Sei sulla pagina 1di 36

LAWS AI{D

EXPLANATION
II{ HISTORY
BY

WI L L I A M DRAY
Assistan PtoJessotof Philosophl
TIv Uniocrsit2of Toronto

O X F O RD UN I V E R S I T Y P R E S S
E sc' r.
r TH E C A U S A L VERSI O N O F THE M O DEL 87
uncommon for philosophers to represent causal laws as having
special explanatory force. Thus C. J. Ducasse, after defining
IV explanation in terms of subsumption under a 'law of con-
nection', and having added that a mere'law of correlation' will
CA U S A L L A WS A N D C A U S A L ANALYSIS not do, goes on to say that laws of the former sort are either
causal or logical.' And many contemporary philosophers of
t. The Causal Versionof the Model science, with quantum physics in mind, would agree with
o far I have said very little about specifically causal Mr. A. P. Ushenko that causal laws alone have "explanatory
explanation.In ChapterII, althoughcausallanguagewas virtue".2
not avoidedaltogether,our concernwas chieflytotestthe No doubt many of those who have phrased the covering law
covering law claims with respect to explanations which were claim in terms of specifically causal laws have used the term
complete in a special sense,and which would not necessarily, 'causal' carelessly.Some have meant no more than 'empirical
or even naturally, be formulated in causal terms. In Chapter laws', by contrast with, say, general principles of logic. Others
III, too, no attempt was made to contrast explanations given have probably had in mind a distinction within the class
by making reference to causal laws with explanations of other of empirical laws, between mere 'probability hypotheses' or
kinds. But some defenders of the model have stated their statistical generalizations and genuinely universal laws-for
claims explicitly in terms of covering causal laws, as if sub- causal laws are often held to set forth invariable connexions.
sumption under these constituted a special case. It may there- But the notion of a causal law is often taken in a more obvious
fore be worth our while, even at the risk of some repetition of sense as simply a law expressible in causal language-a law
points made in a different context of discussion, to ask whether which would naturally assume the form 'X causes In
-y'.
there are any peculiarities about specifically causal explana- assessingthe causal version of the covering law model, it is
tions which might, or might appear to, count either for or this latter interpretation which I propose to adopt.
against the argument which has been developed so far. To say that one sort of thing caasesanother to happen is
The cbusal version of the model, like the broader theory, usually held to mean something more than that phenomena of
may be regarded as formulating both a necessary and a the first type are always followed by phenomena of the second.
sufficient condition of giving an explanation. A. J. Ayer puts As M. R. Cohen puts it, in the course of warning social
the necessary condition claim without qualification when he scientists against philosophers who regard causality as nothing
declare_s:"every assertion of a particular causal connection but repeated succession: l'A causal relation assertsmore than
involves the assertion of a causal law"'t and Gardiner, in mere past coincidence. It affirms that there is some reason
discussing the stock Humian billiard-ball example, observes: or ground why, whenever the antecedent event occurs, the
"the force of the word 'Secause' derives from the fact that a consequent must follow."s
particular case,hasbeen seen to satisfy the requirements of a What sort of 'reason' or 'ground' is envisaged here ? Why
causal law . . . ."' Straightforward statements of the sufficient are specifically causal connexions especially tight and intel-
condition claim are less commonly found. But it is not at all ligible ? According to one currently popular view, a law of
I 'F)xplanation, Mechanism and Teleology', Feigl and Sellars, Readingsin
I Language, Truth and Logic (znd ed,), London, r948' IthilosophicalAnalysis, p. 54o.
P. 55.
2 Op. cit,, p. 2; sce also p, rr4. For other examples, see quotations from Pro- r ''fhe Principles of Causality' The
, Journal of Philosophy,1953,pp. 85-86.
t I'hc Meaning of Human History, p. roz.
fessors Kaufmann and Braithwaite, Chap. I, section z.
88 CAUSAL LAWS AND CAUSAL ANALYSIS cH.rv sE cr.r TH E C A U S A L VERSI O N O F THE M O DEL 8q
causal connexion, by contrast with a mere law of observed of someimplicit theory-indeed, that they need not explain
correlation, derives its necessity from a logical connexion be- their effectsat all.
tween cause and effect, in the light of some accepted general It is worth noticing, in this connexion,that the providing
theory of the subject matter. Thus Ryle holds that causal . ofcausal explanationshasnot alwaysbeenregardedas part of
statements are themselves covertly theoretical. Causes, he the historian's proper task. Indeed, seriousmisgivings have
says, are designated by words which are more heavily'theory- often been expressedby philosophersand methodologistsof
loaded' than the words which designatetheir effects; they have history as to whether the word 'cause' ought to appear in
as part of their meaning an essential theoretical reference.r historical writing at all. What is, on the face of it, more
The reason why 'wound', for instance, is the right kind of curious still, such doubts have been expressednot only by
word to use in indicating the cause of a scar, while 'pain', opponents of the covering law model like Oakeshott and
although also designatingan antecedentcondition, is not, lies Collingwood, but by many of its convinced supporters as
in the fact that it carries the right kind of theoretical load to well.
explain scars-i.e. a medical or physiological one. Similarly, Thus, in the bulletin of the American Social Science
although a red sky is quite incapable of.causinga fall of rain, a ResearchCouncil alreadyreferredto, can be found a warning
cold front may be said to do so becauseof the meteorological from ProfessorHook to the effectthat 'cause'is "an ambiguous
load of the term concerned. and difficult term of varied and complex meaning", which
Such an account of the explanatory force of specifically should be used by historians"with circumspection".IThe
causal laws has the merit of going beyond a mere statement warning so impressedhis historical colleaguesthat they con-
that causal connexions must be more than instances of uni- cluded that the term 'cause'as used by historians "must be
formly observed sequences. Ryle says both what the 'more' regardedas a convenientfigure of speech,describingmotives,
is-a theory-and why it is not always obvious to those who influences,forcesand other antecedentinterrelationsnot fully
recognize the connexion; and if his analysis held good in all, understood".'Andtwo historians,Professors C. A. Beardand
or even the vast maiority of cases,the problem of elucidating A. Vagts, in a minority report, went on to declarethat the
the explanatory role of tausal laws could simply be referrei term "should neverbe usedin,written history", being suitable
back to my discussion in the previous chapter of the way only for "conversations"and t'small practical affairs". In his
theories provide explanations. But it is important for our methodologicalprimer for historians, Gottschalk comments
understanding of causal explanation in history to recognize caustically:"this is a roundaboutadmissionthat the authors
that Ryle's analysis does not hold good generally. In the of this proposition are somewhatbaffied by the problem of
discussion to follow, I shall deny that the causal explanations causation."g Yet he too feelsobligedin the end to admit that
which historians commonly give can be said to require or "the problem of historical causationis still essentiallyun-
presuppose correspondin$ causal laws-for reasonsarising out solved".
of the peculiarities of causal analysis as well as for reasons of The objection of the idealistsis not so much that 'cause'is
the kind already advanced in non-causal cases. But I shall too looseand slippery a word for 'scientific' history, as that it
argue, too, that causesseldom explain their effects by virtue is, when understood,found to be an irrelevantor inappro-
priate category.According to Oakeshott,its use betrays an
r In lectures delivered at Oxford Universiry during Trinity Term, 1952.
Ryle's theory has been developedfarther by N. R. Hanson in 'Causal Chains', I Bulletin No. 54, p. rro. 2 Op. cit., p, r37.
Mind, 1955,pp. 289-3r r. 3 UnderstandingHistory, Chicago, rgsr, p. ?23.
90 CAU SAL LA W S A ND CA US A LA NA L Y S I S c H.rv sE cr.2 TH E D IS C OVERY O F CAUSAL LAWS 9r
anti-historicalway of thinking about the subject-matter-an accompaniedby disease.But what exactly are we to say about
attempt to convert history into a kind of science.rFor Oake- this 'riore'? On the face of it, at any rate, such an example
shott, causalanalysisis loo scientificrather than not scientific would seemto raisedfficulties for Ryle's accountof the theo-
enough.The view of Collingwood is similar, although more retical backgroundto causalstatements'For, if anything'-it
complicated.Collingwood analysesthe concept of causation appearsto 6e the effect word which, in this case,carriesthe
into three related notions, only one of which is a proper his- heaui"r theoreticalload. The word 'dirt' is not in any obvious
torical category,the others being legitimate and illegitimate *ry'ttt.oty-loaded',yetthemeaningofthecausalstatementis
extensionsof the conceptfor scientific purposes.According and it-would probably be regardedas true by
to Collingwood, in so far as we mean anything more by a "1"'r, "r,otgh,
many people.
causethan 'affording someonea motive for doing something' It'mighi, I suppose,be arguedthat the notion of a 'theo-
(he callsthis 'SenseI'), the notion has no placein historical retical llad; musi be taken more subtly than this. For what a
studies.2 word is intended to convey-especially a 'loaded' one-may
Now it is perfectlyclearthat, no matter what thesetheorists be dependentin an imporiant way ypol its context of utter-
say,historiansdo commonlyattemptto provide causalexpla- hh,r., in the motor-car exampleof the previouschapter'
nations of what they study. This is a fact which can be the term 'oil reservoir' had a very different significancefor
".r.".
verified by the most cursory glanceat one or two standard the assistantmechanic,who understoodthe lubricating system'
history textbooks. As Mandelbaum has observed: "This and for me, who thought of it only as a receptacleinto which
acceptancein practice of what is disdainedin theory consti- *", put. We might-say that there is a contextual dimension
-so
tutes a paradox worth investigating.", In examining the "if
to th"oryJoading, that a word which ordinarily lacked a
causalversion of the model in this chapter I shall, to some theoretical referCncemight acquire one in the right conlext'
extent, be investigatingit. For it will be my thesisthat once ,Dirt' might be a casein point. The circumstancesin which
the difference between offering a causal analysis of, and *igtti say 'Dirt disease'-e'g' in a class of prob.a-
applying causallawsto, a particular happeningis appreciated, """ "urrr"-,
suffibiently proficient in sterile tech-
tioner nurses, not yet
rnan]*of the difficulties which the philosophersin question niques-might be such that the word meansmore than' say'
haveseemedto find in the useof the causalconceptin history ,drist,. It mlght mean somethingmore like 'substanceladen
will be seento disappear. with bacteria'.
That an ordinary word like 'dirt' might fluctuate a good
z. The Discooeryof CausalLaax deal in its implicit theoretical referencefrom one context to
Let us begin by investigatingthe notion that a causallaw is another is no doubt true, and it is therefore necessaryto
a law of an especiallytight and, at the sametime, explanatory restateRyle's theory in such a way that this can be taken into
a
sort. What should be soidin this connexionabout a common- account.iet I stroutdstill want to questionthe claim that
sensecausalassertionlike: 'Dirt gausesdisease'?It does, causalstatementlike'Dirt causes disease' could only be said
indeed,appearthat the truth of such a 'law' dependson more t""""i"gzufly, or justifiably, in contexts where one could
than just the observationof a correlation between dirt and ,"urott"Bry tit"t a theoreticalreferencewas understood'
disease-at any rate, it assertsmore than that dirt is always "Ui*of the Rylian account might be willing to.go
A defender
like
I See section
5 below.
2 An EssaSton Metaphjtsics, pp, 285-6. one step farther in the attempt to accommodateexamples
3 'Causal Analysis in History', Jouraal of the History of ldeas, r942,p.3o. the one we are considering.Ii might be allowed that one could
92 CA US A L L A WS A N D C A U S AL A NA LY S IS cs. rv sE cr.z TH E D IS C OVERY O F CAUSAL LAWS ss
meaningfully say 'Dirt causesdisease'without any of the on authority arise. The discovery could have been (and
relevant theoretical knowledge (ca[ it 'the germ tleory of probably was originally in fact) made by observing correlations
disease')as long as one did not deny that there must Desome between dirt and diseasein hospitals of the time. It would be
such connexionbetweenthem. Thus the ward helper might noticed that cleaner hospitals had lower, and dirty hospitals
Iearn the samelessonas the student nurses,without learni"ng had higher, death-rates from disease; and it would be found
the medrcalsignificanceof 'dirt'. For him it is enoughto bi that when she and her helpers cleaned up a dirty hospital,
ple-tg identify dirt in order to get rid of it. The justffication the disease-rate fell. This is quite sufficient to justify her
for his s-aylng'Dirtcausesdisease'isthen indiiect; it is a saying: 'Dirt causes disease.'
matter of a very proper faith in authority. The kernelof Ryle,s Is this to relapse into the position vvhich Ducasse, Cohen,
account would survive, however, in ihat f.or someone,dkt, and Ryle all wish (and I think rightly) to avoid: the view that
must carry a theoretical load. causation is reducible without remainder to correlation; or, to
such a defencere-emphasizesthe considerationwhich led put it in a more precise way, the view that * is the cause of y
to Ryle's analysis:the fact that, evenwherea persondoesnot if whenever * then y? If I had talked only about what Miss
know what the 'connexion'betweencauseani efiect is, he at Nightingale and her helpers obseroed,there would be some
any rate assumesthat there is one to be discovered.Any room for such a charge, for, as Ryle has rightly insisted, we
alternativeaccountto the view that the connexionin question cannot discover causesmerely by looking-nor, indeed, by
is theoreticalmust elucidateits nature in someother way; it repeated looking. But there is an additional fact to be taken
must do more than just return to the simple, Humian ,regu- into account here; for the causal conclusions drawn rested.
Iarity' analysis which Rylers notion of i 'theoretical lo?d, not just on what these women saw, but also onwhat theyfound
supplementsto advantagein so many cases.Let me therefore themselves able to do. The crucial step in their investigations
explain why I do not think that the concessionsmade can was the discovery that if they removed the dirt, the disease-
render Ryle's account universally applicable, and in what rate dropped; if they allowed t\eir sanitary operations to
alternative-way the notion of 'a ionni*ion' may have to be flag, then up it went again. Their quite adequate grounds for
interpretedi concluding that dirt causes diseasewere that by manipulating
. Let us consider the statement,.Dirt causesdisease,,said the dirt-rate, theyfound themselvesable to control the disease-
not by the- supervisor of a modern hospital, brii by, for rate.
example,Florence Nightingale to someof h"t early helpers. One important difference between causal candidates which
I shall assumethat none of them knew the germ iheory of merely satisfy the test of invariable correlation, and those
disease.Even if this was not true of them, iI probably was which also meet such a practical test, is this. Having observed
true of someof their predecessors. Is there .,o wav in which that whenever r then y, if I merely know that from an occur-
they (or such predecessors) 6ould havearrived at tire truth of rence of r it is safe to predict a y, without knowing the nature
the causalstatement? of the 'connexion' between them, then I must always be pre-
rt seemsto me that Florence Nightingale could have dis- pared to entertain the hypothesis that both x and y are effects
coveredthat dirty hospitalscauseddiseaseamongher patients of something else. If, for instance, I observe that the birth-
without aecessarilyknowing why this was so_at any rate, rate of white mice in New York is correlated with the divorce-
without knowing the theoreticalionnexion betweentt two. rate of movie stars in California, I must be ready to entertain
Nor doesthe possibility that she might merely have got " this the hypothesis that both are caused by, say, sun-spot cycles,
94 CA US A L LA WS A N D C A U S AL AN ALY S IS cH .Iv sE cr.2 TH E D IS C OV ERY O F CAUSAL LAWS 95
or the fluctuations of a yet undiscovered element in the To deny that agency is, in this way, an alternatitseto theory
atmosphere.r This, of course, remains mere hypothesis unless in validating an alleged causal connexion could only be jus-
the connexion between them, perhaps in terms of a theory, tified, I think, on the basis of some metaphysical hypothesis
becomes clear. In some cases, for an initially prtzzling cor- of the 'Evil Genius' type. That is, it might be insisted that
relation of this kind, a satisfactory indirect connexion can even if whenever I manipulate tc,y alters in the relevant way'
eventually be found-as, for instance, between the influx of this may still be due to some unknown 'third thing', for
visitors to seaside resorts and crime waves (both may be instance, the synchronizing activities of a Cartesian demon
causedby'summer heat'). A direct causalconnexion may also who delights to deceive us-to make us think that we are in
sometimes be shown to underly a correlation-as, for instance, control. But such an extravagant hypothesis deservesno place
in the case of the correlation between the size of rabbit in our analysis. Indeed, metaphysical arguments could just as
populations and the prevalence of dust storms. In the white easily be found for saying that we can never be sure on any
mice example we should probably regard it as a wziste of time (e.g. even theoretical) grounds that one thing is the cause of
to look for a common cause; we should be content to say that another. The metaphysical objection may seem to derivesome
the correlation was just a coincidence. Yet if it were very force from the possibility that, on some occasion, my attempt
persistent, it would become less and less satisfactory to say to control a certain jir by manipulating a certain r may not
this, and we should feel more and more obliged to look either work. But this is just an aspect of the general corrigibility of
for a direct or indirect connexion of the kinds mentioned. empirical statements. f see no reason to doubt that a causal
Could it be objected that we do sometimes say that one staiement of the form'r causesy', may, in some cases,be
phenomenon is the cause of another merely because one is confirmed to the point where the possibility that, when some-
found to be uniformly prior to the other in experience ? It one has produced an x, a y will not follow, is only a logical
seemsto me that to say this would generally be regarded (and possibility. For anyone but a metaphysician,i.e. for a scientist,
rightly so) as just the expression of a 'hunch', which required historian, or plain man, it would.therefore be unreasonable
to be confirmed by elucidating the nature of the 'connexion'. to take the metaphysical way out.!
