Sei sulla pagina 1di 11

ALAN H.

GOLDMAN

The Broad View of Aesthetic Experience

abstract
Peter Kivy and Noel Carroll advocate a narrow view of aesthetic experience according to which it consists mainly in attention
to formal properties. Excluded are cognitive and moral properties. I defend the broader view that includes the latter properties.
I argue first that cognition and moral assessment can be inseparable in experience from grasp of form and expressiveness.
Second, Kivy and Carroll must extend the notion of form itself beyond ordinary usage to accommodate acknowledged
aesthetic experience. Third, the broad view has a more impressive historical lineage than the narrow view. Fourth, aesthetic
experience is appreciation of aesthetic value, and the latter is more plausibly analyzed in a broad way.

i. the narrow view Of equal or greater importance is what


Carroll means to exclude from the domain of aes-
I argue here against the currently dominant view thetic experience, for one thing cognitive engage-
of aesthetic experience defended by both Noel ment with artworks. He writes: Since the eigh-
Carroll and Peter Kivy. I call their position the teenth century, a recurrent theme in the tradition
narrow view of aesthetic experience. In this first has been that cognitive properties are not aes-
section I criticize their view, in the second section thetic properties and that the cognitive advantages
I describe and defend the proper broader view, offered by engaging with artworks are not part
and in the third section I address objections to my of the aesthetic experience proper of the works
position. in question.2 According to Carroll, also tradi-
Carroll includes within such experience atten- tionally excluded from aesthetic experience are
tion to formal, expressive, and aesthetic properties moral insight, political inspiration, recognition
of artworks. By including the latter properties he of representational content.3
does not mean to imply that formal and expres- Thus, in this passage, although perception of
sive qualities are not aesthetic properties, but he form is the paradigm for aesthetic experience,
means to include also such qualities as the brittle- the engagement of ones recognitional capacity
ness of a dancers movement or the massiveness as recognition of content is excluded. In an ear-
of a sculpture. The clear emphasis is on formal lier paper, Four Concepts of Aesthetic Experi-
properties, although, as we shall see, Carroll may ence, however, he acknowledges that discerning
not mean by form what you and I do. In his most the structure of many novels requires mobiliza-
recent treatment of the topic, he writes: tion of cognitive and emotive scripts and schemas
There appears to be a great deal of agreement that, typ- drawn from everyday life.4 We can ask already
ically, aesthetic experience involves informed attention whether these factors are required and whether
to the form of a work. . . . I do not think anyone has they are separable in the visual experience of a
denied that attending to the form of the work with un- representational painting as well. We can also ask
derstanding is an aesthetic experience.1 more pointedly whether this acknowledgment by
Carroll is consistent with his exclusion of cogni-
If he is right in the latter claim, I will be the first tive properties from aesthetic experience.
to deny the sufficiency of this condition.
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 71:4 Fall 2013

C 2013 The American Society for Aesthetics
324 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

As we saw just above, Carroll also cites as of an artwork as such.9 (I have more to say about
part of the approved tradition the exclusion of this characterization of the broad view below.) But
moral insight from aesthetic experience. And in that earlier paper, too, he already favors a con-
in his most recent paper on the subject, he cept that excludes from the aesthetic experience
seems again to contrast moral and aesthetic of reading novels appreciation of themes about
experience: life and the world, which he calls therapeutic ex-
perience, in contrast to aesthetic.
The formal, aesthetic, and expressive dimensions of art- This exclusion again seems to contrast with
works are each in turn elements in the way in which the earlier quoted passage from Four Concepts.
the artwork is embodied or presented; . . . aesthetic ex- Carroll clearly wants to exclude from aesthetic ex-
periences involve focus on the how of the work. I has- perience the acquisition of knowledge and moral
ten to add that . . . I am not saying that these are the insight, but he wants to include cognitive cate-
only kinds of experiences that artworks qua art do af- gorization of artworks and emotional responses
ford. Artworks may legitimately invite a wide range of to them necessary to discerning the structures es-
other kinds of experiences, including moral, cognitive, pecially of representational works. But if moral
religious, political, and sexual ones. . . . Aesthetic expe- emotional reactions and recognition of previously
rience concerns how [artworks] points and purposes are unconceptualized character types and relations,
embodied and advanced. The moral, cognitive, religious, amounting to the acquisition of knowledge about
and so on content of the work is more of the nature of such character types and relations, are inseparable
what is embodied.5 aspects of the experience of grasping the structure
of narrative works, for example, and if grasping
Yet in his defense of moderate moralism, he that structure is the paradigm of aesthetic expe-
allows that moral defects in works can be aes- rience for Carroll, then these aspects cannot be
thetic defects detected in the course of aesthetic excluded from that experience. So I argue further
experience.6 This is because such defects can block below. The question for Carroll, given what he
the achievement of the purpose of the work, a must acknowledge as included in aesthetic expe-
purpose such as the arousal of an emotional state. rience (because necessary for grasping form as he
And anything that blocks the achievement of a defines it), is whether he can plausibly exclude
works purpose, when that purpose is part of the what he wants to exclude.
content, is by contrast a formal defect according Kivys concept of aesthetic experience is, if
to Carrolls very broad definition of form. I will anything, yet narrower. Once more he admits a
assess his notion of form below, but again we can broader use of aesthetic as referring to experi-
ask already whether excluding moral insight from ence of a work relevant to its evaluation as a work
aesthetic experience is consistent with allowing of art, but he endorses and uses a narrower sense
moral reactions to fictional characters into that in which the concept picks out form as opposed
experience. to content.10 Unlike Carroll, he excludes appreci-
Carroll holds that our current analysis must re- ation of most expressive properties, at least those
flect traditional usage or simply change the sub- that involve emotional engagement or response
ject, but is traditional usage as he views it consis- from the audience or readers. Famously, he de-
tent with such experiences as they occur? And is nies that such response is necessary for recogniz-
traditional usage as he describes it? Again in his ing expressive properties in music. The arousal of
latest paper on the subject, Carroll represents a emotions of any kind is not part of aesthetic expe-
view of aesthetic experience that excludes cogni- rience for Kivy, and expressive properties whose
tive properties and moral insight as a matter of recognition requires such response are excluded.11
consensus, or common knowledge, rooted in a He allows that expressive properties are aes-
uniform or at least consistent history of philosoph- thetic in music, but not in novels, on the ground
ical linguistic usage.7 In an earlier paper, however, also that in novels they are part of content.12
he describes the term aesthetic as a contested Aesthetic properties that do enter aesthetic expe-
technical term from the beginning with shifting rience include mainly phenomenological (phe-
meanings.8 He distinguishes a broad notion in nomenal?) structural properties, perceived prop-
which an aesthetic experience is any appropriate erties of structures or of parts or elements of
response to art: aesthetic experience is experience structures.13
Goldman The Broad View of Aesthetic Experience 325

