Sei sulla pagina 1di 19

Suggested Readings for Pragmatist Social Science seminar

Recommended by Jerry Rosiek

Two years ago I made a presentation at the institute in which I made the case that pragmatist
philosophy, unlike some other major philosophical traditions, had not generated a unique and
detailed methodology of social science inquiry. I offered that there was much within the
pragmatist philosophical tradition that could inform new social science research methodological
practices. And I called on pragmatists philosophers to engage with social science
methodologists in an effort to envision new research methodologies and practices.

In my brief presentation at this years institute, I will outline some of the features I think such a
methodology would have. The first reading I recommend in preparation for this conversation is
John Deweys classic essay The Development of American Pragmatism. This essay examines
the way Peirce, James, and Dewey understood the role of action and the future in the
pragmatist ontology of consequences. To this is appended a short excerpt from Chapter 5 of
Jane Addams Democracy and Social Ethics in which she talks about the folly of a philanthropic
idealism that does not recognize the need for conceptions of social improvement to be
democratically shared, even at the risk of profaning the ideal. Finally, included as a separate
document is Cornel Wests essayPragmatism and the Tragic, in which he deploys Royces
concept of the absolute in an effort to talk about conceptions of loss when considering a
pragmatist doctrine of consequences.

Page lw.2.3

The Development of American Pragmatism

The purpose of this article is to define the principal theories of the philosophical
movements known under the names of Pragmatism, Instrumentalism, or Experimentalism. To
do this we must trace their historical development; for this method seems to present the
simplest way of comprehending these movements and at the same time avoiding certain
current misunderstandings of their doctrines and their aims.

The origin of Pragmatism goes back to Charles Sanders Peirce, the son of one of the
most celebrated mathematicians of the United States, and himself very proficient in the science
of mathematics; he is one of the founders of the modern symbolic logic of relations.
Unfortunately Peirce was not at all a systematic writer and never expounded his ideas in a single
system. The pragmatic method which he developed applies only to a very narrow and limited
universe of discourse. After William James had extended the scope of the method, Peirce wrote
an exposition of the origin of pragmatism as he had first conceived it; it is from this exposition
that we take the following passages.

The term "pragmatic," contrary to the opinion of those who regard pragmatism as an
exclusively American conception, was suggested to him by the study of Kant. In the Metaphysic
of Morals Kant established a distinction between pragmatic and practical. The latter term
applies to moral laws which Kant regards as a priori, whereas the former term applies to the
rules of art and technique which are based on experience and are applicable to experience.
Peirce, who was an empiricist, with the habits of mind, as he put it, of the laboratory,
consequently refused to call his system "practicalism," as some of his friends suggested. As a
logician he was interested in the art and [Page lw.2.4] technique of real thinking, and especially
interested, as far as pragmatic method is concerned, in the art of making concepts clear, or of
construing adequate and effective definitions in accord with the spirit of scientific method.

Following his own words, for a person "who still thought in Kantian terms most readily,
'praktisch' and 'pragmatisch' were as far apart as the two poles; the former belonging in a
region of thought where no mind of the experimental type can ever make sure of solid ground
under his feet, the latter expressing relation to some definite human purpose. Now quite the
most striking feature of the new theory was its recognition of an inseparable connection
between rational cognition and rational purpose."1

In alluding to the experimental type of mind, we are brought to the exact meaning given
by Peirce to the word "pragmatic." In speaking of an experimentalist as a man whose
intelligence is formed in the laboratory, he said: "Whatever assertion you may make to him, he
will either understand as meaning that if a given prescription for an experiment ever can be and
ever is carried out in act, an experience of a given description will result, or else he will see no
sense at all in what you say." And thus Peirce developed the theory that "the rational purport of
a word or other expression, lies exclusively in its conceivable bearing upon the conduct of life;
so that, since obviously nothing that might not result from experiment can have any direct
bearing upon conduct, if one can define accurately all the conceivable experimental phenomena
which the affirmation or denial of a concept could imply, one will have therein a complete
definition of the concept."2

The essay in which Peirce developed his theory bears the title: "How to Make Our Ideas
Clear."3 There is a remarkable similarity here to Kant's doctrine. Peirce's effort was to interpret
the universality of concepts in the domain of experience in the same way in which Kant
established the law of practical reason in thedomain of the a priori. "The rational meaning of
everyproposition lies in the future. . . . But of the myriads of forms intowhich a proposition may
be translated, what is that one which isto be called its very meaning? It is, according to the
pragmatist,[Page lw.2.5]that form in which the proposition becomes applicable to
humanconduct, not in these or those special circumstances, nor whenone entertains this or
that special design, but that form which ismost directly applicable to self-control under every
situation,and to every purpose."4 So also, "the pragmatist does not makethe summumbonum
to consist in action, but makes it to consistin that process of evolution whereby the existent
comes moreand more to embody generals . . ."5--in other wordstheprocess whereby the
existent becomes, with the aid of action, abody of rational tendencies or of habits generalized
as much aspossible. These statements of Peirce are quite conclusive withrespect to two errors
which are commonly committed in regard tothe ideas of the founder of pragmatism. It is often
said ofpragmatism that it makes action the end of life. It is also said ofpragmatism that it
subordinates thought and rational activity toparticular ends of interest and profit. It is true that
the theoryaccording to Peirce's conception implies essentially a certainrelation to action, to
human conduct. But the role of action is thatof an intermediary. In order to be able to attribute
a meaning toconcepts, one must be able to apply them to existence. Now it isby means of
action that this application is made possible. Andthe modification of existence which results
from this applicationconstitutes the true meaning of concepts. Pragmatism is,therefore, far
from being that glorification of action for its own sakewhich is regarded as the peculiar
characteristic of American life.