It would be more accurate in such cases to say, 'I think * In An Essay on Metaphysics Collingwood points out that,
causes!', or'a probably causesy'. But-and this is the point in one of the uses of the term 'cause' (he calls it 'Sense II'),
I wish to emphasize-what we could aof consistently say is the cause of a thing is the handle by means of which we can
that r does not causey even though by manipulating tr we can control it; it is "an event or state of things which it is in our
control y. If whenever the pest control officer in New York power to produce or prevent, and by producing or preventing
succeeds in reducing the size of the white mice population, which we can produce or prevent that whose cause it is said
the divorce-rate falls in California, then we cannot avoid the to be".2 Thus, to quote some of his examples: "The cause of
conclusion that a change irf the birth-rate causesa change in malaria is the bite of a mosquito; the causeof a boat's sinking
the divorce-rate. And in a particular case, we should have to is her being overloaded; the cause of books going mouldy is
allow that the cause of the observed change in the divorce- their being in a damp room; the cause of a man's sweating is
rate was the manipulation of the death-rate-thus applying a dose of aspirin. . . ."3 Such causes, Collingwood adds,
our knowledge of the causpl law. I The sentence which originally ended this paragraph has been deleted in
response to a criticism of Professor John Passmorq
I For a discussion of the problem of distinguishing correlation and causation
" p. z96- ' p. zgg.
in the social sciences see M. R. Cohen, op. cit., p. 16.
96 CAUSAL LAWS AND CAUSAL ANALYSIS cH.rv srcr.z THE DISCOVERY OF CAUSAL LAWS s7
always depend for their operation upon conditionessine quibus no explanatory connexion between cause and effect is known.
non. As Collingwood himself pointed out, the criterion of 'the
There are, however, two ways of interpreting Collingwood's handle' (in what I have called the 'strong' usg) is appropriate
point. On what might be called the 'weak' interpretation, his to the practical rather than the theoretical (i.e. explanatory)
doctrine of 'the handle' might be regarded as merely calling sciences.Thus, although it is necessaryto insist, with Ducasse,
attention to a practical condition which must be satisfied bv Cohen, Ryle, and others, that causation is not reducible to
any causal candidate. If he is right about it, what falls under mere correlation-for it is always more than this-it is impor-
the antecedent clause of a law cannot be a cause-and, a tant to recognize that it may very well be something less than
fortiori, the law cannot be a causal one-unless the condition an explanatory connexion between events. It may only be
specified is a manipulable one. This has often been dismissed (let us call it) a pracrtcal connexion; and in such cases, we
as a correct, but not very important, observation about our cannot expect the causal law, when applied to a particular case
'ordinary' use of the word 'cause'. falling under it, to have much more explanatory force than
But in the present instance, f am not just saying that an ordinary empirical generalization. For we have no 'insight'
manipulability is often one of the criteria to be satisfied before into the.connexio4,; there is no analysis of the case, no reduc-
calling something a cause. What I claim is that there are tion of a gross and opaque connexion to transparent, 'hat-
cases where Collingwood's 'handl e' replaces Ryle's require- doffing'ones.
ment that there be a theoretical connexion between cause and
effect: that if a certain condition satisfies the practical test, 3. The Selection of Causal Conditions
then that is enough to give it causal status. Let us call this the I have argued that there is nothing about the notion of a
strong interpretation of Collingwood's doctrine of the ,handle'. 'causal law', in so far as we mean any law which could be
Even in the strong use, of course, there are still, in theory, expressedin causal language, which would make subsumption
conditiones sine quibus non; for causal laws only indicaie under one invariably explanatory. If we turn now to the
sufficient conditions, ceterisparibus, of what falls under their companion claim that knowl6dge of a causal law is at any rate
apodoses.I But in contexts where we speah with point of the a necessarycondition of giving a causal explanation, we shall
disgovery and use of causal laws, the notion of there being find even less reason for allowing it-especially in history. For
additional necessaryconditions is swallowed up in the assump- in typical historical cases,any causal law extracted from the
tion of a normal application situation for the law-the details historian's particular causal explanation will appear just as
of which we need not have gone into. They are taken into artificial and just as innocent of independent justification as
account by the context of inquiry----e.g. British hospitals in the non-causal examples discussed in Chapter II. The test
the nineteenth century. for Florence Nightingale's causal assertion was: 'Repeat the
In the light of this*account of the way causal laws are often cause and the effect should follow.' No such test is relevant
discovered and used, it would be.rather odd to regard them to an assertion like 'The cause of Louis XIV's unpopularity
as invariably explanatory. For in so far as a causal law---one was his foreign wars'. For the truth of the historian's assertion
which we should naturally express in the form ,r causesy,- does not depend on the particular causal connexion being an
is arrived at by manipulation, we may expect it to be formu- instance of a causal routine.
lated for just that kind of situation where we should admit that If a particular causal explanation does not represent what
r On the use of n"ff:l"U as an instance of some causal routine, what should
'cetarr'spaibus, see Note B, p. r7o.
98 CA US A L L AW S AN D C A U S AL AN A LY S IS cH .rv sBcr.3 SELECTION OF CAUSAL CONDITIONS 99
be said about its logical structure ? On what grounds does an leads Collingwood to assert his doctrine of 'the relativity of
historian represent something as 'the cause' when examining causes': the doctrine that the causeof, say, an explosion, will
a particular state of affairs ? In answering these questions, it is be different for a chemist, a night-watchman, and an investi-
helpful to distinguish between two sorts of tests which would gator from the City Hall. If a dispute were to develop between
seem to be applicable to any causal candidate. On the one these three as to what condition was really the cause,it would
hand, the historian must be able to show that the condition have to be pointed out to them that it depended partly on
called the cause was really necessary, i.e. that without it what kind of steps they were interested in discovering toward
what is to be explained would not have happened. He must avoiding such disasters in future. If an historian, writing later
also be able to show that there is some reason for singling out about the explosion, takes up the point of view of one or other
the condition in question from among the other necessary of these kinds of agents-he may, for instance, be writing
conditions, which, since what is to be explained did in fact 'administrative history'-then his selection of the causal con-
happen, may be presumed to amount to a sufficient set. These dition will be gou.rrr.i accordingly. If he is, on the other hand,
might be called the inductiae and pragmatic tests of causal writing general history, and is therefore not involved in the
selection. Causes,that is, must be important lo the inquirer hypothetical controvers], he may feel obliged to list more than
as well as important for the effect. Let me try to bring out one cause.But he would find it difficult to ignore the practical
briefly some of the features of each of these two kinds of criterion for the selection of causesaltogether.
importance. Collingwood's analysis of the pragmatic test for causes is
Collingwood's doctrine of 'the handle', in what I have called not exhaustive, however. For many other practical considera-
its 'weak' interpretation, formulates one pragmatic criterion tions besides manipulability could be elicited from our
which is often applied. The historian will normally be con- ordinary use of causal language. A causal explanation is often,
cerned to indicate as causes those conditions which were for instance, designed to show what went rivrong; it focuses
humanly important becauseunder human control; and causes attention not just on what was or could have been done, but on
will thus often appear in historical writing as what was done what should or should nothave been done by certain historical
by the ]ristorical agentswho are mentioned in the historian's agents.Thus, selectingthe causalcondition sometimescannot
narrative. It is important to add, of course, that the 'handle' be divorced from assigning blame.I The close connexion
test would apply just as well to caseswhere we are referred to between the two is recognized by Hal6vy when, in writing
what was left un-done; for historical causes are often non- about the fluctuations in the price of wheat in England in
occurrences,absences, failuresto do what could havebeendone. t8t6-t7, he says: "an attempt was made to prove that the
In accepting Collingwood's point, there is no need to push Corn Bill was the cause of these wild fluctuations. But to
it to the paradoxical extreme which he himself allowed-that bring forward such a charge was tantamount to maintaining
the cause must always b*ethe sort of thing which would have that the Bill was ineffective, and had failed to fulfil its authors'
been a possible handle 6r the speaker(or writer). All we need intentions."" It is significant, in this connexion, that historians
to say is that a cause is selected in the light of a certain kind often use expressions like 'was responsible for' when they
of inquiry.' This is sufficient explanation of the puzzle which t The above point may be added to what is said in Chap, V, sections z and
5,
about the way explanation in'the humanities goes beyond anything covering
I As Gardiner puts it, 'cause' is a function of language level (op. cit., p. ro).
law theorists would accept as 'scientific'.
My remarks here are only intended to supplement Gardiner's discussion in Part 2 A History of the English Peoltle in the Nineteenth Cmtury, znd edn, (revised),
III, section 4. tr. by E, I. Watkin, London, r949, vol. ii, p. 6r.
r oo CA US AL L AW S AN D C AU SA L A N A LY S IS cH .rv
sE cr.3 S E LE C TION O F CAUSAL CO NDI TI O NS r or
want to put into other words conclusions which they would
to come into existence, for it is enough generally that it aPpear
also be prepared to frame in causal language.
as an intruder-a foreign element-in the situation envisaged.
Thus, if, with a recent writer on the subject, we were to
As Maclver puts it: "The crucial events regarded as causesare
ask: "Can history really show by its method that Hitler's
assignedthis role becausethey are represented as interferences
invasion of Poland was the cause of the war?", we should be
with normal conditions."t Thus a storm is the cause of a
wise to clarify the question before trying to answer it.t Two
traffic snarl because it blew trees across the roadway. In the
historians who argue, for instance, whether it was Hitler's
language of the social scientist: "The presumption is that a
invasion of Poland or Chamberlain's pledge to defend it
system is operating in a manner congenial to its self-perpetua-
which caused the outbreak of the Second World War are not
tion until something intervenes. . . ."2 fn historical contexts,
just arguing about whether these were necessary conditio4s
the point would simply be that the causal condition is an
of what happened. Nor, indeed, is it likely that they are at
unexpected one in that particular context. If the cause is a
odds about which of thesecandidate-causeswas a manipulable
non-occurrence, this requirement would, of course, be in-
condition-since, in an inter-subjective sense, both clearly
verted: the causal non-occurrence would be something that
were. They are trying, rather, to settle the question of who
was to be expected, but which did not occur. It was not a
was to blame. In such cases,it should be noticed, there is an
causeof the SecondWorld War that Hitler failed to be struck
essentialconnexion between assigning responsibility and attri-
by lightning on 3r August 1939.
buting causal status. The point is not that we cannot hold an
A large-scale attempt to elicit the pragmatic criteria em-
agent responsible for a certain happening unless his action
ployed in causal analysis in history would be beyond the scope
can be said to have caused it. It is rather that, unless we are
of the present discussion, although it is a project well worth
prepared to hold the agent responsible for what happened, we
undertaking for its own sake. I have tried only to indicate the
cannot say that his action was the cause. The pragmatic
sort of thing which might be expected to emerge from a more
criterion is not just something added to a causal judgement
thorough study, and to show how this aspect of causal analysis
already made on other grounds; for that judgement is itself,
raises special difficulties for any attempt to generalize the
in pdrt, the judgement that a certain condition deserves
historian's causal statement as h law. For even a cursory study
special attention.
of the matter seems to me to show that causal explanation
There are many other pragmatic reasonsfor selecting con-
does not just happm in a great many casesto fall short of the
ditions as causal ones. Causes are often, for instance, the standard of completenessemployed in Chapter II. It shows,
initially mysterious or hidden conditions-the ones which
ratJrer, that such explanation is necessarilyincomplete if that
still remain to be discovered after we have gained a pre- standard is accepted; for the very notion of 'discovering the
liminary knowledge of a situation. ProfessorMaclver makes a
cause' requires the isolntion of some condition or conditions.
similar, although not {dentical, point when he says that the The resulting contrast is part of what is demanded by a
causal condition is often a 'precipitant'.2 It is what has to be causal'Why?'
added to certain other conditions already present-like the Covering law theorists who agree that, since historical
spark which ignites an explosion in a powder factory. causes are usually only especially important necessary con-
To be a 'precipitant' a condition need not be the last one ditions of their effects, it would be misleading to say that the
I M. C, Swabey, The historian's causal conclusion was warranted by a covering
fudgmmt of History, New York, 1954,p.26.
2 Social Causation,Boston, rg5z,p. r6t.
2 Op. cit., p. r73.
' Op. cit., p. 186.
roz CAUSAL LAWS AND CAUSAL ANALYSIS cH.rv sE cr.3 S E LE C Ti ON oF CAUSAL CO NDI TI O NS r o3
causal law, may nevertheless be tempted to argue that his besidespursuing the policies he actually did. But the question
conclusion requires a law of another kind. For it may be whether the effect could have been brought about in other ways
thought that in order to satisfy the second, the inductioe, test is not directly relevant to the historian's judgement that, in the
of causal selection, it will be necessaryto show that without an particularsituation under examination,the causewasnecessary.
event of type r-the cause-an event of type y-the effect- It would be an exaggeration, however, to say that this
could not have happened. And this may appear to be equiva- question is entirely irrelevant; for if there was a reasonable
lent to appealing to a law linking effect to necessarycondition: chance of y happening anyway, even without r, then it would
a law which might naturally be expressed in the form, .Only begin to be questionable to call r the cause of y. If, for
if x then y'.' Such 'laws of necessarycondition' would not, of instance, ,swould have been a satisfactory substitute for x, and
course, render predictable what is to be explained; and to the situation could be shown to be one in which s was not at
allow that mere subsumption of r and y under such a law all unlikely, then the causal status of r would probably come
counts as explanation would represent a considerable de- under review. Thus Collingwood, in denying that the length
pafture from the original claims of Popper, Hempel, and of Cleopatra'snose can be considereda genuine cause of the
Gardiner. Yet it may be felt that in insisting that some kind Roman Empire's taking the course it subsequently took,
of law is required by the explanation, the most important castigates what he calls "a bankruptcy of historical method
feature of covering law theory is nevertheless retained. which in despair of genuine explanation acquiescesin the most
It is important to recognize how seriously such an analysis trivial causesfor the vastest effects".' But why, exactly, does
would misrepresent what may be presumed to be the his- the nose in question fall short of full causal status ? It is not
torian's meaning if he said that the condition he selects as because in any obvious sense it is too small a thing to have
cause was necessary for the happening he wishes to explain. caused such a 'vast' effect. A causal condition may, in fact, be
We must remember, as always, that he is talking about par- as small as you please, as long as it is crucial. But to be crucial
ticular happenings in a quite definite historical situaiion. (a notion which includes the pragmatic criterion), a causal
When he says that y would not have happened without r, he condition must be genuinely necessary in the situation en-
does not mean that only in situations where there is an tr-type visaged. And it seems obvious dnough that Cleopatra's nose
event can you expect a y-type. He means that in that particular falls short of causal status because the historian's general
situation, if everything elseremained the same,the y which in knowledge of the situation in which the Roman Empire grew
fact occurred would not have done so; or, at any rate, that it is such that he believes that it would have taken much the
would have been different in important respects. The law, same course if Cleopatra had never existed.