As indicated earlier, Carrolls main and most and so not part of aesthetic experience of fictional
recent argument for the narrow view is historical. narratives either.18 But he offers no support for the
He refers to the origin of the term in Alexan- premise, which appears to be false. To the extent
der Baumgarten, for whom it referred to the sci- that we recognize expressive properties in nonfic-
ence of perception, to David Hume and Immanuel tional narratives, this may well enter into aesthetic
Kant, for whom beauty consisted in perception of evaluation of them as powerful or beautiful, for
forms that gave rise to disinterested pleasure, and example. And if we evaluate them in that way,
to the later formalist tradition instantiated most that is because we experience them aesthetically.
clearly in Clive Bell, for whom aesthetic experi- Likewise for fiction.
ence lay in the peculiar emotion caused by grasp More generally, Kivys distinction between the
of significant form. In this historical philosoph- aesthetic and artistic assumes the narrow view of
ical sequence Carroll sees a consistent emphasis the former instead of supporting it. He argues fur-
on formal qualities as the objects of aesthetic ex- ther for the distinction by claiming that there are
perience. We saw above that attention to expres- artistic values of works, such as originality and
sive and aesthetic properties are for him also part creativity, which do not lie in perceptible proper-
of aesthetic experience, but that is ultimately be- ties, while aesthetic values and the properties that
cause they are part of the way a work is embodied, determine them are perceptible. But first, there
part of its form according to his very broad defi- are formal aesthetic properties, such as those that
nition of form (scrutinized below). characterize the broad structures of novels, which
Kivy invokes traditional usage as well, but he are grasped cognitively and not perceptually. Kivy
has another motive for defending the narrow view. holds that readers do not ordinarily experience
It is fair to say that while I and other more tradi- such properties while reading, but he cannot plau-
tional philosophers of art want to emphasize com- sibly deny that such formal properties are aes-
mon effects, if not common intrinsic properties, of thetic properties. Second, such properties as orig-
great artworks across different media and genres, inality in art are often noted by a comparison of
Kivy wants to focus on differences. Thus, in his perceptible properties, and they are in a sense per-
recent book on fictional literature, he argues that ceptible themselves by in turn influencing the ways
novels, as opposed to music and paintings, com- we perceive works, by making a difference to per-
prise a mainly nonaesthetic art form in that for- ception. We pay closer attention and hence per-
mal structure plays little role in the appreciation or ceive differently the development section of the
reading experience of even most serious readers.14 opening movement of Ludwig van Beethovens
Even they read primarily for the story and are not Eroica symphony when we perceive its originality
consciously aware of formal features of the novels or difference in scope from such sections in ear-
as they are reading.15 Such broad structure affects lier symphonies. If there is no sharp distinction
ones experience of fictional works but is not ex- between perceivable aesthetic properties and un-
perienced as such according to Kivy. perceivable artistic qualities, then this more gen-
For Kivy, as for Carroll, considering or reflect- eral argument for drawing the distinction between
ing on substantive themes and theses in nov- the aesthetic and the artistic breaks down as well.
els is part of our literary or artistic appreciation While I place greater emphasis on the positive
of them, relevant to their evaluation as literary argument for the broad view of aesthetic experi-
works of art, but not part of our aesthetic ex- ence in the section to follow, I do not find the his-
perience of them, which is minimal.16 Kivy is an torical argument for the narrow view convincing
aesthetic autonomistcognitive engagement and either. Carrolls appeal to Baumgartens histori-
moral or emotional response are no part of aes- cal context and to Kant are first of all question-
thetic experiencebut not an artistic autonomist. able as support for an anticognitivist view; and,
Such responses are relevant to artistic evaluation. more important, the broad view can claim deeper
Thus, he sharply separates artistic from aesthetic and philosophically more impressive roots. Baum-
value.17 One argument he offers for this distinc- garten himself emphasized the acquisition of per-
tion appeals to an analogy between nonfictional ceptual knowledge in his science of aesthetics, and
and fictional literature. Expressive properties and the acquisition of knowledge clearly involves cog-
emotional responses to them are not part of aes- nition, the application of concepts in recognizing
thetic experiences of factual narratives, he claims, representational content.19
326 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Francis Hutcheson, writing around the same carry to new and unprecedented heights that unity of
time, in the same early historical context for the sense and impulse, of brain and eye and ear. . . . In final
use of the term aesthetic, pointed to the beauty import they are intellectual. But in their actual occur-
of mathematical theorems in the way they unify rence they were emotional as well; they were purposive
diverse data.20 Such beauty is of course once more and volitional. Yet the experience was not a sum of these
grasped cognitively, not perceptually; and beauty different characters; they were lost in it as distinctive
was, and perhaps still is, the formal aesthetic prop- traits. . . . It is not possible to divide in a vital experi-
erty par excellence. Kant too emphasized attention ence the practical, emotional, and intellectual from one
to form, since he too focused on the aesthetic ex- another.23
perience of beauty, but for him such experience
clearly included engagement of the cognitive fac- For Beardsley also, it is the function of art to
ulty of understanding. Cognitive engagement is an produce aesthetic experience, and certainly not in
equal partner in aesthetic appreciation for Kant, the narrow sense of Carroll or Kivy. He writes:
although not in the form of applying determinate
concepts, since there is no objective concept of I propose to say that a person is having an aesthetic ex-
beauty.21 In the appreciation of beautiful form, perience during a particular stretch of time if and only if
the feeling of perfect comprehensibility, the felt the greater part of his mental activity during that time is
harmony between understanding and the percep- united and made pleasurable by being tied to the form
tual faculty, is as much cognitive as affective or and qualities of a sensuously presented or imaginatively
immediately sensuous. intended object on which his primary attention is con-
To be fair to Carroll, as mentioned earlier, he centrated. . . . In my idea of a unified experience the
allows cognition to enter aesthetic experience in percepts are integrated with affects of various kinds.24
the form of categorizing works in ways relevant
to appreciating their structure. Aesthetic experi- For Beardsley as well as Dewey, appreciation of
ence for him lies typically in grasping form with aesthetic value is not limited to the perception
understanding. This may entail even more cog- of aesthetic properties usually cited as such, but
nitive engagement than Kant allows, since Kant consists in the full and harmonious engagement of
denies the application of concepts or catego- different mental capacities, prominently including
rization in aesthetic experience of at least free both perception and emotional response.
beauty. But the point remains that appeal to such While the narrow view is tied to the formalist
philosophers as Baumgarten and Kant does not theory of aesthetic value of Bell, that theory has
support excluding the cognitive from aesthetic no more claim to historical dominance than the
experience. equally narrow expressivist theory earlier cham-
The later history of the concept of aesthetic ex- pioned by Romantics such as Tolstoy. Bell himself
perience veers more strongly away from a narrow, shares with Hutcheson, Kant, and Beardsley (but
exclusively perceptual focus. Formalists can claim not Dewey) a thesis that can be claimed to further
recent ancestry in Bell, but the more impressive support the broad view. I refer to the claim that
recent philosophical tradition runs through John aesthetic experience detaches us from the world of
Dewey and later Monroe C. Beardsley. There are our practical affairs.25 This detachment, the feeling
two main aspects to Deweys account of aesthetic that artworks constitute alternative imaginary or
experience. The first is the claim that aesthetic fictional worlds for us, results not from being dis-
experiences are coherent wholes that build cu- tanced from the works themselves, as some later
mulatively toward culminations that encapsulate theorists claimed, but from being totally absorbed
the meanings of all that came before. In a dis- or engaged in them.26 For Bell, we could be so
cussion of Dewey, Carroll criticizes this charac- absorbed in the form of the objects alone, but the
terization as universally applicable to all aesthetic broader view makes this thesis more comprehensi-
experience.22 But he does not consider a second ble and plausible. In any case, the broader theory
and, from our point of view, more important fea- that includes the exercise of cognition, emotion,
ture of aesthetic experience according to Dewey. and imagination in the apprehension or consti-
This is that such experience engages the entire tution of aesthetic value can claim a philosophi-
live creature, uniting all faculties in its unfolding. cally more impressive heritage. The broader view
Dewey writes that such experiences of aesthetic experience and value as cognitive,
Goldman The Broad View of Aesthetic Experience 327

