Sei sulla pagina 1di 20

law.

The most important architects of this revised positivism are the


Legal Positivism Austrian jurist Hans Kelsen (1881-1973) and the two dominating figures in
the analytic philosophy of law, H.L.A. Hart (1907-92) and Joseph Raz among
First published Fri Jan 3, 2003 whom there are clear lines of influence, but also important contrasts. Legal
positivism's importance, however, is not confined to the philosophy of law. It
Legal positivism is the thesis that the existence and content of law depends can be seen throughout social theory, particularly in the works of Marx,
on social facts and not on its merits. The English jurist John Austin (1790- Weber, and Durkheim, and also (though here unwittingly) among many
1859) formulated it thus: The existence of law is one thing; its merit and lawyers, including the American legal realists and most contemporary
demerit another. Whether it be or be not is one enquiry; whether it be or be feminist scholars. Although they disagree on many other points, these
not conformable to an assumed standard, is a different enquiry. (1832, p. writers all acknowledge that law is essentially a matter of social fact.
157) The positivist thesis does not say that law's merits are unintelligible, Some of them are, it is true, uncomfortable with the label legal positivism
unimportant, or peripheral to the philosophy of law. It says that they do not and therefore hope to escape it. Their discomfort is sometimes the product of
determine whether laws or legal systems exist. Whether a society has a legal confusion. Lawyers often use positivist abusively, to condemn a formalistic
system depends on the presence of certain structures of governance, not on doctrine according to which law is always clear and, however pointless or
the extent to which it satisfies ideals of justice, democracy, or the rule of law. wrong, is to be rigorously applied by officials and obeyed by subjects. It is
What laws are in force in that system depends on what social standards its doubtful that anyone ever held this view; but it is in any case false, it has
officials recognize as authoritative; for example, legislative enactments, nothing to do with legal positivism, and it is expressly rejected by all leading
judicial decisions, or social customs. The fact that a policy would be just, positivists. Among the philosophically literate another, more intelligible,
wise, efficient, or prudent is never sufficient reason for thinking that it is misunderstanding may interfere. Legal positivism is here sometimes
actually the law, and the fact that it is unjust, unwise, inefficient or associated with the homonymic but independent doctrines of logical
imprudent is never sufficient reason for doubting it. According to positivism, positivism (the meaning of a sentence is its mode of verification) or
law is a matter of what has been posited (ordered, decided, practiced, sociological positivism (social phenomena can be studied only through the
tolerated, etc.); as we might say in a more modern idiom, positivism is the methods of natural science). While there are historical connections, and also
view that law is a social construction. Austin thought the thesis simple and commonalities of temper, among these ideas, they are essentially different.
glaring. While it is probably the dominant view among analytically inclined The view that the existence of law depends on social facts does not rest on a
philosophers of law, it is also the subject of competing interpretations particular semantic thesis, and it is compatible with a range of theories about
together with persistent criticisms and misunderstandings. how one investigates social facts, including non-naturalistic accounts. To say
that the existence of law depends on facts and not on its merits is a thesis
about the relation among laws, facts, and merits, and not otherwise a thesis
1. Development and Influence about the individual relata. Hence, most traditional natural law moral
doctrines--including the belief in a universal, objective morality grounded in
Legal positivism has a long history and a broad influence. It has antecedents human nature--do not contradict legal positivism. The only influential
in ancient political philosophy and is discussed, and the term itself positivist moral theories are the views that moral norms are valid only if they
introduced, in mediaeval legal and political thought (see Finnis 1996). The have a source in divine commands or in social conventions. Such theists and
modern doctrine, however, owes little to these forbears. Its most important relativists apply to morality the constraints that legal positivists think hold
roots lie in the conventionalist political philosophies of Hobbes and Hume, for law.
and its first full elaboration is due to Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) whose
account Austin adopted, modified, and popularized. For much of the next 2. The Existence and Sources of Law
century an amalgam of their views, according to which law is the command
of a sovereign backed by force, dominated legal positivism and English Every human society has some form of social order, some way of marking
philosophical reflection about law. By the mid-twentieth century, however, and encouraging approved behavior, deterring disapproved behavior, and
this account had lost its influence among working legal philosophers. Its resolving disputes. What then is distinctive of societies with legal systems
emphasis on legislative institutions was replaced by a focus on law-applying and, within those societies, of their law? Before exploring some positivist
institutions such as courts, and its insistence of the role of coercive force answers, it bears emphasizing that these are not the only questions worth
gave way to theories emphasizing the systematic and normative character of asking. While an understanding of the nature of law requires an account of
what makes law distinctive, it also requires an understanding of what it coincidental compliance we need something like the idea of subjects being
has in common with other forms of social control. Some Marxists are oriented to, or guided by, the commands. Explicating this will carry us far
positivists about the nature of law while insisting that its distinguishing from the power-based notions with which classical positivism hoped to work.
characteristics matter less than its role in replicating and facilitating other The imperativalists' account of obligation is also subject to decisive
forms of domination. (Though other Marxists disagree: see Pashukanis). objections (Hart, 1994, pp. 26-78; and Hacker). Treating all laws as
They think that the specific nature of law casts little light on their primary commands conceals important differences in their social functions, in the
concerns. But one can hardly know that in advance; it depends on what the ways they operate in practical reasoning, and in the sort of justifications to
nature of law actually is. which they are liable. For instance, laws conferring the power to marry
command nothing; they do not obligate people to marry, or even to marry
According to Bentham and Austin, law is a phenomenon of large according to the prescribed formalities. Nor is reductivism any more
societies with a sovereign: a determinate person or group who have supreme plausible here: we speak of legal obligations when there is no probability of
and absolute de facto power -- they are obeyed by all or most others but do sanctions being applied and when there is no provision for sanctions (as in
not themselves similarly obey anyone else. The laws in that society are a the duty of the highest courts to apply the law). Moreover, we take the
subset of the sovereign's commands: general orders that apply to classes of existence of legal obligations to be a reason for imposing sanctions, not
actions and people and that are backed up by threat of force or sanction. merely a consequence of it.
This imperatival theory is positivist, for it identifies the existence of
legal systems with patterns of command and obedience that can Hans Kelsen retains the imperativalists' monism but abandons their
be ascertained without considering whether the sovereign has a reductivism. On his view, law is characterized by a basic form and basic
moral right to rule or whether his commands are meritorious. It norm. The form of every law is that of a conditional order, directed at the
has two other distinctive features. The theory is monistic: it represents courts, to apply sanctions if a certain behavior (the delict) is performed. On
all laws as having a single form, imposing obligations on their subjects, this view, law is an indirect system of guidance: it does not tell subjects what
though not on the sovereign himself. The imperativalist acknowledges that to do; it tells officials what to do to its subjects under certain conditions.
ultimate legislative power may be self-limiting, or limited externally by what Thus, what we ordinarily regard as the legal duty not to steal is for Kelsen
public opinion will tolerate, and also that legal systems contain provisions merely a logical correlate of the primary norm which stipulates a sanction for
that are not imperatives (for example, permissions, definitions, and so on). stealing (1945, p. 61). The objections to imperatival monism apply also to
But they regard these as part of the non-legal material that is necessary for, this more sophisticated version: the reduction misses important facts, such
and part of, every legal system. (Austin is a bit more liberal on this point). as the point of having a prohibition on theft. (The courts are not indifferent
The theory is also reductivist, for it maintains that the normative language between, on the one hand, people not stealing and, on the other, stealing and
used in describing and stating the law -- talk of authority, rights, obligations, suffering the sanctions.) But in one respect the conditional sanction theory is
and so on -- can all be analyzed without remainder in non-normative terms, in worse shape than is imperativalism, for it has no principled way to fix on
ultimately as concatenations of statements about power and obedience. the delict as the duty-defining condition of the sanction -- that is but one of a
large number of relevant antecedent conditions, including the legal capacity
Imperatival theories are now without influence in legal philosophy (but see of the offender, the jurisdiction of the judge, the constitutionality of the
Ladenson and Morison). What survives of their outlook is the idea that legal offense, and so forth. Which among all these is the content of a legal duty?
theory must ultimately be rooted in some account of the political system, an
insight that came to be shared by all major positivists save Kelsen. Their Kelsen's most important contribution lies in his attack on reductivism and
particular conception of a society under a sovereign commander, however, is his doctrine of the basic norm. He maintains that law is normative and
friendless (except among Foucauldians, who strangely take this relic as the must understood as such. Might does not make right -- not even legal right --
ideal-type of what they call juridical power). It is clear that in complex so the philosophy of law must explain the fact that law is taken to impose
societies there may be no one who has all the attributes of sovereignty, for obligations on its subjects. Moreover, law is a normative system: Law
ultimate authority may be divided among organs and may itself be limited by is not, as it is sometimes said, a rule. It is a set of rules having the
law. Moreover, even when sovereignty is not being used in its legal sense it kind of unity we understand by a system (1945, p. 3). For the
is nonetheless a normative concept. A legislator is one who has authority to imperativalists, the unity of a legal system consists in the fact that all its laws
make laws, and not merely someone with great social power, and it is are commanded by one sovereign. For Kelsen, it consists in the fact that they
doubtful that habits of obedience is a candidate reduction for explaining are all links in one chain of authority. For example, a by-law is legally valid
authority. Obedience is a normative concept. To distinguish it from because it is created by a corporation lawfully exercising the powers
conferred on it by the legislature, which confers those powers in a manner in arguments about what standards they are bound to apply. Hart's account
provided by the constitution, which was itself created in a way provided by is therefore conventionalist (see Marmor, and Coleman, 2001): ultimate
an earlier constitution. But what about the very first constitution, historically legal rules are social norms, although they are neither the product of express
speaking? Its authority, says Kelsen, is presupposed. The condition for agreement nor even conventions in the Schelling-Lewis sense (see Green
interpreting any legal norm as binding is that the first constitution is 1999). Thus for Hart too the legal system is norms all the way down, but at
validated by the following basic norm: the original constitution is to be its root is a social norm that has the kind of normative force that customs
obeyed. Now, the basic norm cannot be a legal norm -- we cannot fully have. It is a regularity of behavior towards which officials take the internal
explain the bindingness of law by reference to more law. Nor can it be a point of view: they use it as a standard for guiding and evaluating their own
social fact, for Kelsen maintains that the reason for the validity of a norm and others' behavior, and this use is displayed in their conduct and speech,
must always be another norm -- no ought from is. It follows, then, that a including the resort to various forms of social pressure to support the rule
legal system must consist of norms all the way down. It bottoms in a and the ready application of normative terms such as duty and obligation
hypothetical, transcendental norm that is the condition of the intelligibility when invoking it.
