Sei sulla pagina 1di 9

TIME IN PHYSICS

Alan Bass. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. Phenomenology of Perception.
[1972]. Translated by Colin Smith. London: Routledge, 1962 [1945].
Derrida, Jacques. Speech and Phenomena, and Other Essays on Negri, Antonio. Time for Revolution. Translated by Matteo
Husserls Theory of Signs. Translated by David Allison. Mandarini. London: Continuum International, 2004.
Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1973 [1967]. Pggeler, Otto. Pathways of Time. The Paths of Heideggers
Durie, Robin, ed. Time and the Instant: Essays in the Physics Life and Thought. Translated by J. Bailiff. Amherst, NY:
and Philosophy of Time. Manchester, U.K.: Clinamen Press, Humanities Press, 1998.
2000. Protevi, John. Time and Exteriority. Lewisburg, PA: Bucknell
Gallagher, Shaun. The Inordinance of Time. Evanston, IL: University Press, 1995.
Northwestern University Press, 1998. Ricoeur, Paul. Time and Narrative. Vols. 13. Translated by
Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. Translated by J. Kathleen McLaughlin and David Pellauer. Chicago:
Macquarrie and E. Robinson. (Especially sections 65, 69, University of Chicago Press, 1990 [1983].
7881), New York: Harper, 1962 [1927]. Sallis, John. Time Out In Echoes: After Heidegger, 4475.
Heidegger, Martin. Contributions to Philosophy: From Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1990.
Enowning. Translated by Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly. Sartre, Jean-Paul. Being and Nothingness. Translated by Hazel
Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1999 [1989]. E. Barnes. New York: Washington Square Press, 1993 [1943].
Heidegger, Martin. History of the Concept of Time: Von Herrmann, Friedrich-Wilhelm. Being and Time and The
Prolegomena. Translated by Theodore Kisiel. (Sections 13, Basic Problems of Phenomenology. Translated by Parvis
18, 3236.), Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1985 Emad and Kenneth Maly. In Reading Heidegger:
[1979]. Commemorations, edited by John Sallis, 118135.
Heidegger, Martin. On Time and Being. Translated by Joan Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1993.
Stambaugh. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002 Wood, David. Reiterating the Temporal: Toward a Rethinking
[1969]. of Heidegger on Time. In Reading Heidegger:
Heidegger, Martin. The Basic Problems of Phenomenology. Commemorations, edited by J. Sallis, 136159. Bloomington:
Translated by Albert Hofstadter. Bloomington: Indiana Indiana University Press, 1993.
University Press, 1982 [1975]. (Especially sections 1922). Wood, David. The Deconstruction of Time. Evanston, IL:
Heidegger, Martin. The Concept of Time. Translated by W. Northwestern University Press, 2001 [1989].
McNeill. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1992 [1989].
Heidegger, Martin. The Concept of Time in the Science of Heath Massey and Leonard Lawlor (2005)
History (1915). Translated by H. S. Taylor, H. W.
Uffelmann, and J. Van Buren. In Supplements, edited by John
Van Buren, 4960. Albany: State University of New York
Press, 2002. time in physics
Heidegger, Martin. Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics.
Translated by Richard Taft, Bloomington: Indiana University No one conception of time emerges from a study of
Press, 1997 [1929]. physics. Ones understanding of physical time changes as
Husserl, Edmund. Concerning the Phenomenology of Internal science itself changes, either through the development of
Time Consciousness, Husserliana. Vol. 10. Translated by John
B. Brough; edited by Rudolf Boehm. Dordrecht: Kluwer
new theories or through new interpretations of a theory.
Academic, 1990 [1928]. Each of these changes and resulting theories of time has
Husserl, Edmund. Die Bernauer Manuscripte ber das been the subject of philosophical scrutiny, so there are
Zeitbewutseins (1917/1918), Husserliana. Vol. 33, edited by many philosophical controversies internal to particular
R. Bernet and D. Lohmar. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, physical theories. For instance, the move to special rela-
2001.
tivity gave rise to debates about the nature of simultane-
Husserl, Edmund. Logical Investigations. Vols. 1 and 2.
Translated by J. N. Findlay; edited by Dermot Moran. ity within the theory itself, such as whether simultaneity
London: Routledge, 2001 [1900/01]. is conventional. Nevertheless, there are some philosophi-
Kisiel, Theodore The Genesis of Heideggers Being and Time. cal puzzles that appear at every stage of the development
Part III. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993. of physics. Perhaps most generally, there is the perennial
Levinas, Emmanuel. Time and the Other. Translated by Richard question, Is there a gap between the conception of time
Cohen. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1987 [1947]. as found in physics and the conception of time as found
Levinas, Emmanuel. Totality and Infinity. Translated by
Alphonso Lingis. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press,
in philosophy?
1969 [1961]. One can understand all of these changes and contro-
McCumber, John Time in the Ditch: American Philosophy and versies as debates over what properties should be attrib-
the McCarthy Era. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University
uted to time. The history of the concept of time in physics
Press, 2001.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. Adventures of the Dialectic. Translated
can then be understood as the history of addition and
by Joseph Bien. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, subtraction of these properties, and the philosophical
1973 [1955]. controversies thus understood as debates about particular