imaginative, and emotional engagement with art- usage that having Hitler as the hero of a story is
works, along with perceptual grasp of their for- part of its content, not its form or structure. Form
mal structures, has a more exalted ancestry than can be captured in variables, excluding proper
the formalism that dates mainly from the birth of names. How, then, can the narrow view of the aes-
modernism in the post-Romantic era. thetic be plausible if it requires not only a category
Returning from the historical argument for the of artistic value to contain what is excluded from
narrow view to its distinction between aesthetic aesthetic value, but also compensatory broaden-
and artistic value, the latter is required as a de- ing of the concept of the formal beyond all recog-
pository for the value appreciated in art that is nition? This broadening is again required if clearly
excluded from the narrow account of aesthetic ex- aesthetic properties are not to be excluded from
perience. Indeed, in search of a backup depository, aesthetic experience.
both Carroll and Kivy feel the need to broaden the Before moving to the positive arguments for
notion of form beyond ordinary recognition. For the broad view, one final argument of Carrolls
Kivy, formal properties are properties of struc- for the narrow view must be assessed. This can
tures or of parts or elements of structures.27 For- be described as an argument from elimination.
mal and structural are indeed near synonyms, Carroll considers and rejects accounts of aesthetic
but the problem here lies in the implicit claim that experience that attempt to differentiate it from
being a property of a part of a structure is suf- other experience on the basis of a particular af-
ficient for being a formal property. This allows fect or emotional state or on the ground that it
Kivy to include not only clearly formal properties is valued for its own sake. He is right that there
like unity, but also such properties as vibrancy and is no single affective tone, be it awe or wonder
garishness within the domain of the aesthetic, hav- or pleasure, that attaches to all aesthetic experi-
ing identified the aesthetic with the formal. Such ence. While emotional engagement is part of the
properties as vibrancy or brilliance of tone are full absorption in artworks that characterizes the
indeed paradigms of aesthetic qualities, but not broad view of aesthetic experience, there is no sin-
normally conceived as formal or structural. gle emotion always present. Being fully engaged
Properties of parts or elements of structures by an artwork is often but not always pleasurable
are not typically structural or formal properties. In and typically not when part of that engagement
fact, virtually all properties that are not properties involves negative emotions. And even works that
of structures are properties of parts or elements do fully engage us might be admired for their ca-
of structures, since all elements or parts of objects pacity to do so without producing a feeling of awe.
enter into their structures, and all objects have The claim that aesthetic experience is valued
structures, either complex or simple. So it seems for its own sake is connected to the traditional
that nothing is excluded from formal properties as claim that it detaches us from the world of our
Kivy characterizes them, which does not sit well ordinary practical affairs, which provides goals to
with his desire to exclude nonformal properties which other values instrumentally attach. As indi-
from the domain of the aesthetic in defense of a cated earlier, I agree with this idea of detachment
narrow view. But this kind of broadening of the that supports the claim of intrinsic value for aes-
concept of form beyond recognition is required if thetic experience. But such experience can also
he is not to throw out the baby with the bath water, be valued for its instrumental benefits, which are
if he is not to exclude clearly aesthetic properties many, and many other experiences can be val-
such as vibrancy or garishness from the realm of ued for their own sake, so that this description
aesthetic experience. does nothing to differentiate the aesthetic. Having
Carrolls characterization of form, if anything, rightly dismissed these alternatives, Carroll con-
sounds even broader. For him, included in form cludes that his content-based account that focuses
is any way a work is embodied or presented so on formal and other aesthetic but not cognitive
as to achieve its purpose, any way it embodies properties is the last man standing.
or presents its content.28 Thus, as an example, he But first, this content-based account is not the
claims that the choice of Hitler as a tragic hero last man standing: Carroll does not consider the
would be a formal mistake, if the purpose of the broader view in this argument, having dismissed
tragedy is the Aristotelian one of evoking pity in it earlier with his somewhat inaccurate historical
the reader. But it seems clear in terms of ordinary argument. And second, an account of a particular
328 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

