000} The Language of the Genes: Biology, History and the Evolution-
M d triT A X ^ tf '^oolstonecraft. Paine ary Future. London: Flamingo.
Hofaann, Hanns Hubert (ed.) (1976a). Quellen zum Verfassungsorgadismus des (1966). Three Comedies. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Hetltgen Romischen Reiches Deutscher Nation, 149S-181S. Darmstadt- Wis Kalhs, Aristotle A. (2008). Nazi Propaganda and the Second World War Basing­
senschafthche_Buchgesellschaft. -L»armstadt. Wis- stoke: Palgrave Macmillan. ^
y^rfassungsorganismus des HeiUgen Kamper, Heidrun (1996). Zeitgeschichte—Sprachgeschichte. Gedanken bei der
Darmstadt W.ssenschaftii- L » S - t 6 2 . ^— ‘-che
Hollstein, Dorothea (1971). yud Suss- und die Deutschen: Antisemitische Voru- SiVh’r^pH^ Kulturkonzept Victor Klemperers. In: Karl Heinz
rteile im nationalsozialistischen Sptelfilm. Frankfurt/Main, Berlin: Ullstein. A ufbau^V erk^ Materialien fur Lehrer. Berlin: ’
188 Bibliography Bibliography 189

Kant, Immanuel (1983). Werke in zehn Bdnden. Ed. Wilhelm Weischedel. Darm­ ------- . (2005b). Awakening from the Nightmare of History: Psychological Inter­
stadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. pretation of War and Genocide, http://www.psych-culture.com/docs/rk-aw.
Kantorowicz, Ernst H. [1957] (1997). The King’s Two Bodies: A Study in Mediae­ html.
val Political Theology. With a new Preface by William Chester Jordan. Princ­ Kokoschka, Oskar (1971). Mem Lehe«. Munich: Bruckmann.
eton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Koschorke, Albrecht, Susanne Liidemann, Thomas Frank and Ethel Matala de
Kaplan, Marion A. (1998). Between Dignity and Despair: Jewish Life in Nazi Mazza (2007). Der fiktive Staat. Konstruktionen des politischen Korpers in der
Germany. New York: Oxford University Press. Geschichte Europas. Frankfurt/Main: Fischer.
Karwowsky, Michael (2004). The British Body Politic (Review of Anthony Samp­ Koselleck, Reinhart (1973). Kritik und Krise. Eine Studie zur Pathogenese der
son, Who Runs This place? The Anatomy of Britain in the 21st Century. Lon­ burgerlichen Welt. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp.
don: John Murray 2004). Contemporary Review, 285 (1666): 304-305. Kovecses, Zoltan (1995). Anger: Its Language, Conceptualization, and Physiology
Kelly, Alfred (1981). The Descent of Darwin: The Popularisation of Darwinism in in the Light of Cross-Cultural Evidence. In: J. R. Taylor and R. E. MacLaury
Germany 1860-1914. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press. (eds.). Language and the Cognitive Construal of the World. Berlin; W. de
Kelly, George Armstrong (1986). Mortal Man, Immortal Society? Political Meta­ Gruyter, 181-196. ^ ^ r j n •
phors in Eighteenth Century France. Political Theory, 14 (1): 5-29. _____. (2002). Metaphor: A Practical Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University
Kempshall,M. S. (1997). The Common Goodin Late Medieval Political Thought. Press*
Oxford: Clarendon Press. ------- . (2005). Metaphor in Culture: Universality and Variation. Cambridge/New
Kershaw, Ian (1983). Popular Opinion and Political Dissent in the Third Reich: York: Cambridge University Press. ^ ,
Bavaria 1933-1945. Oxford: Oxford University Press. _____. (2006). Language, Mind and Culture. A Practical Introduction. Oxtord /
------- . (1999). Hitler, 1889-1936: Hubris. London: Allen Lane. New York: Oxford University Press.
. (2000). Hitler, 1936-1945: Nemesis. London: Allen Lane. ------- (2009). Metaphor, Culture and Discourse: The Pressure of Coherence. In:
------- . 12008]. Hitler, Germans, and the Final Solution. New Haven/London: Andreas Musolff and Jorg Zinken (eds.). Metaphor and Discourse. Basingstoke:
Yale University Press. Palgrave Macmillan, 11-24.
Kertzer, David I. (2003). Out of the Red Shadows: Anti-Semitism in Stalin’s Rus­ Krebs, Birgit-Nicole (1993). Sprachhandlung und Sprachwtrkung. Untersuchun-
sia. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books. gen zur Rhetorik, Sprachkritik und zum Fall Jenninger. Berlin: E. Schmidt.
Kettenacker, Lothar (1983). Der Mythos vom Reich. In: Karl Heinz Bohrer (ed.). Kulka, Otto Dov and Aron Rodrigue (1984). The German Population and the Jews
Mythos und Moderne. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 261-289. in the Third Reich: Recent Publications and Trends in Research on German
Kevles, Daniel J. (1995). In the Name of Eugenics: Genetics and the Uses of Society and the “Jewish Question”. Yad Vashem Studies, 1: 421-425.
Human Heredity. With a new preface by the author. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Kulka, Otto Dov and Eberhard Jackel (eds.) (2004). Die Juden in den gehetmen
University Press. NS-Stimmungsberichten 1933-1945. Diisseldorf: Droste.
Kienpointner, Manfred (2005). Racist Manipulation within Austrian, German, Kwiet Konrad and Helmut Eschwege (1995). Selbstbehauptung und Widerstand.
Dutch, French and Italian Right-Wing Populism. In: Louis de Saussure and Deutsche Juden im Kampf um Existenz und Menschenwiirde 1933-1945.
Peter Schulz (eds.). Manipulation and Ideologies in the Twentieth Century. Hamburg: Christians.
Amsterdam, Philadelphia: Benjamins, 213-235. Lakoff, George (1987). Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories
Klemperer, Victor (1975). LTI: Notizbuch eines Philologen. Leipzig: Philipp Rec­ ‘ Reveal about the Mind. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.
lam Jr. Lakoff, George and Mark Johnson (1980). Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: Uni­
------- . (1995). Ich will Zeugnis ablegen bis zum letzten: Tagebiicher 1933-1945. versity of Chicago Press.
2 vols. Berlin: Aufbau-Verlag. ______ (1999). Philosophy in the Flesh: The embodied Mind and Its Challenge to
------- . (2000). The Language of the Third Reich. LTI. Lingua Tertii Imperii. A Western New York: Basic Books.
Philologist’s Notebook. Trans, by Martin Brady. London and New Brunswick, Lakoff, George and Mark Turner (1989). More than Cool Reason: A Field Guide
NJ: The Athlone Press. to Poetic Metaphor. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.
Koenen, Andreas (1995). Der Fall Carl Schmitt: Sein Aufstieg zum “Kronjuristen Laqueur, Walter (1980). The Terrible Secret: Suppression^fthe-Truth-abotH-Hit-
des Dritten Reiches”. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. ler’s “Final Solution”. Harmondsworth: Penguin, z'
Koenigsberg, Richard (1986). The Psychoanalysis of Racism, Revolution and Leezenberg, Michiel (2001). Contexts of Metaphor. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Nationalism. New York; Library of Social Science (accessed 30 January 2010). Lenin, Vladimir Ilyitsch (1963-69). The State and Revolution. In: Collected Works.
. (1992). Hitler’s Ideology: A Study in Psychoanalytic Sociology. New York: Moscow: Progress Publishers, vol. 25, 381-492.
Library of Social Science (accessed 30 January 2010). Levitas, Ruth (1986). The Ideology of the New Right. Oxford: Blackwell.
. (2004a). Hitler’s Body and the Body Politic. http://www.psych-culture. Liebeschutz, Hans (1950). Mediaeval Humanism in the Life and Writings of John
com/docs/rk-hb.html (accessed 30 January 2010). of Salisbury. London: The Warburg Institute.
------- . (2004b). The Logic of the Holocaust: Why the Nazis killed the Jews, http:// Lincoln, Bruce (1986). Myth, Cosmos and Society: Indo-European Themes of Cre­
home.earthlink.net/%7Elibraryofsocialscience/logic.htm (accessed 30 January ation and Destruction. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Lindemann, Albert S. (2001). Anti-Semitism before the Holocaust. London:
------- . (2005a). Genocide as Immunology: The Psychosomatic Source of Culture.
http://home.earthlink.net/%7Elibraryofsocialscience/gi.htm (accessed 30 Tanu- Linke, Uli (1999). German Bodies: Race and Representation after Hitler. London:
ary2010). ’ Routledge.
190 Bibliography Bibliography 191
Lipstadtj Deborah (1995). Denying the Holocaust: The Growing Assault on Truth Maschke, Gunter (2003). Zum „Leviathan“ von Carl Schmitt. In: Carl Schmitt.
and yiemory. London: Penguin. Der Leviathan in der Staatslehre des Thomas Hobbes. Sinn und Fehlschlag
Lockwood, Shelley (1997). Introduction. In: Sir John Fortescue. On the Laws and eines politischen Symbols. Ed. Gunter Maschke. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta,
Governance of England. Ed. Shelley Lockwood. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni­ 179-244.
versity Press, xv-xxxix. Matthaus, Jurgen (2004). Operation Barbarossa and the Onset of the Holocaust,
Lohenstein, Daniel Casper von (1689). Daniel Caspers von L ohenstein Grossmiithiger June-December 1941. In: Christopher Browning. The Origins of the Final
Feldherr Arminius oder Herrmann / Als Ein tapfferer Beschirmer der deutschen Solution: The Evolution of Nazi Jewish Policy, September 1939—March
Freyheit / Nebst seiner Durchleuchtigen Thussnelda In einer sinnreichen Staats= 1942. With contributions by Jurgen Matthaus. London: William Heinemann,
Liebes= und Helden=Geschichte dem Vaterlande zu Liebe Dem deutschen Adel 244-308.
aber zu Ehren und ruhmlichen Nachfolge In Zweyen Theilen vorgestellet. Und Mayer, T. F. (1989a). Introduction. In: Thomas Starkey (1989). A Dialogue between
mit annehmlichen Kupffern gezieret. Leipzig: Gleditsch. Pole and Lupset. Ed. T. F. Mayer (Camden fourth series, vol. 37). London:
Lohneyss, Georg Engelhard (1622). Aulico P(Aitica. Darin gehandelt wird, 1. Von Offices of the Royal Historical Society, University College London, vii-xvii.
