Sei sulla pagina 1di 15

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 11/24/11, NEWGEN

PA RT
7
Emergence of Culture

30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 647 11/24/2011 2:12:39 PM


30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 648 11/24/2011 2:12:41 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 11/24/11, NEWGEN

C HA P TE R

Roots of Culture in the Umwelt


29
Riin Magnus and Kalevi Kull

Abstract
This chapter begins by introducing the background, basic constituents and principles of the umwelt model
and theory developed by the Baltic German biologist Jakob von Uexküll (1864–1944) in the first decades
of the twentieth century. This is followed by a discussion of the features of the umwelt concept that
has provided the impetus for interpretations of human activities and cultural processes. The once
biology-bound model has by now found its way into very diverse traditions of thought. We concentrate
on four major trends in interpreting cultural phenomena with the help of umwelt theory: (1) the
Uexküllian functional circle model of perception and action as a predecessor of models that couple
human forms of impression and expression; (2) the mediated versus immediate character of human in
contrast with animal worlds; (3) the bridging of natural and cultural phenomena via semiotic processes;
(4) the integration of the cognitive and the social interpretations of (human) mind via two facets of
umwelt. The chapter includes some hints on the aspects of the umwelt model that could be elaborated
further in the analysis of culture.
Keywords: functional circle, impression and expression, modeling systems, semiosphere, Uexküll,
umwelt

Culture, Semiosphere, Umwelt interweaving in a common semiotic space is named


According to the semiotician and culturolo- the semiosphere (Lotman 2005).
gist Juri Lotman, cultures have a structure that is The semiosphere is a necessary medium for all
analogous to individual human minds in several sign processes as well as the totality of sign processes
of its fundamental features. In some of their gen- itself. Like the biosphere, which is the organic totality
eral structural aspects, as well as in some rules of of living matter as well as the precondition for the
their dynamics, these complex semiotic systems are persistence of life, the semiosphere is the result as well
isomorphic to each other (Lotman, 1984,1990). as the precondition for the development of culture
Both a culture and an individual world are fields (Lotman, 2000, p. 125). Departing from Thomas
of sign processes. Both entail many codes, several A. Sebeok’s (1920–2001) thesis, according to which
sign systems, translation processes, heterogeneity, the origin of semiosis (sign process) coincides with
asymmetry, borders, center, and periphery, continu- the origin of life, we can assume that sign processes
ity and discreetness, unpredictability, and a certain (as the basis of recognition, discrimination, signifi-
processual logic. Both are embedded and molded cation) characterize human minds as well as animal
by communication and dialogue, which are primary minds. We can therefore describe the semiosphere
in respect with individual languages. The general of the worlds of organisms, all living organisms
model Lotman proposed for describing personali- included. This is how the concept of semiosphere
ties, texts, and cultures as semiotic systems and their is used in contemporary biosemiotics—the branch

649

30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 649 11/24/2011 2:12:41 PM


OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 11/24/11, NEWGEN

of semiotics dealing with the organic part of the food and the destroyer of food, enemy and prey, and
semiosphere (Cobley, 2010; Hoffmeyer, 2008). above all, male and female in astonishing variations.
A predecessor of such a semiotic view in biology
That semiosic systems are simultaneously
was the Baltic German biologist Jakob von Uexküll
modeling systems was also emphasized in the 1960s
(1864–1944) with his concept of umwelt. Umwelt
by the Tartu-Moscow School of semiotics (Lotman,
is the world an organism creates, in which it lives. It
1967; Levchenko & Salupere 1999; Kull, 2010a).
is the meaningful world based on sign relations. A
Here modeling systems (which encompassed
quite common definition states that umwelt is the
languages as well as arts) were understood as the
personal world of an organism, or a self-centered
structure of elements and the rules of their com-
world, “the world as known or modelled” (Cobley,
bination that stood in an analogical relationship to
2010,p. 348). This definition, although correct
some object of cognition (Lotman, 1967, p. 130).
in itself, may not emphasize the relational aspect
Modeling systems provide the means for com-
of the umwelt concept enough. Therefore we can
prehending the outside world and yet, they are
also complementarily define umwelt as a set of sign
themselves the primary sources of world formation.
relations an organism has in an ecosystem (as in a
Connecting the ideas of Jakob von Uexküll and
semiosphere) (Kull, 2010b).
Juri Lotman, we could also say that culture is contin-
Thus, if umwelt is made of relations, of semiosic
uously created via human umwelt making. Cultural
bonds, we can conclude that organisms are deriva-
modeling as umwelt making includes all of the
tives of (sign) relations. Umwelt (as a relational, i.e.,
building, shaping, and design humans do in their
a meaningful world) exists even prior to the capacity
surroundings (i.e., besides “texts” in a narrow sense,
to use representations, since organisms can often be
also clothes, tools, technologies, architecture, and
involved in sign processes without building repre-
landscape). The umwelt-based semiotic approach to
sentations. Conversely, of course, there cannot be
culture may further widen the understanding of the
an umwelt without life. Life is centered on orga-
borders of culture by including semiosic processes
nisms, in their agency; therefore, umwelten are also
of an ecosystem into a single whole with human
individual and individualized.
culture proper. This means widening the basis of
All organisms participate in the construction
culture from language to semiosis.
of their umwelten. Organisms participate in
A semiotic interpretation, to which we will come
making their umwelten because this is generally a
back later, is just one way of linking the idea of umwelt
communication (including autocommunication)
with culture-specific constructions. In order to bring
process that modifies and constructs umwelten.
forth the variety of those links, we will further sketch
Building and modifying one’s umwelt is simulta-
the chief impetuses the umwelt idea has provided for
neously a communicative process and a modeling
interpretations of human activities and cultural pro-
process.
cesses. We shall demonstrate how different interpreta-
As Thomas Sebeok has pointed out regarding
tions of the umwelt concept allow the integration of
the scientific use of the term “umwelt,” “the closest
otherwise contradictory approaches to culture.
equivalent in English is manifestly “model”“
(Sebeok, 2001, p. 75). The description of a particular
Jakob von Uexküll’s Umwelt Model and Its
umwelt will mean the demonstration of how the
Constituents
organism maps the world, and what, for that orga-
Although the common German word “umwelt”
nism, the meanings of the objects are within it. How
is traditionally translated into English as “environ-
the formation of individual worlds entails meaning-
ment,” its use as a loanword refers to the specific
ful operations was likewise described by Jakob von
concept worked out by Jakob von Uexküll in the
Uexküll in his Theory of Meaning (Bedeutungslehre)
first decades of the twentieth century.1
(Uexküll, 1982 [1940], pp. 64, 69):
Umwelt is the world as accessed and formed
Meaning in nature’s score serves as a connecting link, by the organism via its specific sensory and motor
or rather as a bridge, and takes the place of harmony devices. The section of reality that a biologist should
in a musical score; it joins two of nature’s factors. [ . . . ] describe, according to Uexküll, is thus of the organ-
Each meaning-carrier was always confronted with ism’s own making. In other words, umwelt is the set
a meaning-receiver, even in [ . . . ] earlier umwelten. of perceptual and action-based distinctions, shared
Meaning ruled them all. Meaning tied changing in a large extent by the members of one species and
organs to a changing medium. Meaning connected described by an external observer.