'Only if r then y', might therefore be quite false, without the The point which requires emphasis is that, whether or not
historian's conclusion having to be withdrawn. As we saw in the historian concludes that the suggestedcausewas a neces-
Chapter II, there may,Tor instance, be a number of things sary condition of what he wishes to explain, his argument for
which Louis XIV might have done to make himself unpopular the conclusion he in fact reaches need not raise the question
I Mr, D. Gasking, for instance, points
whether the condition in question was a generally necessary
out to historians that ,,. . . the simplest
kind of general law which might be assumed in an explanation is of oni or one for events of the type to be explained; for the historian's
other of two basic types. They are of the form: Whenever you get I you get .E} explanatory problem is not. to represent a particular causal
(l is a sufficient condition of B), and Whenever you don't get I you don't get B
(l is a necessary condition of B)." 'The Historian's Craft and Scientific History',
connexion as an instance of a recurring one. He does not ask
Historical Studies Australia and Neu Zealand, r95o, p. r 16, I The ldea of History, pp. 8o-8r.
ro 4 CA US A L L A WS AN D C AU SA L A N A LY S IS cH .rv sE cr.4 C A U S A L LA W S AS G ENERALI ZATI O NS r o5
himself, 'What causes.y's?';he asks, 'What is the causeof to discoverthe causeof a particular happening in a deter-
thisy ?'-and he asksthis about ay in a determinatesituation. minate, concretehistorical situation. And I have deniedthat
The conclusionthat r was necessaryfor the occurrenceof y the secondsort of inquiry need be related to the first in the
in that situation will, in fact, usually require.an exerciseof sensethat it applieswhat the first sort of inquiry discovers.
judgementsimilar to the onediscussedin ChapterII (although It may perhapsbe felt that althoughit is true that historians
the questionis no longer whether certain conditionsformed a seldom have to deal with instancesof causal routines, and
sufficientset). It is true that the historianmust be certainthat that the causalversionof the model on its necessarycondition
without r, y could not have happened,if he is to say without side is therefore misleading,my account of the discoveryof
qualificationthat r wasthe causeof y. But there is no needto causallaws does less than justice to the sufficient condition
assume.thatthe only way he could arrive at such certainty is claim. And I must indeedadmit that the reasonsfor doubting
by knowing a law of the tonly if' form. As historicalmethodo- the explanatoryforce of causallaws set out in sectionz need
logists have often pointed out, what the historian has to do not alwayshold. A statementof what was at first merely an
is 'think away' the suggestedcause in order to judge what observed correlation, for instance, could be raised to the
differenceits non-occurrencewould have made in the light status of a causal law by bringing in sufficient theoretical
of what else he knows about the situation studied. If anv considerationsto establishthe connexionbetweencauseand
qualifying phraseis to be attachedto the historian'sconclusion effect. The mere ohseroatian, 'Wheneverwe find dirt we find
it would read,not 'other things being equal', but'the situation disease',although not a causallaw, might attain causalforce
beingwhat it was'-indicating that other mentionedand un- by the discoveryof the germ theory of disease.Causallaws
mentionedfeaturesof the particular situationhavebeentaken may also in somecasesbe directly derivablefrom theoretical
into accountin arriving at the causalconclusion. knowledge,without any enpirical observation of 'sx5sg'-
If the causalexplanationwere seriouslychallengedon its the'laws' then showingtheir origin by being more naturally
inductive side, it might indeed becomenecessaryto bring in, expressedin the subjunctive mood. An example of such a
bit by bit, all the data which in Chapter II were represented law might be: 'sustained nuclear radiation would cause
as constituting a complete explanationrather than a causal genetic deterioration of living beings.' But the fact that a
one. This is not to say that, after all, we must enlargeour iausal law can be theory-backeddoesnot reinstatethe suffi-
conceptionof a causeto that of a sufficient condition rather cient condition claim. It doesnot ensurethat if a specifically
than a merely necessaryone. It is rather that, if pressedto causallaw is 'applied', it must provide an explanationof what
show conclusivelythat r zodsnecessary,the historian might falls under it. And it was the purposeof my discussionof the
have to specifywhat, in fact, the other conditionswer*-i.e. special,experimentdlcaseto show that this gmeral claim of
to rebut the suggestionthat even without * they constituted cbveringliw theory in its causalversion cannot be sustained.
a sufficientset. d Our investigationhas, in fact, shown that there are three
quite different casesto be distinguishedwhen we askaboutthe
4. CausalLaws as Generalizations nature of 'causalconnexion'---or'at any rate, there are three
In the precedingsectionsI have calledattention to impor- different ways an allegedcausalconnexionmight have to be
tant featuresof two quite different kinds of causalinquiries: arguedfor. For the connexioncould be establishedby refer-
those in which the investigator seeksto establish general enie to manipulative experience,by referenceto a logical
causalconnexions-causallaws-and thosein which he seeks connexionin terms of somegeneraltheory, or by referenceto
106 CAUSAL LAWS AND CAUSAL ANALYSIS cH.rv sE cr.4 C A U S A L LA W S AS G ENERALI ZATI O NS r o7
other conditions in a determinate situation which allow the likely to rJe such causal laws, the laws not only could, but
judgement that a certain condition was crucial (both neces- would, be generalizations from knowledge of particular causal
sary and important).I The third way, which requires neither connexions arrived at by an exercise of judgement. We should
prior experimental nor theoretical knowledge of such con- only advance to asserting the law in addition to the individual
nexions, is the standard historical case.Such dicta as F. S. C. diagnosesif the same causeturned up repeatedly in the kind of
Northrop's that "causal necessity or determinism in history investigation concerned.
is only possible in a deductively formulated social science In The Problemof Historical Knowhdge Mandelbaum asserts
which has a theoretical dynamics" must be regarded as the that "the formulation of scientific laws depends upon causal
recommendation of a reformer rather than an account of the analysis" rather than causal analysis upon lawsl-a claim
way causal inquiry in history actually goes.2 which both Hempel and Gardiner have attacked as a naive
It may be worth pointing out in this connexion that causal attempt to ignore what Hume proved about causation.z It
laans,as well as particular, historical causal connexions, h?y should be clear that my own claim here is quite different from
sometimes be established without either experimental or this. It is limited to the kind of causal laws exemplified above;
theoretical justification. Indeed, the relation of 'support' and such laws would scarcely find a place in a list of the dis-
between laws and the particular connexions falling under coveries of, say, chemists and physicists. They might, how-
them, is at times precisely the oppositeof the one envisaged ever, appear among the findings of the social sciences; and it
by covering law theory; for in many casesdiscovery of indi- would not be very surprising to come upon an article in a
vidual causal connexions precedesthe formulation .of causal medical journal assemblin-gevidence by way of cases, inde-
laws, the laws-shocking though it may be to say it-.requiring pendently judged, in support of an assertion like 'Injections
prior knowledge of the particular cases,rather than the cases causetumours' (for in spite of the bad jokes commonly made
requiring support of the covering causal law. at its expense, medicine is not just a practical science). An
How, for instance, might we in practice arrive at a causal exactly parallel case in history would be a law like 'Tyranny
conclusion like 'Speed causesroad accidents'? Would it not causes revolution'. Such a 'law' would almost certainly be a
bE by gmeralization frorn a number of particular causal diagnoses causal g eneraliz ation.
of the form: 'The cause of this accident was excessivespeed,? The suggestion of generatization from casesindependently
The general causal statement is just the sort of thing that a discovered comes out even more strongly when we consider
public safety officer might use as a warning, and it could not laws of the form: 'The cause of y is x' (where these symbols
properly be said unlesshe could point to a number of caseson stand for types, not particulars). For it is difficult to see how
record, each standing on its own logical feet-i.e. to individual this stronger form of causal law could be established experi-
causalconnexionsindegendently validated. Perhapsthe same mentally; and in most cases,theoretical support would not be
law could have been reached experimentally (which, in this available to show that the effect cannot happen without the
case would be a rather cruel business), or even derived from indicated cause. One of Collingwood's examples, 'The cause
theoretical knowledge (which is, in this case,unlikely). But in of malaria is the bite of a mosquito', shows how such theoreti-
at any rate a great number of contexts where we'should be cal support may sometimesfunction, for it is, in this case,our
general knowledge of the nature of the disease, and the way
I As the discussion of section
6 will show, this threefold distinction does not
coincide with Collingwood's division of 'cause' into three .senses,. ' pp.236-8.
z The Logic of the
Sciencesand the Humanities, London, tg47, p, z6o, " Gardiner,op. cit., p. 84; tlempel, op. cit., p. 46r; Crawford,op. cit., p. r64.
ro 8 CA US A L LA WS AN D C AU SA L A N A LY S IS cH .rv sEcr.4 CAUSAL LAWS AS GENERALIZATIONS ro9
the virus must reach the blood-stream, that allows us to regard amongthe antecedentsof a particular war, he would still not
the bite as a general/y necessary condition. But what about know the explanationof the war in question; he would s/i//
'The cause of road accidents is speed', or ,The cause of war have to ask whether greed was in this casethe cause.
is greed'? Laws of the form, 'The causeof y is cc',ate in fact seldom
It seemsto me that where no theoretical backing is available likely to be availableto the historian; they are certainly less
for them, such 'laws' can only be interpreted aJ genertliza- likely to be known than laws of the form, 'X causesy'. Since
tions, and perhaps not even as universal in intention. Thev even where they were available, they would have a very
merely summarize a trend, observed in the particular dubious explanatoryforce, this neednot be thought to create
toward the isolation of one sort of condition as especially "u."S, any difficulty for the giving of causalexplanationsin history-
noteworthy. The law, 'The cause of malaria is the blte of a a f.act sometimeslost sight of in discussionsof the special
mosquito', tells us there is only one way to get malaria. But problems of causal inquiry in history. M. R. Cohen, for
the 'law', 'The cause of road accidents is speed', cannot instance,points out that just aswe cannotaskfor the ca;use of
plausibly beinterpreted in this way; it tells us only that speed disease;so we cannotaskfor the catseof historicalphenomena
is a particularly common or important condition of such like tradedisturbances; fortheclassof thingsinquestion,hesayg
accidents. If this is so, however, the explanatory force of the is too heterogeneous for us to expectto find a commoncause.I
law- i,s obviously nil when we come to investigate a particular In the light of what hasjust beensaid,however,it will be seen
accident, for we have to discover independently whether in that this, althoughit may be true, is no problem whateverfor
that particular casethe usual causewas operativeor not. Such anhistorianwhowishesto explainaparticulartradedisturbance.
a law can be no more than suggestive in the search for the Nor would the explanatoryforce of laws of the kind dis-
actual cause; it merely reminds the historian that (e.g.) on many cussedbe increasedby framing them in terms of a plurality
occasions the cause of war has been found to be greed, so that of causes.Perhapsan historian would not regard it as part
it is worth his while to be on the lookout for ihis factor as of his proper task to give an apswerto a question like 'What
a possible cause. are the causesof war ?' Yet it might very well be regardedas
It is-worth noticing that if laws of the form ,the cause of belongingto the sphereof the generalizingsocialsciences.
y-is. x', strictly interpreted, ztrereused by historians in giving Such a case,however,would illustrate very badly the general
their explanations, we should have to sav that the historian positivist thesis regarding the. proper relationship between
would know the explanation of what he studied without historian and sociologist: that the historian digs up facts,
bothering to find out by historical research what the ante- passesthem to the social scientist so that he can make laws
cedent conditions actually were. For the existenceof the causal out of them, and return them for applicationby the historian
condition could simply be retrodicted by means of the law- in particular explanations.For in the caseenvisaged,the 'facts'
as we should have no'hesitation in doing, for instance, in which the historianwould deliverfor the purposeof generaliza-
the malaria case.In the historical exarnple discussedabove, the tion would already be explained: they would consistof par-
most that would be left for the historian's investigation of the ticular explanationsof particularwars.What the generalization
particular case would be the detailed description of ttt" greed would add to the historian's diagnosesis merely to elicit any
which caused this particular war. But this of course bears no general trend there may be toward the selectionof certain
resemblance to the problem which has to be solved in typical t 'Causation and its Application to History',
Journal of the History of ldeas,
historical cases. For even if the historian should 1 9 4 2 ,P . 1 7 ,n , 2 .
fi.nd.'greed
TTo CAUSAL LAWS AND CAUSAL ANALYSIS cH.rv sEcr.5MISGMNGS ABOUT CAUSAL LANGUAGE rrr
conditions as causes.It is not to depreciate the usefulnessof torians should abandon the claim that they discover causes;
such generalizations to point out that the resulting law can they should say only that certain events and conditions 'arise
scarcely provide the justification for the individual explana- out of' other events and conditions.' A quite different sug-
tions upon which it rests. gestion may be gleaned from the view of those who, like
M. R. Cohen, regard a 'tight' sense of the word 'cause' as
5. Misgioings about Causal Langutagein History strictly correct, but who go on to allow that there is a looser
In the light of the foregoing discussion, what can be said to sensewhich is appropriate in "popular discourse".2 The sug-
ease the misgivings of those who question the propriety of gestion would seem to be that the more carefully, i.e. 'scientifi-
causal terminology in historical writing ? It seems to me that cally', history is written, the more likely it is that we shall find
the objections of both the opponents and the supporters of the 'cause' used to designatea set of sufficient conditions.
covering law model owe a great deal of their plausibility to Should a 'tight' sense of the word be adopted in order to
their failure to take into account some of the features of causal improve the precision of historical writing ? There are right
inquiries which have just been examined. and wrong reasonsfor resisting such a programme. One of the
Is 'cause' a loose or vague term I Those who, like Beard wrong ones was given by Collingwood when he attacked the
and Vagts, have urged its abandonment have generally rested tight sense as self-contradictory (he called it 'Sense III', and
their case on the fact that singular causal statements made by claimed to find it in the literature of the theoretical sciencesof
historians commonly come to grief when they are generalized nature). Collingwood's argument is a development of Russell's
as causallaws. They seethat from most of the conditions which complaint that in order to be strictly sufficient for predicting
historians designate as causes,the effect could not safely have the effect, cause and effect must be coincidml in space and
been predicted. But why should they have expected other- time-so that the cause becomes identical with the effect, and
wise ? It can surely only be because the illicit assumption is hence no cause at all.s But the tight sensedefined by Mandel-
made that a cause, when fully stated, must always be a suffi- baum and Cohen would be subject to Collingwood's and
cient condition of its effect. This assumption has been re- Russell's strictures only if 'suffi.cient' were defined in a meta-
inforce{ from time to time by what philosophers have had to physically absolute way inappropriate to a 'scientific' use. All
say. Thus Mandelbaum, in a careful, formal statement, defines we need mean by the set of sufficient conditions (as I sug-
the cause of an event as "the complete set of those events gested in Chapter II), is those from which, on the criteria
without which the event would not have occurred, or whose we ordinarily accept as appropriate in the subject-matter
non-existence or non-occurrence would have made some concerned, the event could justifiably have been predicted.
difference to it".'. But this, as we have seen, is far from being The right reason for rejecting the suggestion is pragmatic;
the usual senseof the term in history. Indeed, even in con- I.'Foundations of the Social Sciences', International Encyclopedia of the
texts where causal lawq are formulated, the notion is not Unified Sciences, Chicago, rg44, vol, z, No, r, pp. zo-2,r, Gardiner mentions this,
op. cit., p. 9.
screwed up as tightly as this, since the causesin question are It is interesting to note that in a second bulletin ofthe Social Science Research
only sufficient conditions, ceterisparibus. Councilontheoryof history, historians are reported to be"ingeneral agreed that it
would be extremely difficult to devise wortable substitutes for such terms as'cause'
There are two ways in which reformers might hope to deal and 'causality' " (The Social Sciencesin Histoical Study, New York, tgg4, p. rz),
2 'Causation and its Application to History',
with the supposed 'looseness'of causal language in history. Journal of the Histoty of ldeat,
1942, p.19.