Erziehung und Information Junger Herrn. 2. Vom Ampt Tugend und Qualitet ------- . (1989b). Thomas Starkey and the Commonweal: Humanist Politics and
der Fiirsten und bestellung derselben Rath und Officiren. 3. Von bestellung der Religion in the Reign of Henry VIII. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Concilien, die ein Fiirst in seinem Land haben mus. Allen Regenten, fiirstlichen Mcllwain, Charles H. (1918). The Political Works of James I. Cambridge, MA:
Rdthen, Hoff- und Land Officirern. auch sonst den Unterthanen und J[e]der- Harvard University Press.
menniglichen Zu nutz und gut beschrieben. Remlingen: Lohneysen. Meier, Heinrich (1998). Carl Schmitt, Leo Strauss und der "Der Begriff des
Longerich, Peter (1987). Fropagandisten im Krieg: Die Presseabteilung des Aus- Politischen". Zu einem Dialog unter Abwesenden. (Erweiterte Neuausgabe).
wdrtigen Amies unter Ribbentrop. Munich: Oldenbourg. Stuttgart/Weimar: Metzler.
----:— . (2003). The Unwritten Order: Hitler’s Role in the Final Solution. Stroud: Mensch, James R. (2009). Embodiments: From the Body to the Body Politic. Evan­
Tempus. ston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
------- . (2006). “Davon haben wir nichts gewusst!" Die Deutschen und die Juden- Michael, Robert and Karen Doerr (2002). Nazi-Deutsch/Nazi German: An Eng­
uerfolgung. Munich: Siedler. lish Lexicon of the Third Reich. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.
Lorenz, Gottfried (ed.) (1991). Quellen zur Vorgeschichte und zu den Anfangen Mieder, Wolfgang (2000). "In lingua veritas.” Sprichwdrtliche Rhetorik in Victor
des Drei/Iigjdhrigen Krieges. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. Klemperers "Tagebiichern 1933-194S”. Wien: Edition Praesens.
Lovejoy, Arthur Oncken (1936). The Great Chain of Being: A Study of the History Milfull, John (ed.) (1993). Why Germany! National-Socialist Anti-Semitism and
of an Idea. Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press. the European Context. Oxford: Berg Publishers.
Ludemann, Susanne (2007). Kdrper, Organismus. In: Ralf Konersmann (ed.). Miller, Mary and Karl Taube (1993). An Illustrated Dictionary of the Gods and
Worterbuch der philosophischen Metaphern. Darmstadt. Wissenschaftliche Symbols of Ancient Mexico and the Maya. London: Thames and Hudson.
Buchgesellschaft, 168-182. Mintz, Samuel I. (1989). Leviathan as Metaphor. Hobbes Studies, 2: 3-9.
Luther, Martin (1917). Luthers Werke. Ed. Arnold E. Berger. 3 vols. Leipzig/ Mitscherlich, Alexander and Margarete Mitscherlich (1967). Die Unfdhigkeit zu
Vienna: Bibliographisches Institut. trauern. Grundlagen kollektiven Verhaltens. Munich: Piper.
Machiavelli, Niccolo (2003). The Discourses. Edited with an Introduction by Ber­ Moltmann, Gunther (1964). Joseph Goebbels’ Rede zum totalen Krieg am 18.
nard Crick using the translation of Leslie J. Walker, S.J., with revisions by Brian Februar 1943. Vierteljahreshefte fiir Zeitgeschichte, 12: 13-43.
Richardso’n. London: Penguin. Montaigne, Michel de (1965). Essais. 3 vols. Paris: Editions Gallimard.
------- . (2005). The Prince. Translated and Edited by Peter Bondanella. With an Motohashi, Tesuya (1994). Body Politic and Political Body in Coriolanus. Forum
Introduction by Maurizio Viroli. Oxford: Oxford University Press. for Modern Language Studies, 30/2: 97-112.
Mairgiinther, Wilfred (1987). Reichskristallnacht. Kiel: Neuer Malik Verl'ag. Mouton, Nicolaas T. O. (2009). On the Evolution of Social Scientific Metaphors:
Maitland, Frederic William (2003). State, Trust and Corporation. Eds. David Run- A Cognitive-Historical Inquiry into the Divergent Trajectories of the Idea that
ciman and Magnus Ryan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Collective Entities—States and Societies, Cities and Corporations—Are Bio-
Malcolm, Noel (2002). The Title Page of Leviathan, Seen in a Curious Perspective. logical Organisms. Unpublished PhD thesis, CopenhSgen:”Copenhagen Busi­
In: Aspects of Hobbes. Oxford. Clarendon Press, 200-233. ness School.
Mannes, Stefan (1999). Antisemitismus im nationalsozialistischen Propaganda- Muller, Jan-Werner (2003). A Dangerous Mind: Carl Schmitt in Post-War Euro­
film. “Jud Sufi” und "Der ewige Jude”. Cologne: Teiresias. pean Thought. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.
Marie de France (1993). The Fable of a Man, His Belly, and His Limbs. In: Carl Miiller-Richter, Klaus (1998). Einleitung. In: Klaus Muller-Richter and Arturo
Nederman and Kate Langdon Forhan (eds.). Readings in Medieval Political Larcati (eds.). Der Streit um die Metapher: Poetologische Texte von Nietzsche
Theory 1100-1400. Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing, 24-25. bis Handke. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 4-30.
Marsilius of Padua (2005). The Defender of the Peace. Ed., trans. Annabel Brett. Musolff, Andreas (2003). Ideological functions of metaphor: The conceptual
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. metaphors of health and illness in public discourse. In: Rene Dirven, Roslyn
Martinich, A[loysius] P. (1992). The Two Gods of Leviathan: Thomas Hobbes on Frank and Martin Putz (eds.). Cognitive Models in Language and Thought:
Religion and Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ideologies, Metaphors and Meaning. Berlin/New York: Mouton de Gruyter,
------- . (1997). Thomas Hobbes. Basingstoke: Macmillan. 327-352. ,
Marx, Karl (1960). Der achtzehnte Brumaire des Louis Bonaparte. In: Karl Marx ------- . (2004a). Metaphor and Political Discourse: Analogical Reasoning in
und Friedrich Engels. Werke. Berlin/DDR: Dietz Verlag, vol. 8, 149-158. Debates about Europe. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
192 B ibliography Bibliography 193
— (2004b). The Heart of the European Body Politic. British and German Patzold, Kurt and Erika Schwarz (eds.) (1992). Tagesordnung: Judenmord. Die
^ Multicultural Devd- Wannsee-Konferenz am 20. Januar 1942. Berlin: Metropol.
Pauwels, Paul and Anne-Marie Simon-Vandenbergen (1995). Body Parts in Lin­
‘• P ' A p p a r e n t Denunciation of guistic Action: Underlying Schemata and Value judgements. In: Louis Goos-
Metaphor by Thomas Hobbes. Hobbes Studies, XVIII: 95-111 sens, Paul Pauwels, Brygida Rudzka-Ostyn, Anne-Marie Simon-Vandenbergen
. (2005)^, Genetic Information as Part of the “Greai Chain of Being”, meta- and Johan Vanparys. By Word of Mouth: Metaphor, Metonymy and Linguis­
January 20lb/^ fi«p://www.metaphorik.de/08/Musolff.pdf (accessed 30 tic Action in Cognitive Perspective. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: Benjamins,

~1^1)*23-38 in Public Discourse. Metaphor and Symbol, Pechau, Manfred (1935). Nationalsozialismus und deutsche Sprache. Greifswald:
Buchdruckerei Hans Adler.
^ Role Do Metaphors Play in Racial Prejudice?—The Func- Peil, Dietmar (1983). Untersuchungen zur Staats- und Herrschaftsmetaphorik in
41/1 21-44 Imagery in Hitler’s “Mein Kampf”. Patterns of Prejudice, literarischen Zeugnissen von der Antike bis zur Gegenwart. Munich: Fink.
------- . (1985). Der Streit der Glieder mit dem Magen. Studien zur Uberlieferung
B-ingstoke: und Deutungsgeschichte der Fabel des Menenius Agrippa von der Antike bis
ins 20. Jahrhundert. Frankfurt/Main: Lang.
Nederman Cary J- (l^^'sS). A Duty to Kill: John of Salisbury’s Theory of Tyran­ Peltonen, Markku (2009). Political Rhetoric and Citizenship in Coriplanus. In: David
nicide. Keview of Politics, 50: 365-389. ^ ^ Armitage, Conal Condren and Andrew Fitzmaurice (eds.). Shakespeare and Early
— . (1990). ‘Editor’s Introduction’. In: John of Salisbury. Policraticus: Of the Modern Political Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 234-252.
trwolmes of Courtiers and the Footprints of Philosophers. Ed. Carl I. Neder- Peries, Gabriel (1991). La metaphore medico-chirurgicale dans le discours militaire
Cambridge University Press, xv-xxviii. da la “guerre revolutionnaire”. Mots. Les langages de la politique, 26: 5-23.
~ T7f'. Politics: The Diversification of Organic Metaphors in the Picker, Henry (Hrsg.) (2003). Hitlers Tischgesprdche im Fuhrerhauptquartier.
Later Middle Ages. Pensiero Politico Medievale, 2; 59-87. Munich: Propylaen.
Nederman Cary J. Kate Langdon Forhan (eds.) (1993). Readings in Medieval Pizan, Christine de (1994). The Book of the Body Politic. Edited and translated by
^"""^l^n^PoI's/Cambridge; Hackett Publishing. Kate Langdon Forhan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
^ ,^'^J^^l\<^hen Stand / Welcher massen derselbige in Plato (1993). Republic. Ed. Robin Waterfield. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
beharrhchem Wesen erhalten/und was darzu gehoriglauch wie wiederumb zu Pocock, John G. A. (2003). The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political
schaden und untergang gerathen moge: Mit Einfuhrung allerhand zum Burger- Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition. Princeton: Princeton Univer­
sity Press (first edition 1975).