kind of experience in terms of its intrinsic subjec- in various ways.30 But there is no sharp distinction
tive nature or structure is preferable to one that as he wants to draw in this case between what is
appeals only to objective content, if the former experienced and what influences the reading ex-
is available. Experience itself is, of course, sub- perience. While causes are normally distinct from
jective, and so describing it in subjective terms is effects, in this case experiencing how the charac-
more descriptive of its nature. We may now turn ters develop and events ensue in a fictional narra-
to the positive arguments for construing the terms tive, and how those sequences are presented in the
of that description more broadly.29 order of the narrative, is experiencing the struc-
ture of the novel, although the reader may not be
able to articulate that structure as a whole except
ii. the broad view in retrospect and on reflection.
The apprehension of formal structure in a novel
The first argument takes off from the brief pas- often depends on seeing how its characters and the
sages quoted from Dewey. He points to the in- relations between them change in the course of the
dissoluble connection between cognition and the narration, and this seeing requires thought and
other mental faculties, mainly perception and reflection as well as emotional or empathetic re-
emotion, in aesthetic experience. Attention to and actions while reading. All this is an integral part of
grasp of form in complex artworks, the paradigm the experience of reading. Once more we cannot
of aesthetic experience according to the narrow separate out, except analytically and artificially,
view, typically involve all three capacities. Grasp- attention to the form alone as experienced. Kivy
ing the broad structure of musical movements may be right that most readers pay no such at-
while listening, for example, involves sophis- tention to structure as a whole and in itself, but
ticated conceptual capacities acquired through this does not mean that they do not experience
training and prior musical experience. It also in- formal qualities while reading, as this cognitive
volves responding affectively to the felt tensions engagement is combined with other aspects of the
and resolutions of the harmonic and melodic pro- reading experience.
gressions. Musical works engage us cognitively as Examples are countless, but I will mention a
well as perceptually in experiencing their com- few from some of the novels I examine in a just
plex formal progressions, revealed in part through published book.31 In Jane Austens Pride and Prej-
our affective or emotional reactions as we imagi- udice, the formal structure consists partly in the
natively anticipate resolutions of tensions in the main characters moving gradually from an initial
unfolding melodies and harmonies. As Dewey antagonism to a perfect harmony, while contrast-
indicates, we can separate these aspects of the ing with the lack of development and moral imma-
experience of a piece only analytically in retro- turity of all the minor characters. We imagine, per-
spect, much as we can note that a musical tone ceive, feel, and cognitively reflect on this pattern,
involves pitch, duration, volume, and timbre, al- along with its masterful blend with the subtle and
though these analytically separate facets are not, not so subtle irony of the prose (a second-level for-
and indeed cannot be, experienced separately. mal relation), while reading the novel. In Ernest
Appreciation of paintings too is guided and en- Hemingways The Sun Also Rises, the theme of
hanced by interpretation grounded in knowledge moral malaise reinforces and is reinforced by the
of the history and nature of the medium, genre, repetitive or cyclical structure of the narrative and
and style, guided, that is, by cognition. I noted ear- by the terse prose style.
lier that some formal qualities are grasped purely Such implicit themes, in this case as much felt
cognitively, for example the beauty of a mathemat- as cognized, typically dawn on us gradually as we
ical theorem, as recognized long ago by Hutche- read, and they help to constitute form as well as
son. One might say the same of recognizing the content, uniting and explaining the actions and
broad structure, the formal relations among char- events in the story. It might be objected again at
acters, settings, and events, in a novel. According this point that most of what I have argued is com-
to Kivy, most readers do not experience such for- patible with Carrolls if not Kivys position, since
mal aspects while reading, although he admits that Carroll allows cognitive and emotional response
broad structure can affect the experience of read- to enter aesthetic experience insofar as they are
ing, ones reactions to the characters and events, required for discerning the form of a work. But,
Goldman The Broad View of Aesthetic Experience 329