of any (and all) other norms as binding. To presuppose this basic norm is
not to endorse it as good or just -- resupposition is a cognitive stance only -- It is an important feature of Hart's account that the rule of recognition is
but it is, Kelsen thinks, the necessary precondition for a non-reductivist an official custom, and not a standard necessarily shared by the broader
account of law as a normative system. community. If the imperativalists' picture of the political system was
pyramidal power, Hart's is more like Weber's rational bureaucracy. Law is
There are many difficulties with this, not least of which is the fact that if we normally a technical enterprise, characterized by a division of labour.
are willing to tolerate the basic norm as a solution it is not clear why we Ordinary subjects' contribution to the existence of law may therefore amount
thought there was a problem in the first place. One cannot say both that the to no more than passive compliance. Thus, Hart's necessary and
basic norm is the norm presupposing which validates all inferior norms and sufficient conditions for the existence of a legal system are that
also that an inferior norm is part of the legal system only if it is connected by those rules of behavior which are valid according to the system's ultimate
a chain of validity to the basic norm. We need a way into the circle. criteria of validity must be generally obeyed, and ... its rules of recognition
Moreover, it draws the boundaries of legal systems incorrectly. The Canadian specifying the criteria of legal validity and its rules of change and
Constitution of 1982 was lawfully created by an Act of the U.K. Parliament, adjudication must be effectively accepted as common public standards of
and on that basis Canadian law and English law should be parts of a single official behavior by its officials (1994, p. 116). And this division of labour is
legal system, rooted in one basic norm: The (first) U.K. constitution is to be not a normatively neutral fact about law; it is politically charged, for it sets
obeyed. Yet no English law is binding in Canada, and a purported repeal of up the possibility of law becoming remote from the life of a society, a hazard
the Constitution Act by the U.K. would be without legal effect in Canada. to which Hart is acutely alert (1994, p. 117; cf. Waldron).
If law cannot ultimately be grounded in force, or in law, or in a presupposed Although Hart introduces the rule of recognition through a speculative
norm, on what does its authority rest? The most influential solution is now anthropology of how it might emerge in response to certain deficiencies in a
H.L.A. Hart's. His solution resembles Kelsen's in its emphasis on the customary social order, he is not committed to the view that law is a cultural
normative foundations of legal systems, but Hart rejects Kelsen's achievement. To the contrary, the idea that legal order is always a good
transcendentalist, Kantian view of authority in favour of an empirical, thing, and that societies without it are deficient, is a familiar element of
Weberian one. For Hart, the authority of law is social. The ultimate many anti-positivist views, beginning with Henry Maine's criticism of Austin
criterion of validity in a legal system is neither a legal norm nor a on the ground that his theory would not apply to certain Indian villages. The
presupposed norm, but a social rule that exists only because it is objection embraces the error it seeks to avoid. It imperialistically assumes
actually practiced. Law ultimately rests on custom: customs about who shall that it is always a bad thing to lack law, and then makes a dazzling inference
have the authority to decide disputes, what they shall treat as binding from ought to is: if it is good to have law, then each society must have it, and
reasons for decision, i.e. as sources of law, and how customs may be the concept of law must be adjusted to show that it does. If one thinks that
changed. Of these three secondary rules, as Hart calls them, the law is a many splendored thing, one will be tempted by a very wide concept
source-determining rule of recognition is most important, for it of law, for it would seem improper to charge others with missing out.
specifies the ultimate criteria of validity in the legal system. It exists only Positivism simply releases the harness. Law is a distinctive form of political
because it is practiced by officials, and it is not only the recognition rule (or order, not a moral achievement, and whether it is necessary or even useful
rules) that best explains their practice, it is rule to which they actually appeal
depends entirely on its content and context. Societies without law may be The most influential criticisms of legal positivism all flow, in one way or
perfectly adapted to their environments, missing nothing. another, from the suspicion that it fails to give morality its due. A
theory that insists on the facticity of law seems to contribute little to our
A positivist account of the existence and content of law, along any of the understanding that law has important functions in making human life go
above lines, offers a theory of the validity of law in one of the two main well, that the rule of law is a prized ideal, and that the language and practice
senses of that term (see Harris, pp. 107-111). Kelsen says that validity is of law is highly moralized. Accordingly, positivism's critics maintain that the
the specific mode of existence of a norm. An invalid marriage is not a most important features of law are not to be found in its source-based
special kind of marriage having the property of invalidity; it is not a marriage character, but in law's capacity to advance the common good, to
at all. In this sense a valid law is one that is systemically valid in secure human rights, or to govern with integrity. (It is a curious
the jurisdiction -- it is part of the legal system. This is the question fact about anti-positivist theories that, while they all insist on the moral
that positivists answer by reference to social sources. It is distinct from the nature of law, without exception they take its moral nature to be something
idea of validity as moral propriety, i.e. a sound justification for respecting the good. The idea that law might of its very nature be morally problematic does
norm. For the positivist, this depends on its merits. One indication that not seem to have occurred to them.)
these senses differ is that one may know that a society has a legal
system, and know what its laws are, without having any idea It is beyond doubt that moral and political considerations bear on legal
whether they are morally justified. For example, one may know that philosophy. As Finnis says, the reasons we have for establishing, maintaining
the law of ancient Athens included the punishment of ostracism without or reforming law include moral reasons, and these reasons therefore shape
knowing whether it was justified, because one does not know enough about our legal concepts (p. 204). But which concepts? Once one concedes, as
its effects, about the social context, and so forth. Finnis does, that the existence and content of law can be identified without
recourse to moral argument, and that human law is artefact and
No legal positivist argues that the systemic validity of law establishes artifice; and not a conclusion from moral premises, (p. 205) the
its moral validity, i.e. that it should be obeyed by subjects or applied by Thomistic apparatus he tries to resuscitate is largely irrelevant to the truth of
judges. Even Hobbes, to whom this view is sometimes ascribed, required that legal positivism. This vitiates also Lon Fuller's criticisms of Hart (Fuller,
law actually be able to keep the peace, failing which we owe it nothing. 1958 and 1969). Apart from some confused claims about adjudication, Fuller
Bentham and Austin, as utilitarians, hold that such questions always has two main points. First, he thinks that it isn't enough for a legal system to
turn on the consequences and both acknowledge that disobedience is rest on customary social rules, since law could not guide behavior without
therefore sometimes fully justified. Kelsen insists that The science of law also being at least minimally clear, consistent, public, prospective and so on -
does not prescribe that one ought to obey the commands of the creator of the - that is, without exhibiting to some degree those virtues collectively called
constitution (1967, p. 204). Hart thinks that there is only a prima the rule of law. It suffices to note that this is perfectly consistent with law
facie duty to obey, grounded in and thus limited by fairness -- so being source-based. Even if moral properties were identical with, or
there is no obligation to unfair or pointless laws (Hart 1955). Raz supervened upon, these rule-of-law properties, they do so in virtue
goes further still, arguing that there isn't even a prima facie duty of their rule-like character, and not their law-like character.
to obey the law, not even in a just state (Raz 1979, pp. 233-49). The Whatever virtues inhere in or follow from clear, consistent, prospective, and
peculiar accusation that positivists believe the law is always to be obeyed is open practices can be found not only in law but in all other social practices
without foundation. Hart's own view is that an overweening deference to law with those features, including custom and positive morality. And these
consorts more easily with theories that imbue it with moral ideals, virtues are minor: there is little to be said in favour of a clear, consistent,
permitting an enormous overvaluation of the importance of the bare fact prospective, public and impartially administered system of racial
that a rule may be said to be a valid rule of law, as if this, once declared, was segregation, for example. Fuller's second worry is that if law is a matter of
conclusive of the final moral question: Ought this law to be obeyed? (Hart fact, then we are without an explanation of the duty to obey. He gloatingly
1958, p. 75). asks how an amoral datum called law could have the peculiar quality of
Prima Facie- based on the first impression; accepted as correct until creating an obligation to obey it (Fuller, 1958). One possibility he neglects is
proved otherwise. that it doesn't. The fact that law claims to obligate is, of course, a different
matter and is susceptible to other explanations (Green 2001). But even if
3. Moral Principles and the Boundaries of Law Fuller is right in his unargued assumption, the peculiar quality whose
existence he doubts is a familiar feature of many moral practices. Compare
promises: whether a society has a practice of promising, and what someone
has promised to do, are matters of social fact. Yet promising creates moral ponensholds in court as much as outside, but not because it was enacted by
obligations of performance or compensation. An amoral datum may indeed the legislature or decided by the judges, and the fact that there is no social
figure, together with other premises, in a sound argument to moral rule that validates both modus ponens and also the Municipalities Act is true
conclusions. but irrelevant. The authority of principles of logic (or morality) is not
something to be explained by legal philosophy; the authority of acts of
While Finnis and Fuller's views are thus compatible with the positivist thesis, Parliament must be; and accounting for the difference is a central task of the
the same cannot be said of Ronald Dworkin's important works philosophy of law.
