Sei sulla pagina 1di 11

Volume 78, No.

1 THE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF BIOLOGY March 2003

NEW BIOLOGICAL BOOKS


The aim of this section is to give brief indications of the character, content and cost of new books in
the various fields of biology. More books are received by The Quarterly than can be reviewed critically.
All submitted books, however, are carefully considered for originality, timeliness, and reader interest,
and we make every effort to find a competent and conscientious reviewer for each book selected for
review.
Of those books that are selected for consideration, some are merely listed, others are given brief notice,
most receive critical reviews, and a few are featured in lead reviews. Listings, without comments, are
mainly to inform the reader that the books have appeared; examples are books whose titles are self-
explanatory, such as dictionaries and taxonomic revisions, or that are reprints of earlier publications,
or are new editions of well-established works. Unsigned brief notices, written by one of the editors,
may be given to such works as anthologies or symposium volumes that are organized in a fashion that
makes it possible to comment meaningfully on them. Regular reviews are more extensive evaluations
and are signed by the reviewers. The longer lead reviews consider books of special significance. Each
volume reviewed becomes the property of the reviewer. Most books not reviewed are donated to libraries
at SUNY Stony Brook or other appropriate recipient.
The price in each case represents the publisher’s suggested list price at the time the book is received
for review, and is for purchase directly from the publisher.
Authors and publishers of biological books should bear in mind that The Quarterly can consider
for notice only those books that are sent to The Editors, The Quarterly Review of Biology, C-2615
Frank Melville, Jr. Memorial Library, State University of New York, Stony Brook, NY 11794-3349
USA. We welcome prepublication copies as an aid to early preparation of reviews.

ONE, TWO (TOO?), MANY GENES?

Lenny Moss
Department of Philosophy, University of Notre Dame
South Bend, Indiana 46556 USA
e-mail: lenny.moss.9@nd.edu

A review of some motivation for this turn can surely be


The Concept of the Gene in Development attributed to a growing appreciation of the
and Evolution: Historical and Episte- complexity and diversity of meanings in use
mological Perspectives. Cambridge Studies of the word “gene,” one also sees the hall-
in Philosophy and Biology. marks of a changing Zeitgeist. The earlier
Edited by Peter J Beurton, Raphael Falk, and debate grew out of the more ambitiously sys-
Hans-Jörg Rheinberger. Cambridge and New tematizing intentions of Logical Positivism
York: Cambridge University Press. $59.95. xvi and perhaps a more ideologically strident
Ⳮ 384 p; ill.; index. ISBN: 0-521-77187-0. intellectual climate. Today’s disposition
2000. reflects an enhanced sensitivity to empirical,
Where once the question of whether the clas- historical, and rhetorical particulars (let
sical gene could be “reduced” to the molec- alone the exponentially expanded domain of
ular gene was all the rage among philoso- empirical particulars to be sensitive to), but
phers of biology, the tide has turned back also the interpretative influence of multicul-
toward a version of the ancient Greek conun- turalism and metaphysical pluralism. Dupré
drum about the one and the many. Although (1993) provides a good example of one of the

57
58 THE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF BIOLOGY Volume 78