It is also to be noted that there is a scale of possibleapplications of concepts to


existence, and hence a diversity ofmeanings. The greater the extension of the concepts, the
more they arefreed from the restrictions which limit them to particular cases,the more is it
possible for us to attribute the greatest generality ofmeaning to a term. Thus the theory of
Peirce is opposed to everyrestriction of the meaning of a concept to the achievement of
aparticular end, and still more to a personal aim. It is still morestrongly opposed to the idea that
reason or thought should bereduced to being a servant of any interest which is pecuniary
ornarrow. This theory was American in its origin in so far as itinsisted on the necessity of human
conduct and the fulfillment of[Page lw.2.6]some aim in order to clarify thought. But at the same
time, itdisapproves of those aspects of American life which make actionan end in itself, and
which conceive ends too narrowly and too"practically." In considering a system of philosophy in
itsrelation to national factors it is necessary to keep in mind not onlythe aspects of life which
are incorporated in the system, but alsothe aspects against which the system is a protest. There
neverwas a philosopher who has merited the name for the simplereason that he glorified the
tendencies and characteristics of hissocial environment; just as it is also true that there never
has been aphilosopher who has not seized upon certain aspects of the lifeof his time and
idealized them.

The work commenced by Peirce was continued by WilliamJames. In one sense James
narrowed the application of Peirce'spragmatic method, but at the same time he extended it.
Thearticles which Peirce wrote in 1878 commanded almost no attentionfrom philosophical
circles, which were then under thedominating influence of the neo-Kantian idealism of Green,
of Caird, andof the Oxford School, excepting those circles in which theScottish philosophy of
common sense maintained its supremacy. In1898 James inaugurated the new pragmatic
movement in anaddress entitled, "Philosophical Conceptions and PracticalResults," later
reprinted in the volume, Collected Essays andReviews. Even in this early study one can easily
notice the presenceof those two tendencies to restrict and at the same time to extendearly
pragmatism. After having quoted the psychological remark of Peirce that "beliefs are really rules
for action, and the wholefunction of thinking is but one step in the production of habitsof
action," and that every idea which we frame for ourselves ofan object is really an idea of the
possible effects of that object, heexpressed the opinion that all these principles could be
expressedmore broadly than Peirce expressed them. "The ultimate test forus of what a truth
means is indeed the conduct it dictates orinspires. But it inspires that conduct because it first
foretells someparticular turn to our experience which shall call for just thatconduct from us.
And I should prefer to express Peirce'sprinciple by saying that the effective meaning of any
philosophicproposition can always be brought down to some particularconsequence, in our
future practical experience, whether active orpassive; the point lying rather in the fact that the
experience[Page lw.2.7]must be particular, than in the fact that it must be active."6 In anessay
written in 1908 James repeats this statement and states thatwhenever he employs the term
"the practical," he means byit, "the distinctively concrete, the individual, the particularand
effective as opposed to the abstract, general and inert--'Pragmata' are things in their plurality
particularconsequences can perfectly well be of a theoretic nature."7

William James alluded to the development which he gave toPeirce's expression of the
principle. In one sense one can say thathe enlarged the bearing of the principle by the
substitution ofparticular consequences for the general rule or methodapplicable to future
experience. But in another sense this substitutionlimited the application of the principle since it
destroyed theimportance attached by Peirce to the greatest possible applicationof the rule, or
the habit of conduct--its extension to universality.That is to say, William James was much more
of a nominalistthan Peirce.

One can notice an extension of pragmatism in the abovepassage. James there alludes to
the use of a method of determiningthe meaning of truth. Since truth is a term and has
consequentlya meaning, this extension is a legitimate application of pragmaticmethod. But it
should be remarked that here this method servesonly to make clear the meaning of the term
"truth," and hasnothing to do with the truth of a particular judgment. Theprincipal reason
which led James to give a new color to pragmaticmethod was that he was preoccupied with
applying the methodto determine the meaning of philosophical problems andquestions and
that moreover, he chose to submit to examination[Page lw.2.8]philosophical notions of a
theological or religious nature. He wishedto establish a criterion which would enable one to
determinewhether a given philosophical question has an authentic andvital meaning or
whether, on the contrary, it is trivial and purelyverbal; and in the former case, what interests are
at stake, whenone accepts and affirms one or the other of two theses in dispute.Peirce was
above all a logician; whereas James was an educatorand humanist and wished to force the
general public to realizethat certain problems, certain philosophical debates have a
realimportance for mankind, because the beliefs which they bringinto play lead to very different
modes of conduct. If thisimportant distinction is not grasped, it is impossible to understand
themajority of the ambiguities and errors which belong to the laterperiod of the pragmatic
movement.