It has been proposed by O. Neurath, for instance, that his- 3 Russell, Mysticism and Logic, p. r87; Collingwood, Essay on Metaphysics,
I 'Causal Analysis in History', pp. 3r4-r5. Gardiner notes this argument, op. cit, p. 8.
Journel oJ the History of ldeas, 1942,p.39.
rtz CAUSAL LAWS AND CAUSAL ANALYSIS crr.rv sBcr. s MISGIVINGS ABOUT CAUSAL LANGUAGE tt3
for the so-called 'loose' senseof'cause' already has a useful ask what he regards as'the proper historical alternative to
employment in history. Historians use the notion to draw causal explanation. As we noted in Chapter III, he does not
attention to some necessarycondition which, for one reason or deny that the historian explains at all. It is rather that "history
another, is considered important in the context of writing. To accounts for change by means of a full account o/ change.
say that the word is ordinarily used 'vaguely' or 'loosely' is The relationbetutemevents", he says,"is alwaysother events,
thus misleading. We should say rather that the term has its and it is established in history by a full relation of the events."
own peculiar logic, which happens to be different from that According to Oakeshott, "The conception of cause is thus
invented for it by some philosophers. It cannot be tightened replaced by the exhibition of a world of events intrinsically
up in either the metaphysical or scientific ways without related to one another in which no lacuna is tolerated".'
changing its function; and the reformed notion could not, in That something correct and important is here being said I
any case, be employed without bringing historical narrative should not want to question. But, in the light of my discussion
to a halt. Nor need we be tempted by Neurath's curious in the present chapter, the sharp contrast which Oakeshott
linguistic recommendation; for this loses its point if we recog- draws between causal explanation and discovering the actual
nize the fact that there is nothing wrong with calling anything course of events is surely misconceived. Oakeshott assumes
less than a set of sufficient conditions a 'cause'. that to assign a causeto an event is to bring that event under a
The objection that causal analysis in history is not scientific law. True, he does not explicitly say this, but he does define
enough thus arises, at least in part, out ofa failureto appreciate 'cause' for scientific purposes as "the minimum antecedent
the point of causal language.What about the counter-objection circumstances sufficient to account for an etcampleof.a general-
that explanation in terms of causesis loo scientific ? According ized resrtlt"., And by contrast with the inapplicability of the
to Oakeshott, the search for causes is anti-historical in con- causal category to historf, he saysthat it is "possible in science
ception; it belongs to the practical (for him 'scientific') problem only becausethe world of scientific experience is a world, not
of prediction and control. To pick out causes is somehow to of events but of instances".r He concludes: "the strict con-
falsify dre concrete nature of the historian's subject-matter; ception of cause breaks down as the explanatory principle in
to divert attention from the actual course of events which it is historical experience, becausq it contradicts the postulated
the historian's business to reconstruct from the evidence. In character of the historical past. . . ."4
taking such a view, Oakeshott has the qualified support of It is the relegation of the discovery of causesto the world of
some members of the historical profession. Professor Renier, 'instances' which reveals the source of the difficulty. For if
fo.r instance, believes that "the normal interpretation of causa- all causal inquiry was like that experimentation which yields
tion contains dangerous elements which threaten the basic knowledge of causal laws-general causal relationships-
quality of the historical narrative".' And Teggart, too, regards Oakeshott's criticism would have some force. But, as I have
historical narration andathe search for cdusesas incompatible shown, to give and defend a causal explanation in history is
tasks-although, being a campaigner for 'scientific' history, scarcely ever to bring what is explained under a law, and
this leads him to take a jaundiced view of narrative rather almost always involves a descriptive account, a narrative, of
than of causal analysis.2 the actual course of events, in order to justify the judgement
What really bothers Oakeshott comes out more clearly if we
I Op. cit,, p. r43. 2 Op. cit., p. zr r. My italics.
I History, Its Putposeand Mahod, London, r95o, p. r8r. 3 Op. cit., p. rz7. Gardiner notes the objection briefly, op. cit., p. 3o.
1 'Causation in Historical Events', Jownal of the Hittory of ldeas, rg4z, p. 6. a Op. cit., p. r33.
4880.10 I
II4 CAUSAL LAWS AND CAUSAL ANALYSIS cH.Iv sEcr.s MISGIVINGS ABOUT CAUSAL LANGUAGE r15
that the condition indicated was indeed the cause.Finding the wrong sense.For according to Collingrvood, there are three
cause of an historical event is thus no substitute for knowing sensesof 'cause', and the only proper use of the word in
exactly what happened-which Oakeshott rightly regards as history is in SenseI: the sensein which one person can cause
an essentialmark of historical inquiry. Indeed, it involves a another to act in a certain way by providing him with a motive
judgement which depends on knowing just that. for acting so.' Sense II he defines as "an event or state of
It is true that in the explanatory statement which arises out things by producing or preventing which we can produce or
of this detailed knowledge, one or a few conditions are picked prevent that whose cause it is said to be". Sense III he
out as 'the cause'. But this does not amount to opening a defines thus:
'lacuna'; nor does it confer upon the causal condition any . . . that which is 'caused'is an eventor stateof things,and its 'cause'
mysterious ontological priority.' It merely satisfies certain is anothereventor stateof thingsstandingto it in a one-onerelationof
pragmatic criteria of importance which are superimposed upon, causalpriority: i.e.a relationof sucha kind that (a) if the causehappens
but do not replace, the inductive requirement that the causal or existsthe effectmust alsohappenor exist, evenif no further con-
condition be a necessaryone. If Oakeshott were to object ditionsarefulfilled,(1,)the effectcannothappenor existunlessthe cause
further (as I think he would) that to select any conditions at all happensor exists,(c) in somesensewhich remainsto be .defined,the
causeis prior to the effect.. . .2
as of more importance than the rest is to allow an intrusion of
the practical into an 'historical world' where such considera- These three sensesCollingwood regardsas relatedby historical
tions do not belong, I can only resist his a priori conception derivation from each other. SenseII is derived from SenseI
of what the historian should be trying to do when he explains by extending the notion of an effect from the actions of human
a thing-i.e. write history from no point of view whatever.z beings to the behaviour of anything whatever. Sense III is
He is doubtless right to insist that all the conditions of an derived from Sense II by tightening the connexion between
historical event are necessary,and that the making of distinc- cause and effect to one of logical necessity, and making the
tions on grounds of importance must not be allowed to obscure relation between cause and effect one-one.
this truth.r But that necessaryconditions are all necessary is, Collingwood representsSenseII as the one appropriate for
after al! no more than a (perhaps useful) tautology. the practical sciencesof nature,; it is the sense employed in
A misunderstanding of the difference between causal laws the discovery of causallaws by experimentation (as discussed
and causal analysis seemsto me also to lie behind Colling- in section z above). To say that the historian never uses the
wood's restriction of the senseof 'cause' which is properly notion of'cause' in this senseis, perhaps, a pardonable exag-
employed in history. Like Oakeshott, Collingwood believes geration; for, as I have argued, it is true that his explanations
that in using the notion there is a danger that the historian are scarcely ever the applications of causal laws. Yet, as I
may be tempted to slide away from the proper historical task pointed out earlier, there is a weak as well as a strong inter-
into something like scicntific interests. But this will only pretation which might be placed upon Collingwood's criterion
happen, he contends, if the historian uses the word in the of the 'handle', and in the weak interpretation this criterion is
t Renier deplores the
very often applied by the historian in selecting one from a
"feeling that a cause occupies a position superior in
reality to its efrect" (op. cit., pp. r8r and 183-4). number of necessaryconditions as important. Collingwood's
t I ofrer further reasons for denying that the historian's I This sense is further discussed in Chap. V, section
approach is divorced 7. I do not here question
from a'practical'one in Chap. V, section 4. Collingwood's speaking of 'senses' of the word 'cause', although it seems to me
3 ". . . every historical event is necessary, and it is impossible to distinguish
preferable to speak of ways of establishing a causal connexion.
between the importance of necessities" (op. cit., p. rzg), 2 Aa Essay on Metaphyics, p. 285-6.
116 CAUSAL LAWS AND CAUSAL ANALYSIS cH.rv S E cT.5MIS GIV IN GS A BO UT CAUSAL LANG UAG E TI 7
SenseII is therefore open to further analysis.In so far as he
priety of the causal concept outside the spheres of individual
means a cause which is sufficient, ceteris paribus, then this
human relations and the practical sciences. For there is a
sense is an uncommon, uncharacteristic one in historical
perfectly proper use of 'cause' in the applied theoretical
studies. But if he simply means a cause selected becauseit is
sciences.It is the sense brought to our attention by Ryle's
a manipulable necessarycondition in a determinate situation,
doctrine of 'theory-loaded'causal terms. The sensein which a
then it is in quite common use. Let us call the latter, historical
wound may be the cause of a scar is not included in Colling-
sense,SenseIIa.
wood's threefold classification. In such a case,the relationship
Like Oakeshott, Collingwood is suspicious of any attempt
between causeand effect clearly falls short of the requirements
to represent the historian as applying knowledge of general
of Sense III, while going beyond Sense II by virtue of the
causal connexions in historical cases.It is part of his argument
explanatory force of the causal assertion. Let us call this further
against the historical propriety of Sense II that in this sense
use of the term 'Sense IIIa'. I call it this becauseit is the
"every causal proposition is a general proposition", whereas proper substitute for Collingwood's Sense III when we are
in SenseI every one is individual.' In SenseII, he concludes,
applying theoretical science. It might, however, have been
"it would be nonsense to inquire after the cause of any indi-
almost as appropriately designated SenseI16, since the require-
vidual thing as such". While I seeno reason to agree with the
ment that there be a theoretical connexion between causeand
latter conclusion,I think it is true, at any rate, that in SenseIIa,
effect would generally be applied as well as, and not instead of,
a causal proposition need not assert a causal connexion which
Collingwood's criterion of the 'handle'. It seemsto me that
can be generalized.
in his anxiety to discredit the metaphysically exaggerated
Collingwood's Sense III is a very queer fish. As I have
SenseIII, Collingwood overlooked this important'scientific'
already remarked, it involves a senseof 'sufficient condition'
sense of 'cause' altogether. And in doing so, although he
which is tightened up in a metaphysical way. It also, as stated,
would not have liked this suggestion, he failed to give a com-
makes the cause retrodictable from the effect. At the same
plete account of causal explanations in history either; for his
time, causesand effects are represented as coincident in space
classification leaves no room foi the explanations historians
and time. We need have little hesitation in following Colling-
may-perhaps only rarely-give in the light of theoretical
wood in denying the usefulness of this notion in history-or
knowledge derived from the social, or even the natural,
in other studies either, for that matter. In fact, as Collingwood
sciences.
more than half admits, it is a philosopher's invention; it is a
bogus senseof the word 'thought to be' used in the theoretical
sciences of nature. There is perhaps some excuse for the
philosophers concerned in the fact that such sciences do
enunciate simultaneity lgws, and that, relative to some theory,
and in the light of certaih other conditions, it may be logically
impossible for an effect not to follow'a cause.But as Colling-
wood states SenseIII, it is, as he says, self-contradictory.
In defining it as he does, however, Collingwood fails to
prove the point he seems to want to make about the impro-
I Op. cit., p.
3o8.
sE cT.
I H IS TORI CAL UNDERSTANDI NG II9

seco;rd of these claims which I especially want to consider


here.
V The doctrine is commonly expressed with the aid of a
characteristic set of terms. To understand a human action, it
T H E R A T ION A L E OF A CTIONS will be said, it is necessaryfor the inquirer somehow to dis-
cover its 'thought-side'; it is not sufficient merely to know
as' Empathetic'
t. HistoricalUnderstanding the pattern of overt behaviour. The historian must penetrate
y discussion
of the coveringlaw theoryup to this point behind appearances,achieve insight into the situation, idmtifu
has been concernedchiefly with its applicability to himself sympathetically with the protagonist, project himself
explanations given of fairly large-scale historical imaginatively into his situation. He must reoiae, re-enact, /e-
events or conditions. I now want to direct attention to a think, re-experiencethe hopes, fears, plans, desires, views,
narrower range of cases: the kind of explanation historians intentions, &c., of those he seeksto understand. To explain
generally give of the actions of those individuals who are action in terms of covering law would be to achieve, at most,
important enough to be mentioned in the course of historical an external kind of understanding. The historian, by the very
narrative. It will be my thesis in this chapter that the explana- nature of his self-imposed task, seeksto do more than this.
tion of individual human behaviour as it is usually given in It is worth noticing that historians themselves,and not just
history has features which make the covering law model professional philosophers of history, often describe their task
peculiarly inept. in theseterms. ProfessorButterfield is representativeof a large
My argument in Chapter II was, in part, an attempt to group of his professional colleagues when he insists that "the
clarify the sense in which historians' explanations can be, only understanding we ever reach in history is but a refine-
and often are, given of unique events: a doctrine commonly ment, more or less subtle and sensitive, of the difficult-and
found in the writings of certain idealist philosophers of his- sometimes deceptive-process of imagining oneself in another
tory. What I now wish to say may be regarded as an attempt person's place". And elsewherein History and Human Rela-
to rehabilitate to some extent a second traditional doctrine of tions, he writes: I
idealist philosophers of history which Gardiner has attacked Our traditionalhistoricalwriting . . . hasrefusedto be satisfiedwith
at length: the view that the objects of historical study are any merelycausalor stand-o{fishattitudetowardsthe personalitiesof
fundamentally different from those, for example, of the the past. It doesnot treat them as merethings, or just measuresuch
natural sciences, because they are the actions of beings like featuresof them asthe scientistmight measure;and it doesnot content
itself with merelyreportingaboutthem in the way an externalobserver
ourselves;and that even if (for the sakeof argument) we allow would do. It insiststhat the storycannotbe told correctlyunlesswe see
that natural events may be explained by subsuming them the personalities from the inside,feelingwith them as an actor might
under empirical laws, it rfould still be true that this procedure feel the part he is playing-thinking their thoughtsover againand sit-
is inappropriate in history. Sometimes such a view will be ting in the positionnot of the observerbut of the doerof the action.If it
supported by the belief that human actions-at any rate the is arguedthat this is impossible-as indeedit is-not merely doesit
ones we call 'free'-do not fall under law at all. Sometimes still remainthe thing to aspireto, but in anycasethe historianmustput
himselfin the placeof the historicalpersonage, must feel his predica-
it will be alleged only that even if they do fall under law, dis- ment,mustthink asthoughhe lverethat man.Without this art not only
covery of the law would still not enable us to understand them is it impossibleto tell the storycorrectlybut it is impossibleto interpret
in the sense proper to this special subject-matter. It is the the very documentson which the reconstruciiondepends.Traditional
r2 O T HE RA T IO N AL E OF AC T IO N S cH. v sE cr.r H IS I' OR IC A L UNDERSTANDI NG r zr
historical writing emphasizesthe importance of sympathetic imagina- the particular motivations of his heroes; he tentatively generalizeshis
tion for the purpose of getting inside human beings. We may even say findings into a general rule and uses the latter as an explanatory prin-
that this is part of the science of history for it produces communi- ciple in accounting for the actions of the persons involved. Now, this
cable results-the insight of one historian may be ratified by scholarsin procedure may sometimesprove heuristically helpful; but its use does
general,who then give currency to the interpretation that is produced.. . .r not guaranteethe soundnessofthe historical explanationto which it leads.
