Sei sulla pagina 1di 21

Faith and Reason: Aspe cts of Philo sophical Tri nitarianism in

Aquinas and Bo naventure

Philosophical theology owes a good deal to the seminal works of high Scholasticism’s
two most important theologians, Saints Bonaventure of Bagnoregio (1221-1274) and
Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274). Studies of these two Masters of Theology who held
chairs at the University of Paris have predominantly focused on comparisons and
contrasts between the Franciscan and Dominican approaches to the perennial question
of faith, reason and philosophy’s place in theology. In this essay I attempt to narrow
the problem of faith and reason down to the relationship between each of their
scientific, philosophical methods and what is fundamentally unattainable without
faith, the doctrine of the unity and trinity of God in Christian theology.
Unquestionably the Franciscan and the Dominican both approached the doctrine and
study of Trinitarian theology on the basis of Christian faith and divine revelation.
Nevertheless both exhibited an unparalleled confidence in the capacity of reason and
philosophy to explain and defend the Church’s doctrine, albeit with marked
differences that were of enormous significance for the development of Scholastic
theology. In Bonaventure we find a strong use of philosophical reason and theology in
his Quaestiones disputatae de mysterio Trinitatis (1255), the Breviloquium (1257),
the Itinerarium mentis in Deum (1259) and finally the Collationes in Hexaemeron
(1274), all the works upon which this study is based.1 We turn to Thomas’ early work,

1
Disputed Questions on the Mystery of the Trinity, Works of St. Bonaventure III, translated
and introduced by Zachary Hayes (Saint Bonaventure, N.Y.: The Franciscan Institute, 2000).
Hereafter referred to as Disputed Questions. This work was written sometime between 1253
and 1257, that is, later than the Sentence Commentary and shortly before his departure from
the university of Paris to become Minister General of the Franciscan Order. See Introduction
by Zachary Hayes, p. 26.
For the text of Breviloquium, see Bonaventure, Breviloquium, translated by Dominic V.
Monti (Saint Bonaventure, N.Y.: Franciscan Institute Publications, 2005).
For the text of Itinerarium mentis in Deum, see Bonaventure, The Journey of the Mind to
God, translated by Philotheus Boehner; edited, with Introduction and Notes by Stephen F.
Brown (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1993). Hereafter referred to as
Itinerarium.
For Collationes in hexaemeron, see Bonaventure, Collations on the Six Days, The Works of
Bonaventure Vol. V, translated by José de Vinck (Paterson, N.J.: St. Anthony Guild Press,
1970). Hereafter referred to as In hexaemeron.

1
the Expositio super librum Boethii de Trinitate, (his commentary on Boethius’ De
Trinitate., c. 1256-1259), and also to some of his mature works, De potentia and the
Summa theologiae for an understanding of the Dominican’s philosophical
Trinitarianism.2 An important way to critically evaluate the relationship between faith
and reason in these two theologians is to consider how each found ‘evidence’ for the
Trinity in the world of created things. We will also examine the issue of ‘necessary
reasons’ for the Trinity in both, and to attempt an overall view of the connection
between the Trinitarian processions in God and creation.

The Philosophical Trinitarianism of St. Bonaventure

In his most systematic treatise, the Breviloquium, Bonaventure describes theology as


the only perfect science and also “the only perfect wisdom, for it begins with the
supreme cause as the principle of all things that are caused – the very point at which
philosophical knowledge ends.”3 Yet, metaphysics, or the study of the most
fundamental concepts of being and essence, is for the seraphic doctor the first science
from which all enquiry must begin, being as it is the first principle, center and goal of
existence.4 Against the secondary literature that would construe a Bonaventure in
terms of an opposition to Aquinas, or to philosophy per se for that matter, or who
label his outlook a “mystical” theology that treats philosophy as a mere adjunct to
theology, this distinction just quoted needs to be taken into account.5 The implication

2
For the translation of Expositio super librum Boethii De Trinitate used in this essay, see
Thomas Aquinas, Faith, reason and theology, Mediaeval Sources In Translation 32,
translated by Armand Maurer (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1987).
Hereafter referred to as In Boeth. de Trin.
For De potentia, see Thomas Aquinas, The Power of God, translated by Richard J. Regan
(Oxford: OUP, 2012). Hereafter referred to as De potentia.
For Summa Theologiae, see Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, translated the Fathers of
the English Dominican Province (Westminster, Maryland: Christian Classics, 1981).
Hereafter referred to as Summa Theologiae.
3
Bonaventure, Breviloquium, part I, chapter 1: 3, [p. 28]. Does this put a boundary line on
reason, prescribing its scope? See Denys Turner, Faith, Reason and the Existence of God,
(Cambridge, CUP: 2004), p. 88. Yes, for all sciences and even theology have their limit
according to Bonaventure: “they have their evening, for all knowledge shall be destroyed.”
(De reductione, VI.)
4
Bonaventure, In hexaemeron., 1: 11-12 [p. 6-7].
5
Kevin L. Hughes offers a summary of the conventional misconstruals of Bonaventure in his
article “Bonaventure Contra Mundum? The Catholic Theological Tradition Revisited,”
Theological Studies 74 (2013), 372-398. See also Andreas Speer, “Bonaventure and the

2
of Bonaventure’s own words is that philosophy and theology are indeed two distinct
sciences. In this same context Bonaventure describes theology as the science that
makes “the body of faith intelligible,”6––the task he sets out to accomplish in the
Breviloquium. Quoting St. Augustine, he gives the following reason: “what we
believe we owe to authority, what we understand to reason.” The intelligibility of
Christian doctrine therefore depends on understanding that which has been revealed
by authority––by means of reason. The philosopher or metaphysician is able to rise to
a consideration of the very notion of being from created and particular substances, but
cannot attain to the notion of Father, Son and Holy Spirit.7 For Bonaventure, the
metaphysician is only a true metaphysician when he considers being in the light of
that principle which is the exemplary cause of all things. Otherwise his philosophy
remains at the level of physical science or ethics. Christ is not only the centre of
theology, but of the natural or philosophical sciences too: “He Himself is the central
point of all understanding.”8 There is an intentional circularity to the logic of
Bonaventure: If we begin with the first science, metaphysics, first “by reason of
eternal generation,” we can pass through all other sciences to culminate in theology,
the seventh science. “The rational spirit, which emanates from the most blessed trinity
and is a likeness of the trinity, should return after the manner of a certain intelligible
circle...to the most blessed trinity by God-conforming glory.”9

