Sei sulla pagina 1di 169

James Rachelss Defense of Active Euthanasia:

A Critical & Normative Study

Mr. Mohammad Manzoor Malik

A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE


REQUIREMENT FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF
PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY

Graduate School of Philosophy and Religion


Assumption University, Thailand
June, 2008
Dissertation Title: James Rachelss Defense of Active Euthanasia: A Critical and
Normative Study
Researcher: Mr. Mohammad Manzoor Malik
Adm. No. : 462-9481
Degree: Doctor of Philosophy
Majoring in: Philosophy
Advisor: Assistant Professor Dr. Warayuth Sriwarakuel
Academic Year: 2008

ABSTRACT
The researcher believes that James Rachelss defense of active euthanasia

deserves a critical and normative analysis because of its dehumanizing consequences.

The researcher demonstrates that Rachelss position is conceptually, theoretically,

practically, and normatively unjustifiable. The researcher supports his position by three

steps.

Firstly, the researcher criticizes Rachelss conceptual framework which

consists of three distinctions: biological and biographical life; killing and letting die;

and ordinary and extraordinary medical treatment. The research shows that these

distinctions do not provide a valid foundation or criteria for the permissibility of active

euthanasia because of their conceptual, theoretical, and practical inadequacies.

Rachelss first distinction is inadequate due to: (1) reductive fallacy (2) slippery slope

and (3) irrelevance to main arguments. His second distinction is: (1) irrelevant, (2)

extraneous and (3) degressive. His repudiation of the distinction of ordinary and

extraordinary medical treatment is not valid.

Secondly, the researcher argues against Rachelss arguments against CDE.

Rachels proposes four arguments which make the distinction between active and
ii

passive euthanasia morally absurd. Therefore, Rachels argues that wherever passive

euthanasia is allowed, active should be permitted too. The researcher shows that

Rachelss arguments are theoretically flawed to support his position because most of

his premises are either irrelevant or weak. Rachelss first claim is that often active

euthanasia seems more humane than passive and therefore active euthanasia should not

be only permitted but preferred too. The research shows two main responses to

Rachelss claim which render his argument invalid. The first response is that Rachels

argues against CDE on the basis not included in the AMAs statement. The research

forwards the reasons which render Rachelss argument unimportant, irrelevant, and

inadequate. Rachelss second claim is that the conventional view makes life-and-death

decisions on irrelevant grounds therefore the conventional view, CDE, is not true. The

research shows that the relevant grounds in CDE are the killing and termination of

extraordinary medical care. Rachelss third claim is that there is no moral difference

between doings and refraining, therefore wherever refraining is allowed doing should

be permitted too; in other words, wherever passive euthanasia is allowed active should

be allowed too. The research shows that Rachelss argument is invalid due to four

reasons: (1) irrelevance to AMAs statement; (2) differences between the cases because

of intentionality, causality, and agency; (3) straw man fallacy, and (4) weak analogy.

Thirdly, the researcher analyzes and argues against Rachelss direct arguments

for active euthanasia which are from best interests and golden rule and autonomy. The

researcher shows that the arguments are based on subjective moral claims and such

claims are based on indefensible claims from liberty, rights and autonomy. The

research demonstrates three reasons which render the best interest and golden rule
iii

argument invalid. They are: (1) the argument is based on subjective moral judgment,

failing the universalization test; (2) it may not be in my own best interests or in the best

interests of others for me to die; and (3) the argument is based on indefensible

autonomy. Rachelss third argument is from autonomy. The research demonstrates that

argument from autonomy fails to claim the sufficient support to substantiate a

pro-position for the approval of active euthanasia. The related reasons are: (1)

invalidity of civil rights claim; (2) weak analogy (3) unwarranted influence of

patients autonomy, and (4) unattainable autonomy of the patients. Furthermore,

Rachels proposes a modest proposal for the legalization of active euthanasia. The

research demonstrates that Rachelss proposal on legalizing active euthanasia is

problematic and impractical.

Finally, the researcher shows that Rachelss categorization of active and

passive euthanasia into killing and letting die is a false dichotomy. The researcher

argues throughout the research that the third and the only choice is to stop prolongation

of death by advanced medical technology and permitting termination of extraordinary

medical care from dying person by following legitimate procedures.


CONTENTS

Page

Abstract i

Acknowledgements iv

Contents v

Chapters

Chapter One: Introduction 1

1.1. Background, Significance, & Scope of the Study 1

1.2. Thesis Statement 19

1.3. Objectives 19

1.4. Limitation and Methodology of the Research 19

Chapter Two: Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 21

2.1. Introduction 21

2.2. Rachelss Euthanasian Conceptual Framework 23

2.2.1. Biological Life and Biographical Life 23

2.2.2. Killing and Letting Die 24

2.2.3. Ordinary and Extraordinary Means of Treatment 27

2.3. Rachelss Arguments against Traditional Doctrine

on Euthanasia (TDE) 30

2.3.1. Often Active Euthanasia Seems More Humane Than Passive 32

2.3.2. The Conventional View Makes Life-And-Death Decisions

on Irrelevant Grounds 33

2.3.3. There is no Moral Difference between Doing and Refraining 34


vi

2.3.4. Arguments in Favor of the Conventional View do not Work 35

2.4. Rachelss Arguments for Active Euthanasia 36

2.4.1. The Argument from Mercy 37

2.4.2. The Best Interests and Golden Rule Argument 37

2.4.3. The Argument from Autonomy 40

2.5. Proposal for Legalization of Active Euthanasia 42

Chapter Three: Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 45

3.1. Introduction 45

3.2. Criticism of Rachelss Conceptual Framework 46

3.2.1. Criticism of Biological and Biographical Life 46

3.2.2. Criticism of Killing and Letting Die 53

3.2.2.1. Killing and Letting Die: An Irrelevant Distinction 54

3.2.2.2. Killing and Letting Die Distinction and Health Care Professions 57

3.2.3. Criticism of Ordinary and Extraordinary Means of Treatment 61

3.3. Criticism of Rachelss Arguments against Traditional

Doctrine on Euthanasia (TDE) 66

3.3.1. Criticism of that often Active Euthanasia Seems More

Humane than Passive 67

3.3.2. Criticism of the Conventional View Makes Life-And-Death

Decisions on Irrelevant Grounds 75

3.3.3. Criticism of that there is no Moral Difference between

Doings and Refraining 77


vii

3.3.4. Criticism of that the Arguments in Favor of the Conventional

View do not Work 86

3.4. Criticism of Rachelss Arguments for Active Euthanasia 88

3.4.1. Criticism of the Argument from Mercy 90

3.4.2. Criticism of the Best Interests and Golden Rule Argument 90

3.4.3. Criticism of Rachelss Argument from Autonomy 96

3.4.3.1. Self-determination and Euthanasia 97

3.4.3.2. Analogy of Euthanasia with Suicide 100

3.4.3.3. Right, Liberty and Euthanasia 101

3.4.3.4. Autonomy of Patients 103

3.5. Criticism of Rachelss Proposal of Legalizing Active Euthanasia 105

3.6. Modern Advanced Medical Technology and Euthanasia 107

3.6.1. Moral Hazards of Modern Advanced Medical Technology 108

3.6.2. Passive Euthanasia is not Euthanasia / Letting Die 113

3.6.3. Active Euthanasia is Mishandling of those whose

Death is Prolonged 116

Chapter Four: Conclusion 122

Further Research and Recommendations 141

References 142

Autobiography
Acknowledgments

The researcher would like to extend his special gratitude to his dissertation advisor

Assistant Professor Dr. Warayuth Sriwarakuel for advising, inspiration,

encouragement, concern and moral support.

Likewise, the researcher extends his gratitude to all the instructors and class mates for

their meaningful comments on and suggestions to this research during seminar class

presentations.

The special words of thanks are offered to Dr. Imtiyaz Yousuf, Dr. Veerachart

Nimanong, Dr. Joseph I. Fernado and Dr. John Thomas Giordano for their

encouragement and motivating affection.

Finally, thanks to family and friends.


CHAPTER ONE

Introduction

1.1. Background, Significance, & Scope of the Study

This research is a critical and normative study of James Rachelss defense of

active euthanasia. And by its academic and disciplinary nature, it falls within the

philosophical discussions in medical ethics and legal theory. The research is critical and

normative: Rachelss positions and arguments are conceptually, theoretically, and

practically criticized; and his normative conclusions are challenged. In brief, the

research is aimed at establishing the claim that James Rachelss defense of active

euthanasia is conceptually, theoretically, practically, and normatively unjustifiable. To

put Rachelss case briefly, he provides his own conceptual framework for the resolution

of the issues related to euthanasia (Rachels, 1981 / 1994b, 1986b); he allegedly makes

the distinction between active and passive euthanasia morally absurd (1975 / 1994a),

and he finally argues in defense of active euthanasia (Rachels, 1981/ 1994b). In

addition, Rachels provides a modest proposal for the legalization of active euthanasia

(Rachels, 2003). Furthermore, Rachels argues that the opponents can not defend

themselves rationally rather their position, according to him, is based on a muddle of

indefensible claims, backed by tradition but not by reason (1981 / 1994b, p. 153). On

the whole, Rachelss position on euthanasia is widely known as libertarian approach in

contrast to traditional doctrine or conventional approach. Libertarian approach allows

active euthanasia mercy killing, whereas the traditional approach approves passive

euthanasia in the sense of terminating extraordinary medical treatment and does not
Introduction 2

permit active euthanasia.

The driving motivation for the topic stems from researchers conviction that

contemporary, intellectual discourse in support of euthanasia has potential

consequences of leading to dehumanization, which ought to be rejected. The researcher

thinks that permissibility of active euthanasia will lead to reducing a human being to a

product, which at the point of loosing its usefulness is disposed. As a result, human

beings will end up being treated as disposable products rather than dignified persons.

Euthanasia, by definition, is supposed to be for terminally ill persons; therefore children,

adults, and elderly people are subjects to it, however, elderly people are the most

vulnerable. The harshness of euthanasia supporters could be understood from what

Colorado governor Richard D. Lamm said in an address, which was reported in The

New York Times, March 29, 1984, to the Colorado Health Lawyers Association :

"Elderly people who are terminally ill have a duty to die and get out of the way (Kearl ,

1989, p.125). Similarly, Richard Fenigsen, who conducted research on Dutch elderly

people, argues that a society which promotes euthanasia sends a message to the

vulnerable that their lives are not valued. Instead, such a society tells them, we

wouldn't mind getting rid of you (Fenigsen, 1989, Social Implications, para. 1). It

should be noted that active euthanasia is legal in Holland.

To return to the subject of euthanasia, it is of importance to mention that the

issue of euthanasia is both new and old. It is new in the sense that most of the debate on

the issue treats the matter as a consequence of the modern advanced medical

technology. As a matter of fact, the rise of advanced medical technology, especially the

artificially life-sustaining technology, has brought various moral issues to center stage
Introduction 3

such as people can be kept alive against their wishes or in states of pain and in other

forms of suffering. Moreover, it is also possible to keep people alive who are in a coma

or a persistent vegetative state. In cases like these, the use of medical technologies

raises questions about the moral appropriateness of sustaining life versus taking life or

allowing someone to die. On the other hand, the issue of euthanasia is old in the sense

that it involves issues of life and death on which thinkers and philosophers, from the

ancient time, have held positions. The involvement of concepts such as killing and

letting die, omission and commission, rights and duties, intrinsic value and inviolability

of life, intention and foresight, and autonomy and paternalism are such issues which

directly or indirectly touch the issue of euthanasia from many perspectives and link the

issue with the philosophical tradition.

In the following parts of the chapter and in the rest of the research, the

researcher provides the exposition of the issue of euthanasia; its historical origins and

relevance with historical, philosophical debate on suicide; and its full development in

our contemporary time. The crucial part of the research comprises of critical exposition

of James Rachelss thought on the issue of euthanasia and its critical and normative

study, which will eventually lead to evaluation of the issue in the third chapter and the

justification of the thesis statement in the final chapter.

First and foremost, it is very important to have a clear definition of euthanasia.

As a matter of fact, defining euthanasia and the relevant synonymous terms deserve a

thorough tactful analysis because much of the confusion which besets the

contemporary euthanasia debate can be traced to an unfortunate imprecision in

definition. Lack of clarity has hitherto helped to ensure that much of the debate has
Introduction 4

been frustrating and sterile (Otlowski, 1997, pp. 16-17). Therefore, defining

euthanasia and the related terms is necessary in the outset of this research to ensure that

conceptual framework of the subject remains clear, justice with reducing conclusions to

proper definitions is realized, and the debate remains equivocation-free.

Euthanasia etymologically comes from two Greek words, eu, well, and thanatos,

death, it means good or easy death (Baird & Rosenbaum, 1989, p. 9). Gradually the

meaning of one word changed from the connotation of easy death to the actual medical

deed necessary to make death easy. Finally it reached the connotation of mercy killing.

Therefore, the common synonym for euthanasia in both lay and professional

vocabularies has been mercy killing (Koop, 1989a, p. 69). Merriam-Webster's

dictionary defines euthanasia as "an easy and painless death, or, an act or method of

causing death painlessly so as to end suffering: advocated by some as a way to deal with

victims of incurable disease" (2008). Similarly, the Euthanasia Society of America,

founded in 1938, defines euthanasia as the "termination of human life by painless

means for the purpose of ending severe physical suffering" (Hardon, 2004, Euthanasia,

para.14). The American Medical Associations Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs

(1992) defines the term as follows: Euthanasia is commonly defined as the act of

bringing about the death of a hopelessly ill and suffering person in a relatively quick

and painless way for reasons of mercy (p. 2230).

The above definitions show that euthanasia is mercy killing in the sense of

painlessly putting to death a terminally ill patient; however, there are other definitions

which suggest that euthanasia also means refusing unwanted care or withdrawal of

ongoing care (Adams, 1992, p. 2021). Therefore, there are two different uses of the
Introduction 5

term euthanasia. The first is sometimes called the narrow construal of euthanasia. In

this view euthanasia is equivalent to mercy killing. Thus, if a physician injects a patient

with a drug with the intent to kill the patient, that would be an act of euthanasia; but if

the physician withholds some extraordinary and excessively burdensome treatment

from a patient and allows the patient to die in a natural way , that does not count as an

example of euthanasia. The second view, sometimes called the broad construal of

euthanasia, includes within the definition of euthanasia both mercy killing and

cessation of extraordinary medical treatment i.e. active euthanasia and passive

euthanasia. The broad construal is more widely used and is adopted in this research as

well, because of its employment in Rachelss works; although the researcher agrees

only with the narrow construal of euthanasia.

Euthanasia is a general term and there are few widely used corresponding terms.

These terms are definitions which decipher the meaning of different types of euthanasia.

Among these terms are widely used active and passive euthanasia. Active euthanasia or

euthanasia by action, also called mercy killing or positive euthanasia, is intentionally

causing a persons death by performing an action such as by giving a lethal injection.

Passive euthanasia or euthanasia by omission, also called negative euthanasia, is the

withholding or withdrawing the unnecessary and extraordinary medical treatment.

Rachels (1983) widens the definition of active euthanasia; according to him it refers to

the intentional and /or direct killing of an innocent human life either by that person,

suicide, or by another, assisted suicide (p.19). Gifford (1993) describes the difference

between the two types of euthanasia: Passive euthanasia involves allowing a patient to

die by removing her from artificial life support systems such as respirators and feeding
Introduction 6

tubes or simply discontinuing medical treatments necessary to sustain life. Active

euthanasia, by contrast, involves positive steps to end the life of a patient, typically by

lethal injection (p. 1546).

Active and passive euthanasia are the main categories, however, they are further

classified depending on the relevant factors or circumstances such as Voluntary,

Involuntary, and Non-voluntary euthanasia. The American Medical Associations,

AMAs, Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs (1992) makes three distinctions

concerning consent and euthanasia as follows:

Voluntary euthanasia is euthanasia that is provided to a competent person on

his or her informed request. Non-voluntary euthanasia is the provision of

euthanasia to an incompetent person according to a surrogates decision.

Involuntary euthanasia is euthanasia performed without a competent persons

consent. (p. 2230)

These distinctions while combined with the active / passive distinction form six

different types of euthanasia: voluntary active, voluntary passive, non-voluntary active,

non-voluntary passive, involuntary active and involuntary passive. Closely related to

euthanasia are terms such as assisted suicide and physician assisted suicide. Assisted

suicide is when someone provides an individual with the information, guidance, and

means to take his or her own life with the intention that they will be used for this

purpose. Likewise, when it is a doctor who helps another person to kill himself or

herself it is called physician assisted suicide. However, there is a sharp difference

between euthanasia and physician assisted suicide. The AMAs Council on Ethical and
Introduction 7

Judicial Affairs (1992) states as follows:

Euthanasia and assisted suicide differ in the degree of physician participation.

Euthanasia entails a physician performing the immediate life ending action

(e.g., administering a lethal injection). Assisted suicide occurs when a

physician facilitates a patients death by providing the necessary means and /or

information to enable the patient to perform the life-ending act (e.g., the

physician provides sleeping pills and information about the lethal dose, while

aware that the patient may commit suicide). (p. 2231)

The researcher holds that euthanasia is only the narrow construal of euthanasia;

that is active euthanasia alone. The researchers contention is that since euthanasia

enfolds the meaning of intentional, mercy killing in what has come to be known as

passive euthanasia intentional killing is not part of the withholding or withdrawing the

unnecessary and extraordinary medical treatment. The confusion between suicide,

assisted suicide, physician assisted suicide, and euthanasia also deserves some analysis.

This confusion of terms is very widespread in the well circulated literature on

euthanasia; most importantly, Rachels, as noted earlier, confuses these terms too, his

definition of active euthanasia includes mercy killing, suicide, assisted suicide and

physician assisted suicide (Rachels, 1983, p.19).

The researcher holds that passive euthanasia, suicide, assisted suicide, and

physician assisted suicide are not euthanasia; only active euthanasia mercy killing is

euthanasia. The researchers definitional understanding is in consistency with AMAs

definitions. Therefore, the researchers definition of euthanasia is: intentionally causing


Introduction 8

a terminally ill persons death for the reasons of mercy . The analysis of the definition is

as follows:

Person X commits euthanasia on Person Y if

i. X takes the life of Y

ii. Y is suffering from a disease or injury from which Y is not expected to

recover

iii. the action of X's taking Y's life is intentional

The definition includes: voluntary, non-voluntary, and involuntary active

euthanasia. The definition excludes: suicide, assisted suicide, physician-assisted

suicide and passive euthanasia.

The definition is based on the facts that: (1) the death is caused by an agent

(human) instead of the subject (the patient), (2) the causing of death is intentional (3)

the death is caused either by the request of the subject or the state of the subject to make

it different from a pure homicide (4) the death is caused by commission or action and (5)

the subject is terminally ill. Therefore, euthanasia as defined above will include only

active euthanasia.

The reasons behind not considering passive euthanasia as euthanasia is due to:

(1) the death is natural, and not artificial (2) the death is not caused by action of any

agent. The suicide, assisted suicide, and physician assisted suicide are excluded due to:

(1) the death is not caused by an agent other than the subject. The very integral factor of

the notion of euthanasia is being killed by some agent (person) instead of the subject.
Introduction 9

After definitional analysis of euthanasia, a brief historical sketch of euthanasia

and its development is noteworthy to put the intellectual threads on the issue together.