(Dworkin 1978 and 1986). Positivism's most significant critic rejects the
theory on every conceivable level. He denies that there can be any general Other positivists respond differently to Dworkin's phenomenological points,
theory of the existence and content of law; he denies that local theories of accepting their relevance but modifying the theory to accommodate them.
particular legal systems can identify law without recourse to its merits, and So-called inclusive positivists (e.g., Waluchow (to whom the term is due),
he rejects the whole institutional focus of positivism. A theory of law is for Coleman, Soper and Lyons) argue that the merit-based considerations may
Dworkin a theory of how cases ought to be decided and it begins, not with an indeed be part of the law, if they are explicitly or implicitly made so by
account of political organization, but with an abstract ideal regulating the source-based considerations. For example, Canada's constitution explicitly
conditions under which governments may use coercive force over their authorizes for breach of Charter rights, such remedy as the court considers
subjects. Force must only be deployed, he claims, in accordance with appropriate and just in the circumstances. In determining which remedies
principles laid down in advance. A society has a legal system only when, and might be legally valid, judges are thus expressly told to take into account
to the extent that, it honors this ideal, and its law is the set of all their morality. And judges may develop a settled practice of doing this
considerations that the courts of such a society would be morally justified in whether or not it is required by any enactment; it may become customary
applying, whether or not those considerations are determined by any source. practice in certain types of cases. Reference to moral principles may also be
To identify the law of a given society we must engage in moral and political implicit in the web of judge-made law, for instance in the common law
argument, for the law is whatever requirements are consistent with an principle that no one should profit from his own wrongdoing. Such moral
interpretation of its legal practices (subject to a threshold condition of fit) considerations, inclusivists claim, are part of the law because the sources
that shows them to be best justified in light of the animating ideal. In make it so, and thus Dworkin is right that the existence and content of law
addition to those philosophical considerations, Dworkin invokes two features turns on its merits, and wrong only in his explanation of this fact. Legal
of the phenomenology of judging, as he sees it. He finds validity depends on morality, not because of the interpretative consequences
deep controversy among lawyers and judges about how important cases of some ideal about how the government may use force, but because that is
should be decided, and he finds diversity in the considerations that they hold one of the things that may be customarily recognized as an ultimate
relevant to deciding them. The controversy suggests to him that law cannot determinant of legal validity. It is the sources that make the merits relevant.
rest on an official consensus, and the diversity suggests that there is no single
social rule that validates all relevant reasons, moral and non-moral, for To understand and assess this response, some preliminary clarifications are
judicial decisions. needed. First, it is not plausible to hold that the merits are relevant to a
judicial decision only when the sources make it so. It would be odd to think
Dworkin's rich and complex arguments have attracted various lines of reply that justice is a reason for decision only because some source directs an
from positivists. One response denies the relevance of the phenomenological official to decide justly. It is of the nature of justice that it properly bears on
claims. Controversy is a matter of degree, and a consensus-defeating amount certain controversies. In legal decisions, especially important ones, moral
of it is not proved by the existence of adversarial argument in the high and political considerations are present of their own authority; they do not
courts, or indeed in any courts. As important is the broad range of settled law need sources to propel them into action. On the contrary, we expect to see a
that gives rise to few doubts and which guides social life outside the sourcea statute, a decision, or a conventionwhen judges are
courtroom. As for the diversity argument, so far from being a refutation of constrained not to appeal directly to the merits. Second, the fact that there is
positivism, this is an entailment of it. Positivism identifies law, not with all moral language in judicial decisions does not establish the presence of moral
valid reasons for decision, but only with the source-based subset of them. It tests for law, for sources come in various guises. What sounds like moral
is no part of the positivist claim that the rule of recognition tells us how to reasoning in the courts is sometimes really source-based reasoning. For
decide cases, or even tells us all the relevant reasons for decision. Positivists example, when the Supreme Court of Canada says that a publication is
accept that moral, political or economic considerations are properly criminally obscene only if it is harmful, it is not applying J.S. Mill's harm
operative in some legal decisions, just as linguistic or logical ones are. Modus principle, for what that court means by harmful is that it is regarded by the
community as degrading or intolerable. Those are source-based matters, not for rejecting a strict doctrine of separation of powers -- Austin called it a
moral ones. This is just one of many appeals to positive morality, i.e. to the childish fiction -- according to which judges only apply and never make the
moral customs actually practiced by a given society, and no one denies that law, and with it any literal interpretation of Dworkin's ideal that coercion be
positive morality may be a source of law. Moreover, it is important to deployed only according to principles laid down in advance.
remember that law is dynamic and that even a decision that does apply
morality itself becomes a source of law, in the first instance for the parties It has to be said, however, that Hart himself does not consistently view legal
and possibly for others as well. Over time, by the doctrine of precedent where references to morality as marking a zone of discretion. In a passing remark
it exists or through the gradual emergence of an interpretative convention in the first edition of The Concept of Law, he writes, In some legal systems,
where it does not, this gives a factual edge to normative terms. Thus, if a as in the United States, the ultimate criteria of legal validity explicitly
court decides that money damages are in some instances not a just remedy incorporate principles of justice or substantive moral values (1994, p.
then this fact will join with others in fixing what justice means for these 204). This thought sits uneasily with other doctrines of importance to his
purposes. This process may ultimately detach legal concepts from their theory. For Hart also says that when judges exercise moral
moral analogs (thus, legal murder may require no intention to kill, legal judgment in the penumbra of legal rules to suppose that their
fault no moral blameworthiness, an equitable remedy may be manifestly results were already part of existing law is in effect,
unfair, etc.) an invitation to revise our concept of what a legal rule is (1958,
p. 72). The concept of a legal rule, that is, does not include all correctly
Bearing in mind these complications, however, there undeniably remains a reasoned elaborations or determinations of that rule. Later, however, Hart
great deal of moral reasoning in adjudication. Courts are often called on to comes to see his remark about the U.S. constitution as foreshadowing
decide what would reasonable, fair, just, cruel, etc. by explicit or implicit inclusive positivism (soft positivism, as he calls it). Hart's reasons for this
requirement of statute or common law, or because this is the only proper or shift are obscure (Green 1996). He remained clear about how we should
intelligible way to decide. Hart sees this as happening pre-eminently in hard understand ordinary statutory interpretation, for instance, where the
cases in which, owing to the indeterminacy of legal rules or conflicts among legislature has directed that an applicant should have a reasonable time or
them, judges are left with the discretion to make new law. Discretion, that a regulator may permit only a fair price: these grant a bounded
however, may be a potentially misleading term here. First, discretionary discretion to decide the cases on their merits. Why then does Hart -- and
judgments are not arbitrary: they are guided by merit-based considerations, even more insistently, Waluchow and Coleman -- come to regard
and they may also be guided by law even though not fully determined by it -- constitutional adjudication differently? Is there any reason to think that a
judges may be empowered to make certain decisions and yet under a legal constitution permitting only a just remedy requires a different analysis
duty to make them in a particular way, say, in conformity with the spirit of than a statute permitting only a fair rate?
preexisting law or with certain moral principles (Raz 1994, pp. 238-53).
Second, Hart's account might wrongly be taken to suggest that there are One might hazard the following guess. Some of these philosophers think that
fundamentally two kinds of cases, easy ones and hard ones, distinguished by constitutional law expresses the ultimate criteria of legal validity: because
the sorts of reasoning appropriate to each. A more perspicuous way of unjust remedies are constitutionally invalid and void ab initio, legally
putting it would be to say that there are two kinds of reasons that are speaking they never existed (Waluchow). That being so, morality sometimes
operative in every case: source-based reasons and non-source-based reasons. determines the existence or content of law. If this is the underlying intuition,
Law application and law creation are continuous activities for, as Kelsen it is misleading, for the rule of recognition is not to be found in constitutions.
correctly argued, every legal decision is partly determined by law and partly The rule of recognition is the ultimate criterion (or set of criteria) of legal
underdetermined: The higher norm cannot bind in every direction the act validity. If one knows what the constitution of a country is, one knows some
by which it is applied. There must always be more or less room for of its law; but one may know what the rule of recognition is without
discretion, so that the higher norm in relation to the lower one can only have knowing any of its laws. You may know that acts of the Bundestag are a
the character of a frame to be filled by this act (1967, p. 349). This is a source of law in Germany but not be able to name or interpret a single one of
general truth about norms. There are infinitely many ways of complying with them. And constitutional law is itself subject to the ultimate criteria of
a command to close the door (quickly or slowly, with one's right hand or systemic validity. Whether a statute, decision or convention is part of a
left, etc.) Thus, even an easy case will contain discretionary elements. country's constitution can only be determined by applying the rule of
Sometimes such residual discretion is of little importance; sometimes it is recognition. The provisions of the 14th Amendment to the U.S. constitution,
central; and a shift from marginal to major can happen in a flash with for example, are not the rule of recognition in the U.S., for there is an intra-
changes in social or technological circumstances. That is one of the reasons systemic answer to the question why that Amendment is valid law. The U.S.
constitution, like that of all other countries, is law only because it was sources can play this mediating role between persons and ultimate reasons,
created in ways provided by law (through amendment or court decision) or and because the nature of law is partly determined by its role in giving
in ways that came to be accepted as creating law (by constitutional practical guidance, there is a theoretical reason for stopping at source-based
convention and custom). Constitutional cases thus raise no philosophical considerations.
issue not already present in ordinary statutory interpretation, where
inclusive positivists seem content with the theory of judicial discretion. It is, The third argument challenges an underlying idea of inclusive positivism,
of course, open to them to adopt a unified view and treat every explicit or what we might call the Midas Principle. Just as everything King Midas
implicit legal reference to morality -- in cases, statutes, constitutions, and touched turned into gold, everything to which law refers becomes law
customs -- as establishing moral tests for the existence of law. (Although at (Kelsen 1967, p. 161). Kelsen thought that it followed from this principle that
that point it is unclear how their view would differ from Dworkin's.) So we It is possible for the legal order, by obliging the law-creating organs to
should consider the wider question: why not regard as law everything respect or apply certain moral norms or political principles or opinions of
referred to by law? experts to transform these norms, principles, or opinions into legal norms,
and thus into sources of law (Kelsen 1945, p. 132). (Though he regarded this
Exclusive positivists offer three main arguments for stopping at social transformation as effected by a sort of tacit legislation.) If sound, the Midas
sources. The first and most important is that it captures and systematizes Principle holds in general and not only with respect to morality, as Kelsen
distinctions we regularly make and that we have good reason to continue to makes clear. Suppose then that the Income Tax Act penalizes overdue
make. We assign blame and responsibility differently when we think that a accounts at 8% per annum. In a relevant case, an official can determine the
bad decision was mandated by the sources than we do when we think that it content of a legal obligation only by calculating compound interest. Does this
flowed from a judge's exercise of moral or political judgement. When make mathematics part of the law? A contrary indication is that it is not
considering who should be appointed to the judiciary, we are concerned not subject to the rules of change in a legal system -- neither courts nor
only with their acumen as jurists, but also with their morality and politics-- legislators can repeal or amend the law of commutativity. The same holds of
and we take different things as evidence of these traits. These are deeply other social norms, including the norms of foreign legal systems. A conflict-
entrenched distinctions, and there is no reason to abandon them. of-laws rule may direct a Canadian judge to apply Mexican law in a Canadian
case. The conflicts rule is obviously part of the Canadian legal system. But
The second reason for stopping at sources is that this is demonstrably the rule of Mexican law is not, for although Canadian officials can decide
consistent with key features of law's role in practical reasoning. The most whether or not to apply it, they can neither change it nor repeal it, and best
important argument to this conclusion is due to Raz (1994, pp. 210-37). For explanation for its existence and content makes no reference to Canadian
a related argument see Shapiro. For criticism see Perry, Waluchow, Coleman society or its political system. In like manner, moral standards, logic,
2001, and Himma.) Although law does not necessarily have legitimate mathematics, principles of statistical inference, or English grammar, though
authority, it lays claim to it, and can intelligibly do so only if it is the kind of all properly applied in cases, are not themselves the law, for legal organs
thing that could have legitimate authority. It may fail, therefore, in certain have applicative but not creative power over them. The inclusivist thesis is
ways only, for example, by being unjust, pointless, or ineffective. But law actually groping towards an important, but different, truth. Law is
cannot fail to be a candidate authority, for it is constituted in that role by our an open normative system (Raz 1975, pp. 152-54): it adopts and enforces
political practices. According to Raz, practical authorities mediate between many other standards, including moral norms and the rules of social groups.
