Sei sulla pagina 1di 13

Rethinking genotype: Comments on the sources of type in

J
architecture
Response to Julienne Hanson’s ‘The anatomy of privacy in architects’
London houses’ (1998)
S
S
Sonit Bafna
Associate Professor, School of Architecture
Georgia Institute of Technology, Atlanta GA

Pages: 69-80

RETHINKING
GENOTYPE
Comments on
the sources of type
in
architecture
The Journal of Space Syntax
ISSN: 2044-7507 Year: 2012 volume: 3 issue: 1 Online Publication Date: 13 August 2012

http://www.journalofspacesyntax.org/
J Rethinking genotype: Comments on the sources of type in
O architecture
Response to Julienne Hanson’s ‘The anatomy of privacy in architects’
S London houses’ (1998)
S
Sonit Bafna
Associate Professor, School of Architecture
Georgia Institute of Technology, Atlanta GA

Two findings from Hanson’s ‘The anatomy of privacy in architects’ London Houses’ are taken as a point Keywords:

of departure for an exploration of the genotype/phenotype distinction in architecture. In the first part of Typology, phenotype,
sociotype, stylotype,
the paper, the definition of genotype within space syntax literature is reviewed, the problem of ostensibly imaginative function,
typological buildings not showing expected genotypical consistency is described, and two approaches design description

developed to address it partially are discussed. This leads to a reconsideration of the biological origins of
the genotype-phenotype distinction, and to the recognition that the two terms refer to different types, each
identified by traits resulting from causally distinct pathways. In the final, speculative, part of the paper, it is
suggested that this principle might be fruitfully applied to architecture as well, and that analogous to the
concepts of genotype and phenotype in biology, one might propose the presence of two causally distinct
conceptions of type in buildings: ‘sociotypes’ and ‘stylotypes’. The concept of stylotype, it is suggested,
might help explain the distinctive spatial qualities that architects bring to their designs.

1. Architects’ houses
Amongst Julienne Hanson’s many contributions to architects, so merely the involvement of architects
space syntax, the most distinctive are her attempts could not be the criterion of distinction. The distinc-
to characterise what is ‘architectural’ within the more tion in Hanson’s paper, instead, is made on the basis
general domain of building design. There is always of intentions – the bespoke house designed for one’s
a danger of some circularity in addressing this is- own self against the house designed for a generic
sue, since the characterisation itself is a means for user – and this criterion allows the comparison to
making the distinction between architecture and directly address what quality architects bring to
building in the first place. It is a sign of Hanson’s their designs that the market does not identify. A
intuitive sharpness, and something to learn from, premise embedded in her study, one should note, is
that she neatly circumvents this danger by choos- that such a quality would be manifest in the spatial
ing to work with concrete case studies where this organisation of the house.
distinction can be mapped onto unambiguously Of the many theoretical and methodological
defined categories. In ‘The anatomy of privacy in insights in the paper, I want to pick upon two dis-
architects’ London houses’, she sets up a compari- crete findings in my response: the first, the finding
son between houses that architects have designed that leads to her main claim about how architects’
for themselves, and those that were constructed for houses differ from builders’; and the second, a
speculative purposes by builders as explored in her finding on the genotypical patterns observed in her
chapter ‘Shaping the taste of middle England’ in sample. Both these points have implications that go
the same book (Hanson, 1998). Set up in this way, beyond the immediate subject at hand.
the comparison avoids obvious traps. For instance, The first point concerns the kind of differences
it is quite possible for the houses constructed for that Hanson finds between architects’ and build-
speculative purposes by builders to be designed by ers’ houses. These differences, she observers, are