The problem of euthanasia has a long history of philosophical discussion. However,

most of the discussion revolves around the issue of suicide. The discussion of suicide

itself could be related to problem of euthanasia since both of them aim at termination of

life. The researcher thinks that suicide is a general concept whereas euthanasia is a

special case. Euthanasia is about a terminally ill person whereas suicide enfolds various

possibilities and motives for opting termination of life. Therefore, the relation between

suicide and euthanasia is a relation between universal and particular. However, lines of

distinction could be drawn between suicide and euthanasia. Euthanasiait might be

claimedis an alleged solution for the ills of dying, whereas suicide is an alleged cure

for the ills of living ( Donnelly, John, 1998, p.10). On the other hand, wishing death

and planning the steps toward ending a life is shared by both euthanasia and suicide.

The quality of life and its intrinsic value remain central in both euthanasia and suicide.

Both these issues share many common threads which bring suicide and euthanasia on

parallels, if not completely, nevertheless, partially. Therefore, in the historical sketch of

the problem the distinction between suicide and euthanasia is intentionally considered

irrelevant because suicide is general and in principle it includes euthanasia. And

Indeed, to justify either one, suicide or mercy killing, is to justify the other (Fletcher

1987 / 1989, p. 91).

The intellectual and academic debate of euthanasia draws on history of western

philosophy ranging from the ancient to contemporary time. The expounding

philosophers on the issue could be categorized into three groups: opponents,


Introduction 10

proponents, and moderates. Opponents such as Hippocrates, Aquinas, Kant, and Hegel

claim that suicide is always morally wrong; proponents include Epicurus, Seneca,

Montaigne, Montesquieu, Holbach, Diderot, Rousseau, Voltaire, Schopenhauer, and

Nietzsche; and moderates such as Plato and Hume hold that suicide is both moral and

immoral depending on the motivating factors and the contexts. Therefore, the

following account will be a precise literature review of the case with some elaborations

wherever necessary.

In ancient Greece, euthanasia was not practiced, and suicide was generally

disfavored. In fact, Athenian law treated suicide as a crime, punishing the guilty by

amputating the corpse's right hand and denying traditional burial rituals (Mair, 2007,

pp. 26-30). However, Alvarez (1971) suggests that although suicide was taboo, the

Greeks tolerated suicide in some circumstances (p.58). Meanwhile, Hippocrates

(460-370 BCE), the ancient Greek physician, strongly opposed euthanasia, assisted

suicide, and physician assisted suicide. Wording of his famous oath attests his position:

I will not prescribe a deadly drug to please someone, nor give advice that may cause

his death (Hippocrates, 2005). Accordingly, Hippocrates oath has since then

normatively defined the medical profession as life saving. Some Greek philosophers,

such as, Plato did add three exceptions to the immorality of suicide. According to him,

suicide might be permissible when compelled by (1) judicial order, (2) excruciating

misfortune, or (3) moral disgrace (Plato, 1980, p. 268). However, Platos exceptions do

not apply to permissibility of active euthanasia. Nevertheless, Plato seems to be in

favor of passive euthanasia; in The Republic, Plato argued that patients should be

permitted to refuse intrusive medical treatments that may lengthen their lives, while
Introduction 11

making them very unpleasant and useless to the state (Plato, 1991, p. 84-89). On the

contrary, Aristotle believed that suicide was unjust under all circumstances, because it

deprived the community of a citizen (Aristotle, 1999, p. 84). Regardless of Aristotle,

the Stoics focused more strongly on the welfare of the individual than on the

community. Roman Stoics such as Annaeus Seneca (4 B.C.E.-C.E. 65) argued that the

individual should have broad discretion to end his or her own life. Seneca emphasizes

considerations of quality of life over mere existence and recommends dying well as an

escape from the ills of living (Seneca. (1917/ 1998, pp. 35-39).

In medieval times, Christian, Jewish, and Muslim philosophers opposed active

euthanasia, although the Christian Church has always accepted passive euthanasia and

condemned active euthanasia. The most influential and scholastic defense of Catholic

position comes in the thirteenth century by Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274). Aquinas

gave three highly influential arguments for the immorality of suicide: (1) it contravenes

ones duty to oneself and the natural inclination of self-perpetuation; (2) it injures other

people and the community of which the individual is a part; and (3) it violates Gods

authority over life, which is Gods gift (Aquinas, 1947, 11, 11, Q.64, Art.5.). This

position shaped attitudes about suicide that prevailed from the Middle Ages through

the Renaissance and Reformation. By the sixteenth century, philosophers began to

challenge the generally accepted religious condemnation of suicide. Michel de

Montaigne, a sixteenth-century philosopher, argued that suicide was not a question of

Christian belief but a matter of personal choice (Ferngren, 1989, pp. 159-61).

During the Renaissance, Thomas More (1478-1535) defended euthanasia;

according to him when a patient has a torturous and incurable illness, the patient has the
Introduction 12

option to die, either through starvation or opium (More, 1999, p. 22.). In the eighteenth

century, David Hume (1711-1776) made the first unapologetic defense of the moral

permissibility of suicide on grounds of individual autonomy and social benefit. Humes

defense is utilitarian and he disagrees with the arguments of Aquinas. However, Hume

did not advocate that all suicides are justified, but argued that when life is most plagued

by suffering, suicide is most acceptable (Hume, 2004, p.2-8). Other philosophers of the

Age of Reason, such as John Locke and Immanuel Kant, opposed suicide. Locke

argued that life, like liberty, represents an inalienable right, which cannot be taken from,

or given away by, an individual (Ferngren, 1989, pp. 173-75). For Kant (1724-1804),

suicide was a paradigmatic example of an action that violates moral responsibility.

Kant believed that the proper end of rational beings requires self-preservation, and that

suicide would therefore be inconsistent with the fundamental value of human life (Kant,

1785).

The nineteenth and early twentieth centuries brought several developments that,

while not explicitly philosophical, have shaped philosophical thought about suicide.

Michael Cholbi (2004) points out these developments: (1) the emergence of a

Romantic idealized script for suicide in novels by Rousseau, Goethe, and Flaubert,

according to which suicide was the inevitable response of a misunderstood and

anguished soul jilted by love or shunned by society (Lieberman 2003.); (2) the

recognition of psychiatry as an autonomous discipline capable of diagnosing and

treating the ailments responsible for suicide; and (3) the work of sociologists such as

Durkheim and Laplace, who viewed suicide as a social ill reflecting widespread

alienation, anomie, and other attitudinal byproducts of modernity. Moreover, suicide


Introduction 13

was of central concern for the twentieth century existentialists, who saw the choice to

take one's life as impressed upon us by our experience of the absurdity or

meaninglessness of the world and of human endeavor (Section 2.3, para. 9-10).

The late twentieth century represents two aspects of the issue of suicide. The

debate becomes divided into two separate discourses: suicide and euthanasia. Both

these subjects became separate along with their subject matter and arguments; although

there is unavoidable overlap between them. The nature of euthanasia becomes special

because it touches medical profession and debate over rights and duties. Thus

euthanasia widely becomes interdisciplinary and subject of legal analysis in various

countries.

Tracking the developments regarding euthanasia in twentieth century, the

societies which advance the cause of positive euthanasia were founded in 1935 in

England and in 1938 in the United States. Since 1937 assisted suicide has been legal in

Switzerland as long as the person who assists has no personal motive or gain. The

Second World War changed the atmosphere of discussion on euthanasia. In 1939, the

Nazis practiced euthanasia in various specialized medicine departments; the victims

were gassed or poisoned. After the Second World War, the debate became silent for a

long period until the 1970s. In the 1970s and early 1980s, the discussion on euthanasia

became a more extensive academic and public debate. This is the same period when

James Rachels wrote his major works. The Northern Territory of Australia was the first

state to pass laws allowing a physician to end the life of a terminally ill patient, but just

6 months after the first death under the passed act, the act was overturned by the

Australian Federal Senate. On 27 October 1997, the state of Oregon legalized


Introduction 14

physician-assisted suicide. In 1993, the Netherlands decriminalized, under a set of

restricted conditions, voluntary active euthanasia, essentially, physician-assisted

suicide, for the terminally ill, and in 2002 the country legalized physician-assisted

suicide if voluntarily requested by seriously ill patients who face ongoing suffering.

Belgium has also legalized euthanasia since 2002 for certain patients who have

requested it. Besides these developments, the discourse on euthanasia is continuously

in progress attracting attention from experts of various disciplines and likewise the

issue has been subjected to public opinion polls time to time.

Apart from every sort of disciplinary perspective on the issue of euthanasia, the

issue in its essential relation is practically connected with medicine. The issue of

euthanasia has brought the medical profession in question. The traditional and common

sense understanding of the profession is life saving. However, the defenders of active

euthanasia suggest the redefining the profession not only as life saving, but also life

taking. From that point on, the issue touched the legality of practicing euthanasia on the

grounds of autonomy, rights, and duties. Autonomy, not only of patients, but of doctors

too. And duty, not only of doctors to kill a patient, but of patients too in a

psychologically shaped euthanasian culture. And most of all, the status of rights of a

patient to claim such a right. Due to the crucial touch of euthanasia to medical

profession, on December 4, 1973, the House of Delegates of the American Medical

Association (AMA) asserted its position on the issue of euthanasia as follows:

The intentional termination of the life of one human being by

another--mercy killing--is contrary to that for which the medical profession

stands and is contrary to the policy of the American Medical Association.


Introduction 15

The cessation of the employment of extraordinary means to prolong the life

of the body when there is irrefutable evidence that biological death is

imminent is the decision of the patient and/or his immediate family. The

advice and judgment of the physician should be freely available to the

patient and /or his immediate family. (as cited in Rachels, 1975 / 1994a, pp.

112-113)

The above statement generated a prompt debate on the issue both in the field of

ethics and legal theory. The AMAs position on the issue came to be named as

conventional doctrine on euthanasia (CDE) or traditional view. It is important to

mention that AMAs position, although adopted in the United States, its message

resonates globally in the forums and associations that are concerned with the issue. In

accordance with the AMAs position, the World Medical Association's Declaration on

Euthanasia, adopted by the 38th World Medical Assembly, Madrid, Spain, in October

1987, states:

Euthanasia, that is the act of deliberately ending the life of a patient, even at

the patient's own request or at the request of close relatives, is unethical. This

does not prevent the physician from respecting the desire of a patient to allow

the natural process of death to follow its course in the terminal phase of

sickness. (World Medical Association, 2002, Section, 1)

James Rachels (1941-2003), the distinguished American moral philosopher,

criticized the AMAs statement just after its publication; he is the most outspoken

rebutter of the position. His approach to euthanasia came to be known as libertarian


Introduction 16

view. Rachels was born in Columbus; he received his Ph.D. in 1967 from the

University of North Carolina. He taught at the University of Richmond, New York

University, the University of Miami, Duke University, and the University of Alabama

at Birmingham. 1971 saw the publication of his groundbreaking anthology Moral

Problems. In 1975, Rachels wrote "Active and Passive Euthanasia, originally

appearing in the New England Journal of Medicine, this essay has been reprinted 300

times. The End of Life (1986) broadened and deepened his ideas on euthanasia. His

Created from Animals (1990) argued that a Darwinian world-view has widespread

philosophical implications, including drastic implications for our treatment of

nonhuman animals. Can Ethics Provide Answers? (1997) was Rachelss first collection

of papers; The Legacy of Socrates (2007) was his second. Rachelss textbook, The

Elements of Moral Philosophy, is currently the best-selling book in philosophy. Shortly

before being diagnosed with cancer, Rachels finished Problems from Philosophy, an

introduction to his subject, published posthumously. Over his career, Rachels wrote 5

books and 86 essays, edited 7 books and gave about 275 professional lectures (Official

Website of James Rachels, n.d. Brief Biography, para.1-2).

In criticizing the AMAs position on euthanasia, Rachelss first attempt was to

show that there is morally no difference between active and passive euthanasia, and

where passive euthanasia is appropriate, active should be allowed too; he elaborated on

the idea in his article "Active and Passive Euthanasia" (1975/ 1994a). He challenged

the conventional doctrine of euthanasia (CDE) for several reasons: active euthanasia is

in many cases more humane that passive euthanasia; the conventional doctrine leads to

decisions concerning life and death on irrelevant grounds; the doctrine rests on a
Introduction 17

distinction between killing and letting die that itself has no moral importance; and the

most common arguments in favor of the doctrine are invalid. Secondly, Rachels in

More Impertinent Distinctions and a Defense of Active Euthanasia" (1981/ 1994b)

explicitly supported active euthanasia. Rachels stated two main arguments: the first is

the argument from mercy; the second is the argument from the best interests and the

golden rule. He added one more argument for the legalization of active euthanasia

based on the right to liberty and autonomy. (Rachels, 1983, p.19). Thirdly, Rachels is a

moral, utilitarian philosopher; while elaborating his thought on euthanasia, he refers

directly and indirectly to his conceptual framework which permeates all of his

arguments. Rachelss conceptual framework deals with distinctions such as biological

and biographical life, killing and letting die; and ordinary and extraordinary medical

treatment. In addition to that, in his rejoinder article An Argument against Legalizing

Active Euthanasia: The Slippery Slope (2003), Rachels provided the detailed

framework on the legislation for active euthanasia. The chapter two of this research

deals with the abovementioned ideas of Rachels in a detailed form. The ideas are

grouped in three categories respectively: conceptual framework, arguments for

absolution of the distinction between active and passive euthanasia, and arguments for

active euthanasia including the proposal on legislation for active euthanasia

respectively.

The criticism of Rachelss thought on euthanasia is detailed in chapter three.

The criticism is conceptual and normative. The arguments developed by Rachels are

addressed. The chapter analyzes firstly, the conceptual framework of Rachels and

demonstrate its inadequacy on conceptual and practical basis; secondly, it demonstrates


Introduction 18

the theoretical problems in Rachelss arguments which attempt to prove the distinction

between active and passive euthanasia is morally absurd, therefore, the criticism leads

to invalidity of the active euthanasia. And thirdly, it criticizes Rachelss arguments for

active euthanasia by showing their weaknesses which affect their soundness. In

addition, the researcher also shows the problems in Rachelss proposal on the

legalization of active euthanasia which renders his proposal problematic and

impractical. And, lastly, the researcher debates that there is only one type of euthanasia

which is active euthanasia and which ought to be rejected, due to its unjustifiability.

Finally, the researcher shows that Rachelss active and passive dichotomy is a false

dichotomy.

The chapter four summarizes the research and concludes the findings by

establishing the thesis statement and furthermore mentions also the further research

and recommendations.

1.2. Thesis Statement

James Rachelss defense of active euthanasia is conceptually, theoretically,

practically, and normatively unjustifiable.

1.3. Objectives

1.3.1. To provide a detailed exposition of the issue of euthanasia. The exposition

includes the explanation of the terms and definitions, the historical background of the

issue, and the current debate on the issue.

1.3.2. To provide the descriptive exposition of James Rachelss view on euthanasia


Introduction 19

1.3.3. To provide a critical study of Rachelss view on euthanasia.

1.3.4. To provide the justification of the thesis statement.

1. 4. Limitation and Methodology of the Research

The limitations on the research are as follows:

1.4.1. This is a focused research on James Rachelss defense for active euthanasia. The

research is therefore basically confined to his works on the issue.

1.4.2. This research will address only those arguments which are explicitly detailed in

the works of Rachels. It includes the arguments which he develops, supports, or refutes.

1.4.3. The approach of argumentation is secular. Therefore, religious arguments are not

included. However, rational arguments, though, labeled or proclaimed as religious will

be included.

1.4.4. The nature of the research methodology is on parallels with Rachelss

methodology which is conceptual, practical, theoretical and normative.

1.4.5. The methodology employed will combine conceptual analysis, criticism, and

argumentation. Firstly, the analysis and presentation of Rachelss thought will be

undertaken. His arguments and position will be made clear. And secondly criticism of

his arguments and position will be undertaken by two ways: by finding problems within

his thought and by arguing against his position. The debate of the issue is not confined

to any ethical criteria or to any ethical theory among normative ethical theories, rather

the issue is tackled by independent arguments.


Introduction 20

1.4.6. This research is not meant to reach on conclusions on the issue of euthanasia, but

to attempt to reach on conclusions on Rachelss defense of active euthanasia.


CHAPTER TWO

Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia

2.1. Introduction

James Rachelss thought on euthanasia begins from his counter and refuting

responses to the American Medical Associations (AMAs) statement, which stated its

position on euthanasia by endorsing, according to Rachels, the traditional doctrine of

euthanasia (TDE) or conventional doctrine of euthanasia (CDE). Rachelss first attempt

was to show that there is morally no difference between active and passive euthanasia.

In his article "Active and Passive Euthanasia" (1975/ 1994a), which appeared in The

New England Journal of Medicine, he did not argue in support of active euthanasia

explicitly. His main attempt, in the article, was to show that there is no moral difference

between active and passive euthanasia, and where passive euthanasia is appropriate,

active should be allowed too. However, in his rejoinder essay, "More Impertinent

Distinctions and a Defense of Active Euthanasia" (1981/ 1994b), he explicitly

supported active euthanasia in an argumentative manner. Both the abovementioned

articles, and the reproduction of the same thought in his numerous articles (1977, 1979a,

1979b, 1980, 1981a, 1981b, 1984, 1993, 2001, & 2002), contained the most of the

conceptual framework which Rachels uses in his works. Finally, in The End of Life:

Euthanasia and Morality (1986b), Rachels gave a systematic shape to his ideas and

elaborated comprehensively on all aspects of the related issues. Rachelss

abovementioned works suggested the moral and practical permissibility of voluntary

active euthanasia to medical doctors and judicial courts. In addition to that, in his
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 22

rejoinder article An Argument against Legalizing Active Euthanasia: The Slippery

Slope (2003), Rachels provided the detailed framework for the legalization of active

euthanasia.

The arrangement and ordering of Rachelss ideas in this chapter is different

from the chronological order of his writings; due to need of understanding his thought

in a logical order for the convenience of comprehension and criticism. Therefore, his

conceptual framework is sketched firstly; his arguments showing the morally absurd

distinction between active and passive euthanasia are elaborated secondly; thirdly his

arguments in favor of active euthanasia are explained with details; and finally his

proposal on legalizing active euthanasia is stated precisely. Meanwhile, his responses

to rejoinders are mentioned during the course of explicating his arguments. The best

part of his instant responses to rejoinders, during his lifetime, is that they have served a

stimulus to Rachels to speak out more clearly on many related issues. For example, in

his article More Impertinent Distinctions and a Defense of Active Euthanasia (1981/

1994b) which is partially a response to Thomas D. Sullivans article, Active and

passive euthanasia: An impertinent distinction? (1977/1994a), Rachels, further

explains notions such as intentionality; ordinary and extraordinary means of treatment;

and arguments which support active euthanasia.

Therefore, the chapter is based on three areas: conceptual framework,

arguments for absolution of the distinction between active and passive euthanasia, and

arguments for active euthanasia including the proposal on legalization of active

euthanasia respectively.
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 23

2.2. Rachelss Euthanasian Conceptual Framework

Rachels is a moral, utilitarian philosopher; while elaborating his thought on

euthanasia, he refers directly and indirectly to his conceptual framework which, in fact,

permeates all of his arguments. In brief, Rachelss conceptual framework comprises of

distinctions such as biological and biographical life; killing and letting die; and

ordinary and extraordinary medical treatment. The most of these distinctions make

sense both theoretically and practically only if the passive euthanasia is accepted as

given and permissible. On the whole, Rachels shows that biographical life is morally

relevant whereas mere biological life is not so; there is morally no difference between

killing and letting die ; and the ordinary and extraordinary distinction is senseless. The

following part of the chapter precisely explicates this conceptual framework.