It is possible to take Bonaventure’s metaphor of a book to conceptualize the twins of


faith and reason or theology and philosophy: the “Book of Scripture” would
correspond to faith and theology and the “Book of Creation” to reason and
philosophy. Though we need to be careful in making clear-cut divisions between
them, for though there is a relative autonomy between philosophy and theology in the
writings of Bonaventure, both domains have a single origin in the Trinity of Persons,
and in particular reason is attributed to the Word as Exemplar. So both books must be
taken together as foundations upon which to base belief in the Trinity.10 While
theology and philosophy are distinct disciplines, they are not separate, unrelated

Question of a Medieval Philosophy,” Medieval Philosophy and Theology 6 (1997), especially


pps. 29-36.
6
Bonaventure, Breviloquium, I, 1: 4, [p. 29].
7
Bonaventure, In hexaemeron, 1: 13 [p.7]
8
Bonaventure, In hexaemeron, 1: 11 [p. 6].
9
Bonaventure, Disputed Questions, q. 8, ad 7 [p. 266].
10
Bonaventure, Disputed Questions, q. 1 a. 2, concl.

3
sciences. A third book he describes is the “Book of Life,” and this corresponds to the
ultimate goal or end of philosophy and theology, that is, mystical “union with Him
who is above all essence and all knowledge.”11

The Book of Creation


In the “first book”, the book of creation, we read of the perceptible world of sensory
knowledge and natural things, the natural sciences and philosophy. In his Disputed
Questions on the Mystery of the Trinity, Bonaventure says that in the pre-lapsarian
state of humanity, the first book was an efficacious light that bore witness to God as
Trinity.12 The created world is a kind of book reflecting its Maker, the Trinity at three
levels of expression: vestige, image and likeness.13 Vestiges (vestigia: footprints)
mirror God as their single origin in that they have their own unique existence (esse),
and therefore speak to the reader of a threefold efficient, exemplary and final
causality.14 God is the principle, exemplary form and final end or goal of all things
that exist. Vestiges give witness to the Trinity, but only from afar. However much
vestiges mirror their originating cause, the dissimilarity is always greater. They are
unlike the unity, simultaneity, fullness, equality, and substantiality of the Triune God.
Because vestiges imply production and hence an originating principle, they are divine
words expressing and bearing a trace of the Divine Exemplar, the Word through
whom all things are created.

The second level of expression, the image, is a distinct nature which bears a closer
resemblance of its Creator than the vestige in that it mirrors God through the faculties
of memory, intelligence and will. The image ‘grasps’ not only the created essences
below it in the hierarchy of created beings, but “even the creating essence,” above it.
(Here Bonaventure differs from St Thomas).15 Like a mirror, the image receives and

11
Bonaventure, Itinerarium, 7: 5 [p. 39].
12
Q. 1, a. 2. [p. 128]. See also Breviloquium., p. 2, 12: 4 [p. 97].
13
Bonaventure, Breviloquium, II, 12: 1 [p. 96].
14
I Sentences, d. 3, p. 1, q. 2, resp. [p. 73] Translated by Alexis Bugnolo, published by The
Franciscan Archive with footnotes and scholia, 2007 & 2010), CD Edition. The CD version
includes parallel columns of the Latin and English texts and the page numbering of the
Quaracchi editors.
15
Bonaventure, Breviloquium, Part 2, chap. 9. 1 [p.84]; I Sentences, d. 3, p. 1, q. 2, resp. [p.
73] (Published by The Franciscan Archive with footnotes and scholia, 2007, 2010), CD
Edition. [p.73]; see also Zachary Hayes, Introduction, Disputed Questions, 70. This is the
subject of one of the major differences between Bonaventure with Aquinas (e.g., In Boeth. de

4
represents within itself all things.16 The threefold imagery of memory, intelligence
and will analogically reflects the Trinitarian Persons of Father, Son and Holy Spirit.
In human beings, who through intellectual judgment are able to form images, generate
thought, and a likeness of themselves, the book of creation becomes a mirror in which
is reflected “the eternal generation of the Word, the Image and the Son, eternally
emanating from the Father.”17

The Book of Scripture


The Seraphic Doctor uses the metaphor of the book of Scripture to illustrate what
today approximates with faith, revelation and theology. While “Scripture” was the
term Bonaventure often used when he wanted to speak of theology or Christian
doctrine, it should be noted that this did not mean that divine revelation was equated
with the literal reading of the Scriptures.18 Theology involved a study of the
foundational literal sense onto which was built three further spiritual meanings: the
moral, the anagogical and the allegorical interpretations of Scripture.19 Just as the
literal meaning is foundational for the theological, so reason is foundational for good
theology.

According to Bonaventure, a need arises for the book of Scripture due to the fall of
humanity into the “darkness of ignorance” and the loss of the “eye of contemplation.”
This book had been written “in accord with the divine revelation which has never
been deficient nor absent from the beginning of the world to the end,” and which
spreads the light of a more efficacious testimony that God is Trinity.20 With this
universal disclosure of knowledge Bonaventure shows great confidence in the role of
reason in the pre-lapsarian state of humanity. It also manifests the unity of
Bonaventure’s thought on the roles of revelation and reason. But even as Bonaventure
argues that humankind may arrive at knowledge of God through creatures by the

Trin. q. 1, a. 3). Bonaventure maintains in the Itinerarium that pure being is that “which first
comes into the intellect,” and that this cannot be analogous being, “for that has the least
actuality.” (Itinerarium V: 3).
16
Bonaventure, In hexaemeron 12: 16. [p. 180].
17
Bonaventure, Itinerarium, II. 7.
18
Christopher Cullen, Bonaventure (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), 114.
19
Bonaventure, On the Reduction of the Arts to Theology, V. [p.45]
20
Bonaventure, Disputed Questions, Q. 1 A. 2, concl. [p. 129].