69
J
O
The Journal of S
Space Syntax S

Volume 3 • Issue 1

not large enough to support the hypothesis that non-convex boundary spaces are a regular feature
architects belong to a distinctive sub-culture of their of the architects’ houses. Many of these, if one
own (Hanson, 1998, p.236). But the differences scrutinises the house plans and the analytical draw-
are still of interest. The architects’ houses that she ings that Hanson provides, can be seen to convexly
considers – a sample of eighteen, drawn from thirty fragment into a set of interconnected lobbies and
houses presented in Miranda Newton’s Architects’ corridors; a few are associated with use spaces. In
London Houses (Newton, 1992) – have an average short, the architects’ houses are larger in area on
area of 220 square meters. The range, however, is average, but the greater area is not so much the
quite large, varying between 70 square meters, and result of ‘adding more rooms to contain proliferat-
450 square meters. In comparison, she says, not ing household functions’ (Hanson, 1998, p.236),
only is the typical speculative house available in but rather a matter of more elaborate investment in
the London market of this time, much smaller at an transitional zones between use spaces.
average size of 75 square meters, even the higher The second point has to do with Hanson’s at-
end speculative houses are rarely more than 175 tempts to find one or more consistent genotypical
square meters. The larger area of the architects’ signatures within the sample of the architects’
houses does not, however, translate, as one would houses. She finds, however, that there are none.
expect, into a greater number or variety of actual In these houses, she writes, ‘the rank order of the
rooms. Convex partitioning of houses results in two integration of living functions of the eighteen houses
kinds of constituent spaces – fat spaces associ- exhibits almost no duplication. This is not the case
ated with ‘static occupation’ (presumably routine with traditional and vernacular sample of plans
spatially localised activities like dining, sleeping, which, as we have seen in earlier chapters tend
reading, cooking) and long spaces associated with to be consistent in their configurational features to
circulation. When such spaces are tallied for both the point that this becomes the primary means to
architects’ and speculative houses, the numbers detect the imprint of culture on house form.’ (ibid.,p.
of use spaces are surprisingly similar (11 average 235). Taking this lack of consistency in her stride,
spaces for architects’ houses versus 8 for specu- Hanson goes on to describe other findings of inter-
lative ones), at least in comparison to transition est, in particular, the ones I described above. But
spaces (14 versus 4); the average space: transition it is worthwhile, I think, to give some more thought
ratio in architects’ houses is 0.79, which is about half to this observation. Although, not of immediate
of that for the speculative house (1.46). If, however, consequence in the context of the Hanson paper,
the houses are partitioned into boundary spaces it is a result that is often observed in other studies,
(spaces created simply by shutting all doors, thus and, I suspect, is symptomatic of the current state
producing rooms that correspond with activity la- of beliefs and understanding about this interesting
bels, but are not necessarily convex), the number concept in space syntax; I want to take the oppor-
of rooms in both populations is found to be similar tunity to revisit the issue.
– around 10. Hanson reads these data as showing In what follows, I plan to delve a bit more into the
a structural difference between the two populations. idea of the genotype as it has come to be used in
In the speculative houses, the boundary and convex space syntax studies. I will consider the apparent
space maps are very similar; the boundary spaces reasoning and logic behind invoking this biological
are essentially simple convex spaces connected metaphor – a very productive and insightful one, as
directly to each other through doors. In contrast, anyone familiar with space syntax literature might

70
J
O
S Rethinking
S genotype

Bafna, S.

note - and discuss briefly a couple of attempts to critical distinctions that are worth noting:
extend it both operationally and theoretically. Con-
‘The house-by-house review suggests that al-
sideration of the original biological context, however,
though there is no obvious single house “type”
will lead us to reconsider the notion that the differ- in the sample – defined perhaps as a more or
ence between genotype and phenotype represents less standard way of constructing the house and
a type-token distinction, but also offer a principle arranging its rooms – there is evidence of at least
on which such a distinction might be formulated. one functional-spatial “genotype” – defined in
terms of relational and configurational consisten-
From this point on, my paper will take on a more
cies which show themselves under “phenotypical”
speculative note, as I offer suggestions about the
arrangements.’ (Hillier, Hanson, and Graham,
ways in which one might extend the exploration of 1987, p.379)
‘type’ in architecture. I will return to the first, and
major, point in the Hanson paper, which locates The two distinctions are those between ‘type’
the principal generic difference of the architects’ and ‘genotype’, and between ‘genotype’ and
houses from their speculative counterparts in their ‘phenotype.’ Understanding these terms helps to
elaborated interfaces between use spaces. I will see that the idea was introduced in order to solve
argue that the Hanson finding calls for extending a practical problem, but one with some theoretical
the definition of type to one with stylistic origins, in motivations: it is a demand of space syntax theory –
addition to that with origins in social function, and of the theory of the social logic of space – that there
that such definitions can lead syntactical theory to be a systematic description of type, since buildings
a more inclusive account of architecture. that house distinct social institutions should, by
definition, constitute a distinct formal class reflect-
2. The Genotype in Space Syntax Literature ing their shared social function. It also follows from
The idea – more of a practice now – of using the basic space syntactical premises that this social
‘rank order of integration [values] of the living func- function of the building be found expressed in
tions’ as an indicator of a genotype, seems to have the spatial configuration. Descriptions of type that
been first presented formally and empirically verified were routinely advanced in architectural literature
in ‘Ideas are in things’ (Hillier, Hanson, and Graham, on typology during the late 1970s and much of the
1987). The term genotype was already in circula- 1980s, by the Neo-Rationalists (notably, Rossi,
tion in space syntax literature, and the idea of an 1982; see Moneo, 1978, and Bandini, 1984 for
‘inequality genotype’ in terms of ‘relational differen- historical overviews) were clearly not descriptively
tiation of functions’ suggested in Hillier, Hanson, and precise enough to do the job; they did not offer any
Peponis (1984, p.65), but the 1987 paper presented way to distinguish classes of buildings according
a more straightforward operational definition: to their social function. But it is also true that just
‘If numerical differences [integration values] in reducing the buildings to a graph of their spatial
functions are in a consistent order in a sample, configuration would not be sufficient, for even if the
then we can say a cultural pattern exists… This graph distilled out some of the socially significant
particular consistency in spatial patterning, we aspects of the social relationships, one would still
call inequality genotype.’ (Hillier, Hanson, and
need some systematic way to distinguish the vari-
Graham, 1987, p.364)
ation between individuals that belong to the type,
Reading the paper, one finds the definition reas- and identify those aspects of the graph that were
serted a little later, but this time sharpened with two typological. The problem was identified in the

