Sei sulla pagina 1di 38

PRICING

THE PRICELESS:
Cost-Benefit Analysis
of Environmental
Protection

Lisa Heinzerling
Frank Ackerman

Georgetown Environmental Law and Policy Institute


Georgetown University Law Center
About the Authors
Lisa Heinzerling is a Professor of Law Frank Ackerman is an environmental
at Georgetown University Law School, economist and research director of the
specializing in environmental law. Before Global Development and Environment
joining the Georgetown faculty, Professor Institute (G-DAE) at Tufts University.
Heinzerling practiced environmental law He has written widely on the economics
in the Massachusetts Attorney Generals of waste and energy, and on alternative
office and was a Skadden Fellow at a approaches to economic theory. He is
public interest group in Chicago. She the author of Why Do We Recycle? Markets,
clerked for Judge Richard A. Posner of the Values, and Public Policy (Island Press 1997),
U.S. Court of Appeals for the Seventh and of two books on the economic policies
Circuit and for Justice William J. Brennan, of the Reagan administration. He is also
Jr., of the U.S. Supreme Court. Professor the lead editor of three books in the
Heinzerling was editor-in-chief of the G-DAE series on Frontier Issues in
University of Chicago Law Review and Economic Thought, published by
has contributed to numerous law journals, Island Press. Before coming to Tufts
including the Yale Law Journal, the Dr. Ackerman worked at the Tellus
Harvard Law Review, and the University Institute on energy and environmental
of Chicago Law Review. She has been a research, and was a founding editor of
visiting professor at the Yale and Harvard Dollars & Sense magazine. He has taught
law schools. economics at Tufts and at the University
of Massachusetts, and received his PhD
in economics from Harvard University.

The Georgetown Environmental Law and


Policy Institute conducts research and
education on legal and policy issues
relating to protection of the environment
and conservation of natural resources.
The Institute publishes papers and reports
by leading academics and practitioners
applying rigorous analysis to contemporary
environmental and natural resource issues.
The views expressed in Institute
publications are those of the authors and Copyright 2002 Georgetown University.
do not necessarily reflect the views of the All rights reserved. No part of this
staff of the Institute, its board of advisers, publication may be reproduced in any form
or Georgetown University. without prior consent of the publisher.
EXECUTIVE SUMMARY
n recent years the use of cost-benefit potential regulatory actions are worth

I analysis to set environmental standards


has attracted a large and high-profile
group of supporters. According to its
undertaking and in what fashion.
Advocates of cost-benefit analysis also
contend that this method produces
advocates, cost-benefit analysis offers a way more objective and more transparent
of achieving superior environmental results government decision-making by making
at a lower overall cost to society than other more explicit the assumptions and
available approaches. methods underlying regulatory actions.

This view is mistaken. Cost-benefit In fact, cost-benefit analysis is incapable


analysis is a deeply flawed method that of delivering what it promises. First,
repeatedly leads to biased and misleading cost-benefit analysis cannot produce
results. Far from providing a panacea, cost- more efficient decisions because the
benefit analysis offers no clear advantages in process of reducing life, health, and the
making regulatory policy decisions and often natural world to monetary values is
produces inferior results, in terms of both inherently flawed.
environmental protection and overall social
welfare, compared to other approaches. Efforts to value life illustrate the basic
problems. Cost-benefit analysis implicitly
In order to assess the pros and cons of any equates the risk of death with death itself,
particular regulatory standard, cost-benefit when in fact they are quite different and
analysis seeks to translate all relevant should be accounted for separately in
considerations into monetary terms. In considering the benefits of regulatory
cost-benefit analysis, therefore, both the actions. Cost-benefit analysis also ignores
costs of, say, putting a scrubber on a power the fact that citizens are concerned about
plant to reduce air pollution and the risks to their families and others as well as
benefits of doing so, including the saving themselves, ignores the fact that market
of human lives and the prevention of decisions are generally very different
debilitating and painful diseases, are from political decisions, and ignores the
presented in terms of dollars. The costs incomparability of many different types
and (particularly) the benefits of regulation of risks to human life. The kinds of
often will be realized in the future; in problems which arise in attempting to
such cases the numeric estimates of costs define the value of human life in monetary
and benefits are discounted, i.e. treated terms also arise in evaluating the benefits
as equivalent to smaller amounts of of protecting human health and the
money today. environment in general.

Proponents of cost-benefit analysis make Second, the use of discounting


two basic arguments in its favor. First, use systematically and improperly downgrades
of cost-benefit analysis ostensibly leads to the importance of environmental
more efficient allocation of societys regulation. While discounting makes
resources by better identifying which sense in comparing alternative financial

1
investments, it cannot reasonably be used understand and participate in the process.
to make a choice between preventing Thus, in practice, cost-benefit analysis is
noneconomic harms to present generations anything but transparent.
and preventing similar harms to future
generations. Nor can discounting Beyond these inherent flaws, cost-benefit
reasonably be used even to make a choice analysis suffers from serious defects in
between harms to the current generation; practical implementation. Many benefits
the choice between preventing an of public health and environmental
automobile fatality and a cancer death protection have not been quantified and
should not turn on prevailing rates of return cannot easily be quantified given the limits
on financial investments. In addition, on time and resources; thus, in practice,
discounting tends to trivialize long-term cost-benefit analysis is often akin to
environmental risks, minimizing the very shooting in the dark. Even when the data
real threat our society faces from potential gaps are supposedly acknowledged, public
catastrophes and irreversible environmental discussion tends to focus on the misleading
harms, such as those posed by global numeric values produced by cost-benefit
warming and nuclear waste. analysis while relevant but non-monetized
factors are simply ignored. Finally, the cost
Third, cost-benefit analysis ignores the side of cost-benefit analysis is frequently
question of who suffers as a result of exaggerated, because analysts routinely fail
environmental problems and, therefore, to account for the economies that can be
threatens to reinforce existing patterns achieved through innovative efforts to
of economic and social inequality. Cost- meet new environmental standards.
benefit analysis treats questions about
equity as, at best, side issues, contradicting Real-world examples of cost-benefit
the widely shared view that equity should analysis demonstrate the strange lengths
count in public policy. Poor countries, to which this flawed method can be taken.
communities, and individuals are likely to For example, the consulting group Arthur
express less willingness to pay to avoid D. Little, in a study for the Czech
environmental harms simply because they Republic, concluded that encouraging
have fewer resources. Therefore, cost- smoking among Czech citizens was
benefit analysis would justify imposing beneficial to the government because it
greater environmental burdens on them caused citizens to die earlier and thus
than on their wealthier counterparts. With reduced government expenditures on
this kind of analysis, the poor get poorer. pensions, housing, and health care. In
another study, analysts calculated the
Finally, cost-benefit analysis fails to produce value of childrens lives saved by car
the greater objectivity and transparency seats by estimating the amount of time
promised by its proponents. For the reasons required to fasten the seats correctly and
described above, cost-benefit analysis then assigning a value to the time based
rests on a series of assumptions and value on the mothers actual or imputed hourly
judgments that cannot remotely be wage. These studies are not the work
described as objective. Moreover, the of some lunatic fringe; on the contrary,
highly complex, resource-intensive, and they apply methodologies that are
expert-driven nature of this method makes perfectly conventional within the cost-
it extremely difficult for the public to benefit framework.
2
Fortunately, there are many good
alternatives to the use of cost-benefit
analysis. In fact, virtually all of the
environmental protections adopted in
the United States over the last several
decades were developed without the use of
cost-benefit analysis. Technology-based
regulation, market-based regulation such as
pollution trading, and environmental right-
to-know programs all have reduced pollution
and protected the environment without
relying on the problematic method of cost-
benefit analysis.

Given the deep and varied flaws in cost-


benefit analysis, given the fact that a lot of
time and money are required to generate
cost-benefit studies, and given that superior,
time-tested regulatory alternatives are
available, cost-benefit analysis should
be rejected as a tool for evaluating
environmentally protective regulation.

3
1. Introduction 2. What Is Cost-
ow strictly should we regulate Benefit Analysis?
H arsenic in drinking water? Or
carbon dioxide in the atmosphere? ost-benefit analysis tries to mimic
Or pesticides in our food? Or oil drilling in
scenic places? The list of environmental
harms and potential regulatory remedies
often appears to be endless.
C a basic function of markets by setting
an economic standard for measuring
the success of the governments projects and
programs. That is, cost-benefit analysis seeks
to perform, for public policy, a calculation
Is there an objective way to decide how to that markets perform for the private sector.
proceed? Cost-benefit analysis promises In evaluating a proposed new initiative, how
to provide the solution. The sad fact is do we know if it is worth doing or not? The
that cost-benefit analysis is fundamentally answer, it turns out, is much simpler in
unable to fulfill this promise. business than in government.

This paper aims to demonstrate that Private businesses, striving to make money,
the case for cost-benefit analysis of only produce things that they believe
environmental protection is, at best, wildly someone is willing to pay for. That is, firms
optimistic and, at worst, demonstrably only produce things for which the benefits
wrong. For a variety of reasons intrinsic to consumers, measured by consumers
to the methodology, cost-benefit analysis willingness to pay for them, are expected to
simply does not offer the policy-making be greater than the costs of production. It is
panacea its adherents promise. Moreover, technologically possible to produce mens
in practice, cost-benefit analysis frequently business suits in brightly colored polka dots.
produces false and misleading results. Successful producers suspect that no one is
willing to pay for such products, and usually
Section 2 of this paper introduces cost- stick to at most minor variations on suits in
benefit analysis and describes its methods somber, traditional hues. If some firm did
of evaluating costs and benefits. Section 3 happen to produce a polka-dotted business
summarizes the leading arguments for the suit, no one would be forced to buy it; the
use of cost-benefit analysis. Section 4 lays producer would bear the entire loss resulting
out the fundamental problems with cost- from the mistaken decision.
benefit analysis, and Section 5 dissects
some of the most prominent and Government, in the view of many critics, is in
disturbing examples of the use of cost- constant danger of drifting toward producing
benefit analysis. Section 6 argues that polka dot suits and making people pay for
there are better alternatives for establishing them. Policies, regulations, and public
and evaluating public policy. Section 7 spending do not face the test of the
offers brief conclusions. marketplace; there are no consumers who
can withhold their dollars from the
government until it produces the regulatory
equivalent of navy blue and charcoal gray.
There is no single quantitative objective for
4
the public sector comparable to profit is relatively straightforward. (In practice,
maximization for businesses. Even with as we shall see, it is not quite that simple.)
the best of intentions, critics suggest,
government programs can easily go astray The consideration of the costs of
for lack of an objective standard by which environmental protection is not unique
to judge whether or not they are meeting to cost-benefit analysis. Development
citizens needs. of environmental regulations has almost
always involved consideration of economic
Cost-benefit analysis sets out to do for costs, with or without formal cost-benefit
government what the market does for techniques. What is unique to cost-benefit
business: add up the benefits of a public analysis, and far more problematic, is the
policy and compare them to the costs. other side of the balance, the monetary
The two sides of the ledger raise very valuation of the benefits of life, health,
different issues. and nature itself.