more systematic expressions of this perspec- applied parameters derived from features
tive in the philosophy of science. of well-characterized genes” (p 3). Simply
This important collection of papers, stated, investigators have abstracted from the
derived from two workshops held at the Max features of particularly well-characterized
Planck Institute for the History of Science, molecular genes a set of criteria that are nei-
spans the distance from theoretical attempts ther necessary nor sufficient, and which need
to reconstruct a single, unified gene concept not necessarily occur together, and by no
to historical, empirical, and epistemological means are exhaustive. Two of the most salient
arguments on behalf of an irremediable con- examples of such criteria would be evidence
ceptual pluralism. I will attempt to bridge the that the stretch of DNA in question serves as
chasm between the reductionist program of a template for the synthesis of an RNA tran-
the past and the unity-versus-plurality stand- script and the presence of an AT rich “TATA
point of the present by offering, in some box” promoter site. The absence of a TATA
sense, to split the difference. Between the one promoter would be interesting, but it would
and the many I will argue that there are not not deprive a transcript producing sequence
one and not many, but two fundamental gene from being a gene. Nor, however, has the lack
concepts underlying current scientific usage. of a verified transcript prevented sequences
Far from attempting to absorb or assimilate that meet other gene parameters from being
one to the other, the real objective should be counted as genes in genomic analysis. Argu-
to disentangle the two, recognize their inde- ably, a flexible interpretative toolkit is not
pendent and nonoverlapping status, and necessarily a bad thing, but what happens
thereby undercut misleading inferences when empirical reality does not fit the canon-
derived from their unwarranted conflation. ical exemplar of what a molecular gene
Genes were, and continue to be, defined should look like? For example, what should
with respect to phenotype and are also one conclude when what one might want to
defined at the molecular level with respect to call a single locus produces multiple different
DNA sequence. The difficulties of bringing transcripts? The human dystrophin gene has
these together is the basis of what Raphael seven different promoter sites that respond in
Falk, in this volume, refers to as “a concept in tissue-specific ways to produce transcripts and
tension” (p 317), and this distinction, and this polypeptides of different sizes. Is this one
tension, is conceptually critical to every arti- gene or seven? And what if there is one reg-
cle in the collection (and to my own argu- ulatory region, such as the Locus Control
ment as well). Region (LCR), that is involved in the regula-
We are all accustomed to common refer- tion of a cluster of five related globin poly-
ences to the numbers of genes in a sequenced peptide gene sequences? Or cases where tran-
genome. And in as much as no one yet even scripts are derived from two entirely different
claims to know the phenotypic function of chromosomal regions, yet come together to
every gene in a genome, it would appear that produce a single translation product? And
such knowledge is not necessary for individ- what about cases where highly repetitive DNA
uating and tallying up genes on the basis of generally regarded as “junk” DNA for its lack
molecular sequence data. So how is it done? of apparent role in transcription (such as the
What are the criteria that enable a genome ALU sequences) is found to give rise to some
project to tell us how many genes humans, level of transcriptional activity?
flies, worms, yeast, or rice are endowed with? The heuristics for naming and demarcat-
The collection begins with an outstanding ing genes came about with a certain tacit pre-
analysis by Thomas Fogle that discloses how understanding about what the relationship of
empirically problematic this actually is. DNA structure to gene-function should be,
The ability to intelligibly discuss the num- which influenced the selection of the seem-
ber of genes in a genome, Fogle reveals, is ingly well-behaved cases that became exem-
based upon a methodological use of a kind plars. With the expectation of straightforward
of molecular-gene umbrella concept. This structure-function relationships no longer
concept consists of “a collection of flexibly empirically tenable, two principal strategies
March 2003 NEW BIOLOGICAL BOOKS 59

for reconstituting a gene concept present ally interconnected by way of multiple and
themselves. The first strategy, which Fogle has complex interactions. What Fogle is calling
found represented in the leading molecular for is a new vocabulary for the types of molec-
biology textbooks, is that of beginning with a ular interactants that come together contin-
functional outcome, typically a polypeptide, gently, in context-relevant ways, in the course
and backtracking to all of the DNA elements of any actual transcriptional expression. He
(coding and regulatory) that were necessary wants to avoid the bad habit of mistaking any
for its production. These are then included of the interactants, before the fact, with the
in what counts as “the gene” for this polypep- complex and contextually conditioned out-
tide. But the problems with this approach, come of the process in which it participates.
Fogle explains, are legion. There is no clear The gene, he suggests, “could become a
way to demarcate those domains that are quaint term of the past (at least in molecular
involved in transcription in some capacity biology circles) replaced by language that
from those that are not. There is no guaran- more accurately conveys relationships among
tee that the same domains will be involved in domains contributing to phenotypic effects”
each instance of the transcription of the same (p 23). Now, of course, many of these
polypeptide and there are also both coding domains already have names—promoters,
and noncoding domains that are involved in enhancers, and silencers, among others.
the transcription of multiple polypeptides What lacks a deflationary appellation is the
(e.g., the LCR regions discussed above). And template-bearing regions of the DNA. For
if all the DNA elements that regulate tran- this, Fogle proposes the acronym DSAT for
scription are included in the definition of the “domain set for active transcription.” Of
gene, why stop at just DNA sequences? On course, even with the benefit of its deflation-
what basis, for example, would the DNA ary intentions, Fogle’s DSAT would still have
methylation patterns that regulate transcrip- to grapple with the complexity of boundary
tion be excluded? And what about all of the ambiguities, a point that he readily acknowl-
factors that are necessary for posttranscrip- edges.
tional processing, which have an enormous Aside from skepticism about just how
influence on the form of the polypeptide pro- quickly the term gene could be relegated,
duced? This even more inclusive approach to even under the most enlightened of circum-
defining a gene is exactly what is put forward stances, to an innocuous dotage, there is still
by Griffiths and Neumann-Held (1999) and a serious shortcoming of Fogle’s approach.
Neumann-Held (2001)—for a critique, see He is quick to notice the uninvited presence
Moss (2001). Fogle convincingly emphasizes of a Mendelian-like gene concept in his
the complex integration of positional and molecular soup, but pays it little more atten-
contextual factors germane to any and all lev- tion than just trying to shoo it away. Perhaps
els of functional analysis. Is it not, after all, he thinks that it is already moribund, or that
the residue of Mendelian functional unit talk, it is a pest that is simply best ignored, or
projected onto DNA, that is at least covertly maybe that it is just not his department to be
responsible for expectations about how DNA concerned about it. But as I think other
would be able to be parsed into phenotypi- papers in the collection will bear out, this
cally relevant units? other sense of the gene is still alive and well,
The second strategy, which Fogle favors, and the best way to guard against its intru-
could be well described as a deflationary sions is to give it its due while clarifying the
approach. Rather than attempting to fit the nature of its proper boundaries.
square pegs of the Mendelian gene into the When we refer to genes for phenotypes
round holes of the double helix, one can sim- (e.g., genes for blue eyes, breast cancer, cystic
ply parse the DNA on its own terms, albeit fibrosis, or Marfan’s syndrome), we use the
shorn of phenotypic ascriptions. Fogle sug- term in a particular way. I call this sense of
gests that rather than label lots of loci as the gene, “Gene-P” (Moss 2003). A Gene-P is
genes, it would be more useful to map differ- a phenotype predictor. It is defined by its phe-
ent classes of domains that become function- notype, but is indeterminate with respect to
60 THE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF BIOLOGY Volume 78