Poliakov, Leon (1974-75). The History of Anti-Semitism. 3 vols. London: Rout-
ledge & Kegan Paul.
Proctor, Robert N. (1988). Racial Hygiene: Medicine under the Nazis. Cambridge,
Structure and Practice of MA: Harvard University Press.
National Socialism. London: Gollancz. Prokhovnik, Raia (1991). Rhetoric and Philosophy in Hobbes’ Leviathan. New
Niemeier, Susanne (2000). Straight from the Heart—Metonymic and Metaphori­ York and London: Garland.
cal Explorations. In Antonio Barcelona (ed.). Metaphor and Metonymy at the Przyrembel, Alexandra (2003). ‘"Rassenschande”. Reinheitsmythos und Vernichtung-
XT- ^°Snitive Perspective. Beriin/New York: De Gruvter 195-213 slegitimation im Nationalsozialismus. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck 6c Ruprecht.
Pufendotf, Samuel von (1994). Die Verfassung des deutschen Reiches. Ed. and
theJhird Reich.hondon:R.owt\tdge. «/ trans. Horst Denzer. Frankfurt/Main: Insel Verlag.
. (2006). Remembering the Holocaust: Representation, Neglect and Instru- ------- . (2007). The Present State of Germany. Trans. Edmund Bohun [1696], ed.
mentalization. European History Quarterly 36(2): 279-291. Michael J. Seidler. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
Norton, Anne (2004). Leo Strauss and the Politics of American Empire. New Rash, Felicity (2005a). A Database of Metaphors in Adolf Hkltth-dileifTKiimpf
Haven and London: Yale University Press http://webspace.qmul.ac.uk/fjrash/metaphors_meinLkampf.pdf (accessed: 30
January 2010).
--------. (2005b). Metaphor in Hitler’s Mein Kampf metaphorik.de 9, 74-111.
Obst, Dieter (1991). “Reichskristallnachr. Vrsachen und Verlauf des antisemi- http://www.metaphorik.de/09/rash.pdf (accessed 30 January 2010).
------- . (2006). The Language of Violence. Adolf Hitler’s Mein Kampf New York:
rciei IT. I
^ of Contentporary Oerntan Roberts, Penny (2007). The Kingdom’s Two Bodies? Corporeal Rhetoric and Royal
Authority During the Religious Wars. French History, 21 (2): 147-164.
Paine, Thomas (1891). The Rights of Man: Being an Answer to Mr. Burke’s Attack Rohrich, Lutz (2001). Das grofle Lexikon der sprichwortlichen Redensarten (new
on the French Revolution. London: Progressive Publishing Cdmpanv. edition). 3 vols. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
PatKrson, Annabel M. (1991). Fables of Power: Aesopian S itin g and Political Rose, Michael R. (1998). Darwin’s Spectre: Evolutionary Biology in the Modern
History. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. World. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
194 Bibliography Bibliography 195
Roseman, Mark (2002). The Villa, the Lake, the Meeting: Wannsee and the Final Schulze, Winfried (1986). Vom Gemeinnutz zum Eigennutz: Uber den Normenwan-
solution. London: Penguin. del in der standischen Gesellschaft der friihen Neuzeit. Historische Zeitschrift,
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1990). Du Contrat Social: Texte et Contextes. Eds. lose 243: 591-626. ■,
Medina, Andre Senik, Claude Morali et Gerard Chomienne. Paris: Magnard Seidel, Eugen and Ingeborg Seidel-Slotty (1961). Sprachwandel tm Dritten Reich.
(1994a). The Social Contract or the Principles of Political Right Trans Halle: Verlag Sprache und Literatur.
Christopher Betts. In; The Social Contract. Oxford: Oxford University Press^ Seidler, Michael J. (2007). Introduction. In: Samuel von Pufendorf. The Present
State of Germany. Trans. Edmund Bohun, ed. Michael J. Seidler. Indianapolis:
Pohtical Economy (‘Discourse on Political Economy’). Trans. Liberty Fund, ix-xxvii.
Christopher Betts. In; The Social Contract. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Semino, Elena (2008). Metaphor in Discourse. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press. •
Rumpf, Helrnut (1972) Carl Schmitt und Thomas Hobbes. Ideelle Beziehungen Shakespeare, William (1976). Coriolanus. Ed. Philip Brockbank. London: Meth­
und aktuelle Bedeutung. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot uen 8c Co.
Ryle, Gilbert (1949). The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson. ------- . (1983). The Complete Works of William Shakespeare. Edited, with a glos­
Sawday, Jonathan (1995). The Body Emblazoned: Dissection and the Human Body sary by W. J. Craig. London: Henry Pordes.
in Renaissance Culture. London and New York: Routledge. Shields, David (2004). Body Politic: The Great American Sport Machine. New
Schama, Simon (1989). Citizens. A Chronicle of the French Revolution New York* York; Simon 8c Schuster.
Vintage Books/London: Penguin. Shirer, William (1999). This Is Berlin. Reporting from Nazi Germany 1938-40.
Schank, Roger C. and Robert P. Abelson (1977). Scripts, Plans, Goals and Under­ With an introduction by John Keegan. London: Hutchinson.
standing. An Inquiry into Human Knowledge Structures. Hillsdale, NT- Law­ Shogimen, Takashi (2008). Treating the Body Politic: The Medical Metaphor of
rence Erlbaum Associates. Political Rule in Late Medieval Europe and Tokugawa Japan. The Review of
Schilling, Heinz (1994). Hofe und Allianzen. Deutschland 1648-1763 (Band 6- Politics, 70: 77-104.
Siedler Deutsche Geschichte). Berlin: Siedler. Shorter Oxford Dictionary on Historic Principles (2002). Fifth edition. 2 vols.
Schmitt, Carl (1933a). Das Gesetz zur Behebung der Not von Volk und Reich Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung, 38: 455-458. Siever, Holger (2001). Kommunikation und Verstehen. Der Fall Jenninger als
— . (1933b). Das gute Recht der deutschen Revolution. Westdeutscher Beispiel einer semiotischen Kommunikationsanalyse. Frankfurt/Main: Lang.
Beobachter, Amtliches Organ der NSDAP, 12 March 1933. Sieyes, Emmanuel (1989). Qu’est-ce que le Tiers ttat? Precede de L’Essai sur les Priv­
^ 950^*^^ Fuhrer schutzt das Recht. Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung, 39: ileges. Ed. Edme Champion. Paris: Quadrige-Presses Universitaires de France.
Simon, Gerd (2009). "Weifle Juden’' sind nach wie vor verfemt. Das Beispiel
— . (1935). Die Verfassung der Freiheit. Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung, 40: des Tubinger Philosophen Vaihinger. http://homepages.uni-tuebingen.de/gerd.
1X33^XX3 Simon/ (accessed 1 December 2009).
(ed.) {1936). Das Judentum in der Rechtswissenschaft. Ansprachen, Vor- Sington, Derrick and Arthur Weidenfeld (1942). The Goebbels Experiment. Lon­
trage und Ergebnisse der Tagung der Reichsgruppe Hochschullehrer des NSRB don: John Murray.
am 3. und 4. Oktober 1936. Berlin: Deutscher Rechts-Verlag. Skinner, Quentin (1978). The Foundations of Modern Political Thought. 2 vols.
■ begriffdes Politischen. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot. ^ Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
• (2003). Der Leviathan in der Staatslehre des Thomas Hobbes: Sinn und ------- . (1996). Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes. Cambridge:
tehlschlag etn^ politischen Symbols. Ed. Gunter Maschke. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta. Cambridge University Press.
. (2006). neorie des Partisanen. Berlin: Duncker 8c Humblot. ------- . (2000). Machiavelli. A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford Univer­
-■ (2008). The Leviathan in the State Theory of Thomas Hobbes: Meaning sity Press.
^ d Failure of a Political Symbol. Trans. George Schwab and Erna Hilfstein ------- . (2002). Vision of Politics. Vol. 3: Hobbes and Civil Science. Cambridge:
With a new foreword by Tracy B. Strong. Chicago and London: University of Cambridge University Press.
Chicago Press. ^ontag, Susan (1978). Illness as Metaphor. New York: Vijitage-Books,---- —
Schmitz-Bermng, Cornelia (2000). Vokabular des Nationalsozialismus. Berlin ------- . (1991). Illness as Metaphor and AIDS and Its Metaphors. Harmonds-
New York: de Gruyter. worth: Penguin.
Schnettger, Matthias (ed.) (2002). Imperium Romanum—Irregulare Corpus_ Southern, Richard W. (1970). Medieval Humanism and Other Studies. Oxford:
Teutscher Reichs-Staat. Das Alte Reich im Verstdndnis der Zeitgenossen und Blackwell.
der Historiographie. Mainz: Institut fur Europaische Geschichte Speer, Albert (1975). Spandauer Tagebiicher. Frankfurt am Main, Berlin, Vienna:
Schoenberner Gerhard (1980). Der gelbe Stern. Die Judenverfolgung in Europa Ullstein.
1933-1945. Frankfurt/Main: Fischer. Sperber, Dan (1996). Explaining Culture. A Naturalistic Approach. Oxford:
Schoenfeldt, Michael (1997). Fables of the Belly in Early Modern Europe. In: David Blackwell.
Hillmann and Carla Mazzio (eds.). The Body in Parts: Fantasies of Corporeal­ ------- . (2000). An Objection to the Memetic Approach to Culture. In: Rob­
ity in Early Modern Europe. New York, London: Routledge, 243-262. ert Aunger (ed.). Darwinizing Culture: The Status of Memetics as a Science.
Schoeps, Julius H. (Hrsg.) (1996). Ein Volk von Mordernf Die Dokumentation zur Oxford: Oxford University Press, 163-173.