subjects and the ultimate reasons for which they should act. Authorities' There is no warrant for adopting the Midas Principle to explain how or why
directives should be based on such reasons, and they are justified only when it does this.
compliance with the directives makes it more likely that people will comply
with the underlying reasons that apply to them. But they can do that only if
is possible to know what the directives require independent of appeal to 4. Law and Its Merits
those underlying reasons. Consider an example. Suppose we agree to resolve It may clarify the philosophical stakes in legal positivism by comparing it to a
a dispute by consensus, but that after much discussion find ourselves in number of other theses with which it is sometimes wrongly identified, and
disagreement about whether some point is in fact part of the consensus view. not only by its opponents. (See also Hart, 1958, Fuesser, and Schauer.)
It will do nothing to say that we should adopt it if it is indeed properly part of
the consensus. On the other hand, we could agree to adopt it if it were
endorsed by a majority vote, for we could determine the outcome of a vote
4.1 The Fallibility Thesis
without appeal to our ideas about what the consensus should be. Social
Law does not necessarily satisfy the conditions by which it is appropriately the positivist thesis this way, we might interpret the difference between
assessed (Lyons 1984, p. 63, Hart 1994, pp. 185-6). Law should be just, but it exclusive and inclusive positivism in terms of the scope of the modal
may not be; it should promote the common good, but sometimes it doesn't; it operator:
should protect moral rights, but it may fail miserably. This we may call the
moral fallibility thesis. The thesis is correct, but it is not the exclusive (EP) It is necessarily the case that there is no connection between law and
property of positivism. Aquinas accepts it, Fuller accepts it, Finnis accepts it, morality.
and Dworkin accepts it. Only a crude misunderstanding of ideas like (IP) It is not necessarily the case that there is a connection between law and
Aquinas's claim that an unjust law seems to be no law at all might suggest morality.
the contrary. Law may have an essentially moral character and yet be
In reality, however, legal positivism is not to be identified with either thesis
morally deficient. Even if every law always does one kind of justice (formal
and each of them is false. There are many necessary connections, trivial
justice; justice according to law), this does not entail that it does every kind
and non-trivial, between law and morality. As John Gardner notes, legal
of justice. Even if every law has a prima facie claim to be applied or obeyed, it
positivism takes a position only one of them, it rejects any dependence of the
does not follow that it has such a claim all things considered. The gap
existence of law on its merits (Gardner 2001). And with respect to this
between these partial and conclusive judgments is all a natural law theory
dependency relation, legal positivists are concerned with much more than
needs to accommodate the fallibility thesis. It is sometimes said that
the relationship between law and morality, for in the only sense in which
positivism gives a more secure grasp on the fallibility of law, for once we see
they insist on a separation of law and morals they must insist also--and for
that it is a social construction we will be less likely to accord it inappropriate
the same reasons--on a separation of law and economics.
deference and better prepared to engage in a clear-headed moral appraisal of
the law. This claim has appealed to several positivists, including Bentham To exclude this dependency relation, however, is to leave intact many other
and Hart. But while this might follow from the truth of positivism, it cannot interesting possibilities. For instance, it is possible that moral
provide an argument for it. If law has an essentially moral character then it is value derives from the sheer existence of law (Raz 1990, 165-70) If Hobbes is
obfuscating, not clarifying, to describe it as a source-based structure of right, any order is better than chaos and in some circumstances order may be
governance. achievable only through positive law. Or perhaps in a Hegelian way every
existing legal system expresses deliberate governance in a world otherwise
4.2 The Separability Thesis dominated by chance; law is the spirit of the community come to self-
consciousness. Notice that these claims are consistent with the fallibility
At one point, Hart identifies legal positivism with the simple contention that thesis, for they do not deny that these supposedly good things might also
it is no sense a necessary truth that laws reproduce or satisfy certain bring evils, such as too much order or the will to power. Perhaps such
demands of morality, though in fact they have often done so (1994, pp. 185- derivative connections between law and morality are thought innocuous on
86). Many other philosophers, encouraged also by the title of Hart's famous the ground that they show more about human nature than they do about the
essay, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, (1958) treat the nature of law. The same cannot be said of the following necessary
theory as the denial that there is a necessary connection between law and connections between law and morality, each of which goes right to the heart
morality -- they must be in some sense separable even if not in fact of our concept of law:
separate (Coleman, 1982). The separability thesis is generally construed so
as to tolerate any contingent connection between morality and law, provided (1) Necessarily, law deals with moral matters.
only that it is conceivable that the connection might fail. Thus, the
separability thesis is consistent with all of the following: (i) moral principles Kelsen writes, Just as natural and positive law govern the same subject-
are part of the law; (ii) law is usually, or even always in fact, valuable; (iii) the matter, and relate, therefore, to the same norm-object, namely the mutual
best explanation for the content of a society's laws includes reference to the relationships of men -- so both also have in common the universal form of
moral ideals current in that society; and (iv) a legal system cannot survive this governance, namely obligation. (Kelsen 1928, p. 34) This is a matter of
unless it is seen to be, and thus in some measure actually is, just. All four the content of all legal systems. Where there is law there is also morality, and
claims are counted by the separability thesis as contingent connections only; they regulate the same matters by analogous techniques. Of course to say
they do not hold of all possible legal systems -- they probably don't even hold that law deals with morality's subject matter is not to say that it does so well,
of all historical legal systems. As merely contingent truths, it is imagined that and to say that all legal systems create obligations is not to endorse the
they do not affect the concept of law itself. (This is a defective view of duties so created. This is broader than Hart's minimum content thesis
concept-formation, but we may ignore that for these purposes.) If we think of according to which there are basic rules governing violence, property,
fidelity, and kinship that any legal system must encompass if it aims at the kind of thing that is apt for appraisal as just or unjust. This is a very
survival of social creatures like ourselves (Hart 1994, pp. 193-200). Hart significant feature of law. Not all human practices are justice-apt. It makes
regards this as a matter of natural necessity and in that measure is willing no sense to ask whether a certain fugue is just or to demand that it become
to qualify his endorsement of the separability thesis. But even a society that so. The musical standards of fugal excellence are preeminently internal -- a
prefers national glory or the worship of gods to survival will charge its legal good fugue is a good example of its genre; it should be melodic, interesting,
system with the same tasks its morality pursues, so the necessary content of inventive etc. -- and the further we get from these internal standards the less
law is not dependent, as Hart thinks it is, on assuming certain facts about secure evaluative judgments about it become. While some formalists flirt
human nature and certain aims of social existence. He fails to notice that if with similar ideas about law, this is in fact inconsistent with law's place
human nature and life were different, then morality would be too and if law amongst human practices. Even if law has internal standards of merit --
had any role in that society, it would inevitably deal with morality's subject virtues uniquely its own that inhere in its law-like character -- these cannot
matter. Unlike the rules of a health club, law has broad scope and reaches to preclude or displace its assessment on independent criteria of justice. A
the most important things in any society, whatever they may be. Indeed, our fugue may be at its best when it has all the virtues of fugacity; but law
most urgent political worries about law and its claims flow from just this is not best when it excels in legality; law must also be just. A society may
capacity to regulate our most vital interests, and law's wide reach must figure therefore suffer not only from too little of the rule of law, but also from too
in any argument about its legitimacy and its claim to obedience. much of it. This does not presuppose that justice is the only, or even the first,
virtue of a legal system. It means that our concern for its justice as one of its
(2) Necessarily, law makes moral claims on its subjects. virtues cannot be sidelined by any claim of the sort that law's purpose is to be
law, to its most excellent degree. Law stands continuously exposed to
The law tells us what we must do, not merely what it would be virtuous or
demands for justification, and that too shapes its nature and role in our lives
advantageous to do, and it requires us to act without regard to our individual
and culture.
self-interest but in the interests of other individuals, or in the public interest
more generally (except when law itself permits otherwise). That is to say, law These three theses establish connections between law and morality that are
purports to obligate us. But to make categorical demands that people should both necessary and highly significant. Each of them is consistent with the
act in the interests of others is to make moral demands on them. These positivist thesis that the existence and content of law depends on social facts,
demands may be misguided or unjustified for law is fallible; they may be not on its merits. Each of them contributes to an understanding of the nature
made in a spirit that is cynical or half-hearted; but they must be the kind of of law. The familiar idea that legal positivism insists on the separability of
thing that can be offered as, and possibly taken as, obligation-imposing law and morality is therefore significantly mistaken.
requirements. For this reason neither a regime of stark imperatives (see
Kramer, pp. 83-9) nor a price system would be a system of law, for neither 4.3 The Neutrality Thesis
could even lay claim to obligate its subjects. As with many other social
institutions, what law, though its officials, claims determines its character The necessary content thesis and the justice-aptitude thesis together
independent of the truth or validity of those claims. Popes, for example, establish that law is not value-neutral. Although some lawyers regard this
claim apostolic succession from St. Peter. The fact that they claim this partly idea as a revelation (and others as provocation) it is in fact banal. The
determines what it is to be a Pope, even if it is a fiction, and even the Pope thought that law could be value neutral does not even rise to falsity -- it is
himself doubts its truth. The nature of law is similarly shaped by the self- simply incoherent. Law is a normative system, promoting certain values and
image it adopts and projects to its subjects. To make moral demands on their repressing others. Law is not neutral between victim and murderer or
compliance is to stake out a certain territory, to invite certain kinds of between owner and thief. When people complain of the law's lack of
support and, possibly, opposition. It is precisely because law makes these neutrality, they are in fact voicing very different aspirations, such as the
claims that doctrines of legitimacy and political obligation take the shape demand that it be fair, just, impartial, and so forth. A condition of law's
and importance that they do. achieving any of these ideals is that it is not neutral in either its aims or its
effects.