as noted earlier, he clearly wants to exclude from novels on all these mental levels constitutes the
such experience reflection on moral and other aesthetic experience of reading fiction.
themes relating to real-world life, at least as they The simultaneous and harmonious interaction
constitute cognitive and moral insight or the ac- and engagement of all these mental capacities is
quisition of knowledge. But the acquisition of such matched on the objective side by the interaction of
new insight or knowledge is once more insepara- formal, expressive, and representational aspects of
ble in experience from our fresh emotional reac- the works appreciated. Carroll himself notes such
tions to characters as we first encounter them in interpenetration of aesthetic properties in the
fiction and from our grasping of novels themes. object:
The distinction between form and content that
both he and Kivy want to emphasize is not a dis- The form and the aesthetic and expressive properties of
tinction typically found in the experience of art- the work also interact in various ways. Sometimes form
works, but emerges only later in analysis. gives rise to aesthetic properties, such as unity, while
The role of cognition in uncovering or interpret- the succession, evolution, or juxtaposition of expressive
ing themes in literary works is obvious. They not properties can constitute the form of an artwork. . . .
only express the underlying content of their nov- [A]nother object of aesthetic experience is the relation
els, what they are ultimately about, but also reveal of the form, the expressive properties, and the inter-
their unity or coherence across otherwise diverse action thereof to our response to themto the way in
happenings in the narratives, showing how sep- which they shape and guide our reactions.33
arate strands in the story relate to each other in
formal patterns. Just as literary themes are embod- I would modify this passage only to say that our re-
ied in or woven into narrative, characterization, sponse to such interaction of properties on the ob-
setting, formal structure, and prose style of nov- ject side is the aesthetic experience, instead of the
els, so is their cognitive recognition or inference response being the conscious object of that expe-
woven into perception of the language, imagina- rience, and to point out again that this response in-
tion, and emotional response. In Joseph Conrads volves all our mental faculties operating together,
Nostromo, to take a final example, the theme of prominently including cognition. In appreciating
social chaos and moral disintegration goes hand literature, our reading response typically involves
in hand with the novels somewhat chaotic formal grasping literary themes that are both contentful
structure, its rapid and nearly incomprehensible and formal at the same time. Once more it is only
shifts in time and space. The elegance of Pride and the philosopher or literary analyst who makes the
Prejudice, the chilling power of Nostromo, a large response her object.
part of their literary or aesthetic value, depend on A second related argument for the broad view
this perfect union of form and content, grasped was introduced just above. It begins with the
once more through imagination, feeling, and premise that aesthetic experience is appreciation
thought operating together in the experience of in experience of aesthetic value. On a fairly narrow
reading.32 notion of aesthetic value (too narrow, although
Once more, as in musical appreciation, the ex- capturing a part of such value), it consists of an
ercise of these mental capacities in literary appre- objects having positive aesthetic properties. Thus,
ciation, including cognition as memory, reflection, on this view, aesthetic experience would consist
inference, and anticipation, is not experientially of appreciation of aesthetic properties as usually
separable. The experience, if aesthetic, includes conceived. Kivys concept of aesthetic experience
cognition as an essential aspect of appreciation. is already in trouble on this score since he ex-
If cognition and reflective thought are so indis- cludes most expressive properties. If aesthetic ex-
solubly linked with grasp of formal structure and perience includes appreciation of most or all aes-
empathetic emotional reaction in imaginatively thetic properties, or of all those involving affective
identifying with characters and their relationships, response, then Kivys position is far too narrow. It
then all these are equally aspects of literary appre- certainly seems clear that being strident, soothing,
ciation. If literary appreciation is appreciation of serene, jarring, vibrant, or melancholy are as gen-
literary value, if literary value is a subclass of aes- uine aesthetic properties as being unified, elegant,
thetic value, and if aesthetic experience is appre- or disjointed. The former are expressive prop-
ciation of aesthetic value, then engagement with erties that can require affective responses to be
330 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