The latter rather depends upon the factual correctnessof the empirical
Among covering law logicians there is an 'official' answer generalizationswhich the method of understandingmay have suggested.
to philosophers or historians who talk in this way about the Nor is the use of this method indispensablefor historical explanation.
peculiarities of 'historical understanding'. The answer is that A historian may, for example,be incapableof feeling himself into the role
although there is something right about it, the element of truth of a paranoiac historic personality, and yet be able to explain certain
in such an account is not a point of logic; it is a mixture of of his actions; notably by referenceto the principles of abnormalpsycho-
logy. Thus whether the historian is or is not in a position to identify
psychological description and methodological precept. As a
himself with his historical hero, is irrelevant for the correctnessof his
psychological description of the historian's state of mind when explanation; what counts, is the soundnessof the general hypotheses
he succeedsin explaining the action of one of his characters, involved, no matter whether they were suggestedby empathy, or by a
the notion of 'empathy' or'imaginative understandingl, as it strictly behaviouristic procedure.'
is often called, will be allowed some merit-although it will be
represented as involving us all too easily in the philosophical Now I do not wish to deny that there is any value at all in
error of thinking that merely having certain experiences, or this sort of objection. But I think it important to show that
thinking certain thoughts similar to those of the historical the argument does not cut as deeply as covering law theorists
agents, itself constitutes understanding or explaining. Simi- commonly assume. For in recognizing the mixture of psycho-
larly, as a suggestion as to how to go about discovering what logical and methodological elements in many statements of
the agent's motives were, the 'empathy' theory will be admitted the idealist position, and in denying that these amount to an
to have a certain methodological point-although the reserva- analysis of logical stmcture, these theorists fail to notice what
tion will be made that the principle involved often leads the it is about explanations of human actions in history which
invesgigator astray. Professor Hempel puts the position suc- make the idealists want to say what they do-albeit in a quasi-
cinctly in the following passage: psychological and quasi-methodological way. And what is left
out, f wish to maintain, should properly be taken into account
The historian,we aretold, imagineshimselfin the placeof the per-
sonsinvolvedin the eventswhich he wantsto explain;he triesto realize in a logical analysis of explanation as it is given in history. I
ascompletelyaspossiblethe circumstances underwhichtheyacted,and shall argue that idealist theory partially, and perhaps de-
the motiveswhich influencedtheir actions;and by this imaginaryself- fectively, formulates a certain pragmatic criterion operating in
identificationwith his heroes,he arrivesat an understandingand thus explanations of action given by historians, and that when this
at an adequate explanationof the eventswith whichhe is concerned. is ignored, we are quite properly puzzled as to why certain
This methodof empatly is, no doubt,frequentlyappliedby laymen
alleged explanations, which meet the covering law require-
andby expertsin history.But it doesnot in itselfconstitutean explana-
tion; it ratheris essentially
a heuristicdevice;its functionis to suggest ments, would be dismissed by historians as unsatisfactory-
certain psychologicalhypotheseswhich might serveas explanatory perhaps even as 'no explanation at all'.
principlesin the caseunder consideration. Statedin crudeterms,the The discussion to follow may be regarded in part as an
idea underlyingthis function is the following: the historianries to
t Op. cit., p.467. A similar argument is used by Crawford, op. cit., p. rS7;
realizehow he himselfwouldactunderthe givenconditions,andunder
R. S. Peters, op. cit., p. t43; Gardiner, op. cit., p. r2gi A. Danto, in 'Mere
I pp. 145-6. See also pp. 116-17.
Chronicle aod History Proper', Journal of Philosophy,1953,p. 176.
I?2 T HE R AT ION AL E O F AC T I ON S sncr.z EXPLAINING AND JUSTII'YING ACTIONS r"3
attempt to 'make sense' of what Collingwood, in particular, But the notion of discovering the agent'scalculation, it must
has to say about historical understanding-and I make no be admitted, takes us no more than one preliminary step to-
apology for this. But although some reference will be made wards a satisfactoryanalysisof such explanations; and it may
to dicta of his, I shall not offer any close textual discussion of in itself be misleading. It must not be assumed,for instance,
his account. I shall try, rather, to bring out independently, that the agent 'calculated' in the senseof deriving by strict
by reference to examples, features which covering law theory deductive reasoning the practical conclusion he drew-i.e.
seems to me to miss, going on thereafter to discuss likely that the various considerationsare elementsin a calculus. In-
misunderstandings of, and objections to, the logical point deed, Trevelyan's explanation provides an obvious example
which appears to emerge out of such an examination. to the contrary. Nor should we assumethat the explanatory
calculation must have been recited in propositional form,
z. Explaining and Just{ying Actions
either aloud or silently-a notion which one might be for-
The following extract from G. M. Trevelyan's The English given for extracting out of Collingwood's discussion of the
Reaolution is typical of a wide range of explanations of indi- way thought must be re-enacted by historians in order to
vidual actions to be found in ordinary historical writing. In understand intelligent, purposive actions. Not all high-grade
the courseof an account of the invasion of England by William actions are performed deliberately in the sense that they are
of Orange, Trevelyan asks: "Why did Louis make the greatest undertaken with a plan consciouslypreformulated.
mistake of his life in withdrawing military pressurefrom Hol- Indeed, it is tempting to say that in such casesthere is zo
land in the summer of 1688?" His answer is: calculation to be reconstructed by the historian. But such an
He wasvexedwith James,who unwiselychosethis momentof all, to admission need not affect the main point; for in so far as we
refusethe helpand adviceof his Frenchpatron,upon whosefriendship
say an action is purposive at all, no matter at what level of
he had basedhis wholepolicy.But Louis was not entirelypassion's
slave.No doubthe felt irritationwith James,but he alsocalculatedthat, conscious deliberation, there is a calculation which could be
evenif William landedin England,therewould be civil war and long constructed for it: the one the agent would have gone through
troubles,asalwaysin that factiousisland.Meanwhile,he couldconquer if he had had time, if he had not seen what to do in a flash, if
Europeat leisure," For twentyyears,"saysLoid Acton,"it hadbeenhis he had been called upon to account for what he did after the
desireto neutralizeEnglandby internalbroils,and he wasgladto have event, &c. And it is by eliciting some such calculation that we
the Dutch out of the way (in England)while he dealt a blow at the
EmperorLeopold(in Germany)."H" thought"it was impossiblethat explain the action. It might be added that if the agent is to
the conflictbetrveenJamesandWilliam shouldnot yield him an oppor- understand his own actions, i.e. after the event, he may have
tunity." This calculationwasnot asabsurdasit looksafterthe event.It to do so by constructing a calculation in exactly the sameway,
wasonlydefeated by theunexpected r
solidityof anewtypeof Revolution. although at the time he recited no propositions to himself. No
What Trevelyan here makesquite explicit is that, when we ask doubt there are special dangers involved in such construc-
for the explanation of 'ln action, what we very often want is a tion after the fact. But although we may have to examine very
reconstruction of the agent'scalculationof meansto be adopted critically any particular example, the point is that when we do
toward his chosen end in the light of the circumstances in consider ourselvesjustified in accepting an explanation of an
which he forrnd himself. To explain the action we need to individual action, it u'ill most often assumethe generalform of
know what considerations convinced him that he should act an agent's calculation.
as he did. Since the calculation gives what we should normally
I pp. ro5-6, call the agent's leasons for acting as he did, I shall refer
T HE RA T IO N AL E OF AC T IO N S srcr.z E X P LA IN IN G AND JUSTI FYI NG ACTI O NS t zi
r 24 cH. v

hereafter to this broad class of explanationsas 'rational'. along which rational explanations can be ranged. The scale
It should be clear that this use of the expression'rational falls away from the simple case in which we can say: 'I find
explanation'is a narrower one than is often found in philo- his action perfectly intelligible; he did exactly as I should
sophical and semi-philosophicalliterature. It is sometimes have done.' It is a small step from such a case to one where
said, for instance, that all science,all systematicinquiry, we can understand an action when we see that it is what we
seeksa rational explanationfor what is observed,where all should agree was the thing to do in view of the agent's peculiar
that is meant is an explanationwhich takesaccountof all the circumstances. In such a casethe explanation would consist of
facts considercdpuzzling, and which does not violate, say, an account of these circumstances; they are the missing data
the canonsof coherenceand induction. I intend something which permit the construction of a calculation certifying the
much more restrictedthan this: an explanationwhich displays action as appropriate. Sometimes, of course, the agent is
the rationak of what was done. found to have been mistaken about the facts-including (as
The goal of suchexplanationis to showthat what wasdone Trevelyan's example of Louis XIV shows) his views about
was the thing to have done for the reasonsgiven, rather than what the results of certain lines of action will be. The agent
merely the thing that is done on such occasions,perhapsin is thus mistaken about the nature of his circumstances; yet
accordancewith certain laws (looseor otherwise).The phrase his action can still be explained in the rational way so long as
'thing to have done' betraysa crucially important feature of by bringing his erroneous beliefs to bear, the calculation can
explanations in terms of agent calculations-a feature quite be satisfactorily constructed. It may also be necessary, at
different from any we have noticed so far. For the infinitive times, to take note explicitly of the agent's purposes, which
'to do' herefunctionsasa valueterm. I wish to claim therefore may be quite different from the ones which the investigator
that tlrere is an element of.appraisal of.what was done in such would have had in the same circumstances, or even in the
explanations;that what we want to know when we ask to have circumstances the agent envisaged. And the calculation may
the action explainedis in what way it wasWropiate.Inthe also have to take into account certain peculiar principles of the
ordinary courseof affairs, a demandfor explanationis often agent; for the action is rationally explained if it is in accordance
recogrfizedto be bt the sametime a challengeto the agentto with the agent's principles-4o matter what we think of these.
produce either justification or excusefor what was done. In There are thus gradations of rational explanation, depend-
history, too, I want to argue,it will often be found impossible ing on the amount of 'foreign' data which the investigator
to bring out the point of what is offeredas explanationunless must bring in to complete the calculation: beliefs, purposes,
the overlappingof thesenotions,when it is human actionswe principles, &c., of the agent which are different from those we
are interestedin, is explicitly recognized. might have assumed in absence of evidence to the contrary.
Once again,however,I must be on guard againstoverstat- Rational explanation may be regarded as an attempt to reach
ing the point; for I dofrot wish to imply that anything that is a kind of logical equilibrium at which point an action is
explainedon the rational model is.thereby certified aithout matched with a calculation. A demand for explanation arises
qulaliftcationasthe right, or proper, or intelligent thing to have when the equilibrium is upset-when from the 'considerations'
done. In saying that the explanationmust exhibit what was obvious to the investigator it is impossible to see the point of
done as appropriateor justified it is alwaysnecessaryto add what was done. The function of the historian's explanatory
the philosopher'sproviso:'in a sense.' story will in many casesbe to sketch in the corrections to these
The sensein question may be clarified if we note a scale 'obvious' considerations which require to be made if the
,2 6 T HE R AT ION AL E O F A C T ION S cH. v sE cr.3 TH E ' ID E NTI FI CATI O N' M ETAPI {O R r z7
reader is to be able to say: 'Now I understand what he was unless you drop your 2oth century prejudices and try to see
about." things from their point of view', he may be telling the novice
In the light of this account, it should be clear how restricted how to get on with his job, and thus be making a point which
is the sensein which a rational explanation, as I use the term might be called 'methodological'. But I cannot believe that
here, must show that what was done was the appropriate or what the old hand offers his young colleagueis (in Hempel's
right thing to have done. It is not necessaryfor the historian words) "a heuristic device" whose function is "to suggest
to show that the agent had reason for what he did; it is suffi- certain psychological hypotheses which might serve as ex-
cient for explanation to show that he had reasons. But the planatory principles in the case under consideration". As
element of appraisal remains in that what the historian de- Hempel goes on to explain, by this he means that the his-
clares to have been the agent's reasons must really Dereasons torian, since he lacks empirically tested psychological laws
(from the ,agent's point of view). To record what the agent which fit, say, the behaviour of medieval knights, must do
said his reasons were would not be enough to provide a something about repairing the deficiency if he is ever to give
rational explanation unless the cogency of such reported an explanation of knightly activities; for according to the
reasonscould be appreciatedby the historian, when any pecu- covering law theory there is no explanation without em-
liar beliefs, purposes, or principles of the agent were taken into pirical laws. Clearly the historian, especiallythe novice, is in
account. Reported reasons,ifthev are to be explanatory in the no position to work over the whole field himself in search of
rational way, must be good reasonsat least in the sensethat gf the required laws. So, according to Hempel, he takes a short
the situation had been as the agent envisaged it (whether or cut; he imagines himself in the knight's position, asks himself
not we, from our point of vantage, concur in his view of it), whzt he would have done, generalizes the answer as an em-
then what was done would have been the thing to have done. pirical law covering knights (i.e. from a single imaginary case),
The historian must be able to 'work' the agent's calculation. and in this way satisfiesthe logical requirements of the model.
Hempel warns us, of course,,thatthe use of the 'device' does
g. The Point of the'Identification' Metaphor not "guarantee the soundness of the historical explanation to
If rhy account of rational explanation is correct, what should which it leads", which depends rather "upon the factual cor-
we say about the view that historical understanding is 'em- rectness of the empirical generalizations which the method
pathetic'? It seemsto me that our being able to range rational of understanding may have suggested". That is, we may pre-
explanations along a scale in the way described above gives sume, further empirical confirmation of the generalization
a real point to the 'projection' metaphors used by empathy must come in before we can regard the explanation as any-
theorists. Perhaps it is because the scale has been either thing more than an inspired guess. In Hempel's terminolory,
ignored or misunderstood that what such theorists have said the generalization is only a "hypothesis" until it has received
has been so easily written off as obvious but uninteresting, or the sort of empirical confirmation and testing that any re-
as interesting but dangerous. spectable scientific law must undergo, losing in the processthe
Covering law logicians commonly speak of empathy as a marks of its AthenaJike origin.
'methodological dodge'. And it might, I suppose,be claimed In the light of what was said in the previous section, it
that if an old, practised historian were to say to a novice: 'You should be clear how misleading this is as an account of 'em-
will never understand the way medieval knights behaved pathetic understanding'. No doubt there esa methodological
I See note C,p. r7r.
side to the doctrine; and it might be formulated in some such
128 T I { E R AT ION AL E O F A C T ION S cH. v srcr.3 THE 'IDENTIFICATION' METAPHOR rzg
way as: 'Only by putting yourself in the agent's position can mena in questionas somehow'plausible'or'natural'to us . . .
you fi.nd out why he did what he did.' Here the suggestion is by means of attractively worded metaphors".
admittedly that by an imaginative technique we shall dis- No doubt the widespread resistance to admitting the need
cover some neut information-the agent's motives or reasons to cite anything more than antecedent conditions and a general
for acting. When Collingwood saysthat historical understand- law in explaining actions owes something to the air of mystery
ing consists of penetrating to the thought-side of actions- surrounding the language in which 'empathy' theory is often
discovering the thought and nothing further-the temptation framed:'projection','identification','imagination','insight',
to interpret this in the methodological way is understandably 'intuition', &c. Such words arouse the suspicion that, if the
strong. But there is another way in which the doctrine can be conditions of the covering law theory are not met, it will be
formulated: 'Only by putting yourself in the agent's position necessary to claim that the historian's explanation somehow
can you understandwhy he did what he did.' The point of the goes beyond the limits of empirical inquiry into the realm of
'projection' metaphor is, in this case, more plausibly inter- the unverifiable. As Gardiner puts it, historians often seem
preted as a logical one. Its function is not to remind us of to be credited with "an additional power of knowing which
lnw we corne to hnow certain facts, but to formulate, how- allows them to 'penetrate into' the minds of the subjects of
ever tentatively, certain conditions which must be satisfied their study and take, as it were, psychological X-ray photo-
before a historian is prepired to say: 'Now I have the explana- graphs".' And in the bulletin of the American Social Science
tion.' Research Council already referred to, historians are warned
To dismiss 'empathy' as a mere'methodological dodge' is against a view of 'historical understandingr'supposed to be
to assume, falsely, that all there is to notice when rational "achieved not by introducing general laws or relevant ante-
explanations are given is a second-rate method of obtaining cedent events, but by an act of intuition', 'imaginative identi-
the same sort of result as can be obtained more reliably by fication', 'empathy' or 'valuation' which makes the historical
direct attempts to subsume what is to be explained under an occurrence plausible or intelligible", and whose adequacy is
empirical covering law. But, as I have tried to show, at least determined by "a self-certifying insight".z To allow the legiti-
part of what is meant by talking about the 'need to project', macy of empathy appears to many of its opponents as the
&c., is not.achievable at all by the method recommended by granting of a licence to eke out scanty evidence with imagina-
covering law theorists. To accept Hempel's argument against tive filler.