71
J
O
The Journal of S
Space Syntax S

Volume 3 • Issue 1

early formulations of the space syntax theory (for logically infer that a genotype is absent, for it may
instance, Hillier, Hanson, and Peponis, 1984), and be possible that minor variations in the access
one answer, proposed in ‘Ideas are in things’, was, graphs may have altered the rank ordering without
as we have seen above, that while the graphs of necessarily changing the functional implications of
individual buildings belonging to a particular type the house layouts in a drastic way.
would vary, the ranking of spaces according to their Although no one has yet attempted such a for-
integration values would be more consistent, and so mal proof, some authors have tried to address the
more indicative of underlying social type. issue indirectly. One approach has been to actually
It is important to note that Hillier, Hanson, and quantify the similarity between access graphs of
Graham (1987) are careful not to equate either the two buildings. In 2007, Conroy Dalton and Kirsan
graph or the rank order of spaces itself with the developed a procedure for comparing graphs us-
genotype; rather they speak of ‘genotypical tenden- ing a graph-matching algorithm, analogous to the
cies’ (ibid., p.382, p.385) of which the rank order is standard string-matching algorithms. This approach
one feature, and treat the spatial configuration not produces a numerical index whose value is directly
so much as a fixed expression of social organisa- associated with the number of steps one would
tion, but as a device through which standard rela- require in order to convert one graph into another
tionships between categories of inhabitants can (Conroy Dalton and Kirsan, 2007). A set of graphs
be dynamically negotiated (ibid., p.385). But the closest to each other can then be isolated as be-
argument that an underlying functional genotype longing to particular genotypes, for instance, by
results in a consistent rank ordering of integration using standard statistical techniques such as cluster
values of functions is presented as being obvious, analysis; the graphs themselves are described by
and not formally demonstrated. The problem is that the authors as being ‘genotypical signatures’. The
buildings belonging to the same class or type in the value of this technique is that it lets the general
social sense (single family houses from a region, for classes emerge naturally from the data, but my own
instance) will invariably have minor variations in their sense is that what Conroy Dalton and Kirsan are
relational structure (that is, in their convex space ac- capturing here is better described as the prototype,
cess graph) due to incidental factors, and we need rather than a genotype. The difference is that where
some systematic principle to sort out such incidental the concept of genotype refers to a core set of at-
variations from those that point to actual differences tributes which are shared amongst all members of a
of type. The assumption in the definition of inequality class and which help define it (although, as we shall
genotype is that only the typologically significant see later, even this definition requires some further
variations in access graphs will actually disturb qualification), the concept of a prototype (originating
the integration value rank ordering of functional in some highly influential studies in human cognition
spaces. This assumption makes intuitive sense, but by Eleanor Rosch and her colleagues in the 1970s
to be of practical use needs systematic verification, [Rosch, 1978]) refers to an individual that exempli-
either through a mathematical argument or through fies a class without completely defining it, so that it
empirical simulation studies. Lacking such formal may otherwise include quite a varied collection of
demonstration, when one encounters the lack of a individuals. The class of birds, for instance, includes
consistent rank ordering pattern within a sample a sparrow as well as an ostrich and a penguin, but
of buildings, as Hanson does in ‘The anatomy of human subjects tend to consider the sparrow as a
privacy in architects’ London houses’, one cannot more representative example of birds as compared

72
J
O
S Rethinking
S genotype

Bafna, S.

to the other two. The open-ended, graded system of The argument was that individual function spaces in
classification of classes with more and less central a house should be seen as constituents of a larger
members of what is now called ‘prototype theory’ entity (a cluster). A cluster was not merely collec-
was initially formulated to explain the structure of tion of individual spaces, but had a structure of its
folk taxonomies, and arguments for it are based in own, consisting of specific arrangements of use,
basic human cognitive capacity (D’Andrade, 1995). circulation and service spaces. The cluster was
Conroy Dalton’s and Kirsan’s work, thus, seems to itself a functional entity; that is, it corresponded to
open the door to an entirely new way of thinking of specific functional categories (bedroom cluster, or
typology of buildings – one that would be grounded reception room cluster), so one could define each
more directly in human cognition. And although house as a specific configuration of basic clusters
the combination of computational and empirical without specifying the actual internal structure of
work that it calls for goes beyond the scope and the clusters. I argued that the spatial configuration
relevance of this paper, it is to be hoped that many of clusters be considered as defining the genotype,
will feel challenged to take it up. since each house in my sample shared this basic
Another approach to the problem of lack of configuration of functional entities, and since adding
consistency of rank ordering in buildings assumed or removing individual spaces within the clusters
to belong to a type is suggested by set of studies did not disturb this basic configuration; the hierar-
of early twentieth century German Landhäuser chical conception of the genotype, in other words,
(suburban villas) conducted by myself (Bafna, 2001; was able to systematically distinguish what was
1999). What I suggested, first, was that the integra- configurationally constant to the type, from what
tion values of function spaces in individual houses could configurationally vary between individuals.
be treated, not as absolute values, but as statistics Again, although quite satisfactory for the Land-
from which one could estimate parameter values häuser, this argument only suggested a direction in
that represented the actual integration values of which further empirical studies of genotype might
the functions. If given two populations – in my case proceed – it did not actually demonstrate that
the houses designed by Mies van der Rohe, and such hierarchical conceptions should underlie all
those designed by his contemporaries –������������
�������������
the differ- typological cases. Mies’s working design sketches
ences between the parameter estimates of their further strengthened the hierarchical conception of
function spaces could be compared, using stan- genotypes, by showing that the clusters were not
dard statistical procedures, to test whether the two merely theoretical entities, but had tangible pres-
values came from distinct populations (and so from ence as provisional design elements (acting as
distinct genotypes). But while this procedure could provisional place holders for finer scale configura-
compare the rank ordering of estimated integration tions that were not settled). Again, however, such
values of functions in houses drawn from two distinct examples are illustrative rather than demonstrative,
populations, it could not be used to actually prove and clearly the idea needs much further explora-
the existence of (or the absence of) a genotype tion; it should also be mentioned that other studies
from sample drawn from a single population. This have proposed similar configurational descriptions,
is because, given any random sample of houses, quite independently of this work (compare with, for
one can always estimate a specific rank ordering of instance, the idea of ‘sectors’ in Amorim, 1997).
estimated values. In order to address this problem,
I proposed a hierarchical conception of a genotype.