5
natural light of reason,21 he nevertheless draws the line and clearly states that it is not
possible for man to come to knowledge of the Trinity of Persons in the One Divine
Essence through creatures:

The plurality of persons [together] with unity of essence is proper to the divine nature
alone, the like of which cannot be found in creatures, nor may it be found, nor
thought of rationally: for that reason in no manner is the Trinity of the Persons
cognizable through a creature, by ascending rationally from the creature into God.22

That there is a threefold plurality of the one Divine Essence can only be known by
revelation of the Word Incarnate. Bonaventure illustrates this in his Itinerarium with
the analogy of the two cherubim in the Temple sanctuary. By them “we understand
the two kinds or grades (duos modos seu gradus) of contemplation of the invisible
and eternal things of God: the first considers the essential attributes of God; the
second, the proper attributes of the three Persons.”23 The structure of Bonaventure’s
thought is similar to that of Aquinas’ description of Divine oneness and threeness as
what is essential and what is proper to God, but where the Franciscan differs is in
associating the proper attributes with the diffusion of goodness in God. As he
explains, St John Damascene, following the example of Moses who proclaims the
Unity of God in the Old Testament, taught that the more proper name of God is ‘He
Who Is,’ i.e., Being Itself (cf. Ex 3:14). However, it takes a further step to
acknowledge God principally as Good and therefore as the Trinity. For Dionysius
considered God’s name to be more properly Goodness and he followed the example
of Christ who attributed exclusively to God the name Good (Lk 18:19) and revealed
the plurality of God in the New Testament.24

God as subsistent being (He Who Is) may be grasped by the philosopher, yet even this
is only discoverable along the soul’s journey “with the High Priest into the Holy of
Holies.”25 This means that it is only those who are practiced in the way of

21
Bonaventure, I Sent., d. 3, p. 1, a. 1, q. 2, resp. [p.72]
22
Bonaventure, I Sent., d. 3, p. 1, a. 1, q. 4, resp. [p. 76]. Dicendum, quod pluralitas
personarum cum unitate essentiae est proprium divinae naturae solius, cuius simile nec
reperitur in creatura nec potest reperiri nec rationabiliter cogitari: ideo nullo modo trinitas
personarum est cognoscibilis per creaturam, rationabiliter ascendendo a creatura in Deum.
23
Bonaventure, Itinerarium, 5: 1 [p. 28]. Latin text of Itinerarium accessed 29/10/2014 from
the Franciscan Archive www.franciscanos.net/document/itinerl.htm
24
Bonaventure, Itinerarium, 5: 2 [p. 28].
25
Bonaventure, Itinerarium, 5: 1 [p. 28].

6
contemplation, of seeing God ‘above’––and not only ‘outside’ in his vestiges or even
‘within’ in his image––who can approach this level of knowledge. And yet to see God
as He Who Is is manifestly not at the same level as contemplating God under the
aspect of goodness and the plurality of Persons. This takes a further step (gradus).
The soul still needs to be raised from the consideration of God according to His
essential attributes to “the contuition” of God as Pure Goodness also. Here it is not as
evident in Bonaventure as it is in Aquinas that there is such a clear demarcation
between the orders of faith and reason. Just as God’s unity and his triunity are not two
‘things’, so reason and faith for Bonaventure are not so distinct that each be self-
contained. There is an equality represented in the two cherubim facing one another in
the sanctuary, but it would seem that the inequality arises according to the conceptual
order of the knower, who needs to rise from lower to higher knowledge through the
light of Scripture.

Upon reaching the heights of contemplating the communicability and diffusion of the
Good through the Trinitarian manifestations, Bonaventure would have us take a step
back in awe: “But when you contemplate these things, take care that you do not think
you can understand the incomprehensible.”26 It is only through the paradoxical
coincidence of opposites, the “dialectics of dissimilarity”27 that the finite human
creature can understand something of the mystery of the infinite God. This applies
just as much to the knowledge of the essential attributes of God. “If ‘God’ is the name
of the being that is first, eternal, most simple, most actual, and most perfect, such a
being cannot be thought not to be, nor can it be thought to be other than one.”28 We
may come to know of the supreme Being through its opposite, for most pure being
cannot come to our mind except “with the full flight on non-being.”29 We cannot
grasp nothingness (or the non-accompaniment of being) without therefore also
acknowledging pure being having nothing of non-being, both in reality and in our
thinking of it. For Bonaventure, human knowledge does not depend solely on the
active intellect’s abstractions from sensible likenesses, but also on an intuitive grasp

26
Bonaventure, Itinerarium, 6: 3. [p. 34].
27
The description is Timothy J. Johnson’s in his article “Reading Between the Lines:
Apophatic Knowledge and Naming the Divine in Bonaventure’s Book of Creation,”
Franciscan Studies 60 (2002), 139-158.
28
Bonaventure, Itinerarium, 5: 6 [p. 30].
29
Bonaventure, Itinerarium, 5: 3. [p. 29].

7
of Divine Being. 30 Though he does not claim that we are conscious of this reality. We
come to contemplate this only when we transcend our normal ‘phantasmal,’ or
imaginative ways of thinking. Just as the eye sees nothing, or rather is blinded when
looking at the sun, so the mind does not grasp Pure Being even though it is pure
Being that first comes to the mind and through which all other beings are grasped.