650 roots of culture in the umwelt

30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 650 11/24/2011 2:12:41 PM


OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 11/24/11, NEWGEN

Umwelt as the world of meaningful objects, is When in contact with some object, a particular
always paired by its intraorganismic counterpart— perceptual sign (e.g., a sweet taste) is first received
Innenwelt (inner world). If umwelt denotes the by the organism and then projected to the outside
outside world as it appears to the animal via its world as a perceptual cue of that object (the sweet-
perceptual and motor apparatus, then Innenwelt ness of a fruit). The complex of the perceptual sign
refers to the experience side of the phenomena as and perceptual cue further induces the formation
experienced by the organism. However, the organ- of an effector sign. The effector sign is the image of
ism never feels itself as such. What is felt is some the action that is to be carried out in respect with
object of the umwelt, which indirectly refers to the the object (e.g., biting the fruit). Like the percep-
subjective center of world formation via the mean- tual sign, also the effector sign is projected outside
ing it carries to the animal. It is also the external as a cue or property of the object (the “bitability” of
object that serves as a ground for the species-specific the fruit). If the necessary action is accomplished,
coordination between the perceptual and motor a new perceptual sign can emerge and a new circle
apparatus. “Just like the factors of umwelt are will begin. The circles of perception and action fol-
objective, also the effects that they bring about in low one another until the need that initiated them
the nervous system have to be treated in the same has been satisfied (e.g., until the animal has satisfied
manner. These effects are also organized and regu- its hunger).
lated by the building plan. They together form the The model can also be seen as a hybrid of reflex
Innenwelt of the animal”2 (Uexküll, 1909, p. 6). arc schemes from biology and later communica-
The overarching principle that binds umwelt with tion models. At first glance, the Innenwelt part of
Innenwelt is mentioned here as Bauplan (building Uexküll’s model could be interpreted as a unifica-
plan)–—the specific anatomical and physiologi- tion of the afferent and efferent pathways of the
cal structure of the animal. The Bauplan concept reflex arc. The perceptual and motor cues, in turn,
encompasses both the developmental pathways of could be termed as equivalents of stimuli, initia-
the organism as well as the functional aspect of the tors of irritation. As a remarkable difference from
organism’s perceptions and actions. Although the the reflex arc scheme, linear logic models do not
focus for this umwelt concept is on the operation of work here. The explanation needed is therefore
sense organs and motor systems, when the forma- closer to the one used by complex systems theory,
tion of the umwelt is described, these systems are where downward and upward causation have to be
always to be seen as embedded in the totality of the accounted for simultaneously (see Gilbert & Sarkar,
organism itself. The key elements and characteristics 2000). Incorporating all elements of the functional
of the umwelt formation process were modeled by circle under the word welt denotes that the depar-
Uexküll as a schema, which he called a functional ture point for the observer of the animal’s behavior
circle (Funktionskreis) (see an adaptation of Uexküll’s should be the whole set of meanings with all the
schema in Figure 29.1). characteristic relationships between them just as
well as particular acts of perception and action.
Individual causes and effects, and the extraction of
single stimulus and response pairs, can be derived
only from an already understood set of possible
meanings, but the world-formation is itself observ-
Perceptual sign Perceptual cue able and accessible only via the individual acts. We
will return to this principle of part-whole mutual
Subject Object conditioning when describing the Romantic
philosophical roots of Uexküll’s umwelt theory.
Effector sign Effector cue Comparing the functional circle model with
classical models of communication3, may allow us
to see the subject as both a sender of messages about
its physiological state to the outside world and as a
receiver of responses to those states by the object-as-
Innenwelt Umwelt a-sender. However, the functional circle model does
not articulate the difference between the active and
Figure 29.1 An adaptation of Jakob von Uexküll’s functional passive object in the process. It does not therefore
circle model.

magnus, kull 651

30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 651 11/24/2011 2:12:41 PM


OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 11/24/11, NEWGEN

permit a distinction between the acts of perception psychology and philosophy (esp. pragmatism) (cf.
and communication. Phillips, 1971; Bredo, 1998).
John Dewey’s 1896 article “The reflex arc con-
From Reflections to Coordination: How the cept in psychology” identified the persistence of two
Umwelt Concept Emerged kinds of older dualisms in the dominant models of
In order to track the road from umwelt to cul- the reflex arc: (1) the dualism between sensation and
ture and to explain how some principles of cultural idea—as being repeated in the dualism of peripheral
existence are to be viewed if umwelt is seen as their and central structures, and (2) the dualism of body
predecessor, we need to visualize the road leading to and soul—as still present in the dualism of stimulus
the basic model of umwelt theory itself. Jakob von and response (Dewey, 1896). Dewey argued against
Uexküll started his career by researching the physi- the separation of stimulus-response as two distinct
ology of marine invertebrates. While working in the physical absolutes, tied to sensation and reaction
physiology laboratories in Heidelberg and Naples, respectively.
he concentrated on the muscular movements of
What shall we term that which is not sensation-
sea urchins, brittle stars, octopuses, etc. (cf. Rüting
followed-by-movement, but which is primary;
2004, p. 39; Mildenberger, 2007). It is exactly here
which is, as it were, the psychical organism of which
that the empirical grounds of the developed umwelt
sensation, idea and movement are the chief organs?
theory are to be found: in those early works on
Stated on the physiological side, this reality may most
muscular tonus accompanied by research on reflex
conveniently be termed coordination.
movements and the nearly 200 years of debate about
(Dewey, 1972 [1896], p. 97)
the exact mechanisms behind them.
The eighteenth-century explanations of invol- Coordination is always present in each act of sen-
untary movement that preceded the nineteenth- sation or reaction as an “ideal” from which the two
century reflex concept, exhibited disagreements have deviated as conflicting parties and try to regain
on several grounds. One set of disagreements con- the initial state of coordination. Coordination is
cerned the (in)applicability of optical theories of thus presented by Dewey as a process whereby the
reflection to the biological relations of irritation dynamic stability of the organism is achieved.
and movement. Georges Canguilhem has dem- Jakob von Uexküll and his colleagues Theodor
onstrated how the period encountered on the one Beer and Albert Bethe published in 1899 an article
hand convictions that the irritation-movement pair where they suggest a new objective nomenclature
functions according to the mirror law.4 According for physiology. In the article they claim that physi-
to this principle, the texture of the medulla serves ology should be purified from the ambiguous terms
as a “mirror” upon which the incident irritation like “light” or “sound” and terms indicating the
falls and reflects back to the motor nerves. Those physical origin and properties of objective stimuli
claims were countered by authors (e.g., George should be used instead (Beer, Bethe, & Uexküll,
Prochaska and Robert Whytt) who denied the suf- 1899). Here they seem to identify themselves with
ficiency of optical parallels for explaining medullar the tradition of a physics-bound physiology rather
mediation of irritation and movement and who than with the more organism-specific perspective.
asked for the formulation of specific biological laws Solely because of the position presented in this arti-
in order to clarify the issue (Canguilhem, 1994, pp. cle, Uexküll’s research was received as a representa-
179–202). tive of the mechanistic-behaviorist physiology, even
Several classical models of a reflex arc in the in his later career when he distanced himself from
second half of the nineteenth century followed the his earlier theoretical grounds (see Mildenberger,
physicalist line of thought while explaining the 2006; Mildenberger, 2007, p. 58).
organism as a thing among things, comparable to Closer examination reveals that even this objec-
a physical body by which the same impulses always tivist manifesto already contains ontological threads
result in the same reaction. Reflex arc models, leading to the later umweltlehre. What is lacking in
which depicted the nervous system as a mecha- the latter and saliently present in the manifesto is
nism of simple motion transfer (cf. Bains, 2006, a significant discrepancy between the ontological
p. 61), received significant criticism already at the and the epistemological standpoints. While propos-
time of their wider distribution. The earlier critical ing a new nomenclature for sensory physiology, the
fronts came not just from physiology, but also from authors differentiate between the objective stimulus,