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY
2nd edition 493
TIME IN PHYSICS

additions and subtractions. Just as one may take a set of topology


numbers and impose structure on this set to form the real Topological properties are those that are invariant under
number line, one may also take the set of moments or smooth transformations. Technically, these transforma-
events (which will be used interchangeably) and impose tions are one-to-one and bicontinuous; and what they
various types of structure on this set. Each property leave invariant is the so-called neighborhood structure
attributed to time corresponds to the imposition of a that is given by picking out a family of open subsets
kind of structure upon this set of events, making sense of closed under the operations of union and finite intersec-
different claims about time. Let us begin with a bare set of tion. Intuitively, the transformations that leave this struc-
events and successively add structure to this set. In par- ture unchanged correspond to operations such as
ticular, it helps to differentiate ordering properties, topo- stretching or shrinking, as opposed to operations such as
logical properties, and metrical properties of time. ripping and gluing. A coffee cup and a doughnut are,
topologically speaking, the same shape; if made out of an
order infinitely pliable rubber, one could be smoothly trans-
It seems clear that different times are ordered to some formed into the other. Being closed like a circle, having an
extent. Intuitively, one can give a set an order by making edge, and being one-dimensional are examples of topo-
sense of what times are between what other times. The logical properties. No amount of stretching and shrink-
time the cake baked is between the time of mixing the ing can (for instance) make the circle into a line, make an
ingredients and the time of eating the cake; eating the edge disappear, or make a one-dimensional set two-
cake is between the baking and the feeling full, and so on. dimensional.
One can therefore impose an ordering on this set of Many issues in the philosophy of time are in fact
events by adding a ternary between-ness relation of the questions about the topology of time: is time closed or
form: x is between y and z defined for some or all open? discrete? branching? two-dimensional? oriented
moments in the set. If betweenness is defined for some (directed)? Formally, the answers to these questions are
but not all distinct triples of moments, then it can be said determined by the topological structure of time.
that one has a partially ordered set; if betweenness is
defined for every triple of the set, then it can be said that metric
one has a totally ordered set. Newtonian physics, as will be
Once topological structure is added to the set of times,
shown, totally orders classes of simultaneous events. Rel-
most temporal properties are determined. However, there
ativistic physics, by contrast, will only partially order the
is still a major one remaining: duration. Of the set {t1, t2,
set of all events.
t3} it is still not known whether t2 is as far from t1 as it
Between-ness as defined above is not always suffi- is from t3even after all topological properties are speci-
ciently powerful to order topologically nontrivial sets. To fied. The temporal distance between two moments is not
see this, consider a circle with four members of the set on a topological invariant, for it can be smoothly stretched
it: 1 at twelve oclock, 2 at three oclock, 3 at six or shrunk. To capture the idea of temporal distance, a
oclock, and 4 at nine oclock. Because the set is closed, metric must be put on the topological structure. The tem-
2 is between 1 and 3, between 3 and 4, and between 1 and poral metric is a function that gives one a number, the
4. Consequently, the between-ness relation is blind to the temporal distance or duration, between any pair of times.
difference between this layout and the same but with 3 (In relativity what is imposed instead is a spacetime met-
at three oclock and 2 at six oclock. For such sets more ric; see below.)
machinery is needed to order the set. In principle, an infinite number of possible metrics
An ordering does not disclose much about the set of are mathematically possible. One might choose a metric
moments, {t1, t2, t3}. It does not imply whether t2 is as that makes the duration between 1980 and 1990 twice the
far from t1 as from t3. Nor does it imply a direction, duration between 1990 and 2000. However, such a choice
whether times goes from t1 to t3 or t3 to t1. Although the would make a mess of almost all of science. It would
baking example suggests a natural direction to the set of entail, for instance, that the earth went twice as fast
times, an ordering is strictly independent of a direction. around the sun in the 1990s as it did in the 1980s. One
Nor does the ordering specify the dimensionality of the would then have to adjust the rest of physics so as to be
set or most other properties one normally attributes to compatible with this result. As Hans Reichenbach
time. The next level of structure, topology, will help make stresses, there are simpler and more complex choices of
sense of some of these attributions to time. temporal metric.

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY
494 2nd edition
TIME IN PHYSICS