Cost-benefit analysis sets Monetizing Benefits


out to do for government what Since there are no natural prices for a
the market does for business: healthy environment, cost-benefit analysis
add up the benefits of a requires the creation of artificial ones.
This is the hardest part of the process.
public policy and compare Economists create artificial prices for
them to the costs. health and environmental benefits by
studying what people would be willing to
pay for them. One popular method, called
contingent valuation, is essentially a form
Estimating Costs of opinion poll. Researchers ask a cross-
section of the affected population how
The first step in a cost-benefit analysis much they would be willing to pay to
is to calculate the costs of a public policy. preserve or protect something that cant
For example, the government may require a be bought in a store.
certain kind of pollution control equipment,
which businesses must pay for. Even if a Many surveys of this sort have been done,
regulation only sets a ceiling on emissions, producing prices for things that appear to
it results in costs that can be at least be priceless. For example, the average
roughly estimated through research into American household is supposedly willing
available technologies and business to pay $257 to prevent the extinction of
strategies for compliance. bald eagles, $208 to protect humpback
1
whales, and $80 to protect gray wolves.
The costs of protecting human health These numbers are quite large: since there
and the environment through the use are about 100 million households in the
of pollution control devices and other country, the nations total willingness to
approaches are, by their very nature, pay for the preservation of bald eagles
measured in dollars. Thus, at least in alone is ostensibly more than $25 billion.
theory, the cost side of cost-benefit analysis

5
An alternative method of attaching prices $100, say, received today is worth more
to unpriced things infers what people are than $100 received next year, even in the
willing to pay from observation of their absence of inflation. For one thing, you
behavior in other markets. To assign a dollar could put your money in the bank today
value to risks to human life, for example, and earn a little interest by next year.
economists usually calculate the extra wage - Suppose that your bank account earns
or wage premium - that is paid to workers 3 percent interest. In that case, if you
who accept more risky jobs. Suppose that received the $100 today rather than next
two jobs are comparable, except that one is year, you would earn $3 in interest, giving
more dangerous and better paid. If workers you a total of $103 next year. Likewise, in
understand the risk and voluntarily accept order to get $100 next year you only need to
3
the more dangerous job, then they are deposit $97 today. So, at a 3% discount rate,
implicitly setting a price on risk by accepting economists would say that $100 next year
the increased risk of death in exchange for has a present value of $97 in todays dollars.
increased wages.
For longer periods of time, the effect is
What does this indirect inference from magnified: at a 3% discount rate, $100
wage rates have to say about the value of a twenty years from now has a present value
life? A common estimate in recent cost- of only $55. The larger the discount rate,
benefit analyses is that avoiding a risk that and the longer the time intervals involved,
would lead, on average, to one death is the smaller the present value: at a 5%
2
worth roughly $6.3 million. This number, discount rate, for example, $100 twenty
in particular, is of great importance in cost- years from now has a present value
benefit analyses because avoided deaths are of only $38.
the most thoroughly studied benefits of
environmental regulations. Cost-benefit analysis routinely uses the
present value of future benefits. That is,
it compares current costs, not to the actual
dollar value of future benefits, but to the
Discounting the Future smaller amount you would have to put into
a hypothetical savings account today to
One more step requires explanation to obtain those benefits in the future. This
complete this quick sketch of cost-benefit application of discounting is essential, and
analysis. Costs and benefits of a policy indeed commonplace, for many practical
frequently occur at different times. Often, financial decisions. If offered a choice of
costs are incurred today, or in the near investment opportunities with payoffs
future, to prevent harm in the more remote at different times in the future, you can
future. When the analysis spans a number of (and should) discount the future payoffs to
years, future costs and benefits are discounted, the present in order to compare them to
or treated as equivalent to smaller amounts each other. The important issue for
of money in todays dollars. environmental policy, as we shall see, is
whether this logic also applies to outcomes
Discounting is a procedure developed by far in the future, and to opportunities
economists in order to evaluate investments like long life and good health that are
that produce future income. The case for not naturally stated in dollar terms.
discounting begins with the observation that

6
W HAT IS THE
DIFFERENCE effectively reduced with the resources we
BETWEEN COST-BENEFIT have. In colloquial terms, this analysis
ANALYSIS AND OTHER tries to get the biggest bang for our risk-
ANALYTICAL METHODS? reducing buck. (The same is true of a
similar method, cost-effectiveness analysis.)
There are several similar-sounding
Comparative risk analysis does not entail
decision-making frameworks that may be translation of lives and health into dollars.
confused with cost-benefit analysis; it is In other respects, however, it often
important to understand the ways in which replicates the most basic shortcomings of
they are different. The basic difference is cost-benefit analysis; comparative risk
simple to state: no other analytical method analysis tends, for example, to consider only
requires the translation of the benefits of risks to humans, and only fatal risks at that,
regulation long life, good health, clean in assessing the results of environmental
air into dollars. protection; it tends to treat all numerical
risks whether posed by arsenic in drinking
Risk assessment is a scientific method for water or snowboarding in the Rockies as
estimating, often in quantitative terms, equivalent; and it generally incorporates the
the human-health consequences of a technique of discounting human lives saved
particular threat. A risk assessment in the future.
concerning benzene in the workplace, for
example, might conclude that an individual Risk-benefit analysis is usually a mirror-image
worker faces an increased lifetime risk of of cost-benefit analysis: in risk-benefit
cancer of 1 in 1,000 from exposures to this analysis, the benefits are the economic
substance. Combined with figures on the advantages of maintaining the current level
total population of workers exposed to of environmentally damaging activity, and
benzene, this probabilistic estimate might risks are the disadvantages of doing so.
be used to generate an estimate of the total
number of workers expected to get cancer Finally, any simultaneous consideration of
from occupational exposures to benzene. economic costs and health or other benefits
Risk assessment is a building block of many is sometimes referred to as cost-benefit
cost-benefit analyses, but it is far more analysis. For our purposes, this usage is
limited than cost-benefit analysis itself. imprecise and misleading. As we discuss
Risk assessment does not, for example, in section 6, many environmental statutes
attempt to attach a monetary value to the require agencies to take into account
health outcomes it predicts, nor does it both the economic consequences and the
purport to make any judgment about the human-health and environmental results of
relative worth of lives saved today and lives regulatory standards. But only one federal
saved in the future. environmental statute (the Safe Drinking
Water Act) expressly permits an agency to
A similar phrase, comparative risk analysis, translate life, health, and nature into dollars,
is used to describe yet another method. and no statute expressly permits or requires
Comparative risk analysis, in basic terms, any agency to discount the lives of those
attempts to consider the many different ways saved in the future. The cost-benefit
risk might be reduced in our society and to analysis we discuss in this paper embraces
identify those risks that might be most both of these analytical techniques.

7
3. What Are the Arguments in Favor of
Cost-Benefit Analysis?
efore describing the problems with proposed regulations. Thus much of the

B cost-benefit analysis, it will be


useful to set forth the arguments
in favor of this type of analysis. Many
case for cost-benefit analysis depends on
the case against current regulation.

different arguments for cost-benefit analysis One does not have to read very far into the
have been offered over the years. Most of literature on risk regulation before running
the arguments fall into one of two broad across lengthy tables listing the costs per
categories. First, there are economic life saved of various federal regulations.
assertions that better results can be The numbers on such tables are fantastic:
achieved with cost-benefit analysis. according to these lists, we are often
Second, there are legal and political claims spending hundreds of millions, and
that a more objective and more open sometimes billions, of dollars for every
government process can emerge through single human life, or even year of life, we
4
this kind of analysis. save through regulation.

These estimates of regulatory costs and


Better Results benefits have become ubiquitous in
political debates on environmental law.
Economics frequently focuses on increasing Scarcely a congressional hearing on this
efficiency on getting the most desirable subject occurs in which these kinds of
results from the fewest resources. How do numbers do not figure prominently.
we know that greater regulatory efficiency Economists routinely cite these estimates
is needed? For many economists, this is an as proof of the need for more economic
article of faith: greater efficiency is always analysis. Browse the web sites of any of a
a top priority, in regulation or elsewhere. variety of think tanks, and you will find
Cost-benefit analysis supposedly furthers numerous references to the extravagant
efficiency by ensuring that regulations are costs of regulation.
only adopted when benefits exceed costs
and by helping direct regulators attention One widely cited study claims that the
to those problems for which regulatory cost per year of life saved by life-saving
intervention will yield the greatest interventions varies from zero or negative
net benefits. (some life-saving measures impose no new
costs, and may even save money) up to
But many advocates also raise a more $99 billion. The table on the following
specific argument, imbued with a greater page is excerpted from that study. (Note,
sense of urgency. The government, it is however, that not one of the pollution
said, often issues rules that are insanely control measures listed in this table has
expensive, out of all proportion to their ever been proposed by the government,
benefits a problem that could be solved by much less implemented.)
the use of cost-benefit analysis to screen
8
C OSTS PER LIFE-YEAR
SAVED OF HYPOTHETICAL
POLLUTION CONTROLS
6
AT PAPER MILLS
POLLUTION CONTROL MEASURE COST PER LIFE-YEAR

Chloroform emission standard at 17 low cost pulp mills Zero or Negative


Chloroform private well emission standard at 7 papergrade sulfite mills $25,000
Chloroform private well emission standard at 7 pulp mills $620,000
Chloroform reduction by replacing hypochlorite with chlorine dioxide at 1 mill $990,000
Dioxin emission standard of 5 lbs/air dried ton at pulp mills $4,500,000
Dioxin emission standard of 3 (vs. 5) lbs/air dried ton at paper mills $7,500,000
Chloroform emission standard of 0.001 (vs. 0.01) risk level at pulp mills $7,700,000
Chloroform reduction by replacing hypochlorite with chlorine dioxide at 70 mills $8,700,000
Chloroform reduction at 70 (vs. 33 worst) pulp and paper mills $15,000,000
Chloroform reduction at 33 worst pulp and paper mills $57,000,000
Chloroform private well emission standard at 48 pulp mills $99,000,000,000
Source: Tammy O. Tengs, et al., Five-Hundred Life-Saving Interventions and Their
Cost-Effectiveness, 15 Risk Analysis 369(1995).

