Boethius
The Consolations of Music, Logic, Theology, and Philosophy
Henry Chadwick
Preface
HILARIAE
FILIAE DILECTISSIMAE
Born fifteen hundred years ago (within a reasonable approximation), Boethius wrote one of the dazzling
masterpieces of European literature. But he has been seldom studied as a whole, and has been seen more through
the eyes of those whom he influenced than in relation to the writers whom he had read and who influenced him.
The purpose of this book is to see the man in the setting of his own turbulent and tormented age, not to trace his
large posterity in thought and literature. Moreover, the latter concern predominates in the collection of studies on
Boethius by various authors, including myself, edited by Dr Margaret Gibson (Blackwell, 1981). Much is also said
of that in the studies of Boethius by Pierre Courcelle (1967). Modern reappraisal of Boethius, especially since the
work of Klingner (1921) and Courcelle (1948), has concentrated on his debt to the late Platonists of Athens and
especially of Alexandria. The present book continues that line, and adds fresh Neoplatonist evidence for the
interpretation of the five tractates on Christian theology. On the other side, I have also found more affinity with
Augustine than has been generally recognized, and therefore conclude with a portrait of Boethius simultaneously
more deeply Neoplatonic and more deeply Augustinian than has been acknowledged. I have also tried to integrate
the various constituent elements in his intellectual achievement. The substructure of the Consolation of Philosophy
is only clear when one has also seen something of his arithmetic, music, and logic, the last being the grand
obsession of his mind. It is then possible to make a fresh attack on the question of his religious allegiance, debated
since the tenth century when Bovo of Corvey asked how the evidently
Contents
Abbreviations ix
Chronological Table x
Introduction xi
I
Romans and Goths 1
1
Culture and the Public Service
6
Symmachus
16
The Neoplatonic Schools
22
Out of the Ivory Tower: John the Deacon
29
The Hard Road to Church Unity: the Acacian and Laurentian Schisms
46
Master of the Offices
56
The Collapse of Toleration
66
Boethius' Sacrifice
II
Liberal Arts in the Collapse of Culture 69
71
Arithmetic
78
Music
84
Boethius' Treatise on Music and its Sources
102
Geometry and Astronomy
III
Logic 108
108
Part of Philosophy or a Tool of all Philosohy?
111
Logic and Rhetoric
120
Porphyry
127
Neoplatonists after Porphyry: Iamblichus, Syrianus, Proclus, Ammonius
131
Boethius' commentaries on the Isagoge
133
Translator of Aristotle
141
The Ten Categories
152
On Interpretation
157
Future Contingents
163
The Monographs on Logic
166
Propositional Logic and the Hypothetical Syllogism
IV
Christian Theology and the Philosophers 174
175
Faith and History; De Fide Catholica
180
The Person of Christ
185
The Scythian Monks
190
Nature and Person
203
Absolute and Relative Goodness
211
God the Trinity
V
Evil, Freedom, and Providence 223
225
The Lady Philosophy
228
From Stoic Moralism to Platonic Transcendence
234
O Qui Perpetua
235
Degrees of Perfection: the Quest for the One
237
Reminiscence: Natural Theology and the Bible
239
The Problem of Evil
242
Providence and Fate
244
Divine Foreknowledge and Free Will
247
The Religion of Boethius
Preservation and Transmission 254
Editions 258
Bibliography 261
Notes 285
Index 307
Abbreviations
Chronological Table
SECULAR RULERS
East Roman emperors Barbarian kings of Italy
Marcian 450-7
Leo I 457-74
Leo II 474 Odovacar 476-93
Zeno (first time) 474-5
Basiliscus 475-6
Zeno (second time) 476-91 Theoderic 493-526
Anastasius I 491-518
Justin I 518-27
Justinian 527-65 Athnalaric 526-34
(Amalasuintha regent 526-35)
BISHOPS
Rome Constantinople Alexandria
Leo I 440-61 Flavian 446-9 Cyril 412-44
Hilarus 461-8 Anatolius 449-58 Dioscorus 444-51 (d. 454)
Gennadius I 458-
Simplicius 468-83 71 Proterius 451-7
Felix III 483-92 Acacius 472-89
Timothy Aelurus (first) 457-60 (Monophysite)
Gelasius I 492-6 Fravitas 489-90
Timothy Salofaciolus (first) 460-75
(Chalcedonian)
Euphemius 490-6
Anastasius II 496-8 (exiled)
Timothy Aelurus (second) 475-7
Symmachus 498- Macedonius II Peter Mongos (first) 477 31 July-4 Sept. 477
514 496-511 (Monophysite)
(Laurentius 498, (exiled)
501-6)
Hormisdas 514-23 Timothy I 511-18
Timothy Salofaciolus (second) 477-82
John I 523-6
John II the John Talaia June-Dec. 482 (Chalcedonian)
Cappadocian 518-
20
Felix IV 526-30 Epiphanius 520-35
Peter Mongos (second) 482-9
Boniface II 530-2 Thereafter a Monophysite succession at
(Dioscorus 22 Alexandria; no Chalcedonian until 537.