2.2.1. Biological Life and Biographical Life

Rachels makes a distinction between biological and biographical life; his

support for active euthanasia is largely based on this distinction. The biological life is

being a living being. Whereas, according to Rachels, biographical life is the sum of

one's aspirations, decisions, activities, projects, and human relationships (Rachels,

1986b, p. 526, 33, 35, 38, 47, 49-59, 65, 76, 85). Rachels claims that the mere fact that

something has biological life, whether human or nonhuman is relatively unimportant

from an ethical point of view. What is important, according to Rachels, is that someone

has biographical life. The facts of a person's biographical life are those of that person's

history and character. They are the interests that are important and worthwhile from the

point of view of the person himself or herself. The value of one's biographical life is the
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 24

value it has for that person, and something has value if its loss would harm that person

(Rachels, 1986b, p. 38). The distinction is such a drastic that it, in principle, does not

support only voluntary active euthanasia, but also non-voluntary and involuntary,

though Rachels would finally agree on voluntary active euthanasia only.

The significant implication of the above view entails that certain persons

without a prospect for biographical life, and certain terminally ill patients, are of little

intrinsic concern, morally speaking. Though they may be alive in the biological sense,

they are not alive in the biographical sense. And the latter is what is relevant to morality.

Therefore, the distinction gives a considerable and decisive weight to Rachelss

position, that such persons, who are biologically alive but biographically without any

prospect, are subjects of active euthanasia.

2.2.2. Killing and Letting Die

Rachels argues that there is morally no distinction between killing someone and

letting someone die. Furthermore, he argues that intentions are not relevant to moral

judgments. The implication of the distinction is related to the active/passive dichotomy.

According to Rachels, active euthanasia involves actually killing the sick individual,

whereas passive euthanasia involves simply letting the person die. Rachels, by applying

the above concept, attempts to show that the active / passive dichotomy is a distinction

without difference. To demonstrate the distinction, he forwards a main argument: the

bare difference argument or equivalence thesis. The implication, which follows from

the argument, is that the cases where passive euthanasia is permissible are also the cases

where active euthanasia should be permissible too.


Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 25

Rachels, while explaining the above distinction, sets up two cases that are

supposed to be exactly alike except that one involves killing and the other involves

letting die. The cases are hypothetical, which involve two characters: Smith and Jones.

Smith stands to gain a large inheritance if anything should happen to his six-year-old

cousin. One evening while the child is taking his bath, Smith sneaks into the bathroom

and drowns the child, and then arranges things so that it will look like an accident. As a

result, Smith gets his inheritance without getting caught. On the other hand, Jones also

stands to gain if anything should happen to his six-year-old cousin. Like Smith, Jones

sneaks in planning to drown the child in his bath. However, just as he enters the

bathroom Jones sees the child slip, hit his head, and fall face-down in the water. Jones is

delighted; he stands by; ready to push the child's head back under if necessary, but it is

not necessary. With only a little thrashing about, the child drowns all by himself,

accidentally, as Jones watches and does nothing. As a result, Jones gets his inheritance

without facing any blame (Rachels, 1975/ 1994a, pp. 115-116; 1986b, p. 112).

According to Rachels, neither man behaved better even though Smith killed the

child and Jones merely let the child die. Both acted from the same motive, personal gain,

and the results were identical, death. Thus according to Rachels, the only difference

between the two cases is killing versus letting die, and since the cases are morally

equivalent, this distinction is morally irrelevant. Therefore, the above hypothetical case,

according to Rachels, makes the distinction between active and passive euthanasia

absurd. They are morally the same; therefore, where letting die is permissible,

killing should be allowed too. The other meaning could be if killing is not allowed,

letting die should be prohibited too; but that is not what Rachels aims at, he would
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 26

rather, support killing in the case.

The bare difference argument, as illustrated above, which shows that there is no

difference between killing and letting die, faced a response from Thomas D. Sullivan.

In summary, Thomas D. Sullivans point is that the difference is due to difference in

intentions (1977/1994a). He claims that in active euthanasia the doctor intends to kill,

whereas in passive euthanasia the intent is not involved. Rachels attempts to refute the

claim, and while discrediting Sullivans position, Rachels concludes that rightness or

wrongness of an act is determined by the reasons for it or against it, and intention as

such has morally no importance. Rachels further adds that if a person is trying to decide

whether treatment should be continued; he should think about the reasons for and

against it. Rachels responds that on the one hand, if treatment is ceased the terminally

ill person will die very soon, and on the other hand, the person will die eventually

anyway, even if treatment is continued. He adds that, moreover, if the persons life is

prolonged, its suffering will be prolonged as well, and the medical resources used will

be unavailable to others who would have a better chance of a satisfactory cure.

In light of all this, Rachels concludes, you may well decide against continued

treatment. Rachels draws attention to the fact that there is no mention here of anybody's

intentions. Rachels emphasizes that the intention you would have, if you decided to

cease treatment, is not one of the things you need to consider. It is not among the

reasons either for or against the action. That is why it is irrelevant to determining

whether the action is right (Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p.143). Rachels further states that a

person's intention is relevant to an assessment of his character; intentions are relevant

for thinking a person a good or a bad person. But, according to Rachels, the intention is
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 27

not relevant to determining whether the act itself is morally right; according to Rachels,

the rightness of the act must be decided on the basis of the objective reasons for or

against it. He, therefore, concludes that the traditional view is mistaken on this point

(Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p.143).

2.2.3. Ordinary and Extraordinary Means of Treatment

Rachels, while attempting to find the flaws in the AMAs statement, criticizes

the statement which states that life sustaining treatment may sometimes be stopped if

the means of treatment are "extraordinary"; with the implication that "ordinary" means

of treatment may not be withheld (Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p.143). The distinction

between ordinary and extraordinary treatments is crucial and Thomas D. Sullivan

reemphasizes and reaffirms its importance in a rejoinder to Rachels (Sullivan, 1994b).

Responding to the above distinction as held in the traditional view, Rachels

states that, however, upon reflection it is clear that it is sometimes permissible to omit

even very ordinary sorts of treatments. (Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p.143). Rachels

debates the definitions of ordinary and extraordinary means of treatment which are

briefly mentioned in the AMAs statement and are well extended by Thomas D.

Sullivan. Rachels, therefore, makes his objections to the Sullivans understanding of

the distinction as a representing commentary of the AMAs statement.

Thomas D. Sullivan in fact bases his understanding of the distinction on the

following definitions of Paul Ramsey:

Ordinary means of preserving life are all medicines, treatments, and

operations, which offer a reasonable hope of benefit for the patient and
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 28

which can be obtained and used without excessive expense, pain, and other

inconveniences. Extraordinary means of preserving life are all those

medicines, treatments, and operations which cannot be obtained without

excessive expense, pain, or other inconvenience, or which, if used, would

not offer a reasonable hope of benefit. (as cited in Sullivan, 1994a, p. 135)

Rachels criticizes the above definitions and claims that they are useless. He

states two problems regarding the distinction which, according to his understanding,

render the distinction senseless. Rachels takes the definitional analysis of the

distinction.

Rachels, firstly criticizes the way the word "excessive" functions in these

definitions. He states that it is said that a treatment is extraordinary if it cannot be

obtained without excessive expense or pain. He, therefore, poses the question: when is

an expense "excessive"? He adds, is a cost of $10,000 excessive? If it would save the

life of a young woman and restore her to perfect health, $10,000 does not seem

excessive. But if it would only prolong the life of Ramsey's cancer-stricken diabetic a

short while, perhaps $10,000 is excessive. Rachels concludes that the point is not

merely that what is excessive because it changes from case to case; what is excessive

depends on whether it would be a good thing for the life in question to be prolonged

(Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p. 144).

Secondly, Rachels turns to the use of the word "benefit" in the definitions. He

states that it is said that ordinary treatments offer a reasonable hope of benefit for the

patient; and that treatments are extraordinary if they will not benefit the patient

(Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p. 145). Rachels responds to the above by saying that how do
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 29

we tell if a treatment will benefit the patient? He reminds that we are talking about life

prolonging treatments; the "benefit," if any, is the continuation of life. Whether

continued life is a benefit depends on the details of the particular case. For a person

with a painful terminal illness, a temporarily continued life may not be a benefit. For a

person in irreversible coma, such as Karen Quinlan, continued biological existence is

almost certainly not a benefit. On the other hand, for a person who can be cured and

resume a normal life, life-sustaining treatment definitely is a benefit. Therefore he

concludes that in order to decide whether life-sustaining treatment is a benefit we must

first decide whether it would be a good thing for the life in question to be prolonged

(Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p. 145).

After making above two objections, Rachels concludes that these definitions

do not mark out a distinction that can be used to help us decide when treatment may be

omitted. Rachels states that we cannot, by using the definitions, identify which

treatments are extraordinary, and then use that information to determine whether the

treatment may be omitted. For the definitions, Rachels points out, require that we must

already have decided the moral questions of life and death before we can answer the

question of which treatments are extraordinary (Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p. 145) Rachels

concludes his debate as follows:

If we apply the distinction in a straightforward, commonsense way, the

traditional doctrine is false, for it is clear that it is sometimes permissible to

omit ordinary treatments. On the other hand, if we define the terms as

suggested by Ramsey and Sullivan, the distinction is useless in practical

decision making. In either case, the distinction provides no help in


Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 30

formulating an acceptable ethic of letting die. (Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p.

145)

The above mentioned conceptual framework which sets distinctions is present

almost in every argument of Rachels. The following part of the chapter presents

Rachels arguments against traditional doctrine on euthanasia (TDE), which makes the

distinction between active and passive euthanasia; Rachels argues that the distinction is

morally absurd and , therefore, where passive euthanasia is allowed, active euthanasia

should be permitted as well.

2.3. Rachelss Arguments against Traditional Doctrine on Euthanasia (TDE)

Rachels argues against the traditional doctrine on euthanasia, which is also

called as conventional doctrine on euthanasia (CDE) or standard view; which makes a

distinction between active and passive euthanasia. This view is, according to Rachels,

endorsed by the American Medical Association. According to the conventional view,

passive euthanasia is sometimes permitted, whereas active euthanasia is prohibited.

Rachels in arguing against the conventional view refers to the statements made by the

American Medical Association which states:

The intentional termination of the life of one human being by

another--mercy killing--is contrary to that for which the medical

profession stands and is contrary to the policy of the American Medical

Association. The cessation of the employment of extraordinary means to

prolong the life of the body when there is irrefutable evidence that

biological death is imminent is the decision of the patient and/or his


Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 31

immediate family. The advice and judgment of the physician should be

freely available to the patient and/or his immediate family. (as cited in

Rachels, 1975 / 1994a, pp. 112-113)

The AMA statement does not include terminology such as active and passive

euthanasia. However, the way the statement is laid out refers to two categories: (1)

termination of extraordinary medical treatment in face of irrefutable evidence that

biological death is imminent and patients consent is favorable, and (2) the prohibition

of intentional termination of the life of one human being by another. The meaning of

the statement is matter of interpretation. The researcher holds that the statement does

refer to active euthanasia and prohibits it and it does not refer to passive euthanasia as

understood by Rachels. Rather, the statement refers to the cessation of the employment

of extraordinary means to prolong the life. However, the passive euthanasia is used for

convenience in this chapter due to Rachelss formulation of the statement.

Rachelss position against CDE is briefly summarized in the abstract of his

famous article, Active and Passive Euthanasia as follow:

The traditional distinction between active and passive euthanasia requires

critical analysis. The conventional doctrine is that there is such an important

moral difference between the two that, although the latter is sometimes

permissible, the former is always forbidden. This doctrine may be challenged

for several reasons. First of all, active euthanasia is in many cases more

humane that passive euthanasia. Secondly, the conventional doctrine leads to

decisions concerning life and death on irrelevant grounds. Thirdly, the


Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 32

doctrine rests on a distinction between killing and letting die that itself has no

moral importance. Fourthly, the most common arguments in favor of the

doctrine are invalid. I therefore suggest that the America Medical Association

policy statement that endorses this doctrine is unsound. (Rachels,

1975/1994a, p.112)

Rachels in the following arguments attempts to show that the conventional

view which permits passive euthanasia, in fact, leads to permissibility of active

euthanasia. The ultimate goal of his arguments is that there is no moral difference

between active and passive euthanasia, and where passive euthanasia is permitted,

active ought to be permitted, but preferred too. In arguing against the positions taken in

the AMAs statement, Rachels proposes four challenges as follows:

2.3.1. Often Active Euthanasia Seems More Humane Than Passive

Rachels claims that active euthanasia seems more humane than passive

euthanasia. Therefore, active euthanasia should not be only permitted but preferred.

Rachels illustrates the above challenge by examples. He gives a few examples of

patients who suffer unbearable pain and, therefore, he suggests that it would be better to

kill such patients for the sake of ending their suffering. Rachels gives an example of a

cancer patient who is dying of incurable cancer of the throat is in terrible pain, which

can no longer be satisfactorily alleviated. He is certain to die within a few days, even if

present treatment is continued, but he does not want to go on living for those days since

the pain is unbearable. So he asks the doctor for an end to it, and his family joins in the

request (Rachels, 1975/ 1994a, p.113).


Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 33

Rachels considers the choices available in such a case which are: (1) keeping

the patient alive with life-supporting equipment, in that case he will experience a few

more painful months, (2) allowing the patient to die by removing the life-supporting

equipment, instead of months it will be days, then (3) actively ending the patients life,

so that the pain will stop right away. Rachels holds that sometimes doctors and patients

choose option (2), because they want to reduce the patients pain. But, Rachels claims,

option (3) does a much better job at eliminating pain. Rachels gives a few more

examples to show that there are other cases where allowing the patient to die is much

more painful and inhumane than active euthanasia (Rachels, 1975/ 1994a, p.113).

Therefore, in such cases, Rachels claims that active euthanasia seems more humane

than passive euthanasia.

2.3.2. The Conventional View Makes Life-And-Death Decisions on Irrelevant

Grounds

Rachels in support of the claim that the conventional view makes

life-and-death decisions on irrelevant grounds, refers to the case of babies with Down

syndrome. Babies with such kind of disease require a surgical operation. But in certain

cases, parents refrain from having the child operated, as a result of which it will die. He

utilizes a situation in which the child is also born with a congenital defect; in this case it

is an intestinal obstruction. If the parents make the decision to deny operation and

allow the baby to die naturally, the infant will most likely perish from dehydration and

infection. Rachels points out that this painful process could be avoided through active

euthanasia. He calls attention to the cruelty involved in permitting the child to suffer
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 34

when there is a lethal injection available that can put him out of his misery. Rachels

draws the attention to the fact that if the lives of these infants are worth living, then

their lives should be preserved. Therefore, he argues that allowing to die and

actively killing would be equally wrong. Rachels concludes:

What makes this situation possible, of course, is the idea that when there is an

intestinal blockage, one can let the baby die, but when there is no such defect

there is nothing that can be done, for one must not kill it. The fact that this

idea leads to such results as deciding life or death on irrelevant grounds is

another good reason why the doctrine should be rejected. (Rachels, 1975/

1994a, p.115)

2.3.3. There is no Moral Difference between Doing and Refraining

Rachels, before attempting to prove that there is no difference between doing and

allowing, explores the commonsense point of view on the issue. He maintains that the

reason why so many people think that there is an important moral difference between

active and passive euthanasia is that they think killing someone is morally worse than

letting someone die. Rachels questions the view and to investigate this issue, he

suggests that two cases may be considered that are exactly alike except that one

involves killing whereas the other involves letting someone die. Rachels gives the

example of Smith and Johns as mentioned earlier under 2.2.2. Killing and Letting Die.

In short, Rachels maintains that there is no moral difference between doing or allowing/

killing or letting die; and intentions are not morally relevant.


Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 35

2.3.4. Arguments in Favor of the Conventional View do not Work

Rachels claims that the arguments given in favor of conventional view are

unconvincing. He mentions the most common argument in favor of the conventional

view: the important difference between active and passive euthanasia is that, in passive

euthanasia, the doctor does not do anything to bring about the patients death; and the

patient dies of whatever ills already afflict him. In active euthanasia, however the

doctor does something to bring about the patients death: he kills him (Rachels, 1975/

1994a, p.117 ).

Rachels responses to the above argument; he maintains that of course, one can

be held responsible for something that one does not do. Rachels comments that it is not

exactly correct to say that in passive euthanasia the doctor does nothing, for he does do

one thing that is very important: he lets the patient die. Rachels states that the decision

to let a patient die is subject to moral appraisal in the same way that a decision to kill

him would be subject to moral appraisal: it may be assessed as wise or unwise,

compassionate or sadistic, right of wrong. Rachels concludes that if a doctor

deliberately let a patient die who was suffering from a routinely curable illness, the

doctor would certainly be to blame for what he had done, just as he would be to blame

if he had needlessly killed the patient (Rachels, 1975/ 1994a, p.118).

2.4. Rachelss Arguments for Active Euthanasia

Rachelss arguments for active euthanasia are of types. The first type is based

directly on his biological and biographical distinction as elaborated in the conceptual

framework. The second type of arguments, by which he supports active euthanasia, is


Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 36

the arguments which attempt to establish that the distinction between active euthanasia

and passive euthanasia is morally absurd. Therefore, wherever passive euthanasia is

applicable, active should be permissible as well. This has been shown in the second part

of this chapter. The first two types of arguments can be classified as indirect arguments.

The third type of arguments includes his direct arguments as elaborated in the following

part of the chapter. Rachels states I believe that it [active euthanasia] is morally

justified in some instances and that at least two strong arguments support this position.

The first is the argument from mercy; the second is the argument from the golden rule

(Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p.146). He adds one more argument for the legalization of

active euthanasia based on the right to liberty (Rachels, 1983). Briefly, this argument

argues that dying people should be free to choose euthanasia as a matter of personal

liberty and autonomy. The arguments are explained in the following part of the chapter.

2.4.1. The Argument from Mercy

Rachels believes that the single most powerful argument in support of

euthanasia is the argument from mercy (Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p.146 ). He claims that,

it is also an exceptionally simple argument, at least in its main idea, which makes one

uncomplicated point. Rachels explains that terminal patients sometimes suffer pain so

horrible that it is beyond the comprehension of those who have not actually

experienced it. Their suffering can be so terrible that we do not like even to read about it

or think about it; we recoil even from the descriptions of such agony. The argument

from mercy says: euthanasia is justified because it provides an end to that (Rachels,

1981/ 1994b, p.146). Rachels illustrates the above statement by a few examples,

describing the pain of terminally ill patients. The argument is similar to Rachelss first
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 37

argument against CDE as mentioned earlier.

2.4.2. The Best Interests and Golden Rule Argument

Rachels while continuing the similar line of thought as in the mercy argument,

attempts to forward two aspects of the same argument separately. The argument is

admixture of the best interests and the golden rule. Rachels starts from the utilitarian

argument in favor of active euthanasia, however, he states that if an argument is based

on the mercy alone on the utilitarian grounds, the argument will be faulty due to the

Principle of Utility as a premise of the argument. Therefore, Rachels tries to avoid such

a problem and comes up with an alternative argument, which is inspired, according to

Rachels, by utilitarianism, but which avoids the difficulties of the pure utilitarian

version of the argument, by not making the Principle of Utility a premise of the

argument. Therefore, Rachels provides the following argument based on doing what is

in everyone's best interests, and he claims that the argument is sound and proves that

active euthanasia can be justified:

1. If an action promotes the best interests of everyone concerned, and violates

no one's rights, then that action is morally acceptable.