To sum up, Bonaventure uses the philosophical tools at his disposal to develop his
analogies of God’s relation to creation expressed in the characteristically symbolic
language ‘vestige,’ ‘image,’ and ‘likeness’ of the Latin Middle Ages to demonstrate
the unknowability of the Divine Trinity. He shows what the human mind cannot know
if only in order that it might recognize its own inability and thereby seek that which is
infinitely more simple, perfect, powerful, wise and good. The darkening of the
intellect is an apophatic means of intuiting an even more splendid Light to be sought
and loved. “This very darkness is in fact the supreme illumination of our mind.”31 His
confidence in reason together with his understanding of the limits of the mind in
respect of the Infinite, and his modesty in regard to what we can grasp of Trinitarian
revelation, are critical to understanding the relationship between faith and reason in
the Seraphic Doctor. As Denys Turner so ably summarizes, reason is a point of entry
into the ‘darkness of God,’ “just as the human nature of Christ is, as Bonaventure tells
us, a transitus into the Deus absconditus of Christian faith.”32

The role of necessary reasons in Sts. Bonaventure and Thomas Aquinas

The relationship between Bonaventure’s theology and philosophy has often been
studied by way of contrast with the more dominant Thomistic thought of Catholic
theology, and has therefore also been interpreted in terms of St. Thomas. In his
Trinitarian theology, Bonaventure’s daring use of the so-called ‘necessary reasons’
for plurality within the One Divine Essence has been one such area of discussion,
recently in the work of Gilles Emery, O.P.33 Emery’s summary of the Scholastic
treatment of God’s Oneness and Threeness in these two Scholastic theologians is
focused on necessary reasons as constituting the principle difference between the
30
Christopher Cullen, Bonaventure, 61-2.
31
Bonaventure, Itinerarium, V: 4 [p. 29]
32
Turner, Faith, Reason and the Existence of God, 261.
33
E.g., Disputed Questions, Q. 2, A. 2, arg. 10 [p.151]

8
two.34 In fact he claims that Bonaventure “go[es] from oneness to the affirmation of
the Trinity” by means of necessary reasons. Further, he argues that Bonaventure’s
Trinitarian theology does not limit itself to establishing the non-contradiction or
harmony between oneness and threeness (to which Aquinas restricts his study), but
that the very aim of Bonaventure’s Disputed Questions on the Mystery of the Trinity
functions as a “disenvelopment” of Threeness from Oneness “using the resources of
reason,” i.e., necessary reasons.35 Emery’s elaboration on Bonaventure’s true purpose
needs to be weighed against the Franciscan’s conviction that the reasonableness of the
Trinity is rooted in his taking it on faith that God is what he is necessarily, and that
there must therefore be necessary and rational reasons for who He is––apart from our
making sense of the fact that in Bonaventure’s mind there is an obligation imposed by
the Gospel itself and that this does not itself run counter to reason. There must be a
necessary relation between the unity of God’s essence and the Trinity of Divine
Persons, even if we cannot know this philosophically. We can however think about it
with the light of revelation and “by intelligence lifted up by faith.”36 Indeed, there is
no possibility, even in Bonaventure’s confidence in humanity’s pre-lapsarian ability,
that humankind ever possessed knowledge of God as a Trinity of Persons without the
preordained and guiding hand of revelation. As we saw, Bonaventure understood
Divine revelation to be present to humanity “from the beginning of the world.” Yet, to
believe in the Trinity is a “truth beyond reason.”37 No matter how much Bonaventure
speculates as to necessary reasons for generation and procession in the Godhead, this
is always subject to the presuppositions of revealed faith, and they are not, strictly
speaking, the kind of demonstrable arguments that Aquinas taught should never and
cannot be used to ‘prove’ the Trinity.

The only reasons Aquinas would allow were the so-called “adaptations” or “probable
arguments”, which are arguments capable of showing that what is proposed to faith is

34
Gilles Emery, “The Threeness and Oneness of God in Twelfth- to Fourteenth-Century
Scholasticism,” Nova et Vetera, English Edition 1 (2003), 62-65.
35
Gilles Emery, “Threeness and Oneness,” 66 & 63. Perhaps this misunderstanding of
Thomas’ structure in the Summa Theologiae (prima pars, QQ. 1-26 and 27-43) of the division
representing respectively de deo uno (reason) and de deo trino (faith) has colored the way
Bonaventure’s Trinitarian theology is read.
36
Bonaventure, In hexaemeron, 11. 5 [p. 160] ; Zachary Hayes, Introduction, 28-29.
37
Disputed Questions Q. 1, A. 2 concl. [p.130].

9
not unreasonable or impossible.38 All that the so-called necessary reasons really
amount to in Thomas’ thought are probable arguments that do not have the force of
necessity. To attempt to prove that God is a Trinity by natural reason is to derogate
from the dignity of faith. For, as Thomas says, the Catholic faith is firstly concerned
with invisible realities that do not come under the sway of human reason, mysteries
that are in fact hidden or veiled.39 The only way we may use such arguments in
Trinitarian theology is to show that the presuppositions of the faith are not
incongruous or unreasonable, and to bolster the faith against attacks. But these cannot
be considered to be adequate proofs.40 To ‘prove’ supernatural realities by means of
natural reasons is to give unbelievers the impression that we believe because of
reasons that in fact are not cogent or simply unconvincing.

Aquinas outlines two kinds of reasoning by which we investigate matters human or


divine.41 One is demonstrative, the syllogistic argument based on premises and
conclusion and which necessarily compels the mind’s assent. St Thomas is clear that
matters of faith cannot be demonstratively proved in this way, for faith must be
voluntary. The best necessary reasons and demonstrative arguments can offer is to
show that belief in the Trinity is not impossible. And though the matters of faith
cannot be demonstratively proved, “neither can they be demonstratively disproved.”42
The second kind of reasoning is persuasive. Only this kind of argument can fall within
the scope of faith and sacra doctrina in the hope of persuading the truth of faith to the
doubtful or unbelievers. Persuasive reason draws on analogies to confirm the truths of
faith, and this goes to show a further reason why necessary or demonstrative
arguments cannot be legitimately used to ‘prove’ the Trinity: doing so would make
the argument about God depend on creatures, the conclusion would be made subject
to analogies (and therefore in terms of premises that refer principally to created
things). This would be a kind of natural theology in which God and creation are
univocally predicated, thereby reducing the mysteries of faith to the mere shadows of
philosophy reason. That would therefore not be knowledge of the God of Christian
theology.

38
Gilles Emery, Trinity in Aquinas (Ave Maria University: Sapientia Press, 2006), 126.
39
S.T. 1a Q. 32, A. 1, with reference to I Cor 2: 6-7.
40
Thomas Aquinas, S.T., 1a, Q. 32, A. 1, ad. 2 [169-70].
41
Aquinas, In Boeth. de Trin., Q. 2, A. 1, ad 5, [p. 39].
42
Aquinas, In Boeth. de Trin., Q. 2, A. 1, ad 5.