recognized (something that Kivy denies in the case I have so far made two main points in answer
of music). Artworks can be better for having these to this question: First, these aspects are not sepa-
properties, and experiencing them can be part of rable from the other acknowledged aspects of the
appreciating the aesthetic value of the works. They appreciative experience of artworks as it occurs;
therefore enter into aesthetic experience, even on and second, the argument from historical usage
a narrow view of aesthetic value. of the term aesthetic fails in undercharacterizing
Carroll is on firmer ground here, since he in- early usage in Baumgarten, Hutcheson, and Kant
cludes such expressive properties in aesthetic ex- and in omitting major later figures in aesthetics. A
perience, being concerned only to banish cognitive third point once more appeals to usage, as I also
and moral insight from the realm of the aesthetic. appealed to common usage of the term form.
We have seen, however, that, like Kivy, he too While we speak of artistic value, we do not speak
needs a separate category of artistic value to con- of artistic properties or artistic experience (unless
tain those exiled aspects of the experience that it is once more the experience of an artist in creat-
are still relevant to the evaluation of artworks, ing an artwork, irrelevant here). Thus, if cognitive
since he rightly holds along with Kivy that cog- and moral engagement with artworks is part of
nitive and moral interest are so relevant. Artistic our experience of them, and if this all engaged
value and its experience cannot, however, be char- experience is a subjectively distinct kind of expe-
acterized by describing its subjective nature, as rience, it must be part of our aesthetic experience
aesthetic value and its experience are properly so of these objects. There is no subjectively distinct
characterized. Artistic value is simply the value artistic experience to which it could belong.
of an artwork qua artwork. Aesthetic value is I can offer one further ordinary language ar-
what is appreciated in aesthetic experience; artis- gument in favor of the conceptual distinction be-
tic value is not what is appreciated in artistic ex- tween aesthetic value and experience on the one
perience, since there is no such experience per se hand and artistic value as construed above on the
(unless it is the experience of an artist in creating a other. We can instruct or advise others to attend to
work). It is therefore problematic to posit artistic certain artworks, although we would not call this
value as a kind of value on a par with aesthetic advising them to have artistic experiences. Once
value, containing distinct but similar aspects in its more, there is no such experience per se. We do
experience. not because we cannot fruitfully advise or instruct
We saw that Kivy and Carroll, despite prefer- others to have aesthetic experiences, although we
ring the narrow view, both recognize a broad con- can predict with more or less reliability that they
cept of aesthetic value according to which it is will have such experiences if they attend to cer-
simply artistic value. On my view, artistic value tain artworks. While aesthetic experiences are in
reduces to aesthetic value in that the proper func- one sense fully active, involving, as emphasized, all
tion of artworks is, as Dewey and Beardsley held, mental faculties operating in concert, in another
to produce aesthetic experience. The concepts of sense they are passive. One must be captured or
artistic and aesthetic value are nevertheless not grabbed by an artwork in order to have an aes-
the same. The connection between aesthetic and thetic experience of it, and one cannot normally
artistic value is not conceptual. Aesthetic value is successfully will to be so fully engaged. I can try
to be defined in terms of the production of aes- to exercise all my mental capacities, for instance,
thetic experience, while artistic value is, as said, to be emotionally responsive to a given work, but
simply the value of artworks as such. The latter if the work does not sustain that response, I will
reduces to the former, but the reduction is not not be successful in trying to have an aesthetic
a matter of proper definition. The only way we experience of it.
can give an account of the value of artworks in It follows from this point that while, as I have
aesthetic terms, however, is by appeal to a broad been arguing, aesthetic experience is broader than
concept of aesthetic experience and value. The its description by Carroll and Kivy, it is also in one
question is whether there is any justification or respect narrower. As indicated at the beginning
point to separating out cognitive and moral en- of this article, I disagree with Carrolls apparent
gagement and insight from aesthetic experience claim that attention to and grasp of formal proper-
so as to leave a residue of artistic value beyond ties is always an aesthetic experience. Noting that
the aesthetic. a monochromatic canvas or the desk on which I
Goldman The Broad View of Aesthetic Experience 331

am typing is rectangular is grasping a formal or limited to attending to aesthetic properties as usu-


structural property, but it is not an aesthetic ex- ally listed. It is more intuitive in light of this point
perience. This follows not only from intuition, but to say that aesthetic experience extends beyond
also from the point of the previous paragraph, in the grasp of particular aesthetic properties than
that while I can certainly instruct someone to at- to say that moral properties are themselves aes-
tend to the shape of the canvas or my desk, I can- thetic properties. Being morally admirable and
not instruct them to have an aesthetic experience having morally enlightening themes are not aes-
of it. Thus, to attend to the shape of the desk is thetic properties, but responses to such properties
not automatically to have (or in this case to have of works, as once more inseparable experientially
at all) an aesthetic experience. from other cognitive and affective responses, are
It is obvious that formal properties are not nec- part of the aesthetic experience of them. Express-
essarily aesthetic properties. No one has ever sug- ing a morally right attitude is not in itself an aes-
gested that squareness is an aesthetic property, but thetic or artistic value, but prompting engagement
it is a formal or structural property. To be fair to with a work on a moral level, as part of the expe-
Carroll, although he sometimes seems to suggest rience of reading or viewing the work, is. It can
that attending to form is sufficient for aesthetic once more be an integral and inseparable aspect
experience, he may only mean to suggest that it of our full experience of or engagement with the
is necessary. But he certainly claims that when work.
it qualifies as an aesthetic experience, it typically
constitutes the totality of that experience (given
his broad definition of form). This is what I have iii. objections
denied. Aesthetic experience is narrower than at-
tention to formal properties, as the squareness ex- I will conclude by briefly addressing some objec-
ample shows. It is also broader than attention to tions to the broad view of aesthetic experience.
aesthetic properties. The first is that, while the view is broad in including
I have suggested that we evaluate artworks, emotional and cognitive engagement along with
including literary works, by how fully they en- perception of form in aesthetic experience, it is too
gage us on all levels, by their ability to prompt narrow for just that reason in excluding a major
aesthetic experience.34 Moral engagement with realm of aesthetic appreciation. I refer to the aes-
a work and moral insight, as part of cognitive thetic appreciation of nature and its picturesque
and emotional response to it, which, I have ar- scenes. Here it will be noted that such aesthetic
gued, can be inseparable from other aspects of experiences, of beautiful sunsets for example, do
the reading experience, are part of this experi- not normally contain major cognitive components,
ence relevant to literary value and evaluation. but instead consist entirely of immediate percep-
Such engagement is most easily prompted not tual responses. Here is aesthetic experience that
by literature that gives us pat moral truths or seems to fit the narrow account and not the broad
characters, or by works that elicit automatic ap- account.
proval of their implied moral attitudes, but by One reply would be to point out that such re-
literature that presents moral ambiguity, morally sponses may be affective or emotional as well,
enigmatic characters like Hamlet, Ahab, or Don and may even include cognitive reflection. But
Quixote, or that challenges our ethical assump- I would not want to insist on the necessity of a
tions. Works that implicitly advocate objection- cognitive aspect for a correct description of such
able moral views are not aesthetically worse experiences as aesthetic. Nor, however, would I
on that score alone, but instead because they characterize response to the beautiful color of a
turn us off from further engagement with them. sunset as grasp of a formal or structural property.
Carroll agrees. But then he wants to exclude moral The better reply is to distinguish what is called
insight from aesthetic experience. The problem is aesthetic experiences of sunsets or flowers from
that those moral defects that turn us off and those typical experiences of great artworks. That we call
challenges that engage us can be experienced as the former aesthetic appreciation hearkens back
the acquisition of moral insight or knowledge. to the earlier use of these terms to refer exclu-
Our responses in this regard while reflectively sively to the perception of or response to beauty.
reading, again imaginative, affective, and cogni- To experience nature aesthetically is to experi-
tive responses at the same time, are clearly not ence its beauty, or perhaps its sublimity, the latter
332 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