Numbers like these have been used to argue called the existing state of affairs
5
that current regulatory costs are not only statistical murder.
chaotically variable but also unacceptably
high. They have even been relied upon to From this perspective, cost-benefit
claim that the existing regulatory system analysis emerges as both a money-saver
actually kills people by imposing some very and a life-saver. By subjecting regulations
costly life-saving requirements while other, to a cost-benefit test, we would not only
less expensive and more effective life-saving stop spending hundreds of millions or
possibilities remain untouched. Indeed, billions of dollars to save a single life, we
a study drawing upon these data could also take that money and spend it
concluded that we could save as many on saving even more lives through
as 60,000 more lives every year with no different life-saving measures.
increase in costs if we simply spent our
money on the least rather than most That, at least, is the theory. We will argue
expensive opportunities for saving lives. in the following sections that there are
Relying on this research, John Graham, the good reasons to question both the theory
current head of the Office of Information and the facts it rests on. Nevertheless,
and Regulatory Affairs in the Office of the notion that the current system
Management and Budget and a prominent produces crazy, even deadly, rules, and
proponent of cost-benefit analysis, has that better economic analysis would avert

9
this terrible result, remains one of the most In order for the public to be part of the
persistent arguments offered on behalf of process of decision making about the
cost-benefit analysis. environment, these judgments must
be offered and debated in language
accessible to people who are not
Objectivity and Transparency biologists, toxicologists, or other kinds of
experts. Many advocates of cost-benefit
A second important set of arguments holds analysis believe that their methodology
that cost-benefit analysis would produce a provides such a language. They also assert
better regulatory process more objective that cost-benefit analysis renders decision-
and more transparent, and thus more making transparent insofar as it requires
accountable to the public. decision-makers to reveal all of the
assumptions and uncertainties reflected
The holy grail of administrative law is in their decisions.
agency decision making based on objective
standards. The idea is to prevent an agency
either from just doing anything it wants or,
more invidiously, from benefiting politically
favored groups through its decisions. Cost-
benefit analysis has been offered as a means
of constraining agency discretion to avoid
these kinds of results.

Another important goal said to be


promoted by cost-benefit analysis is
transparency of administrative procedures.
Decisions about environmental protection
are notoriously complex. They reflect
the input of biologists, toxicologists,
epidemiologists, economists, engineers,
lawyers, and other experts whose work is
complicated and arcane. The technical
details of these decisions often raise
important questions about how much
scientific uncertainty is too much,
which human populations should be
protected from illness and even death,
and how important the future is relative
to the present.

10
4. Why It Doesnt Work:
Fundamental Flaws

A
s we have seen, cost-benefit analysis individual steps in the pursuit of any goal,
involves the creation of artificial set for the long haul, that cannot be
markets for things - like good health, reached overnight - including, for example,
long life, and clean air - that are not bought the achievement of a clean environment.
and sold. It also involves the devaluation of
future events through discounting. Moving beyond these intuitive responses,
we offer in this section a detailed
So described, the mind-set of the cost- explanation of why cost-benefit analysis
benefit analyst is likely to seem quite of environmental protection fails to live up
foreign. The translation of all good things to the hopes and claims of its advocates.
into dollars and the devaluation of the There is no quick fix, because these
future are inconsistent with the way many failures are intrinsic to the methodology,
people view the world. Most of us believe appearing whenever it is applied to any
that money doesnt buy happiness. Most complex environmental problem. In our
religions tell us that every human life is view, cost-benefit analysis suffers from
sacred; it is obviously illegal, as well as four fundamental flaws, addressed in each
immoral, to buy and sell human lives. of the next four subsections:
Most parents tell their children to eat
their vegetables and do their homework, The standard economic approaches to
even though the rewards of these onerous valuation are inaccurate and implausible.
activities lie far in the future. Monetizing
human lives and discounting future The use of discounting improperly trivializes
benefits seem at odds with these future harms and the irreversibility of some
common perspectives. environmental problems.

The cost-benefit approach also is The reliance on aggregate, monetized benefits


inconsistent with the way many of us excludes questions of fairness and morality.
make daily decisions. Imagine performing
a new cost-benefit analysis to decide The value-laden and complex cost-benefit
whether to get up and go to work every process is neither objective nor transparent.
morning, whether to exercise or eat right on
any given day, whether to wash the dishes or
leave them in the sink, and so on. Inaction Dollars Without Sense
would win far too often and an absurd
amount of effort would be spent on Recall that cost-benefit analysis requires
analysis. Most people have long-run goals, the creation of artificial prices for all
commitments, and habits that make such relevant health and environmental
daily balancing exercises either redundant impacts. To weigh the benefits of
or counterproductive. The same might be regulation against the costs, we need to
true of society as a whole undertaking know the monetary value of preventing
11
the extinction of species, preserving many The standard response is that a value like
different ecosystems, avoiding all manner $6.3 million is not actually a price on an
of serious health impacts, and even saving individuals life or death. Rather, it is a
human lives. Without such numbers, cost- way of expressing the value of small risks
benefit analysis cannot be conducted. of death; for example, it is one million
times the value of a one in a million risk.
Artificial prices have been estimated for If people are willing to pay $6.30 to avoid
many, though by no means all, benefits of a one in a million increase in the risk of
regulation. As discussed, preventing the death, then the value of a statistical life
extinction of bald eagles reportedly goes for is $6.3 million.
somewhat more than $250 per household.
Preventing retardation due to childhood Unfortunately, this explanation fails to
lead poisoning comes in at about $9,000 resolve the dilemma. It is true that risk
per lost IQ point (although, as we will (or statistical life) and life itself are
see in Section 5, a much lower price has distinct concepts. But if human life is too
recently been proposed). Saving a life is sacred to buy and sell, why is it permissible
ostensibly worth $6.3 million. to trade small risks of losing that ultimate
value? One-millionth of an immeasurable
This quantitative precision, achieved or infinite value is still immeasurable or
7
through a variety of indirect techniques for infinite, not $6.30.
valuation, comes at the expense of accuracy
and even common sense. Though problems
arise in many areas of valuation, we will Human life is the
focus primarily on the efforts to attach a ultimate example of a
monetary value to human life, both because
of its importance in cost-benefit analysis
value that is not a commodity,
and because of its glaring contradictions. and does not have a price.

There Are No Statistical People


In practice, moreover, analysts often
What can it mean to say that saving one life ignore the distinction between valuing
8

is worth $6.3 million? Human life is the risk and valuing life. Many regulations
ultimate example of a value that is not a reduce risk for a large number of people,
commodity, and does not have a price. and avoid actual death for a much smaller
You cannot buy the right to kill someone number. A complete cost-benefit analysis
for $6.3 million, nor for any other price. should, therefore, include valuation of both
Most systems of ethical and religious of these benefits. However, the standard
belief maintain that every life is sacred. If practice is to calculate a value only for
analysts calculated the value of life itself by statistical life and to ignore life itself.
asking people what it is worth to them (the
The confusion between the valuation of
most common method of valuation of other
risk and the valuation of life itself is
environmental benefits), the answer would
embedded in current regulatory practice
be infinite, as no finite amount of money
in another way as well. The Office of
could compensate a person for the loss of
Management and Budget which reviews
his life, simply because money is no good
6 cost-benefit analyses prepared by federal
to him when he is dead.
12
agencies pursuant to executive order People Care About Other People
instructs agencies to discount the benefits
of life-saving regulations from the moment Another large problem with this approach
of avoided death, rather than from the time to valuation of life is that it asks
9
when the risk of death is reduced. individuals (either directly through
surveys, or indirectly through observing

Most spiritual beliefs wage and job choices) only about their
attitudes toward risks to themselves.
call on us to value the lives
A recurring theme in literature suggests
of others - not only those closest that our deepest and noblest sentiments
to us, but also those whom we involve valuing someone elses life more
have never met. highly than our own: think of parents
devotion to their children, soldiers
commitment to those whom they are
This approach to discounting is plainly protecting, lovers concern for each other.
inconsistent with the claim that cost- Most spiritual beliefs call on us to value
benefit analysis seeks to evaluate risk. the lives of others - not only those closest
When a life-threatening disease such as to us, but also those whom we have
cancer has a long latency period, many never met.
years may pass between the time when a
This point echoes a procedure that
risk is imposed and the time of death.
has become familiar in other areas of
If monetary valuations of statistical
environmental valuation. Economists
life represented risk, and not life, then
often ask about existence values: how
the value of statistical life would be
much is the existence of a wilderness area
discounted from the date of a change in
or an endangered species worth to you,
risk (typically, when a new regulation is
even if you will never personally
enforced) rather than from the much
10 experience it? If this question makes
later date of avoided actual death.
sense for bald eagles and national parks,
In acknowledging the monetary value of it must be at least as important when
reducing risk, economic analysts have applied to safe drinking water and working
contributed to our growing awareness that conditions for people we dont know.
life-threatening risk itself and not just the
The difficulty is that the answer to this
end result of such risk, death is an injury.
type of question cannot be deduced
But they have blurred the line between
solely from your attitudes toward risks to
risks and actual deaths, by calculating the
yourself. We are not aware of any attempts
value of reduced risk while pretending that
to quantify the existence value of the life
they have produced a valuation of life itself.
of a stranger, let alone a relative or a friend,
The paradox of monetizing the infinite or
but we are sure that most belief systems
immeasurable value of human life has not
affirm that this value is substantial
been resolved; it has only been glossed over.
(assuming, of course, that the value
of life is a number in the first place).