Sept.-14 Oct. 530)
PHILOSOPHERS
Ptolemy (Claudius Ptolemaeus) fl. AD 127-48
Nicomachus of Gerasa fl. c.150
Apuleius (Carthage) 123-c.180
Alexander of Aphrodisias (Athens) fl. c.200
Plotinus (Rome) 205-70
Porphyry of Tyre (Rome, Sicily) c.250-c.305
Iamblichus (Syria) c.250-c.325
Marius Victorinus (Rome) c.285-c.370
Syrianus (Athens) d. 437
Hierocles (Alexandria and Constantinople) fl. c.440-70
Proclus (Athens) 412-85
Ammonius son of Hermias (Alexandria) c.436-517 (or 445-526)
Martianus Capella (Carthage) fl. c.470 (?)
Damascius (Athens) fl. c.490-c.537-38
Simplicius (Alexandria, Athens) fl. 515-45 or later
Philoponus (Alexandria), Christian pupil of Ammonius c.490-c.570
Elias fl. c.550-c.600
Introduction
`LAST of the Romans, first of the scholastics': the tag echoes a famous judgement on Boethius by the humanist
Lorenzo Valla in the fifteenth century. Valla saw in Boethius a man whose diction and philosophy were touched by
barbarisms but nevertheless allowed him a claim to be the last classical writer in the Latin tongue. Renaissance
humanism mixed its admiration for Boethius with the expression of occasional misgivings. Did his concept of
education allow a sufficient place to literary values? Granted that he adorned the Consolation of Philosophy with a
series of poems including some of real distinction, yet his prose is another matter; and he makes it clear that for
him philosophy and theology are altogether more serious than the pleasures of the Muses who, in Platonic fashion,
receive discourteous treatment in his pages. Renaissance men could also come to feel constricted by Boethius'
writings on arithmetic, music, and dialectic which dominated the medieval schools. His studies in dialectic had in
fact long been the object of mingled admiration and dislike, as one may see in John of Salisbury's Metalogicon of
1159, itself a classic of the twelfth-century renaissance. It was not, of course, a new thing in the fifteenth century
that literary humanists should feel irritated by rigorous training in dialectic which could end by producing tiresome
young nit-pickers who made the subject seem trivial.
As an educator Boethius consistently believes practice to be far less important than theory. His educational ideal is
intended to produce men of understanding rather than of practical action and technique. The disciplines of moral
philosophy, politics, and economics were held in respect and no doubt counted for much in public and political
life; but the purer mental skills for Boethius, as for the Platonic schools of his time, lie in the natural sciences,
mathematics, and metaphysics. And by the study of the natural sciences Boethius really meant the philosophical
questions discussed in Aristotle's Physics (e.g. the nature of change, causation and necessity, the infinite, the
definition of place and of time, the Prime Mover) or De caelo, on the heavenly bodies, or De generatione et
corrup-
I
Romans and Goths
Symmachus
Symmachus' eminence in Italian society as an arbiter of literary excellence is illustrated by the dedication to him of
three works on Latin rhetoric by Priscian,21 resident at Constantinople, who hoped to attract Symmachus'
patronage on a visit that the senator paid to Byzantium about 500, probably as Theoderic's ambassador to the
Byzantine court. In the West the ambitious, place-hunting Ennodius who, like Boethius, owed his upbringing and
education to rich family friends, also dedicated to Symmachus a short tract written about 511 advising two aspiring
young men, Ambrosius and Beatus, how to get on in society.22 The tract ends with a request in verse to further
Ennodius' own career. In alternating prose and verse Ennodius counsels the youths to love God and their
neighbour, to study modesty, chastity, faith, grammar, and above all rhetoric. So they should follow the eloquence
of the living masters in the present senate. And Ennodius names Faustus Niger (consul 490), his son Avienus (cos.