James took as an example the controversy between theism andmaterialism. It follows


from this principle that if the course ofthe world is considered as completed, it is equally
legitimate toassert that God or matter is its cause. Whether one way or theother, the facts are
what they are, and it is they which determinewhatever meaning is to be given to their cause.
Consequently thename which we can give to this cause is entirely arbitrary. It isentirely different
if we take the future into account. God then hasthe meaning of a power concerned with
assuring the finaltriumph of ideal and spiritual values, and matter becomes a powerindifferent
to the triumph or defeat of these values. And our lifetakes a different direction according as we
adopt one or theother of these alternatives. In the lectures on pragmatismpublished in 1907, he
applies the same criticism to the philosophicalproblem of the One and the Many, that is to say
of Monism andPluralism, as well as to other questions. Thus he shows thatMonism is equivalent
to a rigid universe where everything is fixedand immutably united to others, where
indetermination, freechoice, novelty, and the unforeseen in experience have no place;a
universe which demands the sacrifice of the concrete andcomplex diversity of things to the
simplicity and nobility of anarchitectural structure. In what concerns our beliefs,
Monismdemands a rationalistic temperament leading to a fixed anddogmatic attitude.
Pluralism, on the other hand, leaves room forcontingence, liberty, novelty, and gives complete
liberty of actionto the empirical method, which can be indefinitely extended. It[Page
lw.2.9]accepts unity where it finds it, but it does not attempt to force thevast diversity of events
and things into a single rational mold.

From the point of view of an educator or of a student or, if youwill, of those who are
thoroughly interested in these problems,in philosophical discussions and controversies, there is
no reasonfor contesting the value of this application of pragmatic method,but it is no less
important to determine the nature of thisapplication. It affords a means of discovering the
implications forhuman life of philosophical conceptions which are often treated asof no
importance and of a purely dialectical nature. It furnishes acriterion for determining the vital
implications of beliefs whichpresent themselves as alternatives in any theory. Thus as hehimself
said, "the whole function of philosophy ought to be to findthe characteristic influences which
you and I would undergo at a determinate moment of our lives, if one or the other formula
ofthe universe were true." However, in saying that the wholefunction of philosophy has this
aim, it seems that he is referringrather to the teaching than to the construction of
philosophy.For such a statement implies that the world formulas havealready all been made,
and that the necessary work of producingthem has already been finished, so that there remains
only todefine the consequences which are reflected in life by theacceptance of one or the other
of these formulas as true.

From the point of view of Peirce, the object of philosophywould be rather to give a fixed
meaning to the universe byformulas which correspond to our attitudes or our most
generalhabits of response to the environment; and this generalitydepends on the extension of
the applicability of these formulas tospecific future events. The meaning of concepts of
"matter" andof "God" must be fixed before we can even attempt to reach anunderstanding
concerning the value of our belief in theseconcepts. Materialism would signify that the world
demands on ourpart a single kind of constant and general habits; and God wouldsignify the
demand for another type of habits; the differencebetween materialism and theism would be
tantamount to thedifference in the habits required to face all the detailed facts of theuniverse.
The world would be one in so far as it would bepossible for us to form a single habit of action
which would takeaccount of all future existences and would be applicable to them. Itwould be
many in so far as it is necessary for us to form several[Page lw.2.10]habits, differing from each
other and irreducible to each other, inorder to be able to meet the events in the world and
control them.

In short, Peirce wrote as a logician and James as a humanist.

William James accomplished a new advance in Pragmatism byhis theory of the will to
believe, or as he himself later called it,the right to believe. The discovery of the
fundamentalconsequences of one or another belief has without fail a certaininfluence on that
belief itself. If a man cherishes novelty, risk,opportunity and a variegated esthetic reality, he will
certainly rejectany belief in Monism, when he clearly perceives the import ofthis system. But if,
from the very start, he is attracted by estheticharmony, classic proportions, fixity even to the
extent ofabsolute security and logical coherence, it is quite natural that heshould put faith in
Monism. Thus William James took intoaccount those motives of instinctive sympathy which play
a greaterrole in our choice of a philosophic system than do formalreasonings; and he thought
that we should be rendering a service to thecause of philosophical sincerity if we would openly
recognize themotives which inspire us. He also maintained the thesis that thegreater part of
philosophic problems and especially those whichtouch on religious fields are of such a nature
that they are notsusceptible of decisive evidence one way or the other.Consequently he claimed
the right of a man to choose his beliefs notonly in the presence of proofs or conclusive facts, but
also in theabsence of all such proof. Above all when he is forced to choosebetween one
meaning or another, or when by refusing to choosehe has a right to assume the risks of faith, his
refusal is itselfequivalent to a choice. The theory of the will to believe gives riseto
misunderstandings and even to ridicule; and therefore it isnecessary to understand clearly in
what way James used it. Weare always obliged to act in any case; our actions and with
themtheir consequences actually change according to the beliefswhich we have chosen.
Moreover it may be that, in order todiscover the proofs which will ultimately be the
intellectualjustification of certain beliefs--the belief in freedom, for example, orthe belief in
God--it is necessary to begin to act in accordancewith this belief.