10
For Bonaventure the obligation to believe in what cannot be known without the
authority of revelation is that which is mediated in the so-called book of Scripture,
which bears witness to the truth that God is a Trinity, especially in the sacraments and
teaching of the New Testament. “This testimony is so express and efficacious that it
renders this truth not only credible –– i.e. congruous for belief –– but necessary as
well, since it obliges us and constrains us to believe it.”43 Bonaventure’s necessary
reasons must therefore be seen within the context of faith seeking understanding: that
contemplating God in the “highest and most reverent way” necessitates us to think
that he both understands Himself and wills His Goodness. Nevertheless this reasoning
is
not dictated by the innate light itself, but by the infused light from which ––together
with the natural light –– one concludes that God is to be thought of as one who
generates and spirates one co-equal to and consubstantial with Himself, and thus one
44
thinks of God in the highest and most reverent way.

To think of God in the highest and most reverent way for Bonaventure is a fruit of the
meeting of faith and reason. It is faith that moves us to think of God in the most
elevated and loving way, in this way affecting our natural reason to think at a higher
level to believe that God communicates himself in the most complete way,

and it would not be most loving if, believing him so able, we thought him unwilling
to do so...faith tells us that God totally communicates himself by eternally having a
45
beloved and another who is loved by both. In this way God is both one and three.

The necessary reasons in the Disputed Questions are not therefore a derivation of
threeness from oneness as Emery claims ––just as they are not so in Aquinas––but are
the fruit of Bonaventure’s thinking on the close interrelation of being and goodness.
The structure of essential attributes juxtaposed alongside the personal plurality in God
in chapter 5 of the Itinerarium (symbolized by the two cherubim) is consistent with
the literary structure of the Disputed Questions. In the latter, the first seven questions
are divided into two articles each, the first article dealing with God in his essential
attributes, and the second with the distinction of the Persons. The final and eighth
question of the work does not distinguish these two aspects of the doctrine separately.

43
Disputed Questions, Q. 1, A. 2 [130].
44
Emphasis added. Bonaventure, Disputed Questions, Q. 1, A. 2 [p. 131].
45
Bonaventure, Breviloquium., Part 1, chap 2. 3 [p.30-1]

11
Instead it brings the essential attribute of primacy and personal properties together as
a distinct synthesis. The Christian doctrines of the Trinity and non-eternity and non-
necessity of Creation are all expressed sympathetically in terms of the resources of
thirteenth century philosophy: the Aristotelian principle of the two modes of
procession by way of nature and will and the neo-Platonic emanation of the One (the
threefold perfection, fontality and fecundity in the one God). So the Father is
described as the original fontal principle of the common fontality of both Trinitarian
inner, necessary life and God’s temporal, creative action. Such a view emphasizes the
single origin of both theology and philosophy, faith and reason. The plurality of the
Trinitarian Persons remains underivable by means of reason alone, but the articulation
of the Dionysian and Victorine self-diffusive goodness and charity in God as
supremely communicable is a flowering of the seed of reason in the light of
revelation’s gift. If for Bonaventure created reality is not properly intelligible without
the philosopher being informed by theological understanding, then, as Gregory
LaNave put it, “created reality is intelligible not in terms of the divine work ad extra,
but in terms of the law of God’s very being. Because God is supremely self-
communicative within himself, the world is intelligible. The logic of the Trinity is the
explanation of being itself. The Word is the basis for all that is.”46

St Thomas Aquinas and Philosophical Trinitarianism

Like Bonaventure, St. Thomas Aquinas held that it is impossible to attain knowledge
of the Triune God by natural reason. Perfect knowledge of “the unity and trinity of the
one God” can only occur “in the life to come” through divine grace and not by
47
anything due to our nature. Nevertheless, incomprehension does not entail
unintelligibility. Faith provides the presuppositions needed to acquire knowledge of
the Trinity “at the beginning of our belief,” just as the beginner in natural science also
needs to believe certain principles on the authority of a teacher.48 For Thomas, we
study the Church’s Trinitarian doctrine without the presumption of understanding it,
in order to defend the faith against error, and to show that belief in the Trinity is

46
Gregory LaNave, “God, Creation, and the Possibility of Philosophical Wisdom: The
Perspectives of Bonaventure and Aquinas,” Theological Studies 69 (2008), 823.
47
Aquinas, In Boeth. de Trin., Q. 3, A. 1, reply [p. 67].
48
Aquinas, In Boeth. de Trin., Q. 2, A. 2, ad. 5 [p. 44].

12
reasonably thinkable.49 That there can be no necessary reasons to demonstrate or
prove matters of faith also means no arguments against the faith are compelling. It is
possible, albeit difficult, to attain to the knowledge of God’s existence without the aid
of faith, though entirely impossible to know the Triune God by reason alone.

The structure of Thomas’ analysis of God reflects a faith-based, Christian philosophy


informed by that which reason could not possibly know without the divine
transformation of nature and reason in the ascent of a return (reditus) to God.
Aquinas discusses what is common in God, that is, the essential divine attributes (de
deo uno) and then moves on to what is proper, the Trinitarian processions (de deo
trino). The relationship between God and creation is one of the important fruits of the
framework of exitus and reditus, especially in the Summa theologiae. This conceptual
relationship between the one divine essence and the three divine persons forms a
consistent and lucid pattern, contributing to an intricate and innovative synthesis of
the Church’s ancient teaching with the resources of reason and philosophy. Not less
important is Thomas’ study of the Trinitarian dogma in one of his early (though
incomplete) works, the Expositio of Boethius’ De Trinitate.50