its nucleic acid sequence. How could this be? and breast cancer. Although a negative test
Surprisingly perhaps, this concept of a gene result could never rule out the possibility of
as Gene-P was understood by Wilhelm a Gene-P for reasons just discussed, a positive
Johannsen, the very individual who coined test for the presence of an already character-
the term “gene.” In his 1923 paper, he told us ized aberrant sequence can be used in the
that “[w]hen we regard Mendelian ‘pairs’, predictive capacity of a Gene-P. The explan-
Aa, Bb and so on, it is in most cases a normal atory “game” played by Gene-P is thus not
reaction (character) that is the ‘allele’ to an confined to purely classical methods, which
abnormal. Yellow in ripe pease is normal, the unfortunately has made it all the easier to
green is an expression for imperfect ripeness conflate the meaning of this “gene” with the
as can easily be proven experimentally e.g. by one I will refer to as “Gene-D.”
etherization” ( Johannsen 1923:138). Johann- Quite unlike Gene-P, Gene-D is defined by
sen got this right. Genes-P can serve as valu- its nucleic acid sequence. A Gene-D is a devel-
able predictors of a great many phenotypes opmental resource (hence the “D”) which in
because it is often the case that within some itself is indeterminate with respect to phe-
range of environmental and developmental notype. The sense of my Gene-D bears a strik-
contexts, organisms lacking a certain “nor- ing resemblance to the intent of Fogle’s
mal” sequence will respond predictably. DSAT. To be a Gene-D is to be a region on a
Genes-P are not defined by sequence because chromosome within which is contained
invariably there are many ways to lack or devi- molecular template resources, used in the
ate from a norm. It continues to be useful in synthesis of various “gene-products.” All of
genetic counseling, and other areas, to speak Fogle’s provisos about context sensitivity and
as if (but only as if) a Gene-P determined the dependence apply. The very same Gene-D
phenotype. But it does not—it merely pre- can be used for all sorts of different pheno-
dicts what the organism is likely to do. The typic end-products, both felicitously or aber-
“normal” BRCA1 (breast cancer) protein is a rantly, depending upon the developmental or
large molecule that is involved in transcrip- physiological context. Gene-P and Gene-D
tional regulation events in many tissues at constitute qualitatively different kinds of
many times. It by no means constitutes explanatory concepts. There is no gene that
instructions for making healthy breasts, nor is simultaneously a Gene-P and a Gene-D; to
does it even have a special relationship to this conflate them is just as much a conceptual
part of the anatomy. But given the context of category mistake as an empirical error. To see
a family with a history of breast cancer, there this clearly one need only consider a locus
are many deviations of the BRCA1 sequence, such as that associated with the Gene-P for
the presence of which are highly correlated cystic fibrosis. Considered as a Gene-D it con-
with the appearance of breast cancer at some stitutes template resources for a cellular trans-
point during a woman’s lifetime. Breast can- membrane chloride ion channel protein that
cer is one example, Marfan syndrome is is contingently expressed at different times
another. There are at least 150 sequence devi- and in different places. As a Gene-D its sig-
ations that will result in some version of Mar- nificance is wholly determined by its context
fan syndrome. These are Genes-P. They do and dynamic history. Considered as a Gene-
not constitute instructions for making tall, P, the presence of one out of over 900 possible
gaunt bodies (which is a complex develop- deviations on each of the chromosomes pro-
mental consequence of a failure to incorpo- vides a certain predictive power with respect
rate fibrillin into connective tissue microfi- to a complex pathophysiology of the lungs
brills), but they are predictive of such. that involves the buildup of mucus and the
Although Genes-P are defined by their pre- inclusion of bacteria. Hyperbolic talk about
dictive relationship to a phenotype and not genes as programs for phenotypes (let alone
by specific sequence, they are no longer as the ontological groundwork of life itself)
purely classical as opposed to molecular. follows from the conflationary desire to have
Molecular probes can, and are, being used to it both ways, Gene-P and Gene-D simulta-
detect Genes-P such as those for cystic fibrosis neously, molecular templates that “code for”
March 2003 NEW BIOLOGICAL BOOKS 61