In his lectures on Pragmatism, and in his volume of essaysbearing the title The Meaning
of Truth, which appeared in 1909,James extended the use of the pragmatic method to the
problem[Page lw.2.11]of the nature of truth. So far we have considered the pragmaticmethod
as an instrument in determining the meaning of wordsand the vital importance of philosophic
beliefs. Now and thenwe have made allusion to the future consequences which areimplied.
James showed, among other things, that in certainphilosophic conceptions, the affirmation of
certain beliefs could bejustified by means of the nature of their consequences, or by
thedifferences which these beliefs make in existence. But then whynot push the argument to
the point of maintaining that themeaning of truth in general is determined by its
consequences?We must not forget here that James was an empiricist before hewas a
pragmatist, and repeatedly stated that pragmatism ismerely empiricism pushed to its legitimate
conclusions. From ageneral point of view, the pragmatic attitude consists in "lookingaway from
first things, principles, 'categories,' supposednecessities; and of looking towards last things,
fruits, consequences,facts." It is only one step further to apply the pragmatic methodto the
problem of truth. In the natural sciences there is atendency to identify truth in any particular
case with a verification.The verification of a theory, or of a concept, is carried on by
theobservation of particular facts. Even the most scientific andharmonious physical theory is
merely an hypothesis until itsimplications, deduced by mathematical reasoning or by any
otherkind of inference, are verified by observed facts. What directiontherefore, must an
empirical philosopher take who wishes toarrive at a definition of truth by means of an empirical
method? Hemust, if he wants to apply this method, and without bringing infor the present the
pragmatic formula, first find particular casesfrom which he then generalizes. It is therefore in
submittingconceptions to the control of experience, in the process of verifyingthem, that one
finds examples of what is called truth. Thereforeany philosopher who applies this empirical
method, without theleast prejudice in favor of pragmatic doctrine, can be led toconclude that
truth "means" verification, or if one prefers, thatverification either actual or possible, is the
definition of truth.
In combining this conception of empirical method with thetheory of pragmatism, we
come upon other importantphilosophical results. The classic theories of truth in terms of
thecoherence or compatibility of terms, and of the correspondence ofan idea with a thing,
hereby receive a new interpretation. A[Page lw.2.12]merely mental coherence without
experimental verification doesnot enable us to get beyond the realm of hypothesis. If a notionor
a theory makes pretense of corresponding to reality or to thefacts, this pretense cannot be put
to the test and confirmed orrefuted except by causing it to pass over into the realm of
actionand by noting the results which it yields in the form of theconcrete observable facts to
which this notion or theory leads. If, inacting upon this notion, we are brought to the fact which
itimplies or which it demands, then this notion is true. A theorycorresponds to the facts when it
leads to the facts which are itsconsequences, by the intermediary of experience. And from
thisconsideration the pragmatic generalization is drawn that allknowledge is prospective in its
results, except in the case wherenotions and theories after having been first prospective in
theirapplication, have already been tried out and verified.Theoretically, however, even such
verifications or truths could not beabsolute. They would be based upon practical or
moralcertainty, but they are always subject to being corrected byunforeseen future
consequences or by observed facts which had beendisregarded. Every proposition concerning
truths is really in thelast analysis hypothetical and provisional, although a largenumber of these
propositions have been so frequently verifiedwithout failure that we are justified in using them
as if they wereabsolutely true. But logically absolute truth is an ideal whichcannot be realized,
at least not until all the facts have beenregistered, or as James says "bagged," and until it is no
longerpossible to make other observations and other experiences.

Pragmatism, thus, presents itself as an extension of historicalempiricism, but with this


fundamental difference, that it doesnot insist upon antecedent phenomena but upon
consequentphenomena; not upon the precedents but upon the possibilitiesof action. And this
change in point of view is almostrevolutionary in its consequences. An empiricism which is
content withrepeating facts already past has no place for possibility and forliberty. It cannot find
room for general conceptions or ideas, at leastno more than to consider them as summaries or
records. Butwhen we take the point of view of pragmatism we see thatgeneral ideas have a very
different role to play than that of reportingand registering past experiences. They are the bases
fororganizing future observations and experiences. Whereas, for[Page lw.2.13]empiricism, in a
world already constructed and determined, reason orgeneral thought has no other meaning
than that of summing upparticular cases, in a world where the future is not a mere word,where
theories, general notions, rational ideas haveconsequences for action, reason necessarily has a
constructivefunction. Nevertheless the conceptions of reasoning have only asecondary interest
in comparison with the reality of facts, since theymust be confronted with concrete
observations.8
Pragmatism thus has a metaphysical implication. The doctrineof the value of
consequences leads us to take the future intoconsideration. And this taking into consideration
of the future takesus to the conception of a universe whose evolution is notfinished, of a
universe which is still, in James' term, "in themaking," "in the process of becoming," of a
universe up to a certainpoint still plastic.Consequently reason, or thought, in its more general
sense,has a real, though limited function, a creative, constructivefunction. If we form general
ideas and if we put them in action,consequences are produced which could not be produced
otherwise.Under these conditions the world will be different from what itwould have been if
thought had not intervened. Thisconsideration confirms the human and moral importance of
thought andof its reflective operation in experience. It is therefore not true tosay that James
treated reason, thought and knowledge withcontempt, or that he regarded them as mere
means of gainingpersonal or even social profits. For him reason has a creativefunction, limited
because specific, which helps to make the worldother than it would have been without it. It
makes the worldreally more reasonable; it gives to it an intrinsic value. One willunderstand the
philosophy of James better if one considers it inits totality as a revision of English empiricism, a
revision whichreplaces the value of past experience, of what is already given, bythe future, by
that which is as yet mere possibility.