Here he expresses that which human reason is capable of knowing, i.e., that God
exists, but that it is incapable of grasping God’s essence. We can know that God exists
as First Cause and as Being itself. Creatures lead to an analogical knowledge of their
Creator as effects lead to their cause. For “human reason in the development of its
natural knowledge must advance from things that are posterior to those that are prior,
and from creatures to God.”51 Through the light of natural reason obtained through
the senses, the mind can grasp that he is one, that his essential attributes are
simplicity, perfection, goodness, infinity, immutability, eternity, and unity.52 Here we
see that natural reason can only reduce created effects to a single principle or cause.
Therefore, according to Thomas, the power of creation ex nihilo is common to the one
Divine Essence rather than proper to the Persons. Because divine creative causality
49
De potentia, Q. 9, A. 5 [p. 254]. Thomas says that such rational enquiry is not useless,
“since it raises the spirit to capture the part of truth sufficient to exclude errors.” See also
Gilles Emery, Trinity in Aquinas (Ave Maria University: Sapientia Press, 2006), 127.
50
Douglas C. Hall, The Trinity: An Analysis of St. Thomas Aquinas’ Expositio of the De
Trinitate of Boethius, (Leiden, E.J. Brill, 1992), 43.
51
In Boeth. de trin., Prologue [p.4].
52
Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, part 1a, questions 3-10.

13
belongs to the whole Trinity, it is the Unity only, and therefore not the Trinity of
Persons that may be knowable to us by divine causality.53

Responding to a question in the Expositio, “Can the human mind arrive at a


knowledge of God?” Thomas replies:

God is known only through the form of his effect. Now effects are of two
kinds. One is equal to the power of its cause, and through an effect of this sort the
power––and consequently the essence––of the cause is fully known. The other effect
falls short of the above-mentioned equality, and through such an effect the power of
the agent cannot be fully grasped and consequently neither can its essence: we can
only know that the cause exists (quod est). And so knowledge of the effect functions
as the principle of knowing that a cause exists (an est), as the essence of the cause
itself does when it is known through its form. Now all effects stand in this relation to
God. It follows that in the present life we can only come to know that he exists (quia
est).54

In the first effect by which God is known as Aquinas describes it, we can assume that
the knowledge that is equal to the power of its cause, and known through the form of
its essence, is the Wisdom that proceeds from the Father’s perfect knowledge, the
Word who is of the same nature as the Father. Because God’s essence transcends
every created form, it is unknowable to the finite human mind without participation in
God through the illumination of faith and the gifts of wisdom and understanding, the
strengthening of the creature’s own natural light.55 Thomas concludes further on in
the reply that the creature “is not competent to penetrate to a vision of his essence.”
Reason demonstrates that it cannot know, and in that unknowing reason is said to
transcend it own natural limits, thereby becoming intellect (intellectus), which is a
participation in the divine light of truth.56 If God is hardly known in his essence, how
much less must he be known in the inner, personal life of the relations of knowledge
and will, those powers by which the human intellect apprehends an analogy of the
Trinity within itself, in whose image it is created.

Aquinas’ apophatic understanding of God gives us further reason to argue that it is


impossible to conceive of the Trinity by deriving the doctrine of the plurality of

53
Aquinas, In Boeth. de Trin., Q. 1, A. 4, reply, [p. 32].
54
Aquinas, In Boeth. de Trin., Q. 1, A. 2, reply [p. 21-2].
55
Douglas C. Hall, The Trinity: An Analysis of St. Thomas Aquinas’ Expositio of the De
Trinitate of Boethius, (Leiden, E.J. Brill, 1992), 65.
56
Denys Turner, Faith, Reason and the Existence of God, (Cambridge, CUP: 2004), 84-88.

14
persons from the divine unity and essential attributes. Aquinas’ treatment of the
essential attributes of God is not an account of the One God as distinct from God as
Three. Gilles Emery argues that “this thesis, too little known even today, constitutes
one of the absolutely fundamental traits of St Thomas’s Trinitarian theology.”57 That
God is one and three is a truth that can only be attained through believing the
authority of divine revelation. Nevertheless, “the method used in treating of the
Trinity is twofold, as Augustine says: authority and reason.”58 For the authority of
revelation for Aquinas is not an imposition on human reason. Faith cannot be contrary
to nature. Just as grace does not destroy nature, but rather perfects it, so nature is a
“preamble” to grace and reason the preamble to faith. Both reason and faith are from
God and since “what is imperfect bears a resemblance to what is perfect, what we
know by natural reason has some likeness to what is taught to us by faith.”59 It is
impossible for the light of reason to be contrary to the light of faith, though natural
reason and philosophy fall short of faith and theology. Therefore, a philosophy that
contradicts the contents of faith is simply bad philosophy or the result of faulty
reasoning.60

Relation or Emanation

One of the most important and original insights into the link between Trinitarian faith
and reason in Aquinas is that of the concept of relation in God. Aquinas had adopted
St. Anselm of Canterbury’s rule that “in God all is unity except where there is
opposition of relations,” and made the opposition of relations the principle of
Trinitarian distinction.61 (This contrasts with Bonaventure as representative of the
Franciscan school that would emphasize the Father as ‘fontal plenitude’ and origin of
emanation). Aquinas bases his understanding of relation on Aristotle’s Metaphysics
and this becomes the philosophical key to his systematic treatment of both immanent
Trinitarian theology and the relation of God ad extra, to creation.62 Thomas thus

57
Gilles Emery, Trinity in Aquinas (Ave Maria University: Sapientia Press, 2006), 126.
58
Aquinas, In Boeth. de Trin., Prologue, [p. 5].
59
Aquinas, In Boeth. de Trin., Q. 2, A. 3, reply [p. 48].
60
Aquinas, In Boeth. de trin. Q. 2, A. 3 [p. 49].
61
Russell L. Friedman, The Use of Philosophical Psychology in Trinitarian Theology Among
the Franciscans and Dominicans, 1250-1350, Vol 1 (Leiden: Brill, 2013), 62.
62
Najeeb Awad, “Thomas Aquinas’ Metaphysics of ‘Relation’ and ‘Participation’ and
Contemporary Trinitarian Theology,” New Blackfriars 93 (2012), 656-57.