(3) Necessarily, law is justice-apt.
Positivism is however sometimes more credibly associated with the idea
In view of the normative function of law in creating and enforcing that legal philosophy is or should be value-neutral. Kelsen, for example,
obligations and rights, it always makes sense to ask whether law is just, and says, the function of the science of law is not the evaluation of its subject,
where it is found deficient to demand reform. Legal systems are therefore the but its value-free description (1967, p. 68) and Hart at one point described
his work as descriptive sociology (1994, p. v). Since it is well known that count as merits of law (must law be efficient or elegant as well as just?); of
there are convincing arguments for the ineliminability of values in the social what role law should play in adjudication (should valid law always be
sciences, those who have taken on board Quinian holisms, Kuhnian applied?); of what claim law has on our obedience (is there a duty to obey?);
paradigms, or Foucauldian espistemes, may suppose that positivism should and also of the pivotal questions of what laws we should have and whether
be rejected a priori, as promising something that no theory can deliver. we should have law at all. Legal positivism does not aspire to answer these
questions, though its claim that the existence and content of law depends
There are complex questions here, but some advance may be made by only on social facts does give them shape.
noticing that Kelsen's alternatives are a false dichotomy. Legal positivism is
indeed not an evaluation of its subject, i.e., an evaluation of the law. And to
say that the existence of law depends on social facts does not commit one to
thinking that it is a good thing that this is so. (Nor does it preclude it: see
MacCormick and Campbell) Thus far Kelsen is on secure ground. But it does Legal Positivism
not follow that legal philosophy therefore offers a value-free description of
its subject. There can be no such thing. Whatever the relation between facts Legal positivism is a philosophy of law that emphasizes the conventional
and values, there is no doubt about the relationship nature of lawthat it is socially constructed. According to legal
between descriptions and values. Every description is value-laden. It selects positivism, law is synonymous with positive norms, that is, norms made
and systematizes only a subset of the infinite number of facts about its by the legislator or considered as common law or case law. Formal
subject. To describe law as resting on customary social rules is to omit many criteria of laws origin, law enforcement and legal effectiveness are all
other truths about it including, for example, truths about its connection to sufficient for social norms to be considered law. Legal positivism does
the demand for paper or silk. Our warrant for doing this must rest on the not base law on divine commandments, reason, or human rights. As an
view that the former facts are more important than the latter. In this way, all
historical matter, positivism arose in opposition to classical natural law
descriptions express choices about what is salient or significant, and these in
theory, according to which there are necessary moral constraints on the
turn cannot be understood without reference to values. So legal philosophy,
even if not directly an evaluation of its subject is nonetheless indirectly content of law.
evaluative (Dickson, 2001). Moreover, law itself is an anthropocentric Legal positivism does not imply an ethical justification for the content of
subject, dependent not merely on our sensory embodiment but also, as its the law, nor a decision for or against the obedience to law. Positivists do
necessary connections to morality show, on our moral sense and capacities. not judge laws by questions of justice or humanity, but merely by the
Legal kinds such as courts, decisions, and rules will not appear in a purely ways in which the laws have been created. This includes the view that
physical description of the universe and may not even appear in every social judges make new law in deciding cases not falling clearly under a legal
description. (This may limit the prospects for a naturalized jurisprudence; rule. Practicing, deciding or tolerating certain practices of law can each
though for a spirited defense of the contrary view, see Leiter) be considered a way of creating law.
It may seem, however, that legal positivism at least requires a stand on the
so-called fact-value problem. There is no doubt that certain positivists, Within legal doctrine, legal positivism would be opposed to sociological
especially Kelsen, believe this to be so. In reality, positivism may cohabit jurisprudence and hermeneutics of law, which study the concrete
with a range of views here -- value statements may be entailed by factual prevailing circumstances of statutory interpretationin society.
statements; values may supervene on facts; values may be kind of fact. Legal The word positivism was probably first used to draw attention to the
positivism requires only that it be in virtue of its facticity rather than its idea that law is positive or posited, as opposed to being natural in
meritoriousness that something is law, and that we can describe that facticity the sense of being derived from natural law or morality.
without assessing its merits. In this regard, it is important to bear in mind
that not every kind of evaluative statement would count among the merits of
a given rule; its merits are only those values that could bear on its
justification.
Table of Contents
Evaluative argument is, of course, central to the philosophy of law more 1. The Pedigree Thesis
generally. No legal philosopher can be only a legal positivist. A complete 2. The Separability Thesis
theory of law requires also an account of what kinds of things could possibly a. Inclusive vs. Exclusive Positivism
3. The Discretion Thesis confers no rights; it imposes no duties; it is, in legal contemplation, as
4. Classic Criticisms of Positivism inoperative as though it had never been passed." (Norton v. Shelby County,
. Fuller's Internal Morality of Law 118 U.S. 425 (1886)). Moreover, these constraints purport to be legal
a. Positivism and Legal Principles constraints: the Supremacy Clause of Article VI of the Constitution states
b. The Semantic Sting that "[t]his Constitution ... shall be the supreme Law of the Land; and the
5. References and Further Reading Judges in every State shall be bound thereby."
1. The Pedigree Thesis The most influential criticisms of Austin's version of the pedigree thesis,
however, owe to H. L. A. Hart's seminal work, The Concept of Law. Hart
The pedigree thesis asserts that legal validity is a function of certain
points out that Austin's theory provides, at best, a partial account of legal
social facts. Borrowing heavily from Jeremy Bentham, John Austin argues
validity because it focuses on one kind of rule, namely that which
that the principal distinguishing feature of a legal system is the presence
requires citizens "to do or abstain from certain actions, whether they
of a sovereign who is habitually obeyed by most people in the society, but
wish to or not" (Hart 1994, p. 81). While every legal system must contain
not in the habit of obeying any determinate human superior (Austin
so-called primary rules that regulate citizen behavior, Hart believes a
1995, p. 166). On Austin's view, a rule R is legally valid (that is, is a law)
system consisting entirely of the kind of liberty restrictions found in the
in a society S if and only if R is commanded by the sovereign in S and is
criminal law is, at best, a rudimentary or primitive legal system.
backed up with the threat of a sanction. The severity of the threatened
On Hart's view, Austin's emphasis on coercive force leads him to
sanction is irrelevant; any general sovereign imperative supported by a
overlook the presence of a second kind of primary rule that confers upon
threat of even the smallest harm is a law.
citizens the power to create, modify, and extinguish rights and
jAustin's command theory of law is vulnerable to a number of criticisms.
obligations in other persons. As Hart points out, the rules governing the
One problem is that there appears to be no identifiable sovereign in
creation of contracts and wills cannot plausibly be characterized as
democratic societies. In the United States, for example, the ultimate
restrictions on freedom that are backed by the threat of a sanction. These
political power seems to belong to the people, who elect lawmakers to
rules empower persons to structure their legal relations within the
represent their interests. Elected lawmakers have the power to coerce
coercive framework of the law-a feature that Hart correctly regards as
behavior but are regarded as servants of the people and not as
one of "law's greatest contributions to social life." The operation of
repositories of sovereign power. The voting population, on the other
power-conferring primary rules, according to Hart, indicates the
hand, seems to be the repository of ultimate political authority yet lacks
presence of a more sophisticated system for regulating behavior.
the immediate power to coerce behavior. Thus, in democracies like that
of the United States, the ultimate political authority and the power to
coerce behavior seem to reside in different entities. But what ultimately distinguishes societies with full-blown systems of
law from those with only rudimentary or primitive forms of law is that
the former have, in addition to first-order primary rules, secondary
A second problem has to do with Austin's view that the sovereign
meta-rules that have as their subject matter the primary rules
lawmaking authority is incapable of legal limitation. On Austin's view, a
themselves:
sovereign cannot be legally constrained because no person (or body of
persons) can coerce herself (or itself). Since constitutional provisions
limit the authority of the legislative body to make laws, Austin is forced [Secondary rules] may all be said to be on a different level from the primary
to argue that what we refer to as constitutional law is really not law at all; rules, for they are all about such rules; in the sense that while primary rules are
rather, it is principally a matter of "positive morality" (Austin 1977, p. concerned with the actions that individuals must or must not do, these
107). secondary rules are all concerned with the primary rules themselves. They
specify the way in which the primary rules may be conclusively ascertained,
introduced, eliminated, varied, and the fact of their violation conclusively
Austin's view is difficult to reconcile with constitutional law in the
United States. Courts regard the procedural and substantive provisions determined (Hart 1994, p. 92).
of the constitution as constraints on legal validity. The Supreme Court
has held, for example, that "an unconstitutional act is not a law; it
Hart distinguishes three types of secondary rules that mark the validity: "the reality of the situation is that a great proportion of ordinary
transition from primitive forms of law to full-blown legal systems: (1) the citizens-perhaps a majority-have no general conception of the legal
rule of recognition, which "specif[ies] some feature or features structure or its criteria of validity" (Hart 1994, p. 111). Instead, Hart
possession of which by a suggested rule is taken as a conclusive argues that what is necessary to the existence of a legal system is that the
affirmative indication that it is a rule of the group to be supported by the majority of officials take the internal point of view towards the rule of
social pressure it exerts" (Hart 1994, p. 92); (2) the rule of change, which recognition and its criteria of validity. All that is required of citizens is
enables a society to add, remove, and modify valid rules; and (3) the rule that they generally obey the primary rules that are legally valid according
of adjudication, which provides a mechanism for determining whether a to the rule of recognition.
valid rule has been violated. On Hart's view, then, every society with a
full-blown legal system necessarily has a rule of recognition that Thus, on Hart's view, there are two minimum conditions sufficient and
articulates criteria for legal validity that include provisions for making, necessary for the existence of a legal system: "On the one hand those
changing and adjudicating law. Law is, to use Hart's famous phrase, "the rules of behavior which are valid according to the system's ultimate
union of primary and secondary rules" (Hart 1994, p. 107). Austin theory criteria of validity must be generally obeyed, and, on the other hand, its
fails, on Hart's view, because it fails to acknowledge the importance of rules of recognition specifying the criteria of legal validity and its rules of
secondary rules in manufacturing legal validity. change and adjudication must be effectively accepted as common public
standards of official behavior by its officials" (Hart 1994, p. 113).