13
Voting Is Different From Buying In a similar vein, the philosopher Henry
Richardson argues that reliance on the
Cost-benefit analysis, which relies on cost-benefit standard forecloses the
estimates of individuals preferences process of democratic deliberation that is
as consumers, also fails to address necessary for intelligent decision-making.
the collective choice presented to In his view, attempts to make decisions
society by most public health and based on monetary valuation of benefits
environmental problems. freeze preferences in advance, leaving no
room for the changes in response to new
Under the cost-benefit approach, valuation information, rethinking of the issues, and
of environmental benefits is based on negotiated compromises that lie at the
13
individuals private decisions as consumers heart of the deliberative process.
or workers, not on their public values as
citizens. However, policies that protect Cost-benefit analysis turns public citizens
the environment are often public goods, into selfish consumers, and interconnected
and are not available for purchase in communities into atomized individuals.
individual portions. In a classic example In this way, it distorts the question it sets
of this distinction, the philosopher Mark out to answer: how much do we, as a society,
Sagoff found that his students, in their value health and the environment?
role as citizens, opposed commercial ski
development in a nearby wilderness area,
but, in their role as consumers, would plan
Numbers Dont Tell Us Everything
to go skiing there if the development was
11
built. There is no contradiction between A few simple examples illustrate another
these two views: as individual consumers, problem that numerically equal risks are
the students would have no way to express not always equally deserving of regulatory
their collective preference for wilderness response. The death rate is roughly the
preservation. Their individual willingness same (somewhat less than one in a million)
to pay for skiing would send a misleading from a day of downhill skiing, from a day
signal about their views as citizens. of working in the construction industry,
or from drinking about 20 liters of water
It is often impossible to arrive at a containing 50 parts per billion of arsenic,
meaningful social valuation by adding the old regulatory limit that was recently
up the willingness to pay expressed by revised by the Bush administration.
individuals. What could it mean to ask how This does not mean that societys
much you personally are willing to pay to responsibility to reduce risks is the
clean up a major oil spill? If no one else same in each case.
contributes, the clean-up wont happen
regardless of your decision. As the Nobel Most people view risks imposed by others,
Prize-winning economist Amartya Sen has without an individuals consent, as more
pointed out, if your willingness to pay for a worthy of government intervention than
large-scale public initiative is independent risks that an individual knowingly accepts.
of what others are paying, then you probably On that basis, the highest priority among
have not understood the nature of the our three examples is to reduce drinking
12
problem. Instead, a collective decision water contamination, a hazard to which
about collective resources is required.
14
no one has consented. The acceptance of economists have to find some way to
a risky occupation such as construction is mimic the operation of the market.
at best quasi-voluntary it involves somewhat Unfortunately the process is far from
more individual discretion than the choice automatic, it is certainly not costless, and
of public drinking water supplies, but many it has to be repeated every time an
people go to work under great economic updated price is needed.
pressure, and with little information about
occupational hazards. In contrast, the choice As a result, there is constant pressure to
of risky recreational pursuits such as skiing use outdated or inappropriate valuations.
is entirely discretionary; obviously no Indeed, there are sound economic reasons
one is forced to ski. Safety regulation in for doing so: no one can afford constant
construction work is thus more urgent than updates, and significant savings can be
regulation of skiing, despite the equality of achieved by using valuations created for
numerical risk. other cases. In the EPAs original cost-
benefit analysis of arsenic (see the arsenic
In short, even for ultimate values such case study, starting at page 17), the
as life and death, the social context is estimated value of a case of chronic
decisive in our evaluation of risks. Cost- bronchitis was used to represent the
benefit analysis assumes the existence value of a case of nonfatal bladder cancer.
of generic, acontextual risk, and thereby
ignores the contextual information that This is not, we hope and believe, because
determines how many of us, in practice, anyone thinks that bronchitis and bladder
think about real risks to real people. cancer are the same disease. The reason
is more mundane: no one has performed
an analysis of the cost of bladder cancer,
Artificial Prices Are Expensive and even the extensive analysis of arsenic
regulations did not include enough time
Finally, the economic valuation called for and money to do so. Therefore, the
by cost-benefit analysis is fundamentally investigators used an estimated value
flawed because it demands an enormous for a very different disease. The only
volume of consistently updated information, explanation offered for this procedure
which is beyond the practical capacity of was that it had been done before, and
our society to generate. nothing better was available.

All attempts at valuation of the environment Use of the bronchitis valuation to


begin with a problem: the goal is to assign represent bladder cancer can charitably be
monetary prices to things that have no described as grasping at straws. Lacking
prices, because they are not for sale. One the time and money to fill in the blank
of the great strengths of the market is that carefully, the economists simply picked a
it provides so much information about real number. This is not remotely close to the
prices. For any commodity that is actually level of rigor that is seen throughout the
bought and sold, prices are communicated natural science, engineering, and public
automatically, almost costlessly, and with health portions of the arsenic analysis. Yet
constant updates as needed. To create it will happen again, for exactly the same
artificial prices for environmental values, reason. It is not a failure of will or intellect,
but rather the inescapable limitations of
15
time and budget, that lead to reliance It is a biased and misleading premise to
on dated, inappropriate, and incomplete assume that individuals willingness
information to fill in the gaps on the to pay to avoid certain risks can be
benefit side of a cost-benefit analysis. aggregated to arrive at a figure for what
society should pay to protect human life.
Risk of death is not the same as death
Summing Up itself, and not all risks can reasonably be
compared one to the other. Moreover, the
There are, in short, a host of problems with value to society of protecting human life
the process of valuation. On a philosophical cannot be arrived at simply by toting up
level, human life may belong in the category individual consumer preferences.
of things that are too valuable to buy and
sell. Most ethical and religious beliefs place The same kind of problems affect other
the protection of human life in the same valuation issues raised by cost-benefit
category as love, family, religion, democracy, analysis, such as estimating the value
and other ultimate values, which are not of clean water, biodiversity, or entire
and cannot be priced. ecosystems. The upshot is that cost-
benefit analysis is fundamentally
incapable of delivering on its promise of
more economically efficient decisions
Absent a credible about protecting human life, health,
and the environment. Absent a credible
monetary metric
monetary metric for calculating the
for calculating the benefits of regulation, cost-benefit
benefits of regulation, analysis is inherently unreliable.
cost-benefit analysis is (main text continued on page 21)
inherently unreliable.

16
COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS IN
PRACTICE:

A RSENIC IN DRINKING WATER


ne thing is certain: arsenic is bad The Safe Drinking Water Act, as amended

O for you. It causes cancers of the


bladder, lungs, skin, kidneys, nasal
passages, liver, and prostate, as well as other
in 1996, is the only federal environmental
statute that explicitly sanctions cost-
benefit analysis based on consumers
cardiovascular, pulmonary, neurological, willingness to pay for environmental
immunological, and endocrine problems. protection. The controversy that has
It is found naturally in rock formations and erupted over the arsenic rule well
dissolves into drinking water supplies, illustrates the inability of cost-benefit
the principal source of exposure. analysis to answer important questions
of social policy. It also shows how the
Until the Bush administration issued a new controversial and value-laden assumptions
standard for arsenic, federal law limited of cost-benefit analysis become invisible
arsenic in drinking water to 50 parts per in public debates based on such analysis.
billion (ppb), a standard set in 1942.
Almost forty years ago, in 1962, the U.S.
Public Health Service recommended that EPAs Analysis
drinking water should not contain more In developing the new standard, EPA
a
than 10 ppb. considered four possible standards: 3, 5,
c
10, and 20 ppb. Testing and monitoring
On three occasions in the past thirty years, are not reliable below 3 ppb, so it is the
Congress has directed EPA to update the lowest possible level for regulation.
50 ppb standard. A 1999 report by the
National Academy of Sciences concluded On the cost side, detailed engineering
that the 50 ppb standard requires descriptions are available for an array of
b
downward revision as promptly as possible. possible technologies for water treatment
At last, in January 2001, EPA announced a and disposal of resulting residues. The
new standard of 10 ppb (the standard choice of technology depends on the size
recommended by the World Health and circumstances of community water
Organization and adopted by many systems. EPAs estimates express only a
European countries). Less than two narrow range of uncertainty about costs,
months later, the Bush administration as shown in the table on page 18. Note
withdrew this standard only to accept it that if these pollution control technologies
again after eight months of further review become cheaper once the arsenic rule is
and debate. implemented as often happens when
environmental rules are enforced the
estimated costs will prove too high.
17
E PAS ESTIMATES
OF COSTS AND
BENEFITS
OF DIFFERENT
ARSENIC STANDARDS

ARSENIC COMPLIANCE HEALTH BLADDER AND


STANDARD COSTS BENEFITS LUNG CANCER
(PPB) (MILLIONS) (MILLIONS) CASES AVOIDED

3 $700-790 $210-490 57-140

5 $420-470 $190-360 51-100

10 $180-210 $140-200 37-56

20 $67-77 $66-75 19-20

Source: EPA, National Primary Drinking Water Regulations; Arsenic and Clarifications to
Compliance and New Source Contaminants Monitoring; Final Rules, 66 Fed. Reg. 6976,
7009, 7017 (Jan. 22, 2001) (rounded to two significant figures). Costs and benefits are
in 1999 dollars.