2. In at least some cases, active euthanasia promotes the best interests of

everyone concerned and violates no one's rights.

3 Therefore, in at least some cases active euthanasia is morally acceptable.

(Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p.149-150)

Rachels, after presenting the above argument, states the benefits of employing the

argument in voluntary active euthanasia. His words in their tune and emotion are as
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 38

follows:

It would have been in everyone's best interests if active euthanasia had been

employed in the case of Stewart Alsop's friend, Jack [a terminally ill patient

who died in a painful death]. First, and most important, it would have been in

Jack's own interests, since it would have provided him with an easier, better

death, without pain. (Who among us would choose Jack's death, if we had a

choice, rather than a quick painless death?) Second, it would have been in the

best interests of Jack's wife. Her misery, helplessly watching him suffer, must

have been almost equal to his. Third, the hospital staff's best interests would

have been served, since if Jack's dying had not been prolonged, they could

have turned their attention to other patients whom they could have helped.

Fourth, other patients would have benefited since medical resources would no

longer have been used in the sad, pointless maintenance of Jack's physical

existence. Finally, if Jack himself requested to be killed, the act would not

have violated his rights. Considering all this, how can active euthanasia in this

case be wrong? How can it be wrong to do an action that is merciful, that

benefits everyone concerned, and that violates no one's rights? (Rachels,

1981/ 1994b, p.150)

Rachels after presenting the above argument complements the argument by

other argument inspired by the golden rule. Rachelss golden rule argument is actually

the reinforcement of his best interest argument. Rachels states that Immanuel Kant

incorporated the basic idea of the golden rule into his system of ethics. Rachels

discusses the categorical imperative of Kant which says: act only according to that
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 39

maxim by which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law.

Rachels elaborates on the principle: that we should act only on rules that we are

willing to have applied universally; that is, we should behave as we would be willing to

have everyone behave (Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p.151). Rachels while taking the

careful analysis of the principle states that the basic idea behind the golden rule is a

good one. He points out the following principle:

the basic idea is that moral rules apply impartially to everyone alike; therefore,

you cannot say that you are justified in treating someone else in a certain way

unless you are willing to admit that that person would also be justified in

treating you in that way if your positions were reversed. (Rachels, 1981/ 1994b,

p.151)

Rachels after going into explanatory details about the maxim, ultimately tries to

explain the meaning of the maxim and its relation to the case of euthanasia as follows:

The application of all this to the question of euthanasia is fairly obvious. Each

of us is going to die someday, although most of us do not know when or how.

But suppose you were told that you would die in one of two ways, and you

were asked to choose between them. First, you could die quietly, and without

pain, from a fatal injection. Or second, you could choose to die of an affliction

so painful that for several days before death you would be reduced to howling

like a dog, with your family standing by helplessly, trying to comfort you, but

going through its own psychological hell. It is hard to believe that any sane

person, when confronted by these possibilities, would choose to have a rule


Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 40

applied that would force upon him or her the second option. And if we would

not want such a rule, which excludes euthanasia, applied to us, then we should

not apply such a rule to others. (Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p.151-152)

2.4.3. The Argument from Autonomy

Rachelss main arguments in favor of active euthanasia are basically and

essentially based on the consent of the terminally ill patient, that the justification of

such practice is based on the free will and autonomy of the patient and furthermore on

the joint consent of the other parties involved as briefed in the aforementioned

arguments. Therefore, the argument from autonomy in favor of voluntary active

euthanasia stands as the foundation of Rachelss thesis which according to him is based

on two strong arguments, the golden rule and the best interest arguments. The

autonomy argument involves discussions on liberty, rights, self determination and

conception of autonomy itself. Rachels in his works refers to all these concepts to gain

more warranty for his argument.

Rachelss distinction between biological and biographical life shows that

biological life is not the moral issue. Rachels view states that life is not intrinsically

valuable, the moral issue is about having a biographical life (Rachels, 1986b, p. 5).

Biographical life entails that a human being is an autonomous being. Therefore, if a

person autonomously chooses to end his or her life or have someone else assist him or

her in doing so, then it is morally permissible. One should be free to do as one chooses

as long as no harm is done to others. In supporting the position, Rachels develops a

further argument for the legalization of active euthanasia based on the right to liberty.
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 41

Briefly, this argument is that dying people should be free to choose euthanasia as a

matter of personal liberty. The supporting argument frequently advanced in support of

legalization of active voluntary euthanasia proceeds by way of analogy to the law of

suicide. Rachels also supports his position by the same argument. The argument begins

with the proposition that since it is not unlawful for a person to commit or attempt to

commit suicide, the law, implicitly at least, recognizes the right of an individual to take

his or her life. From this premise it is argued that if an individual does have the right to

take his or her life, he or she should be able to seek the assistance of others in achieving

this end (Rachels, 1983, p.19 ). It should be noted here that Rachels refers to the

American criminal law. Furthermore, Rachelss arguments such as the golden rule and

the best interest argument are based on the same notion of autonomy that if a terminally

ill patient chooses euthanasia as his best interest, such a patient should be granted his

wish.

2.5. Proposal for Legalization of Active Euthanasia

Rachels proposes what he calls the modest proposal for the legalization of

active euthanasia. Before proposing such a proposal, Rachels makes some elementary

points about American law. He states that according to the American law individuals

charged with a crime have no obligations to prove their innocence. Instead of that, the

burden of proof is on the prosecution, and if the prosecution has not discharged its

obligation to prove guilt, the jury's duty is to acquit the defendant. However, if the

prosecution does establish a strong case against the defendant, a more active defense is

required. In such a case, Rachels states that there are two options available.
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 42

The defendant may deny having done the criminal act in question. Or, while

admitting to the act, the defendant may nevertheless argue that he or she should not be

punished for it. Rachels further elaborating on the second case that there are two legally

accepted ways of arguing that a person should not be punished for an act even while

admitting that the act is prohibited by law and that the person did it. First, an excuse

may be offered, such as insanity, coercion, ignorance of fact, unavoidable accident, and

so on. He states that in case of successfully proving any of the grounds then the

defendant may be acquitted. Second a justification may be offered. A plea of

self-defense against a charge of murder is an example of a justification that you were

insane or that the killing was a tragic accident for which you are blameless or that you

had to kill him in self-defense. If none of these defenses can be made out, then you will

be acquitted of the crime even though you admittedly did kill the victim.

Rachels therefore concludes that it is not quite accurate to say that under

American law the burden of proof is always on the prosecution. If the defendant

concedes to having performed the act in question but claims an excuse or justification

for the act, the burden of proof may shift so that the defense is required to show that he

excuse or justification should be accepted (Rachels, 2003).

Rachels while using the above fundamental procedure in the criminal trials in

American courts proposes a legal scenario in which there is legally a successful

possibility of making active voluntary euthanasia a reality without any adverse

repercussions to the physician who performs such an act.

Rachels states that proposal for legalizing active euthanasia is that a plea of
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 43

mercy killing be acceptable as a defense against a charge of murder in much the same

way that a plea of self-defense is acceptable as a defense. He further elaborates that

under his proposal, someone charged with murder could also plead mercy killing; and

then if it could be proven that the victim while competent requested death, and that the

victim was suffering from a painful terminal illness, the person pleading mercy killing

would also be acquitted (Rachels, 2003). Rachels while explaining the above

procedure mentions that under the above proposal no one would be "authorized" to

decide when a patient should be killed. He adds that there are no committees to be

established within which people may cast private votes for which they are not really

accountable; people who choose to mercy kill bear full legal responsibility, as

individuals, for their actions (Rachels, 2003).

How the above procedure would be practically applicable to the cases of voluntary

active euthanasia, Rachels explains the practicality of the case as follows:

In practice, this would mean that anyone contemplating mercy killing would

have to be very sure that there are independent witnesses to testify concerning

the patient's condition and desire to die; for otherwise, one might not be able to

make out a defense in a court of law - if it would come to that - and would be

legally liable for murder. However, if this proposal were adopted, it would not

mean that every time active euthanasia was performed a court trail would

follow. In clear cases of self-defense, prosecutors simply do not bring charges,

since it would be a pointless waste of time. Similarly, in clear cases of mercy

killing, where there is no doubt about the patient's hopeless condition or desire

to die, charges would not be brought for the same reason. (Rachels, 2003)
Exposition of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 44

Rachels after proposing the above proposal claims that under the proposal, the

need to write difficult legislation permitting euthanasia is bypassed. He further

explains that by following the above proposal we would rely on the good sense of

judges and juries to separate the cases of justifiable euthanasia from the cases of

unjustifiable murder, just as we already rely on them to separate the cases of

self-defense and insanity and coercion (Rachels, 2003).


CHAPTER THREE

Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia


3.1. Introduction

The criticism of Rachelss thought on euthanasia is the subject of this chapter.

The arguments developed by Rachels are addressed. The chapter analyzes firstly, the

conceptual framework of Rachels and demonstrates its inadequacy on conceptual and

practical basis ; secondly, it demonstrates the theoretical problems in Rachelss

arguments which attempt to prove the distinction between active and passive

euthanasia is morally absurd , therefore, the criticism leads to invalidity of the validity

of active euthanasia on the basis of the permissibility of so called passive euthanasia,

and thirdly, it criticizes Rachelss arguments for active euthanasia by showing their

weaknesses which affect their soundness. In addition, the researcher also shows the

problems in Rachelss proposal on the legalization of active euthanasia which renders

his proposal problematic and impractical. And, lastly, the researcher debates that there

is only one type of euthanasia which is active euthanasia and which ought to be

rejected, due to unjustifiability of Rachelss arguments, and due to reasons that the

cases of active euthanasia are medically mishandled patients whose death is

unnecessarily prolonged by the use of advanced medical technology. Furthermore, the

researcher demonstrates that passive euthanasia in the sense of letting die is not

euthanasia. Passive euthanasia is an invented name for natural death and it is

misconstrued as passive euthanasia by creating confusion between letting die and

withholding, withdrawing and terminating extraordinary medical treatment. Finally,

the researcher shows that Rachelss active and passive dichotomy is a false dichotomy.
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 46

3.2. Criticism of Rachelss Conceptual Framework

Rachelss conceptual framework includes few distinctions: (1) biological and

biographical life; (2) killing and letting die; and (3) ordinary and extraordinary

medical treatment. On Rachelss view, these distinctions allegedly substantiate his

claim for active euthanasia; however, most of the distinctions make sense only if

passive euthanasia is accepted permissible. Moreover, these distinctions make

premises of Rachelss proposed arguments; therefore their analysis and criticism

directly affects the validity of his given arguments.

The following part of the chapter deals the above distinctions respectively.

The researcher substantiates the claim that Rachelss conceptual framework has

various problems which are reasonably not enough to support the soundness of his

position and that of arguments which mainly draw on such concepts.

3.2.1. Criticism of Biological and Biographical Life

In brief, Rachels makes a distinction between biological and biographical life.

Biological life is merely being a living being; whereas biographical life is the sum of

one's characteristics which are: (1) aspirations, (2) decisions, (3) activities, (4)

projects, and (5) human relationships; and theses characteristics are valuable for a

person and their loss would harm that person. Therefore, Rachels states that only

biographical life is morally relevant (Rachels, 1986b, p. 526, 38). Consequently,

Rachels argues for active euthanasia on the basis of the distinction (Rachels, 1986b, p.

54).
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 47

In spite of the simplicity of the above distinction, the following study shows

that the distinction between biological and biographical life does not provide a valid

foundation or criteria for the permissibility of active euthanasia. The distinction is

rather inadequate due to: (1) reductive fallacy oversimplification; (2) slippery slope

and (3) inconsistency with the main arguments of Rachels.

The first reason is that Rachelss distinction of biological and biographical life

leads to reductive fallacy; he oversimplifies the human nature. The main implication

of the above distinction is that a human person is defined in functional terms and such

a definition is indefensible both conceptually and practically. From Rachelss

distinction it appears that the biographical life, according to Rachels, is a set of

capacities an entity with biological life should posses. This analysis and the

distinction of biological and biographical life are actually aimed at having a definition

of a human person in functional terms. As a matter of fact, Rachels in holding such a

view is not alone; in the same manner, ethicist like Mary Ann Warren draws a more

sophisticated demarcation between so-called genetic humanity and moral

humanity, claiming only those in the latter group are persons. Persons, she claims,

must meet one of five criteria: (1) consciousness; (2) reasoning; (3) self-motivated

activity; (4) the capacity to communicate; and (5) the presence of self-concepts

(Warren, 1996). Likewise, Joseph Fletcher adds the capacities: (1) self-control; (2) a

sense of the future and the past; (3) the ability to relate to others; and (4) curiosity

(Fletcher, 1972). As a result, on this view, the definition of a human person relies on

certain properties, capacities, and functions.


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 48

The above functional view is basically derived from Rene Descartes or John

Locke. Descartess cogito, ergo sum shows what is to be; he claims that a thing

cannot exist without its essential components but being united with the human body

in the proper sense is no part of the essence of mind (Descartes, 1931, p. 97).

Likewise, Locke defines a person as a thinking intelligent being, that has reason and

reflection, and can consider itself as itself, the same thinking thing in different times

and places by that consciousness, which is inseparable from thinking (Locke, 1894, p.

246). According to Descartes and Locke a human person is someone who is actually

acting at the time in a rational manner. In short, if one is acting rationally one is a

person. On the contrary to the above view, there are philosophers on the opposite side.

Aristotelian and Thomastic position argues that there is no distinction between a

human person and a human being; they are inseparable. According to Aristotle, the

human being is defined as one composite substance - the vegetative, sensitive and

rational powers of the soul together with the human body. The whole soul is

homogenous, and in each part of the body as one whole composite; this means that

the several parts of the soul are indiscoverable from one another (as cited in Irving,

1993, endnote. 38). For Thomas Aquinas the name of person does not belong to the

rational part of the soul, nor to the whole soul alone - but to the entire human

substance. He further explains that human being is a human person, and the later

characteristics, such as rational attributes, autonomous willing or sentience, are only

consequential and secondary or accidental actions which follow upon certain powers ,

not parts, which themselves follow upon the essential nature of the human being itself

( as cited in Irving, 1993, endnotes.42, 43).


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 49

The above two opposing trends of thought on divisibility of a human being

has been the center of the philosophy of mind; the discussion in the philosophy of

mind revolves around the distinction between mind and body. This conceptual

divisibility has taken different names and in a derived sense the distinction of human

being and human person belongs to the same category. The survey of this

distinction in the philosophy of mind shows that substance dualism is a discredited

position, and the rest of the positions are either inclusive of or reduced to material or

biological substance. Thus, these theories, in aggregate, lead to the conclusion that the

above mentioned distinctions could be made conceptually but not physically.

The abovementioned conflicting views show that even conceptual

demarcation between a human person and a human being could not be demarcated

precisely; however the practical aspects of such conceptualization are ethically

relevant to the modern developments such as euthanasia and abortion. Therefore, any

derivation on the conceptual distinction of a human entity for justifying the matters of

life and death has practically indefensible consequences. The definition of a human

person in functional terms by ethicists like Rachels, Mary Ann Warren, and Joseph

Fletcher, is not a matter of conceptual hair splitting but of practical nature.

From the functional definition of personhood, it follows that essential

personhood is a degreed property. Therefore, it is undeniable that the first several

years of normal life outside the womb include an increasing expression of human

capacities. Likewise, the last several years of life may include a decreasing expression

of human capacities. Consequently, if the functionalist view is correct, the possession


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 50

of personhood could be expressed by a bell curve, in which a human being moves

toward full personhood in her first years of life, reaches full personhood at a given

point, and then gradually loses her personhood until the end of her life. Presumably,

the commensurate rights of persons would increase, stabilize and decrease in the

process. Without appealing to something other than function, it is difficult to resist

this counterintuitive conclusion. Indeed, intellectual honesty has driven many to

embrace this conclusion, and the slope is ever so slippery. In the same manner, Helga

Kuhse and Peter Singer comment on the ontological status of newborns:

. . . . When we kill a newborn, there is no person whose life has begun.

When I think of myself as the person I am now, I realize that I did not

come into existence until sometime after my birth. . . . It is the

beginning of the life of the person, rather than of the physical organism,

that is crucial so far as the right to life is concerned. (as cited in

Mitchell & Rae, 1996, p. 30)

Furthermore, if the functional model is true, then the mentally ill and retarded,

drug and alcohol addicts and patients with Parkinson's and Alzheimer's diseases are

not persons. The threat is that such model has potential of including the various types

of people with disabilities or diseases. Now it must be admitted that these arguments

apply to the newborn baby as much as to the fetus. And philosopher Richard Frey

pushing Singer's logic one step further, suggests that mentally ill human beings are

therefore also not "persons", and therefore they might be used in purely destructive
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 51

experimental research in place of the higher animals who are "persons"( as cited in

Irving, 1993, endnote.97).

The oversimplification of a human being in the terms of capacities as

described above becomes more troublesome and slippery if Rachelss distinction is

applied in deciding life and death matters. According to Rachels the importance of a

biographical life is that a person has the capacity to set and achieve goals, plans, and

interests that are important from the point of view of the individual. To better grasp

this, consider Rachelss treatment of the 1973 "Texas burn case" where a man known

as Donald C. was horribly burned but was kept alive for two years in the hospital

against his will, and is still alive today. Rachels believes this man's desire to die was

rational because he had lost his biographical life. Rachels suggests:

Now what could be said in defense of the judgment that this man's desire

to die was rational? I believe focusing on the notion of his life (in the

biographical sense) points us in the right direction. He was, among other

things, a rodeo performer, a pilot, and what used to be called a "ladies'

man." His life was not the life of a scholar or a solitary dreamer. What his

injury had done, from his point of view, was to destroy his ability to lead

the life that made him the distinctive individual that he was. There could

be no more rodeos, no more aeroplanes, no more dancing with the ladies,

and a lot more. Donald's position was that if he could not lead that life, he

didn't want to live. (Rachels, 1986b, p. 54)

As illustrated in the above example, it appears that Rachelss definition of


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 52

the biographical life is a very loose definition. The definition does not only justify

mercy killing for suffering terminally ill patients, but also its inclusiveness

justifies killing any one who by the definition seems to fulfill the requirements.

Therefore, euthanasia on such formulation is not only for terminally ill patients as

Rachels argues in his works but for those non terminally ill patients too, who have

lost hope or by some misfortune could not live the life they strive for. The other

aspect of this definition is that if the definition is decisive on life and death of a

person then many other persons besides terminally ill patients will loose right to

life involuntarily. Therefore, Rachelss distinction of biological and biographical

life fails as the distinction entails more than what Rachelss work demands and

accepting such a distinction becomes easy target to slippery slope. Therefore, the

distinction on its own is not sufficient enough to declare a human being

impersonal. As a matter of fact, from the practical point, the Dutch scenario

attests the above inevitable consequences. Herbert Hendin, of the American

Foundation for Suicide Prevention, and two Dutch colleagues, writing in the

Journal of the American Medical Association (June 4, 1997), maintains that

Holland is already sliding down the "slippery slope." In recent decades, they write,

"the Netherlands has moved ... from euthanasia for terminally ill patients to

euthanasia for those who are chronically ill, from euthanasia for physical illness

to euthanasia for psychological distress, and from voluntary euthanasia to non-

voluntary and involuntary euthanasia" (Hendin, 1997, pp. 128-130).