Goldhagen-Kontroverse urn die Rolle der Deutschen im Holocaust. Hambure- Spicci, Mauro (2007). The Body as Metaphor: Digestive Bodies and Political Sur­
Rowohlt. gery in Shakespeare’s Macbeth. Medical Humanities, 33: 67-69.
196 Bibliography
Bibliography 197
- applied to H,tleri»,. Tendahl, Markus and Raymond W. Gibbs (2008). Complementary Perspectives on
Metaphor: Cognitive Linguistic and Relevance Theory. Jo«r««/ of Pragmatics
40/1:1823-1864.
Theweleit, Klaus (1980). Mdnnerphantasien. 2 vols. Reinbek: Rowohlt.
^^°^°”^ervatwe Publishers in Tillyard, E. M. W. (1982). The Elizabethan World Picture. Harmondsworth: Pen­
Starkey T hL ff?r9Sg/^ Hill: University of North Carolina Press. guin (first published in 1943).
ir ^ A v ^ between Pole and Lupset. Ed. T. F Maver Townsend, Rebecca (2005). ‘Hatten wir Schutzrechte wie Frosche oder Pandas,
S v J s h y to ^ K ' a f >■ H ls to ric a fs S ' ware unset Volk nicht vom Aussterben bedroht’: The use of Metaphor in Far-
Right Discourse. Paper at Conference of the Forum of Germanic Language
Studies, Cambridge University, Newnham College.
Steen, Gerard (2009). Three Kinds of Metaphor in Discourse- A T;no,„c,-- t Tucholsky, Kurt (1960). Gesammelte Werke in 10 Bdnden. Ed. Mary Gerold-Tu-
cholsky and Fritz J. Raddatz. Reinbek: Rowohlt.
Turner, Mark and Gilles Fauconnier (2003). Metaphor, Metonymy, and Binding.
In: Rene Dirven and Ralf Porings (eds.). Metaphor and Metonymy in Compari­
son and Contrast (Cognitive Linguistics Research 20). Berlin/New York: De
Gruyter, 469-487.
Tri,nc Metaphorik: Ein Versuch uber die sL ah ’
irans. Jorg Trabitius. Akzente, 34; 194-212 .^noan. Vande Winkel, Roel and David Welch (2007). Europe’s New Hollywood? The Ger­
Deutschen: Stimmung und Hal- man Film Industry under Nazi Rule. In: Roel Vande Winkel and David Welch
tung der deutschen Bevolkerung im Zweiten Weltkrieg Diisseldorf-Frnn (eds.). Cinema and the Swastika: The International Expansion of Third Reich
Stern Josef (2000). Metaphor in Context. Cambridse^MAMU^^^ Cinema. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 6-24.
^'Tuch^Zl Wilhelm E. Suskind (1989). dem Worter- Verhandlungen des Reichstags (1930). Stenographische Berichte, V. Wahlperiode.
buch des Unmenschen (Neue erweiterte Ausgabe mit Zeugnissen des Streites Vol. 444. Berlin: Reichsdruckerei.
c*- Sprachkritik). Frankfurt/Main, Berlin: Ullstein. Vogel, Christian (1992). Rassenhygiene—Rassenideologie—Sozialdarwinismus:
die Wurzeln des Holocaust. In: Hannes Friedrich and Wolfgang Matzow (eds.).
^ Stammbaum und Fortwachs oder Diensthare Medizin: Arzte hetrachten ihr Each im Nationalsozialismus. Got­
Munich: Kosel {first edition 1691).
tingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 11-31.
^ W 9^^^ ^^bmitt. Crown Jurist of the Third Reich- On Pre
Volmert, Johannes (1989). Politische Rhetorik des Nationalsozialismus. In: Konrad
S r P r T s s ': Empire. Lewiston, NY: Edwin Ehlich (ed.). Sprache im Faschismus. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 137-161.»
Walzer, Michael (ed.) (1992). Regicide and Revolution: Speeches at the Trial of Louis
Eechts in Deutschland. Vol 1 XVI. Translated by Marian Rothstein. New York: Columbia University Press.
^ rfn n if Tk “«D ^^^'l^y^^ssenschaft 1600-1800. Munich: C. H. Beck Weikart, Richard (2004). From Darwin to Hitler: Evolutionary Ethics, Eugenics,
• 7 u Tj , p Respubhca mixta” in the 17th Century On the Reren
and Racism in Germany. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Weinberg, Gerhard L. (ed.) (1961). Hitlers Zweites Buch: Ein Dokument aus
dem Jahr 1928. Mit einem Geleitwort von Hans Rothfels. Stuttgart: Deutsche
Verlags-Anstalt.
Weindlmg, Paul (1989). Health, Race and German Politics between National Uni­
'“K a titS S s S ^ '^ r ' offentliche Sprachsensibilitat: Ein fication and Nazism, 1870—1945. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
LTjittrSfdS,"^ W -^enschaft Weingart, Peter, Jurgen Kroll and Kurt Bayertz (1988). Rasse, Blut, Gene.
Geschichte der Eugenik und Rassenhygiene in Deutschland. Frankfurt/Main:
Suhrkamp.
— — n 99SI A^ Chicago: Chicago University Press. Weise, Christian (1686). Christian Weisens PoUtischerNirscherJAussUnte^hie-
rich M e^Sd )T99S? E^^’-Eegriffdes PoUtischen. In: Hein- denen Gedanken hervor gesucht / und alien Liebhal/ern zur Lust/alien Interes-
nch Meier (ed. (1998). Carl Schmitt, Leo Strauss und “der Begriffdes PoUtischen”
senten zu Nutz! nunmehro in Druck befordert. Leipzig: Fritzsch.
Welch, David (2007). Propaganda and the German Cinema 1933-1945. Revised
ed. London/NewYork: I. B. Tauris.
Wiegrefe, Klaus (2006). Das feme Reich. Der Spiegel, 32/2006.
( c’ of the Organism in the Political Theory of Tohn Wieland, Christoph Martin (1797). Ober die Rechte und Pflichten der Schriftsteller,
in Absicht ihrer Nachrichten und Urtheile fiber Nazionen, Regierungen, und
t i l B la S e n ; 3“ o /S .hs^«r/O xL d: andere offentliche Gegenstande. Sdmmtliche Werke. Vol. 30. Leiozie: Goschen
137-154 (first published 1785). ’
”^%l°rsky Prefs’. Categorization. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford Uni- Wildmann, Daniel (1998). Begehrte Korper: Konstruktion und Inszenierung des
Tegel, Susan (2007). Nazis and the Cinema. London: Continuum. “arischen” Mdnnerkdrpers im “Dritten Reich”. Wfirzburg: Konigshausen &
Neumann.
198 Bibliography

of SaUsbury. Oxford: Basil


on Early Modern
Index

Beri°nTunsttin ■ ‘”' F'^nkLt/Main, Vienna,


'^“ j^F?anrR;i!?Dk^^^^^ 7 ‘T ” oniture. In:Roslyn

drC ruT ter^st^W :


Zavadil Jeffery (2009). Bodies Politic and Bodies Cosmic: The Roman Stoic The

A Bacon, Francis, 105-106,115,


"pil23S.E'rs^^^^^ Abel, Karl'Dietrich, 155 169nn58-62
Zinken, Jorg and Andreas Musolff (2009) A Disconrce r#.ntr:»,4 v Abelson, Robert P., 153 Balakrishnan, Gopal, 175n56,175n75,
^ n k t < s; » “ d UndLran’d 4 ° r r d S r M t & ^ ^ ^ Ach, Manfred, 154 175n79,176n92
Zmken (eds.). Metaphor and Discourse. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan! Adrian IV (Pope), 85 Balistier, Thomas, 155n4
Aesop, 4, 82,148,163 Bankier, David, 155n2,157n39,
Zinken, Jorg, Ima Hellsten and Brigitte Nerlich (2008). Discourse Metanhors Tn- Agamben, Giorgio, 133,177 157n41,158n49,160nl02,
Roslyn Frank, Rene Dirven, Tom Ziemke and Enrique Bernardez (eds ) Bod^i Albertus Magnus, 122,164n52,165n67 160nll0,161nl27
S .I-?.dnessT er£:‘t'u to n “t Alkemeyer, Thomas, 148 Banks, Kathryn, 166nl
analogy/analogical argument. See Barnden, John, 151n3
metaphor Barsch, Claus-Ekkehard, 32-33,
geschichtliches 246 ^73 anti-Semitism, 11-23, 28, 30, 32-33, 154n69,154nn74-77
41^5, 47, 49, 51-57, 59, 61, Bartolus of Saxoferrato, 95,165n70
63, 65-67, 70-71, 76-77, 89, Bass, Allen M., 163nnl0-ll, 163n24,
127,132,134,137,153n65, 164n24
155nl04, 173nl0,174n39, Bauer, Yehuda, 28,153n46
176n89, 176n92. See also Holo­ Baumann, Zygmunt, 45-46, 70,
caust, National Socialism, racism 156nn20-22
elminationist, 13, 28, 71 Baumgold, Deborah, 169n3
intentionalist v. functionalist explana­ Baur, Erwin, 22