complex phenotypes. Gene-P needs to be in his 1933 Nobel lecture—“it does not make
given its proper due, but be kept distinct from the slightest difference whether the gene is a
Gene-D. Uncontaminated by Gene-P, Gene-D hypothetical unit or whether the gene is a
is consistent with Fogle’s deflationary inten- material particle” (p 79). Finally, with the
tions. molecular phase beginning in the 1950s, the
Where Fogle’s analysis is wholly synchronic units of heredity (the molecular gene) are
in nature, many of the articles address the understood to be real. Now for Gayon, even
theme of the book through analyses that are if the edges are blurry, it is just intrinsically
at least partially historical. Jean Gayon’s con- interesting that a science, genetics, could have
tribution offers an epistemological periodi- gone through such philosophically distinctive
zation of the history of thinking about hered- phases: “I know of no other history of a mod-
ity going back a century and a half. He begins ern biological discipline that could be recon-
by distinguishing between two fundamentally structed in terms of such successive epistemo-
different ways of physicalizing heredity, where logical shifts” (p 87). But Gayon’s historical/
heredity is conceived of as a physical force epistemological periodization opens up an-
that, like other physical forces, could be mea- other line of inquiry as well.
sured in terms of magnitudes, versus heredity The operationalist/instrumentalist stand-
as based upon a physical structure. Mid-19th- point of the Mendelian phase gave rise to
century breeders and biologists “unequivo- Gene-P. But what happens to the Gene-P con-
cally” regarded heredity as a force. Common cept when instrumentalism gives way to real-
belief held that the longer a trait was repro- ism? The contribution by Sara Schwartz pro-
duced in succeeding generations, the vides an opportunity to consider exactly this
stronger its hereditary force would be—a doc- issue. Her contribution, The Differential
trine known as the “constancy of race” Concept of the Gene: Past and Present, offers
(although unremarked upon by Gayon, one a historical story, but with a practical intent.
can quickly fathom the likely influence of She veers in the direction of a unificationist
these views on the rise of 19th-century racial approach and of all the contributors comes
degeneration ideologies, such as that of Gob- the closest to trying to unify the gene under
ineau, as well as upon the thinking of Nietz- something close to a pure Gene-P concept.
sche and late 19th century “Lebensphiloso- The differential concept that is constitutive of
phie.”) Gene-P served the instrumental purposes of
Gayon schematizes the modern history of its enterprise because it did not depend upon
heredity into three phases that correspond to a one-to-one relationship between gene and
three different epistemological standpoints. trait. Classical genes and Genes-P are differ-
Biometry (1870–1900) still conceptualizes ence makers, and it is the predictability of
within the framework of a hereditary force, some discrete phenotypic difference that
but especially for Pearson, that which the counts. But how does one understand the
biometrician measures and statistically ana- role of the gene in relation to that difference?
lyzes is taken in a purely phenomenalist vein. If one assumes a many-to-many relationship
There is no force that is being ontologized, between genes and traits then one does not
only apparent patterns of inheritance that interpret a single gene, in a realist vein, as the
can be quantitatively described. In the second cause of the trait associated with it. Indeed,
Mendelian-Chromosome Phase (1900–1950) Morgan had originally attempted to formu-
heredity as a force gives way to heredity as late a nomenclature using several letters to
structure, with its quantification denoting not indicate that the appearance of a trait was not
magnitudes, but hypothetical entities. The due to the difference maker, but rather to the
ontological status of these entities was not at “residuum—the factors left when this factor is
all clear, but this did not matter to the pre- missing” (p 29). But Morgan was soon to give
dictive power of the enterprise, thus leading up on this nomenclature and, for simplicity’s
to an operationalist or instrumentalist epis- sake, endorse the formalism of attributing
temological self-understanding on the part of the different phenotype to the “difference
the discipline. As Morgan is quoted as saying maker.” Exactly when did the instrumentalist
62 THE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF BIOLOGY Volume 78