Nevertheless, Rachelss distinction of biological and biographical life

makes sense in the cases when a dying patient is kept alive by the employment of
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 53

life sustaining machines, however, in such a case killing actively is not the only

option, in such a case , the extraordinary medical treatment can be withdrawn or

withheld. Therefore, active euthanasia becomes unnecessary. Moreover, further

problem which emerges from the distinction is that the generality of the

distinction leads to abuse of patients on wider scale.

Again, even though the distinction of biological and biographical life is

supposed to be valid on its own, as a result, problems emerge in Rachels's thought,

because the distinction defines a human person in way which is not coherent with

the main arguments of Rachels which are based on patients consent and

autonomy. The distinction, consequently, leads to permissibility, not only of

voluntary active euthanasia, but also of non-voluntary and involuntary. Although,

Rachels advocates only for permissibility of voluntary active euthanasia in his

main arguments, but his distinction entails the consequences which hardly seem to

escape being the easy target of slippery slope. If the distinction is sufficient, then

any need of patient consent becomes irrelevant. Therefore, the distinction leads to

inconsistency and incoherence in Rachels's thought, and the distinction becomes

irrelevant to Rachelss main arguments for active euthanasia, which are best

interest and golden rule argument and autonomy argument. And both these

arguments are based on patient consent and autonomy.

3.2.2. Criticism of Killing and Letting Die

Killing and letting die distinction in other words could be formulated as

omission and commission. Rachels argues that there is morally no distinction between
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 54

killing someone and letting someone die. The implication of the distinction is related

to the active and passive dichotomy. Rachels by applying above concept attempts to

show that the active and passive dichotomy is a distinction without difference. He

calls it the equivalence thesis, and the main argument for it is called the bare

difference argument: Rachels hypothesizes two cases that are supposed to be exactly

alike except that one involves killing and the other involves letting die. Rachels uses

the distinction in many arguments to force his viewpoint. The distinction is very vivid

in his arguments such as mercy argument, bare difference argument and etc.

The researchers counter position to Rachels is that the distinction between

killing and letting die is: (1) irrelevant, (2) extraneous to the medical profession, and

methodologically degressive.

3.2.2.1. Killing and Letting Die: An Irrelevant Distinction

The killing and letting die discussion is both relevant and irrelevant to the

issue of euthanasia. The relevance could be made when a doctor intentionally

withdraws or withholds the treatment to kill a curable patient; and if such treatment is

continued the patient will live healthy. Thus, in this case there is no difference

between killing and letting die. The distinction is irrelevant to euthanasia because it is

not the case that doctors let the patient die with the intention of killing. The

researchers main claim is that though killing and letting die may be of importance in

various moral issues, however the distinction is itself irrelevant to the issue of

euthanasia. The distinction is unnecessarily brought into the debate on euthanasia to

support killing on the basis of letting die, whereas in fact letting a patient die
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 55

intentionally is not supported by doctors or practically found happening. The

distinction misrepresents the act of withholding, withdrawing and terminating

extraordinary medical treatment, and equates it with letting die. From the very

commonsense point of view, one can save a dying person if the person is in the range

of recovery and when such a person is out of such a range , it is not possible to save

such a person and death of such a person could not be termed as letting die . The

following very simple hypothetical example shows the issue clearly:

Jason was walking on a bridge which is over a deadly river and suddenly he

heard a bomb explosion. He found that the people were running and falling. The walls

of the bridge were destroyed. He found on his right a person, Adam, who was

hanging there grabbing the destroyed wall of the bridge and was about to fall into the

river. On Jasons left was Peter who had just fallen from the bridge and was crying,

falling toward the river and was out of Jasons reach. Jason hopelessly looking at

falling Peter gave his hand to Adam and rescued him.

In the above example the following two cases could be made:

1. Jason saved Adam, because Adam was about to fall and die, however it was

possible for Jason to rescue him. Should Jason be praised for his action or

should he be blamed for not letting Adam die?

2. Jason saw that Peter had already gone out of his reach and was falling to the

river. Should Jason be blamed for letting Peter die?

The response to (2) is clear that Jason did not let Peter die. It was not possible

for him to save him because Peter had gone out of his reach. The same happens in the
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 56

hospitals where a person with a curable disease is saved and those who are incurable

with deadly disease are left on their own with some help which could minimize their

suffering. Rachels treats the issue as letting die. Whereas, the fact is that doctor did

not let the patient die; he simply could not do anything about it. Nevertheless, if a

doctor withholds the treatment from a patient who suffers a curable disease and dies

due to doctors negligence or refusal of treatment, in such a case, it could be claimed

that letting die takes place. Rachels confuses both these cases and tries to make his

point by claiming that the doctor let the patient die in the first case.

The AMAs statement actually holds that it is not allowed to kill a patient and

if the medical treatment seems hopeless and useless, in such a case the patient has

choice to refuse the extraordinary treatment. As the treatment apparently is not going

to show any improvement in the health condition of the patient, the doctor and the

patient, both have reason to agree on termination of medical treatment. The future of

the patient remains hidden with possibilities in the future, and the possibility of

patients recovery from the disease could not be just anticipated as impossible, the

evidence to contrary shows that there are such patients who have recovered after

certain time.

Basically AMAs statement involves two choices: (1) that it is impermissible

for the doctor or anyone else to terminate intentionally the life of a patient, but (2)

that it is permissible in some cases to cease the employment of "extraordinary means"

of preserving life, even though the death of the patient is a foreseeable consequence

(Sullivan, 1994a, p. 132). The first choice could be classified as active euthanasia, it
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 57

includes actively killing a patient and AMAs statement prohibits it. The (2) choice

deserves a clarity. Rachels tries to classify the second option as passive euthanasia

and his definition of passive euthanasia literally means letting die. However, as

shown in the above example the (2) is not passive euthanasia in the sense Rachels

treats it. Therefore, the application of killing and letting distinction to euthanasia is

irrelevant.

3.2.2.2. Killing and Letting Die Distinction and Health Care Professions

The distinction between killing and letting on the wording of Rachels is that in

passive euthanasia a patient is killed by letting him die and in active euthanasia a

patient is killed and both these acts are due to the terminal illness of the patient.

Therefore, killing and letting die are the same and if passive euthanasia is allowed,

active should be permitted too.

Rachelss understanding of the distinction of killing and letting die is actually

inspired by a certain legal and moral understanding of the omission and commission

distinction. The legal position on the distinction varies in different countries and legal

systems. Ernest S. Weinreb (1980) states that in Anglo-American common law unlike

many other legal systems, no general duty requires a passerby to render a stranger

affirmative assistance. Despite the legal tradition, many in America and England

passionately argued that anyone who failed to render assistance should be prosecuted.

Some American states, including Vermont, Minnesota, and Rhode Island, have

adopted statutes requiring strangers to provide affirmative assistance to persons in

distress when they can do so without harm to themselves (as cited in Gorsuch, 2000,
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 58

footnote. 239); however, the legal and moral standing on the issue in special

professions is different. The professional situation where a special relationship exists,

and the patient-physician setting is a paradigmatic example, omissions of ordinary

care are as punishable as affirmative misdeeds. Indeed, a physician's omission of

readily available treatment is clearly a professional malpractice.

In light of the above, the distinction of killing and letting die is very

extraneous to the medical profession. If the distinction is allowed to find its

acceptance into the discipline, it would lead the profession to the wrong side; literally

the profession will become not only life saving but also life taking. As a result, life

care professions will be endangered. The application of the distinction becomes

irrelevant to the professions meant for life caring such as life-guards, fire-fighting,

health care, child care and early child-hood centers such as nurseries, and baby care

centers etc. Here particularly, health care needs a special discussion. Health care or

medicine develops from the objective to save lives and not to take lives. Killing or

letting die a patient changes the definition of the profession itself. The severity of the

issue has given a serious concern to doctors in the field of medicine as follows:

This issue touches medicine at its very moral center; if this moral center

collapses, if physicians become killers or are even merely licensed to kill,

the professionand, therewith, each physicianwill never again be

worthy of trust and respect as healer and comforter and protector of life in

all its frailty. For if medicine's power over life may be used equally to heal

or to kill, the doctor is no more a moral professional but rather a morally


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 59

neutered technician. (Gaylin, Kass, Pellegrino, & Siegler, 1989, p. 26)

Besides the irrelevance of the distinction to the nature of medical profession,

the introduction of the distinction into the profession violates many other foundations

and historical professional grounding of the profession; as first of all it grows the

mistrust and suspicion between the patient and the doctor and secondly this kind of

intrusion is not without other repercussions which freely lead to slippery slope and, in

consequence, elderly people would be eliminated not just because of the reason of

health but of economy. Moreover, the distinction will have adverse psychological

impact on patients; the patient can no longer look at his physician as his advocate for

the extension of lifebecause when in the mind of that physician that patient's life is

waning, the sick person has no guarantee that the physician will approach him in the

role of life preserver; he may be coming as executioner (Koop, 1976/ 1989a, pp. 82-

83).

The relationship between a doctor and patient is professionally that a patient

submits himself to a doctor and entrusts him his life. In such a relationship the doctor

takes the patient through many stages with the hope to save his life. The following

statement clearly depicts the doctors role in handling the patients at various stages of

the health conditions.

I am in the life-saving business and that comes first, but I recognize also that

I am in the business of alleviating suffering. I never take a deliberate action

with the motive of terminating a patient's life. It is possible that a patient's

life might be shortened by some therapeutic measure I employ with the intent
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 60

of relieving suffering. In some circumstances where I believe that I have

sufficient experience and expertise with the life history of a disease process

and my patient's response to that disease as well as to his therapy, I might

withhold treatment that could be considered extraordinary or heroic in the

given circumstance in reference to the quality of life that might be salvaged

for a short period of time. (Koop, 1976/ 1989a, p. 83)

Gay-Williams (1979/1989) while criticizing permissibility of euthanasia on

practical grounds, states that doctors and nurses are, for the most part, totally

committed to saving lives. Their failure in saving a life is like a personal failure and

an insult to their skills and knowledge. He refers to the possibility that euthanasia as a

practice might well alter this. Moreover, it could have a corrupting influence so that

in any case that is severe doctors and nurses might not try hard enough to save the

patient. They might decide that the patient would simply be better off dead and take

the steps necessary to make that come about. He concludes that this attitude could

then carry over to their dealings with patients less seriously ill. The result would be an

overall decline in the quality of medical care (pp. 100-101). Gay-Williams said

concern leads to other concern which is methodologically of crucial importance to the

medical profession. It is a well known fact that the diseases which are easily curable

in our time are the same diseases which were considered fatal at some point of the

history. It is due to hard efforts of medical scientists that their cure became possible.

Against this history of achievements in the medical science, if Rachelss distinction

of killing and letting die is positively considered in the practice of medicine, it will

lead to methodological problems into the discipline. There is possibility that those
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 61

patients who are suffering from deadly diseases will be killed and the effort needed to

help such cases will not be spent. So the introduction of the distinction into medical

practice creates two main problems one is that it changes the definition of the

profession and such definition creates other problems such as mistrust between the

patient and the doctor, secondly it removes the skeptic nature of scientific

methodology which is progressive and the distinction aims at terminating every odds

without making any effort to find any solutions.

3.2.3. Criticism of Ordinary and Extraordinary Means of Treatment

Rachels while finding flaws in the American Medical Associations policy

statement claims that the statement states that life sustaining treatment may

sometimes be stopped if the means of treatment are "extraordinary", Rachels adds, the

implication is that "ordinary" means of treatment may not be withheld. To above

position, Rachels states that, however, upon reflection it is clear that it is sometimes

permissible to omit even very ordinary sorts of treatments (Rachels, 1981/ 1994b,

p.143).

Rachels debates the definitions of ordinary and extraordinary forwarded by

Paul Ramsey and supported by Thomas Sullivan. Rachels criticizes the definition is

useless. He states that two problems regarding the distinction and shows that the

distinction is senseless. He firstly criticizes the way the word "excessive" functions in

these definitions. Secondly, Rachels turns to the use of the word "benefit" in the

definitions. Rachels concludes that if the distinction is applied in a straightforward,

commonsense way, the traditional doctrine is false, for it is clear that it is sometimes
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 62

permissible to omit ordinary treatments. On the other hand, if we define the terms as

suggested by Ramsey and Sullivan, the distinction is useless in practical decision

making (Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p. 145).

In response to Rachels, the researcher argues that Rachelss claim against

AMA statement is not valid. There are two reasons to support such a claim: (1)

AMAs statement does not make any distinction between ordinary and extraordinary

medical care and (2) the distinction of ordinary and extraordinary is useful in

practical decision making.

The first reason as stated above is that AMAs statement does not make a

distinction between ordinary and extraordinary medical treatment. The statement is

rather carefully worded; it mentions only the cessation of the employment of

extraordinary means to prolong the life. The statement does not mention what is

ordinary and what is extraordinary. The fact is that there is always something

extraordinary about everything. And, what Rachels thinks is ordinary, may in fact be

extraordinary, and vice versa. The drafting committee of the AMAs statement has

shown sharpness and wisdom in avoiding any demarcation between ordinary and

extraordinary medical treatment. Professionally, what could be classified as ordinary

and extraordinary in the medical treatment is by no means a laypersons game. Even

the most ordinary aid such as food and water could become extraordinary in

circumstances when a person is feed by tubes in a vegetative state. Therefore, the

demarcation of ordinary and extraordinary should be left to the experts of the field as

the researcher considers it in the second reason.


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 63

The second reason is that the distinction between ordinary and extraordinary

medical treatment is valid and useful. The fact is that the definition of ordinary and

extraordinary is evolutionary in its content. Technologically, medicine has advanced

so quickly that older, unwritten understandings of "ordinary" and "extraordinary" care

no longer seem applicable. What might have been considered "extraordinary" care a

few years ago is now so commonplace as to be called "ordinary" - respirators,

pacemakers, kidney dialysis machines, etc. The following example is very suitable in

discerning the nature and meaning of ordinary and extraordinary medical treatment.

If one had acute appendicitis and postoperatively developed a situation

where his kidneys did not function, to put him on a dialysis machine (an

artificial kidney) which could handle his urinary function temporarily

would be an extraordinary act and might at times be considered to be

"extraordinary" care. However, in a vigorous, alert, productive individual

with a normal life expectancy of several decades ahead of him, it should not

be considered "extraordinary" care. On the other hand, if in a ninety-year-

old individual the same kidney shutdown took place and was the result of a

disease process that inevitably would take this patient's life, the institution

of dialysis would be an "extraordinary procedure" and would definitely be

thought of, by any medically competent individual, as providing

"extraordinary" care. (Koop, 1976/ 1989a, pp. 72-73)

The above example shows that the difference between ordinary and

extraordinary treatment is a matter of physicians experience , it would most of the


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 64

time depend on many factors such as the condition of the patient, and to what level a

patient would be able or viable to bear the expenses of in case any expensive aid or

treatment is required. Rachelss view that there is no demarcation between ordinary

and extraordinary treatment is therefore an uneducated guess. The distinction between

ordinary and extraordinary treatment depends on the wisdom of a physician what his

prudence would lead to. It is worthwhile to quote Max J. Charlesworth as follows:

But while there is obviously something in this distinction [ordinary and

extraordinary] it is, as we have seen, a relative and variable one. In fact, it is

rather like the legal criterion of 'the reasonable man'. In certain cases we ask

ourselves, 'What would the reasonable man have done? ' or 'How would the

reasonable man have acted in this situation?' We are all aware that this is a

very rough and ready criterion since what the 'reasonable man' would have

done in Victorian times in the nineteenth century is clearly very different

from what the 'reasonable man' might do in our present enlightened and

liberated times. Again, what the Anglo-Saxon 'reasonable man' might do

will be very different from what the Turkish or Greek 'reasonable man'

might do. Nevertheless the criterion works in a rough and ready way at the

practical level. (Charlesworth, 1989, pp. 65-66)

The second objection which Rachels poses to ordinary and extraordinary

treatment is about the use of the word "benefit" in the definitions. It is said that

ordinary treatments offer a reasonable hope of benefit for the patient; and that

treatments are extraordinary if they will not benefit the patient. Rachels notes that
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 65

how do we tell if a treatment will benefit the patient? Again, the point is that in order

to decide whether life-sustaining treatment is a benefit we must first decide whether it

would be a good thing for the life in question to be prolonged(Rachels, 1981/ 1994b,

p. 145). The objection of Rachels could be responded by stating that first of all the

distinction between ordinary and extraordinary firstly depends on the prudence of the

practitioner as stated above and secondly it appeals to the severity of the condition a

patient goes through. The benefit of the care to the patients health condition is what

is a real matter a doctor should be concerned about not what Rachels suggests. Should

the life in question to be prolonged is something very judgmental on life and death

and a doctor is not supposed to be judging that. It must always be clear that the

doctor's role is not to assess the value or worth of the patient but that of the treatment'

(British Medical Association, 1999/ 2007, p.8). The real concern a doctor should have

is that will the available care to patient make an ordinary or extraordinary treatment.

Therefore, Rachelss claim is normatively unjustifiable because the benefit of the care

to the patients health condition is what is a real matter a doctor should be concerned

about; deciding the life and death of the patient puts the physician in an unwarranted

prerogative role which is problematic due to legal complexities, rights, duties, and

autonomy. Such a judgmental role is also prone to abuse and corruption. Therefore,

the doctors role is not to assess the value or worth of the patient but that of the

treatment.
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 66

3.3. Criticism of Rachelss Arguments against Traditional Doctrine on

Euthanasia (TDE)

Rachels argues against the traditional doctrine on euthanasia (TDE) or

conventional doctrine on euthanasia (CDE) which is also called as conventional view

or standard view which makes a distinction between active and passive euthanasia.

This view, on Rachelss understanding, is upheld by the American Medical

Association. According to Rachels the conventional view, passive euthanasia is

sometimes permitted whereas active euthanasia is never permitted. It is necessary to

note here that AMAs statement which is the actual target of Rachelss criticism does

not make such a distinction. The statement disallows intentional killing of terminal

patients and permits the termination of extraordinary medical care, in doing so the

statement allows the cessation of medical treatment in extraordinary cases.

In arguing against CDE Rachels gives four arguments which on his

formulation render the distinction between active and passive euthanasia morally

absurd. Therefore, Rachels tries to prove that whereas passive euthanasia is allowed

active euthanasia should be permitted too. The arguments are explained in the second

chapter of this research. In the following part of the chapter the researcher, after

highlighting the main points of Rachelss arguments, criticizes the arguments

respectively.
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 67

3.3.1. Criticism of that often Active Euthanasia Seems More Humane than

Passive

Rachels claims that often active euthanasia seems more humane than passive

and therefore active euthanasia should not be only permitted but preferred too.

Rachels reinforces his position in mercy argument. He illustrates the claim by

examples of terminally ill patients to show that allowing the patient to die is much

more painful and inhumane than active euthanasia (Rachels, 1975/ 1994a, p.113).

The logical form of the argument according to Don Berkich is as follows:

1. If CDE is true then passive euthanasia never produces more suffering than

active euthanasia.

2. It is not the case that passive euthanasia never produces more suffering

than active euthanasia.