On the benefit side, reduction in arsenic in avoided death at $6.1 million in 1999
drinking water has many health advantages. dollars, based on wage-risk studies
As noted, arsenic causes many different measuring the wage premium required
cancers and other neurological, to attract workers to dangerous jobs - a
immunological, and endocrine problems. procedure discussed in Section 3 of the
However, EPAs analysts were only able text. For other health effects, EPA found
to produce quantitative estimates of the that there was no willingness-to-pay
health effects for bladder and lung cancer; value available for nonfatal cancers
all numerical analysis of benefits refers to so it used the value of reducing chronic
d
preventing these two cancers alone. bronchitis instead! For health effects
other than cancers, EPA did not provide
Even with this narrow focus, EPA faced a dollar equivalent.
difficult challenges in monetizing the health
effects of arsenic. In the U.S., death occurs The gap between the upper and lower
within five years of diagnosis for 88% of lung estimates of monetized health benefits
cancer cases, but only 26% of bladder cancer (shown in the table above) reflects solely
cases. Thus the monetization of these the uncertainty about the number of
cancers requires estimates of both the avoided cancers; the valuations of fatal
value of avoided deaths, and the value of and non-fatal cancers are provided in
avoided nonfatal cancers, particularly precise dollar amounts. As seen in the
bladder cancers. EPA set the value of an table, costs and benefits are comparable
18
for 20 ppb and 10 ppb. At 5 ppb and 3 ppb, response curve in estimating the cancer
the monetized benefits are below the costs. risks of arsenic. That is, EPA assumed
that the number of cancer cases is
proportional to total exposure, a long-
AEI-Brookings Analysis established assumption that is routinely
used in the absence of evidence to the
The AEI-Brookings Joint Center for contrary. Making up a different dose-
Regulatory Studies has been a vocal response relationship, Hahn and Burnett,
proponent of cost-benefit analysis of neither of whom is a scientist, offered
environmental rules. Nevertheless, their best estimate (again, on an almost
when EPA first issued its new rule, AEI- evidence-free basis) that there were only
Brookings produced a study authored by one-fifth as many cases of cancer due to
Robert Hahn and Jason Burnett, highly arsenic as EPA had projected.
e
critical of the rule. This rival study is
worth focusing on both because it With these and other adjustments, Hahn
achieved high visibility in the media, and Burnett found the costs to be roughly
and because its methods reveal the extent ten times the benefits of arsenic reduction,
to which the devil is in the details of costing a shocking $65 million per life
cost-benefit analysis. saved. They speculated that even 50 ppb
might be too strict a standard, in light of
EPA had erred in two ways, the AEI- the low benefits.
Brookings study concluded, which led to
overestimates of the benefits of arsenic When the National Academy of Sciences
reduction. First, the study criticized EPA (NAS) reviewed the arsenic standard
for failing to discount the lives saved by the yet again, in 2001, it found exactly the
arsenic rule. Because exposure to arsenic opposite of Hahn and Burnetts best
leads to cancer only after a latency period, estimate. That is, NAS concluded that
Hahn and Burnett thought EPA should have arsenic would cause more cancer cases
discounted the benefits of the rule. than EPA had projected. This finding,
no doubt combined with the public outcry
EPA had rejected discounting because over the issue, helped persuade the Bush
it was unable, given current scientific administration to relent and accept the
knowledge, to identify the latency period 10 ppb standard.
for the cancers associated with arsenic.
Hahn and Burnett were not deterred by this
lack of knowledge. They simply picked a Public Debate
latency period (without citing any arsenic-
related scientific evidence) of 30 years for Once the rival EPA and Hahn-Burnett
their best estimate scenario. This guess numbers made their way into the public
at the latency period, combined with a forum, the assumptions, qualifications,
7 percent discount rate, had the effect of and uncertainties surrounding them were
reducing the present value of a life saved forgotten. Also ignored were the benefits
from $6.1 million to $1.1 million. of the rule that EPA had been unable to
quantify, and the value-laden assumptions
Second, the AEI-Brookings study undergirding the very different analyses
criticized EPA for using a linear dose- offered by EPA and AEI-Brookings.

19
One way to gauge the misunderstanding Footnotes
that ensued is to look at press accounts of
the arsenic rule. The Washington Post, a. National Resources Defense Council,
for example, ran a series of opinion pieces Arsenic and Old Laws (2000),
criticizing EPAs 10ppb standard when http://www.nrdc.org.
originally issued in early 2001 (before the
f
latest NAS study appeared). These pieces b. National Research Council, Arsenic in
made a variety of mistakes, all stemming Drinking Water 9 (National Academy
from a failure to distinguish precision Press 1999).
from accuracy.
c. EPA, National Primary Drinking Water
First, these opinion pieces assumed that Regulations; Arsenic and Clarifications
the Clinton-era rule was not justified to Compliance and New Source
unless quantified and monetized benefits Contaminants Monitoring; Final Rules,
were higher than the costs. Because the 66 Fed. Reg. 6976 (Jan. 22, 2001).
rule (at 10 ppb) was predicted to cost
$210 billion and the benefits were valued d. Id. at 7012.
at $170 billion, these essays concluded
that the rule was not worth it. Completely e. Jason K. Burnett and Robert W. Hahn,
ignored were the many unquantified and EPAs Arsenic Rule: The Benefits of the
unmonetized benefits EPA had felt certain Standard Do Not Justify the Costs,
would flow from the rule. AEI-Brookings Joint Center for
Regulatory Studies, Regulatory Analysis
Second, these essays referred to the 01-02 (Jan. 2001).
Hahn-Burnett analysis without once even
mentioning the discounting and dubious f. Sebastian Mallaby, Saving Statistical
scientific adjustments that so influenced Lives, The Washington Post A19 (Mar. 5,
its results. Journalist Michael Kinsley 2001); Michael Kinsley, Bush Is Right
noted the $65 million price tag per life On Arsenic. Darn!, The Washington Post
saved according to Hahn and Burnetts A23 (Apr. 13, 2001); George F. Will,
analysis, and opined, without dwelling on The Costs of Moral Exhibitionism,
the details, that its assumptions seemed to The Washington Post B7 (Apr. 15, 2001).
g
him reasonable.
g. Michael Kinsley, Bush Is Right On
The public dialogue in the aftermath of Arsenic. Darn!, The Washington Post A23
the Bush administrations initial withdrawal (Apr. 13, 2001).
of the new arsenic rule was not about
discounting future life-saving, or cancer
risk assessment, or the value of a life. Yet
the numerical estimates of the benefits turn
almost entirely on these issues, and the
theories on which they rest. Cost-benefit
analysis has not enriched the public dialogue;
it has impoverished it, covering the topic
with poorly understood numbers rather than
clarifying the underlying clash of values.

20
Trivializing the Future Cost-benefit analysis systematically
downgrades the importance of the future
One of the great triumphs of environmental in two ways: through the technique
law is its focus on the future: it seeks of discounting, and through predictive
to avert harms to people and to natural methodologies that take inadequate
resources in the future, and not only account of the possibility of catastrophic
within this generation, but within future and irreversible events.
generations as well. Indeed, one of the
primary objectives of the National The most common, and commonsense,
Environmental Policy Act, which has been argument in favor of discounting future
called our basic charter of environmental human lives saved, illnesses averted, and
protection, is to nudge the nation into ecological disasters prevented is that it is
fulfill[ing] the responsibilities of each better to suffer a harm later rather than
generation as trustee of the environment sooner. Whats wrong with this argument?
14
for succeeding generations. A lot, as it turns out.

Protection of endangered species and


ecosystems, reduction of pollution from Do Future Generations Count?
persistent chemicals such as dioxin and
The first problem with the later-is-better
DDT, prevention of long-latency diseases
argument for discounting is that it assumes
such as cancer, protection of the unborn
that one person is deciding between dying
against the health hazards from exposure
or falling ill now, or dying or falling ill later.
to toxins in the womb all of these
In that case, virtually everyone would
protections are afforded by environmental
prefer later. But many environmental
law, and all of them look to the future as
programs protect the far future, beyond
the lifetime of todays decision-makers.
At a discount rate Thus the choice implicit in discounting is
of 5 percent the between preventing harms to the current
generation and preventing similar harms
death of a billion to future generations. Seen in this way,
people 500 years from discounting looks like a fancy justification
now becomes less for foisting our problems off onto the
people who come after us.
serious than the death
of one person today. The time periods involved in protecting
the environment are often enormous
many decades for a wide range of problems,
well as to the present. Environmental law and even many centuries, in the case of
seeks, moreover, to avoid the unpleasant climate change, radioactive waste, and
surprises that come with discontinuities other persistent toxins. With time spans
and irreversibility the kinds of events this long, discounting at any positive rate
that outstrip our powers of quantitative will make even global catastrophes seem
prediction. Here, too, environmental law trivial. At a discount rate of 5 percent,
tries to protect the future in addition for example, the death of a billion people
to the present. 500 years from now becomes less serious
than the death of one person today.
21
Does Haste Prevent Waste? Cost-benefit analysts, for the most part, do
not assume the possibility of crisis. Their
The argument for discounting also assumes worldview assumes stable problems, with
that environmental problems wont get any control costs that are stable or declining
worse if we wait to address them. In the over time, and thus finds precautionary
market paradigm, buying environmental investment in environmental protection
protection is just like buying any other to be a needless expense. Discounting is
commodity. You can buy a new computer part of this non-crisis perspective. By
now or later and if you dont need it this implying that the present cost of future
year, you should probably wait. The environmental harms declines, lockstep,
technology will undoubtedly keep with every year that we look ahead,
improving, so next years models will do discounting ignores the possibility of
more yet cost less. An exactly parallel catastrophic and irreversible harms.
argument has been made about climate For this very reason, some prominent
change (and other environmental economists have rejected the discounting
problems) by some economists: if we wait of intangibles. As William Baumol wrote
for further technological progress, we will in an important early article on discounting
get more for our climate change mitigation the benefits of public projects:
dollars in the future.
There are important externalities and investments
If environmental protection was mass- of the public goods variety which cry for special
produced by the computer industry, and if attention. Irreversibilities constitute a prime
environmental problems would agree to example. If we poison our soil so that never again
stand still indefinitely and wait for us to will it be the same, if we destroy the Grand Canyon
respond, this might be a reasonable and turn it into a hydroelectric plant, we give up
approach. In the real world, however, assets which like Goldsmiths bold peasantry,
it is a ludicrous and dangerous strategy. their countrys pride, when once destroyd can
never be supplied. All the wealth and resources of
15
Too many years of delay may mean that the future generations will not suffice to restore them.
polar ice cap melts, the spent uranium leaks
out of the containment ponds, the hazardous Most cost-benefit analysts do not exhibit
waste seeps into groundwater and basements this kind of humility about what the future
and backyards at which point we cant put might hold in store for us.
the genie back in the bottle at any
reasonable cost (or perhaps not at all).
Begging the Question
Environmentalists often talk of potential
crises, of threats that problems will Extensive discounting of future
become suddenly and irreversibly environmental problems lies at the
worse. In response to such threats, heart of many recent studies of regulatory
environmentalists and some governments costs and benefits that charge statistical
advocate the so-called precautionary murder. When the costs and benefits of
principle, which calls upon regulators to environmental protection are compared
err on the side of caution and protection to those of safety rules (like requiring
when risks are uncertain. fire extinguishers for airplanes) or medical
procedures (like vaccinating children
22
against disease), environmental protection they take on a different role. The future
almost always comes out the loser. seems to matter much more to American
16
Why is this so? citizens than to American consumers, even
though they are of course the same people.
These studies all discount future
environmental benefits by at least 5 percent For example, Americans are notoriously bad
per year. This has little effect on the at saving money on their own, apparently
evaluation of programs, like auto safety expressing a disinterest in the future. But
rules requiring seat belts and fire safety rules Social Security is arguably the most popular
requiring smoke alarms, that could start entitlement program in the United States.
saving lives right away. However, for The tension between Americans personal
environmental programs like hazardous saving habits and their enthusiasm for
waste cleanups and control of persistent Social Security implies a sharp divergence
toxins that save lives in the future, between the temporal preferences of
discounting matters a great deal people as consumers and as citizens. Thus
especially since, as explained above, the private preferences for current over future
benefits are assumed to occur in the future consumption should not be used to subvert
when deaths are avoided, rather than in public judgments that future harms are as
the near term when risks are reduced. important as immediate ones.