and realist heuristics begin to become every Gene-D into a realistically construed
blurred? Is it the case that bringing the differ- (i.e., conflationary) Gene-P is not the way to go
ential concept of the gene from Gayon’s then what alternatives are there? Perhaps an
instrumentalist period to his realist period is alternative model of the meaning of a Gene-
precisely tantamount to the conflation of D can be found in the expanding framework
Gene-P and Gene-D? Schwartz would like to of the developmental gene concept.
salvage the differential gene concept as an Evelyn Fox Keller, Scott Gilbert, and Michel
explanatory strategy that can survive the shift Morange contribute articles that are con-
to molecular and even genomic paradigms, cerned in some way with genes and develop-
but she is not oblivious to the difficulties that ment. Although Keller’s piece examines the
have been encountered in attempting to do so. distinction between the idea of a “develop-
The creation of transgenic knockout mice mental program” versus a “genetic program,”
in order to identify the function of the gene Gilbert and Morange address, albeit in differ-
knocked out has given rise to results notori- ent ways, the notion of the developmental
ously counter to expectations based upon the gene. Gilbert’s paper turns on a very sugges-
differential gene strategy (for example, the tive comparison of the gene of population
deletion of genes such as “p53” and “src,” genetics that was presupposed by the evolu-
which had been shown to be of importance tionary Modern Synthesis and the gene of
in cancer and other studies, resulted in rela- developmental genetics that is now being
tively normal mice). Likewise, the attempts to taken up by proponents of a new model of
identify the function of unknown genes in evolution based upon an evolutionary-devel-
yeast by deleting them and seeing what hap- opmental synthesis (evo-devo). Gilbert enu-
pens proved to be problematic. But should merates these differences as follows: Where
this really have been a surprise? These the population (Pop) gene was an abstraction
research strategies, focusing on analyzing with no physical referent the developmental
Genes-D, are built on a Gene-P concept. The (Dev) gene refers to specific sequences of
Gene-P idea arose at a time when discrete
DNA that include not only coding regions,
differences in phenotype were all that were
but regulatory regions such as promoters,
available to work with. And as Johannsen
enhancers, silencers, and introns, among oth-
(1923:140) presciently asked: “Is the whole of
ers; Pop genes were picked out as difference
Mendelism perhaps nothing but an establish-
makers, but Dev genes have been identified
ment of very many chromosomal irregulari-
on the basis of their similarity across taxa; Pop
ties, disturbances or diseases of enormously
genes were meant to explain mechanisms of
practical and theoretical importance but
without deeper value for an understanding of selection and Dev genes explain the con-
the ‘normal’ constitution of natural bio- straints that underlie phylogenetic patterns;
types?” Pop genes were assumed to pertain to
Genes-P represent a special group—the changes in enzymes and structural proteins,
cases in which a deviation in a Gene-D results and Dev genes are seen to encode proteins
in a distinctive (and viable) phenotype (that involved in signaling and the regulation of pro-
for the sake of utility can be treated instru- cesses such as transcription and splicing; Pop
mentally as a direct causal consequence of genes were presumed to be active in adults
that deviation). But there is no reason to fighting for fitness, but Dev genes are
assume that any or even most Genes-D would expressed during organogenesis by the embryo;
provide such an allelic deviation, but even and the Pop gene was conceived of as acting
more to the point there is no reason to in a context-independent atomistic fashion,
believe that when they do, when there is a while the Dev genes are seen as context depen-
Gene-P phenotype such as cystic fibrosis, Mar- dent parts of a pathway. Gilbert goes on to dis-
fan syndrome, or blue eyes, it provides an cuss the history and status of MyoD as an
accurate impression of the histological or exemplar of a developmental gene, but
developmental scope of the respective Gene- numerous homeotic genes and many other
D expression, or an accurate insight into the examples could also have been used.
mechanisms of its activity. But if trying to turn Gilbert’s comparison is offered in a descrip-
March 2003 NEW BIOLOGICAL BOOKS 63