502) now at Ravenna; Festus (cos. 472) and Symmachus (cos. 485) at Rome; or Probinus (cos. 489) and his son
Cethegus (cos. 504), the brilliant young Boethius (cos. 510), Agapitus (cos. 517) and Probus (cos. 525). Or if they
seek feminine exemplars, there is Barbara the very flower of the Roman spirit, or Stephania (Faustus' sister,
The Hard Road to Church Unity: the Acacian and Laurentian Schisms 44
Since the Council of Chalcedon (451) ecclesiastical dissension had come to have social and political consequences
for
Boethius' Sacrifice
A question that the historian is left asking at the end of the narrative is how far Justinian foresaw the outcome, so
greatly
II
Liberal Arts in the Collapse of Culture
Aristotle observes in the Categories that if something is to be known, it must be knowable; conversely something
can be knowable without anyone actually knowing it, either because it has not yet been discovered (such as the
method for squaring the circle) or because it has sadly been forgotten and then by much effort needs to be
rediscovered. This last observation fascinated Boethius, and his commentary on this passage treats it as a word for
his own times. It is his great fear that amid the general collapse of higher studies in his time, the knowledge
acquired by the philosophers and scientists of classical Greece may simply be obliterated by a failure in
transmission. 1 Books may lie in libraries but, if they are to survive for more than a generation, they need users
who understand and value their contents or they will rapidly suffer from neglect, and the valuable space they
occupy will be applied to other purposes. `It is one thing to have reason, another to use it', he writes. `To abandon
the stretching of one's mind's power is to lose it.' Or, with a sharper point, `Men who have long been idle in using
their minds adopt positions from which they never move, and learn nothing until their old age.'2
The Latin world possessed good guides in grammar and in rhetoric. In the middle of the fourth century Jerome
himself had been among those who sat at the feet of the famous grammarian Donatus whose works have been
preserved. Donatus seemed to Boethius a scholar and teacher fit to be compared with the great Alexandrian scholar
Aristarchus in the Greek world. Moreover, his own contemporary Priscian, who taught a more advanced grammar
than that of Donatus, was busy teaching Latin at Constantinople, dedicating works on style to Boethius' father-in-
law, and composing treatises on Latin grammar which became indispensable in medieval schoolrooms. In rhetoric
there was the incomparable model of Cicero, whose treatises on rhetoric explained the tricks of the
Arithmetic
Nicomachus of Gerasa (Jerash in northern Jordan, a few miles south-east of the Sea of Galilee) lived in the middle
of the second century AD and took Pythagoras as his guide to life. He wrote a tract on the Pythagorean order of
daily living, later used by Porphyry and especially by Iamblichus. 3 In this tract Pythagoras' life and wonder-
working career are held up as an example of moral and personal discipline; for Pythagoras suffered
misunderstanding and attack, descended to the underworld and returned, and called an intimate group of disciples
to observe ritual instructions, to heed his gnomic maxims, and to begin and end each day with special chants and
prayers of self-examination.
Nicomachus' Introduction to Arithmetic achieved the status of being a standard textbook in the Neoplatonic schools
of Athens and Alexandria. The work survives in its original Greek. First printed at Paris, 1538, it was last edited by
Hoche in the Teubner series (1866), and has received an English translation and full commentary by M.L. D'Ooge,
F.E. Robbins and L.C. Karpinski (1926 repr. 1972). It received commentaries, also extant, from Iamblichus in the
fourth century, from Asclepius of Tralles, and from Philoponus in the
Music
The Pythagoreans had a high reputation for their researches in number-theory and music.11 They first discovered
that the relative pitch of musical sounds depends on the lengths of
The group of numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, whose sum is 10, give a perfect triangle (according to the modern
algebraic formula for triangular numbers 1/2n(n+1)).
For Pythagoreanism it is no mere social convention or the fact that we count on our fingers that leads all people to
divide
The figures for the internal intervals are computed first for the diatonic genus by calculating the two descending
whole tones in 9:8 proportion. Nine-eighths of 2304 is 2592, and
From Hypate (A) to Paramese (H) and from Mese (G) to Nete hyperboleon (O) are octaves, Boethius notes. He
carelessly
III
Logic
Porphyry
Aristotle's logic was notorious in antiquity for its difficulty to
Translator of Aristotle 45
Boethius approached both Plato and Aristotle with deep rever-
That is to say, four links are possible: substance (which is of but not in a subject) and accident (in but not of a
subject) can either be universal or be individual and particular.