Hart also finds fault with Austin's view that legal obligation is essentially
coercive. According to Hart, there is no difference between the Austinian Hart's view is vulnerable to the same criticism that he levels against
sovereign who governs by coercing behavior and the gunman who orders Austin. Hart rejects Austin's view because the institutional application of
someone to hand over her money. In both cases, the subject can coercive force can no more give rise to an obligation than can the
plausibly be characterized as being "obliged" to comply with the application of coercive force by a gunman. But the situation is no
commands, but not as being "duty-bound" or "obligated" to do so (Hart different if the gunman takes the internal point of view towards his
1994, p. 80). On Hart's view, the application of coercive force alone can authority to make such a threat. Despite the gunman's belief that he is
never give rise to an obligation-legal or otherwise. entitled to make the threat, the victim is obliged, but not obligated, to
comply with the gunman's orders. The gunman's behavior is no less
Legal rules are obligatory, according to Hart, because people accept coercive because he believes he is entitled to make the threat.
them as standards that justify criticism and, in extreme cases,
punishment of deviations: Similarly, in the minimal legal system, only the officials of the legal
system take the internal point of view towards the rule of recognition
What is necessary is that there should be a critical reflective attitude to certain that endows them with authority to make, execute, adjudicate, and
patterns of behavior as a common standard, and that this should display itself in enforce the rules. The mere presence of a belief in the officials that they
criticism (including self-criticism), demands for conformity, and in are entitled to make law cannot give rise to an obligation in other people
acknowledgements that such criticism and demands are justified, all of which to comply with their enactments any more than the presence of a belief
find their characteristic expression in the normative terminology of 'ought', on the part of a gunman that he is entitled to issue orders gives rise to an
'must', and 'should', and 'right' and 'wrong' (Hart 1994, p. 56). obligation in the victim to comply with those orders. Hart's minimal
legal system is no less coercive than Austin's legal system.
The subject who reflectively accepts the rule as providing a standard that
justifies criticism of deviations is said to take "the internal point of view"
towards it. 2. The Separability Thesis
The second thesis comprising the foundation of legal positivism is the
separability thesis. In its most general form, the separability thesis
On Hart's view, it would be too much to require that the bulk of the
asserts that law and morality are conceptually distinct. This abstract
population accept the rule of recognition as the ultimate criteria for legal
formulation can be interpreted in a number of ways. For example, Klaus At first glance, exclusive positivism may seem difficult to reconcile with
Faber (1996) interprets it as making a meta-level claim that the what appear to be moral criteria of legal validity in legal systems like that
definition of law must be entirely free of moral notions. This of the United States. For example, the Fourth Amendment provides that
interpretation implies that any reference to moral considerations in "[t]he right of the people to be secure in their persons, houses, papers,
defining the related notions of law, legal validity, and legal system is and effects against unreasonable searches and seizures, shall not be
inconsistent with the separability thesis. violated." Likewise, the First Amendment prohibits laws abridging the
right of free speech. Taken at face value, these amendments seem to
More commonly, the separability thesis is interpreted as making only an make moral standards part of the conditions for legal validity.
object-level claim about the existence conditions for legal validity. As
H.L.A. Hart describes it, the separability thesis is no more than the Exclusive positivists argue that such amendments can require judges to
"simple contention that it is in no sense a necessary truth that laws consider moral standards in certain circumstances, but cannot
reproduce or satisfy certain demands of morality, though in fact they incorporate those standards into the law. When a judge makes reference
have often done so" (Hart 1994, pp. 181-82). Insofar as the object-level to moral considerations in deciding a case, she necessarily creates new
interpretation of the separability thesis denies it is a necessary truth that law on an issue-and this is so even when the law directs her to consider
there are moral constraints on legal validity, it implies the existence of a moral considerations, as the Bill of Rights does in certain circumstances.
possible legal system in which there are no moral constraints on legal On this view, all law is settled law and questions of settled law can be
validity. resolved without recourse to moral arguments:

a. Inclusive vs. Exclusive Positivism The law on a question is settled when legally binding sources provide its
Though all positivists agree there are possible legal systems without solution. In such cases judges are typically said to apply the law, and since it is
moral constraints on legal validity, there are conflicting views on source-based, its application involves technical, legal skills in reasoning from
whether there are possible legal systems with such constraints. those sources and does not call for moral acumen. If a legal question is not
According to inclusive positivism (also known as incorporationism and answered by standards deriving from legal sources then it lacks a legal answer-
soft positivism), it is possible for a society's rule of recognition to the law on such questions is unsettled. In deciding such cases courts inevitably
incorporate moral constraints on the content of law. Prominent inclusive break new (legal) ground and their decision develops the law.... Naturally, their
positivists include Jules Coleman and H.L.A. Hart, who maintains that decisions in such cases rely at least partly on moral and other extra-legal
"the rule of recognition may incorporate as criteria of legal validity considerations (Raz 1979, pp. 49-50).
conformity with moral principles or substantive values ... such as the
Sixteenth or Nineteenth Amendments to the United States Constitution If the judge can resolve an issue involving the First Amendment merely
respecting the establishment of religion or abridgements of the right to by applying past court decisions, then the issue is settled by the law; if
vote" (Hart 1994, p. 250). not, then the issue is unsettled. Insofar as the judge looks to
controversial moral standards to resolve the issue, she is going beyond
the law because the mere presence of controversy about the law implies
In contrast, exclusive positivism (also called hard positivism) denies that that it is indeterminate. Thus, on Raz's view, references to moral
a legal system can incorporate moral constraints on legal validity. language in the law, at most, direct judges to consider moral
Exclusive positivists like Joseph Raz (1979, p. 47) subscribe to the source requirements in resolving certain unsettled questions of law. They
thesis, according to which the existence and content of law can always be cannot incorporate moral requirements into the law.
determined by reference to its sources without recourse to moral
argument. On this view, the sources of law include both the
circumstances of its promulgation and relevant interpretative materials, 3. The Discretion Thesis
such as court cases involving its application. Third thesis commonly associated with positivism is the discretion
thesis, according to which judges decide difficult cases by making new
law in the exercise of discretion. Ronald Dworkin describes this thesis as possible legal system. But insofar as the natural law is incomplete, there
follows: will inevitably arise issues that have multiple outcomes consistent with
the natural law. Since none of the relevant outcomes in such cases offend
The set of these valid legal rules is exhaustive of 'the law', so that if someone's the natural law, there is nothing in the assumption of necessary moral
case is not clearly covered by such a rule . . . then that case cannot be decided constraints on the content of law, in and of itself, that precludes
by 'applying the law.' It must be decided by some official, like a judge, Blackstone from endorsing the discretion thesis in such cases. Of course,
'exercising his discretion,' which means reaching beyond the law for some other if Blackstone believes the natural law contains a principle denying
sort of standard to guide him in manufacturing a fresh legal rule or discretion to judges, then that commitment is inconsistent with the
supplementing an old one (Dworkin 1977, p. 17). discretion thesis. But the assertion there are necessary constraints on the
content of law, in and of itself, is consistent with the discretion thesis,
On this view, a judge cannot decide a case that does not fall clearly under even construed as a conceptual claim, as long as there are cases to which
a valid rule by interpreting or applying the law; she must decide the case the natural law is indifferent.
by creating or promulgating a law that did not exist prior to the In any event, Dworkin distinguishes three different senses in which a
adjudication. Thus, the discretion thesis implies that judges are judge might be said to have discretion: (1) a judge has discretion when
empowered with a quasi-legislative lawmaking authority in cases that she exercises judgment in applying a legal standard to a particular case;
cannot be decided merely by applying law. (2) a judge has discretion when her decision is not subject to reversal by
any other authority; and (3) a judge has discretion when her decision is
not bound by any legal standards.
Though often associated with positivism, the discretion thesis does not
belong to positivism's theoretical core. The pedigree and separability
theses purport to be conceptual claims that are true of every possible According to Dworkin, positivism's discretion thesis is committed to the
legal system. These two claims jointly assert that, in every possible legal third sense of discretion, which he refers to as strong discretion. On
system, propositions of law are valid in virtue of having been Dworkin's view, the thesis that judges have discretion only in the sense
manufactured according to some set of social conventions. On this view, that they exercise judgment is trivially true, while the thesis that judges
there are no moral constraints on the content of law that hold in every have discretion in the sense that their decisions are not subject to being
possible legal system. reversed by a higher authority is false. Even the Supreme Court can be
reversed by Congress or by constitutional amendment. Thus, on
Dworkin's view, the discretion thesis implies that judges have discretion
But many positivists regard the discretion thesis as a contingent claim to decide hard cases by what amounts to an act of legislation because the
that is true of some, but not all, possible legal systems. Hart, for
judge is not bound by any legal standards.
example, believes there will inevitably arise cases that do not fall clearly
under a rule, but concedes a rule of recognition could deny judges
discretion to make law in such cases by requiring judges "to disclaim Thus construed, the discretion thesis is inconsistent with ordinary legal
jurisdiction or to refer the points not regulated by the existing law to the practice. Even in the most difficult of cases where there is no clearly
legislature to decide" (Hart 1994, p. 272). Indeed, Hart's inclusive applicable law, lawyers do not ask that the judge decide the relevant
positivism allows him to hold that a rule of recognition could require issue by making new law. Each lawyer cites cases favorable to her client's
judges to decide cases in precisely the manner that Dworkin advocates position and argues that the judge is bound by those cases to decide in
(Hart 1994, p. 263; and see Section IV-2, infra). Thus, at least for her client's favor. As a practical matter, lawyers rarely, if ever, concede
inclusive positivists like Hart, the discretion thesis makes a different there are no legal standards governing a case and ask the judge to
kind of claim than the conceptual claims that form positivism's legislate in the exercise of discretion.
theoretical core (Himma 1999).