tions of, 42, 51,53,158n68 Bayerlz, Kurt, 153n51
Jewish question, 42, 48-52, 57-58, Beermann, R. 172n74
67,127,157n40 Behemoth, 128,131-132,134-135,
Protocols of the Elders of Zion, 36 138,174n44,177nl07
redemptive, 28, 32-35, 41-42, 60, Behnken, Klaus, 155-158,175n75
71, 87,116 Bein, Alexand^l74ji39__-—-—-—
Archambault, Paul, 148nl6 Benjamin, \^Iter, 57
Arendt, Hannah, 71,162n4,172n67 Berlin, Isaiah, 104,127-128,174n33
Arndt, Ernst Moritz, 127,174n37 Berschin, Walter, 125,173n24
Aristotle, 4,18, 81, 90-93, 95-96, 98, Bertau, Marie-Cecile, 169n8
123,151n3,163nn5-7,164n50, Bertelli, Sergio, 167nnl9-20
166n95,169nll, 170nl9 Bible, 4, 32-33, 82, 86, 90, 93,108,
Axton, Marie, 167nl8 125,134-135,153n65,154n76,
Augustine (of Hippo), 82, 91-93, 163nl0, 166n88,174nn45-I7,
95-96, 98,163nnl2-13 176n90
Deuteronomy, 166
B Genesis, 82,100
Baader, Gerhard, 153n51 Job, 128-129,134,174nn45-46,
Bachrach, Susan, 156n4 176n90
200 Index
Paul’s Epistles, 4, 82, 90-91, 95,102, Index 201
122,164n24,167nl8 Boberach, Heinz, 155nl, 158n65,
159n88,160nl01 member/limb, 5-6, 82, 85-89, Charles I, King of England, 111
Peter’s Epistles, 92,122,156n79 91-94, 96-97, 99,104,108, Charles VI, King of France, 94
biology/biological metaphors. See also Bockenforde, Ernst-Wolfgang, 148nl6
165n72, 177nn2-3 ^ 113,117,122-123,125-126, Charles IV, Emperor of the Holy
body metaphors, disease/illness Bodin,Jean, 166nl 172n64,173n30 Roman Empire, 156n71
metaphors, medical metaphors mouth, 84,171n52 Charles VII, Emperor of the Holy
animal metaphors, 13, 16, 29, 69-70 body metaphors, 1-8,11,14-16 nerves, 108-110
19-20,22-29,31, 34-41,’ Roman Empire, 125
81, 91, 111, 117135 43-48, 50-52, 55-56, 58-60, organ, 1, 5-6, 82, 85-87, 97,100, Charlesworth, Brian and Deborah,
. -leech, 24, 36-38 109-110,117,134,137,139, 151n65,153n54
maggot, 12,17, 36 62, 64-67, 69-10, 72-77, 170n26, 171n52
81-105, 107-113,115-129, Charteris-Black, Jonathan, 16,149n24,
rats, 36, 55 procreation, 110-114, 170n22 150n44, 162n8
133-145,147-148,150-152, sinews, 97
vermin, 13,24,3 6 ,3 8 ,5 5 ,5 7 , Chickering, Roger, 158n58
121, 143 i p , 163-174,177-178. See strength, 24, 46, 64, 97,108,110,
also biology, disease/illness meta­ Chilton, Paul, 19-21, 38,151nn55-58,
viper, 24, 36-39 115,118,134-135,176n90 151n66,159n77,162n8
bacillus, 21, 24-27, 35-38, 40, phors, medical metaphors soul, 1, 81-82, 84, 86-89, 91-93,
arm (of the law), 1, 94, 100,110 Christ. See also religion
156n9,160n98,160nl04 115,118 95, 98,108-110,113,129,132, body of, 82-83, 91-92, 95,122,143,
bacterium, 17, 36, 64-65,140 arteries, 24,113-114 174n52 164n24,167nl9
evolution, 18, 20-21, 30-32, 34, 69, toe/toenail, 1,5-6,100,107,147n3 C. as head of the Church, 82-83, 90,
74, 76-77 belly/stomach, 4-5, 82-83, 85-86 tongue, 87-88,100
88-90, 94-100,105,142,163n9, 92,123
instinct, 2,12, 24, 26, 34 veins, 24 C. as the good Shepherd, 95
nature,23-42, 81,91,103, 111, 165nn84-85,167h3,171n52 Bohun, Edmund, 173nl9
,birth/rebirth, 24, 118 Christine de Pizan, 94-97,142,
118, 130,135,165n64,166n88, Boniface VIII, Pope, 92, 165n58 165nn77-78, 165nn80-85,
171n42,172n67 blood/bloodstream, 5,11, 24-25 Borne, Ludwig, 132
29, 34-41, 46-49, 96-97,109, 166n86
organism/host organism, 12,16, Bosmajian, Haig, 14, 38,149nl2 ’ Cicero, 87
21, 24-25, 30-31, 34, 36, 38, 113,115-116,119,127, 140, Bossuet, Jacques Benigne, 175n64
153n48,170nl9,171n42, Clark, Carol E., 166nl
46, 54, 69-70,110,117,119, Brandt, Reinhart, 170nl4, Coker, Francis W., 148nl6,177n3
125,127,131,140,142-143, 174n36. See also disease/illness Brewer’s Dictionary of Phrase and
metaphors, blood mix, blood cognitive theory/linguistics, 4, 7,11,
173-174 Fable, 147nl, 155nl01, 13-25, 59, 74-75, 76, 89,
parasite, 1 ^ , 6-7, 11-17,19-22, poisoning, bloodsucker 155nl07
bowels/intestines/entrails, 84, 86 88 108-109,139,148nl4,170nll.
24-26, 36-41, 43-50, 52-71, 104, 113-114 Brodie, Richard, 151n63 See also metaphor, semantics
73, 75-77, 119-121,127-128, brain, 5, 117, 124,137, 171n52 Brodye, Isaac, 174n47 blending, 11, 14,19-21, 30, 48, 69,
134,136-137, 139-145, capillaries, 149n26 Browning, Christopher, 23, 28,149nl9, 76,116,167nl9,170nll,
150n44,151n56,157n40, carcass, 44, 113-114 151n2,153n46,155nl21, conceptual/mental space, 6,14,19,
160nl00,174n39,178nl3 corpse, 12,173n28 159n73, 159n86,159n95, 30,134,143
bloodsucker, 24, 36-37, 39 160n96,160n98,160nl02, framing, 4,12,19, 21-22, 23-24
119,155nl01 decomposition, 13,19, 24, 36-38 162n3
47, 55, 62, 65,127,132-133, cognitive import, 11,14,17-18, 23,
vampire, 24, 37,119 Bruning, Heinrich, 44,156n7 69, 71-72, 75, 94,141
plant, 16,100,119,127,140 143-144
ear, 84, 87, 88, 124 Brunetto Latini, 91,165n78 embodiment, 4, 74,134
race, 3, 6, 7,13,15-16,18-20, 24 Bullock,'Alan, 29 ,153n50 entrenchment, 76
28^0, 45,47-49, 51-53, 55, 57, foot, 84-90, 94-95,100,109,118
hand, 84, 87-88,94,109,123 Burke, Edmund, 119,166n95,172n71 mapping, 11,14,19, 22, 24, 26-27,
59-60, 66, 68-69, 71, 75-76, 81, head, 1, 6, 44, 82-103,105,107 Burke, Kenneth, 11, 23, 32,149nn2-3 30, 35,40^1,71,72, 74, 83,
89,131,134,138,142,153n64, Burleigh, Michael, 156nl6, 158n57 87, 89r469;'12-2-l^ 13^140,
154n83,157n35,157n37, 109-111,115,117-119, 122- Bussemer, Thymian, 149n21,155n4
125,127, 129,137-138,143, 142,'170nll, 178nl5
160nl04 (see also racism) Bytwerk, Randall L., 155n4,157n33 projection, 11, 15, 36,132
species, 24, 29-31, 35, 40, 165n84, 167nnl8-19,168n51,
171n52,174n52, schema, 26-27, 39,117,139,153n45
struggle for existence, 33 C colour, 15-17
virus, 19, 21, 26-27, 35, 40^1, 76 health, 1-2, 6, 24-26, 72, 81, 83, 85 Caird, G.B., 183nll
87-88, 92,95, 97-100,104- black—white, 14-19, 39
139,144, 149n25 camouflage terminology; 3, 66-67, common good, the, 90-93,144
Birnbaum, Pierre, 162n4 105,108,110,113, 128,135,
140,148nl5,165n64,174n36 70-71,141. See also holocaust, commonplace, 99-101,107,124
Blackmore, Susan, 20,151n59 final solution Cooper, David E., 169n8
Blasius, Dirk, 176n71 heart, 1,5, 24, 30, 84, 87-88,
95-98,100,102-103,109,114 deportation, 3, 60,141,160nl08 Cooper, Laurence, 172n67
blending theory. See cognitive theory special treatment, 3,12, 70,141 Cornwell, John, 153n51
Bloch, Marc, 167n20 117-119,124,170nl9, l-71n42’ Cassirer, Ernst, 129 Coulson, Seana, 151n53
Blum, Carol, 172n67 leg, 94-95,100
life cycle, 112, 117,143 Cesarani, David, 155nl21, Croft, William, 76-77, 137,
Chamberlain, Houston Stuart, 17, 71 162nnl8-23,177n4
202 Index Index 203
Cromwell, Oliver, 111 102-105,107,112-116,118- blood poisoning, 25, 27-28, The Eternal Jew (Der ewige Jude),
Cromwell, Thomas, 101 120,124,135,137,171n45. See 35-36, 38-41 {see also blood 53-56, 58,159n76
Cruse, D. Alan, 76-77,137, also biology/biological meta­ mix) The Rothschilds (Die Rothschilds),
162nnl8-23,177n4 phors, body metaphors, medical contamination, 14 53-56
culture, 45, 50, 74-75,101, 121, metaphors cyanide, 1 Jew Siiss (Jud Suss), 53-54, 56-57
126-127,138,143,163n3 agent of disease, 2, 5,19, 24-26, venom, 112,114 Fischer, Eugen, 22