'empathy' is to obliterate a distinction between explanation It is the.reforeworth my denying explicitly that what I have
types: a distinction between representing something as the called rational explanation is in any damaging sense beyond
thing generally done, and representing it as the appropriate empirical inquiry. As I have pointed out already, it has an
thing to have done. Thus, when Hempel, after the passage inductive, empirical side, for we build up to explanatory
quoted, goes on to say;:"The kind of understanding thus con- equilibrium from the eoidence.To get inside Disraeli's shoes
veyed must be clearly separated from scientific understand- the historian does not simply ask himself : 'What would I have
ing", I have no objection to make, provided that by'scientific done ?'; he readsDisraeli's dispatches,his letters, his speeches,
understanding' is meant 'knowing to fall under an empirical &c.-and not with the purpose of discovering antecedentcon-
law'. But Hempel's account of the alternative is quite un- ditions falling under some empirically validated law, but rather
satisfactory. For'empathetic understanding', interpreted as in the hope of appreciating the problem as Disraeli saw it. The
'rational explanation', is not a matter of "presenting the pheno- t Op. cit., p. rz8, 2 Bulletin No,
54, p, n8.
4980.10
r3 o T HE RAT ION AL E OF AC T IO N S cH. v srcr.3 THE 'IDENTIFICATION' METAPHOR r3r
attempt to provide rational explanation is thus-if you like mistake has been made in the inductive reasoning which pro-
the term-'scientific' explanation in a broad sense; there is vided the factual information for the calculation. It is always
no question of the investigator letting his imagination run possible that further data may come in which will upset the
riot. Indeed, many'empathy' theorists have expressly guarded logical equilibrium-perhaps evidence that the agbnt did not
against such a misinterpretation of their views. To Butterfield, know something which it was at first thought he did. The
for instance, historical understanding is not a deliberate com- ability of the historian to go through what he takes to be a
mission of the sin of anachronism; it is a "process of emptying relevant calculation does not guarantee the correctness of the
oneself in order to catch the outlook and feelings of men not explanation given; correctforrn is never a guarantee of correct
like-minded with oneself".' contmt. But this is nothing more than the normal hazard of
ft is true, of course, that the direction of inquiry in the any empirical inquiry.
explanation of actions is generally from what the inquirer
presumes the relevant agent calculation to be-using his own, 4. Gmeralizations and Principles of Action
or his society'sconception of rational purposesand principles Some exponents of the covering law model, while accepting
-to what he discovers to be the peculiar data of the historical the thesis of the two preceding sections, may object that this
agent: a direction suggested by the scale already indicated. only amounts to recognizingan additional condition of a prag-
In view of this, Butterfield's admonition to 'empty ourselves' matic sort which explanations must often satisfy in ordinary
is a little sweeping. In achieving rational explanation of an historical writing. It may be held, therefore, that what I say
action we do project-but we project from our own point of about rational explanation affects the claims of covering law
view. In each case, the inclusion of 'foreign' data in the cal- theory only on its sufficient condition side. It seems to me,
culation requires positive evidence that the zgent was not however, that in caseswhere we want to elicit the rationale of
like-minded with us. The historian does not build up to what was done, there are special reasons for regarding the
explanatory equilibrium from scratch. But this is far from model as false or misleading gn its necessary condition side
admitting the covering law objection that the whole direction as well. For in an important sense, rational explanation falls
of the inquiry amounts to a vicious methodology. The pro- short of, as well as goes beyond, subsuming a case under a
cedure is self-corrective. general empirical larv.
There is thus no reason to think that what I am calling Any argument to the effect that a satisfactory or complete
'rational' explanations are put forward as self-evidently true, rational explanation must subsume what is explained under
as some philosophers who talk of insight'may seem to imply. an empirically ascertainable 'regularity' depends on treating
Collingwood has sometimes been thought to provide justi- the data of the agent's calculation as 'antecedent conditions'
fication for those who attack empathy theory on this account (no doubt a very complicated set). It will be said that no
-e.9. when he repre*nts the understanding of an action as matter what elseis said about these conditions, they must be
an immediate leap to the discovery of its 'inside', without the data from which what was done could have been predicted;
aid of any general laws, and (it may appear) without the use of and that the only difficulties we should encounter in trying
any inductive reasoning at all." But it is always possible that a to formulate the implicit covering law linking these to actions
I Op. cit., p. 146. of the kind performed would be the ones discussed in Chapter
2 e.g.
"When [the historian] knows what happened, he already knows why it II above (which I propose to ignore here). If we say: 'Disraeli
happened" (The ldea of llistory, p.2r4), attacked Peel becausePeel was ruining the landed class', we
r32 T HE R AT ION AL E O F AC T IO N S cH. v
sEcT.4 P R IN C I PLES O F ACTI O N 133
mean inter alia that anyone like Disraeli in certain respects rational way those of his actions which were in accordance
would have done the same thing in a situation similar in with it. The connexionbetweena principle of action and the
certain respects-the respects in question being discol'ered by
'cases'falling under it is thus intentionally and peculiarly
pressing for amplification of the single reasongiven. loose.
Now this objection is an important one, becauseits plausi- I do not deny, of course,that we often canpredict success-
bility arises out of a genuine characteristic of rational explana- fully a person's responseto a situation if we know, among
tion which ought to be made clear. For it is quite true that other things, what his principles are (in so far as they are
'reasons for acting' as well as 'conditions for predicting' have peculiar).fn representingthe actionasthe thing to havedone,
a hind of generality or universality. If y is a good reason for even in the extendedsenserequired for rational explanation,
A to do r, then y would be a good reason for anyone suffi- we to someextent licensethe conclusionthat it was the thing
ciently hke A to do r under sufficiently similar circumstances. to haveexpected.Having said'A did r becauseofl', wherey
But this universality of reasons is unlike the generality of an is I's reasonfor doing r, we could alsosay thata bystander
empirically validated law in a way which makes it especially who knew the fact !, and also knew what l's purposesand
hazardous to say that by giving a rational explanation, an principleswere,shouldnot be surprisedat A's doing r. It is
historian commits himself to the truth of a corresponding law. thus easyenough,under the guidanceof a generaltheory of
For if a negative instance is found for a general empirical law, explanationwhich requires it, to slip into believing that the
the law itself must be modified or rejected, since it statesthat real force of the original explanationresidesin alleviatingsuch
people dobehavein a certain way under certain circumstances. surprise;that its point is to shorvthat this is the kind of thing
But if a negative instance is found for the sort of general state- we can expect to be done by such a person in such circum-
ment which might be extracted out of a rational explanation, stances,and that the justification for the expectationmust be
the latter would not necessarilybe falsified. For that statement found in experience of similar cases.
would expressa judgement of the form: 'When in a situation The widespreadfailure to distinguish betweenexplanations
of type CL . . . C" the thing to do is r.' The 'implicit law' in which '"pply' empirical laws and those which 'apply' prin-
such explanation is better called a principle of action than a ciples of action may owe sornethingto the fact that the word
generalization(or even a principle of inference).' 'because'is systematicallyambiguousin this connexion.Taken
It is true that finding a large number of negative instances in isolation,it is very seldombeyondall doubtwhethera given
-finding that people often do not act in accordancewith it- explanatorystatementof the form 'He did r becauseof y' is to
would create a presumption against the claim of a given prin- be takenin the rational senseor not, i.e. whether the 'because'
ciple to universal validity. But it would not compel its with- derivesits explanatoryforce from an empirical law or a prin-
drawal; and if it was not withdrawn, the explanatory value of ciple. The particular 'because'does not carry its language
the principle for thosenactionswhich were in accordancewith level on its face; this has to be determinedby other means.
it would remain. It is true, too, that if a particular person It is thus often possible to interpret an explanation at the
often acted at variance with a principle which he was said to wrong level for a long time without committing any obvious
hold, the statement that he held that principle would come logical errors.And this leavesplenty of room for maneuvring
into question. But that statement would not necessarily be by philosopherswho havea thesisto maintainwhich requires
falsified; and if it rvere retained, we could still explain in the that only one level be recognized.
I Se e No te D, p . r 7 r . Whether an explanationof a piece of behaviour is to be
4+ T I { E R A T IO N AL E O F AC T IO N S cH. v sEcT.4 P R IN C I PLES O F ACTI O N r 35

interpreted rationally or not will often depend on the context employs in An Introduction to Philosoplry of History, when
of utterance; we may have to ask how the explanation would arguing that explanations of action in history are accomplished
be argued for, what else would be said if it were expanded, &c. by means of basic non-technical generalizations.r "We are
Take the following example from Trevelyan's discussion of agreed", Walsh declares, "that to understand an historical
the problem of the early eighteenth-centurysmog in London: situation we must bring some kind of general knowledge to
On dayswhen the north-eastwind carriedthe smoke-cloud,even bear on it, and the first question to ask here is clearly in what
Chelseabecamedangerousto the asthmatic,as the mild philosopher this general knowledge consists." Against the positivists he
Earl of Shaftesburyhad reasonto complain.There is no wonderthat maintains that the most important generalizations used in an
King William with his weaklungshadlivedat HamptonCourtwhenhe historian's explanations do not come from any of the sciences;
could,andat Kensington.lvhen he must.r they are fundamental judgements about human nature-
The explanation offered can easily be reduced to a 'because' "judgments about the characteristic responseshuman beings
statement.But what exactly doesthe historian mean to imply: made to the various challenges set them in the course of their
does he mean that any person would have done so, circum- lives, whether by the natural conditions in which they live, or
stances being rvhat they were ? Or does he mean that any by their fellow beings". These constitute a 'scienceof hurnan
sensibleperson would have done so ? The explanation could nature' distinguishable from scientific psychology; they pro-
surely be pushed either way, depending on how we cared to vide the historian with a criterion of rvhat is 'humanly pos-
read it. And the expianation may be satisfactory(in the sense sible', rvhen he seeksto understand the past.
of 'adequate for its type') no matter which way it is read. But the 'science of human nature' here described does not
Butterfield would no doubt elect to defend it in the second, differ logically from scientific psychology; it is really just the
or rational, way, while Gardiner, in the interests of his thesis, common-sense psychology of the plain man. If left at that,
could choose the regularity way without obvious logical error. Walsh's argument would make no other point against the
We cannot settle the issue between them until the writer positivists than Hempel's own admission that, becauseof the
gives us a more definite indication of what he intends. It is unfortunate backwardness of the science of psychology, his-
worth noticing, in this connexion, that many of the examples torians must formulate many of the 'laws of human nature'
used by Gardiner to support the covering law model could required on the basis of their owir experience. But the facts of
be plausibly re-analysedin the rational way. The force of the historical writing which stimulate Walsh's sympathy with the
explanation of Louis XIV's unpopularity in terms of his idealists seem to me to require our drawing, not a distinction
policies being detrimental to French interests is very likely to merely between different sourcesof empirical laws used, but
be found in the detailed description of the aspirations,beliefs, between different types of. explanation. For we sometimes
and problems of Louis's subjects. Given these men and their want to explain actions not by representing them as instances
situation, Louis and his policies, their dislike of the king was of laws, but as the reasonable thing to have done; and when
an appropriale response. we do, if we appeal to 'general knowledge' zt all, it is to prin-
Nor is the ambiguity confined to the word 'because'; it can ciples of behaviour rather than empirical generalizations;
be traced through a wide variety of terms used to describeand to knowledge of what to do rather than of what is usually or
explain actions. It can be found, for instance, in the terms always done.
'natural' and 'humanly possible', which Mr. W. H. Walsh Walsh does not put it this way, yet there are suggestions of
t Chap. III, sections 4, 5.
I EnglishSocial History, London, 1946,p,337.
46 T H E R AT ION AL E O F AC TION S cH. v sEcT. 4 P R I NCI PLES O F ACTI O N r37

the point in some of his remarks. For instance, in pointing principles on which any man may be expected to order his
out that the basic general knowledge which historians bring to activities.
their work differs from one historian to another, he includis
both knowledge of how men do and (he adds 'perhaps') 5. The Standpoint of Historical Writing
should behave.r And again, in a footnote, he considers favour- I have argued that rational explanation is a recognizably
ably Ryle's term'knowledge how' (i.e. practical knowledge of distinct type of explanation; that it employs a criterion of
some kind) as a characterization of what is to be included in intelligibility which is different from that formulated by the
the envisaged'science of human nature'.z There is a hint of the covering law model, and that there are special reasons for
sameview in his acceptanceof the suggestion that the 'science' objecting to the claim that such explanations require the truth
in question is continuous with common sense-which, it may of correspondingempirical laws. Let me now ask what we can
be remarked, is generally taken to cover our knowledge of say about the relation between such explanation and other
what to do, as well as of what is generally done.r And the use kinds, and what, in general, is its role in historical writing.
of 'challenge-response' terminology in describing the nature It seems to me that there is a general presumption that a
of the fundamental judgements concerned points roughly in given action will be explicable on the rational model if we
the same direction.+ study it closely enough. The general belief that people act for
Walsh's terms 'humanly possible' and'human nature'are sufficient reason does not arise out of definite pieces of evi-
located at the centre of the difficulty; they straddle the dis- dence in particular cases;it is a standing presumption which
tinction between explanation types, or between the levels of requires contrary evidence in a particular case to defeat'
language at which we talk about actions. Consider the follow- Acknorvledging the presumption does not imply that all
ing explanatory remark of Ramsey Muir about a political actions must ultimately be done for sufficient reasons-even in
decision of George III. "The king", he writes, ". . . naturally the weak sensesketchedin the foregoing sections; but it does
chose Shelburne rather than the hated Whigs."s fn z wa1yt register the conviction that it wil generally be worth while
this word does, as Walsh might say, representthe action as a making a sustainedeffort to 'save the appearances'rationally.
charatteristic response, in that anyone with George III's If the first calculation we trylto match with an action fails to
political memories would have tried to keep the Whigs out. fit it, then we normally consider ourselvesobliged to look for
But there is a very strong suggestion,too, that this response evidenceof additional, and perhaps queer' beliefs, &c', of the
was appropriate in a rational sense; to say the choice naturally agent which, when explicitlyrecognized, permit the construc-
went to Shelburne is to imply that this was obviously the tion of a calculation which enjoins what was done. On the
right thing for the king to do-from his point of view. Simi- other hand, if we have satisfactorily achieved an equilibrium,
larly, saying that an historian has a keen appreciation of what we tend to regard this as a proper stopping place. The rational
is 'humanly possible'dneayrefer to the sort of law-governed explanation of an action at a particular level carries a certain
phenomenon Walsh cites, e.g. "that men who undergo great degree of plausibility on its face.
physical privations are for the most part lacking in mental It is impossible to set theoretical limits to the guiding force
energy". But I think it may just aswell refer to the fundamental of the presumption of rationality. It may often, for instance,
lead us into attributing unconscious motives for action.
t p.69.
t p.65. Psychoanalystsseemto find it therapeutically useful to extend
' p.66'
s A Short History of the British Commonwealth.
vol. ii, p. ro5. the scope of the presumption beyond the limits which would
r3 8 T HE R AT ION AL E O F A C T ION S cH. v scr. s S TA N D P OIN T O F HTSTO RI CAL WRI TI NG r 3e
be countenanced in ordinary historical writing. But although accustomed to using it in the course of his work that he
no firm boundary can be drawn here, it is neverthelessneces- appropriates it as the model of 'historical explanation', rele-
sary to recognize the fact that there will be particular casesin gating the other kind (like Collingwood) to the attention of
which u'e find it impossible to rationalize what was done, so psychologists.r In so sharply repudiating any responsibility for
that if an explanation is to be given at all, it will have to be of giving a psychological explanation, Jones no doubt goes too
another kind. To say a priori that all actions must have a far; for if a psychological theory were necessaryand available
rationale, no matter how hard to discover, is just a dogma- to explain Monck's 'cryptic' behaviour, it would be the his-
although we could make it analytically true by a suitable torian's business to use it, and it would be of interest to the
definition of 'action'. In the ordinary course of affairs, rational reader to know it. But except in history deliberately written to
and non-rational explanations of actions are alternatives- a thesis, non-rational explanation only supplements, it does
and alternatives sought in a certain order. We give reasons if not replace, the rational sort.