652 roots of culture in the umwelt

30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 652 11/24/2011 2:12:41 PM


OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 11/24/11, NEWGEN

the physiological proceeding, and the eventual sen- superimposition of one of the systems on the other.
sation. The footnote to the objective stimulus, how- On the contrary, the central concept for describing
ever, states: these relations is punctus contra punctum—they have
to match like two notes in a chord. The principle
We admit that the stimulus is nothing but an
of responsive, counterpoint-like correspondence is
objectified sensation, but we stay by the conviction
central for understanding how it is possible to pro-
that natural scientists, in order to retain a stable
ceed from the perceptual systems to the commu-
ground, should take an unbiased standpoint, from
nicative, dialogical ones. This key factor also opens
where one could observe the outwards projected
up the possibility for umwelt-based research to serve
Erscheinungswelt5 as materially present. (Beer, Bethe,
not just as a descriptive system, but also as a tool for
& Uexküll, 1899, p. 517)
understanding. The animal in this case is not merely
The new nomenclature is therefore suggested an object of scientific observation but a response
because of merely heuristic reasons; the authors to the research question posed by the researcher’s
attempt to deny asserting any reality to the objec- own perceptual and cognitive schemes. Partaking
tive stimulus. Uexküll’s later writing on umweltlehre in the communicative act provides the researcher
resolved this former discrepancy by adjusting the with as much knowledge about his own mind as it
theoretical framework according to his ontological does about the communicatively observed animal.
axioms. And the more conscious one becomes of one’s own
How could such a step be taken? What enabled perceptual restrictions, clarifying thus the structure
the initially self-determined scientific methodology of one’s own research tools, the more the under-
to be attuned to the “demands” of biological standing of the other will correspond to the features
reality? of the other. Scientific truth in this case does not
Above all, this leap in Uexküll’s ontological com- need to choose sides between idealistic or realistic
mitments is caused by the synthesis of philosophical premises—it is formed only while participating in
and scientific standpoints. The philosophical per- the mutual exchange of information, where the
spective, traditionally bracketed out from strictly object explicates the subject’s characteristics and
scientific investigations, was brought in to take part vice versa.
in the explorations of the living world. Only through
the coordination and integration of ideas belonging Umwelt Theory as a Springboard for Models
to different realms of human knowledge (either of Culture
to scientific, philosophical, or artistic) could orga- Uexküll himself did not provide significant
nisms be understood as entities who themselves base reflections on how his umwelt theory could be
their existence on coordination and integration.6 applied particularly to human beings (setting aside
This synthetic understanding of human knowl- his constant reminder that all researchers are bound
edge, which formed the epistemological founda- with their own perceptual boundaries, even when
tion of the umwelt idea, was the legacy of Romantic talking about the umwelt of another species, and
theories of human mind. First, it followed the his rather loose transfer of the umwelt concept to
Romantic ideals of the entwined architectonics of describe the characters of his friends). But Uexküll’s
human comprehension. Secondly, it considered the writings on the umwelt concept have served as an
principle of the isomorphic relations between the impetus for later philosophers and representatives of
object and the tools of research. Goethe figuratively other humanities to delve on the issue of its applica-
expressed the latter in the introduction to his Colour bility to human beings.
Theory (Zur Farbenlehre), quoted also by Uexküll: For the sake of conciseness, we are not aiming at
“If the eye were not sun-like, it could never behold describing all directions of influence, as the idea has
the sun. If the sun were not eye-like, it could not found its way into very diverse traditions of thought
shine in any sky,”7 and in his statement that “simi- (for overviews see Kull, 2001; Mildenberger, 2007; on
lar can be recognized only by a similar” (nur von the additional aspects, see Berthoz & Christen, 2009;
Gleichem werde Gleiches erkannt) (Goethe, 1810, Chang, 2009; Kliková & Kleisner, 2006; Magnus,
p. xxxviii). The structural principles of the object 2008). We therefore focus on four kinds of topics
and the descriptive system have to match with each in umwelt theory that have triggered discussions
other. Such matching and likeness of the observer on the question of specifically human umwelten:
and the observed does not require an overlap or (1) the perception-action pairing as a fundamental

magnus, kull 653

30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 653 11/24/2011 2:12:41 PM


OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 11/24/11, NEWGEN

property of “being alive” and as a source for the fur- activities of an organism, rely on the encoded differ-
ther developments of human-specific impressions ence between its perception and action, impression
and expressions; (2) the immediacy vs. mediated- and expression. The latter principle—the necessity
ness of animal and human action; (3) the semiotic of twofold activities for the preservation of complex
embeddedness of all living beings, which leads to phenomena or forms—is a topic that has provided
the view of life as the primary threshold of semiotic common discussion ground for the philosophy
activity; (4) the integration of the perspective of the of biology on the one hand and phenomenology
subject and the perspective of the system. of perception and philosophy of art on the other.
One of the central authors uniting those two fields
The Principle of Counterpoints: is Maurice Merleau-Ponty who also found a strong
Relating Impression with Expression impetus from Uexküll’s umwelt theory, particularly
Let us first examine the first of those four—to for his courses on nature held at the Collège de
what extent is the basic model of the functional cir- France from 1956 to 1958.
cle applicable to human sensations and expressions? Merleau-Ponty’s idea about the compulsory two-
According to Uexküll, all objects enter the animal’s fold nature of the body as a perceiver and as per-
umwelt via their perceptual as well as effector cues ceived can be summed up with his central motive of
by inducing clearly distinguished perceptual and the “double sensation,” when my one hand touches
effector responses. Such a twofold process of receiv- my other hand (see Merleau-Ponty, 2002 [1945], p.
ing information followed by returning it reworked 106, 1968 [1964], p. 141, 2003 [1995], pp. 74–75).
in an organism-specific form is characteristic for all It explains how one and the same body serves as a
living beings. Although there is a long evolution- ground for acting and being acted upon and yet can
ary distance between the recognitions carried out never be in the two positions simultaneously. This
by the cellular receptor proteins and signaling mol- temporal hiatus between the always reversible states
ecules (as perception), and corresponding genetic of touching and being touched, seeing and being
expressions, metabolic changes, or apoptotic beha- visible, as Merleau-Ponty explains, does not result
vior (as effects), and the orientation of vertebrates in an ontological void between the two states, but
via highly differentiated sense organs (as receptors) “is spanned by the total being of my body, and by
and the limbic system (as effectors), both systems that of the world, it is the zero of pressure between
involve the establishment of a coded correspon- two solids that makes them adhere to one another”
dence between the receptor and effector activities as (Merleau-Ponty, 1968 [1964], p. 148). Merleau-
their basis. This does not amount to stating that the Ponty further postulated that the principle of
same impulse always results in the same response. reversibility does not reside just in one’s own body,
The organism with its specific form and current but also among different organisms, which he des-
physiological state serves as a translation matrix that ignated with the word intercorporeity. By perceiving
uses the correspondence between the perceptual we thus also perceive the others as perceiving, as far
and the motor systems in order to preserve its own as sensibility is unbound from its belonging to one
organic form with each object-oriented functional and the same consciousness. This sort of a possibil-
circle. The coded duality of perception and action is ity for the perception of the other as a perceiving
simply a device via which the organism encounters subject is absent in the Uexküllian umwelt model.
meanings essential for its specific form of existence. Here, the reversibility of umwelt and Innenwelt, of
Interpreting the organism as a translational matrix the perceived objects and the perceiving subject, is
means that it provides an interpretational frame- not possible, as the subject’s identity is solely based
work, in which all perceived objects are approached on the specific contacts with the objects as counter-
as actionable and actioned objects as perceivable. structures. All objects in the world of an animal
We may thus infer from this that the specific are directed toward its own existence; there is no
linkage between what the organism perceives about object for another. Uexküll thereby remained true
the environment and how it responds can be formed to the Kantian treatment of the subject, where “I
only via a common meaningful framework between can grasp the unity of the I only through its pro-
the two. Further, it is important to note that once ductions” (Merleau-Ponty, 2003 [1995], p. 22). In
such a relation has been established, its functioning the Uexküllian approach, there is a correspondence
becomes a necessity for preserving the meaningful between the different umwelten, but it is not caused
framework itself. Thus the particular form, as well as by the subject’s perception of the other as a subject

654 roots of culture in the umwelt

30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 654 11/24/2011 2:12:41 PM


OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 11/24/11, NEWGEN

and an object simultaneously, but it is caused by a prior to feeling adhered perception to action, feeling
general, supra-subjective plan of nature. then becomes attached to its reverse in the form of
The function of presenting oneself as a perceiv- expression. This kind of a “felt life” unites and serves
able object can be elaborated by special organs as a foundation both for biological expressions such
which exteriorize the organism in the same manner as gestures, postures, etc., as well as for artistic pre-
as the sense organs interiorize the world. This is sentational symbols (see Weber, 2002). The latter
the manner in which the Swiss zoologist Adolf are distinguished from discursive symbols, as they
Portmann discussed the function of the skin and express not merely ideas, providing access to the
other body surfaces as phenomena that have devel- more basic levels of organic existence.
oped with the potential of being perceived by Biological expressions as well as presentational
someone else (Portmann, 1990; cf. Kleisner, 2008). symbols both express a certain significance and value
Firstly, the merely physiological function of several that impressions have for the particular form of life.
morphological traits has been enriched with a com- By filtering and sorting out only those bits of infor-
municative function during evolution. The hair and mation that are meaningful for the particular living
plumage of warm-blooded animals became organs being, the peripheral organs already act toward the
of communication besides their initial role of fix- preservation of the form of which they constitute a
ing stable body temperature; the skin’s capillary part. Langer (1988 [1972], p. 55) has noted:
network intensifies the color of the skin and thus
[ . . . ] The primary characteristics which animals see
serves as a sign for the psychosomatic state of the
are values, and all the qualities of form, color, shape,
animal (Portmann, 1961, pp. 77–97). Secondly,
sound, warmth, and even smell, by which we would
there are multiple examples of morphological
naturally expect them to recognize things, enter into
features that have never served any specific physio-
their perceptual acts only as they enter into their
logical function for the organism at all and to which
overt behaviour as values for action.
Portmann attributes the role of the “self-expression/
or presentation” of the organism. Those traits may Susanne Langer’s philosophy of presentational forms
also attain a communicative function in the course highlights the role of perception in opening up the
of time, as is the case with some color patterns world for signs, taking sense-data as receptacles of
that acquire a mimetic value or begin to operate as meaning (Langer, 1956 [1942]). “Eyes that did not
warning signals. see forms could never furnish it [the human mind]
Yet another variation on the topic of the antici- with images; ears that did not hear articulated
pation of action in perception (and vice versa) as a sounds could never open it to words” (Langer, 1956
binding phenomenon of humans and other living [1942], p. 73). However, in the Uexküllian umwelt,
beings is provided by the American philosopher of the meanings occur always together with forms. As
art, Susanne Langer. Like Merleau-Ponty, Langer far as all forms are functional and function is based
turned to biophilosophical questions in her later on meaning, there is no before or after the meaning,
works while also integrating critical accounts of the as those categories are already abstractions unattain-
umwelt theory (Langer, 1986 [1967]). The central able to the animal itself.
notion upon which Langer builds her theory of the
rootedness of artistic expression in the biological Poor Animals and Deficient Humans
experience is “feeling.” As for an organism, what is Both Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Susanne
felt is an action in the organism, either in the form Langer had explicated a particular organism-centric
of an impact or as autogenic action (Langer, 1986 mode of existence that opens the organism up for
[1967] pp. 23–24). Prior to the arousal of feelings, the world and yet, at the same time, encloses the
the simpler organisms already based their exis- organism in its specific modes of appearance. Both
tence on perception containing “values for action.” had stressed the importance of seeing the anticipa-
With the development of the nervous system, feel- tion of action in even the most primitive perceptual
ing arises not as a property, but as a phase of vital contacts with the world; perception was understood
activity (like ice is a phase of water), providing thus as already being attuned to the behavioral setting
several physiological processes with the new status and to the set of possible actions, (Merleau-Ponty,
of “being felt.” The arousal of the domain of feeling 2002 [1945]; cf. also Harney, 2007) or carrying
is necessarily accompanied by its transfiguration values for the subsequent activities (Langer, 1988
into an expression. Thus if the organism’s condition [1972]; cf. Weber, 2002).

magnus, kull 655

30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 655 11/24/2011 2:12:41 PM


OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 11/24/11, NEWGEN

The umwelt theory provided quite a different is characteristic to all nonhuman worlds (Heidegger,
impetus for two other thinkers—Martin Heidegger 1983), is echoed also in the work of his other-
and Arnold Gehlen. Although using different argu- wise critical student, Czech phenomenologist Jan
ments and bodies of knowledge, they both main- Patočka (Patočka, 1998 [1995]). Patočka contrasts
tained the impossibility of departing from the the animal, embedded in the relations of immedi-
notion of umwelt while tackling any of the essen- ate relevancy, forced into the constraints of constant
tial questions concerning human beings. They both presence, with the human, who is open not just to
appreciate Uexküll’s contribution to the descrip- the domains of past and future, but also to all pos-
tion of the fundamental conditions of “being an sible forms of past and future, which he calls quasi-
animal,” but demand a new contrastive principle for structures (quasi-future, quasi-present) (Patočka,
the explication of human conduct. 1998 [1995], p. 32).
Gehlen found that human imperfection (der Excluding the aspects of past and future from the
Mensch als Mängelwesen) in relation to any specific activity of any living being is highly problematic if
environmental condition is striking when compar- the preservation of organic form is to be explained.
ing it with the perfect matching of the animal and Each act and activity of an organism already antici-
its environment.8 He traced the idea of the deficient pates some further biological state, thus contribut-
human being, lacking all means that would allow ing to the presence of the specific organic form in
him to attach, to fix himself to any environmental the future. Each value and meaning that an animal
affordances, back to J. G. Herder’s reflections on the encounters in the objects of its environment is at
origin of culture (Gehlen, 1997 [1940]). Inapt to the same time an encounter with a possible future
face any demands of the environment by means of state. The “not yet” of the organism is touched
specialized organs, humans had to choose a different upon with each perceptual act, giving way to the
strategy for getting by. Culture was thus established continuation of the self without reducing duration
as a compensatory mechanism for biological insuf- to an extracted present. A living being, therefore, is
ficiencies. In the biological sense, man is not yet never a point in space, but an ontogenetic as well as
ready, according to Gehlen; he is a task for himself. phylogenetic extension, without a fixed moment of
Unlike Arnold Gehlen, Max Scheler, and Adolf beginning and end, but with definite choices for the
Portmann, philosophers Martin Heidegger and self-specific persistence.
Ernst Cassirer9 did not take specific morphological All interpretations of Uexküll’s umwelt concept
traits of man nor the adaptive inaptness accom- introduced in this chapter, refer to it as a model that
panying them as a departure point for describing explicates the strict adaptations and deterministic,
man’s exceptional position among other living although species-specific, attachment of animal to
beings. Both Cassirer and Heidegger focused more its environment. In the next chapter, we return to
strictly on man’s specific mental modes of relating the semiotic interpretations and see how the above-
to the outer world. In broad terms, they both dis- mentioned versions were challenged by a number
closed the semiotic or symbolic hiatus between man of authors who questioned the claim that mediated
and animal, the human escape from the restraints access to the world is a privilege of humankind.
of immediate physiological reactions. In his “An
Essay on Man: An Introduction to a Philosophy Across the Semiotic Pass
of Human Culture,” Cassirer, when discussing the A new merging of umweltlehre and the humani-
human entrance to the world of symbolic forms, ties in the form of a semiotic synthesis took place
also considers the new coercion that is thereby set in the mid-1970s. It was a time when the language-
on man (Cassirer, 1944). Once the novel sphere of and culture-bound discipline of semiotics started to
symbolic interactions is opened up, man becomes seriously question its scope and extent. The coming
fully enmeshed and enclosed in it. From then on, years featured intensive discussions on the need to
symbolic filtering becomes the single pathway lower the semiotic threshold, i.e., to realize that the
leading from the self to the world, although, in human mind and language are not the first instances
essence, it always results in auto-communication, of semiotic activity, but that animals, plants and in
with man being caught in the forms of knowledge fact the whole living domain is based on the use of
that establish his own identity. signs and the functioning of sign processes. Those
Martin Heidegger’s concern with the human new questions and research perspectives led to the
world, free from the captivity of the immediacy that establishment of a field called biosemiotics, which

656 roots of culture in the umwelt

30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 656 11/24/2011 2:12:41 PM


OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 11/24/11, NEWGEN

concentrates specifically on the semiotic character The Integration of Two Meanings of Umwelt
of various biological processes (from immunological Despite centuries of debate, contemporary
recognition to animal communication). sciences of man still find themselves in what have
As the establishment of any new field is accom- been called the “turf wars between sociology and
panied by the awakening and construction of its psychology” (Watson & Coulter, 2008, p. 2), i.e.,
dormant historic background, so was the case for the debates between the social versus cognitive
biosemiotics. After clarifying its basic principles, interpretations of the human mind. Whereas the
biosemiotics began with a search for the confir- contradiction inside the humanities has gained
mational past. One of the founders of biosemiot- further support from a corresponding institutional
ics, Thomas A. Sebeok, with his primary interest in segregation, a number of philosophical endeavors,
animal cognition and communication, found his from phenomenology to pragmatism, have aimed
predecessors mostly from ethological circles (Heini at undermining the battleground. Extending and
Hediger, Jakob von Uexküll) (Sebeok, 1999, 2001). contextualizing the problem of mind, incorporating
The list of forefathers grew with the expansion of knowledge from areas separated by disciplinary bor-
the field itself to include scientists from a number ders, and inventing fully novel research arenas have
of subfields of biology; for example the embryolo- all granted some assuagement, to a certain extent at
gist Karl Ernst von Baer and the psychologist James least. Seen in the light of these developments, the
Mark Baldwin. This biosemiotic quest for ancestors theory of umwelt and its later cultural theoretical
stemming from biology ran parallel with the reread- adaptations also face two alternatives—to join the
ings of the classical authors of semiotics. Although debaters on either side of the cognitive-social divide
American pragmatist philosopher Charles Sanders or to adhere to the challenging efforts.
Peirce was to become the historical mentor for a The umwelt concept could contribute to either
significant part of biosemiotic research (Thomas one of the sides, if suitable threads of thought are
Sebeok had called him the loadstar of semiotics (cf. extracted from the full web of the theory. Thus
Deely, 2004)), it is perhaps even more interesting the cognitive enclosure of an animal (including
to see how authors strictly bound to the humanities humans) results in fully one-sided construction of
were linked to discussions of biosemiotics and to all objects, unless the organism itself is simultane-
biological umwelt models. ously explained as a product of the constitutive
Thus Jakob von Uexküll’s son, Thure von Uexküll ecological or social relations. On the other hand,
(1908–2004), who related the umwelt theory to the (biological) subject’s meaning-initiated activity
very different models of semiotic processes, linked dissolves into a chain of causal reactions to envi-
it even with a theory that is otherwise considered ronmental stimuli, unless the role of the organism
to be in opposition with biosemiotic principles. He as an active center of meaning formation is taken
explicated a homomorphic relationship between the into account. In order to not thereby tear apart the
principles of Jakob von Uexküll’s umweltlehre and subject-as-meaning-provider and subject-as-rela-
the structural semiotics of Ferdinand de Saussure.10 tions-induced, it is essential to find a framework of
According to T. von Uexküll, Saussure’s distinc- analysis that would maintain the two meanings of
tion between the abstract language system (langue) umwelt: as a world initiated and comprehended by
and the concrete speech acts (parole) (Saussure, the subject and as a node in the set of ecological
1998 [1916]) might be seen as corresponding to relations encompassing the whole biosphere. Those
Jakob von Uexküll’s differentiation between plan two could also be referred to as the phenomeno-
of nature and its concrete realizations in life activ- logical and ecological facets of the theory of the
ity (T. v. Uexküll, 1992, pp. 4–6). T. von Uexküll umwelt. Only the simultaneous presence and usage
made an important distinction between biological of the two can guarantee a steady position outside
and linguistic sign systems, however, naming the the above-mentioned dilemma.
former perceptual or monological systems (based on The essential question therefore is whether we
innate codes) and the latter dialogical systems (based could indicate some primary integrative mechanism
on learned cultural codes). The classical authors of that guarantees and produces the coherence of the
semiotics whose ideas Thure von Uexküll integrated two, and that logically explains their simultaneous
with those of Jakob von Uexküll, included Charles presence? Uexküll himself has suggested what he
Morris, Gottlob Frege and C. S. Peirce (T. von called planmässigkeit, as a ground for the synthesis
Uexküll, 1982, 1992, 1999). (Uexküll, 1927, 1973 [1928]). As the word seems