These considerations naturally bring us to the movementcalled instrumentalism. The


survey which we have just made ofJames' philosophy shows that he regarded conceptions
andtheories purely as instruments which can serve to constitute futurefacts in a specific
manner. But James devoted himself primarilyto the moral aspects of this theory, to the support
which it gaveto "meliorism" and moral idealism, and to the consequenceswhich followed from it
concerning the sentimental value and thebearing of various philosophical systems, particularly
to itsdestructive implications for monistic rationalism and forabsolutism in all its forms. He
never attempted to develop a completetheory of the forms or "structures" and of the logical
operationswhich are founded on this conception. Instrumentalism is anattempt to establish a
precise logical theory of concepts, ofjudgments and inferences in their various forms, by
consideringprimarily how thought functions in the experimentaldeterminations of future
consequences. That is to say, it attempts toestablish universally recognized distinctions and rules
of logic byderiving them from the reconstructive or mediative functionascribed to reason. It
aims to constitute a theory of the generalforms of conception and reasoning, and not of this or
thatparticular judgment or concept related to its own content, or to itsparticular implications.

As far as the historical antecedents of instrumentalism areconcerned, two factors are


particularly important, over andabove this matter of experimental verification which we
havealready mentioned in connection with James. The first of thesetwo factors is psychological,
and the second is a critique of thetheory of knowledge and of logic which has resulted from
thetheory proposed by neo-Kantian idealism and expounded in thelogical writings of such
philosophers as Lotze, Bosanquet, andF. H. Bradley. As we have already said, neo-Kantian
influencewas very marked in the United States during the last decade ofthe nineteenth century.
I myself, and those who havecollaborated with me in the exposition of instrumentalism, began
bybeing neo-Kantians, in the same way that Peirce's point ofdeparture was Kantianism and that
of James was the empiricism of theBritish School.

The psychological tendencies which have exerted an influenceon instrumentalism are of


a biological rather than aphysiological nature. They are, more or less, closely related to the[Page
lw.2.15]important movement whose promoter in psychology has been DoctorJohn Watson and
to which he has given the name ofBehaviourism. Briefly, the point of departure of this theory is
theconception of the brain as an organ for the coordination of sensestimuli (to which one
should add modifications caused by habit,unconscious memory, or what are called today
"conditionedreflexes") for the purpose of effecting appropriate motorresponses. On the basis of
the theory of organic evolution it ismaintained that the analysis of intelligence and of its
operationsshould be compatible with the order of known biological facts,concerning the
intermediate position occupied by the centralnervous system in making possible responses to
the environmentadequate to the needs of the living organism. It is particularlyinteresting to
note that in the Studies in Logical Theory (1903),which was their first declaration, the
instrumentalists recognizedhow much they owed to William James for having forged
theinstruments which they used, while at the same time, in the courseof the studies, the
authors constantly declared their belief in aclose union of the "normative" principles of logic
and the realprocesses of thought, in so far as these are determined by anobjective or biological
psychology and not by an introspectivepsychology of states of consciousness. But it is curious to
note thatthe "instruments" to which allusion is made, are not theconsiderations which were of
the greatest service to James. Theyprecede his pragmatism and it is among some of the pages
of hisPrinciples of Psychology that one must look for them. Thisimportant work (1890) really
developed two distinct theses.

The one is a re-interpretation of introspective psychology, inwhich James denies that


sensations, images and ideas are discreteand in which he replaces them by a continuous stream
which hecalls "the stream of consciousness." This conception necessitatesa consideration of
relations as an immediate part of the field ofconsciousness, having the same status as qualities.
Andthroughout his Psychology James gives a philosophical tinge to thisconception by using it in
criticising the atomism of Locke and ofHume as well as the a-priorism of the synthesis of
rationalprinciples by Kant and his successors, among whom should bementioned in England,
Thomas Hill Green, who was then at theheight of his influence.

The other aspect of his Principles of Psychology is of a[Page lw.2.16]biological nature. It


shows itself in its full force in the criterion whichJames established for discovering the existence
of mind. "Thepursuance of future ends and the choice of means for theirattainment are thus
the mark and criterion of the presence ofmentality in a phenomenon."9 The force of this
criterion is plainlyshown in the chapter on Attention, and its relation to Interestconsidered as
the force which controls it, and its teleologicalfunction of selection and integration; in the
chapter onDiscrimination and Comparison (Analysis and Abstraction), where hediscusses the
way in which ends to be attained and the means forattaining them evoke and control
intellectual analysis; and in thechapter on Conception, where he shows that a general idea is
amode of signifying particular things and not merely anabstraction from particular cases or a
super-empirical function,--that itis a teleological instrument. James then develops this idea in
thechapter on reasoning where he says that "the only meaning ofessence is teleological, and
that classification and conception arepurely teleological weapons of mind."

One might complete this brief enumeration by mentioningalso the chapter of James'
book in which he discusses the Natureof Necessary Truths and the Effects of Experience, and
affirms inopposition to Herbert Spencer, that many of our most importantmodes of perception
and conception of the world of sensibleobjects are not the cumulative products of particular
experience,but rather original biological sports, spontaneous variationswhich are maintained
because of their applicability to concreteexperiences after once having been created. Number,
space,time, resemblance and other important "categories" could havebeen brought into
existence, he says, as a consequence of someparticular cerebral instability, but they could by no
means, havebeen registered on the mind by outside influence. Manysignificant and useless
concepts also arise in the same manner. Butthe fundamental categories have been cumulatively
extended andreinforced because of their value when applied to concreteinstances and things of
experience. It is therefore not the origin ofa concept, it is its application which becomes the
criterion of itsvalue; and here we have the whole of pragmatism in embryo. Aphrase of James'
very well summarizes its import: "the popular[Page lw.2.17]notion that 'Science' is forced on the
mind ab extra, and thatour interests have nothing to do with its constructions, isutterly absurd."