we can, and turn to empirical laws if we must.r In this respect history is logically continuous with literature
Not only is this done in the ordinary course of affairs; it rather than social science, if by the latter we mean something
is done, too, in ordinary historical writing. Historians, as well like a social 'physics'. This sort of claim has often been made,
as plain men, tend to push their explanations as high up the but usually for reasonswhich fail to reduce the cogency of the
'scale of understanding' as possible. Proof for this assertion covering law theory as an account of the logical structure of all
would have to rest upon a detailed examination of historical explanation. Trevelyan, for instance, seemsto regard the use
writing, which cannot be undertaken here. But the following of narrative in the presentation of results as the feature which
quotation appears to me typical in what it reveals about the puts history among the humanities.'zFor to a narrative exposi-
workaday approach of historians to the problem of explaining tion, the canons of literary taste apply. The authors of the
human actions. In The English Ra:olution, while describing American Social ScienceResearchCouncil's Bulletin No. 64,
the last years of the Interregnum, f . D. Jonesremarks: on the other hand, regard muc.h historical writing as "in the
It would be falsifyinghistory to bring orderout of the confusionof tradition of the humanities" because, on their view, its con-
theyeafbetween thefall of Richardandthereturnof CharlesIl. Thereis clusions lack empirical verifieation.3 Both views leave the
n9 logicor reasonin it. The resurrections andre-burialsof the Rump:
the meteoricenergiesandextinctionof Lambert,now a Fifth Monarch- logical claims of the model intact. But my claim is rather that
ist, nowconsidered aneligiblefather-inJawto CharlesStuart:theryptic certain criteria of what shall count as etcplanation are applied
esolutionof Monck from the Cromwellian,Republican,Presbyterian throughout the humane studies which have, to say the least'
to Royalist: the alliancesof Fleetwoodwith Ludlow, Lambert, the a doubtful place in most programmes of social science. Even
Anabaptistsand the Rump-all theseeventsproducea tangledskein those who deplore this fact have often seen the point at issue.
of desperation, irresolutionand treacherywhichneedse psychologist,s F. J. Teggart, a self-conscious reformer of history, in attacking
rather than a historian'salpbs;s."
the unregenerate kind, observes sourly: "The intelligibility
The passagesuggests that Jones has an ideal of explanation which the historian thus introduces into the materials which
which he finds frustratingly inapplicable to the case of, for he selectsfor his composition is of the sameorder as that pro-
example, Monck's observed behaviour in 1658-9. He is so I ln The Idea of History (p. z9) Collingwood attacks history whose "chief pur-
pose is to affirm laws, psychological laws". This, he says, is "not history at all,
t The relation between giving the reasons for, and giving
the causes of, an but natural science of a special kind".
action is a little more complicated. I discuss this in section 7. 7 History and the Reader, London, rg45, pp. ro ff.; and Trevelyan's plea for
2 London, r93r, p. ro6, my italics. 3 pp. r3o-r.
'literary history' in CIio, A Muse, London, r93o, PP' t4o-76.
sE cr.s S TA N D P OIN T O F HI STO RI CAL WRI TI NG r 4r
t40 T HE R AT ION AL E O F AC T IO N S cH. v

vided by the author of a historical novel or drama."t The more detailed studies on which such general histories rest
comparison is, of course, in Teggart's eyes quite damning. would show that what the 'calculation' in question really ex-
What is at stakehere is the proper'standpoint' or'approach' plains is the actions of those individuals who were authorized
to at any rate a large part of the subject-matter of history. io act 'for Germany'. In other casesthe actions of groups
Collingwood declares that history is not a,spectacle.zWhat he are explained on the rational model by means of a kind of
means could perhaps be put in terms of a distinction between 'typical' calculation---e.g. when an historian asks why the
two standpoints from which human actions can be studied. Puritans, in particular, became exercised about taxation in
When we subsume an action under a law, our approach is that seventeenth-century England, or why the Slavswere especially
of a spectator of the action; we look for a pattern or regularity hostile to the Hapsburg monarchy in the early years of the
in it. But when we give an explanation in terms of the purpose present century. Such extensions of rational explanation
which guided the action, the problem which it was intended would appear to raise no problem other than the practical
to resolve, the principle which it applied, &c., we adopt the one of determining whether, in a particular case, the group
standpoint from which the action was done: the standpoint concerned is homogeneous enough for this kind of treat-
of an agent. In adopting this standpoint, the investigator ment.
appreciates the agent's problem and appraises his response to A different, although related, problem which is sometimes
it. The importance in history of explanations given from the raised by the extension of what I have called rational explana-
agent's standpoint gives some point to well-known idealist tion beyond the sphere of particular actions of particular
dicta like 'All history is contemporary history', and 'All history individuals, is whether the motives, purposes' circumstances,
is history ofthought'. Such slogans are exaggeratedand para- &c., of historical agents afford suftcient explanation of large-
doxical, but they do register an awarenessthat the problems scale historical phenomena. There is, as Whitehead has put it,
of historical agents have to be faced by the reader and the a "senselessside" to history;r and by this he meansmore than
investigator if they are to understand what was done. that natural phenomena, which cannot' of course, be explained
It should, perhaps, be added that the historian's preference rationally, have to be taken into account by historians- For
for the rational model sometimes leads him into making highly the 'senseless' also appears in, larger-scale social results of
elliptical explanatory statements when group rather than individual actions which are not themselves explicable on the
individual behaviour is being considered-statements which rational model because they are not what any individual-
have sometimes scandalized literal-minded philosophers when even one acting for a group-intended or even wanted to
they have come to analyse them. In highly condensed general happen; and they may often, indeed, be quite the reverse.
histories, classesand nations and societiesare often personified According to Mrs. K. Cornforth, it is precisely this sort of
and written about in a quasi-rational way. Thus Germany's thing (e.g. "the introduction of steam in modern times, and
attack on Russia in r94t may be explained by citing the threat the development of the cinema industry") which can be
of Russian encirclement-as if a 'calculation' of this sort were explained by general 'scientific' theories of the historical pro-
relevant to the actions of a super-agent called 'Germany'. The ceis; and she regards such explanations as the more profound
precise analysis of such statements would, no doubt, often and important ones.z M. R. Cohen, too' warns us against
present difficulties; but I think it is clear that referenceto the I Adoentures of ldeas, Cambridge, 1933' p.8.
I Theory and Processes 2 'Explanation in History', Proceedings of the Atistoteli%,t Socie4t, SuPP' Vol',
of History, Berkeley and Los Angeles, r94r, p. 78.
2 Op. cit,, pp. t64, zr4. 1935r P . r37.
r4 2 T HE R A T IO N AL E O F AC T IO N S cH .v secr.6 MOD E L OF DI SPO SI TI O N. A. L STATEM ENT r 43
exaggerating the extent to which the notion of 'purpose' can explanations in terms of motives, desires, intentions, and so
be appealed to in explaining social phenomena.' The voyage forth" is summarizedin the following passage, with reference
of Columbus was a cause of the spread of European civiliza- to the example: 'John hit you with a hammer because he is
tion to America, but the result is not explained by the voyage, bad-tempered.' Of this statement, he writes:
nor did Columbus intend it. It would be absurd to deny that this is an explanation: but it would
What Cornforth and Cohen say has a certain point, but it be equally ludicrous to imagine that it could in some manner be 're-
can be misleading. For to say that the sort of phenomena they duced' to an explanation assertinga causalrelation between two events
or processes, one of which is labelled'John'sbad temper'. 'John is bad-
have in mind cannot be explained, or explained adequately,
tempered' is a sentencewhich, amongst other things, is predictive of
in purposive terms may mean one or another of two things. If how John is likely to behave in various (only vaguely indicated) types
it means merely that they cannot be explained in terms of the of situations. The function of the 'because'in the statement alluded to
purposes of some individual who stage.managed the whole is to set a statement referring to a specific action within the context of
thing, then of course no objection need be raised at all. But if a general statement about John's behaviour which can be 'unpacked'
into an indefinite rangeof statementsconcerninghis reactionsto various
they mean that a perfectly adequate explanation of the gross
kinds of circumstances.It represents,if you like, an instanceof how he
event cannot be given in terms of the rationale of the activities can in general be expected to behave under certain conditions. It sets
of the various individuals involved-and this is strongly sug- John's action within a pattern, the pattern of his normal behaviour.
gested-then it is surely necessaryto disagree. An historian's It is in terms of this usageof 'explanation', rathbr than in terms of the
explanation of the spread of European civilization to America cause-effectusage,that historians' (and ordinary persons') accountsof
will normally be what I called in Chapter II 'piecemeal'; and human actions of the kind we are considering are to be understood.
This is not to say that it would be correct to bundle together into an
it will involve a detailed examination, mainly in rational terms, amorphous heap historical explanationsreferring to desires,intentions,
of the activities and motives of countless individuals and purposes, plans, and programmes, as if there were not important
groups; the French Jesuits and the English Puritans as well as differences between them. To say that an individual's actions were
Columbus; Colbert and Raleigh as well as Philip II; fur planned or conformed to a progrdnme or policy may be very different
traders, explorers, gold-seekers, land-hungry peasants, and from saying that they were intended; and again, to say that they were
intended can be different from ,saying that they were motivated by
a host of others. As for the question whether explanation can
such-and-sucha desire. And these casesagain are different from those
or cannot, should or should not, be given in terms of 'theories in which rile say that his actions were 'reasoned'or'considered'. But in
of the historical process' where these are available, all that all theseinstancesit is with explanationin the senseof fitting a particular
needs to be said is that this would be uncharacteristic of action within a certain pattern that we are concerned. The patterns are
ordinary historical writing. And I can see no reason to brand familiar to us both from experience of our own behaviour and from
the more charaiteristic sort of thing less 'profound'. experienceof the ways other people behave; and it is in virtue of this
that we are able to make the inferences and provide the explanations
6 in question.r
6. The Model of the DispositionalStatement
There remainsthe questionof how my accountof typical Gardiner here contends that statements attributing motives,
explanationsof action in history squareswith the alternative purposes, intentions, &c., have a peculiar and complex logical
analysisoffered by Gardiner in The Nature of Historical Etc- form. He admits that such statements cannot be forced into
planation. Gardiner's accountof the way we are "to interpret the Procrustean Bed of the covering law model, and in admit-
ting this, he parts companywith both Popper and Hempel.
t
'The Social Sciences and the Natural Sciences', The Social Scicncesand their t pp. rz4-5.
ftttertelations, cds, W. F. Ogbum and A. Goldenweiser, Boston, ry27rpp.445-5.
r44 T HE R AT ION AL E O F AC T I ON S cH. v s rq r. 6 MO DE L O F D I S P O S I T I O N A LS T A T E M E N T r 4 5
In a passagequoted in Chapter I, Popper remarks: ". . . if we or processes,then event-predicatesand process-predicates
explain Caesar'sdecision to cross the Rubicon by his ambition should be applicable.But, as Ryle's book is designedto show
and energy, say, then we are using some very trivial psycholo- in impressivedetail, the attemptto apply them generatesnon-
gical generalizations which would hardly ever arouse the sense.
attention of a psychologist". And Hempel, too, goesout of his If, for thesereasons,explanationin terms of motivescannot
way to deny that explanations in terms of the motives of require the currencyof a generallaw, what is its logicalforce?
individuals raise any difficulties for the covering law analysis. Ryle answersthis questionwith a generalaccountof the logic
Such explanations,he says,are not "essentially different from of dispositionalcharacteristics.He arguesthat to attribute a
the causal explanations of physics and chemistry". For motive to an agentis to relatethe motivatedaction to certain
Hempel, motives are antecedent conditions which must be other things the agentdid, or would have done, in theseand
linked to resulting actions by covering laws before they have other circumstances.To use Gardiner'sphrase,the "function
explanatory force.'Presumably he would deal in a similar way of the 'because'" in a motive explanationis to indicate the
with all those explanationswhich attribute desires,emotions, generalpattern of behaviourof which the particular actionis a
pu{poses,plans, &c., to historical agents. part. The logical model for explanationof this kind is given
Gardiner's refusal to follow Popper and Hempel here is at its simplestin Ryle's celebratedcontrastbetweentwo kinds
based on a general analysis of 'mental conduct concepts' of thing \trecan say about the breakingof a pane of glass.If
similar to the one offered by Ryle in The Concept of Mind." we say'The glassbrokewhen the stonehit it becausewhenever
According to Ryle, laws connect events or govern processes- stoneshit glassit breaks',we give (subjectto the qualifications
but motives are neither events nor processes. The notion urged in precedingchapters)a law-coveredexplanation.But
that a motive could be a special kind of antecedent condition if we say 'The glassbroke when the stone hit it becauseit is
or cause of actions, i.e. a mental kind, he repudiates as a brittle', we explain what happenedin terms of a dispositional
'logical howler'; for if true, it would make a large range of property of glass. The dispositional characteristic 'being
causal statements about actions empirically unverifiable-not brittle' is neither an additional antecedenthappening nor a
just frr practice, but in principle. It is not just that, in the case law. It has,however,an explanatoqyvalue of its own because,
of other people, we cannot observe the ghostly events or p"ro- like a law, there is generalityin it.
cesses-the various motives-which would have to be men- A statementattributing a dispositional characteristiclike
tioned in the protases of the law statements supposed to be 'brittle' might be called 'lawlike' because,like a law, it is at
required for causal explanation. We cannot properly be said leastpartly hypotheticalin what it implies; it can be satisfied
to observe such mental causeseven in ourselves-a contention by a wide range of behaviour, of which shattering on the
which undercuts any protest that we argue by analogy from impact of a stoneis only one kind. The relation which cover-
our own experienceto the existehce of mental causes cor- ing law theoristsclaim to find betweenpredictionand explana-
related with other people's overt .behaviour. Ryle maintains tion is therefore,to someextent, preserved.If we know that
that our ordinary use of motive languagelends support to his glassis brittle, we know what sort of thing to expectwhen we
thesis here. To put it formally: if motive words name events hearthat a brick hasbeenthrown at a window pane.The pre-
cision of prediction decreases, of course,with the complexity
r Such laws, linking motive with action motivated, should not be confused of the behaviourpattern indicated by the dispositionalterm.
with laws linking circumstances with actions responding to them.