time in classical physics from the ground and forming perfect vases while a bull
Time in classical physics is normally assumed to have the backs out of a china shop.
ordering, topological, and metrical structure of the real
number line. That is, it is one-dimensional, continuous, time in special relativity
infinite in both directions, and so on. The temporal met- In classical physics, material processes take place on a
ric is just the one used for the real line: between any two background arena of space and time, described above.
times, a and b, the duration is ba. Time in classical The move from classical physics to special relativity is
physics does have a number of remarkable properties, of usually taken as a change in the background arena from
which three will be mentioned here. The first two concern classical space and time to the spacetime of Hermann
the metrical properties of time, whereas the third is more Minkowski. This new entity, spacetime, is fundamental,
a property of the dynamics than of time itself. and space and time only exist in a derivative fashion. On
First, the metric of time is independent of the metric this conception, there is not one metric for time and
of space. This feature implies that the amount of time another for space; rather, there is one spacetime metric
between any two events is path-independent: if persons A supplying spatiotemporal distances between four-dimen-
and B leave an event e1 and then meet at a later event e2, sional events. These spacetime distances are invariant
the amount of time that has elapsed for A is equal to the properties of the spacetime. Time can be decoupled from
amount of time that has elapsed for B. The distinct spa- space only in an observer-dependent way; each distinct
tial distances traveled by A and B are irrelevant to how possible inertial observer (one who feels no forces) carves
much time has passed between e1 and e2. up spacetime into space and time in a different way. In a
sense, there is no such thing as time in Minkowski space-
Second, simultaneity is absolute. Before explaining
time, if by time one conceives of something fundamen-
absolute, consider the simultaneous with relation. For
tal.
any event e, there is a whole class of events that are simul-
taneous with e. Indeed, the simultaneous with relation There are, however, two times in Minkowski space-
is an equivalence relation in classical physics. Equivalence time that correspond to different aspects of classical time,
relations are reflexive, symmetric, and transitive; for this namely, coordinate time and proper time. Let us take
example, what is important is that they partition a set coordinate time first. Think of an arrow in three-dimen-
into disjoint subsets. Hence the simultaneous with rela- sional Euclidean space. One can decompose this arrow
tion partitions the set of all events into proper subsets, all relative to an arbitrary basis {x,y,z} by measuring how far
of whose members are simultaneous with one another. It the arrow extends in the x-direction, how far in the y-
is these classes of simultaneous events, rather than the direction, and how far in the z-direction, where x, y, and
events themselves, that are totally ordered. What is inter- z are perpendicular, and the arrows base lies at the origin.
esting about this partition in classical physics is that it is The same arrow would decompose differently in a differ-
unique. Classical physics states that every observer, no ent basis {x',y',z'}. As one can decompose a vector in
matter their state of motion, in principle agrees on Euclidean space along indefinitely many different bases,
whether any two events are simultaneous. This observa- so too can one decompose a four-dimensional spacetime
tion translates into only one partition (or foliation) being vector along many different bases in Minkowski space-
the right one. In this sense simultaneity is absoluteit time. Mathematically, coordinate time in special relativity
does not depend on ones frame of reference but is an is just one component of an invariant spacetime four-
observer-independent fact of the Newtonian world. vector, just as y is one component of a Euclidean spatial
Third, classical physics is time reversal invariant. vector. In the Euclidean case, the value of the arrow along
Consider a sequence of particle positions over time, the first component of the decomposition varies with
(x1,t1), (x2,t2), (x3,t3)(xn,tn). The fundamental classical basis; so too in spacetime, the value of the first compo-
laws of evolution are such that if this sequence is a solu- nenthere, coordinate timevaries with frame of refer-
tion of the laws, then so is the time-reversed sequence ence.
(xn,tn)(x3,t3), (x2,t2), (x1,t1). The classical laws are invari- The second bit of residue of the classical time is the
ant under the transformation of t for t. This is true also so-called proper time. The proper time is a kind of
of arbitrarily large multi-particle systems and even of parameter associated with individual trajectories in
classical fields. If a bull entering a china shop and subse- spacetime. It is often thought of as a kind of clock tied to
quently breaking vases is a lawful history, then so is a an object through its motion. This time is a scalarthat
bunch of scattered vase shards spontaneously jumping is, just a numberand as such is an invariant of the

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY
2nd edition 495
TIME IN PHYSICS