Therefore

3. CDE is not true. (1& 2). ( Berkich , 2003 )

Rachels above argument mainly faces two responses which render his

argument invalid. The first response is that Rachels argues against CDE on the basis

not included in the AMAs statement. Rachelss argument against AMAs position is

irrelevant. Rachelss arguments against CDE are actually supposed to be strictly

against the text of the AMA statement, whereas the above argument actually does

not address the statement. The AMAs statement does not make difference because of

pain or suffering. Therefore, Rachelss argument does not render the statement false
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 68

or invalid. According the AMAs statement, CDE is not based on suffering and no

consideration is included on methods which produce less or more suffering. The

validity test of the argument turns the argument invalid if the case is strictly

considered against the AMAs statement. Because, AMAs statement makes the

difference between killing and termination of extraordinary medical treatment. The

suffering as such is not the part of the statement. Therefore, the argument doest not

give any problem to AMAs position.

The second response could be made if Rachelss argument is taken against

CDE from the point of suffering as a separate argument with the content not

considered in AMAs statement; that killing a terminally ill patient is better than

leaving the patient suffer in pain. The argument from its simplicity, make a

convincing point. However, the following arguments can be made against such an

argument which render Rachelss argument unimportant, irrelevant, and inadequate.

The first point is that, though, a person is thought to be dying after a few days

when such a patient is terminated from medical treatment as a potential subject to

death, still the fact of dying is in the future. Will that patient die or live another few

healthy years is not known as a matter of fact. There are cases in which the

terminated person lived longer or healthier after being terminated from the treatment.

To show how difficult predictions might be, Medical World News on May 5, 1974,

reported a case of a woman with myasthenia gravis who lived "artificially" for 652

days in intensive care and then made a remarkable recovery. Said a hospital

representative at the Harbor General Hospital in Torrance, California, "She made us


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 69

recognize that there was no such thing as inordinate effort. She had such a tenacity for

life we felt that everything we did, no matter how extraordinary, was appropriate to

the situation (Koop, 1976/ 1989a, p.73). The case from the practical point goes

against the active euthanasia, because recovery is a probability, therefore it is better to

terminate the medical aid than actively kill a person. It is a well known fact that

people have been known to recover from comas after considerable periods, and some

terminally ill patients make miraculous recoveries. Allowing euthanasia would risk

killing people who could otherwise have had years more life. With euthanasia the

price of a mistake is too high. Philosophically, appeal to the future is itself a fallacy,

arguing that evidence will someday be discovered which will, then, support your

point. Now this appeal to the future as a fallacy applies to argument for active

euthanasia instead of terminating extraordinary medical care. In case of terminating

extraordinary medical treatment, the doctors withhold or withdraw the medical

treatment on the conviction that the treatment is useless and the patient will die,

whereas within the same conditions of conviction, in active euthanasia, the doctors

kill the patient. It is the second case in which doctors, if allowed, are about to commit

the fallacy as they take the future as a fact and granted.

The second point is that modern advanced medical technology has most

developed treatment to control the pain or suffering of a patient. Therefore, the

argument which states that a suffering person could be killed has no basis except that

the medical care is not ready to support those ant-pain killing treatment.

The pain and suffering should they be the basis for deciding the permissibility
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 70

of active euthanasia, the case is contrary to what Rachels states. If the need of active

euthanasia is due to suffering, but, on the other hand, suffering could be controlled by

medication without actively killing a patient, therefore active euthanasia seems

undesirable. With the highly effective painkillers now available there is never any

need even for the terminally ill to suffer great pain. Use of painkillers, not euthanasia,

is the answer to painful terminal illness. [I]n up to 90 percent of [cancer] patients,

the pain can be controlled by relatively simple means. Nevertheless, under treatment

of cancer pain is common because of clinicians' inadequate knowledge of effective

assessment and management practices, negative attitudes of patients and clinicians

toward the use of drugs for the relief of pain, and a variety of problems related to

reimbursement for effective pain management (Jacox, Carr, & Payne, 1994, p.651-

655).

The other connected issue is that if suffering is the basis for permissibility of

active euthanasia then only terminally ill patients are not the only subjects of the

active euthanasia, there are many patients with diseases and suffering who are not

terminally ill. Kelley & Clifford (1997) reported that Edwin S. Schneidman, founder

of the American Association of Suicidology, maintains that dying is not painful; it is

the illness that causes the pain. However, an individual does not have to have a

terminal illness to have intractable pain, to which many people with conditions such

as arthritis and fibromyalgia will attest (as cited in Manetta & Wells, 2001).

The other important notion which is connected with suffering is the

conception of suffering itself. The suffering can be physical and it can be mental or
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 71

psychological. The euthanasia supporters may claim the end to physical suffering but

what about psychological suffering. If suffering becomes the basis for the

permissibility of active euthanasia, then many patients who are not terminally ill but

psychologically suffering or non-terminally ill patients , will be subjects of euthanasia

as well. Therefore, suffering as itself is an inadequate reason for permissibility of

active euthanasia. The other reason is that suffering is actually about the attitude. The

argument from suffering reaches beyond medicine's responsibility and competence; it

extends into metaphysical questions about the nature of human happiness and of what

constitutes a meaningful life. To enlist a physician to achieve release from a

meaningless life of suffering presumes that the physician is competent to judge what

kinds of life is worth of living. The roots of suffering are more than physical. The

degree to which people suffer and whether they find life empty or meaningful depend

more on their attitude than on their physical condition (Gula, 1999a, pp.501-5).

From the practical point of view, suffering is irrelevant to the issue of

euthanasia due to advances in palliative care. In many cases of terminal cancer the

choice is no longer between dying in agony and deliberately ending one's life since

appropriate palliative care enables such patients to live out their lives in relative ease

and peace. However, while it may be true that in many cases one may die in such a

way as to keep one's self-respect without taking measures to end one's life, there are

surely many situations where a person might, for very good reasons, no longer wish

to prolong his or her life. These cases are cited in Rachelss works also. He illustrates

his arguments by such examples. However, the reason which renders such a position

invalid is that the cases are of patients who were kept alive by extraordinary means;
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 72

their death was prolonged due to inappropriate use of advanced medical technology.

One of the famous examples of such cases is of Karen Ann Quinlan (March 29,

1954 June 11, 1985). When she was 21, Quinlan became unconscious after coming

home from a party, and lapsed into a persistent vegetative state. After she was kept

alive on a ventilator for several months without improvement, her parents requested

the hospital discontinue active care and allow her to die. Karen Ann Quinlan's

parents, for example, believed that their daughter would not have wanted to live in a

comatose, 'human vegetable', state for ten years. But, as we know, they were unable

to get her physicians to discontinue her life-sustaining treatment (Charlesworth,

1989, pp. 75-77). Karens case is one of the most illustrated cases in the history of

euthanasia. The analysis of her case clearly shows that she was kept alive in

vegetative state for long time , had her life sustaining machines disconnected she

could have died earlier with out suffering herself and her parents. The point is that if a

person could not be cured by ordinary medical treatment and providing extraordinary

treatment to such a patient when death is foreseen would only create suffering.

Unfortunately, Rachels has nothing to say about it in his works. He has not made any

contribution in showing that the root cause of pitiful cases is actually mishandling of

patients by advanced medical technology.

However, responding to above counter reasoning, Rachels can argue and he

has actually argued that there are still patients, their death is foreseen and instead of

killing them they are left to die and their dying process takes days and weeks in

suffering. He therefore argues that such patients could have been better off by active

euthanasia by putting end to their suffering. The researcher argues against it from two
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 73

reasons. The first as elaborated earlier is that pain killers and palliative care has made

suffering irrelevant. The second reason is that those patients who are terminally ill

and their life may be miserable due to the pain which is caused by illness. For such

patients double doctrine effect opens the way and avoids any need of active

euthanasia. Simply, those patients will go through their dying process and their pain

will be controlled by medicine even though such medication may shorten their lives

as a side effect, so the shortening life will be treated as a side effect and not as the

intended consequence. This last solution which prescribes pain medication to painful

terminally ill patients comes with the famous principle called as Doctrine of Double

Effect (DDE).

There are many names for Doctrine of Double Effect (DDE) such as Principle

of Double Effect (PDE), Rule of Double Effect (RDE), Double-Effect Reasoning

(DER), and simply Double Effect. The mention of DDE is of paramount importance

because of its use in practical medicine and its existence as a backbone for many

arguments which propose pain medication to alleviate the suffering of terminally ill

patients. Thomas Aquinas is credited with introducing the principle of double effect

in his discussion of the permissibility of self-defense in the Summa Theologica (II-II,

Qu. 64, and Art.7). According to him, nothing hinders one act from having two

effects, only one of which is intended, while the other is beside the intention (as

cited in McIntyre, 2004). The classical formulation of the principle requires

fulfillment of four conditions if the action in question is permissible: (1) that the

action contemplated be in itself either morally good or morally indifferent; (2) that

the bad result not be directly intended; (3) that the good result not be a direct causal
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 74

result of the bad result; and (4) that the good result be "proportionate to" the bad

result. Where all these conditions are met, the action under consideration is morally

permissible despite the bad result (Solomon, n.d. Formulation of the Principle).

Thought the doctrine has many applications; in particular, its application in

treating terminally ill is widely accepted and traditionally practiced. The principle is

used to justify the case where a doctor gives drugs to a patient to relieve distressing

symptoms even though he knows doing this may shorten the patient's life. This is

because the doctor is not aiming directly at killing the patient - the bad result of the

patient's death is a side-effect of the good result of reducing the patient's pain. Many

doctors use this doctrine to justify the use of high doses of drugs such as morphine for

the purpose of relieving suffering in terminally-ill patients even though they know the

drugs are likely to cause the patient to die sooner. The double effect doctrine, as

applied in medicine, is based on two basic presuppositions: the doctor's motivation is

to alleviate suffering; and the treatment must be proportional to the illness. The

doctrine applies if 1) the desired outcome is judged to be good e.g., relief of suffering;

2) the bad outcome e.g., death of patient is not intended; 3) the good outcome is not

achieved by means of the bad, and 4) the good outcome outweighs the bad (Cohen-

Almagor, 2000, pp. 267-278). Theses conditions of the principle are well elaborated

on practical grounds by Wanzer et al. (1989/1990); they suggest that in the patient

whose dying process is irreversible, the balance between minimizing pain and

suffering and potentially hastening death should be struck clearly in favor of pain

relief. They recommend that pain medication should be given in whatever dose and

by whatever route is necessary for relief. They further suggest that in extreme cases it
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 75

is morally correct to increase the dose, even though the medication may contribute to

the depression of respiration or blood pressure, the dulling of consciousness, or even

death, provided the primary goal of the physician is to relieve suffering. They suggest

that however the proper dose of pain medication is the dose that is sufficient to

relieve pain and suffering, even to the point of unconsciousness (p. 287).

It is therefore an accepted practice to use doctrine of double effect in such cases

which contain suffering. Even in cases where death is imminent and pain cannot be

minimized or eliminated through normally accepted dosages of medication, active

euthanasia is not the only option. A doctor can give the necessary pain medication if

the intent is solely to alleviate pain and not to kill, even if it can be foreseen that such

an action will hasten death. In this case death is a foreseen, tolerated, but an

unintended effect.

3.3.2. Criticism of the Conventional View Makes Life-And-Death Decisions

on Irrelevant Grounds

Rachels claims that the conventional view makes life-and-death decisions on

irrelevant grounds therefore the conventional view, CDE, is not true. In support of

the claim he refers to the case of babies with Down syndrome. He emphasizes the

cruelty involved in permitting the child to suffer when there is a lethal injection

available that can put him out of his misery. Rachels draws the attention towards that

if the lives of these infants are worth living, then their lives should be preserved.

Allowing to die and actively killing would be equally wrong (Rachels, 1975/

1994a, p.115). Rachels's point is that hence the babies are being left to die; it would
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 76

be for better to kill such babies and therefore terminate their suffering. The logical

form of the argument according to Don Berkich is as follows:

1. If acting in accordance with CDE leads to decisions about passive

euthanasia being made on irrelevant grounds, then CDE is false.

2. Acting in accordance with CDE leads to decisions about passive

euthanasia being made on irrelevant grounds.

Therefore

3. CDE is false. (1&2). ( Berkich , 2003 )

What exactly are the irrelevant grounds which Rachels is trying to show? The

grounds which seem irrelevant to Rachels are killing and letting die on the basis of

suffering. To him relevant ground ought to be suffering of the patient which should

be considered in deciding the killing of a patient; that the suffering is what should

allow a doctor to eliminate a human being actively and what minimizes that suffering

should be the relevant ground. The researcher thinks that the case is somehow

different. The relevant grounds in CDE are the ordinary and extraordinary medical

care; there is no mention of suffering at all. The CDE makes case clear that when

doctors are hopeless about the recovery of a patient; then such doctors can

discontinue the treatment. Had the CDE being based on minimizing suffering,

Rachels argument would have won the case from the utilitarian point of view. Simply,

it could be argued that the premise 2 in the argument is false as the relevant ground

for passive euthanasia in CDE is relevant and that is confirming that the employed

health care is useless and most expectedly the patient will die as a natural course. The
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 77

concept of suffering in the whole debate seems an interesting invention by Rachels.

His whole thought is based on the same grounds. In every argument he would be

appealing to suffering and showing that suffering could be minimized by active

euthanasia alone.

Allowing to die and actively killing, are the irrelevant grounds which Rachels

thinks that CDE is based on. That allowing to die should be permitted whereas

actively killing should be opposed. As said in the previous argument if a patient is

dying and the process is painful, such suffering can be controlled by the application

of doctrine of double effect. There is no such a need to recourse to active euthanasia.

Therefore, the suffering is not the relevant ground and its irrelevance is shown

in the previous arguments. The relevant grounds are killing and terminating the

extraordinary care. These are relevant in CDE and on this relevance the distinction

between active euthanasia and terminating extraordinary medical care is based.

3.3.3. Criticism of that there is no Moral Difference between Doings and

Refraining

Rachels claims that there is no moral difference between doings and

refraining, therefore wherever refraining is allowed doing should be permitted too.

From the claim, Rachels attempts to prove that wherever passive euthanasia is

allowed active should be allowed too. And, therefore according to Rachels CDE is

false. The logical form of the argument according to Don Berkich is as follows:
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 78

1. If killing is morally worse than letting die, then for any two cases C1 and

C2, where C1 and C2 are exactly alike in all respects except that in C1 there

is a killing while in C2 there is a letting die, C1 is morally worse than C2.

2. It is not the case that for any two cases C1 and C2, where C1 and C2 are

exactly alike in all respects except that in C1 there is a killing while in C2

there is a letting die, C1 is morally worse than C2.

Therefore

3. It is not the case that killing is morally worse (1&2)

4. If CDE is true then killing is morally worse than letting die.

Therefore

5. CDE is not true. (3& 4). ( Berkich , 2003 )

In other words, the argument argues that CDE is false by showing that passive

euthanasia is morally no better than active euthanasia or, equivalently, that active

euthanasia is morally no worse than passive euthanasia.

The researchers position is that Rachelss argument is invalid due to four

reasons: (1) irrelevance to AMAs statement; (2) differences between the cases

because of intentionality, causality, and agency; (3) straw man fallacy, (4) and weak

analogy.

The first reason is that the argument is irrelevant to AMAs statement which

does not make any distinction between killing and letting die. The AMAs statement

prohibits the intentional killing and allows the termination of extraordinary medical
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 79

treatment. Rachelss argument against the statement is irrelevant because the

statement is not about letting die as elaborated in the conceptual framework of this

chapter.

The second reason is that even if Rachels thinks that withholding

extraordinary treatment is letting die, nevertheless, his argument still fails because in

active euthanasia killing is intended whereas death in passive euthanasia happens

naturally without any intention. The crucial differences between active and passive

euthanasia which make them different are: intentionality, causality, and agency and

these three concepts make a moral difference. Therefore, the premise (1) in the above

argument is invalid. C1 and C2 are not alike; therefore they are not alike morally. It

should be noted here that Rachels is making argument against AMAs statement.

The first argument in favor of above claim is that the intention in both cases is

different therefore the cases are different morally. The difference of intention is well

understood by Rachels; that is why he has disregarded such difference. Moreover,

Rachels is a utilitarian consequantilist, therefore intentions are not considered by him,

and only consequences are relevant to his ethical theory. Rachels suggests that bad

intentions and good intentions are relevant to bad and good characters and they have

no connection with moral actions as such. However, Rachelss disregard of intentions

is not sufficient to remove the importance of intentions from the subject of delivering

any position on any ethical action. The researcher thinks that relevance of intentions

is of importance the morality of actions; furthermore, the researcher suggests the

view that killing and letting die are not just morally different due to intentions alone,
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 80

but due to other factors which are morally relevant such as causation and agency.

Rachelss immediate respondent, Thomas Sullivan, pointed out the problem of

intentionality in Rachelss thought and he suggested that Rachels makes the

distinction between the act of killing and the act of letting die be "a distinction that

puts a moral premium on overt behavior moving or not moving one's parts

while totally ignoring the intentions of the agent" (Sullivan, 1977/ 1994a, p. 135). The

fact is that an intentional action or omission is different in character, both morally and

legally, from an unintended consequence. Our intentional actions say something

about us and our character that no unintended side-effect possibly can. Unlike

unintended consequences, our intentional conduct is always within our control. An

intentional act is one of choice. An intended act "remains, persists, ... [and] is

synthesized into one's will, one's practical orientation and stance in the world (Finnis ,

1990). As Charles Fried has put the point:

[I]t is natural that the most stringent moral judgments should relate to

intentional acts.... Morality is about the good and the right way of our

being in the world as human beings. And the way we relate to the world as

human beings is as we pursue our purposes in the world, i.e., as we act

intentionally.... This primacy of intention explains why in law and morals a

sharp line is drawn between the result, which is intended [,] ... and the certain

concomitant, which [is not] intended.... To see a paradox in this distinction

assumes that because the result in the world is the same in the two cases the
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 81

judgment in them must be too. In short, it ignores the element of purpose.

(Fried ,1976)

To return to practical nature of euthanasia, the main difference between active

and passive euthanasia is because the intention in both cases is different. In passive

euthanasia, the patients and doctors who resort to withdrawing or terminating medical

care do so not for the reasons of intending the death of the patient. Moreover, the

Patients who decline the extraordinary medical care do so for many reasons that in no

way implicate an intention to die. They may wish to avoid further pain associated

with the invasive treatments and tubes and the poking and prodding of modern

medical care. They may wish to avoid the sense of indignity that dependence on

medical machinery sometimes can bring. They may wish simply to go home from the

hospital, to be with loved ones, and to restore their privacy. None of these decisions--

or any of the other countless reasons for refusing care expressed every day by persons

confronting an inevitable death--involves intent to die even when death is foreseen.

Likewise, those persons who assist patients in declining unwanted treatment need not

necessarily intend death as either a means or as an end. They may intend only to

discontinue treatment to permit the patient to go home, to live without intrusive

assistance, to avoid further pain associated with treatment. They may foresee death as

a result of their actions without ever purposefully seeking it out. As the AMA (1992)

has put the point, the "withdrawing or withholding of life-sustaining treatment is not

inherently contrary to the principles of beneficence and non malfeasance," while

assisted suicide is "contrary to the prohibition against [intentionally] using the tools

of medicine to cause a patient's death (pp. 2230-33).