73
J
O
The Journal of S
Space Syntax S

Volume 3 • Issue 1

3. Rethinking Genotypes instructions which are variably unfolded are not


Despite their differences, what is common to all written down or  genetically programmed, but
embedded in the artificial systems which we call
these studies is the idea that the genotype refers
“cultures”. Deep cultural structures may be trans-
to those aspects of the spatial organisation that ex- mitted unchanged through several generations,
press its core sociological functioning. But why call yet produce great variety at the observable level.
the socially relevant typological element of build- Such underlying stable structure corresponds to
ings a ‘genotype’? The term was first introduced what biologists call “genotypes”, compared to a
into space syntax literature in a very early paper “phenotype” which is a variably developed ob-
servable form. In the army example, the genotype
by Hillier and Adrian Leaman (Hillier and Leaman,
is the information carried in the instructions and
1974). And there, it was introduced to make another embedded in the instrumental set; the phenotype
critical distinction - the difference between what was is the observed layout and activity of the camp.’
actually built and the general rules that determine (Hillier and Leaman, 1974, p.4-5)
how a building is to be built. The classic example
Hillier and Leaman, aware of the limitations of
that was invoked to illustrate the idea was that of a
the biological analogy, went on to advocate the use
Roman army encampment:
of the terms g-model and p-model to replace geno-
‘Consider an example. An army marches all day. type and phenotype (developed further in Hillier and
At nightfall a halt is called and unpacking begins.
Hanson, 1984, p.198-222). The main problem with
Within a short time a structured environment ap-
the analogy, they felt, lay in the nature of design
pears. ... A complete environment is, as it were,
“unfolded”. The army experiences this as a sim- process - ‘the cultural genotypes [the structured
ple, repetitive procedure. But looked at scientifi- sets of instructions] evolve much faster than biologi-
cally in terms of the structures which must exist for cal genotypes and may be able to alter themselves
such a simple “unfolding” to be possible, it is both by self-reference’ (Hillier and Leaman, 1974, p.5).
complex and  illuminating. First, the observable
However, there is another deeper problem with
environment which is unfolded is based on a set
the analogy. The genotype/phenotype distinction,
of instructions in the army manual or in standing
orders. Second, these abstract instructions and as well as the g-model / p-model distinction, was
relations are “embedded” in the items the army taken to be a type/token distinction, the term ‘token’
carries about with it to manufacture this environ- being used to represent the concrete instantiation
ment, which may be called its “instrumental set”. of the otherwise abstract type. The ‘phenotype,
Third, and most important, it will be noted that any
which is a variably developed observable form’
series of camps unfolded by the army will exhibit
(see quote above) is thus interpreted as a token.
both similarities and difference. In this simplified
and artificially deterministic example, the source But as the biologist Richard Lewontin cautions us,
of similarity is the set of instructions as embedded the difference between genotype and phenotype
in the instrumental set, and the source of differ- is a difference between two types (Lewontin, 2011).
ences is the local constraints and contingency, The phenotype, as much as a genotype, is a type.
which will include personal and environmental
Both terms refer to sets of characteristics or traits
factors, strategic considerations and so on.’ 
that define, not an individual, but a class or species.
(Hillier and Leaman, 1974, p.4).
‘The genotype of an organism is the class to
And following this, which that organism belongs as determined by
‘Although an extreme example, this structure the description of the actual physical material
does illuminate certain pervasive properties of made up of DNA that was passed to the organ-
cultural forms. In many situations, sets of basic ism by its parents at the organism’s conception….

74
J
O
S Rethinking
S genotype

Bafna, S.