spacetime. All observers will agree on the value of proper fact. Only the timelike related events are invariantly
time for A as he travels from e1 to e2; all will agree on the ordered.
value of proper time for B as she travels from e1 to e2; and Third, and perhaps most famously, in a sense time
all will agree that these values will not be the same if they passes more slowly for a moving observer than for one at
take different paths. Unlike with classical time, the tem- rest. Consider two inertial observers, A and B, traveling at
poral distance in Minkowski space is not independent of a constant velocity relative to one another, and let a clock
spatial distance. The amount of time between any two be at rest in As frame. Looking at the ticks of the clock,
events is path-dependent: if persons A and B leave an the special relativistic metric entails that B will conclude
event e1 and then meet at a later event e2, the amount of that the clock in As frame is running slow. This effect,
time that has elapsed for A is in general not equal to the known as time dilation, is entirely symmetrical: A would
amount of time that has elapsed for B. Spatial distances find a clock at rest in Bs frame to be running slow, too.
can only be completely disentangled from temporal dis- Time dilation has many experimentally confirmed pre-
tance in a given inertial frame of reference. dictions, such as that atomic clocks on planes tick slowly
Time in classical physics plays the role of coordinate relative to clocks on land and that mesons have longer
time and the role of proper time. A little reflection reveals lifetimes than they should from the earths frame of ref-
that it can accomplish this task because in classical erence.
physics the amount of time between any two events is
path-independent. time in general relativity
Three consequences of the shift to special relativity General relativity, unlike special relativity, treats the phe-
ought to be highlighted. First, simultaneity is not absolute nomenon of gravitation. It famously does away with
in Minkowski spacetime. Simultaneity is a temporal fea- Newtons gravitational force, understanding gravitational
ture, yet the temporal does not disentangle from the spa- phenomena as instead a manifestation of spacetime cur-
tial except within an inertial reference frame. What events vature. Loosely put, the idea is that matter curves space-
are simultaneous with one another is observer-depend- time and spacetime curvature explains the gravitational
ent. Given spacelike-related events e1 and e2, inertial aspects of matter in motion. Hence the largest conceptual
observer A may (rightly) say they are simultaneous difference between special and general relativity is that
whereas inertial observer B, traveling at a constant veloc- Minkowski spacetime is flat whereas general relativistic
ity with respect to A, may (rightly) say e1 is earlier than e2. spacetimes may be curved in an indefinite number of
In Minkowski spacetime, they do not disagree over any ways. Otherwise, as regards time, again there is a division
observer-independent fact of the matter. In terms of the between coordinate time and proper time, no privileged
earlier discussion, it can then be said that the simultane- foliation of spacetime, only a partial temporal ordering,
ous with relation partitions Minkowski spacetime, but and the possibility of time dilation.
only within a frame of reference. In terms of the previous division, curvature is a met-
Second, the temporal ordering in Minkowski space- rical property, so the primary difference between special
time is partial, not total. The only temporal ordering that and general relativity is that the formers metric is merely
all observers agree on is the ordering among timelike one of the many possible metrics allowed by the latter.
events. Timelike related events are those that are in prin- General relativity places various constraints between the
ciple connectible by any particle going slower than the spacetime metric, or geometry, and the distribution of
speed of light in a vacuum. Think of all the events that matter-energy. Thinking of these constraints as the laws
can be reached from any given event that way. Consider of general relativity, general relativity claims a variety of
the event of your elementary school graduation (e1) and spacetime geometries are physically possible. Because
the event of your high school graduation (e2). Obviously these different metrics allow and sometimes demand dif-
sub-luminal particles could make it from one to the ferent topologies and even orderings, time may have dra-
other; for instance, you are a set of such particles. Due to matically different ordering, topological, and metrical
the finite speed of light, however, there are many events properties depending on the spacetime model. Some con-
that such particles could not reachfor example, what- sequences of this fact are especially worthy of note.
ever was going on at Alpha Centuri simultaneous with (in First, there are spacetimes without a single global
your reference frame) e2. What happened on Alpha Cen- moment. In special relativity, simultaneity was observer-
turi simultaneous with e2 is not an observer-independent dependent. Minkowski spacetime could be carved up, or
fact. But that e2 follows e1 is an observer-independent foliated, into a succession of three-dimensional spaces

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY
496 2nd edition
TIME IN PHYSICS

evolving along a one-dimensional time an indefinite from a study of physics. On the horizon of research are
number of waysa distinct foliation for every possible the various programs of quantum gravity, the would-be
inertial observer. Though this may also be the case in gen- theory that unifies or at least makes consistent our best
eral relativity, there are spacetime models that prohibit theory of matter, quantum field theory, and the best the-
even one foliation of spacetime into space and time. The ory of spacetime, general relativity. Though speculative,
famous Gdel spacetime, named after the great logician virtually all of these programs are entertaining dramatic
Kurt Gdel, is an example of such a spacetime. Due to the changes for the conception of spacetime, ranging from
effects of curvature, in such spacetimes it is impossible to the idea that spacetime is discrete to the idea that time is
find even a single global always-spatial three-dimensional an emergent property arising from some more funda-
surface. There is no global moment of time in such space- mental stuff.
times. There is no way to conceive of world history, in
such a spacetime, as the successive marching of three-
philosophical controversies
dimensional surfaces through time.
There are many philosophical problems concerning time
Second, perhaps most famously, general relativity
in physics. Philosophers have discussed the physical pos-
has models that permit interesting time travel. In these
sibility of time travel in general relativity, the possibility
models a traveler can start off at event e, and by traveling
of discrete time, the nature of time reversal invariance,
always to the local future (that is, into es future light-
the possibility of backward causation in physics, such as
cone), eventually come back to events that are to es past
(that is, in es past lightcone). Indeed, these models will in the Wheeler-Feynman time-symmetric version of elec-
allow one to travel back to an earlier event: an observers tromagnetism, the possibility of time emerging from
worldline may intersect e, and then after some proper something more fundamental in quantum gravity, and
time has elapsed, intersect e again. These causal loops more. In addition, it will not be surprising that many top-
are called closed timelike curves. Of the many models ics typically dealt with in the context of space also have
that allow time travel, the Gdel model is again remark- temporal counterparts. The absolute-versus-relational
able for it allows the time traveler the fullest menu of pos- debate, famously discussed by Gottfried Leibniz and
sibilities: in the model, it is possible (given enough time Samuel Clarke and more than a hundred authors there-
and energy) to get from any event e1 to any other event e2 after, is often discussed in the classical context of space;
on the entire spacetime, including the case where e1=e2. but those arguments apply equally well to the case of
time, and in the modern version of the debate, to space-
Third, whether time is infinite or finite can be an
time. And the many deliberations surrounding the con-
observer-dependent fact. When discussing Minkowski
ventionality of the metric apply just as well to the
spacetime it was noted that there are different ways to
temporal metric as the spatial metric (and of course the
decompose spacetime into space and time; alternatively,
spacetime metric). Here the discussion focuses on
there are generally many ways to foliate a spacetime.
When nontrivial topologies are considered, there are whether physical time captures all the fundamental prop-
spacetimes consistent with general relativity that make erties of time and the so-called problem of the direction
whether time is infinite or finite a foliation-dependent of time.
matter. That is, there are foliations of one and the same
spacetime that make time finite and foliations that make tense
time infinite. In spacetimes admitting two such foliations, In the famous terminology of J. E. McTaggart, the tempo-
the age-old question of whether time is finite or infinite ral relations of earlier than, later than, and simultaneous
would be answered with a convention. In such a world with are called B-properties and the monadic proper-
there is no coordinate-independent fact of the matter ties of past-ness, present-ness, and futurity are called A-
regarding how long time persists. The universe might last properties. Those who argue that the B-properties are
an infinite amount of time according to one coordiniza-
the fundamental features of time are dubbed advocates of
tion, or language, and a finite amount of time according
the tenseless theory of time; those who argue that
to another coordinization, or language.
instead the A-properties are fundamental are dubbed
advocates of the tensed theory of time. Much of the
time in future physical theories work in philosophy of time, especially throughout the
As mentioned, because physical theories are always twentieth century, can be described as a debate between
changing, there is no one conception of time emerging tensers and detensers.