15
brings together the common essence and the distinction of the three Persons under the
aspect of relation, constituting the notion of ‘subsistent Relations’.63 The three
Persons are identified by the very relations between them, so that there is no real
difference between God’s unity and his plurality except for a conceptual one on our
part.64 In contrast with other scholastic theologians including Bonaventure, for
Thomas, the relations not only manifest the divine hypostases but also distinguish
them.65

Real relations in God can be understood only in regard to those actions according to
which there are internal, and not external processions in God. These processions are
two only, one derived from the action of the intellect, the procession of the Word, and
the other from the action of the will, the procession of love. In respect of these two
processions, two opposite relations arise, one of which is the relation of the Person
proceeding from the principle; the other is the relation of the principle Himself.66

This is an opposition according to relation, e.g., active generation from the Father
(paternity), passive generation of the Son (filiation) and the procession of love from
both by passive spiration, constituting the Holy Spirit.67

Aquinas differs from Bonaventure in the order in which he understands origin and
relation in the procession of the Persons. This has implications for the way in which
we understand the application of philosophy in their respective Trinitarian theologies.
Bonaventure sees origin and emanation in the Father rather than the real relations as
the absolutely primary aspect in which to understand order in God. The real relations
in God are distinctions founded in origin, i.e., the Father is the Father because he
generates and generation is the basis of our speaking about paternity in God the
Father.68 Aquinas would admit this on conceptual grounds only, for it is relation
rather than origin that distinguishes the Persons.69 The Father is Father because of the

63
Gilles Emery, “Threeness and Oneness,” 70.
64
Aquinas, De potentia, Q. 2, A. 6 [p. 34].
65
Aquinas, De potentia, Q. 10, A. 2 [p. 280].
66
Aquinas, Summa theologiae, 1a, Q. 28, A. 4 [p. 154]
67
Russell L. Friedman, Medieval Trinitarian Thought from Aquinas to Ockham (Cambridge:
CUA, 2010), 10. To give modern expression to the scholastic terminology ‘opposition of
relations’ Friedman explains them as “mutually implicative” and “correlative opposites.”
68
Russel L. Friedman, Use of Philosophical Psychology, 70. See Bonaventure, I Sentences, d.
27, p. 1, a. 1, q. 2 [p. 469].
69
Aquinas, De potentia, Q. 8, A. 3 [p. 235]; Q. 10, A. 2 [p. 280-82].

16
relative opposition of paternity and sonship.70 So, the substantial relation of Sonship
constitutes the Son, Fatherhood the Father, and Spiration the Holy Spirit. For the
Father to be unbegotten and to be characterized by the property of innascibility is for
Aquinas a merely negative characteristic simply meaning “not a son.”71 But
Bonaventure, drawing on what he thought was an Aristotelian axiom, “the more prior
a being is, the more it is fecund,” argued that this term also implies an affirmation,
“since unbegottenness posits in the Father a fountain-fullness.”72

Bonaventure’s line of reasoning is well described by Kevin L. Hughes as “a logic of


transformed perception” in contrast with St Thomas Aquinas’ “logic of ordered
relation.”73 And that is the difference between knowledge of things in Christ and
knowledge of things in themselves. Aquinas is known for his ‘common-sense’
approach to reality, as perceived by the senses. Even so, this cannot lead directly to
the knowledge of the Trinity, though by grace and faith in the triune Mystery in its
incomprehensibility but supreme intelligibility, philosophy and reason’s analogies
assist in making the mystery more intelligible.74 Bonaventure would not have
disagreed with Thomas, though he was more inclined to emphasize created things as
patterns analogically reflecting the eternal light given by Exemplaric Word. The
Word is expressive of the Father and the Spirit, and, as Zachary Hayes suggests, is
“the ontological basis for all that is other than the Father, and in it is contained the
basis for all other relation.”75 It is the procession of the Word that is the absolute
centre of the inner dynamic life of the Trinitarian relations. The Word is a middle way
(media) between communicated and communicating, the Son who proceeds from the
Father and sends forth the Holy Spirit, and who both gives and accepts love from

70
Russell L. Friedman, Medieval Trinitarian Thought from Aquinas to Ockham (Cambridge:
CUA, 2010), 22.
71
Aquinas, Summa theologiae, 1a, Q. 33, A. 4, Reply Obj. 1, [p. 176].
72
Bonaventure, Breviloquium, Part 1, chap. 3: 7 [p. 35]. See also 1 Sent., d. 2, a. 1, [p. 53] &
1 Sent., 27, p.1, a. 1, q. 2 [p. 471] The quotation is from the Book of Causes, which is now
ascribed to the fifth century neo-Platonic philosopher, Proclus.
73
Hughes, “Bonaventure Contra Mundum?” 392.
74
see Derek Simon, “Divine Science in Aquinas’ Expositio Super Librum De Trinitate:
Trinitarian Apophatic Theology and the Transformation of Metaphysics,” Science et Espirit,
L/2 (1998), 151.
75
Bonaventure, In hexaemeron, 9. 2; Hayes, “Christology & Metaphysics,” 90.

17
both.76 Whereas intra-Trinitarian relation in Aquinas is the cause, the reason and the
exemplar of distinction in creatures, for Bonaventure the focus is on the Word who is
expressive of all that God has created.77 The Father’s fountain-fullness or fontality is
at the origin of the common fontality of the Trinity as the principle of creation. Just as
for Aquinas the real relations are the reason and cause of created existence, so for
Bonaventure the primacy and fontality of the Father as origin of the Son and Holy
Spirit is the overriding logic in our thinking about the production of creatures.78

Aquinas therefore seeks knowledge of the Trinity as the proper methodology for
getting the doctrine of creation right. We understand creation in terms of God
precisely as uncreated, and not God in terms of creation. By making the distinction
between uncreated and created he speaks of all things either in terms of God or as
relative to him as their origin and end.79 The processions within God are then seen as
the cause of every other procession outside of God. Distinction in God produces a
creation of distinct realities, hence the plurality, diversity and multitude within
creation is an exemplum of distinction within unity. Trinitarian faith illuminates
natural plurality within creation. “Plurality is not a falling away from unity, but rather
a participation in the fullness of Trinitarian life.”80 By making the distinction between
uncreated and created Aquinas does not separate God from creation, but rather,
Trinitarian theology is wedded to creation, and by the same token so is created reason,
which is no less than a share in the supreme Wisdom of God.