The phenotype of an organism is the class to One could easily make the case that it would not.
which that organism belongs as determined by Already in 1979, as the main ideas behind space
the description of the physical and behavioral
syntax were being formulated, Philip Steadman had
characteristics of the organism, for example its
made the telling observation that technological evo-
size and shape, its metabolic activities and its
pattern of movement.’ lution would be better described as being Lamarck-
(Lewontin, 2011, original emphasis) ian, rather than Darwinian, in character – changes
in designs of objects are often made due to lack of
The type-token distinction, in contrast, is recog- environmental fit, and if they work, such changes
nised by referring to the two aspects of the physical persist through succeeding generations, because
organism itself, as the ‘genome’ and the ‘phenome’. they are literally copied by succeeding craftsmen,
Here is Lewontin, again, continuing his description: designers, or builders (Steadman, 1979, p.124-34);
there are, in other words, no separate causal de-
‘It is essential to distinguish the descriptors of the
organism, its genotype and phenotype, from the velopmental and genetic pathways in the shaping
material objects that are being described. The of artifacts. But, this point, however valid, is not the
genotype is the descriptor of the genome which entire story, for the point to take away from biology
is the set of physical DNA molecules inherited is not that there may exist architectural analogues
from the organism’s parents. The phenotype is the
of genotypes and phenotypes, or analogues of
descriptor of the phenome, the manifest physical
developmental and hereditary pathways, but rather
properties of the organism, its physiology, mor-
phology and behavior.’ the general principle that characteristics and traits
(Lewontin, 2011, original emphasis) observed in an individual may result from generative
processes that follow causally different pathways.
Now, at one level, to point this out is to indulge To understand why such a principle would be
in a bit of academic pedantry; the terms persist in useful, recall that the operational procedure to de-
space syntax theory not so much on the strength scribe the genotype in a sample of buildings has
of their biological origin, but because they serve an been to collect together a set of observed traits that
analytical purpose within the theoretical discourse, are consistently present within all, or most of the
and by now have come to acquire quite stable and buildings in the sample – the rank ordering of func-
unambiguous meanings in space syntax literature tions according to integration values being the result
irrespective of their correspondence with the of such consistency within the access graphs that
original biological terms. But, correct terminology are constructed to capture the discrete relational
aside, the recognition of the difference does have structure of the buildings’ spatial configuration. But
some practical values. When the terms were first it is entirely possible that the observed consistency
introduced in biology by the Danish botanist Wilhelm (or, for that matter, the lack of an observed consist-
Johanssen in 1908, their use was to acknowledge ency, when expected) may be the result of the
that the observed characteristics of an organism spatial configuration being structured as a result
came from two entirely different causal pathways – of more than one causal process; some aspects
one through hereditary transmission, and the other of the spatial configuration of buildings (and so of
by natural development in the course of life of the the access graphs derived from it) may arise from
organism. Without stretching the biological analogy requirements of social function, but possibly some
past the point of snapping, could such a distinction other aspects of the graph structure might arise from
be of use to architecture as well? an entirely different kind of source. If this is true, then

75
J
O
The Journal of S
Space Syntax S

Volume 3 • Issue 1

it points to the usefulness of introducing some kind tional specification, or of relational features exhibited
of a description of design process into our under- by actual buildings, but rather as the description of
standing of the shaping of buildings. Interestingly, a generative or production mechanism. And this
even the brief history of the genotype concept that I shift in the understanding of the genotype was not
have sketched so far suggests that this is not entirely incidental. As the very title of the 1987 paper (‘Ideas
a new line of thinking within space syntax. are in things’) indicates, the theoretical notion ad-
vanced to support the shift was that since genotypi-
4. Varieties of formal types cal ideas were transmitted through the retrieval of
Consider the interesting shift that happened in the social knowledge embodied in buildings, it would
invocation of genotypes between 1974 and 1987. In not be necessary to describe the actual design
the 1987 paper, Hillier, Hanson and Graham define and building procedures – the finding of function-
genotype in terms of ‘relational and configurational ally relevant consistency in graphs would naturally
consistencies’ (p.379) of the spatial configuration give the definition, whatever the actual processes
of individual buildings, through which ‘social rela- by which the graphs were brought about.
tions and processes express themselves in space’ What I am arguing for, in this context, is to revisit
(p.362); Hillier (1996) repeats this formulation, the original definition of genotypes as generative
and this is much the sense in which subsequent mechanisms. This does not mean discarding the
papers on space syntax have used it. The point to idea of the inequality genotype, but rather to rec-
note is that the terms in which the genotype is de- ognise other valid descriptions of type depending
scribed – as the distribution of integration values of upon the causal processes that may generate them.
functional spaces (their rank order, their difference The integration-rank-ordering of the inequality geno-
factor values, the identification of the most integrat- type is a signature of what we may call a sociotype
ing function, and so on) – are essentially terms of of buildings – that is a class of common relational
functional specification. The genotype is essentially structures that enable the specific general social
the description of structural relations amongst the function which the building must satisfy. But, in addi-
discrete programmatic spaces that are to hold if tion to this, other aspects of the spatial configuration
the building is to fulfill its social function correctly. (and so features of the access graphs describing
Compare this definition to the one advanced in the them) may also result from what we may call a sty-
1974 paper. There, Hillier and Leaman identify the lotype – a class of specific formal traits that result
genotype as an informational entity quite distinct from the demands of what at least provisionally we
from the building itself. In the army camp, the geno- may define as design-governed, or stylistic, criteria.
type consists of ‘the information carried in instruc- The term ‘stylistic criteria’ is general and admit-
tion manuals and embedded in the instrumental tedly somewhat loose. But rather than specify it
set’. Even when they generalise the notion to cover more precisely from the outset, I will try to give a
the set of buildings at large, which naturally do not sense of it by describing its role in creating typo-
come with specific design or construction manuals logical structures. To do this, I return back to the
or with a physically embodied instrumental set of Hanson paper on architects’ houses in London.
the encampment, they still speak of genotypes as The Hanson findings, as I pointed out earlier, are
being constituted in ‘sets of basic instructions’, and particularly insightful in illustrating broader points
‘deep cultural structures’. The original definition of about type; the following discussion should make
the genotype was, therefore, not in terms of a func- clear what I meant. It will be recalled that Hanson