Porphyry's Question and Answer commentary remarks that Aristotle's division is `chiastic' (78, 36) which suggests
that a diagram could originally have been attached to this text to illustrate the point. The diagram is a regular part
of the school convention. It reappears in Philoponus' commentary on the Categories (28, 25). A development of a
similar diagrammatic scheme was developed to become the Pons Asinorum of the medieval logicians.
With chapter 5 Aristotle reaches the concept of substance: `primary' substance for individuals, `secondary'
substance when referring to the species and genera which contain the individuals. For Aristotle the particular is
prior to the universal. We infer the species man and the genus animal only from our knowledge of those particular
instances that share
On Interpretation
The most extended single work from Boethius' pen is his double exposition of Aristotle's difficult treatise `On
Interpretation', which the early editors of the Peripatetic school placed second in the Organon after the Categories.
Aristotle's study of the logic of the simple proposition and of modal sentences containing the words `necessary' and
`possible' was famous in antiquity and later for causing headaches in its interpreters. The commentaries by Boethius
and Ammonius are the principal ancient survivors of a rich exegetical mine. The commentaries by Stephanus (CAG
XVIII, 3) and Proba (extant only in Syriac) depend on Ammonius and have no independent value. A little light,
however, to illuminate Boethius' relation to his sources can occasionally be derived from the tenth-century
commentary and treatise by the Arab philosopher of Baghdad, Al-Farabi. His work is now translated into English
by F.W. Zimmermann (1981).
About AD 200 Alexander of Aphrodisias felt the impulse to write a commentary on the problematic work in
consequence, he says (Boethius ii, 3), of the bewildering disagreements of the exegetes. Porphyry (Boethius ii, 293,
27) declares that in his
The purpose of the diagram is to illustrate where contradictions lie. A particular negation is contradictory of a
universal affirmation, a universal negative of a particular affirmative.
Concerning the indefinite proposition `A man is (or is not) white', where there is no quantifier, Boethius reports
Alexander's opinion that since it is reducible either to a particular or to a universal, it can carry opposite meanings.
But he then prefers Porphyry's subtle analysis of negative indefinite propositions which include the contrary of the
affirmation which they deny, e.g. `a man is not white' may mean `a man is black' (Boethius ii, 159). Boethius
concludes that the indefinite has the force of the particular (ii, 172 cf. Syll. Cat. i, 802D). He rejects Syrianus'
opinion, which he supported by texts from both Plato and Aristotle, that an indefinite negative has the
Future Contingents
The famous ninth chapter of Aristotle, De interpretatione, provokes from Boethius the observation that it touches
on matters too deep for a textbook of mere logic. Many questions in it converge with the treatment of possibility in
the Prior Analytics. 62
Events of the past or present cannot be reversed and so are `necessary'. There are also constants about the physical
world which are `necessary' because they are always the case, even if we cannot always know about them, as, for
example, whether the number of the stars is even or odd; they must be one or the other, but which we cannot
know. (Boethius confuses `they must be either one or the other' with `whichever they are is subject to necessity'.)