cultural model, 13,16 28, 34, 36,38,41,45,134, sclerosis, 1, 24 Fischer, Heinrich, 149n2
political, 6, 73, 120,138 143-144 symptom, 25-26, 65,104,112,135 Fisher, John, 102
popular, 22, ague, 113-115,171n42 syphilis, 24,136 folk-theory, 75,143
National Socialist view of, 15, 29, biles, 112,114 ulcer, 46,121,169n60 Foolen, Ad, 162nl6
31, 34, 153n48 blood mix/defilement, 29, 34, 39^1, wens, 112-114 Forhan, Kate Langdon, 164nn52-54,
Western, 30, 75, 81,133,138, 140 153n48 {see also poison: blood wound, 44, 86,103,112-113, 164n56,165n62,165n65,
Cunningham, Andrew, 170nl9 poisoning) 169n60 165n73,165n78,165n80
bulimia, 113-115 Dodd, Bill, 149n6 Forster, Georg, 119,172n70
D cancer, 24, 72,139 Doerr, Karin, 149n2,151n73 Fortescue, Sir John, 94, 96-98,
d’Alembert, Jean Baptiste le Rond, metastasizing, 1 Domarus, Max, 151, 156,158-161 165-166
171n52 tumour, 1, 2 4 ,177nl Donoso Cortes, Juan, 175n64 Francis II, last Emperor of the Holy
d’Alquen, Gunther, 150n35 conjoined twins, 114-115,171n47 Diihring, Eugen Karl, 127,174n39 Roman Empire, 125
Dahlmann, Friedrich Christoph, consumption, 103,113-114 Frank, Roslyn M., 163n25
174n36 contagion, 114 E Frank, Hans, 131,139
Daim, Wilfried, 71 crisis, 25, 27-28, 51-52, 65, 85-86, Eckart, Dietrich, 32-33, 71 Frederick II, King of Prussia, 125
Darwin, Charles, 30-31, 33, 37, . ' 118-119,128,142-144 Edward IV, King of England, 94 Friedtlieb, Christian Werner, 123-124,
153nn55-62,154nn81-83 death, 24, 37-38,108,110,118, Einstein, Albert, 15 173nnl3-14
Dawkins, Richard, 20-21, 126, 133, 166nl04 Eitz, Thorsten, 148n25 Friihsorge, Gotthardt, 173nnl3-17
151nn59-60,151nn63-65 deformity, 102 Elyot, Sir Thomas, 101-102 Frei, Norbert, 155n4
de Baecque, Antoine, 172n69 dropsy, 102 Enlightenment, 36, 72-73, 77,107, Friedlander, Saul, 28, 32, 57, 61,
de Maistre, Joseph, 175n64 epilepsy, 113-114,171n45 117,126,130,138-139,144 153-162
Deignan, Alice, 174nl frenzy, 102 Ensink, Titus, 148n25
Deissler, Dirk, 149n2 germ, 24, 36,121 Enzensberger, Hans-Magnus, 137, G
Derathe, Robert, 172n67 gout, 102 177n5 Galton, Francis, 37
Descartes, Rene, 111, 170nl9 hydrophobia, 112 Eschwege, Helmut, 157n40 Ganz, Peter R, 126-127,148n23,
Desmet, Pierre, 172n69 hygiene, 22, 30 eugenics, 22, 30, 37 172n4
Dhorn-van-Rossum, Gerhard, 148nl6, hysteria, 1 Evans, Richard J., 29,153nn5D-51, Geeraerts, Dirk, 162nl3
165n72,177nn2-3 impotence, 24,119 155n2,156nl6,156n25, Gellately, Robert, 155-158,160-161
Diderot, Denis, 171n52 infection, 2, 21, 35-37, 40, 60, 63, 156n30,157n35,157n37, genetics, 20-21, 37, 77
Diller, Ansgar, 155n4 84, 88, 100 157n39,157n41,157n43, Gentner, Dedre, 151n3
Dionysius of Halicarnassus, 82 lethargy, 113-114 157n48, 158nn57-58, 158n65, Gevaert, Caroline, 162nl3
discourse, 1-8, 69-78, 81, 85, 98, 118: malady, 102-105 159n72,159n84,162n3 Gibbs, Raymond W, 148nl4,162nl2
171n45 meagreness, 102 Gilbert, Martin, 157n46
' analysis of, 11-12,149nl, 162n8 monster, 24,107,128,134-135, F Giles of Rome, 92,165n78
d. career, 66 173n24 Fabiszak, Malgorzata, 162nl5 Gilman, Sander L., lAgnll ----- -----
d. community, 76,140 muscles, 109 fable of the belly {see body metaphor, Gitelman, Zji 172n74
d. history/tradition, 7, 77, 93,122, palsy, 102 belly) Goatly, Andrew, 15,150n29,162nl5,
136-145,163n25,166nl paralysis, 2, 24,132 Falk, Richard, 178nl0 169n7,170nl9
d. memory, 6-7,137,177nl pathology, 24, 37,107,115,119, Fauconnier, Gilles, 19,148nl4, Godfrey of Fontaine, 92
d. metaphor {see metaphor) 127,132,138,171n45 149n23,151nn53-54 Goebbels, Joseph, 1-2, 32-33, 43-44,
political, 1, 7,11-12, 41, 69-70, 72, pestilence/plague, 12, 24, 36, 54-55, Feldman, Karen S., 169n9 46, 48-50, 52-54, 57-58, 60,
119,121, 128,138,140-141, 60, 65, 67,92,101-102,123 Fenske, Wolfgang, 153n65,154n74 62-64, 66, 70, 73,141,147n9,
151n3, 161nl41,162n24 physiology, 2,15, 74, 83, 111, 116, Fest, Joachim C., 153n52, 154n78 156-157,159-161
public, 4,139,140,142, 162n8, ^126-127,135,140 Fetscher, Iring, 161nl20 Goethe, Johann Wolfgang (von), 126
162n24 pleurisy, 113-115,171n42 Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 175n64 Goldhagen, Daniel Jonah, 13, 28, 71,
disease/iUness metaphors, 2-3, 6,12, poison/poisoning, 24-28, 35-41, film 149nnl6-18,149n20,150n49,
20, 23-27, 29,31,33,35-42, 45-48, 65, 67, 73,112-114, Campaign in Poland (Feldzug in 153n46,162nnl-2
55, 66, 72, 81, 84, 86-89,100, 119,127,168n40 Poleri), 159n70 Goring, Hermann, 131
204 Index
Gould, Stephen Jay, 153n54 Index 205
Grady, Joseph, 151n53,162nl2 Henry IV, King of England, 100
Henry VI, King of England, 94 Crystal Night pogrom, 48, 66, Johnston, Paul, 178n8
Great Chain of Being, 15-19, 72 74 Henry VIII, King of England, 101-103 157n48 Jones, Steve, 150n30,155nnl08-110
81, 83, 85, 90, 99,101,140,’ (final) solution, 3, 41-42, 52, 55, Jonson, Ben, 178nl3
150n52 ' Herder, Johann Gottfried, 73,127 140 57-58, 62, 70,144,147nl2
macrocosm, 16, 72, 85, 89, 101 142,145,174n32,174n34’ ’ holocaust "prophecy”. 51-53, K
microcosm, 16, 72, 85 Herf, Jeffrey, 149n21, 156n4,
158nn56-57 55-62, 67, 69-70, 144,159n92, Kamper, Heidrun, 156n5
principle of continuity, 16,18-19, 83 Heydrich, Reinhard, 131 160nl00,160nl04 Kallis, Aristotle A., 149n21,156n4,
_ prjnciple of gradation, 16,18, 83,’ Wannsee conference, 47,156n30, 157n44,159n70,161nl20
150n52 Heritage, Sidney J., 167n22,168n37 160nl04
Hilberg, Raul, 57,147nl0,155n2 Kant, Immanuel, 37, 126,142,173n30,
principle of plenitude, 16,18-19 83 159n87, 173nl0 Holyoak, Keith, 151n3 174n30,
Gregor, Neil, 3 ,147nll,154n76, ’ Himmler, Heinrich, 63,141 144 Holy Roman Empire, 94,123,125- Kantorowicz, Ernst H., 100,148nl6,
155nlll 127,173n28 163-164,167,170,173-174
Greive, Hermann, 13,149nl4,154n76 Hippier, Fritz, 56,159n70,159n76
159n80 homo saceii 133 Kaplan, Marion A., 50,158n52
Grimm, Jacob and Wilhelm, 155nl01 Hirsch, Emil G., 147n47 Hughes, Geoffrey, 167nl7 Karwowsky, Michael, 178n8
155nll6,174n36,178nl4 ’ history, 2-8,11-13,15,17-18, 20-23 Huizinga, Johan, 99,164n24 Kelly, Alfred, 153n51
Grondelaers, Stefan, 162nl3 Hull, David L., 76 Kelly, George Armstrong, 172n67
Gross, Raphael, 174-176 27, 29-30, 36, 38-39, 42,49-50, Humanism, 84, 90,104,108,129,135,
52, 54, 60, 63, 69-77,81-84 Kempshall, M.S., 163-165,
Grynspan, Herschel, 50 144,174n50. See also Middle Kershaw, Ian, 29, 50,148n22,151-
Guilhaumou, Jacques, 172n67 89. 97,101,104,107,112,120,
Ages, Renaissance 153,155-158,161
Guillaume de Conches, 84 122,124,126-127,130-134, Hunt, Lynn, 172n69
136-140,142-145,150,151, Kertzer, David L, 162n4
Guldin, Rainer, 148nnl6-17,162-164 Hunt, Maurice, 167nll Kettenacker, Lothar, 173n28
170nl9 153-156, 163,170,173-176 hyperbole, 17
discourse history (see discourse) Kevles, Daniel J., 155nll0
Gunther, Hans F. K., 22 Kienpointner, Manfred, 148n24
Gurian, Waldemar, 131, 174n43 conceptual history, 6, 76, 81, I
136-138,150n30,150n52 Klemperer, Victor, 12, 44, 46, 52, 61,
175n76 ideology, 3-4, 6-7,11, 13-17,19, 63-64, 66-67, 70,149,156,
Gustloff, Wilhelm, 49 history of ideas, 4, 72-73,101,