magnus, kull 657

30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 657 11/24/2011 2:12:42 PM


OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 11/24/11, NEWGEN

to hint to a metaphysical grounding based on a pre- two constancies calling forth one another. The self-
established harmony, preformationism, teleology, regulative and self-maintaining capacities of the
and an idealized state of affairs, it has not found organism had been a research interest of physiolo-
many elaborations by later authors (although see gists at least since the works of Claude Bernard in
Hoffmeyer, 2004, 2008, pp. 172–173; Cheung, the mid-nineteenth century. Observations and dis-
2004). However, several additional processes have cussions about the corresponding properties of eco-
been suggested for what could also ground the systems, however, were just emerging in the 1920s
integration of the phenomenal and the ecological and 1930s (in the works of, e.g., Frederic Clements,
in umwelt theory, irrespective of whether planmäs- John F. V. Phillips, Victor Shelford), at the time
sigkeit is accepted or not. They can all be seen as Uexküll wrote his major works. As the theories of
mechanisms capable of establishing the relative the self-regulation of ecosystems were still in their
autonomy of some entity, applicable at the same outset in the first decades of the twentieth century,
time to a number of natural and cultural phenomena it may have been one of the reasons why Uexküll,
(thus the phenomena of mind just as well as cells, in an organicist manner, used at some occasions the
organisms, and whole ecosystems can be included). metaphor of the organism for describing the regu-
Frederick Stjernfelt, for example, has used subject- larities in whole ecosystems, instead of discussing
dependent categorical perception as a bonding the characteristics of the ecosystems proper (cf.
mechanism between different species-specific phe- Uexküll, 1909, p. 196).
nomenal worlds:
Conclusion
[ . . . ] the condition of possibility for nature to link We indicated a variety of ways in which Jakob
up in these strange ‘harmonies’ between different von Uexküll’s theory of the species-specific umwelt
species’ umwelten depends precisely on categorical has been thus far applied to the analysis of culture
perception: the perceptual categories form the tones and the human mind. These concrete derivations
in the metaphor, and it is their categoricity only that have departed from different aspects of the theory
permits them to enter into counterpoint between the while using it as a springboard for inferences con-
single umwelten. (Stjernfelt, 2007, p. 236) cerning man. The following associations between
umwelt theory and its cultural implications can
The traces of categorization and the complemen-
hence be brought out:
tarity of the categories of different species are
observable by any kind of spatial and temporal 1. If umwelt theory is interpreted as a
discreteness. Unless the form and expressions of demonstration of how biological form and
one species and the perception of another—e.g., behavior expose the sensory impressions an
the movement speed of the prey animal and the organism is capable of receiving, it may also
predator animal’s perceptual time-sectioning, the draw attention to questions of the coupling of
resolution of the insect’s eye and the size of its food artistic forms of expression and the underlying
object, the sound range of the male bird’s voice impressions;
organs and the female’s hearing range—correspond 2. If umwelt theory is read as a theory of ideal
to each other, the two species or organisms lack the biological adaptations and specialization of all
means to enter one another’s umwelt. The depen- living beings, except man, then culture appears to
dence of ecological relations on perceptual units be an extension of the same vital need to cope with
and categories appears thereby evident. the environment, although of a different kind than
Individual percepts and categories never operate all the previous morphological and physiological
as individual units, as though demanding some ones;
extra mechanism for their integration. They never 3. If we direct attention to the questions of
appear outside of the regulative and homeostatic meaning and sign-relations as expressed in the
self-maintenance process of the whole organism. concept of umwelt, then research on the common
Although the latter terms are mostly used for semiotic footing of all living beings is to follow;
describing how the ontogenetic continuity of one 4. If umwelt theory is seen as a way of
organism is preserved in the fixed limits of certain integrating the subjective and the systemic
parameters, self-regulation of the individual orga- perspectives, then a possible solution to the
nism would not be possible unless it is supported cognitive-social divide in humanities may be
by the coupled constancy of the environment, the suggested.

658 roots of culture in the umwelt

30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 658 11/24/2011 2:12:42 PM


OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 11/24/11, NEWGEN

All this has given umwelt theory a remarkable into consideration for whom else may the object in
place in several approaches to culture. The funda- question be valuable. The acknowledgement of the
ments of umwelt theory have passed through signif- interest fields that surround the objects should not
icant transformations every time they have entered be seen as a source of competition, though. That
a new cultural theoretical paradigm. In the face of might rather lead to the establishment of shared
this, we don’t see a reason to strive for a purified interests and to a search for creative solutions for
essence of the theory, independent of all its inter- how the interest fields could further accommo-
pretations and therefore suggest that umwelt theory date the diversity of subjects that they attract. That
itself can be seen as a good indicator of cultural would also mean seeing other subjects behind one-
theoretical change. It offers a number of culture- self ’s actions, to the recognition that no activity can
bound elaborations, the character and concrete be only self-directed.
realization of which is specified by the cultural and
philosophical environment where it finds itself. Acknowledgements
This research was supported by the European Union through
Future Directions the European Regional Development Fund (Center of Excellence
CECT) and by the Estonian Science Foundation Grants ETF
Bearing in mind what we inferred in the con-
8403 and SF0182748s06.
clusion, we can only rather generally suppose, what
could further be the culture-bound questions,
whereby umwelt theory can be employed. Notes
1. The term “umwelt,” if used as a loanword in English,
First, there is still enough work for cultural may also refer to the milieu concept of the French philosopher
studies to be done on how language itself func- and historian Hippolyte Taine (as the outer world that affects
tions as a system of perception and action and what the organisms) and to the modern common-sense meaning of
are its relations to other sign systems that humans umwelt in German (Sutrop, 2001, p. 458). For the historic over-
view of the development of the terms “milieu,” “environment,”
possess. A number of studies belonging to the field
and “umwelt” see, e.g., Canguilhem (2001 [1948]) and Chien
of embodied cognition, situated cognition, enactiv- (2005).
ism that have in the past decades demonstrated the 2. “Ebenso objektiv wie die Faktoren der Umwelt sind, müs-
sensorimotoric embeddedness of linguistic catego- sen die von ihnen hervorgerufenen Wirkungen im Nervensystem
ries provide a strong foothold for further studies aufgefaßt werden. Diese Wirkungen sind ebenfalls durch
den Bauplan gesichtet und geregelt. Sie bilden zusammen die
that might also encompass the principles Jakob von
Innenwelt der Tiere.”
Uexküll delineated in respect with sensorimotoric 3. Under the classical models we understand here the linear
coupling and its role in the formation of meanings. models of communication (e.g., Wilbur-Shramm’s, Shannon-
All those theories have paid attention to how the Weaver’s, and Jakobson’s communication models). Although we
symbolic domain of language is strongly tied with are aware of the differences between them, such differences may
the human bodily reactions and perceptions and be discarded in the context they are used here.
4. The mirror law or the law of reflection in physics charac-
Uexküll’s contribution might help to clarify how terises specular reflection, where the angle of incidence equals the
the connections of the latter are brought about in angle of reflection.
the first place. 5. Erscheinungswelt (the world of appearances) is the world of
Another possible future investigation thread may meaningful objects as it appears to the subject. Unlike umwelt, it
lead to the questions about the transitions from per- is not accessible to the external observer.
6. From Uexküll’s legacy, we find a significant number of
ception to communication. Is Jakob von Uexküll’s articles and essays on philosophical issues in science. These writ-
model of the functional circle still applicable, when ings touch first and foremost on the differences in the physi-
the two interconnected entities are mutually “talk- ologist’s and the biologist’s approaches to living phenomena. As
ative,” both carrying their own values and mean- Uexküll described the physiological approach as a mechanical
one, he identified his own position with the one of biologist.
ings? To think that there is always another who has
7. Wär’ nicht das Auge sonnenhaft / Wie könnten wir das
a say toward a subject’s actions, does not concern Licht erblicken? (Goethe, 1810, p. xxxviii).
only situations where two or more living beings are 8. Max Scheler (1874–1928), who like Gehlen, belonged
directly involved. It comprises any situations where to the circles of German philosophical anthropology, reflected
interests are in play. The other may therefore be upon the same principle of nonadaptation as a biological
impetus for the evolution of human species. Scheler called the
present only indirectly, through the claim he may
latter an organological dilettantism (organologische Dilettantismus).
have for the same thing the subject is striving for. He relied hereby on the evolutionary theories of the German
This means while making a choice (whether it’s a physical anthropologist Hermann Klaatsch (1863–1916)
living place, a piece of food or something else) taking (Scheler, 2001).

magnus, kull 659

30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 659 11/24/2011 2:12:42 PM


OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 11/24/11, NEWGEN

9. For in-depth studies on the relations of Uexküll’s umwelt Harney, M. (2007). Merleau-Ponty, ecology, and biosemiotics.
theory and Cassirer’s philosophy see Chien (2006), Krois (2004), In S. L. Cataldi, & W. S. Hamrick (Eds.), Merleau-Ponty
Heusden (2001), Weber (2004); for the relations of Uexküll and and environmental philosophy: Dwelling on the landscapes of
Heidegger, see Buchanan (2008), Chien (2006). thought (pp. 133–146). Albany, NY: State University of New
10. Thure von Uexküll defines homomorphic relations as York Press.
based on “[ . . . ] a fundamental conformity repeated on various Heidegger, M. (1983). Gesamtausgabe. Abteilung II, Vorlesungen,
levels of complexity, each time in a different way, but basically 1923–1944. Band 29/30, Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik:
always in the same form [ . . . ]” (T. v. Uexküll, 1982, p. 5). Welt – Endlichkeit – Einsamkeit. Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann.
Heusden, B. v. (2001). Jakob von Uexküll and Ernst Cassirer.
References Semiotica, 134(1/4), 275–292.
Bains, Paul (2006). The primacy of semiosis: An ontology of Hoffmeyer, J. (2004). Uexküllian Planmässigkeit. Sign Systems
relations. Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto Press. Studies, 32(1/2), 73–97.
Beer, T., Bethe, A.. & Uexküll J., von (1899). Vorschläge zu Hoffmeyer, J. (2008). Biosemiotics: An examination into the
einer objectivierenden Nomenklatur in der Physiologie des signs of life and the life of signs. Scranton, PA: University of
Nervensystems. Biologisches Centralblatt, 19, 517–521. Scranton Press.
Berthoz, A., & Christen, Y. (Eds.) (2009). Neurobiology of “umwelt”: Kleisner, K. (2008). The semantic morphology of Adolf
How living beings perceive the world. Berlin: Springer. Portmann: A starting point for the biosemiotics of organic
Bredo, E. (1998). Evolution, psychology, and John Dewey’s form? Biosemiotics, 1, 207–219.
critique of the “reflex arc concept.” The Elementary School Kliková, A., & Kleisner, K. (Eds.) (2006). Umwelt: Koncepce
Journal, 98(5), 447–466. žitého sveta Jakoba von Uexkülla. Prague, Czech Republic:
Buchanan, B. (2008). Onto-ethologies: The animal environments Pavel Mervart.
of Uexküll, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty and Deleuze. New York: Krois, J. (2004). Ernst Cassirer’s philosophy of biology. Sign
Suny Press. Systems Studies, 32(1/2), 277–295.
Canguilhem, G. 1994. A vital rationalist: selected writings. New Kull, K. (2001). Jakob von Uexküll: An introduction. Semiotica,
York: Zone Books. 134(1/4), 1–59.
Canguilhem, G. (2001 [1948]). The living and its milieu. Grey Kull, K. (2010a). Umwelt and modelling. In P. Cobley (Ed.),
Room, 3, 7–31. The Routledge companion to semiotics (pp. 43–56). London:
Cassirer, Ernst (1944). An essay on man: An introduction to a philos- Routledge.
ophy of human culture. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Kull, K. (2010b). Ecosystems are made of semiosic bonds:
Chang, R. S. (Ed.) (2009). Relating to environments: A new look Consortia, umwelten, biophony and ecological codes.
at umwelt. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing. Biosemiotics, 3(3). 347–357.
Cheung, T. (2004). From protoplasm to umwelt: Plans and Langer, S. (1956 [1942]). Philosophy in a new key: A study in the
the technique of nature in Jakob von Uexküll’s theory of symbolism of reason, rite, and art. New York: New American
organismic order. Sign Systems Studies 32(1/2), 139–167. Library.
Chien, J. A. (2005). Umweltforschung as a method of inquiry: Langer, S. (1986 [1967]). Mind: An essay on human feeling (Vol.
Jakob von Uexküll’s ‘semiotics’ and its fortune home and away, I). Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Press.
1920–2004. (Dissertation, National Taiwan University). Langer, S. (1988 [1972]). Mind: An essay on human feeling (Vol.
Chien, J. (2006). Of animals and men: A study of umwelt in II). Baltimore, MD and London: Johns Hopkins Press.
Uexküll, Cassirer, and Heidegger. Concentric: Literary and Levchenko, J., & Salupere, S. (Eds.) (1999). Conceptual diction-
Cultural Studies 32(1), 57–79. ary of the Tartu–Moscow Semiotic School. (Tartu Semiotics
Cobley, P. (Ed.) (2010). The Routledge companion to semiotics. Library, Vol. 2.) Tartu, Estonia: Tartu University Press.
London: Routledge. Lotman, J. (1967). Tezisy k probleme “Iskusstvo v ryadu mod-
Deely, J. (2004). Thomas Albert Sebeok, Biologist Manqué eliruyuschih sistem”. Sign Systems Studies (Trudy po znakovym
(Sebeok Memorial Essay). International Association for sistemam), 3, 130–145.
Semiotic Studies, 2004 World Congress, Lyon. Lotman, J. (1984). Kultuur ja organism. In T. Tiivel,
Dewey, J. (1972 [1896]). The reflex arc concept in psychology. K. Kull, T. Neuman, & U. Sutrop (Eds.), Teooria ja
In A. Boydston, & F. Bowers (Eds.), The early works of John mudelid eluteaduses (pp. 215–220). Tartu, Estonia: Eesti
Dewey, 1882–1898 (pp. 96–110). Carbondale: Southern Looduseuurijate Selts.
Illinois University Press. [First published in Psychological Lotman, J. (1990). Universe of the mind: A semiotic theory of
Review 3(4), 357–370.] culture. London: I. B. Tauris.
Eickstedt, E. F. v. (1959). Stammesgeschichte des Seelischen Lotman, J. (2005 [1984]). On the semiosphere. Sign Systems
(Paläopsychologie). In G. Heberer (Ed.), Die Evolution der Studies, 33(1), 215–239.
Organismen: Ergebnisse und Probleme der Abstammungslehre Magnus, R. (2008). Biosemiotics within and without biologi-
(2te Auflage) (pp. 1192–1242). Stuttgart, Germany: Gustav cal holism: A semio-historical analysis. Biosemiotics, 1(3),
Fischer Verlag. 379–396.
Gehlen, A. (1997 [1940]). Der Mensch: Seine Natur und seine Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968 [1964]). The visible and the invisible.
Stellung in der Welt. Wiesbaden, Germany: Quelle & Meyer. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
Gilbert, S. F., & Sarkar, S. (2000). Embracing complexity: Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002 [1945]). The phenomenology of percep-
Organicism for the 21st century. Developmental Dynamics tion. London: Routledge.
219(1), 1–9. Merleau-Ponty, M. (2003 [1995]). Nature: Course notes from the
Goethe, J. W. von (1810). Zur Farbenlehre. Erster Band. Collège de France. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University
Tübingen: J.G. Gotta’schen Buchhandlung. Press.