76
J
O
S Rethinking
S genotype

Bafna, S.

reported architects’ houses to be significantly larger who are designing their own houses, and may be
in area as compared to speculative houses, and more tolerant of them, are not likely to specify or list
that the difference in size was accounted for in a them explicitly. Given this, the finding that there are
large part by the increased investment in transitional more functional spaces cannot directly lead to the
spaces. In purely descriptive terms, the architects’ inference that more spaces as such were desired;
houses featured many more elongated convex it is quite possible that such spaces are Gouldian
spaces, which were for the most part dedicated to spandrels, their presence being an inadvertent re-
circulation and or ancillary activities, rather than the sult of other considerations in the design process. To
main domestic functions. The question to ask of this say this is not to deny that, in the architects’ houses
finding, as Hanson does, is whether this is a matter of Hanson’s sample, there was some functional
of sociological import – does this difference imply specification of elaborated buffer zones between
that architects’ houses belong to a fundamentally rooms, or of increased flexibility in altering the
different sub-culture, with a distinctive set of values internal privacy of rooms. It is rather to say that the
different from those of the overarching culture, within existence of such a functional specification, would
the overall domestic culture expressed in the late not by itself account for the presence of increased
twentieth century London single family house? Her transitional spaces. Such functional requirements
answer is that while the architects’ houses clearly could be satisfied by other kinds of spatial organisa-
share the overall values with the larger culture to tion, as Mies demonstrated in his courtyard houses
which they belong – a culture that finds its expres- of the early 1930s. So, descriptions of functional
sion in increased mutual privacy and respect for the specifications are not adequate by themselves as
individual within the house – the increased invest- explanations of observed characteristics of spatial
ment in transitional spaces allows them to bring a configurations. What one needs to make the expla-
greater degree of flexibility and more articulation nation work is a more explicit account of how the
to the expression of these values. Largely because observed regularities in the spatial configuration
of the presence and disposition of the transitional of these houses resulted from the conditions within
spaces, the individual in the architects’ houses has which the houses were designed.
a greater control and choice in fine-tuning his or her Such an account is not yet available – indeed,
relative privacy. part of my intention in this paper is to make a case
All this is both reasonable and telling, but it also for a program of research to develop such an ac-
raises the question of how such layouts are brought count – but from the little that we know of design
about. For however typological this transitional- processes, it may be argued that observed regulari-
space-oriented house may be, the means by which ties of the spatial organisation may arise either from
such a configuration is to be achieved cannot eas- general functional requirements, or as by-products
ily be pre-specified. Circulation spaces, as most of particular ways of working that may include de-
architects will know, are, for the most part, treated liberately adopted stylistic approaches, aesthetic
as non-programmed spaces. That is, they are not judgments, consciously adopted design-strategies
usually specified distinctly in programmatic briefs and design conceits, or of unconscious habits of
that architects are given. Clients concerned with problem-solving that invariably accompany the work
economy and efficiency will often expect such of trained designers (for some studies that offer
spaces to be minimised, which explains their scar- evidentiary support on this point, see Keller and
city in the builders’ houses; but even architects’ Keller, 1996; Glassie, 1975). However, even in the