history of science, 76 21-23, 30, 32-33, 42, 52-54, 157-161
H Hitler, Adolf, 1, 3, 6-7,11-76, 88-89 58, 62, 66, 71, 74-75, 81, 83, Kloft, Michael, 149n21,156n4,
120,128, 130-131, 133-134, 99,113, 120,122,134,136- 161nl20
Habermas, Jiirgen, 176n92 138, 141,148-151,177 Koenen, Andreas, 174n43,175-176
Hachmeister, Lutz, 149n21, 156n4 140, 142-144,147-156,
158-161,178 Indsley, John, 149n5 Koenigsberg, Richard, 150n44
161nl20 IMT (International Military Tribunal), Kohler, Kaufmann, 174n47
Hale, David George, 110,112,115 Mein Kampf 2-3, 7,12-15,17-19
21-29, 31-43, 52, 60, 65-66, 161nl24 Kokinov, Boicho N., 151n3
148nnl6-17,163-164, 167,’ 69, 71, 87,128,132,134, Kokoschka, Oskar, 5 ,148n21
169-171,176-177 141-142 J Koschorke, Albrecht, 148nnl6-17,
Hamann, Brigitte, 148nn21-22, Jackel, Eberhard, 13, 23, 29, 148nl3, 163n9,163n21,165n72,166nl,
151n67, 151n70, 153n51, Hobbes, Thomas, 72-73, 106-120
128-136, 142-145,169-171 151n71,151nl, 153n49, 173nl6, 177n3
153n53,153n65,155nll5, 174-177 153n52,155nl, 155n3,157n35, Koselleck, Reinhart, 172n67
Hamann, Johann Georg, 176n95 159nn73-74,159nn88-91, Kovecses, Zoltan, 75,148nl4,162nl3,
Hampsher-Monk, Iain, 162n9 Hodson,Jane, 162n24
Hofmann, Hanns Hubert, 125,173n22 160nl01, 160nlll, 161nll6, 162nnl6-17
Harris, Jonathan Gil, 115,148nl6, 173n26-27 161nl22,161nnl25-127 Krauss, Werner, 56
166nl, 167nl8,167n23, Hollstein, Dorothea, 159n71 Jager, Hans-Wolf, 172n67 Krebs, Birgit-Nicole, 148n25‘
169n61,169nl, 171nn44^5, holocaust, 1, 2, 4, 6-8,11-14,16-18 James of Viterbo, 92 Kroll, Jurgen, 153n51
171n60 James I, King of England, 167nl8 Kuhn, Axel, 151n71, 153n52
Harvey, William, 111, 170nl9 23,28, 42^3, 56, 61, 63, 67, Jenninger, Philipp, 148n25
70-71, 136, 141,148nl3, Kulka, Otto Dov, 155nl, 155n3,
Harwood, John T., 170nll Jessen, Hans, 173n25 157n40,159-161
Hawkins, Bruce, 14-16, 38, 155nl21,158n53, 159n92, John of Paris, 92,165n62
160n98,161nl41,162nl41 Kwiet, Konrad, 157n40
149nn25-28,150nn40-43, John of Salisbury, 73, 83-90, 92-98,
162n8 annihilation/elimination/extermi- 102,107, 142,163nnl8-22, L
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 77 nation, 2, 13,17, 27-28, 35, 164-166
38, 41-42, 46, 51-53, 55-57, Lakoff, George, 16-17, 74,148-151,
175n64 Johnson, Boris, 1, 5 162,169
Heine, Heinrich, 132, 176n86 59-65, 67-68,- 70-71, 75, 87, Johnson, Mark, 17,148nl4,149n22,
120, 133,137,141-142,144, Laqueur, Walter 155n2,158n53
Henry of Ghent, 92 151n53,162nl2, 169n7 Leezenberg, Michiel, 169n7
Henry U, King of England, 84 147nl2,160nl00, 160nl04 Johnston, David, 108,169n4,169n9,
162nl41 Lehmann, Julius E, 22
170nl9 Lenin, Vladimir Ilyitsch, 119,172n73
206 Index Index 207

Lenz, Fritz, 22 import of (see cognitive theory, cogni­ 153,157-161,173,176-177.


antidote, 112,114 See also Hitlei^ Goebbels,
Leviathan, 73,106-112,114-117, care, 82-83, 88-89, 95,97 tive import)
128-136,143,145,169,170, literal interpretation of, 3,11-13,17, Goring, Himmler
cure, 1-2, 6, 20, 24, 26-28, 35-36, Das Reich (magazine), 160nl04
174,176 38,40^1, 54,61,72, 76, 20, 23,38,41,52, 59, 69-72,
Levkas, Ruth, 148n24 77, 83,90,137,141-142, Das schwarze Korps (magazine), 15,
85-87, 90, 93,100,103-105, 131,150n35
Liberalism, 130,135 107,120,129,142,142-144, 148nl5
Liebeschiitz, Hans 163n21,163n24 m. tradition, 6-7, 74, 82,101, 111, Der Sturmer (magazine), 47,157n33
168 GESTAPO, 43, 50, 65-66,141,
Lincoln,_Bruce, 163n3 diagnosis, 25, 27-28, 35,103,105, 128
Lindemann, Albert S., 162n4 128, 143,168 m. scenario, 24, 26-28, 32-44, 48, 157n35
Linke, Uli, 148nl5,148n24 52, 56-70, 73, 75-77,86-89, Neo-Nazis, 7, 74,149n26
healing, 4, 24-28, 34, 44, 47, 63, NSDAP (Nationalsozialistische
Livy, 82, 103 72,81,83, 85, 87-88, 92, 95, 100,105,107,116,120,127-
Lockwood, Shelley, 165n74 128,133,136-145,152n44, Deutsche Arbeiterpartei), 44, 63,
97-106,108, no, 113,116- 130,160nl00
Lohenstein, Daniel Casper von, 124, 119,128,135,140,142,148, 153n45,157n40,161nl41,
173nl6 174n39 Nuremberg party conference/Nurem-
154,165-166,174 berg race laws, 45,47-49, 55,
Lohneyss, Georg Engelhard, 124,173nl5 humours, 37,103,105,112, personification, 17,134-135
Longerich, Peter, 147-148,155-159, 114-116,169n60 simile/similitude, 14, 64,108-109, 131,153n64,157n37
161 physician, 103,105, 112,118 115,124-125,142,144, Rohm putsch, 46,131
Lorenz, Gottfried, 173nl2 169nll, 170nll SD (SicherheitsdienstySD-itports,
prescription, 24 43,49-50, 52-53, 56-59, 63,
Lovejoy, Arthur Oncken, 18, 72-73, regeneration, 24 tertium comparationis, 90-91,129,
81, 83,150, 163 remedy, 86,103-104 177nl07 67, 70,131,141,155,159,
Lucken, Steven, 156n4 therapy, 7, 21, 24, 26, 28, metonymy, 14, 74,105,155nll6, 160-161,172
Ludemann, Susanne, 174n30 35-36, 53, 60, 62-64, 66-67, 170n22 SA (Sturmabteilung), 46, 50
Lueger, Karl, 12 Meyerbeer, Giacomo, 132 SS (Schutzstaffel), 15, 49-50, 52, 59,
71, 74-75, 86-87, 89, 96, 63, 65-66,131,160nl04
Luther, Manin, 122-123,172-173 103-105,107,119,123,133, Michael, Robert, 149n2,151n73
Middle Ages, 4, 7,18, 55, 72, 77, Volkischer Beobachter (newspaper),
136-137,142-144,162nl41, 50,158n50
M 166n99 81-85, 89-91,93, 95-99, 101,
Machiavelli, Niccolo, 73,103-105, 119,122,125,127,131,136, Nederman, Cary J., 148nl6,163nl9,
Meier, Heinrich, 175nn56-58, 163n21,163n23,164n52,
142,166nl,168-169 175nn69-70 138-140,143-144,150,156,
Mcllwain, Charles H., 167nl8 memetics, 20-21, 76-77 173-174. See also humanism- 164nn54-56,165n62,165n80
Mairgunther, Wilfred, 157n46 Mendel, Gregor, 37 scholasticism, 90-93, 98 Negelein, Paul, 124
Maitland, Frederic William, 148nl6, Mieder, Wolfgang, 156n5 Neoplatonism, 4,18, 72, 81, 83, 90
Mendelssohn, Moses, 132,176n95 Nestle, Wilhelm, 148nl7
163nl7,167nl7,167nl9 Mensch, James R., 178nl0 Milfull, John, 162n4
Malcolm, Noel, 170nl4 Miller, Mary, 163n3 Neumann, Franz Leopold, 128,134-
metaphor. See also animal m., biologi­ 135,138,174n48,177nnl07-
Manheim, Ralph, 24,147n7,149n27, cal m., body-state m., disease m., Mintz, Samuel I., 169n3,170nl4
155nll2 medical m., cognitive theory Mitscherlich, Alexander and Margarete, 113
Manipulation, 11-12,14 161nl41 Nicolas of Cusa, 122,165n72
analogy/analogical argument, 20-21, Niemeier, Susanne, 162n8
Mannes, Stefan, 159n71 23-24, 27-28, 30-31, 35, 38, Moltmann, Gunther, 161nl20
Marian, Ferdinand, 56 Molotov, Vyacheslaw, 54 Niven, William, 148n25,149n2,
41, 55, 58-59, 71, 76, 81, 161nl41
Marie Be France, 164n31 83-87, 89-97, 100, 103, 105, monster/monstrous, see disease, monster
Marsilius of Padua, 92,101,123, 107,109,111-112,115,119, Montaigne, Michel de, 166nl, 171n47 North, Thomas, 166n2
165nn64-65 More, Sir Thomas, 102 Norton, Anne, 175^6 _________
129,138,141-143, 151n3,
Martinich, A[loysius] P., 169n3, 159n92,165nn84-85,169n61, Motohashi, Tesuya, 166n2
170nl3 177n3 Mouton, Nicolaas T.O., 148nl6, O ^
Marx, Karl, 119,132,172n72 conceptual m., 15, 65, 74-75,121, 162nl6,177n3 Oakley, Todd, 151n53
Matthaus, Jurgen, 159n86,159n95 136,151n53 Muller, Jan-Wernei^ 175n56,176n86 Obama, Barack, 139,147n2,178n9