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY
2nd edition 497
TIME IN PHYSICS

Because the categories tensed and tenseless are FLOW OR BECOMING. Physical theory also does not
broad umbrellas covering many different doctrines, it is describe a property corresponding to the flow of time or
probably best not to think of this as one debate. A better to a process of becoming. Again, the different events are
way to frame the debate is to conceive it on the model of ordered, have a certain distance from one another, and so
the debate between mind-body dualists and materialists. on, but there does not seem to be anything that flows
Dualists find the description of the mind by the natural (such as the Now). Nor is there a distinction made among
sciences to be either incomplete or simply wrong. Various events, such that it makes sense to talk about the Now
features of mental statesfor example, consciousness turning an unreal future real. Again, some philosophers
are said to be either left out or indescribable by these nat- argue, based on experience or the study of various puz-
ural sciences. Materialists counter either by denying the zles, that there is genuine becoming in the world. C. D.
reality of these features or by explaining why the natural Broad, for example, proposed a model wherein the past
sciences do manage to explain such features. and present are real and the future successively becomes
present and hence real.
One can conceive the debate regarding time in the
same mold. Though the features attributed to time vary TIMES ARROW. If physical time is time-reversal invari-
with physical theory, some philosophers feel that physical ant, then nowhere does it distinguish one direction of
theory has consistently missed out on one or more essen- time. But there are many asymmetric processes: physical
tial properties of time. Physical theory orders some or all ones, such as the radiation and thermodynamic asymme-
of the events in time, just as the relations of right and left tries; metaphysical ones, such as the asymmetry of causa-
order events in space. In classical (relativistic) physics, for tion and of counterfactual dependence; epistemological
any (some) pair of events, e1, e2, physical theory states ones, such as that one typically knows more about the
whether e1 is earlier, later, or simultaneous with e2. The past than the future; and emotional ones, such as that
theories use relational temporal properties and not people usually care more about the future than the past.
monadic ones. One can of course say e1 is to the past of To explain one or more of these asymmetries, some
e2, but that is just to say that e1 is earlier than e2. Physical philosophers have posited a directionality to physical
theory seems to require only tenseless temporal relations. time. Others answer that that the physical asymmetries
Broadly speaking, the debate is between those who would do not themselves need explanation and that they in turn
add some metaphysical feature to time as it is found in can explain the other asymmetries. To mention one pos-
science and those who would not. Various arguments are sible sequence of moves, one might try to show that the
adduced to show that such features are needed or not thermodynamic and radiative temporal asymmetries
needed, compatible with science or incompatible, and so explain the memory asymmetry (people have memories
on. Consider now three features often felt to be left out by of the past, not the future), the memory asymmetry
physical time. explains the knowledge asymmetry, and the knowledge
asymmetry explains the psychological asymmetry.
THE PRESENT. Physical theory does not identify which There are also two famous conceptual arguments
time is Now. That is, it judges which events are earlier, against the idea that time itself flows (and depending on
later, and simultaneous with which other events, but it the model of becoming, against becoming). One, McTag-
fails to mention which among all sets of events are the garts Paradox, claims that the idea of time flowing leads
present ones. Some philosophers argue, based on experi- to a logical contradiction. Essential to the idea that time
ence, analysis of ordinary language, or study of puzzles flows, says McTaggart, is the idea that events change their
surrounding change, that physical theory misses out on a A-properties: for instance, the event of Socratess death
genuine property of time, Now-ness. Others reply that was future, then present, and then past. So every event has
the idea of a metaphysically special present is wrong- all three monadic properties. But this is in straightfor-
headed. Linguistic features of the now are explained via ward conflict with the claim if an event is future it is not
the properties of indexicals in general. Because one would past. McTaggart and his supporters claim that any way of
not reify the here, one should not reify the now. Attempts discharging the contradiction by insisting that events are
are then made to show that the language, thought, and not at the same time past, present, and future leads to
behavior attributing objectivity to the present can be infinite regress.
explained by facts about human beings and their typical Another argument, by the philosophers C. D. Broad
physical environments. and J. J. C. Smart, begins by noting that change is always