There are other constants such as the rising and setting of the sun, the property of fire to give heat as long as it
burns, the indelible rationality of humanity. Other things are `contingent'; that is, they need not necessarily be as
they are but could be otherwise. `Contingent' Boethius explains as meaning that the likelihood of a thing being one
thing rather than another is equal, and here wants to distinguish it from what is possible but very unusual and from
what is usual but not invariable, e.g. if a man's hair fails to whiten in
But the Stoics correctly regarded a proposition as possible if and only if its negation is non-necessary, and
impossible if and only if its negation is necessary. The scheme is therefore a square of opposition:
IV
Christian Theology and the Philosophers
Five tractates of varying length dealing with questions of theology are transmitted by the manuscripts, often in
association with the Consolation of Philosophy, but in many cases independently. The first three and fifth of these
pieces attempt tersely to disentangle some of the central logical problems besetting the traditional language of the
Latin churches. These tractates attracted great interest from medieval commentators from the ninth century
onwards, culminating in masterful discussions of the first and third from the pen of St. Thomas Aquinas. Although
the third contains nothing specifically Christian, the remainder discuss fundamental questions of Church
Dogmaticsthe Trinity and the Person of Christand can only have been written by a Christian thinker with a special
interest in logical questions. At one time it was customary to contrast the Christian opuscula with the pagan
Consolation, and to propose the hypothesis of two different authors, perhaps of the same name. In the tenth century
Bovo of Corvey considered this possibility, but rightly rejected it on stylistic grounds. In the modern period the
hypothesis was favoured in the eighteenth and especially the nineteenth centuries, going back to Gottfried Arnold's
highly prejudiced `Impartial Church History to the Year 1688' (1700), I, vi, 3, 7. The most elaborate statement
advocating this hypothesis was advanced by Nitzsch in 1860, but has long been seen to rest on radical
misunderstandings. Today it is accepted by all scholars who have given attention to the subject that the careful
Neoplatonic logician who, in the first three and fifth tractates, seeks to unravel logical tangles in the usage of the
Church, is none other than the author of the Consolation and of the commentaries on Aristotle, with which they
manifest numerous parallels in thought and diction. It has come to be acknowledged, and will be made clear
beyond a peradventure in the present chapter, that the tractates, other than the fourth,
V
Evil, Freedom, and Providence
Since the Renaissance, and especially since the scientific revolution of the seventeenth century altered our
understanding of the nature and structure of our environment, Boethius has come to seem a rather lonely and
forgotten foreigner in a world grown strange. Yet something of that isolation belongs to him even during his
lifetime, and never more so than in the near dereliction of the imprisonment during which he wrote the Consolation
of Philosophy. 1 By common consent this remains one of the high masterpieces of European literature, translated
since early mediaeval times into many languages; a work whose English translators alone include King Alfred,
Geoffrey Chaucer, and Queen Elizabeth I; a dominant force (with Thomas Aquinas) in the making of Dante's mind.
The Consolation is the work of a refined humanist scholar with a richly stocked memory, delighting in lyrical
poetry and elegant prose, fascinated by logical problems almost to the point of obsession. In Theoderic's prison at
Pavia he knew that his time was limited (iv, 6, 5), but he evidently had more than sufficient leisure to produce
polished composition and a sophisticated structure. The work has a Virgilian quality in being almost a mosaic of
subtle literary allusions. Joachim Gruber's commentary (1978) marks a signal advance in the identification of his
literary echoes, but also makes it clear that he is not transcribing sources. This is not a man composing with a
library of books open before him, but a very well-read mind which can recall a phrase from here or from there at
will. His Latin is densely packed with concentrated argument; and the argument is carried on from the prose
sections into the poems which he inserts, he says (iv, 6, 57), with the intention of lightening the reader's task with a
difficult subject. The poems normally have subtle links with the prose sections that precede or follow them.
The method of mixing prose and verse had been practised by
O Qui Perpetua
In the 38 hexameters of O qui perpetua Boethius fashioned an exquisite poem of petition to the Creator. It is a
nodal point in the work as a whole, and Boethius knew it. An acute observation in the recent commentary by
Joachim Gruber (1978) has noted that the various metres of the poems in the Consolation are grouped in an
ordered and symmetrical structure round O qui perpetua which occupies a central position. This shows, in passing,
that there is no good reason to embrace speculations that something is likely to have been lost at the end of the last
book.
Boethius' ecstatic hymn is reminiscent of the Neoplatonic hymns on cosmic theology characteristic of Synesius and
Proclus. The ideas of the hymn are derived both from Plato and from Proclus' commentary. This was established by
Klingner (1921). The Creator, himself at rest, is cause of motion to everything (Proclus, In Tim. i, 396, 24 f., a
theme going back to Aristotle's Metaphysics). Boethius will repeat this in prose at iii, 12, 37. God is moved to
create by his own goodness (Tim. 29e), not by any external cause. In creating he realized a heavenly pattern,
forming the cosmos in beauty and perfection (30b). Taking a theme also expounded in his Institutio musica (i, 2)
Boethius says that God binds the world's elements together on mathematical principles, `by numbers' (Tim. 31c
`analogia', or proportion). Thus he keeps the equilibrium of cold and hot, dry and wet (31bc). So also he binds the
worldsoul in its harmonious parts (per consona membra) and gives it a threefold structure (35ab; 37a), set in the
middle of the cosmos (36e) to move all things (as Plato's Laws 896e, Phaedrus 245c). Proclus (In Tim. ii, 197, 16)
says that the Creator `divides the Soul among the various parts, fits together the diverse elements and makes them
consonant with one another'.
This divided Soul is split into two, each part to move in a circle (Tim. 36bc) so as to return upon itselfa theme very