Mayer, T.F., 167n22,168n37 definition of, 2-3 Muller-Richter, Klaus, 169n8 Obst, Dieter, 157n46
medical metaphors , 20-24, 27-28, discourse m., 76 Musolff, Andreas, 147-148,151-152, Olden, Rudolf, 149n2
30, 37, 39,41,45, 69, 71-72, domain (source, target d.), 2, 4,12, 159,162,169
81, 83, 88, 97, 105, 110-113, 14,19,21-22, 24,26-28, 30, P
115-116,118-119,137-140, 32, 34-36, 39-Jl, 43, 72, 83, • N Pechau, Manfred, 149n2
155,162,169,170. See also 86. 116,127,135,139-140, Nationalism, 126-127 Paechter, Heinz,, 149n2
disease/illness metaphors 144,170nll National Socialism/Nazism, 3-8, Paine, Thomas, 119,172n70
amputation, 86-89, 93, 96,100,105, event structure, 27, 35, 40, 93 11-78, 81,120-121,128-131, Patterson, Annabel M., 148nl7
119,142,166n99 iconographic reference, 14-16,18 133-138,141-144,148-150, Patzold, Kurt, 156n30
Index 209
208 Index
Spurgeon, Caroline F.E., 166n2
Pauwels, Paul, 147nl, 162n8 rhetoric, 7,11-12,14,17, 25, 42, 88,115,119,129-130,140, Stahl, Friedrich Julius, 132-133
Peil, Dietmar, 148nnl6-17,163n9 48,56, 59, 62,-66-67, 70, 147,149,174 Stalingrad, German defeat at 61, 67
Peltonen, Markku, 166n2,167n3 72, 89-90, 95, 99,100,108, category mistake, 4 ,1 3 ,149nl5 Stark, Gray D., 151n68
Pentrop, Clemens, 154n74 112,120,124,141-142,145, encyclopaedic knowledge, 6 Starkey, Thomas, 102-103,105,115,
Peries, Gabriel, 162n8 169-170,178 ontology, 18, 23, 27, 89 142,168
Philip rV, King of France, 29,101 Roberts, Penny, 166nl presupposition, 28 Starobinski, Jean, 171n60
Pickex, Henry, 154n78 semantic development/drift,/6 //,
Robertus Pullus, 84 Steen, Gerard, 151n3
Plato, 4,18, 72, 81,102,m 163n4 Rodrigue, Aron, 157n40 137,139 Steiner, George, 148n25
Pococ^, John G.A., 166nn95-96,169n56 Rohrich, Lutz, 156nl2 semantic transfer, 3,11-12, 22, 41, Steinert, Marlis G., 161nl23
Pole, Reginald, 102-103 Rooryck, Johan E., 172n69 140,170nl9 {see also cognitive
theory: mapping, metaphor) Stern, Josef, 148nl4 ‘
Poliakov, Leon, 162n4 Rose, Michael R., 153n54 Sternberger, Dolf, 12, 66,149,161
Plutarch, 82-87, 89-90, 93-94,107, Roseman, Mark, 156n30,160nl04 Semino, Elena, 152n44,162nl6
166n2 Rosenberg, Alfred, 32-33 ' Shakespeare, William, 5-6, 82, 99-101, Stieler, Kaspar, 124,173nl8
139,148, 166-167 Stirk, Peter M. R., 174n43
Proctor, Robert N., 151n69,153n51 Rothschild, 53-56,132-133 Stocker, Adolf, 127,174n38
Prokhovnik, Raia, 108,169n3,169n8 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 73,117-120, Coriolanus, 5, 82, 99-100, 148,166
stoicism, 4, 81
propaganda, 1, 3, 7,12,14, 20-23, 126,129,139,142,145, Hamlet, 100,167 Stolleis, Michael, 173n24
33, 43-44, 47-50, 52, 54, 171nn50-63,172nn64-66, Julius Caesar, 167nl3 Storz, Gerhard, 12, 66,149,161
56-57, 59, 61-64, 66-67, 71, 172n67 Richard II, 100,167n9 Stotzel, Georg, 148n25 •
74-77,125,137,141,144,148, Ryle, Gilbert, 149nl5 Richard III, 100,167n\Q Strauss, Leo, 128-130,135-136,
159-161,177. See also camou­ Troilus and Cressida, 100, 169-170,174-175
flage terminology S 167nnl2-13 Streicher, Julius, 47, 65,157n33
Przyrembel, Alexandra, 157n34 Sarkozy, Nicolas, 139 Shields, David, 178n9 . Struve, Tilman, 163nl5,164n24
Ptolemy of Lucca, 91 Shirei^ William, 52, 158nn65-66
Sawday, Jonathan, 148nl6 Suskind, Wilhelm E., 12, 66,149,161
Pufendorf, Samuel von, 124-125, Schama, Simon, 172n67,172n69 Shogimen, Takashi, 162nl6,177n7 Siiss-Oppenheimer, Joseph, 54
173nnl9-20 Schank, Roger C., 153n45 Shorter Oxford Dictionary, 155nlUU,
155nl07,178nl2 Swiggers, Pierre, 172n69
Schechter, Salomon, 174n47
Q Schiller, Friedrich (von), 121 Sieyes, Emmanuel, 172n68,174n35
Siever, Holger, 148n25 T
Quintus Serenus Sammonicus, 85 Schilling, Heinz, 125,173n21,173n23 Taboo, 48, 50, 52, 67,141
Schleicher, Kurt von, 46 Simon, Gerd, 150n35, Taine, Hippolyte, 175n64
R Schmitz-Berning, Cornelia, 149nl2, Simon-Vandenbergen, Anne-Marie,
Taube, Karl, I63n3
racism, 2, 6-8,11-13,15-19, 21-23, 151n73,156nl3,174n32, 162n8 Taylor, John R., 153n45
Sington, Derrick, 155n4
25, 29-32, 34-35, 37-39, 42, 174n34,174nn37-39 Tegel, Susan, 159n71,159n76,159n78,
44, 47, 49, 53-54, 58, 62, 67, Schmitt, Carl, 73,128-136,143,145, Skinner, Quentin, 73,101, 105, 108, 159nn82-83
71, 74,101,120-121,136,138- 174-177 162-165,167-170,173-174
social Darwinism, 30, 33, 71,140, Tendahl, Markus, 148nl4
140,143,149-150,153,155, Schmitz, Johannes, 155n4 Theweleit, Klaus, 47,148nl5
173,177. See also anti-Semitism, Schnettger, Matthias, 173n24 153n51 Thirty Years War, 123-124
holocaust, National Socialism Schoenberner, Gerhard, 157n37‘ sociolinguistics, 14,16
xenophobia, 12,17, 21,177nl Schoenfeldt Michael, 163n9 variation, 19, 75, 83, 85, 90, 98, Thomas Aquinas, 73, 91,164n52,
101,122,138-139,141 164n55
Raleigh, Sir Walter, 101 Schonbohm, Jorg, 1 Thomas Becket (Archbishop of Canter-
Rash, Felicity, 17-18, 22, 44, Schonerer, Georg von, 12 Soderbaum, Kristina, 56
Sontag, Susan, 36, 72-73 8^, ^9, 97, bury),^r-16in2Q.--------- -
150nn45-49,151n72,151nl, Schoeps, Julius H., 149nl9 Tillyard, E^M.W., 72-73, 83, 85,
154n76,159n77 Schulze, Winfried, 173nl4 102-105,112,116,119,135, 89-91,100-101,150,162,164,
religion, 11, 32-34, 87,132,166n88. Schultz, Ulrich, 153n51 137,142,148,154,162,164,
166,168-170,177 167
See also Christ Schwarz, Erika, 156n30
creator/Lord, 28-29, 31-32, 35, Seidel, Eugen and Ingeborg Seidel- Sopade-Ttpotts, 43, 47,155n3,157n45 Tilmans, Torquemada,
Karin, 162n9
Juan de, 165n72
40-41, 66 . Slotty, 149nl2 Southern, Richard W, 163n24
Sovereignty, 115-117,129,132,134 Townsend, Rebecca, 148n24
devil, 32, 35, 40^1, 62, 64, 87-89, Seidler, Michael, 173n21 Tucholsky, Kurt, 149n2
143 semantics, 3-4, 6,12-13, 74-77,101, Spenser, Edmund, 101 Turner, Mark, 16,19
reformation, 44, 84, 99,122,156nl2 122,137,139-141,148-149, Speer, Albert, 154n78
Remigio di Girolami, 92,156n66 151-152,156,160,178. See Sperber, Dan, 20-21,151n59,
151nn61-62 V
Renaissance, 7,18, 72-73, 77, 99,101, also cognitive theory, metaphor Vande Winkel, Roel, 159n71,159n75
103,105,119,122,138-139, euphemism, 3 Spied, Mauro, I67nll van Vree, Frank, 162n9 .
143,150n52,166nl, 168n51. categorization, 3-4,11,13-14,17, Spinoza, Baruch de, 132 Verhandlungen des Reichstags, 156n/
See also Humanism 19,23-24,28, 30,46, 54, 71, Spitzer, Leo, 150n52
I

210 Index
Vogel, Christian, 153n51 Wildmann, Daniel, 148nl5
Volmert, Johannes, 149nl2 Wilks, Michael, 163nl9
vom Rath, Ernst, 50 William of Ockham, 93,123,
165nn68-69
W Wilson, Peter H., 173n24
Wagner, Richard, 17, 54, 71 Winock, Michel, 162n4
■V^lzer, Michael, 172n69 Wulf, Joseph, 159n71,159n82
Weidenfeld, Arthur, 155n4
Weikart, Richard, 151nn68-69,153n51 Y
Weinberg, Gerhard L., 151n71,151nl Yu, Ning, 162nl4
Weindling, Paul, 151n69,153n51
Weingart, Peter, 153n51 Z
Weise, Christian, 124,173nl7 Zavadil, Jeffery, 163n8,163nl2
Welch, David, 159n71,159nn75-76, Zinken, Jorg, 76,148nl4,162nl6
159nn79-80,159nn83-84 Zmarzlik, Hans-Giinte^ 153n51
Wiegrefe, Klaus, 173n29 Zuckert, Catherine and Michael,
Wieland, Christoph Martin, 126,174n31 175n56

Potrebbero piacerti anche