tive and pluralistic vein, but in this sense his those who would drag developmental genes
analysis stops short of many of its own impli- from being Genes-D to being little architects
cations. This extended discussion could well of the phenotype, Morange asks: “But it is also
begin by asking where, despite its 60 years of possible that the developmental genes are
age, are the comparable exemplars of popu- only the molecular components used to build
lation genes that played the role in evolution the organisms: Their study will not reveal any
that the Modern Synthesis ascribed to them? principle of construction. Building of an
Gilbert’s distinction between Pop genes and organism is similar to the assembly of a nest
Dev genes map onto the Gene-P/Gene-D dis- by wasp colonies; it results only from the
tinction with little remainder (and happily responses of individuals to local configura-
the Ps and Ds are already there). The gene of tions and it is written nowhere” (p 207).
population genetics is a Gene-P. It is an Developmental genes are developmental
abstract difference maker methodologically resources (Genes-D) and there is no clear
treated as an independent atomic unit. Popu- boundary between them and other Genes-D.
lation genetics took an instrumental con- The truth of this is further evidenced by Mor-
struct and turned it into a mathematical for- ange in pointing out that many “developmen-
malism. The Modern Synthesis (or at least the tal genes” also serve as templates for proteins
Fisherian end of it) adeptly explained how used in structural capacities (e.g., photore-
evolution would work if organisms were truly ceptors in Drosophila) and metabolic capaci-
composed of Genes-P. But they are not. The “Pan- ties (e.g., glycogen metabolism).
glossian” adaptationism, famously criticized Metaphors matter, as Evelyn Fox Keller tells
by Lewontin, Gould and others, is simply an us here and in many of her other writings.
implication that follows from a theory built The conflationary depiction of developmen-
on Gene-P, and hence the lack of examples. tal genes as developmental blueprints that
Gilbert points out that developmental genes Morange challenges has another name—the
are highly conserved across taxa—but so are genetic program. If the metaphorical appro-
genes for structural and enzymatic proteins. The priation of the computer model for thinking
fact that two species of bird have distinctly dif- about development was inevitable, the partic-
ferent beaks that serve distinctly different ular formulation of it expressed as “the
feeding habits does not mean that there genetic program” idea was not. Rather than
needs to be gross differences in the molecular conceiving of the linear sequence of DNA as
composition of the beak nor of their digestive a program, it could also have been modeled
enzymes (although fine-tuning differences as data. Indeed, an early attempt (Apter and
could certainly be present). New evolutionary Wolpert 1965) at bringing cybernetics to bear
forms are built largely out of the same con- on the question of development assimilated,
stituents by way of dynamic, developmental, not the DNA, but the entire egg cell with all
and organizational innovations. There is no its maternal endowments to the function of a
set of species-defining (structural and enzy- computer program: “In this kind of system,
matic) genes to fulfill the desideratum of the instructions do not exist at particular local-
Modern Synthesis because at the level of the ized sites, but the system acts as a dynamic
material reality of Gene-D there is no contrast whole” (p 163). Keller exposes some of the
class to those properties described by Gilbert contingent twists and turns that were taken
under the heading of developmental genes. by developmental biologists such as Bonner,
Now this is not to say that developmental and ultimately Wolpert himself, in endorsing
genes are immune to contamination and con- the rhetoric of the genetic program, but her
flation with Gene-P. Quite the contrary. And larger objective is to recover that earlier intu-
it is very much to this point that Morange’s ition. She cleverly gives phrase to this idea by
article is addressed. The declaration that cer- bouncing off of a phrase of my own: “Supple-
tain homeotic genes are “master-control menting Lenny Moss’s observation that a
genes” is nothing short of an attempt to pull genetic program is ‘an object nowhere to be
them out of their context and declare them found’ (Moss 1992, 335), I would propose the
to be materialized Genes-P. In response to developmental program as an entity that is
64 THE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF BIOLOGY Volume 78

everywhere to be found” (p 176). Keller’s dis- boundary object that better suits the episte-
tinction between a genetic program and a mic needs. Rheinberger offers the postulate
developmental program partitions quite of colinearity between DNA and code as an
nicely as projections of the Gene-P/Gene-D example of a fuzzy boundary object that was
distinction, respectively, onto development. productive, not only despite but perhaps
Of course, the whole take-home of Gene-D because of its fuzziness.
would be that DNA has to be parsed on its own Although this thesis of colinearity ulti-
terms (very much as Fogle proposes with his mately proved to be untenably simplistic,
desideratum for a new vocabulary) and func- along the way to finding its limits it enabled
tionally recontextualized among the myriad the fleshing out of a theory of “code” to take
of other molecular resources of the cell. place. Is it the case then that attempting to
Gene-P councils one to always track causality make distinctions and to hold concepts to
back to the gene. Gene-D councils one to pre- standards of logical and empirical account-
suppose no constituent as causally privileged ability is just the wrong way to go? Rheinber-
in advance but rather to elucidate the dynam- ger’s answer to this appears to be, well, fuzzy:
ics of living systems at the hierarchical level “The gene has been a powerful epistemic
and from the point of departure that best entity in the history of heredity, in all the
befits the empirical demands of the inquiry. vagueness that is characteristic for such enti-
An attempt to provide experimental, histori- ties. It is tempting to generalize this statement
cal, and philosophical perspectives conso- and assume that fruitful scientific concepts
nant with this outlook can be found in the are bound to be polysemic. I will resist this
recent anthology, Cycles of Contingency: Devel- temptation and assure my critics that I do by
opmental Systems and Evolution (Oyama et al. no means deny the value of precision in sci-
2001). ence. But precision itself has historically
Two of the editors, Beurton and Rheinber- changing boundaries” (pp 235–236).
ger, provide the yin and yang of the one ver- But consider what appears to be Rheinber-
sus the many question with their respective ger’s summary statement about the main
contributions to the anthology—Rheinber- topic of the book: “You may expect me to
ger on behalf of pluralism, Beurton on the come up with a nice solution to the mean-
side of unity. Rheinberger builds a defense of dering story of the gene at the end. As far as
pluralism about gene meanings on an epis- the scientific story goes, there is none. As to
temology of scientific knowledge that is an epistemological take-home lesson, I have
informed by the conceptual tools of textual one. Alas, it is a very disappointing message
criticism. Science, we can agree, is realized for nondeconstructivists. I might say . . . [a]
and constituted in practices and “[t]he prac- gene is a gene is a gene. This is a strong claim.
tices in which the sciences are grounded . . . Taken seriously, it means that in science
engender epistemic objects” (p 220). The every presumed referent is turned into a
gene is an epistemic object. An epistemic future signifier” (p 235). Now what does this
object is not some brute fact of the matter, mean? The boundary object that is formed in
but rather a kind of focused learning space, the practical/discursive scientific nebula is a
a niche in the complex nebulae of epistemic referent. That conceptual space, that is the
practices in which the nucleus of an object of boundary object, takes itself to be pointing to,
inquiry proceeds to take shape. An object or perhaps engulfing, something in nature
whose shape is formed along the contours of and giving it definition. As it obtains defini-
an epistemic possibility space is thus a tion it likewise becomes part of the signifying
“boundary object.” Now much of Rheinber- nebula and semantically shapes the space in
ger’s message is to say that the contours of the which new objects can be referred to and
boundary space should not be sanded into allowed to show up (or not). Gene-P, episte-
smoothness by philosophical (or other) pre- mologically qualified as an instrumental con-
suppositions about the (epistemic) virtues of struct by Johannsen, and at least the early
clarity or sharpness. Where one must grapple Morgan, was a permissive signifier. But when
with real complexity, it will be the fuzzier it got taken up by population genetics and
March 2003 NEW BIOLOGICAL BOOKS 65