Given the point of view which we have just specified, and theinterest attaching to a
logical theory of conception andjudgment, and there results a theory of the following
description.The adaptations made by inferior organisms, for example theireffective and
coordinated responses to stimuli, becometeleological in man and therefore give occasion to
thought. Reflection isan indirect response to the environment, and the element of, indirection
can itself become great and very complicated. But it hasits origin in biological adaptive
behaviour and the ultimatefunction of its cognitive aspect is a prospective control of
theconditions of the environment. The function of intelligence istherefore not that of copying
the objects of the environment, butrather of taking account of the way in which more effective
andmore profitable relations with these objects may be establishedin the future.
How this point of view has been applied to the theory ofjudgment is too long a story to
be told here. We shall confineourselves here to saying that, in general, the "subject" of a
judgmentrepresents that portion of the environment to which a reactionmust be made; the
predicate represents the possible response orhabit or manner in which one should behave
towards theenvironment; the copula represents the organic and concrete act bywhich the
connection is made between the fact and itssignification; and finally the conclusion, or the
definitive object ofjudgment, is simply the original situation transformed, a situationwhich
implies a change as well in the original subject (includingits mind) as in the environment itself.
The new and harmoniousunity thus attained verifies the bearing of the data which were atfirst
chosen to serve as subject and of the concepts introducedinto the situation during the process
as teleological instrumentsfor its elaboration. Until this final unification is attained
theperceptual data and the conceptual principles, theories, are merelyhypotheses from a logical
point of view. Moreover, affirmationand negation are intrinsically a-logical: they are acts.

Such a summary survey can hardly pretend to be eitherconvincing or suggestive.


However, in noting the points ofresemblance and difference between this phase of pragmatism
and the[Page lw.2.18]logic of neo-Hegelian idealism, we are bringing out a point of great
importance. According to the latter logic, thoughtconstitutes in the last analysis its object and
even the universe. It isnecessary to affirm the existence of a series of forms of
judgment,because our first judgments, which are nearest to sense, succeedin constituting
objects in only a partial and fragmentary fashion,even to the extent of involving in their nature
an element ofcontradiction. There results a dialectic which permits each inferiorand partial type
of judgment to pass into a more complete formuntil we finally arrive at the total judgment
where the thoughtwhich comprehends the entire object or the universe is anorganic whole of
interrelated mental distinctions. It is evident thatthis theory magnifies the role of thought
beyond all proportion.It is an objective and rational idealism which is opposed to anddistinct
from the subjective and perceptual idealism of Berkeley'sschool. Instrumentalism, however,
assigns a positive function tothought, that of reconstituting the present stage of things
insteadof merely knowing it. As a consequence, there cannot be intrinsicdegrees, or a hierarchy
of forms of judgments. Each type has itsown end, and its validity is entirely determined by its
efficacy inthe pursuit of its end. A limited perceptual judgment, adapted tothe situation which
has given it birth, is as true in its place as isthe most complete and significant philosophic or
scientificjudgment. Logic, therefore, leads to a realistic metaphysics in so faras it accepts things
and events for what they are independently ofthought, and to an idealistic metaphysics in so far
as it contendsthat thought gives birth to distinctive acts which modify futurefacts and events in
such a way as to render them morereasonable, that is to say, more adequate to the ends which
we proposefor ourselves. This ideal element is more and more accentuatedby the inclusion
progressively of social factors in humanenvironment over and above natural factors; so that the
needswhich are fulfilled, the ends which are attained are no longer of amerely biological or
particular character, but include also theends and activities of other members of society.

It is natural that continental thinkers should be interested inAmerican philosophy as it