77
J
O
The Journal of S
Space Syntax S

Volume 3 • Issue 1

absence of systematic procedures and actual de- not seem unreasonable to infer a few typical design
sign protocols from houses in the Hanson sample, considerations that give rise to it. For instance, it
we can still offer reasonable speculative accounts is created often by the exercise of fitting oddly,
for the sake of presenting an illustrative argument. and variously sized rooms within a larger regular
Comparing the actual plans of the houses with the block (the fitting of living, dining, kitchen, and an
partitioned diagrams, and hypothesising a con- assortment of cabinets in the main block of house
ventional design process, one can begin to get 1), in which the programmatically open circulation
a sense of how the extra, unplanned transitional spaces absorb the left-over, and therefore, oddly
spaces might have come about. The most com- shaped areas. In other cases, (very likely, in the
mon way for such spaces to appear in a design joint of entrance and bedroom corridors in house
is when it is necessary to connect several rooms 7, for instance) it is created explicitly by the kind
at an equal depth from another room, or from the of requirement that Hanson describes – assuring
rest of house; these are the typical lobbies and visual privacy by breaking a direct line of sight.
short corridors that connect, for instance, a living In all these house plans, then, the actual spatial
room, or staircase to the two or three bedrooms configuration emerges partly in response to direct
(for instance, in the first floor of houses 1 and 2). functional requirements, but partly also as the un-
However, such conditions arise once or perhaps intended result of specific tactical design moves.
twice in a single house of the kind being considered The presence of the relatively large number of
here, so transition spaces created deliberately for transitional spaces is quite likely a product of the
graph theoretical reasons are not likely to proliferate latter, rather than the former (although this does
within a building. The houses in the builders’ sample not preclude their social functioning along the lines
would be very likely to contain such spaces as well. indicated by Hanson in the closing arguments of
But where the architects’ sample differs, I think, is her paper). If this is true, then we can draw some
in the transitions created by other typical moves. interesting conclusions about the emergence of
One such move, which can be discerned easily types in architecture, for the point to note is that
from the actual plans, is of inserting ‘islands’ within despite the considerable variations in the design ap-
a larger area. In house 16, which has the lowest proaches of the architects of these houses, taken as
use/transition ratio of 0.39, the single design move a whole they do produce some kind of consistency
of inserting a large cut-out on two floors, in order to in spatial configuration. The investment in transition
create a void, creates at least seven relatively narrow spaces, organised in rings, which produces ‘the
convex passages around it. The fragmentation of spatial signature that identifies these houses as
space around the open stairwell in both the ground a group’ (Hanson, 1998, p.240), but is not quite a
and first floors of house 3, also in order to create genotype, can be taken to be fairly good indicator
a void, gives another example of such a condition. of a stylotype.
Another type of move that results in fragmented Although this spatial signature is an indicator of
space and multiple transitional spaces is through a stylotype, it is not a full descriptor of it; the discus-
misalignment of the interior partitions; instances of sion above shows – I hope at least provocatively, if
this misalignment are easily discerned in houses 1 not persuasively – that we need a systematic theory
and 7, although it can be found to some extent in of description of the stylotype. But short of that, we
almost all the houses. The misalignment is, by itself, can still make a few points about the nature of the
not a desirable or sought after condition; but it does stylotype.

78
J
O
S Rethinking
S genotype

Bafna, S.

The first point is to recognise that designers tend also seems likely that the social knowledge embed-
to work in a Euclidean space – inserting an island ded in buildings that is reproduced in the sociotype
within a larger space is a move that requires careful is located within the procedural strategies and
calibration of dimensions and perception of scale, umbrella plans that generate the designs. It could
and so does the deliberate misalignment of walls in be suggested that in the practice of designing
plan. The Euclidean geometry in such cases acts as and executing buildings it is the stylotype which is
a constraint on the emergent discrete topology of generative; rules governing it are constitutive, as
the spatial configuration. This observation reverses compared to the sociotype, the rules governing
the conventional idea that the discrete topological which are regulative.
structure of a building is the more general and so If all this is to be accepted, what does it tell
governing element in the design of a building in us regarding the question that Hanson postulates
comparison with the geometry of the building, and in her paper – do architects’ houses constitute a
prepares us to see that descriptions of type may lie separate sub-culture defined by the distinctiveness
as much in the geometrical description of buildings. of the spatial structure of their own houses? Her
A second point is to note again is that the answer that these houses are distinguished from
sources of stylotype are varied, but very likely to the speculative houses not by exhibiting entirely
be based in human cognitive capacity. As cogni- different relational structures, but by offering far
tive studies of designers-in-action have shown, greater and more subtle opportunities of spatial re-
those, like architects, who are trained to address configuration and fine-tuning of privacy gradients,
problems with incompletely specified solutions, is characteristically nuanced and simultaneously
develop consistent procedural strategies to deal sharp. What I have hoped to do in my paper is to
with such problems. These strategies include low- build on this insight by suggesting that the presence
level protocols to do basic routine tasks, as well of such spatial opportunities (or their relative lack in
as high level ‘umbrella plans’ that organise a given the speculative houses) can also be described as a
problem into sub-problems defined in terms of the matter of type, if one could describe type in terms of
low-level protocols (Keller and Keller, 1996; but features resulting from specific design approaches.
also pre-figured in Glassie, 1975). Such procedural One of the key issues that Hanson has identified for
protocols and umbrella plans are not just mental space syntax research, and to which she has made
entities, but include a mix of operations partially foundational contributions, has been the extension
embedded in physical tools and supported by an of syntactical theory to account for the shaping
empirical knowledge base. And although such of buildings by concept-driven, critically-oriented
protocols might include some personal element – architectural practices. In the paper on architects’
individual aesthetic preferences or preferred strate- London houses, but also in papers on Gerrit Re-
gies – overall designers from a particular milieu are itveld’s Schröder house and in her comparative
likely to share many of these procedural protocols, study of contemporary architects’ houses, Hanson
hence making the emergence of style-oriented type has repeatedly shown that the houses feature sys-
in their designs quite unsurprising. temic spatial properties whose function is to fine
Taken together, both these points imply that the tune and enrich their inhabitants’ lived experience
stylotype is, in terms of design logic, prior to the (Hanson, 1998, p.196-214 and p.242-68). My hope
sociotype; the specification of the sociotype seems is that further work on stylistic or design conception
far more permissive than that of the stylotype, and it of type will show that such functions are not just an