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY
498 2nd edition
TIME IN PHYSICS

the change of some property with respect to time. Move- lar spacetime model and what one means by privileged.
ment, for example, is having different locations at differ- In some models, ones with realistic distributions of mat-
ent times. So if time flowsif, say, the Present ter and energy, one can define a global cosmic time. Cos-
movesthen Broad and Smart suggest that it must be mic time is defined with respect to the mean motion of
that the Present moves with respect to time. But this time, matter. The possibility exists of a tenser using cosmic
Smart claims, must be a hyper-time; and if this hyper- time, which mimics some features of classical time, as the
time is a kind of time, it must flow with respect to a time of becoming, passage, and so on. Challenges to this
hyper-hyper-time, and so on. There are too many use include the fact that cosmic time can only be defined
responses to this argument to consider them all here. in some subset of the solutions to Einsteins field equa-
It should not be surprising that considerations from tions, and questions of arbitrariness in the choice of a
physics enter these debates. cosmic time function.
With the possibility of cosmic time in mind, Kurt
special relativity and tense Gdel argued that general relativity, far from rescuing
Some also argue that a metaphysically distinguished pres- tenses, in fact showed that time is ideal, or not funda-
ent is inconsistent with special relativity. The reason is mental. Reflecting on the odd eponymous spacetime
obvious: since simultaneity is relative, how can a monadic mentioned above, Gdel states that it is obvious that time
feature of events such as presentness be frame-depend- does not flow in the spacetime he discovered. But that
ent? In Minkowski spacetime, there will be cases where means, Gdel says, that time does not flow in the space-
for observer O1, e1 is present and e2 is later, whereas for time of the actual world either. Why? In brief, his idea is
observer O2, e2 is present and e1 is later. Assuming pre- that time flow should not be contingent, yet because
sentness is not frame-dependent, there appears to be a Gdel spacetime enjoys the same laws of nature as does
contradiction. This argument, originally made by Hilary the actual world, it differs from this world only in the
Putnam and C. W. Rietdijk, also would affect positions contingent distribution of matter and energy. Indeed,
claiming time flows, if the flowing is done by a unique Gdel goes so far as to presume times flow is essential to
present. Even if correct, by itself this argument does not time, and hence concludes that Gdel spacetime shows
tell how to arrange the conflict into premises and conclu- that there is no such thing as time in this world.
sion. Does relativity disprove the present or does the pres-
ent disprove relativity? Naturalistically inclined the problem of the direction of
philosophers are loath to consider the latter reading; but time
strictly speaking, if there were enough prior reason to So far this entry has described issues concerning time in
believe in a privileged present, then alternatives to fundamental or near-fundamental physics. There also
Minkowski spacetime would need to be considered exists a philosophical problem arising from an apparent
such as embedding relativistic phenomena in classical conflict between the way microphysics seems to treat time
space and time in the manner H. A. Lorentz favored. and the way macroscopic physics treats time. While
microphysics may be time reversal invariant, the physics
general relativity and tense describing macroscopic behavior such as the warming or
From the perspective of general relativity, the attack on cooling of bodies to room temperature, the expansion of
tenses from special relativity seems rather limited. gases, and so on, is not time reversal invariant. Consider
Minkowski spacetime may locally be a good approxima- the volume of an initially localized sample of a light gas
tion to whatever the true global spacetime is, but strictly released in the corner of a room. As time goes on, it will
speaking special relativity is only valid on planes that are spread through its available volume: (v1, t1) (v2, t2) (v3,
tangent to mere points of the general relativistic geome- t3), where v3>v2v1 and t3>t2>t1, and so on. While classi-
try. There appears no particular reason to think that gen- cal mechanics implies that the opposite shrinking process
eral relativitys impact on the tenses debate will mirror from v3 to v1 is lawful, thermodynamics states that it is
special relativitys impact. not.
As mentioned, general relativity takes from special The science of statistical mechanics seems to recon-
relativity a division between coordinate time and proper cile the two by introducing probabilistic considerations:
time and only a partial temporal ordering. The question the process from v3 to v1 is possible, says statistical
is whether it banishes a privileged foliation of spacetime mechanics, but highly unlikely, whereas the process from
into space and time. The answer depends on the particu- v1 to v3 is highly likely. However, statistical mechanics