660 roots of culture in the umwelt

30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 660 11/24/2011 2:12:42 PM


OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 11/24/11, NEWGEN

Mildenberger, F. (2006). The Bethe/Beer/Uexküll paper (1899) Uexküll, J. v. (1909). Umwelt und Innenwelt der tiere. Berlin: J.
and misinterpretations surrounding ‘vitalistic behviorism’. Springer.
History and Philosophy of Life Sciences, 28, 175–190. Uexküll, J. v. (1927). Die Einpassung. In A. Bethe, G. v.
Mildenberger, F. (2007). Umwelt als vision: Leben und werk Bergmann, G. Embden, & A. Ellinger (Eds.), Handbuch der
Jakob von Uexkülls (1864–1944). [Sudhoffs Archiv, Heft 56]. normalen und pathologischen Physiologie: Mit Berücksichtigung
Stuttgart, Germany: Franz Steiner Verlag. der experimentellen Pharmakologie (Vol. 1) (pp. 693–701).
Patočka, J. (1998 [1995]). Body, community, language, world. Berlin: J. Springer.
Chicago: Open Court. Uexküll, J. v. (1973 [1928]). Theoretische Biologie. Frankfurt a.
Phillips, D. C. (1971). James, Dewey, and the reflex arc. Journal M., Germany: Suhrkamp Taschenbuch Wissenschaft.
of the History of Ideas, 32(4), 555–568. Uexküll, J. v. (1982 [1940]). The theory of meaning. Semiotica,
Portmann, A. (1961). Animals as social beings. New York: The 42(1), 25–82.
Viking Press. Uexküll, T. v. (1982). Introduction: Meaning and science in
Portmann, A. (1990). Essays in philosophical zoology: The living Jakob von Uexküll’s concept of biology. Semiotica, 42(1),
form and the seeing eye. (Carter, R. B., trans.). Lewiston, NY: 1–24.
Edwin Mellen Press. Uexküll, T. v. (1992). Introduction: The sign theory of Jakob von
Rüting, T. (2004). History and significance of Jakob von Uexküll Uexküll. Semiotica, 89(4), 279–315.
and of his institute in Hamburg. Sign Systems Studies, Uexküll, T. v. (1999). The relationship between semiotics and
32(1/2), 35–72. mechanical models of explanation in the life sciences.
Saussure, F. d. (1998 [1916]). Course in general linguistics. Semiotica, 127(1/4), 647–655.
London: Duckworth. Watson, R., & Coulter, J. (2008). The debate over cognitivism.
Scheler, M. (2001). Schriften zur Anthropologie. Stuttgart, Theory, Culture & Society, 25, 1–17
Germany: Reclam. Weber, A. (2002). Feeling the signs: Organic experience, intrinsic
Sebeok, T. A. (1999). Editor’s note: Towards a prehistory of teleology and the origins of meaning in the biological phi-
biosemiotics. Semiotica, 127(1/4), 1–3. losophy of Hans Jonas and Susanne K. Langer. Sign Systems
Sebeok, T. A. (2001). Biosemiotics: Its roots, proliferation, and Studies, 30(1), 183–200.
prospects. Semiotica, 134(1/4), 61–78. Weber, A. (2004). Mimesis and metaphor: The biosemiotic gen-
Stjernfelt, F. (2007). Diagrammatology: An investigation on eration of meaning in Cassirer and Uexküll. Sign Systems
the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics. Studies, 32(1/2), 297–307.
Dordrecht, the Netherlands: Springer. Weber, A., & Varela, F. J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes
Sutrop, U. (2001). Umwelt—Word and concept: Two hundred and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality.
years of semantic change. Semiotica, 134(1/4), 447–462. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(2), 97–125.

magnus, kull 661

30_Valsiner_Chap-29.indd 661 11/24/2011 2:12:42 PM

Potrebbero piacerti anche