2 London, 1949, especially chap, iv. In the caseof glass,and in the caseof human reflexesand
146 T H E R A T IO N AL E OF AC TION S cH. v srcr.6 MODEL OF DISPOSITIONAL STATEMENT r47
habits-Ryle's'single-track' or determinate dispositions- tion, that in the caseof the glass we know that objects of this
zctloalizationsfollow a narrowly restricted pattern. But in the kind will have the dispositional property mentioned. The
caseof motives-which are 'many-tracked' or determinable- modification of the covering law theory represented by the
they do not. Thus to say that Disraeli attacked Peel in 1846 recognition of dispositional explanation is therefore quite a
becausehe was ambitious is to imply only that the attack was major one.
one of a number of things, systematically related, which the Like explanations in terms of a covering generalization,
use of the word 'ambition' licenses us to expect. It is not to dispositional explanations often appear so trivial as to invite
imply that from the conditions of 1846 it could have been the judgement: 'Really no explanation at all.' In general, the
deduced(with the aid of the dispositional statement) that he more 'single-track' the disposition referred to, the more trivial
would make such an attack. will the explanation appear. This helps to explain the fact that
Covering law theorists may be tempted to argue that the the logical respectability of dispositional explanation has not
connexion between dispositional and law-covered explana- always been admitted even in quarters where 'regularity' is
tions is really much closer than I have made it appear; for taken as the watchword. Crawford, for instance, attacks his
just as, in the case of the breaking glass, we may assume that fellow historian, Lord Elton, in withering terms for declaring,
the dispositional property holds by virtue of certain physical in an account of the failure of local government in the early
laws concerning the behaviour of glass and bricks, so the dis- years of the French Revolution:"Centralization is in the blood
positional properties attributed to human agents may appear of Frenchmen; and Frenchmen must be administered, even if
to be applicable becauseof there being regularities in human they are not governed." This Crar,vford castigates as a mere
behaviour which are formulable in terms of laws (however "seeming explanation".t It can be reduced, he says, to the
'loose'). But if this is taken to mean that a dispositional statement : "Frenchmen preferred centralized administration
explanation of a particular human action depends in any way becausethey had the habit of preferring centralized administra-
on the truth of such laws, it involves a misunderstanding of tion." And this (although formally sound on the dispositional
the distinction which has been drawn between explanation model) he finds quite unenlightening. Crawford's'reduction'
types.'For 'ambition' is not a. general characteristic of men of this rather flowery exampleof dispositional explanation to a
(or even, perhaps, of politicians) in the way 'being brittle' is of 'habit' statement may perhaps go too far. But any answer to
glass.To say'Disraeli attackedPeel becausehe was ambitious' the question'Why?' which could be reduced to'It's habitual
draws attention to the general pattern of action into which his with him', would at least leave room for argument as to
particular action fits, but it implies nothing about the kind of whether it offered a very trivial explanation, or avoided the
men from whom this kind of action can be expected. It merely demand for explanation altogether.
implies that action of this. general pattern can be expected The majority of dispositional statements about people,
from Disraeli; it subsrrtneshis action under a regularity said to however, are not trivial in this way, and it is not hard to dis-
hold for a particular person, rather than a regulariry said to cover historical examples whose logical force is much more
hold for all persons of a certain type.' Dispositional explana- plausibly elicited by Ryle's model of the breaking glassthan by
tion thus falls short of law-covered explanation in its par- the original covering law theory. S. R. Gardiner, for instance,
ticularity (a point which Gardiner's brief discussion may not explains the fatal policy of Charles I dispositionally when he
have made clear). It is accidental, not essential,to the explana- observes: "What he was doing he did from a lwe of order,
r See Note Erp. t7r. I Op. cit., p. 16.
r4 8 T HE R A T IO N AL E O F A C T ION S cH. v srcr.6 MOD E L OF DI SPO SI TI O NAL STATEM ENT r 4e
combined with sheer ignorance of mankind." And the same adequately, explains his sudden adoption of the extremists in May
sort of explanation is often also given of the behaviour of fi47 and December 1648,and his final decisionon Charles' death. . . . t
groups, for example, in accounting for the peculiarities of Irish
Americans by referring to their Anglophobia. Here ]ones explains the impulsive, inadequately reasoned
The question which remains to be answered, however, is decisionsof 647-8 by locating them in a generalpattern of
whether all explanations of human action in terms of motives, Cromwell's behaviourduring thoseyears.When we seethem
intentions, pulposes, &c., can be accountedfor in terms of the in this context of dispositionswe are no longer surprised.
dispositional model: in particular, whether dispositional Similarly, in the case of the explanation of the policy of
analysis brings out the real point of what, in previous sections, Charles I, quoted above, the historian-perhaps becauseof
I called 'rational explanation'. And it seemsto me clear enough the greatstupidity of the king's behaviour-is contentto show
that it does not. A pure dispositional explanation tells us that that it was characteristic.
the person or thing under investigation tended to do things of But although dispositional characterizationmay alleviate
(perhaps roughly) the sort done, under certain (unspecified) surprise,it doesnot do it by revealingthe point or rationale
circumstances. It shows that what was done was the sort of of what was done. For 'disposition' is a spectator'sword; it
thing we might have expected-it was the sort of thing that belongsto the languageof observingand predicting, rather
would be done by this person or thing. But in most historical than of deliberatingand deciding.If the agentweteto explain
contexts, such an explanation would tell us scarcely anything his actionby pointing out which of his dispositionalcharacter-
we really wanted to know when we asked: 'Why did he do it?' istics he had actualized,his explanationwould seem oddly
For in giving the dispositional answer, the point of what was irrelevant. Nor should we think of saying: 'So that's the dis-
done tends to drop out of sight. To attempt to analyseexplana- position Smith wasactualizing!Now I seewhat he wasup to!'
tions of the form, 'A did x in order to achievey', as covertly It is true, of course, that many of the component factual
dispositional simply ignores the question which we may statementsof a rational explanation-e.g. statementsof what
reasonably assumethe investigator to have had in mind when the agent's beliefs and attitudes were-may be acceptedon
he reprgsented this as an explanation. the basisof argumentsof the form: 'He tends to do so-and-
It is not without significance in this connexion to remark so, so he must believeso-and-sb.'And it may evenbe alleged
that dispositional explanation is very frequently given in his- that belief is, itself, a dispositionalcharacteristic.But to allow
tory where it is necessary to head off the reader's incipient this would not be to admit that the explanationgiven by
demand to know'Why?' in the rational sense.The following meansof suchfactualstatementsis itself dispositionalin form.
example of a genuine dispositional explanation of a rather In his discussionof dispositionalanalysis,Ryle warns us
complex sort illustrates the point. I. D. Jones, in accounting that we must avoid "equating understandingwith psycho-
for Cromwell's political4lecisions of the late r64o's, declares: logical diagnosis,i.e. with causalinferencesfrom overt be-
His speeches and lettersshowhis difficultyin reachingdecisionsand haviour to mental processesin accordancewith lawsyet to be
his reluctanceto assumeresponsibility;he had not the mind that could discoveredby the psychologists. . .".2 With this I haveno
planahead,but the geniusthat actedon impulse.He originatednoneof quarrel, but I think the statementjust astrue if 'psychological
the manyschemes of his party; he tookfire from theideasof others,such diagnosis'is taken more broadly than Ryle's proviso allows.
as Ireton, Harrisonand T.ambert.He waited,often in agonies of inde- For we must also avoid equatingunderstandingwith merely
cision,for guidancefrom "Providsnsss"-ths handof God revealedin
events;he read the omenslike a Roman Consul. This, alone and I The English Ranolution,p. 85. 2 Op, cit., p.
58,
rso THE RATIONALE OF ACTIONS cH. v sncr.7 D IS P OS ITION S, REASO NS, AND CAUSES r 5r

recognizing that actions fall under certain behaviour patterns' analysedas dispositionsto behavein certainways,rather than
or that they are likely to be preceded and followed by actions as occurrences,cannot be causes.At one point, for instance,
of a related kind. he saysthat motive explanationsare "not causalat all".r In
In saying this I am not complaining, as some critics have, this he appearsto follow Ryle, who, in The Conceptof Mind,
that dispositional analysis, when applied to 'mental conduct declared:"Motives are not happenings,and aretherefore not
concepts', is akind of.behaaiowism.For the distinction between of the right type to be causes."z
dispositions and occurrences cuts across that between what is That this conclusioncannotbe correctis strongly suggested
covert and what is overt, so that some exercisesof most human by the very common citation of dispositionalcharacteristics
dispositional characteristics will be overt, while others will be as causesby historians. Sir David Keir, having pointed out
covert. My complaint is rather that, as an account of what have that, following English reversesin the Dutch War of t665-7,
often been called'teleological explanations', dispositional there was "a new encroachmenton the Prerogative" by the
analysis is a kind of.spectatorisrn It misconstrues the logic of Commons,observes:"Charles' resentmentat this intrusion
typical explanations of human actions because it manceuvres was undoubtedly one of the many causeswhich led him to
the investigator into considering them from the wrong stand- abandonClarendonto impeachmentin r667."t And someof
point. There is a senseof 'explain' in which an action is only the dispositionalexamplesnotedintheprecedingsectioncould
explained when it is seen in a context of rational deliberation; easilybe recastinto causalform-for instance,'The causeof
when it is seenfrom the point of view of an agent. Ryle appears the fatalpolicy of CharlesI washis loveof order and ignorance
to me to be a much safer guide to the analysis of such expla- of mankind', or 'It was Disraeli's ambition which causedhis
nations when, at several points in The Concept of Mind, he attackon Peelin 1646'.What modificationsshouldbe madein
represents understanding another person's action as a matter the Ryle-Gardiner theory in the light of such cases?
of 'following the workings' of his mind.' For into this notion I do not think that the admission that 'bad temper' or
could be read most of what I have tried to sav about rational 'ambition' or 'ignorance'canbe a causeneedgive any comfort
explanation. to thosewho (asRyle might put it) wish to reinstatethe ghost
in the machine.For there is no needto assumethat because
7. Dispositions, Reasons,and Causes motives,intentions,habits, beliefs,and the rest can be causes,
There is one other question arising out of Gardiner's dis- they arethereforeto be regardedasmental eventsor processes
positional theory which requires comment if we are not to be after all. The error is to be located rather in thinking that only
misled about the nature of explanation of action in history. eventsor processescan be causes,whereasthere would seem
Gardiner, like Ryle, draws a sharp distinction between dis- to be virtually no restriction whateverupon the type of thing
positional and causal explanation; he says, for instance, that that can qualify as a cause,provided it passes,in a particular
the statement, 'John hit you with a hammer becausehe is bad- context, what, in Chapter IV, I called the pragmatic and
tempered' cannot be "reduced to arr explanation asserting a inductive tests. If John would not have hit me had he been
causal relation between two events or processes,one of which good tempered (i.e. the presumption is that the occasion
is labelled 'John's bad temper"'. But although this is true, r Op. cit., p. r34. Gardiner does deny that explanationsare always in terms
Gardiner appears to me to reach his conclusion for the wrong of events; but this is only to leaveroom for explanationsin terms of (non-causal)
reason, i.e. that motives like 'bad temper' since they are to be dispositions, rather than for causeswhich are not events (seep. r).
t p. 6r . ' p. rr3.
t ConstitutianalHistory of Modun Bitain (4th edn.), rg1o,p.24g.
t52 TIIE R AT ION AL E OF A C T ION S cH. v srcr.7 DISPOSITIONS, REASONS, AND CAUSES r53
scarcelyjustified the blow), then his bad temper may be a difference between answers in terms of reasons and causes
regardedas a necessarycondition; and sincewe may feel that do. For (to put it a little crudely) reasons, too, can be causes.
it is high time he took his temper in hand, we may selecttlis Consider, for instance, Hal6vy's explanation of a strike at
necessarycondition as the pragmatically important one, and Newcastle in May 1816: it was, he writes "caused by insuffi-
thus call it the cause.As ProfessorIJrmson haspointed out, cient wages and the high price of bread".' It is surely not
"what is referred to in one context as a motive may be re- misreading what is asserted to say that the conditions here
ferred to in another as a cause".' It is the conteit of inquiry described as the cause are precisely those which were 'taken
which determineswhether a dispositionalcharacteristicwill into account' by the strikers in reaching the decision to stop
be a causalcandidateor not. work. The rational basis of the asserted causal connexion is
The apparentlogical cleavagebetweencausaland disposi- even more explicitly brought out in the following explanation
tional explanationhassometimesbeenclosedin anotherway. by D. Thomson of the cleavage between the landed and
Mr. P. Alexander,for instance,remindsus that for a disposi- industrial groups in England in the nineteenth century. He
tion to be actualizedthere must be 4n essssisn-\ /hich he writes:
calls the cause.2A piece of glassshatterswhen a stonehits it The use to which the landedinterestsput their predominancein
Dol&becauseit has the dispositionalproperty of being brittle Parliamentto protect themselvesin this way at the expenseof the
and becausesomeoneprovidesa causeby throwing a brick at industrial populationsof the townsand the manufacturinginterests
it. But although I agreethat to cite a dispositionalproperty causedthe first big open split betweenlanded and manufacturing
might properly be regardedas an incompleteexplanationof interests.All alike wantedsteadyand level prices: but the industrial
interests,employersand workersalike,wantedthis to be at a low level,
what happenedif the occasionis unknown, to regard the
so as to makeu'agesgo further, keepwage-billslow and thereforethe
occasion,rather than the dispositionalproperty, as 'the cause' cost of manufacturedgoodslow, and enablethem to redp maximum
is to makethe mistakealreadymentioned.It is to assumethat benefitsin world markets.The cotton-merchantslikewisewanted the
causalconditionsmust be eventsor processes (while shrinking plentiful import of cheapcorn to enablethe corn-exportingcountriesto
from admitting that they may be 'mental' ones).Alexander pay for the manufacturedcotton'goodsthat Englandexported.The
.thinkethat to call a motive a cause"would be absurd". But landownersand farmerswantedcorn-pricesstabilizedat a high level.
Thus two distinctgroupsof econdmicinterestsgrewuP' bitterly hostile
this supposedabsurdity is actually a commonplace.A dis. to one another:and this led to the long agitationfor the repealofthe
positionalcharacteristic is a type of 'standingcondition'; and Corn Laws,the FreeTrade movementasa whole,and the demandfor
standing conditions,as well as precipitating ones, can be the lesseningof the powerenjoyedby the agriculturaland landedin-
causes. terestsin Parliament.z
The distinction betweencausaland dispositionalexplana-
In Other Minds, Professor John Wisdom observes, truly,
tion, althoughit is important to draw it, should thereforenot
that some causes are very nearly reasons.3But this does not
be drawn in such a u{ay that dispositionsas such are denied
quite say what such examples require us to say about the rela-
causalstatus.A somewhatsimilar qualificationwill be found
tion between causal and rational explanation; for even this
necessaryif we attempt to draw a logical line betweencausal
remark preserves the dichotomy. What is required is a
and rational explanation,as many philosopherswho recognize
qualified restatement of Collingwood's doctrine that in history
r 'Motives and Causes', ProceedingsoJ the Aristotelian Society, Supp, Vol., r Op. cit., vol. ii, p. ro.
1952,P. r93. 2 England in the Ninetee?.thCentury,I{armondsworth, r95o' p. 37.
2 'Cause and Cure in Psychotherapy', ibid., 1955, p. 3 Orford, 1952.,P. 2.
34.
r5 4 T HE R AT ION AL E O F A C T ION S cH. v srcr.7 DISPOSITIONS, REASONS, AND CAUSES r55
the term 'cause'is often (he, as we saw in Chapter IV, said manipulator-although of one well aware that he is dealing
'always')usedin SenseI: the sensein which to causesomeone with agents who act on rational considerations. Butterfield,
to do somethingis to provide him with a motive for doing in the passage quoted in section r, contrasts empathetic
it (where nmotive'means'reason'). As Collingwood himself understanding with "a causal or stand-offish attitude" l and
observed,to be causedto act in this sensedoesnot imply that this distinction remains even when it is admitted that the
the agentdid not makeup his mind to do what he did on the causeof an action may be that which provides the agent with a
basisof certainrationalconsiderations.rIt is true that in many reason for doing what was done. And it is a fact of ordinary
cases,we should not saythat the agentactedfreely; for often historical writing that historians do sometimes take up this
providing someonewith reasonsfor doing something, for 'stand-offish' attitude in explaining even the rational behaviour
example,holding a pistol to his head, is preciselywhat we of their characters.
meanby compellinghim to do what he does.But evenin such
a case,the causalconnexionbetweenthe pointed pistol and
the agent's subsequentbehaviour is to be understood in
rational terms.
The important point for our accountof explanationin his-
tory is that the necessityof a causalconnexion,when it is
actionswe are lalking about, is very often rational necessity.
In Chapter IV, in discussingthe logic of 'cause',I said that
althoughthere are variousways of arguingfor a causalasser-
tion, the causehad to be a necessarycondition of its effect.
But there is more than one kind of necessity;and in history
the relevantkind will often be that found in action donefor a
good r,eason(from the agent'spoint of view). In the situation
sketchedby Hal6vy, for instance,if we are to establishthe
causalconnexionbetweenthe strikeandthe "insufficientwages
and the high price of bread", we shall haveto fill out the cir-
cumstances,beliefs, &c., of the strikers to the point where
we can saythat without the additional conditionscited, there
rrould havebeeninsufficientreasonfor going out.
Is there no important difference,then, betweensaying of
the action of a rationaf agent,'/'s reasonfor doing tr wosjl'r
and saying'The causeof A's doing * wasy' ? The difference,
I think, is oneof approach,or point of view, or kind of inquiry.
To say the first sort of thing is-as has been suggestedat
length in the presentchapter-to adoptthe point of view of an
agent. To say the secondis to adopt the point of view of a
' An Essayon Metaphysirs,p,2go.

Potrebbero piacerti anche