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY
2nd edition 499
TIME IN PHYSICS

itself is time reversal invariant. It manages to state that Gdel, Kurt. A Remark about the Relationship Between
evolution from v3 to v1 is unlikely and v1 to v3 likely. Relativity and Idealistic Philosophy. In Albert Einstein:
Philosopher-Scientist, edited by P. Schilpp, 557562. La Salle,
Looked at more closely, however, it implies that given v1,
IL: Open Court, 1949.
v3 is more likely in either time direction. In other words, Grnbaum, Adolf. The Meaning of Time. In Basic Issues in
it rightly states that v3 is a likely state to evolve to, but it the Philosophy of Time, edited by E. Freeman and W. Sellars,
also implies that it is a likely state to have evolved from. 195228. La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1971.
The second implication is obviously wrong. This problem Grnbaum, Adolf. Philosophical Problems of Space and Time,
and related ones occupied many of the founders of statis- (2nd, enlarged edition). Dordrecht, Netherlands: D. Reidel,
1973.
tical physics, including Ludwig Stephan Boltzmann, J. C.
Horwich, P. Asymmetries in Time: Problems in the Philosophy of
Maxwell, Joseph Loschmidt, and Ernest Zermelo. Solu- Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987.
tions to the problem seem to require inserting a temporal Kroes, Peter. Time: Its Structure and Role in Physical Theories.
asymmetry somewhere in the physics, either by assuming Synthese Library, 179. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer,
temporally asymmetric boundary conditions or by intro- 1985.
ducing new laws of nature. Le Poidevin, Robin, ed. Questions of Time and Tense. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1998.
Le Poidevin, Robin, and Murray McBeath, eds. The Philosophy
See also Philosophy of Physics; Relativity Theory.
of Time. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993.
Lewis, David, The Paradoxes of Time Travel. In Philosophical
Papers, vol. 2, edited by David Lewis. Oxford: Oxford
Bibliography University Press, 1986.
Albert, David. Time and Chance. Cambridge, MA: Harvard McCall, Storrs. A Model of the Universe. Oxford: Clarendon
University Press, 2000. Press, 1994.
Arntzenius, Frank, and Tim Maudlin. Time Travel and McTaggart, J. M. E. The Unreality of Time. Mind New Series
Modern Physics. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 68 (1908): 457484.
(Spring 2002 Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. Available Mellor, D. H. Real Time II. London: Routledge, 1998.
from http://plato.stanford.edu/. Reprinted in Time, Reality
Minkowski, H. Space and Time, as reprinted and translated
and Experience, edited by Craig Callender. Cambridge, U.K.:
in The Principle of Relativity, 7391. New York: Dover, 1952.
Cambridge University Press, 2002.
Nerlich, Graham. What Spacetime Explains. Cambridge, U.K.:
Barbour, Julian. The End of Time. London: Weidenfeld &
Cambridge University Press, 1994.
Nicholson, 1999.
Newton-Smith, W. H. The Structure of Time. London:
Broad, C. D. Examination of McTaggarts Philosophy, vol. 2, part
Routledge, 1980.
1. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 1983.
Poincar, Henri. Science and Hypothesis. New York: Dover,
Butterfield, Jeremy, ed. The Arguments of Time. Oxford: The 1952.
British Academy, 1999.
Price, Huw. Times Arrow & Archimedes Point: New Directions
Callender, Craig, ed. Time, Reality and Experience. Cambridge, for the Physics of Time. New York: Oxford University Press,
U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 2002. 1996.
Callender, Craig Thermodynamic Asymmetry in Time. In Putnam, Hilary. Time and Physical Geometry. Journal of
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2002 Philosophy 64 (1967): 240247. Reprinted in Putnams
Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. Available from Collected Papers, vol. 1. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge
http://plato.stanford.edu/. University Press, 1975.
Craig, William L. Time and the Metaphysics of Relativity. Reichenbach, Hans. The Philosophy of Space and Time. New
Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer, 2001. York: Dover, 1957.
Dainton, Barry. Time and Space. Ithaca, NY: McGill-Queens Reichenbach, Hans. The Direction of Time. Berkeley: University
University Press, 2001. of California Press, 1958.
Dorato, Mauro. Time and Reality: Spacetime Physics and the Rietdijk, C. A Rigorous Proof of Determinism Derived from
Objectivity of Temporal Becoming. Bologna, Italy: CLUEB, the Special Theory of Relativity. Philosophy of Science 33
1995. (1966): 341344.
Earman, John. An Attempt to Add a Little Direction to The Savitt, Steven, ed. Times Arrows Today: Recent Physical and
Problem of the Direction of Time. Philosophy of Science 41 Philosophical Work on the Direction of Time. Cambridge,
(1974): 1547. U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 1995.
Earman, John. Bangs, Crunches, Whimpers and Shrieks. Oxford: Savitt, Steven. Being and Becoming in Modern Physics. In
Oxford University Press, 1995. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2002
Einstein, Albert. On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies, Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. Available from
as reprinted and translated in The Principle of Relativity, http://plato.stanford.edu/.
3565. New York: Dover, 1952. Sklar, Lawrence. Space, Time, and Spacetime. Berkeley:
Friedman, Michael. Foundations of Space-Time Theories: University of California Press, 1974.
Relativistic Physics and Philosophy of Science. Princeton, NJ: Sklar, Lawrence. Up, Down, Left and Right, Past and Future.
Princeton University Press, 1983. Nous 15 (1981): 111129. Reprinted in The Philosophy of