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 82

The second argument which supports the above claim is that causation and

agency make the cases of active and passive euthanasia morally different. Philippa

Foot has argued very well on the issue. Her argument makes a distinction between

active and passive euthanasia by stating that a death comes about through our

agency if we send someone poisoned food or cut him up for spare parts, but not

(ordinarily) if we fail to save him when he is threatened by accident or disease (Foot,

1984 /1994b, p.282). She furthermore states that the difference between act and

omission is in fact irrelevant to any moral issue except in so far as it corresponds to

the distinction between allowing something to happen and being the agent to whom

the happening can be ascribed (Foot, 1984 /1994b, p.281). She therefore challenges

the utilitarians, who place the whole moral significance of an action in its production

of good or harm, that they must treat the difference between initiating and allowing as

having no independent influence on morality. Philippa Foots suggestion is that in

active euthanasia the physician is cause and agent who performs the action of killing,

whereas in passive euthanasia the physician is neither cause nor agent to killing or

letting die a patient.

The third argument is that Rachelss claim unreasonably disregards the

distinction between ignorance of law and ignorance of fact. The distinction is widely

held decisive in every criminal or civil law texts and accordingly acted upon by courts.

Rachels uses ignorance of fact in his legalization proposal, therefore, the researcher

believes that the mention of ignorance of fact does not stand outside the context. The

ignorance of fact, if understood properly is that it speaks about the intentionality,

motive, and purpose. The law reflects the distinct moral force of intention that we
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 83

understand through our common experience. A crime committed intentionally

receives greater punishment than the same act done unintentionally. We recognize

differing "degrees" of homicide, and countless other crimes, depending upon whether

the act was done intentionally, knowingly, recklessly, or negligently. Such

differentiation continues through sentencing. Thus, the law treats the driver who

speeds recklessly but harms the darting child accidentally differently than the

depraved killer who deliberately plans to harm the child. However, Rachels may

object to this analysis that his position is moral and not legal. The response to such

claim is that though it is a fact that a legal action does not need to be a moral one and

vice versa, but the context in which Rachels states his position is a legal one. His

normative decisions are addressed to physicians and courts alike. And his proposal on

legalizing active euthanasia is also of legal nature. Therefore, Rachelss position is

not in a shape to avoid its legal criticism and therefore the adverse ramifications of

his position. Therefore, Rachelss removal of intention from judging an action

morally or legally is not only against the positive legal procedures but also against his

own legalization proposal where he states that a physician can defend his act of mercy

killing, besides other grounds, on the basis of ignorance of fact.

The third reason is that Rachels makes very superficial and shallow claim that

if a patient is dying and could be in fact cured and doctor leaves such a patient

without care and such a patient dies, and in the case killing and letting die would

make no difference. Rachels claims that in the same manner a physician lets a patient

die. Therefore, active and passive euthanasia are the same. Rachelss claim is very

irresponsible and subject to fallacies such as straw man fallacy, missing the point,
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 84

and equivocation; because terminating ordinary medical care when the patient is

potentially able to recover is not the subject matter of active euthanasia or passive

euthanasia. Of course, if a doctor lets a curable patient die by withholding,

withdrawing or terminating medical care in such a case the physicians act would not

be even an active euthanasia; his action will be a homicide, a crime. Rachelss by

arguing from such a proposition diverts the debate and leads his argument to straw

man fallacy; he therefore misses the point and leads to equivocation: passive

euthanasia therefore becomes neither mercy killing, nor letting die but a murder.

From the above reasons, it is clear that the intention is crucial in making a

moral and legal difference between two actions with similar consequences or

unintended consequences. The same is true about the two hypothetical cases of Smith

and Johns which Rachels gives in his argument. The cases are different, therefore

active and passive euthanasia are different.

The fourth reason is that Rachelss illustration of Smith and Johns in support

of his argument commits fallacy of weak analogy. Rachels hypothetical case as

mentioned earlier is called bare difference" argument of Rachels. The argument

contrasts two cases of Smith and Jones. The contrast is an attempt to show that two

different actions one killing and other letting die are morally the same. In fact,

the cases are supposed to show as presented by Rachels that the difference between

killing and letting die is irrelevant to any moral judgment. But the contrast fails to

make the point. Both the cases show the same result, however, the contrast is not

analogous with the actual case of euthanasia. The analysis of the case shows that in
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 85

both of these cases the victim is a person who is potentially able to live. In Smiths

case the victim is deliberately murdered and in Jones case the victim is intentionally

left to die. Comparing the same case with euthanasia, in active euthanasia a person

whose fate is not yet known whether he will live or die or at most he may be going to

die, is being killed whereas in passive euthanasia such a person is left to die.

Comparing case of Jones and passive euthanasia the analogy becomes problematic. In

Jones case the victim is a healthy young boy with a good potential for life, whereas

in passive euthanasia the patient is terminally ill with no hope of recovery. In Jones

case if help is extended to the victim, he could be saved, whereas, in passive

euthanasia even extending help would not make things better or rescue the dying

person from process of death. Furthermore, Unlike Jones cousin, the recipients of

passive euthanasia are not victims; they are autonomous agents who have the right to

refuse treatment. If a doctor administers treatment against the will of patient, he

infringes on the rights of the patient as a free agent and is guilty of assault and battery.

Thus in the case of passive euthanasia, the doctor is not allowed to help the patient

and should not be held morally responsible for the death of the patient. Jones has a

choice to save his cousin and does nothing while the doctor is unable to do anything

to save his patient because of the patients autonomy and right to refuse treatment.

Thus even though there is , on Rachelss formulation, no moral distinction between

killing and letting die there is a distinction between active and passive euthanasia.

The two cases are not analogous and the distinction between active and passive

euthanasia lies in the patients autonomy and ability to refuse treatment. Therefore,

the inference from killing and letting die to active and passive euthanasia does not
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 86

stand valid.

3.3.4. Criticism of that the Arguments in Favor of the Conventional View do not

Work

Rachels mentions that one often heard argument for the conventional view

goes like that in passive euthanasia, there is nothing that the doctor does which can be

called cause of death. The disease causes the patient to die, not the doctor. So how

can the doctor be held responsible for the death, if he doesnt even do anything?

The logical form of the argument according to Don Berkich is as follows:

1. Active euthanasia is doing something to bring about death.

2. Passive euthanasia is not doing anything

3. Doing something to bring about death is worse than not doing anything.

Therefore

4. Active euthanasia is worse than passive euthanasia (1, 2&3)

5. If active euthanasia is worse than passive euthanasia, then CDE is true.

Therefore

6. CDE is true (4&5) . ( Berkich , 2003 )

Rachels responses to above argument and shows that the argument in favor of

CDE is unsound. Rachels shows that premise 2 Passive euthanasia is not doing

anything and premise 3 Doing something to bring about death is worse than not

doing anything are false.


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 87

Passive euthanasia is not doing anything, as the premise 2 states in the

argument. But Rachels maintains that letting a patient die is also doing. Rachelss

argument is unsound due to two reasons: (1) the direct cause of death is different, in

the active it is the doctor an in the passive it is the disease itself; (2) Rachelss

argument is fallacious due to straw man fallacy.

The first reason is that the direct cause of death is different; in active

euthanasia it is the doctor as a human agent who actually kills the patient, whereas in

the passive euthanasia it is the disease itself. The distinction between active and

passive euthanasia is clear that causality of the death in active euthanasia is a lethal

injection whereas in passive euthanasia the cause of the death is disease itself. The

distinction pivots on the way we understand causality and culpability. In killing, the

cause of death is the lethal intervention. In allowing to die, the cause of death is the

natural biological process. When the cause of death is the impersonal force of nature,

no one can be held responsible. But if death results from the human action of

injecting or ingesting lethal medication, then someone can be held culpable. The

causality in killing and letting die cannot be the same; Daniel Callahan has put the

difference succinctly as follows:

[I]t confuses reality and moral judgment to see an omitted action as having

the same causal status as one that directly kills. A lethal injection will kill

both a healthy person and a sick person. A physician's omitted treatment will

have no effect on a healthy person. Turn off the machine on me, a healthy

person, and nothing will happen. It will only, in contrast, bring the life of a
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 88

sick person to an end because of an underlying fatal disease. (Callahan, 1992,

pp. 52-55)

The above case vividly shows that as far as the death of a patient is concerned

it is in active euthanasia, that a doctor does something which kills the patient and in

passive euthanasia the case is just not the same, therefore the premise 2 in the

argument is valid. The premise 3 is per se valid that doing something is literally

killing and killing is worse from not killing and it is even worse than letting die

because of the reason shown in this research, mostly where it is shown that Rachelss

argument that active euthanasia is more humane than passive euthanasia is criticized.

The second reason is that the misrepresentation of the case is evidently shown

in this matter. The AMAs statement does not state about doing and not doing. It

explains that not doing in case if the doctor foresees the death. But Rachels's rebuttal

relates to the case when the patient is suffering the curable diseases (Rachels, 1975/

1994a, p.118). Therefore, Rachels is committing straw man fallacy.

3.4. Criticism of Rachelss Arguments for Active Euthanasia

Rachelss arguments for active euthanasia are of types. The first type is based

directly on his biological and biographical distinction as elaborated in the conceptual

framework. The second type of arguments by which he supports active euthanasia are

those which show that the distinction between active euthanasia and passive

euthanasia is absurd morally. And wherever passive euthanasia is applicable, active

should be permissible as well. This has been shown in the second part of this chapter.

The first two types of arguments can be classified as indirect arguments. The third
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 89

type of arguments is Rachels's direct arguments as discussed in this part of the

chapter. The ethical arguments for and against euthanasia have remained largely

unchanged for centuries. These arguments can be organized under three themes:

autonomy, killing vs. allowing dying, and beneficence (Gula, 1999a, pp. 501-505).

Rachelss arguments are not different from these arguments; however his way of

presenting them is different.

Rachels believes that active euthanasia is morally justified in some instances

and that at least two strong arguments support this position. The first is the argument

from mercy; the second is the argument from the best interests and golden rule

(Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p.146). He adds one more argument for the legalization of

active euthanasia based on the right to liberty (Rachels, 1983). Briefly, this argument

states that dying people should be free to choose euthanasia as a matter of personal

liberty.

The very crucial part of Rachelss argument for active euthanasia is that they

are interconnected in a way that no single argument stands on its own to support his

position. His first argument from mercy shows the problem of pure utilitarianism, to

remove such a difficulty, he moves to best interest argument, where he feels helpless

to support his best interest which he tries to support by the golden rule argument and

the golden rule argument ultimately depends on autonomy. Autonomy becomes

problematic and more problematic by his legalization proposal for active euthanasia.

Therefore, there are main three arguments as criticized in the following part of the

chapter.
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 90

3.4.1. Criticism of the Argument from Mercy

Rachelss position is that it is cruel and inhumane to refuse the plea of a

terminally ill person that his or her life may be ended to avoid unnecessary suffering

and pain. Allowing such a person to terminate his or her life is an act of

mercy. Rachels supports this argument by documenting various cases in which he

describes the suffering of terminally ill patients and suggests that their suffering could

be stopped by active euthanasia.

The above argument is similar to the first argument against CDE which shows

that active euthanasia is more humane than passive euthanasia. The response to that

argument is given in the respective place. The response, however, is not different

from the response given to the former argument under 3.3.1. Criticism of That Often

Active Euthanasia Seems More Humane Than Passive.

3.4.2. Criticism of the Best Interests and Golden Rule Argument

Rachelss argument from mercy is a utilitarian argument. Rachels is himself

uncomfortable with the pure utilitarian argument, therefore he suggests the best

interest and golden rule argument. He claims that the following argument is sound and

proves that active euthanasia can be justified:

If an action promotes the best interests of everyone concerned, and violates

no one's rights, then that action is morally acceptable.

In at least some cases, active euthanasia promotes the best interests of

everyone concerned and violates no one's rights.


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 91

Therefore, in at least some cases active euthanasia is morally acceptable.

(Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p.149-150)

Rachels supports the above argument with golden rule argument. Rachels

relates the Golden Rule to active euthanasia by saying that if there are two choices to

die: (1) to die quietly, and without pain, from a fatal injection; and (2) to die of an

affliction so painful that for several days before death you would be reduced to

howling like a dog, with your family standing by helplessly, trying to comfort you,

but going through its own psychological hell. Rachels states that it is hard to believe

that any sane person, when confronted by these possibilities, would choose to have a

rule applied that would force upon him or her the second option. And if we would not

want such a rule, which excludes euthanasia, applied to us, then we should not apply

such a rule to others (Rachels, 1981/ 1994b, p.151-152).

There are three reasonable ways to argue against the Best Interests and Golden

Rule Argument and therefore rendering them invalid. They are: (1) the argument is

based on subjective moral judgment, failing the universalization test; (2) it may not be

in my own best interests or in the best interests of others for me to die; and (3) the

argument is based on indefensible autonomy.

Firstly, the best interest and golden rule arguments are based on subjective

moral judgment, therefore the arguments fail the morally universalization test and

become subject of partiality. The universalization test is crucial because Rachels

himself accepts categorical imperative and therefore he is supposed to be having no


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 92

objection if his moral position is subjected to such a test. If a person takes anything in

his own interest, it does not guarantee that such an act would be desirable to other

people. Similarly, not everything people would wish to have done to them is morally

appropriate. Put differently, people can dehumanize themselves and actually do so

in active euthanasia by intentionally killing themselves or by others intentionally

killing them. The golden rule argument fails due to its partiality and it fails the test of

generality. First of all if active euthanasia is accepted by it acceptance from some

patients and that does not make it generally acceptable. The approval is very

subjective in its nature. M. Cathleen Kaveny has suggestion also supports the above

position as follows:

The most pressing challenge facing opponents of assisted suicide or

voluntary euthanasia can be found in the faces of those who request such

practices in order to put an end to their suffering. They are pointing to their

own pain as a justification for carving out an exception to the general legal

and moral rule against intentionally killing the innocent. (Kaveny, 1997)

The closely connected to the above position is that the justification which some

terminally ill patients give for euthanasia need to be scrutinized. The researches

suggest that such approval of euthanasia is based mostly on the opinions of patients

whose decision power is clouded either by medication or depression. Hendin, Foley,

& White (1998b) have referred to theses researches which scientifically describe the

psychological conditions of terminally ill patients. The diagnosis of depression is

particularly important since like other suicidal individuals, patients who desire an
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 93

early death during a serious or terminal illness are usually suffering from a treatable

depressive condition (Harvey et al. & Ezekiel et al.). Although pain and other factors,

such as a lack of family support, may contribute to a patient's wish for death,

depression is the most important factor. In fact, researchers have found depression to

be the only factor that significantly predicts the wish for death (ibid.). Two-thirds of

patients requesting assisted suicide are depressed (ibid.) about the same percentage as

those who attempt or commit suicide unaided (Robins et al. & Barraclough et al.).

Hopelessness, the aspect of depression that helps distinguish depressed patients who

are suicidal from those who are not, has been shown to play a similar role in

predicting suicidal ideation in patients who are terminally ill (Harvey et al. ) ( pp.

243-70) . In face of all these evidences, Rachelss case again fails the test of

universalization which includes that the decision should be autonomous, but the

researches show that the euthanasia willing patients are not rationally autonomous,

they are either depressed or they are driven by other factors than reason.

Furthermore, it is important to elaborate on Kants categorical imperative,

which negates the conclusions of Rachels. For Kant, our rational wills are the source

of our moral duty, and it is therefore a kind of practical contradiction to suppose that

the same will can permissibly destroy itself. Given the distinctive worth of an

autonomous rational will, suicide is an attack on the very source of moral authority.

Consequently, disposing of oneself as a mere means to some discretionary end is

debasing humanity in one's person (as cited in Cholbi, 2004). Kant argued that taking

ones own life was inconsistent with the notion of autonomy, properly understood.

Autonomy, in Kants view, does not mean the freedom to do whatever one wants, but
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 94

instead depends on the knowing subjugation of ones desires and inclinations to ones

rational understanding of universally valid moral rules. (as cited in the New York

State Task Force on Life and the Law , 1994, chap.5)

Secondly, it may not be in my own best interests or in the best interests of

others for me to die. If I am willing to allow others to perform active euthanasia on

me and, by the Golden Rule argument, I'm willing to do so to them, I am mistaken in

my perspective and leaving out morally relevant information. Rachels's point that

once we are old what should be done to us could be objected by the similar questions.

"As I lie dying, will I be offered humane care, will I be done in too soon by some

expediency, or will I be subjected to terminal torture?(Vaux, 1989, p.29). Do

terminally ill patients really ask for euthanasia the research on the topic negates the

affirmation.

A new study published in the November 15 Journal of the American

Medical Association has found that most terminally ill patients would not

choose physician-assisted suicide or euthanasia to end their lives.

Interviews with 988 terminally ill adults and their primary caregivers

revealed that around one in ten people seriously considered using

physician-assisted suicide or euthanasia and that less than 6 percent had

seriously discussed the possibility or taken steps to commit suicide. The

researchers, led by Ezekiel J. Emanuel of the Department of Bioethics at the

National Institutes of Health, also found that those who considered either

option are affected by depression, feel unappreciated, and have significant


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 95

need for help with the basics of living. The study's authors warn that

doctors who receive requests for physician-assisted suicide or euthanasia

should not consider patients to be definite about their decisions. (Emanuel ,

2000, p. 1267 )

After presenting the above studies, it is contextually suitable to look into a

cited case of active euthanasia where a patient asks for lethal injection. Kuhse ( 1994)

reports the following case:

Mary F. was dying from a progressively debilitating disease. She

had reached the stage where she was almost totally paralyzed and,

periodically, needed a respirator to keep her alive. She was

suffering considerable distress. Knowing that there was no hope

and that things would get worse, Mary F. wanted to die. She asked

her doctor to give her a lethal injection to end her life. After

consultation with her family and members of the healthcare team,

Dr H. administered the asked-for-lethal injection, and Mary F.

died.( p. 295)

The case of Mary F. who was totally paralyzed and periodically needed a

respirator to keep her alive shows that she was kept alive by artificial means and

these artificial means of prolonging death could be desperate to the level that a patient

can ask for active euthanasia. The problem is if such a person was not kept alive in

the first place by artificial means such need and desperation would have not occurred.
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 96

The main problem with Rachels is that he does not write anywhere about the misuse

of medical technology.

Thirdly, both best interest and golden rule arguments are based on autonomy. The

related and separate argument from autonomy is repudiated in the next part of the

chapter. The repudiation of the autonomy argument invalidates both best interest and

golden rule argument.

3.4.3. Criticism of Rachelss Argument from Autonomy

Rachelss conception of biographical life entails that a human being is an

autonomous being; therefore, if a person autonomously chooses to end his or her life

then it is morally permissible. And that dying people should be free to choose

euthanasia as a matter of personal liberty. Rachels also supports his position by the

analogy to the law of suicide. The argument begins with the proposition that since it

is not unlawful for a person to commit or attempt to commit suicide, the law,

implicitly at least, recognizes the right of an individual to take his or her life. From

this premise it is argued that if an individual does have the right to take his or her life,

he or she should be able to seek the assistance of others in achieving this end (Rachels,

1983, p. 19). Likewise, Rachelss main arguments in favor of active euthanasia are

basically and essentially based on the consent of the terminally ill patient, that the

justification of such practice is based on the free will and autonomy of the patient and

furthermore on the joint consent of the other parties involved. Therefore, the

argument from autonomy in favor of voluntary active euthanasia stands as the

foundation of Rachelss thesis which according to him is based on two strong


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 97

arguments, the golden rule and the best interest arguments. The autonomy argument,

by and large, involves discussions on liberty, rights, self determination and

conception of autonomy itself. Rachels in his works refers to all these concepts to

gain more warranty for his argument.

The researchers position is that argument from autonomy fails to claim the

sufficient support to substantiate a pro-position for the approval of active euthanasia.