Moreover, the discretion thesis is consistent with some forms of natural Nevertheless, the problem with Dworkin's analysis is that it falsely
law theory. According to Blackstone's classical naturalism, conformity presupposes an official cannot make new law unless there are no legal
with the natural law is a necessary condition for legal validity in every standards constraining the official's decision. Indeed, lawmaking
authorities in legal systems like the U.S. never have what Dworkin But if fairness precludes taking property from a defendant under a law
describes as strong discretion. Even the legislative decisions of Congress, that did not exist at the time of the relevant behavior, it also precludes
the highest legislative authority in the nation, are always constrained by taking property from a defendant under a law that did not give
constitutional standards. For example, under the Fourteenth reasonable notice that the relevant behavior gives rise to liability. Due
Amendment, Congress cannot enact a law that sets one speed limit for process and fundamental fairness require reasonable notice of which
male drivers on interstate highways and another for female drivers. behaviors give rise to liability. As long as Dworkin acknowledges the
existence of cases so difficult that only the best of judges can solve them,
For his part, Hart concedes that judicial lawmaking authority is limited his theory is vulnerable to the same charge of unfairness that he levels at
in two respects: "not only are the judge's powers subject to many the discretion thesis.
constraints narrowing his choice from which a legislature may be quite
free, but since the judge's powers are exercised only to dispose of
particular instant cases he cannot use these to introduce large-scale
4. Classic Criticisms of Positivism
reforms or new codes" (Hart 1994, p. 273). What explains the judge's a. Fuller's Internal Morality of Law
discretion to make new law in a given case, on Hart's view, is not the In The Morality of Law, Lon L. Fuller argues that law is subject to an
absence of legal standards constraining her decision; rather it is the internal morality consisting of eight principles: (P1) the rules must be
absence of legal standards that dictate a uniquely correct answer to the expressed in general terms; (P2) the rules must be publicly promulgated;
case. The judge cannot decide such a case merely by applying existing (P3) the rules must be (for the most part) prospective in effect; (P4) the
law because there is more than one available outcome that coheres with rules must be expressed in understandable terms; (P5) the rules must be
existing law. In such instances, it is impossible to render a substantive consistent with one another; (P6) the rules must not require conduct
decision (as opposed to simply referring the matter back to the beyond the powers of the affected parties; (P7) the rules must not be
legislature) without creating new law. changed so frequently that the subject cannot rely on them; and (P8) the
The discretion thesis is vulnerable to one powerful objection. Insofar as a rules must be administered in a manner consistent with their wording
judge decides a difficult case by making new law in the exercise of (Fuller 1964, p. 39).
discretion, the case is being decided on the basis of a law that did not On Fuller's view, no system of rules that fails minimally to satisfy these
exist at the time the dispute arose. If, for example, a judge awards principles of legality can achieve law's essential purpose of achieving
damages to a plaintiff by making new law in the exercise of discretion, it social order through the use of rules that guide behavior. A system of
follows that she has held the defendant liable under a law that did not rules that fails to satisfy (P2) or (P4), for example, cannot guide behavior
exist at the time the dispute arose. And, as Dworkin points out, it seems because people will not be able to determine what the rules require.
patently unfair to deprive a defendant of property for behavior that did Accordingly, Fuller concludes that his eight principles are "internal" to
not give rise to liability at the time the behavior occurred. law in the sense that they are built into the existence conditions for law:
"A total failure in any one of these eight directions does not simply result
in a bad system of law; it results in something that is not properly called
Nevertheless, Dworkin's view fares no better on this count. While
Dworkin acknowledges the existence of difficult cases that do not fall a legal system at all" (Fuller 1964, p. 39).
clearly under a rule, he believes they are not resolved by an exercise of
judicial discretion. On Dworkin's view, there is always a right answer to These internal principles constitute a morality, according to Fuller,
such cases implicit in the pre-existing law. Of course, it sometimes takes because law necessarily has positive moral value in two respects: (1) law
a judge of Herculean intellectual ability to discern what the right answer conduces to a state of social order and (2) does so by respecting human
is, but it is always there to be found in pre-existing law. Since the right autonomy because rules guide behavior. Since no system of rules can
answer to even hard legal disputes is always part of pre-existing law, achieve these morally valuable objectives without minimally complying
Dworkin believes that a judge can take property from a defendant in a with the principles of legality, it follows, on Fuller's view, that they
hard case without unfairness (Dworkin 1977, pp. 87-130). constitute a morality. Since these moral principles are built into the
existence conditions for law, they are internal and hence represent a
conceptual connection between law and morality that is inconsistent the existence of a legal system is consistent with considerable divergence
with the separability thesis. from the principles of legality. Legal standards, for example, are
Hart responds by denying Fuller's claim that the principles of legality necessarily promulgated in general terms that inevitably give rise to
constitute an internal morality; on Hart's view, Fuller confuses the problems of vagueness. And officials all too often fail to administer the
notions of morality and efficacy: laws in a fair and even-handed manner-even in the best of legal systems.
These divergences may always be prima facie objectionable, but they are
[T]he author's insistence on classifying these principles of legality as a inconsistent with a legal system only when they render a legal system
"morality" is a source of confusion both for him and his readers.... [T]he crucial incapable of performing its essential function of guiding behavior.
objection to the designation of these principles of good legal craftsmanship as Insofar as these principles are built into the existence conditions for law,
morality, in spite of the qualification "inner," is that it perpetrates a confusion it is because they operate as efficacy conditions-and not because they
between two notions that it is vital to hold apart: the notions of purposive function as moral ideals.
activity and morality. Poisoning is no doubt a purposive activity, and reflections Fuller's jurisprudential legacy, however, should not be underestimated.
on its purpose may show that it has its internal principles. ("Avoid poisons While positivists have long acknowledged that law's essential purpose is
however lethal if they cause the victim to vomit"....) But to call these principles to guide behavior through rules (e.g., John Austin writes that "[a] law ..
of the poisoner's art "the morality of poisoning" would simply blur the may be defined as a rule laid down for the guidance of an intelligent
distinction between the notion of efficiency for a purpose and those final being by an intelligent being having power over him" Austin 1977, p. 5),
judgments about activities and purposes with which morality in its various they have not always appreciated the implications of this purpose.
forms is concerned (Hart 1965, pp. 1285-86). Fuller's lasting contribution to the theory of law was to flesh out these
implications in the form of his principles of legality.
On Hart's view, all actions, including virtuous acts like lawmaking and
impermissible acts like poisoning, have their own internal standards of b. Positivism and Legal Principles
efficacy. But insofar as such standards of efficacy conflict with morality, Dworkin argues that, in deciding hard cases, judges often invoke legal
as they do in the case of poisoning, it follows that they are distinct from principles that do not derive their authority from an official act of
moral standards. Thus, while Hart concedes that something like Fuller's promulgation (Dworkin 1977, p. 40). These principles, Dworkin believes,
eight principles are built into the existence conditions for law, he must be characterized as law because judges are bound to consider them
concludes that they do not constitute a conceptual connection between when relevant. But if unpromulgated legal principles constitute law, then
law and morality. it is false, contra the pedigree thesis, that a proposition of law is valid
only in virtue of having been formally promulgated.
Unfortunately, Hart's response overlooks the fact that most of Fuller's According to Dworkin, principles and rules differ in the kind of guidance
eight principles double as moral ideals of fairness. For example, public they provide to judges:
promulgation in understandable terms may be a necessary condition for
efficacy, but it is also a moral ideal; it is morally objectionable for a state Rules are applicable in an all-or-nothing fashion. If the facts a rule stipulates are
to enforce rules that have not been publicly promulgated in terms given, then either the rule is valid, in which case the answer it supplies must be
reasonably calculated to give notice of what is required. Similarly, we accepted, or it is not, in which case it contributes nothing to the decision.... But
take it for granted that it is wrong for a state to enact retroactive rules, this is not the way principles operate.... [A principle] states a reason that argues
inconsistent rules, and rules that require what is impossible. Poisoning in one direction, but does not necessitate a particular decision (Dworkin 1977,
may have its internal standards of efficacy, but such standards are pp. 24-25).
distinguishable from the principles of legality in that they conflict with
moral ideals. On Dworkin's view, conflicting principles provide competing reasons
that must be weighed according to the importance of the respective
Nevertheless, Fuller's principles operate internally, not as moral ideals, values they express. Thus, rules are distinguishable from principles in
but merely as principles of efficacy. As Fuller would likely acknowledge, two related respects: (1) rules necessitate, where principles only suggest,
a particular outcome; and (2) principles have, where rules lack, the In response, positivists concede that there are legal principles, but argue
dimension of weight. that their authority as law can be explained in terms of the conventions
contained in the rule of recognition:
Dworkin cites the case of Riggs v. Palmer as representative of how judges
use principles to decide hard cases. In Riggs, the court considered the Legal principles, like other laws, can be enacted or repealed by legislatures and
question of whether a murderer could take under the will of his victim. administrative authorities. They can also become legally binding through
At the time the case was decided, neither the statutes nor the case law establishment by the courts. Many legal systems recognize that both rules and
governing wills expressly prohibited a murderer from taking under his principles can be made into law or lose their status as law through precedent
victim's will. Despite this, the court declined to award the defendant his (Raz 1972, p. 848).
gift under the will on the ground that it would be wrong to allow him to
profit from such a grievous wrong. On Dworkin's view, the court decided According to this view, legal principles are like legal rules in that both
the case by citing "the principle that no man may profit from his own derive their authority under the rule of recognition from the official acts
wrong as a background standard against which to read the statute of of courts and legislatures. If the Riggs principle that no person shall
wills and in this way justified a new interpretation of that statute" profit from her own wrong has legal authority, it is because that principle
(Dworkin 1977, p. 29). was either declared by a court in the course of adjudicating a dispute or
The positivist might respond that when the Riggs court considered this formally promulgated by the appropriate legislative body.
principle, it was reaching beyond the law to extralegal standards in the Further, inclusive positivists argue that Dworkin's account of principles
exercise of judicial discretion. But Dworkin points out that is itself consistent with the pedigree thesis. As Hart puts it, "this
the Riggs judges would "rightfully" have been criticized had they failed to interpretative test seems not to be an alternative to a criterion provided
consider this principle; if it were merely an extralegal standard, there by a rule of recognition, but ... only a complex 'soft-positivist' form of
would be no rightful grounds to criticize a failure to consider it (Dworkin such a criterion identifying principles by their content not by their
1977, p. 35). Accordingly, Dworkin concludes that the best explanation pedigree" (Hart 1994, p. 263). The idea, familiar from Section II, is that a
for the propriety of such criticism is that principles are part of the law. rule of recognition can incorporate content-based constraints on legal
Further, Dworkin maintains that the legal authority of standards like validity, even those rooted ultimately in morality.