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY
500 2nd edition
TIMON OF PHLIUS

Time, edited by Robin Le Poidevin and Murray McBeath. But Timon also wrote prose works and a crucial
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993. report of one of them, Pytho, survives in a fragment of
Smart, J. J. C. Problems of Space and Time. London: Macmillan, the Peripatetic Aristocles (around the first century CE),
1964.
Stein, H. On Relativity Theory and Openness of the Future. itself preserved in a text of Eusebius. Timon is reported as
Philosophy of Science 58 (1991): 147167. saying that anyone seeking happiness should consider
Swinburne, Richard. Space and Time. London: Macmillan, these three questions: How are things by nature? What
1968. attitude should we adopt toward them? What will be the
Whitrow, G. The Natural Philosophy of Time. Oxford: Oxford outcome for those who have this attitude? And he goes on
University Press, 1961. (2nd edition, 1980.)
to report (controversially) Pyrrhos answer: Things are
Williams, Donald C. The Myth of Passage. Journal of
Philosophy 48 (1951): 457472. indifferent, unmeasurable, and undecidable; neither sen-
Yourgrau, Palle. Gdel Meets Einstein: Time Travel in the Gdel sation nor judgment is determinably true or false; and so
Universe. La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1999. one should not be opinionated, but be uncommitted and
Craig Callender (2005) unwavering, saying about everything that it no more is
than is not, or that it both is and is not, or that it neither
is nor is not. Once accepted, the result is tranquility. In
other words, we do not know how things really are; and
timon of phlius once we accept that inability, it does not matter. However,
(320230 BCE) Timons Pyrrho, in contrast with later Pyrrhonians,
claimed to be purveying a practical truth, albeit a skepti-
Most of Timons importance rests upon his reputation as cal one; in his other philosophical poem, Images, Timon
a reporter, but he was also responsible for one or two writes: The story of the truth has a correct rule, namely
original twists to the philosophy of his masterPyrrho. the nature of the divine and the good, from which derives
He was a literary virtuoso, composing in a variety of verse the most equable life for man (Diels 1901, p. 68).
forms. Seventy-one fragments of his poetry survive in
quotations by later writers, sixty-five of them deriving The same poem contained the line: the appearance
from one work, the Silloi, a mock-epic series of lampoons prevails everywhere, wherever it comes from (Diels 1901,
in verse. The majority of them deal with philosophers p. 70). Here Timon encapsulates the central tenet of later
other than Pyrrho, whom Timon attacks with wit and skeptical philosophy, that one can neither question, nor
verve, frequently in pointed parody of Homeric verse; but go beyond, the content of appearances. Again anticipat-
Timons purpose is to exalt Pyrrho at their expense: ing a skeptical topos, in a work On Sensations, he wrote
Truly, no other mortal could rival Pyrrho; such was the that honey is sweet I do not affirm, but I accept that it
man I saw, unproud, and unsubdued by everything which appears so (Diels 1901, p. 74).
has subdued known and unknown alike, volatile crowds In these passages, we may perhaps discern Timons
of people, weighed down in all directions by passions, independent philosophizing; and reports in Sextus attrib-
opinion, and vain legislation (Diels 1901, pgs. 8 and 9). ute views to Timon himself rather than via him to his
Timon portrays his hero as a superman: Old man, master. In Against the Geometers, Sextus Empiricus
how and whence did you find escape from the bondage of attacks geometers on the ultimately Platonic grounds that
opinions and the empty wisdom of the sophists? How did they assume as firm principles what are in fact mere
you break the chains of all deception and persuasion? You hypotheses, alluding to Timons Against the Physicists as
did not concern yourself with what winds pass over saying that one should investigate whether anything
Greece, and from what and into what each thing passes should be accepted on the basis of a hypothesis. Sextus
(Diels 1901, p.48). gives no context; but the title of Timons volume suggests
that he would not have had the geometrical notion specif-
This philosophical hagiography deliberately recalls
that of Socrates (note the rejection of natural science in ically in mind, but rather have been more generally con-
the last fragment); Pyrrho is presented as a man apart cerned with the epistemic status of allegedly explanatory
from and immune to the seductive claims of pseudo- postulates. In this, too, he anticipates characteristic moves
knowledge. But in the verse little of genuine philosophi- of later Pyrrhonism, in particular that encapsulated in the
cal substance is found, apart from the rejection of fourth mode of Agrippa.
anything that smacks of dogmatic opinion: dogma Timon also dealt with time. Sextus reports that he
unsupportable by persuasive argument, and the implica- argued against the indivisibility of the momentary pres-
tion that such a rejection brings with it tranquillity. ent on the grounds that no divisible thing such as

ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY
2nd edition 501

Potrebbero piacerti anche