reflects, in a certain sense, Americanlife. Thus it should be clear after this rapid survey of
thehistory of pragmatism that American thought continues Europeanthought. We have
imported our language, our laws, our[Page lw.2.19]institutions, our morals, and our religion
from Europe, and we haveadapted them to the new conditions of our life. The same is trueof
our ideas. For long years our philosophical thought wasmerely an echo of European thought.
The pragmatic movementwhich we have traced in the present essay as well as neo-
realism,behaviourism, the absolute idealism of Royce, the naturalisticidealism of Santayana, are
all attempts at re-adaptation; but theyare not creations de novo. They have their roots in British
andEuropean thought. Since these systems are re-adaptations theytake into consideration the
distinctive traits of the environmentof American life. But as has already been said, they are
notlimited to reproducing what is worn and imperfect in thisenvironment. They do not aim to
glorify the energy and the love ofaction which the new conditions of American life
exaggerated.They do not reflect the excessive mercantilism of American life.Without doubt all
these traits of the environment have not beenwithout a certain influence on American
philosophical thought;our philosophy would not be national or spontaneous if it werenot
subject to this influence. But the fundamental idea which themovements of which we have just
spoken, have attempted toexpress, is the idea that action and opportunity justify
themselvesonly to the degree in which they render life more reasonable andincrease its value.
Instrumentalism maintains in opposition tomany contrary tendencies in the American
environment, thataction should be intelligent and reflective, and that thought shouldoccupy a
central position in life. That is the reason for ourinsistence on the teleological phase of thought
and knowledge. If itmust be teleological in particular and not merely true in theabstract, that is
probably due to the practical element which isfound in all the phases of American life. However
that may be,what we insist upon above all else is that intelligence be regardedas the only
source and sole guarantee of a desirable and happyfuture. It is beyond doubt that the
progressive and unstablecharacter of American life and civilization has facilitated the birth ofa
philosophy which regards the world as being in continuousformation, where there is still place
for indeterminism, for thenew and for a real future. But this idea is not exclusivelyAmerican,
although the conditions of American life have aided thisidea in becoming self-conscious. It is
also true that Americanstend to underestimate the value of tradition and of rationality[Page
lw.2.20]considered as an achievement of the past. But the world has alsogiven proof of
irrationality in the past and this irrationality isincorporated in our beliefs and our institutions.
There are badtraditions as there are good ones: it is always important todistinguish. Our neglect
of the traditions of the past, with whateverthis negligence implies in the way of spiritual
impoverishment ofour life, has its compensation in the idea that the world is re-commencing
and being re-made under our eyes. The future aswell as the past can be a source of interest and
consolation andgive meaning to the present. Pragmatism and instrumentalexperimentalism
bring into prominence the importance of theindividual. It is he who is the carrier of creative
thought, the authorof action, and of its application. Subjectivism is an old story inphilosophy; a
story which began in Europe and not in America.But American philosophy, in the systems which
we haveexpounded, has given to the subject, to the individual mind, apractical rather than an
epistemological function. The individualmind is important because only the individual mind is
the organof modifications in traditions and institutions, the vehicle ofexperimental creation.
One-sided and egoistic individualism inAmerican life has left its imprint on our practices. For
better orfor worse, depending on the point of view, it has transformed theesthetic and fixed
individualism of the old European culture intoan active individualism. But the idea of a society
of individualsis not foreign to American thought; it penetrates even ourcurrent individualism
which is unreflective and brutal. And theindividual which American thought idealises is not an
individual perse, an individual fixed in isolation and set up for himself, but anindividual who
evolves and develops in a natural and humanenvironment, an individual who can be educated.

If I were asked to give an historical parallel to this movementin American thought I


would remind my reader of the Frenchphilosophy of the enlightenment. Everyone knows that
thethinkers who made that movement illustrious were inspired byBacon, Locke, and Newton;
what interested them was theapplication of scientific method and the conclusions of
anexperimental theory of knowledge to human affairs, the critique andreconstruction of beliefs
and institutions. As Hffding writes,they were animated by "a fervent faith in intelligence,
progress,and humanity." And certainly they are not accused today, just[Page lw.2.21]because of
their educational and social significance, of havingsought to subordinate intelligence and
science to ordinaryutilitarian aims. They merely sought to free intelligence from itsimpurities
and to render it sovereign. One can scarcely say thatthose who glorify intelligence and reason in
the abstract, becauseof their value for those who find personal satisfaction in theirpossession,
estimate intelligence more truly than those who wishto make it the indispensable guide of
intellectual and social life.When an American critic says of instrumentalism that it regardsideas
as mere servants which make for success in life, he onlyreacts, without reflection, to the
ordinary verbal associations of theword "instrumental," as many others have reacted in the
samemanner to the use of the word "practical." Similarly a recentItalian writer after having said
that pragmatism andinstrumentalism are characteristic products of American thought, adds
thatthese systems "regard intelligence as a mere mechanism of belief,and consequently attempt
to re-establish the dignity of reason bymaking of it a machine for the production of beliefs
useful tomorals and society." This criticism does not hold. It is by nomeans the production of
beliefs useful to morals and societywhich these systems pursue. It is the formation of a faith
inintelligence, as the one and indispensable belief necessary to moraland social life. The more
one appreciates the intrinsic esthetic,immediate value of thought and of science, the more one
takesinto account what intelligence itself adds to the joy and dignityof life, the more one should
feel grieved at a situation in whichthe exercise and joy of reason are limited to a narrow, closed
andtechnical social group and the more one should ask how it ispossible to make all men
participators in this inestimable wealth.[Page lw.2.22]

[First published in Studies in the History of Ideas, ed. Department of Philosophy,

Columbia University (New York: Columbia University Press, 1925), 2:353-77.]

Dewey: Page lw.2.4

1. Monist, vol. 15, p. 163.

Dewey: Page lw.2.4

2. Monist, vol. 15, p. 162.

Dewey: Page lw.2.4

3. Popular Science Monthly, 1878.

Dewey: Page lw.2.5

4. Monist, vol. 15, pp. 173-74.

Dewey: Page lw.2.5

5. Monist, vol. 15, p. 178.

Dewey: Page lw.2.7

6. Collected Essays and Reviews, p. 412.

Dewey: Page lw.2.7

7. The Meaning of Truth, pp. 209-211. In a footnote James gave an example of

the errors which are committed in connection with the term "Practical,"

quoting M. Bourdeau who had written that "Pragmatism is an Anglo-Saxon

reaction against the intellectualism and rationalism of the Latin mind. . . . It is a

philosophy without words, a philosophy of gestures and of acts, which

abandons what is general and holds only to what is particular." In his lecture at

California, James brought out the idea that his pragmatism was inspired to a

considerable extent by the thought of the British philosophers, Locke,


Berkeley, Hume, Mill, Bain, and Shadworth Hodgson. But he contrasted this

method with German transcendentalism, and particularly with that of Kant. It

is especially interesting to notice this difference between Peirce and James: the

former attempted to give an experimental, not an a priori interpretation of

Kant, whereas James tried to develop the point of view of the British thinkers.