79
J
O
The Journal of S
Space Syntax S

Volume 3 • Issue 1

experiential bonus, but rather essential to the role About the author:
buildings play in our lives – that just as the sociotype
Sonit Bafna (sonit.bafna@
caters to the generic social function of buildings, coa.gatech.edu), studies
the principles that govern
the stylotype may be shown to cater to their generic
the shape of the built en-
imaginative function (Bafna, 2012). vironment and mediate its
relationship with social, cul-
tural, and imaginative life.
His work has focused on the
mathematical description
References of spatial organisation in
buildings, empirical studies
Amorim, L. (1997), ‘The sectors’ paradigm: Understanding Hillier, B. (1996), Space is The Machine, Cambridge: of the relationship between
space and behaviour, and
modern functionalism and its effects in configuring Cambridge University Press. historical and critical expla-
domestic spaces’. In: Major, M. D., Amorim, L. and Hillier, B. and Leaman, A. (1974), ‘How is design possible?’. nations of design. This work
is published in Environment
Dufaux, D. (eds.), Proceedings of the First International In: JAR, Vol. 3 (1), p.4-11. and Behavior, Environment
Space Syntax Symposium, London: Univesrity College Hillier, B. and Hanson, J. (1984), The Social Logic of Space, and Planning B, Journal
of Space Syntax, Journal
London, Vol. 2, p.18.1-18.14. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
of Architecture, Journal
Bafna, S. (2012), ‘The imaginative function of architecture: Hillier, B., Hanson, J. and Peponis, J. (1984), ‘What do of Building Performance
and Simulation, Health En-
A clarification of some conceptual issues’. In: Greene, we mean by building function?’ In: Powell, J.A. and
vironment and Research
M., Reyes, J. and Castro, A. (eds.), Proceedings of Cooper, I. and Lera, S., (eds.), Designing for building Design, and the Journal of
the Eighth International Space Syntax Symposium, utilisation, p.61-72, London, UK: E & F.N. Spon Ltd. the Society of Architectural
Historians. His research
Santiago de Chile: PUC, p.8117.1-8117.19. Hillier, B., Hanson, J. and Graham, H. (1987), ‘Ideas are has been sponsored by the
Bafna, S. (2001), ‘The geometrical intuition of genotypes’. in things: An application of the space syntax method General Services Adminis-
tration, Steelcase, Ascen-
In: Peponis, J., Wineman, J. and Bafna, S. (eds.), for discovering house genotypes’. In: Environment and sion Health, and Kaiser
Proceedings of the Third International Space Syntax Planning B: Planning and Design, Vol. 14, p.363-385. Permanente. He is currently
an associate professor in
Symposium, Atlanta, U.S.A: Georgia Institute of Tech- Keller, C. M. and Keller, J. D. (1996), Cognition and Tool
architecture at Georgia
nology, p.20.1-20.16. Use: The blacksmith at work, Cambridge: Cambridge Institute of Technology.
Bafna, S. (1999), ‘The morphology of open plan residen- University Press.
tial designs: Geometry and genotype in the work of Lewontin, R. (2011), ‘The genotype/phenotype distinction’.
Mies van der Rohe’. In: Major, M. D. and Amorim, L. In: Edward, N. Z. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of
(eds.), Proceedings of the Second International Space Philosophy (Summer 2011 edition). Available at: <
Syntax Symposium, Brazilia: Universidade de Brasilia, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/
p.22.1-22.18. genotype-phenotype/ > [Accessed 23 May 2011].
Bandini, M. (1984), ‘Typology as a form of convention’. In: Moneo, R. (1978), ‘On typology’. In: Oppositions, Vol. 13,
AA Files, Vol. 6, p.73-82. p.23-45.
Conroy Dalton, R. and Kirsan, C. (2007), ‘Small-graph Rosch, E. and Lloyd, B. (1978), Cognition and Categoriza-
matching and building genotypes’. In: Environment and tion, Hillsdale: Erlbaum.
Planning B: Planning and Design, Vol. 35, p.810-30. Rossi, A. (1982), The Architecture of the City, Cambridge,
D’Andrade, R. (1995), The Development of Cognitive An- MA: The MIT Press.
thropology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Newton, M. (1992), Architects’ London Houses, London:
Glassie, H. (1975), Folk Housing in Middle Virginia, Knox- Butterworth.
ville: University of Tennessee Press. Steadman, J. P. (1979), The Evolution of Designs: Bio-
Hanson, J. (1998), Chapter Eight ‘ The anatomy of privacy logical Analogy in Architecture and the Applied Arts,
in architects’ London houses’. In: Decoding Homes Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
and Houses, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
p.215-241.

80

Potrebbero piacerti anche