By using discounting, analysts assume the


answer to the question they purport to be
Exacerbating Inequality
addressing, that is, which programs are most
worthwhile. The researchers begin with
The third fundamental defect of cost-
premises that guarantee that programs
benefit analysis is that it tends to ignore,
designed for the long haul like
and therefore to reinforce, patterns of
environmental protection are not as
economic and social inequality. Cost-
important as programs that look to the
benefit analysis consists of adding up all the
shorter term. When repeated without
costs of a policy, adding up all the benefits,
discounting (or with benefits assumed
and comparing the totals. Implicit in this
to occur when risks are reduced), these
innocuous-sounding procedure is the
studies support many more environmental
controversial assumption that it doesnt
programs, and the cry of statistical
matter who gets the benefits and who
murder rings hollow.
pays the costs. Both benefits and costs
are measured simply as dollar totals; those
Citizens and Consumers Reprise totals are silent on questions of equity and
distribution of resources.
The issue of discounting illustrates once
again the failure of cost-benefit analysis to Yet in our society, concerns about equity
take into account the difference between frequently do and should enter into
citizens and consumers. Many people debates over public policy. There is an
advocate discounting on the ground that it important difference between spending
reflects peoples preferences, as expressed state tax revenues to improve the parks in
in market decisions concerning risk. rich communities, and spending the same
But again, this omits the possibility that revenues to clean up pollution in poor
people will have different preferences when communities. The dollar value of these
23
two initiatives, measured using cost-benefit Your reasoning is perfectly logical but totally
analysis, might be the same in both cases, insane Your thoughts [provide] a concrete
but this does not mean that the two policies example of the unbelievable alienation,
are equally urgent or desirable. reductionist thinking, social ruthlessness and
the arrogant ignorance of many conventional
The problem of equity runs even deeper. economists concerning the nature of the world
18
Benefits are typically measured by we live in.
willingness to pay for environmental
improvement, and the rich are able and If decisions are based strictly on cost-
willing to pay for more than the poor. benefit analysis and willingness to pay,
Imagine a cost-benefit analysis of siting most environmental burdens will end
an undesirable facility, such as a landfill up being imposed on the countries,
or incinerator. Wealthy communities are communities, and individuals with the
willing to pay more for the benefit of not least resources. This theoretical pattern
having the facility in their backyards; thus bears an uncomfortably close resemblance
the net benefits to society as a whole will to reality. Cost-benefit methods should
be maximized by putting the facility in a not be blamed for existing patterns of
low-income area. (Note that wealthy environmental injustice; we suspect
communities do not actually have to pay that pollution is typically dumped on the
for the benefit of avoiding the facility; the poor without waiting for formal analysis.
analysis depends only on the fact that they
are willing to pay.)
If decisions are based
This kind of logic was made (in)famous strictly on cost-benefit analysis
in a 1991 memo circulated by Lawrence and willingness to pay,
Summers (former Secretary of the Treasury,
now President of Harvard University) when
most environmental burdens
he was the chief economist at the World will end up being imposed
Bank. Discussing the migration of dirty on the countries, communities,
industries to developing countries,
Summers memo explained:
and individuals with
the least resources.
The measurements of the costs of health impairing
pollution depend[] on the foregone earnings from
increased morbidity and mortality. From this point Still, cost-benefit analysis rationalizes
of view a given amount of health impairing pollution and reinforces the problem, allowing
should be done in the country with the lowest cost, environmental burdens to flow downhill
which will be the country with the lowest wages. I along the income gradients of an unequal
think the economic logic behind dumping a load of world. It is hard to see this as part of an
toxic waste in the lowest wage country is impeccable economically optimal or politically
17
and we should face up to that. objective method of decision-making.

After this memo became public, Brazils In short, equity is an important criterion
then-Secretary of the Environment Jose for evaluation of public policy, but it does
Lutzenburger wrote to Summers: not fit into the cost-benefit framework.

24
The same is true of questions of rights and Less Objectivity
morality, principles that are not reducible
to monetary terms. Calculations that are
and Transparency
acceptable, even common sense, for financial A fourth fundamental flaw of cost-benefit
matters can prove absurd or objectionable analysis is that it is unable to deliver on
when applied to moral issues, as shown by the promise of more objective and more
the following example. transparent decision-making. In fact, in
most cases, the use of cost-benefit analysis
A financial investment with benefits worth is likely to deliver less objectivity and
five times its costs would seem like an less transparency.
obviously attractive bargain. Compare this
to one studys estimate that front airbags on
the passenger side of automobiles may cause Because value-laden premises
one death, usually of a child, for every five permeate cost-benefit analysis,
lives saved. If we really believed that the claim that cost-benefit
lives even statistical lives were worth
$6 million, or any other finite dollar amount,
analysis offers an objective
endorsing the airbags should be no more way to make government
complicated than accepting the financial decisions is simply bogus.
investment. However, many people do find
the airbag tradeoff troubling or unacceptable,
implying that there is a different, non- For the reasons we have discussed, there is
quantitative value of a life that is at stake nothing objective about the basic premises
here. If a public policy brought some of cost-benefit analysis. Treating individuals
people five dollars of benefits for every solely as consumers, rather than as citizens
one dollar it cost to others, the winners with a sense of moral responsibility to the
could in theory compensate the losers. larger society, represents a distinct and
No such compensation is possible if winning highly contestable worldview. Likewise,
and losing are measured in deaths rather the use of discounting reflects judgments
19
than dollars. about the nature of environmental risks
and citizens responsibilities toward future
In comparing the deaths of adults prevented generations which are, at a minimum,
by airbags with the deaths of children caused debatable. Because value-laden premises
by airbags, or in exploring countless other permeate cost-benefit analysis, the claim
harms that might be mitigated through that cost-benefit analysis offers an
regulation, the real debate is not between objective way to make government
rival cost-benefit analyses. Rather, it is decisions is simply bogus.
between environmental advocates who
frame the issue as a matter of rights and Furthermore, as we have seen, cost-benefit
ethics, and others who see it as an analysis relies on a byzantine array of
acceptable area for economic calculation. approximations, simplifications, and
That debate is inescapable, and is logically counterfactual hypotheses. Thus, the
prior to the details of evaluating costs actual use of cost-benefit analysis inevitably
and benefits. involves countless judgment calls. People
with strong, and clashing, partisan positions
will naturally advocate that discretion in
25
the application of this methodology be decide whether to embrace them without
exercised in favor of their positions, further thinking through the whole range of
undermining the claim that cost-benefit moral issues they raise. Yet once one has
analysis is objective. thought through these issues, there is no
need then to collapse the complex moral
Perhaps the best way to illustrate how inquiry into a series of numbers. Pricing
little economic analysis has to contribute, the priceless merely translates our inquiry
objectively, to the fundamental question of into a different, and foreign, language, one
how clean and safe we want our environment with a painfully impoverished vocabulary.
to be is to refer again to the controversy over
cost-benefit analysis of EPAs regulation of For many of the same reasons, cost-benefit
arsenic in drinking water. As legal scholar analysis also generally fails to achieve the
Cass Sunstein has recently argued, the goal of transparency. Cost-benefit analysis
available information on the benefits of is a complex, resource-intensive, and expert-
arsenic reduction supports estimates of net driven process. It requires a great deal of
benefits from regulation ranging from less time and effort to attempt to unpack even
than zero, up to $560 million or more. the simplest cost-benefit analysis. Few
The number of deaths avoided annually by community groups, for example, have
regulation is, according to Sunstein, between access to the kind of scientific and
20
0 and 112. A procedure that allows such an technical expertise that would allow
enormous range of different evaluations of a them to evaluate whether, intentionally
single rule is certainly not the objective, or unintentionally, the authors of a cost-
transparent decision rule that its benefit analysis have unfairly slighted the
advocates have advertised. interests of the community or some of its
members. Few members of the public can
These uncertainties arise both from the meaningfully participate in the debates
limited knowledge of the epidemiology about the use of particular regression
and toxicology of exposure to arsenic, analyses or discount rates which are
and from the controversial series of central to the cost-benefit method.
assumptions required for valuation and
discounting of costs and (particularly) The translation of lives, health, and
benefits. As Sunstein explains, a number nature into dollars also renders decision-
of different positions, including most of making about the underlying social values
those heard in the recent controversy over less rather than more transparent. As we
arsenic regulation, could be supported by have discussed, all of the various steps
21
one or another reading of the evidence. required to reduce a human life to a dollar
value are open to debate and subject to
Some analysts might respond that this uncertainty. However, the specific dollar
enormous range of outcomes is not possible values kicked out by cost-benefit analysis
if the proper economic assumptions are used; tend to obscure these underlying issues
if, for example, human lives are valued at rather than encourage full public debate
$6 million apiece and discounted at a about them.
5 percent yearly rate (or, depending on the
analyst, other favorite numbers). But these
assumptions beg fundamental questions
about ethics and equity, and one cannot
26
5. Why It Doesnt Work:
Practical Problems

T
he last section showed that there minute numbers but which have been
are deep, inherent problems with thoroughly evaluated in numerical terms.
cost-benefit analysis. In practice, But the formaldehyde regulation also
these problems only get worse; leading prevents many painful but nonfatal
examples of cost-benefit analysis fall far illnesses, excluded from the $72 billion
short of the theoretical model. The figure. If described solely as a means of
existence of these practical problems reducing cancer, the regulation would
further undercuts the utility and wisdom indeed be very expensive. But if described
of using cost-benefit analysis to evaluate as a means of reducing cancer and other
environmental policy. diseases, the regulation makes a good
deal of sense. Workplace regulation of
formaldehyde is not a bad answer, but it
The Limits of Quantification does happen to be an answer to a
Cost-benefit studies of regulations focus different question.
on quantified benefits of the proposed
action and generally ignore other, non- The formaldehyde case is by no means
quantified health and environmental unique: often the only regulatory benefit
benefits. This raises a serious problem that can be quantified is the prevention of
because many benefits of environmental cancer. Yet cancer has a latency period of
programs - including the prevention of between 5 and 40 years. When discounted
many nonfatal diseases and harms to the at 5 percent, a cancer death 40 years from
ecosystem - either have not been quantified now has a present value of only one-
or are not capable of being quantified at seventh of a death today. Thus, one
this time. Indeed, for many environmental of the benefits that can most often be
regulations, the only benefit that can be quantified allowing it to be folded into
quantified is the prevention of cancer cost-benefit analysis is also one that is
deaths. On the other hand, one can heavily discounted, making the benefits
virtually always come up with some number of preventive regulation seem trivial.
for the total costs of an environmental
regulation. Thus, in practice, cost-benefit
analysis tends to skew decision-making Ignoring What Cannot
against protecting public health and Be Counted
the environment.
A related practical problem is that, even
For example, regulation of workers exposure when the existence of unquantified or
to formaldehyde is often presented as the unquantifiable benefits is recognized, their
extreme of inefficiency, supposedly costing importance is frequently ignored. Many
$72 billion per life saved. This figure is advocates of cost-benefit analysis concede
based on the finding that the regulation that the decision-making process must
prevents cancers, which occur only in make some room for non-quantitative