Dewey: Page lw.2.13

8. William James said in a happy metaphor, that they must be "cashed in," by

producing specific consequences. This expression means that they must be

able to lead to concrete facts. But for those who are not familiar with

American idioms, James' formula was taken to mean that the consequences

themselves of our rational conceptions must be narrowly limited by their pecuniary

value. Thus Mr. Bertrand Russell wrote recently that pragmatism is merely a

manifestation of American commercialism.

Dewey: Page lw.2.16

9. Psychology, vol. 1, p. 8.

An Excerpt from Chapter 5 of Jane Addams book Democracy and Social Ethics,

A wise man has said that "the consent of men and your own conscience are two wings given you whereby you

may rise to God." It is so easy for the good and powerful to think that they can rise by following the dictates

of conscience, by pursuing their own ideals, that they are prone to leave those ideals unconnected with the

consent of their fellow-men. The president of the company thought out within his own mind a beautiful town.

He had power with which to build this town, but he did not appeal to nor obtain the consent of the men who

were living in it. The most unambitious reform, recognizing the necessity for this consent, makes for slow but

sane and strenuous progress, while the most ambitious of social plans and experiments, ignoring this, is prone

to failure.
The man who insists upon consent, who moves with the people, is bound to consult the "feasible right" as well

as the absolute right. He is often obliged to attain only Mr. Lincoln's "best possible," and then has the

sickening sense of compromise with his best convictions. He has to move along with those whom he leads

toward a goal that neither he nor they see very clearly till they come to it. He has to discover what people

really want, and then "provide the channels in which the growing moral force of their lives shall flow." What

he does attain, however, is not the result of his individual striving, as a solitary mountain-climber beyond that

of the valley multitude but it is sustained and upheld by the sentiments and aspirations of many others.

Progress has been slower perpendicularly, but incomparably greater because lateral. He has not taught his

contemporaries to climb mountains, but he has persuaded the villagers to move up a few feet higher; added to

this, he has made secure his progress. A few months after the death of the promoter of this model town, a

court decision made it obligatory upon the company to divest itself of the management of the town as

involving a function beyond its corporate powers. The parks, flowers, and fountains of this far-famed

industrialcentre were dismantled, with scarcely a protest from the inhabitants themselves.

The man who disassociates his ambition, however disinterested, from the coperation of his fellows, always

takes this risk of ultimate failure. He does not take advantage of the great conserver and guarantee of his own

permanent success which associated efforts afford. Genuine experiments toward higher social conditions must

have a more democratic faith and practice than those which underlie private venture. Public parks and

improvements, intended for the common use, are after all only safe in the hands of the public itself; and

associated effort toward social progress, although much more awkward and stumbling than that same effort

managed by a capable individual, does yet enlist deeper forces and evoke higher social capacities.

The successful business man who is also the philanthropist is in more than the usual danger of getting widely

separated from his employees. The men already have the American veneration for wealth and successful

business capacity, and, added to this, they are dazzled by his good works. The workmen have the same kindly

impulses as he, but while they organize their charity into mutual benefit associations and distribute their

money in small amounts in relief for the widows and insurance for the injured, the employer may build model

towns, erect college buildings, which are tangible and enduring, and thereby display his goodness in
concentrated form.

By the very exigencies of business demands, the employer is too often cut off from the social ethics

developing in regard to our larger social relationships, and from the great moral life springing from our

common experiences. This is sure to happen when he is good "to" people rather than "with" them, when he

allows himself to decide what is best for them instead of consulting them. He thus misses the rectifying

influence of that fellowship which is so big that it leaves no room for sensitiveness or gratitude. Without this

fellowship we may never know how great the divergence between ourselves and others may become, nor how

cruel the misunderstandings.

During a recent strike of the employees of a large factory in Ohio, the president of the company expressed

himself as bitterly disappointed by the results of his many kindnesses, and evidently considered the employees

utterly unappreciative. His state of mind was the result of the fallacy of ministering to social needs from an

individual impulse and expecting a socialized return of gratitude and loyalty. If the lunch-room was necessary,

it was a necessity in order that the employees might have better food, and, when they had received the better

food, the legitimate aim of the lunch-room was met. If baths were desirable, and the fifteen minutes of

calisthenic exercise given the women in the middle of each half day brought a needed rest and change to their

muscles, then theincreased cleanliness and the increased bodily comfort of so many people should of

themselves have justified the experiment.

To demand, as a further result, that there should be no strikes in the factory, no revolt against the will of the

employer because the employees were filled with loyalty as the result of the kindness, was of course to take

the experiment from an individual basis to a social one.

Large mining companies and manufacturing concerns are constantly appealing to their stockholders for funds,

or for permission to take a percentage of the profits, in order that the money may be used for educational and

social schemes designed for the benefit of the employees. The promoters of these schemes use as an argument
and as an appeal, that better relations will be thus established, that strikes will be prevented, and that in the

end the money returned to the stockholders will be increased. However praiseworthy this appeal may be in

motive, it involves a distinct confusion of issues, and in theory deserves the failure it so often meets with in

practice. In the clash which follows a strike, the employees are accused of an ingratitude, when there was no

legitimate reason to expect gratitude; and useless bitterness, which has really a factitious basis, may be

developed on both sides.

Indeed, unless the relation becomes a democratic one, the chances of misunderstanding are increased, when to

the relation of employer and employees is added the relation of benefactor to beneficiaries, in so far as there is

still another opportunity for acting upon the individual code of ethics.

Potrebbero piacerti anche