hardened into the Modern Synthesis, and tion to detect, begins to qualify as a gene.
then materialized into a conflationary Gene- Hence, a gene need not be located in any one
P/Gene-D, it became rather imperious and place. All those DNA variations that, due to
unforgiving. this common guidance (because they all
The prevailing conflationary gene concept share in the production of one adaptive dif-
of much of the last 50 years was surely fuzzy ference), spread at the same rate in a popu-
in many (including some productive) ways lation qualify as a single gene irrespective of
and yet it was also sharp enough to cut the location. It is this sameness of reproductive rate
entirety of developmental biology out of the by which these DNA variations begin to meet
mainstream of evolutionary thought, to dis- the standards of being one single gene. Such
miss the majority of the constituents of a cell a gene lacks physical discreteness but never-
from the study of heredity, and to draw a nar- theless acquires some distinctness as the
row preformationist line in the sand between smallest unit of selection. This is, I suggest,
cultural studies and putatively natural sci- the unifying element in genes, the near-invis-
ences of man. Critiques of the gene concept, ibility of which has been constantly bedeviling
here and elsewhere, have been motivated by us. This element possesses the potential to
a desire to release the straightjacket, not to bring together a variety of divergent gene
tighten the strings. Rheinberger wants to concepts and to synthesize them into one
advocate the epistemic value of the local, sit- common view of the gene” (pp 299–300).
uated, engaged standpoint. But where are the In Beurton’s first step, the diachronic
presumed philosophical critics standing at a mind’s eye perspective of the evolutionist
distance and demanding clarity for its own must be able to look into the genome of an
sake? Critical distinctions can well open up organism and see what the synchronic view of
the space for many new and productive lines the molecular biologist cannot. This critical
of inquiry. Blanket advocacy for pluralism first move turns on a couple of presupposi-
may overlook epistemically stifling collusions tions the empirical plausibility of which Beur-
at the roots. Because the standpoint of episte- ton does not explicate. Beurton is positing a
mic fuzziness does not seem to offer the gene, or really a proto-gene, on its way to
resources for making distinctions about dis- becoming a gene. What gives the proto-gene
tinctions, this might well suggest that it is the its coherence is that no matter how it is dis-
deconstructionist who is in danger of trying tributed in the genome it is just that, and dis-
to legislate from afar. tinctly that, which is responsible for exactly
At the other end of the unity-plurality spec- one phenotypic trait whose adaptive advan-
trum, Peter Beurton offers what may read like tage results in a uniform rate of selection
a heroic last chance attempt to reconstitute wherever it is present. Now if one does not
the unified gene. Granting that molecular presuppose the existence of discrete func-
biology has debunked the idea that DNA con- tional genes to begin with, and Beurton claims
sists of discrete functional genetic units that he cannot, then what exactly is the basis
(Genes-P) to offer natural selection as its for believing that adaptive advantages are
input, Beurton tries to turn the model upside realized in discrete differences in traits (as
down and argue that such discrete functional opposed to complex differences in the per-
genes are what natural selection produces as formance of the whole organismic system)?
its output. The argument begins with the And likewise, if he is not presupposing that
claim that although the DNA that provides end result he is trying to derive, on what basis
the wherewithal for any particular transcrip- is he warranted to abstract out only the dis-
tional event may be scattered about, natural persed segments of DNA from all of the
selection will still pick out differences in dis- molecular machinery which is actually
tributed patterns of DNA that make a differ- involved in the processes that may result in
ence. “I suggest that such an array of non- adaptive advantage? And, finally, given the
localized DNA variations, whose reproduction real heterogeneity of organisms, how plausi-
comes to be controlled by some such an adap- ble is it that Beurton’s envisaged array of DNA
tive difference large enough for natural selec- will rise above the variable genomic, dynamic,
66 THE QUARTERLY REVIEW OF BIOLOGY Volume 78