27
considerations. Some environmental by the regulated industries themselves,
benefits have never been subjected to which have an obvious incentive to offer
rigorous economic evaluation. Other high estimates of costs as a way of warding
important considerations in environmental off new regulatory requirements.
protection - such as the fairness of the
distribution of environmental risks - One study found that costs estimated in
cannot be quantified and priced. Even if advance of regulation were more than
22

these factors cannot be quantified, they twice actual costs in 11 out of 12 cases.
are surely relevant. Another study found that advance cost
estimates were more than 25 percent
In practice, however, unquantified values higher than actual costs for 14 out of 28
are often forgotten, or even denigrated, once regulations; advance estimates were more
all the numbers have been crunched. No than 25 percent too low in only 3 of the
23
matter how many times the Environmental 28 cases. Before the 1990 Clean Air
Protection Agency, for example, says that Act Amendments took effect, industry
one of its rules will produce many benefits anticipated that the cost of sulfur
like the prevention of illness or the reduction under the amendments would
protection of ecosystems that cannot be be $1,500 per ton. In 2000, the actual
quantified, the non-quantitative aspects of cost was under $150 per ton.
its analyses are almost invariably ignored in
public discussions of its policies.
No matter how many times
When the Clinton Administrations EPA the Environmental Protection
proposed, for example, strengthening the
standard for arsenic in drinking water, it
Agency says that one of
cited many human illnesses that would be its rules will produce
prevented by the new standard but that many benefits like the
could not be expressed in numerical terms.
Subsequent public discussion of EPAs cost-
prevention of illness or the
benefit analysis of this standard, however, protection of ecosystems
inevitably referred only to EPAs numerical that cannot be quantified,
analysis and forgot about the cases of the non-quantitative aspects
avoided illness that could not be quantified.
of its analyses are almost
invariably ignored in public
Overstated Costs
discussions of its policies.
There is also a tendency, as a matter of
practice, to overestimate the costs of
regulations in advance of their Of course, not all cost-benefit analyses
implementation. This happens in overstate the actual costs of regulation.
part because regulations often encourage But given the technology-forcing character
new technologies and more efficient ways of environmental regulations, it is not
of doing business; these innovations reduce surprising to find a marked propensity to
the cost of compliance. It is also important overestimate the costs of such rules.
to keep in mind, when reviewing cost In a related vein, many companies have
estimates, that they are usually provided begun to discover that environmental
28
protection can actually be good for business in and expense of providing nursing home
some respects. Increased energy efficiency, care and other services associated with an
profitable products made from waste, and aging population.
decreased use of raw materials are just a
few of the cost-saving or even profit-making
results of turning more corporate attention Arthur D. Little found that
to environmentally protective business
24
smoking was a financial boon
practices. Cost-benefit analyses typically do for the Czech government
not take such money-saving possibilities into
account in evaluating the costs of regulation.
in part because it caused
citizens to die earlier and
Should We Laugh or Cry? thus reduced government
expenditure on pensions,
Each of these problems with cost-benefit
analysis as practiced the inability to
housing, and health care.
quantify all relevant values, the tendency
to ignore non-quantified benefits, and
the overstatement of compliance costs Viscusi didnt stop there. So great, under
describes, in a way, the trees rather than Viscusis assumptions, were the financial
the forest of cost-benefit analysis. It is also benefits to the states of their citizens
worthwhile to look at some of the products premature deaths that, he suggested,
of this method and ask, more generally, cigarette smoking should be subsidized rather
25

does the method make sense? than taxed.

Consider the following examples, which we Amazingly, this cynical conclusion has not
are not making up. They are not the work of been swept into the dustbin where it
a lunatic fringe, but on the contrary, they belongs, but instead has recently been
reflect the work products of some of the revived: the tobacco company Philip Morris
most influential and reputable of todays commissioned the well-known consulting
cost-benefit practitioners. We are not sure group Arthur D. Little to examine the
whether to laugh or cry; we find it impossible financial benefits, to the Czech Republic,
to treat these studies as serious contributions of smoking among Czech citizens.
to a rational discussion. Arthur D. Little found that smoking was
a financial boon for the government in
Several years ago, states were in the middle part because it caused citizens to die
of their litigation against tobacco companies, earlier and thus reduced government
seeking to recoup the medical expenditures expenditure on pensions, housing, and
26
they had incurred as a result of smoking. At health care. This conclusion relies, so
that time, W. Kip Viscusi a professor of law far as we can determine, on perfectly
and economics at Harvard and the primary conventional cost-benefit analysis.
source of the current $6.3 million estimate
for the value of a statistical life undertook There is more. In recent years, much
research concluding that states, in fact, saved has been learned about the special risks
money as the result of smoking by their children face due to pesticides in their food,
citizens. Why? Because they died early! contaminants in their drinking water, ozone
They thus saved their states the trouble in the air, and so on. As a result of the
29
increasing prominence of cost-benefit Why should environmental standards
analysis, there is now a budding industry in be based on what individuals are now
valuing childrens health. Its products are spending on desperate personal efforts to
often bizarre. overcome social problems?

Take the problem of lead poisoning in For sheer analytical audacity, Lutters study
children. One of the most serious and faces some stiff competition from another
disturbing effects of lead is the neurological study concerning children this one
damage it can cause in young children, concerning the value, not of childrens
including permanently lowered mental health, but of their lives. In this second
ability. Putting a dollar value on the study, researchers examined mothers car-
28
(avoidable, environmentally caused) seat fastening practices. They calculated
retardation of children is a daunting the difference between the time required
task, but economic analysts have not to fasten the seats correctly and the time
been daunted. mothers actually spent fastening their
children into their seats. Then they
Randall Lutter, a frequent regulatory critic assigned a monetary value to this interval
and a scholar at the AEI-Brookings Joint of time based on the mothers hourly wage
Center for Regulatory Studies, argues that rate (or, in the case of non-working moms,
the way to value the damage lead causes based on a guess at the wages they might
in children is to look at how much parents have earned). When mothers saved time
of affected children spend on chelation and, by hypothesis, money by fastening
therapy, a chemical treatment that is their childrens car seats incorrectly,
supposed to cause excretion of lead from they were, according to the researchers,
the body. Parental spending on chelation implicitly placing a finite monetary value
supports an estimated valuation of only on the life-threatening risks to their
about $1,500 per IQ point lost due to lead children posed by car accidents.
poisoning. Previous economic analyses by
EPA, based on the childrens loss of expected Building on this calculation, the researchers
future earnings, have estimated the value to were able to answer the vexing question
be much higher up to $9,000 per IQ point. of how much a statistical childs life is
Based on his lower figure, Lutter claims to worth to its mother. (As the mother of a
have discovered that too much effort is statistical child, she is naturally adept at
going into controlling lead: complex calculations comparing the value
of saving a few seconds versus the slightly
Hazard standards that protect children far more increased risk to her child!) The answer
than their parents think is appropriate may make parallels Lutters finding that we are
little sense. The agencies should consider relaxing valuing our children too highly: in car-seat-
27
their lead standards. land, a childs life is worth only $500,000.

In fact, Lutter presents no evidence about


what parents think, only about what they
spend on one rare variety of private medical
treatments (which, as it turns out, has not
been proven medically effective for chronic,
low-level lead poisoning).

30
6. The Many Alternatives to
Cost-Benefit Analysis

A
common response to the criticisms Over the years, EPA has learned that
of cost-benefit analysis is a simple flexibility is a good idea when it comes
question: whats the alternative? to technology-based regulation, and thus
The implication is that despite its flaws, has tended to avoid specifying particular
cost-benefit analysis is really the only technologies or processes for use by
tool we have for figuring out how much regulated firms; instead, the agency
environmental protection to provide. has increasingly relied on performance-
based regulation, which tells firms to
This is just not true. For thirty years, the clean up to a certain, specified extent,
federal government has been protecting but doesnt tell them precisely how to
human health and the environment without do it. Technology-based regulation
relying on cost-benefit analysis. The menu generally takes costs into account in
of regulatory options that has emerged determining the required level of
from this experience is large and varied. pollution control, but does not demand
Choosing among these possibilities depends the kind of precisely quantified and
on a variety of case-specific circumstances, monetized balancing process that is
such as the nature of the pollution involved, needed for cost-benefit analysis.
the degree of scientific knowledge about it,
and the conditions under which people are Another regulatory strategy that has gained
exposed to it. As the following brief sketch a large following in recent years is the use
of alternatives reveals, cost-benefit analysis - of pollution trading, as in the sulfur
a one-size-fits-all approach to regulation - dioxide emissions trading program created
just cant be squared with the multiplicity for power plants under the 1990 Clean Air
of circumstances surrounding different Act Amendments. That program grants
environmental problems. firms a limited number of permits for
pollution, but allows them to buy permits
For the most part, environmental programs from other firms. Thus firms with high
rely on a form of technology-based pollution control costs can save money
regulation, the essence of which is to by buying permits, while those with low
require the best available methods for control costs can save money by controlling
controlling pollution. This avoids the emissions and selling their permits.
massive research effort needed to quantify
and monetize the precise harms caused by The fixed supply of permits, created by
specific amounts of pollution, which is law, sets the cap on total emissions; the
required by cost-benefit analysis. In trading process allows industry to decide
contrast, the technology-based approach where and how it is most economical to
allows regulators to proceed directly to reduce emissions to fit under the cap.
controlling emissions. Simply put, the idea Trading programs have become an
is that we should do the best we can to important part of the federal program for
mitigate pollution we believe to be harmful. controlling pollution. These programs,