being more clearly an emotional response. But the the novels theme and point. In reply, defense of
experience of fine artworks includes far more. the detachment thesis can allow that action in the
A more probable objection is that the account real world is a proper response to reading that
is too broad, in that many activities other than kind of literature, but it will be a response after
the appreciation of art fully engage our mental the fact of the reading experience. That experi-
capacities, competing in sports or writing philoso- ence can still consist of full absorption in the fic-
phy articles, for example. The objection assumes tional world of the work, followed by reflection
that I am in the business here of definition, ei- on a comparison of that world to the real one, and
ther defining art by its production of a unique finally by the response prompted by the reflective
kind of experience or differentiating aesthetic ex- comparison and recognition of appropriate action
perience from every other kind. My main project in light of it. Such remote effects are irrelevant
here has been neither of these, but that of offer- to the proper description of the aesthetic read-
ing a correct description of aesthetic experience. I ing experience itself. While moral reflection can
could, like Dewey, hold that aesthetic experiences be part of that experience, it will be reflection on
in the broad sense occur in contexts other than the moral characteristics of the characters in the
that of appreciating artworks. Or I could hold that fictional circumstances in which they find them-
the most prominent features of aesthetic experi- selves. Changed moral attitudes that might result
ence are as I have described them, but that other and actions in light of them are again separable
features, for example, content, differentiate such effects.
experience from all other kinds. Finally, although I am not primarily in the busi-
I do, however, believe that aesthetic experi- ness of defining art here, I have agreed with
ences of artworks are distinct. Along these lines, Dewey and Beardsley that the proper function
I could question the presence elsewhere to the of artworks is to promote aesthetic experiences in
same degree or in the same way of some fac- their audiences, a function that does seem to be
ulty involved in the aesthetic appreciation of art, unique to art. This claim will give rise to two re-
for instance, imagination in the case of sports or lated objections. First, since producing such expe-
emotion in the case of philosophy articles (I am rience is also a measure of a works value, it might
neither worked up emotionally against Carroll or seem that on this account there cannot be bad
Kivy, whom I consider friends, nor elated at op- or indifferent art, an objection that Carroll raises
posing them). But I think the best appeal here against other definitions of art in terms of aesthetic
is to the overall immediate effect of the full en- experience, otherwise but still positively defined.
gagement I have described as characterizing aes- An initial reply is that defining art in terms of
thetic experience. The effect is to seem to us an its function does not imply that all artworks suc-
alternative world in which we are occupied for ceed in fulfilling that function. It can be further
brief periods of escape from our ordinary affairs. I questioned, however, whether all acknowledged
mentioned earlier this traditional claim of detach- artworks aim to fulfill that function as I have de-
ment from practical affairs, dating at least back to scribed it, whether minimalist paintings have the
Kant. In my view, it translates to full engagement aim of engaging us on so many different levels, for
with the work of art. By contrast, exercise of our example. I believe we can be so engaged with such
capacities in other activities such as sports or writ- works, if we experience them as richly symbolic or
ing articles takes place in the real physical world in terms of their place and point in the history of
and includes practical goals or interests. The mea- the genre, for example. It should be emphasized
sure of value of an artwork is its capacity to so also that this evaluative criterion is fully satisfied
fully engage us: not so with practical goals or even only by great works that serve as paradigms. Other
with games that set their own goals. artworks qualify as such by sharing a place in a his-
Carroll sees a tension between being engaged torical narrative or by sharing certain other prop-
with a work of art, a novel, for example, and be- erties with the paradigms, including the aim that
ing disinterested in the real world, divorced from only the best works satisfy.
practical affairs, since many novels are intended In the end, if the different genres of fine art
to prompt action in the real world.35 If one is sym- have anything in common, and if that common
pathetically engaged in such a work, one will not thread has to do with the type of experience we
be disinterested in practical affairs, since such de- have of them, with the reason we value experi-
tachment will signal lack of serious attention to encing them so highly, it must be the production
Goldman The Broad View of Aesthetic Experience 333