and biochemical contexts in which it is a force in the opposite direction? The com-
embedded and distinguish itself as a discrete plexity and diversity of binding motifs, and
unit of selection by way of its relatively context the roster of transcriptional factors involved
independent affect on reproductive rate? in the formation of regulatory complexes,
Surely there are organisms with differences has increased not decreased with the evolu-
in DNA sequences here and there, and dif- tion of more complex life forms (Interna-
ferent reproductive rates, but unless these tional Human Genome Sequencing Consor-
three assumptions are tenable, then the units tium 2001). How can we rule out the
of evolution become nothing short of the possibility that natural selection has selected
whole developmental system (Griffiths and Gray for more complexly dispersed genomic archi-
1994). But let us provisionally grant the pos- tectures in the case of more complex, phe-
sibility of Beurton’s initial move and consider notypically plastic organisms? Beurton seems
the next step. Beurton believes that given this to take it that the condensation of DNA into
first condition, natural selection would then discrete atomic units constitutes some kind of
act to bring these dispersed units together attractor state in evolution. We can give this
into a physically discrete gene: “To say such attractor state a name: it is Gene-P. Where a
an adaptive difference causes the origin of a materialized misconstrual of Gene-P had
new gene is to say that a genomic overall dif- served as the point of departure for the Mod-
ference between individuals causes via its adap- ern Synthesis, Beurton now wants to insinuate
tive effect and the good offices of natural Gene-P back as the very telos of evolution. In
selection the emergence of a gene inside indi- the absence of a prior assumption of the con-
flationary Gene-P/Gene-D gene, both steps
viduals in a process of downward causation
of Beurton’s model are problematic and his
(or genomic compartmentation, or genic
attempt at a grand unification of the gene
individuation). This is how some specific
founders.
genomic difference hardens into a single
The Concept of the Gene in Development and
gene” (p 302). Evolution also includes articles by Fred Gif-
But why should we believe that the force of ford, Michael Dietrich, James Greisemer, and
evolution is toward the condensation of DNA Frederick Holmes, as well as an overview
segments into discrete units associated with (which I have referred to) by Raphael Falk. It
discrete traits? Why cannot the opposite constitutes the first multidisciplinary collec-
direction of movement be just as likely? Biol- tion of studies on the concept of the gene,
ogists such as Nina Federoff (1999) and James and is thus long overdue. It is a very well-
Shapiro (1999) have suggested that the edited volume that could serve as a valuable
restructuring of genomes, possibly through a nucleus for a seminar on a timely topic and a
kind of regulated use of transposon activity, point of departure for both biologists and
has played a central role in generating evo- philosophers grappling with the meaning of
lutionary diversity. Would this not constitute the gene.

REFERENCES
Apter M J, Wolpert L. 1965. Cybernetics and devel- Griffiths P E, Neumann-Held E M. 1999. Thinking of
opment. Journal of Theoretical Biology 8:244–257. biology: the many faces of the gene. Biosciences
Dupré J. 1993. The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foun- 49(8):656–662.
dations of the Disunity of Science. Cambridge (MA): Johannsen W. 1923. Some remarks about units in
Harvard University Press. heredity. Hereditas 4:133–141.
Fedoroff N. 1999. Transposable elements as a molec- International Human Genome Sequencing Consor-
ular evolutionary force. Annals of the New York Acad- tium. 2001. Initial sequencing and analysis of the
emy of Sciences 870:251–264. human genome. Nature 409(6822):860–921.
Griffiths P E, Gray R D. 1994. Developmental systems Moss L. 1992. A kernal of truth? On the reality of the
and evolutionary explanation. Journal of Philosophy genetic program. Pages 335–348 in PSA 1992: Pro-
91(6):277–304. ceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of
March 2003 NEW BIOLOGICAL BOOKS 67

Science Association, edited by D Hull, M Forbes, and the process molecular gene concept and its con-
K Okruhlik. East Lansing (MI): Philosophy of Sci- text. Pages 69–84 in Cycles of Contingency: Develop-
ence Association. mental Systems and Evolution, edited by S Oyama, P
Moss L. 2001. Deconstructing the gene and recon- E Griffiths, and R D Gray. Cambridge (MA): MIT
structing molecular developmental systems. Pages Press.
85–98 in Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems Oyama S, Griffiths P E, Gray R D. 2001. Cycles of Con-
and Evolution, edited by S Oyama, P E Griffiths, and tingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution. Cam-
R D Gray. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press. bridge (MA): MIT Press.
Moss L. 2003. What Genes Can’t Do. Cambridge (MA): Shapiro J. 1999. Genome system architecture and nat-
MIT Press. ural genetic engineering in evolution. Annals of the
Neumann-Held E M. 2001. Let’s talk about genes: New York Academy of Sciences 870:23–35.

Potrebbero piacerti anche