With this outlook we can account for something of the distinctive rationales of
Thomas’ and Bonaventure’s Trinitarian philosophies. Though the doctrine held on
faith is an unfathomable Mystery, it is nonetheless supremely intelligible. For on the
Thomist view human reason is a participation in God’s very own self-understanding,
76
Quae dat et accipit, in qua est amor permixtus ex utroque. Bonaventure, 1 Sent., d. 2, a. 1,
q. 4, resp. [p. 57]. Cf. Hayes, “Christology and Metaphysics,” The Journal of Religion,
Supplement 58 (1978), 89.
77
Gilles, “Threeness and Oneness,” 72.
78
St Thomas says, “The processions of the divine Persons are the cause of creation...”
(S.T.,1a, Q. 45 A. 6 ad 1) and Bonaventure: “God the Father through the Son and with the
Holy Spirit is the principle of everything created; for if He did not produce them eternally, He
could not produce through anything in time.” Bonaventure, Disputed Questions, Q VIII, ad 7
[p. 266]
79
Emery, Trinity in Aquinas, 131-32.
80
Gilles Emery, The Trinitarian Theology of St Thomas Aquinas, translated by Francesca
Aran Murphy (Oxford: OUP, 2007), 357.

18
and in Bonaventure the one divine essence can be conceived in a light which itself
cannot be seen. There is an intrinsic complementarity in these distinct approaches to
the Trinity that have their source in supreme Unity. The work of Aquinas and
Bonaventure is an old but unsurpassed example of the serious engagement with
intellectually demanding problems that confront the thinking believer. Scripture and
tradition lay at the heart of both theologians, but contrary to the presuppositions of
much of post-Kantian thought, Aquinas and Bonaventure were not fumbling in an
irrational subservience to an imposed authority. Their Trinitarian theology
demonstrates that they did not preclude the new insights that arose outside of
Christian revelation, but embraced them in order to shed light on what they already
took to be true. Their reasoning might be depicted as incredible, but it was neither
unreasonable nor unintelligible, and few have dared to expand on reason’s capacity
with the lucidity of Aquinas and the readiness of Bonaventure. These Scholastics
intuited a Trinitarian structure to the universe because they believed, but this was far
from closed in on itself. It was critically open to the best reason and contemporary
learning had to offer. They are the historical foundations for the insights of today and
the history of thought is the ladder on which we too stand.

‡AΩ‡

Bibliography

Primary Sources

Aquinas, Thomas, St. Faith, Reason and Theology. Mediaeval Sources In Translation
32. Translated by Armand Maurer. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies,
1987.

–––––. The Power of God. Translated by Richard J. Regan. Oxford: OUP, 2012.

–––––. Summa Theologica. Translated the Fathers of the English Dominican


Province. Westminster, Maryland: Christian Classics, 1981.

Bonaventure, St. Commentaries on the First & Second Books of the Sentences of
Master Peter Lombard. Translated by Alexis Bugnolo. CD Edition. Published by The
Franciscan Archive with footnotes and scholia, 2007 & 2010.

19
––––––. Disputed Questions on the Mystery of the Trinity. Works of St. Bonaventure,
Vol III. Translated and introduced by Zachary Hayes. Saint Bonaventure, N.Y.: The
Franciscan Institute, 2000.

–––––. Breviloquium. Translated by Dominic V. Monti (Saint Bonaventure, N.Y.:


Franciscan Institute Publications, 2005).

–––––. The Journey of the Mind to God, translated by Philotheus Boehner; edited,
with Introduction and Notes by Stephen F. Brown (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing
Company, 1993).

–––––. Collations on the Six Days, The Works of Bonaventure Vol. V, translated by
José de Vinck (Paterson, N.J.: St. Anthony Guild Press, 1970). Hereafter referred to
as In hexaemeron.

Secondary Sources

Awad, Najeeb. “Thomas Aquinas’ Metaphysics of ‘Relation’ and ‘Participation’ and


Contemporary Trinitarian Theology.” New Blackfriars 93 (2012): 652-670.

Cullen, Christopher. Bonaventure. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.

Emery, Gilles. “The Threeness and Oneness of God in Twelfth- to Fourteenth-


Century Scholasticism.” Nova et Vetera English Edition 1 (2003): 43-74.

––––––. Trinity in Aquinas. Ave Maria University: Sapientia Press, 2006.

––––––. The Trinitarian Theology of St Thomas Aquinas. Translated by Francesca


Aran Murphy. Oxford: OUP, 2007.

Friedman, Russell L. Medieval Trinitarian Thought from Aquinas to Ockham.


Cambridge: CUA, 2010.

––––––. The Use of Philosophical Psychology in Trinitarian Theology Among the


Franciscans and Dominicans, 1250-1350. Leiden: Brill, 2013.

Hall, Douglas C. The Trinity: An Analysis of St. Thomas Aquinas’ Expositio of the De
Trinitate of Boethius, (Leiden, E.J. Brill, 1992).

Hayes, Zachary. “Christology and Metaphysics in the Thought of Bonaventure.” The


Journal of Religion Supplement 58 (1978): 82-96.

Hughes, Kevin L. “Bonaventure Contra Mundum? The Catholic Theological


Tradition Revisited.” Theological Studies 74 (2013): 372-398.

20
Johnson, Timothy J. “Reading between the lines: Apophatic knowledge and Naming
the Divine in Bonaventure’s Book of Creation.” Franciscan Studies 60 (2002): 139-
158.

Simon, Derek. “Divine Science in Aquinas’ Expositio Super Librum De Trinitate:


Trinitarian Apophatic Theology and the Transformation of Metaphysics.” Science et
Espirit, L/2 (1998): 127-153.

Speer, Andreas. “Bonaventure and the Question of a Medieval Philosophy.” Medieval


Philosophy and Theology 6 (1997): 25-46.

Te Velde, Rudi. Aquinas on God: The ‘Divine Science’ of the Summa Theologiae.
Aldershot: Ashgate, 2006.

Turner, Denys. Faith, Reason and the Existence of God. Cambridge: CUP, 2004.

21

Potrebbero piacerti anche