of aesthetic experience in the broad sense. Not Christian Kleyb, 1750; reprint Hildesheim: Georg Holms,
that artworks do not all have some kind of formal 1961), p. 1.
20. Francis Hutcheson, Of the Beauty of Theorems,
structure, but so do all other kinds of objects. We
in An Inquiry Concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony, De-
certainly would not group the fine arts together or sign, ed. Peter Kivy (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973),
value them on that score. We seek out works that pp. 4854.
can so fully engage us, and critics guide us toward 21. Immanuel Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment,
them. Sensuous perception, informed by cogni- ed. Paul Guyer, trans. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews (Cam-
bridge University Press, 2000), pp. 2627, 114.
tion, enlarged by imagination, and prompting 22. Carroll, Four Concepts of Aesthetic Experience,
emotional responsesuch intense and meaning- p. 51.
ful experienceis what we seek and find in such 23. John Dewey, Art as Experience (New York:
works. Anyone who has seen and heard the clos- Capricon, 1958), pp. 2223, 37, 55.
24. Monroe Beardsley, Aesthetic Experience Re-

ing scene of Richard Wagners Gotterd ammerung,
gained, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 28
has read the final chapter of Herman Melvilles (1969): 311, at p. 5, and Aesthetics: Problems in the Phi-
Moby Dick, or stared up at the ceiling of the Sis- losophy of Criticism, 2nd ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981),
tine Chapel (fill in your own favorite aesthetic ex- p. lxi.
periences) must recognize how impoverished the 25. Clive Bell, Art (London: Chatto and Windus, 1914),
p. 27.
narrow account of such paradigm aesthetic expe- 26. I defend the claim that even abstract artworks, such
riences is.36 as pure musical works, can be described as alternative worlds
in Aesthetic Value (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1995),
pp. 151155.
ALAN H. GOLDMAN 27. Kivy, Once Told Tales, p. 48.
Department of Philosophy 28. Carroll, Aesthetic Experience Revisited, p. 165.
College of William & Mary 29. Two other recent accounts of aesthetic experience
worth mentioning are those of Jerrold Levinson, What Is
Williamsburg, Virginia 23187
Aesthetic Pleasure? in The Pleasures of Aesthetics: Philo-
internet: ahgold@wm.edu sophical Essays (Cornell University Press, 1996), pp. 310,
and Berys Gaut, Art, Emotion and Ethics (Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 2007). Levinson allows that aesthetic appreciation
1. Noel Carroll, Recent Approaches to Aesthetic Ex- attends not only to form, but also to meanings or content.
perience, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 70 But he insists that it must grasp the dependence of content on
(2012): 165177, at p. 173. perceptible structure, the basic perceptual configuration.
2. Carroll, Recent Approaches to Aesthetic Experi- My account of course includes perception along with imagi-
ence, p. 172. nation, emotion, and cognition, but it does not privilege the
3. Noel Carroll, Aesthetic Experience Revisited, The perceptual base in this way. The case of literature and aes-
British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (2002): 145168, at p. 163. thetic reading experiences shows that we need not focus on
4. Noel Carroll, Four Concepts of Aesthetic Experi- or think of content as arising from a directly perceived struc-
ence, in Beyond Aesthetics: Philosophical Essays (Cam- tural base while having aesthetic experience. Berys Gaut
bridge University Press, 2001), pp. 4162, at pp. 4546. defends a broad view of experience, as I do, but he focuses
5. Carroll, Recent Approaches to Aesthetic Experi- on a broader account of aesthetic properties. I argue in the
ence, p. 174. next section that this in itself is an overly narrow focus that
6. Noel Carroll, Moderate Moralism, The British leads to an implausibly inflated list of aesthetic properties.
Journal of Aesthetics 36 (1996): 223238. 30. Kivy, Once Told Tales, pp. 32, 3637.
7. Carroll, Aesthetic Experience Revisited, p. 163. 31. Alan H. Goldman, Philosophy and the Novel
8. Noel Carroll, Art and the Domain of the Aesthetic, (Oxford University Press, 2013).
The British Journal of Aesthetics 40 (2000): 191208, at p. 192. 32. It might be objected also that I am relying here
9. Carroll, Art and the Domain of the Aesthetic, on my own experience of reading and on an appeal to the
p. 193. readers experience of fiction. Such introspection might be
10. Peter Kivy, Once Told Tales (Oxford: Wiley- held to be a shaky basis for an argument. But surely Kivy
Blackwell, 2011), pp. 13, 14. and Carroll are on no firmer ground in their separability
11. Kivy, Once Told Tales, pp. 27, 30. thesis. (Kivy is explicit in also making this appeal.) And we
12. Kivy, Once Told Tales, pp. 3031. are speaking of experience.
13. Kivy, Once Told Tales, pp. 28, 48. 33. Carroll, Aesthetic Experience Revisited, p. 164.
14. Kivy, Once Told Tales, pp. 36, 73. 34. I defend this claim much more fully in Aesthetic
15. Kivy, Once Told Tales, p. 30. Value.
16. Kivy, Once Told Tales, p. 33. 35. Carroll, Art and the Domain of the Aesthetic,
17. Kivy, Once Told Tales, pp. 1314. p. 196.
18. Kivy, Once Told Tales, p. 37. 36. This article benefitted from comments by Bob
19. Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten, Aesthetica, Stecker, Ted Gracyk, and anonymous referees for this
Part I. Aesthetica Theoretica (Frankfurt an der Oder: Johann journal.

Potrebbero piacerti anche