31
too, have not used cost-benefit analysis in The arguments for flexible technology-
their implementation. Congress, the EPA, based regulation and for incentive-based
or other officials set the emissions cap, and programs like pollution trading and
the market does the rest. disclosure requirements are sometimes
confused with the arguments for cost-
It is theoretically possible that cost-benefit benefit analysis. But both technology-
analysis could be used to choose the based and incentive-based regulation take
overall limit on pollution that guides both their goals from elected representatives
performance-based and market-based rather than from economic analysts,
regulatory programs. However, this has even though the means adopted by
not been standard practice in the past; these regulatory strategies are strongly
the limit on sulfur emissions in the 1990 influenced by attention to costs. The
Clean Air Act Amendments, for example, current style of cost-benefit analysis,
was set by a process of political compromise. however, purports to set the ends, not
Given the problems with cost-benefit just the means, of environmental policy,
analysis, political compromise cannot be and that is where its aspirations amount
viewed as an inferior way to set a cap on to arrogance.
emissions. Many regulatory programs have
been a terrific success without using cost- Economic analysis has had its successes
benefit analysis to set pollution limits. and made its contributions; it has taught
us a great deal over the years about how
One last example (a desire for reasonable we can most efficiently and cheaply reach
brevity prevents us from listing more) is a given environmental goal. It has taught
informational regulation, which requires us relatively little, however, about what
disclosures to the public and/or to our environmental goals should be.
consumers about risks they face from Indeed, while economists have spent
exposures to chemicals. These right-to- three decades wrangling about how
know regimes allow citizens and consumers much a human life, or a bald eagle, or
not only to know about the risks they face, a beautiful stretch of river, is worth in
but also empower them to do something dollars, ecologists, engineers, and other
about those risks. The Toxic Release specialists have gone about the business
Inventory created by the Emergency of saving lives and eagles and rivers,
Planning and Community Right-to-Know without waiting for formal, quantitative
Act, the product warning labels required analysis proving that saving these things
by Californias Proposition 65, and the is worthwhile.
consumer notices now required regarding
drinking water that contains hazardous
chemicals, are all variants of this type of
information-based regulation. Not one of
these popular and effective programs relies
on cost-benefit analysis.

32
7. Conclusion
wo features of cost-benefit analysis
While economists
have spent three decades
wrangling about how much
T distinguish it from other approaches
to evaluating the advantages and
disadvantages of environmentally protective
regulations: the translation of lives, health,
a human life, or a bald eagle, and the natural environment into monetary
or a beautiful stretch of river, terms, and the discounting of harms to
human health and the environment that
is worth in dollars, ecologists, are expected to occur in the future.
engineers, and other These features of cost-benefit analysis
specialists have gone about make it a terrible way to make decisions
about environmental protection, for both
the business of saving lives intrinsic and practical reasons.
and eagles and rivers,
Nor is it useful to keep cost-benefit analysis
without waiting for formal, around as a kind of regulatory tag-along,
quantitative analysis providing information that regulators may
proving that saving these find interesting even if not decisive.
things is worthwhile. Cost-benefit analysis is exceedingly time-
and resource-intensive, and its flaws are so
deep and so large that this time and these
resources are wasted on it. Moreover, given
the intrinsic conflict between cost-benefit
analysis and the principles of fairness that
animate, or should animate, our national
policy toward protecting people from being
hurt by other people, the results of cost-
benefit analysis cannot simply be given
some weight along with other factors
without undermining the fundamental
equality of all citizens rich and poor,
young and old, healthy and sick.

Cost-benefit analysis cannot overcome its


fatal flaw: it is completely reliant on the
impossible attempt to price the priceless
values of life, health, nature, and the future.
Better public policy decisions can be made
without cost-benefit analysis, by combining
the successes of traditional regulation
with the best of the innovative and flexible
approaches that have gained ground in
recent years.
33
Footnotes 6. John Broome, Trying to Value a
Life, 9 J. Pub. Econ. 91, 92 (1978).
1. John B. Loomis and Douglas S. White,
Economic Benefits of Rare and 7. E.g., Elizabeth Anderson, Value in
Endangered Species: Summary and Ethics and Economics (Harvard University
Meta-analysis, 18 Ecological Economics 197, Press, 1993).
199 Table 1(1996) (converted to year 2000
dollars using the consumer price index). 8. For further elaboration, see Lisa
Heinzerling, The Rights of Statistical
2. The original calculation, based on People, 24 Harv. Envtl. L. Rev. 189,
research by W. Kip Viscusi, can be found in 203-06 (2000).
EPA, The Benefits and Costs of the Clean Air Act,
1970 to 1990, Appendix I (1997). For 9. Economic Analysis of Federal
an example of a subsequent analysis citing Regulations Under Executive Order 12,
the Clean Air Act analysis and adjusting only 866, at pt. III.B.5(a) (Report of
for inflation, see EPA, Arsenic in Drinking Interagency Group Chaired by a Member
Water Rule: Economic Analysis, EPA Document of the Council of Economic Advisors)
815-R-00-026, 5-23 (December 2000). The (Jan. 11, 1996).
arsenic study used $6.1 million in 1999
10. Lisa Heinzerling, Discounting Our
dollars, which is equivalent to $6.3 million
Future, 34 Land & Water L. Rev. 39, 71
in 2000 dollars.
(1999); Lisa Heinzerling, Discounting
3. The examples in the text are rounded off Life, 108 Yale L.J. 1911, 1913 (1999).
to the nearest dollar.
11. Mark Sagoff, The Economy of the Earth:
4. See, for example, John F. Morrall III, Philosophy, Law, and the Environment 50-52
A Review of the Record, Regulation, (Cambridge University Press, 1988).
Nov./Dec. 1986, at 25, 30 Table 4, relied
12. Amartya Sen, The Discipline of
upon in, among others, Stephen Breyer,
Cost-Benefit Analysis, 29 Journal of Legal
Breaking the Vicious Circle: Toward Effective
Studies 931-952 (June 2000).
Risk Regulation 24-27 (1993); W. Kip Viscusi,
Fatal Tradeoffs: Public and Private 13. Henry S. Richardson, The Stupidity
Responsibilities for Risk 264 (1992); OMB, of the Cost-Benefit Standard, 29 Journal
Regulatory Program of the United States of Legal Studies 971-1003 (2000). On the
Government, April 1, 1991-March 31, importance of allowing preference change
1992, at 12 (1991) (reproducing version of in response to deliberation, see also
Morralls table); Kenneth J. Arrow et al., Cass R. Sunstein, Preferences and
Is There a Role for Benefit-Cost Analysis Politics, 1 Philosophy and Public Affairs
in Environmental, Health, and Safety 20 (1991).
Regulation?, 272 Science 221 (April 1996).
14. 42 U.S.C. 4331(b)(1).
5. Risk Assessment and Cost-benefit Analysis:
Hearings Before the Comm. on Science, United 15. William J. Baumol, On the Social
States House of Representatives, 104th Cong., Rate of Discount, 58 Am. Econ. Rev.
1st Sess. 1124 (1995) (written testimony of 788, 801 (1968).
John D. Graham).

34
16. This discussion is based on Lisa 22. Eban Goodstein, Polluted Data,
Heinzerling, Regulatory Costs of Mythic American Prospect 8, November-December
Proportions, 107 Yale L.J. 1981 (1998), and 1997 (http://www.prospect.org); Hart
on Lisa Heinzerlings written testimony on Hodges, Falling Prices: Cost of
John Grahams nomination to be head of Complying With Environmental
OIRA: Nomination of John D. Graham as Admr Regulations Almost Always Less
of the Office of Info. and Regulatory Affairs at the Than Advertised, Economic Policy
Office of Mgmt. and Budget: Hearing Before the Institute, 1997 (http://epinet.org). Both
Comm. on Governmental Affairs, U.S. Senate publications report on the same study.
107th Cong. 1st Sess. (2001).
23. Winston Harrington, Richard D.
17. Available at http://www.whirledbank. Morgenstern, and Peter Nelson, On the
org/ourwords/summers.html. Accuracy of Regulatory Cost Estimates,
19 Journal of Policy Analysis and Management
18. Available at http://www.whirledbank. 297-322 (Spring 2000).
org/ourwords/summers.html.
24. For a recent report on this
19. Fred Kuchler and Elise Golan, Assigning phenomenon, see Claudia H. Deutsch,
Values to Life: Comparing Methods for Together at Last: Cutting Pollution
Valuing Health Risks, Economic Research and Making Money, The New York Times
Service, U.S. Department of Agriculture, (Sept. 9, 2001).
Agricultural Economic Report No. 784,
52 (1999). 25. W. Kip Viscusi, Cigarette Taxation
and the Social Consequences of Smoking,
20. Cass R. Sunstein, The Arithmetic of Working Paper No. 4891, 33 (National
Arsenic, AEI-Brookings Joint Center for Bureau of Economic Research
Regulatory Studies, Working Paper 01-10, October 1994).
(August 2001).
26. Public Finance Balance of Smoking
21. Given this enormous range of in the Czech Republic, available at
uncertainty, it is hard to understand http://europe.com/2001/BUSINESS/
Sunsteins belief (expressed in the same 07/16/czech.morris./index.html.
working paper) that cost-benefit analysis is
still useful for screening regulatory options. 27. Randall Lutter, Valuing Childrens
This could only be true if a significant Health: A Reassessment of the Benefits
number of serious proposals had costs that of Lower Lead Levels, AEI-Brookings
were many orders of magnitude greater than Joint Center for Regulatory Studies
their benefits. As we have discussed, this is Working Paper 00-02, at 3 (March 2000).
a widely held, but empirically false, view of
environmental regulation. 28. Paul S. Carlin and Robert Sandy,
Estimating the Implicit Value of a Young
Childs Life, 58 So. Econ. J. 186 (1991).

35
Georgetown Environmental Law and Policy Institute
Georgetown University Law Center

The Georgetown Environmental Law and Policy Institute


conducts research and education on legal and policy
issues relating to protection of the environment
and conservation of natural resources.

For additional copies please contact:


Georgetown Environmental Law and Policy Institute
Georgetown University Law Center
600 New Jersey Avenue, N.W.
Washington, D.C. 20001
(202) 662-9850
fax (202) 662-9005
gelpi@law.georgetown.edu

PRINTED ON RECYCLED PAPER

Potrebbero piacerti anche