the Riggs principle cannot derive from promulgation in accordance with
purely formal requirements: "[e]ven though principles draw support
from the official acts of legal institutions, they do not have a simple or
c. The Semantic Sting
direct enough connection with these acts to frame that connection in In Law's Empire, Dworkin distinguishes two kinds of disagreement legal
terms of criteria specified by some ultimate master rule of recognition" practitioners can have about the law. Lawyers can agree on the criteria a
(Dworkin 1977, p. 41). Unlike legal rules, legal principles lack a canonical rule must satisfy to be legally valid, but disagree on whether those
form and hence cannot be explained by formal promulgation. criteria are satisfied by a particular rule. For example, two lawyers might
On Dworkin's view, the legal authority of a binding principle derives agree that a rule is valid if enacted by the state legislature, but disagree
from the contribution it makes to the best moral justification for a on whether the rule at issue was actually enacted by the state legislature.
society's legal practices considered as a whole. According to Dworkin, a Such disagreements are empirical in nature and hence pose no
legal principle maximally contributes to such a justification if and only if theoretical difficulties for positivism.
it satisfies two conditions: (1) the principle coheres with existing legal There is, however, a second kind of disagreement that Dworkin believes
materials; and (2) the principle is the most morally attractive standard is inconsistent with positivism. Lawyers often agree on the facts about a
that satisfies (1). The correct legal principle is the one that makes the law rule's creation, but disagree on whether those facts are sufficient to
the moral best it can be. Thus, Dworkin concludes, "if we treat principles endow the rule with legal authority. Such disagreement is considerably
as law we must reject the positivists' first tenet, that the law of a deeper than empirical disagreement as it concerns the criteria for legal
community is distinguished from other social standards by some test in validity-which, according to positivism, are exhausted by the rule of
the form of a master rule" (Dworkin 1977, p. 44). recognition. Dworkin calls this second kind of disagreement theoretical
disagreement about the law.
Theoretical disagreement, on Dworkin's view, is inconsistent with the On Dworkin's view, the requirements of a social rule cannot be uncertain
pedigree thesis because the pedigree thesis explains the concept of law in since a social rule is constituted by acceptance and conforming behavior
terms of shared criteria for creating, changing and adjudicating law: by most people in the relevant group: "two people whose rules differ ...
cannot be appealing to the same social rule, and at least one of them
If legal argument is mainly or even partly about [the properties that make a cannot be appealing to any social rule at all" (Dworkin 1977, p. 55).
proposition legally valid], then lawyers cannot all be using the same factual
criteria for deciding when propositions of law are true and false. Their Jules Coleman responds that if the rule of recognition is a social rule,
arguments would be mainly or partly about which criteria they should use. So then Hart's view implies there must be general agreement among the
the project of the semantic theories, the project of digging out shared rules from officials of a legal system about what standards constitute the rule of
a careful study of what lawyers say and do, would be doomed to fail (Dworkin recognition, but it does not imply there cannot be disagreement as to
1986, p. 43). what those standards require in any given instance:

If lawyers disagree about the criteria of legal validity, then the grounds of The controversy among judges does not arise over the content of the rule of
legal validity cannot be exhausted by the shared criteria contained in a recognition itself. It arises over which norms satisfy the standards set forth in it.
rule of recognition. The semantic sting, then, implies that there must be The divergence in behavior among officials as exemplified in their identifying
more to the concept of legal validity than can be explained by different standards as legal ones does not establish their failure to accept the
promulgation in accordance with shared criteria embodied in a rule of same rule of recognition. On the contrary, judges accept the same truth
recognition. conditions for propositions of law.... They disagree about which propositions
satisfy those conditions (Coleman 1982, p. 156).
The semantic sting resembles one of Dworkin's earlier criticisms of
Hart's pedigree thesis. Hart believes that the rule of recognition is a Coleman, then, distinguishes two kinds of disagreement practitioners
social rule and is hence constituted by the conforming behavior of people can have about the rule of recognition: (1) disagreement about what
who also accept the rule as a ground for criticizing deviations. Like all standards constitute the rule of recognition; and (2) disagreement about
social rules, then, the rule of recognition has an external and internal what propositions satisfy those standards. On Coleman's view, Hart's
aspect. The external aspect of the rule of recognition consists in general analysis of social rules implies only that (1) is impossible.
obedience to those rules satisfying its criteria of validity; the internal
aspect is constituted by its acceptance as a public standard of official Under the U.S. rule of recognition, for example, a federal statute is
behavior. Hart believes it is this double aspect of the rule of recognition legally valid if and only if it has been enacted in accordance with the
that accounts for its normativity and enables him to distinguish his procedural requirements described in the body of the Constitution and is
theory from Austin's view of law as a system of coercive commands. For, consistent with the first fourteen amendments. Since, on Hart's view, the
as Hart points out, a purely coercive command can oblige, but never U.S. rule of recognition is a social rule, U.S. officials must agree on the
obligate, a person to comply (see Section I, supra). procedures the federal government must follow in enacting law, the set
Dworkin argues that this feature of Hart's theory commits him to the of sentences constituting the first fourteen amendments, and the
claim that there cannot be any disagreement about the content of rule of requirement that federal enactments be consistent with those
recognition: amendments.

Hart's qualification ... that the rule of recognition may be uncertain at particular But Hart's view of social rules does not imply there cannot be any
points ... undermines [his theory].... If judges are in fact divided about what they disagreement about whether a given enactment is consistent with the
must do if a subsequent Parliament tries to repeal an entrenched rule, then it is first fourteen amendments. Legal practitioners can and do disagree on
not uncertain whether any social rule [of recognition] governs that decision; on what Hart calls penumbral (or borderline) issues regarding the various
the contrary, it is certain that none does (Dworkin 1977, pp. 61-62). amendments. While every competent practitioner in the U.S. would
agree, for example, that torturing a person to induce a confession
violates the fifth amendment right against self-incrimination, there is The problem, on Dworkin's view, is that many difficult appellate cases
considerable disagreement about whether compelling a defendant to like Riggs involve theoretical disagreement about pivotal cases:
undergo a psychiatric examination for the purpose of increasing her The various judges who argued about our sample cases did not think they were
sentence also violates that right. On Coleman's view, there is nothing in defending marginal or borderline claims. Their disagreements about legislation
Hart's analysis of social rules that precludes such borderline and precedent were fundamental; their arguments showed that they disagreed
disagreements about whether a practice is consistent with the Fifth not only about whether Elmer should have his inheritance, but about why any
Amendment. legislative act, even traffic codes and rates of taxation, impose the rights and
obligations everyone agrees they do.... They disagreed about what makes a
Despite its resemblance to this earlier criticism, Dworkin's semantic proposition of law true not just at the margin but in the core as well (Dworkin
sting argument takes aim at a deeper target. The semantic sting targets 1986, pp. 42-43).
all so-called semantic theories of law that articulate the concept of law in
terms of "shared rules ... that set out criteria that supply the word's On Dworkin's view, the judges in Riggs were not having a borderline
meaning" (Dworkin 1986, p. 31). Thus, while the earlier criticism is dispute about some accepted criterion for the application of the concept
directed at Hart's extraneous account of social rules, the semantic sting of law. Rather, they were having a disagreement about the status of some
is directed at what Dworkin takes to be the very heart of positivism's putatively fundamental criterion itself: the majority believed, while the
theoretical core, namely, the claim that there are shared criteria that dissent denied, that courts have power to modify unambiguous
exhaust the conditions for the correct application of the concept of law. legislative enactments.
Accordingly, theoretical disagreement about pivotal cases like Riggs is
inconsistent with semantic theories of law, on Dworkin's view, because it
At the root of the problem with semantic theories, on Dworkin's view, is
shows that shared criteria do not exhaust the proper conditions for the
a flawed theory of what makes disagreement possible. According to
application of the concept of law. For the majority and dissenting judges
Dworkin, semantic theories mistakenly assume that meaningful
in Riggs were having a sensible disagreement about law even though it
disagreement is impossible unless "we all accept and follow the same
centered on a pivotal case involving the criteria of legal validity. Thus,
criteria for deciding when our claims are sound, even if we cannot state
Dworkin concludes, the concept of law cannot be explained by so-called
exactly, as a philosopher might hope to do, what these criteria are"
criterial semantics.
(Dworkin 1986, p. 45). On this flawed assumption, two people whose
In response, Hart denies both that his theory is a semantic theory and
concepts of law differ cannot be disagreeing about the same thing.
that it assumes such an account of what makes disagreement possible:

Perhaps with Coleman's response to his earlier criticism in mind,


[N]othing in my book or in anything else I have written supports [a semantic
Dworkin concedes that semantic theories are consistent with theoretical
account] of my theory. Thus, my doctrine that developed municipal legal
disagreements about borderline or penumbral cases: "people do
systems contain a rule of recognition specifying the criteria for the identification
sometimes speak at cross-purposes in the way the borderline defense
of the laws which courts have to apply may be mistaken, but I nowhere base
describes" (Dworkin 1986, p. 41). But Dworkin denies semantic theories
this doctrine on the mistaken idea that it is part of the meaning of the word 'law'
are consistent with theoretical disagreement about pivotal (or core)
that there should be such a rule of recognition in all legal systems, or on the
cases. According to semantic theories, he says,
even more mistaken idea that if the criteria for the identification of the grounds
of law were not uncontroversially fixed, 'law' would mean different things to
[Y]ou and I can sensibly discuss how many books I have on my shelf, for different people (Hart 1994, p. 246).
example, only if we both agree, at least roughly, about what a book is. We can
disagree over borderline cases: I may call something a slim book that you would Instead, Hart argues that his theory of law is "a descriptive account of
call a pamphlet. But we cannot disagree over what I called pivotal cases. If you the distinctive features of law in general as a complex social
do not count my copy of Moby-Dick as a book because in your view novels are phenomenon" (Hart 1994, p. 246). Hart presents his theory, not as an
not books, any disagreement is bound to be senseless (Dworkin 1986, p. 45). account of how people apply the concept of law, but rather as an account
of what distinguishes systems of law from other systems of social rules.
On Hart's view, it is the presence of a rule of recognition establishing
criteria of validity that distinguishes law from other systems of social
rules. Thus, according to Hart, Dworkin's criticism fails because it
mischaracterizes positivism as providing a criterial explanation of the
concept of law.

Potrebbero piacerti anche