The reasons which support such a position are: (1) invalidity of civil rights claim; (2)

weak analogy between suicide and euthanasia; (3) unwarranted influence of patients

autonomy on doctors autonomy; and (4) unattainable autonomy of the terminally ill

patients.

3.4.3.1.Self-determination and Euthanasia

Among many grounds to claim that a person enjoys a right to euthanasia is

from self- ownership and closely connected to this is similar claim from self-

determination.

The self-ownership claim states that a person enjoys a right to euthanasia

because a person owns his body and hence such a person is morally permitted to

dispose his body as he wishes. The claim on Rachelss view is sound as long as such

giving away does not infringe anyone's rights. The claim from its nature is one of

those related to right of property and ownership. And the implication, from this view,

is that our relationship to our bodies is like that of our relationship to other items over

which we enjoy property rights. Therefore, we can dispose our bodies as we dispose

other owned things and objects. As a result, since property rights are exclusive
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 98

therefore others may not interfere with our efforts to end our lives. The concept of

self-ownership whether related to euthanasia or suicide is one of the famous

arguments. However, the very important factor is that the analogy between property-

ownership and self-ownership is that we cannot own ourselves the way we own

things which belong to us. There are two very important points which should be

considered; one is that we own things because they are metaphysically distinct from

us, whereas our bodies are not so. Even under all dualistic views of human nature,

our selves are not sufficiently distinct from our bodies to implicate any ownership.

Rachelss distinction of biological and biographical life is also one of such views; his

biographical life is necessarily connected to and dependent on biological life. Indeed,

the fact that certain ways of treating ordinary property are not available to us as ways

of treating our bodies, we cannot give away or sell our bodies in any literal sense,

suggests that self-ownership may be only a metaphor meant to capture a deeper moral

relationship (Kluge, as cited in Chobli, 2004, Libertarian Views and the Right to

Suicide, para.4). The other point is that even if we accept the self-ownership claim,

the claim from its implication will lead to extreme moral subjectivism. Acting out of

subjective moral discretion , even if it does not harm any one, may be somehow

acceptable in some case, however such case will not be sufficiently enough to make a

moral claim and subsequently will lack in becoming a legal position.

The right of self-ownership is closely connected to the right of self-

determination. It is a right to shape the circumstances of our lives so long as we do

not harm or imperil others. However, relating right of self-determination to

determining the circumstances of death is a different case. Because, it does not seem
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 99

to follow from having a right to life that a person has a right to death. The rights are

of two kinds: inalienable and alienable. Inalienable rights are those that by their

nature cannot be taken away, violated, or transferred from one person to another.

They are considered more fundamental than alienable rights, such as rights in a

specific piece of property. The right to life is inalienable, since in order for me to kill

myself, I must first renounce my inalienable right to life, which I cannot do (Feinberg

as cited in Chobli, 2004). John Locke has the similar views he states that in the

State of Nature no one has the right to take their own life, or assist in the death of

another individual (Locke, 2001, pp. 72-73).

Rachelss position on self-determination is however a confused one if a

holistic view of his thought is taken. His claim for autonomy and self determination

leads from two positions: biographical life and civil liberty.

From the point of biographical life it does not entail that a person who has lost

his biographical status could claim any inalienable and alienable right. As the

researcher has mentioned earlier while criticizing the biological and biographical

distinction that the distinction is slippery and leads to involuntary and non-voluntary

euthanasia. However, from the same perspective Morelands (1990) following

conclusion briefly shows the conceptual complications in Rachels:

According to Rachels, the rule not to kill is no longer morally relevant to

people without biographical lives. This is because the point of the rule is to

protect people with biographical lives. It would seem, then, that a person who

no longer has such a life -- who has no point of view -- is no longer included in
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 100

our duty not to kill. But if the person has lost the right not to be killed, it would

seem that other rights would be lost as well, since the right to life is basic to

other rights. In this case, it would be morally permissible to experiment on

such a person or kill him or her brutally. Why? Because we are no longer

dealing with an object that has the relevant rights. ( p. 74)

From the above analysis, it seems that Rachelss biographical life and autonomy

are in conceptual tension to lead to any clear position because of conceptual and

theoretical complications. Nevertheless, Rachelss claim from civil liberty is a clear

stand on the issue. However, it is practically and theoretically impossible to include

euthanasia in civil liberties; on the contrary, euthanasia by its nature can only claim

to be included in rights; and claiming euthanasia on the basis of rights is indefensible.

3.4.3.2. Analogy of Euthanasia with Suicide

Rachels attempts to defend his claim for active euthanasia by making the

suicide and euthanasia equal. He therefore makes an analogy between suicide and

euthanasia. When in fact, Rachelss analogy is weak and problematic. A crucial

question which needs to be addressed is what significance, if any, should be attached

to the fact that active voluntary euthanasia involves the direct assistance of a second

party. It could be argued that an important distinction exists between suicide on the

one hand, which is an autonomous and self-regarding act, and assisted suicide or

active voluntary euthanasia on the other, which requires the involvement and

assistance of a second party (Callahan,1989, pp. 4- 5) . This second party

involvement constitutes a crucial difference because the conduct changes from being
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 101

a purely private act to a form of public action with ramifications extending beyond

the parties involved. Moreover, it could be argued as well that if the argument for

active voluntary euthanasia is based on dignity of human freedom and self-

determination, then it is inconsistent to ask someone else to assist (Linacre Centre

Working Party, 1982, pp. 28-9).

3.4.3.3. Right, Liberty and Euthanasia

To return to the principle of self-determination, if one accepts the principle as

the basis for active voluntary euthanasia, it remains to be determined what legal status

should be given to such a right; should that be a basic human right or a legal right.

The recognition of the right to die as a human right would create duties on the part of

the state; it would not confer on individuals any legally enforceable right to active

voluntary euthanasia or impose any obligation on doctors to participate in its

administration. In light of this, it seems practically impossible for euthanasia to

happen, because euthanasia involves physicians who under such right cannot be

forced to involve with euthanasia practice.

The situation is more problematic where the right to die is expressed in terms

of a legally enforceable right. Apart from problems of definition, there are potential

difficulties in adopting a strict rights-based model as the basis for legalization of

active voluntary euthanasia. Although the notion of 'rights' is expansive and, in its

wider sense, can be used to encompass a variety of legal concepts, (Hohfeld , 1919,

pp. 6-7, 36-8) strictly speaking, rights, as distinct from liberties or privileges are

correlative with duties. Thus, the creation of any right to active euthanasia tends to
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 102

imply a corresponding duty on the part of someone to become actively involved in

bringing about death. Whereas, according to accepted principles of autonomy and

liberty, individuals should be free to pursue their own life choices, provided that this

does not violate the rights of any other parties. In promoting the self-determination

and autonomy of the patient, there appears the responsibility not to interfere with the

autonomy of others. In particular, doctors should not be required to abdicate their

autonomy in favor of that of the patient. The position of other parties, and their right

to remain free of involvement in the practice of active euthanasia poses a general

problem in any attempt of approving right to euthanasia as a claim right. Certainly in

the US constitutional context, the courts have already indicated that the recognition of

a constitutional right to physician assisted suicide does not entail any duty on the part

of any doctor (Compassion in Dying v. State of Washington, 1996).

Another possibility is for the right to active voluntary euthanasia to be framed

simply in terms of a right of one person to authorize another to kill him or her

intentionally and directly but without creating a right to demand such assistance.

There is broad agreement amongst euthanasia advocates that it would be

inappropriate to impose a duty on any person to take the life of another. Although

such a duty would uphold the autonomy of the patient who requests assistance, it is

recognized that it would be an unjustifiable interference with the autonomy of others.

It is primarily to avoid the implication of any such duty and the resulting infringement

of the autonomy of other parties that a strictly rights-based model has been widely

rejected as an appropriate basis for the legalization of active voluntary euthanasia

(Trowell, 1973, pp. 116-21). Therefore, argument from autonomy involves rights and
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 103

duties , and a terminally ill patients autonomy cannot be realized unless autonomy of

other parties are endangered, and doing so is not possible by any rights based model

for euthanasia.

3.4.3.4. Autonomy of Patients

The further objection to the argument based on autonomy is about autonomy

itself and that is the consent of the patient on termination of life actively. The

concerns involved are various such as how can it be sure that the person in condition

which requires active euthanasia could have a free will; there could be concern that

the use of a pain killer in a dying individual could so cloud his conscious response

that he might not in his dying moments be in a position to make decisions ( Koop ,

1989a, p.73). The consent therefore received could not be accepted as reasonable and

sound to substantiate such a decision.

To support the above concern on practical grounds, the researches show that

most of the patients who wish for death are depressed persons. The patients who

desire an early death during a serious or terminal illness are usually suffering from a

treatable depressive condition. Although pain and other factors, such as a lack of

family support, may contribute to a patient's wish for death, depression is the most

important factor. In fact, researchers have found depression to be the only factor that

significantly predicts the wish for death. Researches show that two-thirds of patients

requesting assisted suicide are depressed about the same percentage as those who

attempt or commit suicide unaided. Hopelessness, the aspect of depression that helps

distinguish depressed patients who are suicidal from those who are not, has been
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 104

shown to play a similar role in predicting suicidal ideation in patients who are

terminally ill ( Hendin, Foley, & White, 1998, p. 243-70 ) . Paul R. McHugh argues,

but when it comes to terminally ill patients, "outside forces" are likely to "overwhelm

the self, rendering it vulnerable to unreflective impulses" (McHugh, 1999, p. 5-6).

Due to these factors, realization of patients true autonomy becomes unattainable.

Aristotle rightly points out the difficulty of making a rational decision while in the

grip of pain and suffering. He describes the case of physicians that though they are

experts on matters of life and death; they even ask other physicians to treat them

when they fall sick. Aristotle states:

Doctors themselves call in others doctors to treat them when they are sick,

and trainers call in other trainers when they are exercising, their

assumption being that they are unable to judge truly because they are

judging about their own cases, and while in pain. (Aristotle, 2000, iii

16.1287a41 b3)

Besides above grounds, Rachelss argument for active euthanasia is

unnecessary. There is practically no such a need to resort to active euthanasia if

medical technology is not allowed to mishandle the patients and prolong their dying

process. On the other hand if a person is being kept alive by artificial and

extraordinary means, in such a case the treatment can be withdrawn. And in cases of

patients whose life is painful, their problem can be successfully resolved by the pain

medication and wider use of principle of double effect. Therefore, as such, active

euthanasia is indefensible because of serious inadequacy of autonomy argument.


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 105

3.5.Criticism of Rachelss Proposal of Legalizing Active Euthanasia

Rachels while using the fundamental procedure in the criminal trials in

American courts proposes a legal scenario in which there is legally a successful

possibility of making active voluntary euthanasia a reality without any adverse

repercussions to the physician who performs such an act. He elaborates that under his

proposal, someone charged with murder could also plead mercy killing; and then if it

could be proven that the victim while competent requested death, and that the victim

was suffering from a painful terminal illness, the person pleading mercy killing would

also be acquitted (Rachels, 2003). Rachels while explaining the above procedure

mentions that under the above proposal no one would be "authorized" to decide when

a patient should be killed. He adds that there are no committees to be established

within which people may cast private votes for which they are not really accountable;

people who choose to mercy kill bear full legal responsibility, as individuals, for their

actions (Rachels, 2003). Rachels further explains that by following the proposal we

would rely on the good sense of judges and juries to separate the cases of justifiable

euthanasia from the cases of unjustifiable murder, just as we already rely on them to

separate the cases of self-defense and insanity and coercion (Rachels, 2003).

Rachelss proposal of legalizing active euthanasia is problematic and

unpersuasive. After analyzing his proposal from the legal and practical points, his

proposal turns out to be impractical. The main problems in the proposal are

enumerated as follows:
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 106

(1). The proposal fails to provide clear guidelines. The proposal has very

ambiguous guidelines for both doctors and courts. For example, Rachels

recommends doctors to recourse to ignorance of fact and recommends judges that

doctors who have committed mercy killing could be acquitted on basis as judges

consider in criminal trials such as grounds of insanity. This ambiguity renders the

proposal unclear , therefore not worthy of adaptation.

(2). The proposal suggests that the mercy killing act would be a murder and could

deserve a trial where a doctor can defend his action. This is practically very

difficult, but impossible. The impossibility specially arises when the murdered

person is killed and there is no one left to follow his killing or those who follow

have vested interests.

(3). Rachels is very naive about homicide and criminal law procedures. He

suggests that when there will be no one to follow the murder case as guardians

will give consent positively, the doctor will not be bothered by any court trial.

Rachels ignores the role of the state and police. Rachels confuses criminal trial

with civil trial.

(4). The other problem is if such proposal accepted who would be ready to face

the trial and jury after every act of mercy killing. Would not such a doctor be

scared who could expect anything from jury in absence of any guidelines and

legalized procedures. There will not be many doctors available on earth who

would be ready to go for murder trial after every euthanasia, and such a way will

easily open way for corruption of the physicians who are historically thought to
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 107

be humane.

(5). The biggest problem which the proposal fails to deal with is that on one hand

Rachels dismisses any committees which could decide the euthanasia, whereas on

the other hand he leaves the matter unto doctors that they could defend

themselves on commonsense or ignorance of fact, which gives an easy hand to a

doctor to kill people without any requirements.

3.6. Modern Advanced Medical Technology and Euthanasia

This research used broad construal definition of euthanasia for the sake of

convention and criticism, however the researcher agrees only on the narrow construal

definition of euthanasia which includes only active euthanasia as euthanasia. And

active euthanasia should be prohibited. To support such a position, the researcher

starts with the propositions: (1) that among moral hazards of advanced medical

technology is that it allows prolonging of death; (2) the cases of passive euthanasia

are the cases of the natural state of extinction and thought to be passive euthanasia

due to inappropriate use of advanced medical technology; and (3) the need of active

euthanasia as defended by Rachels due to some case studies of patients is also un-

defendable due to two reasons: (I) that the cases are actually mishandled by doctors

due to misuse of medical technology by prolonging life of dying patients and (II) if

there are terminally ill patients in anticipation of death and living in painful state ,

such patients could be given pain killers to get their pain under control even though

such medication shortens their life due to the side affects of such medication.
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 108

Therefore, Rachelss interpretation of active euthanasia as killing and passive

euthanasia as letting die is a false dichotomy.

In the following part of the chapter, the researcher will elaborate on the above

propositions respectively.

3.6.1. Moral Hazards of Modern Advanced Medical Technology

The most crucial and serious part related to euthanasia is the role of modern

advanced medical technology; and Rachels has almost left it untouched. He focuses

on the problem of those suffering in some ailment and focuses on the solution of such

cases. Whereas, the beginning and causes of problems remain untouched in Rachelss

thought; he apparently has no suggestions on that part to medical and legal authorities.

However, he has suggestions to both doctors and courts on the ways and methods of

how terminally ill patients could be killed.

As a matter of fact, modernity and advance of science and technology, besides

other goals, remain centered to one main issue and that is discovering natural causes,

and devising technological tools and machines, which could allow imitation of natural

processes and with higher ambition of bringing nature ultimately under control. On

one hand the ambition has brought comfort and progress to humanity in various ways,

and on the other hand the same science and technology has brought hazards and

misfortune to humanity in various domains on variety of levels and degrees. The

medical profession could be treated as the most beneficiary of the modern science,

however the misplaced use of medical technology has also created many ethical

problems and among such problems is the issue of euthanasia. Joseph Fletcher has
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 109

put the case succinctly: Most of our major moral problems are posed by scientific

discoveries and by the subsequent technical know-how we gain, in the control of life

and health and death. Ethical questions jump out at us from every laboratory and

clinic (Fletcher, 1987/ 1989, p. 88).

The involvement of medical technology with death and issue of euthanasia

particularly stems from two main facts. The first reason is that, whereas in the past

most people died in their homes, the vast majority now dies in institutions governed

by the medical profession. In the United States and likewise in other developed

countries, during the twentieth century, death moved out of the home and into

medical institutions. In 1983 President's Commission for the Study of Ethical

Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioural Research, a report about US

stated that: As medicine has been able to do more for dying patients, their care has

increasingly been delivered in institutional settings. By 1949 institutions were the

sites of 50 per cent of all deaths; by 1958 the figure was 61 per cent; and by 1977

over 70 per cent. Perhaps 80 per cent of the deaths in the United States now occur in

hospitals and long-term care institutions, such as nursing homes ( 1983, p 17). The

same trend is being reported in other countries, briefly, the developed countries top

the list. (Bryant, 2003, p.205). Sharon R. Kaufman comments that Today, more

Americans die in hospitals than anywhere else, and the most frequent response to

critical illness there is to try to stave off death with the most sophisticated

technological means available. Approximately one-quarter of all hospitalized patients

are treated in intensive care or cardiac care units before they die(Kaufman, 2005,

pp.1-8). Likewise, the other countries follow the same road; therefore death is now
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 110

very much a medical business. The other reason is that the fact that most people now

die in hospitals has another side to it that modern hospitals usually provide high

technology medicine with sophisticated resuscitation equipment and life sustaining

machinery. The intensive care and employment of high technology complicates the

process of dying and in fact prolong the process of dying in an unnatural way.

Accordingly, Max J. Charlesworth (1989) has depicted the scene as follows:

In a sense the high technology hospital creates its own special ethical

problems simply because it has the technology to artificially sustain and

prolong the lives of gravely disabled newborns and others. The Karen Ann

Quinlan case was a product of such a hospital situation in that since the

life-sustaining technology was at hand it had to be used. Had Karen Ann

been sent to a remote country hospital, nature would have quickly taken its

course and she would have died. What is 'ordinary' run-of-the-mill

treatment in a large high technology hospital is of ten quite 'extraordinary'

beyond-the call-of-duty treatment in a smaller country hospital. In

hospitals with sophisticated medical technology physicians would be

culpably negligent if the complex medical technology were not used. As a

result the tendency in such hospitals is to sustain people's lives just

because the technology is available. (pp. 64-65)

As a result, the use of high technology has given the sense to humans that they

are no more helpless onlookers in the presence of death; they are now increasingly

able to intervene in the process, using technological resources to direct or delay the
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 111

inevitable (Veatch, 1989, p. 2) . Furthermore, the human medical interventions have

interrupted the natural death process to such an extent that very few illnesses can be

said to have a natural course (Omar, 1993, p. 613). These interventions have lead to

prolongation of death and suffering. With this in mind, Omar Mendez states:

Sometimes, because of legal issues, we are driven to the point of doing the inhumane

by artificially maintaining a body that has no cognitive functions despite the

family's requests and even the previously expressed wishes of the patient (Omar,

1993, p. 614).

The abovementioned well documented scenario which takes place in medical

setting encourages that a dying person should be first of all hospitalized, secondly

such a person should be kept under high intensive care laid on life sustaining

machines, and thirdly such a person should not be given chance to natural way of

passing away. These reasons stand at the root of the problem of euthanasia; and they

are totally ignored by Rachels. Rachels has nothing to say about it. This medical

situation which is actually a set of unnatural settings has made the case of terminally

ill persons so overwhelming on every front that has made Rachels and his proponents

surrender before its inevitable demand of killing of mishandled and medically over-

treated patients. The unfortunate picture of these patients which emerges because of

the given reasons, is on an emotional level being the main drive behind the euthanasia

movement and rationalization of mercy killing; the picture, being artificial and mess,

provides arguments which are misguiding and compelling to mobilize support for

active euthanasia. In other words, this intellectual helplessness in face of the

circumstances is a vivid description in what Van Den Haag acknowledges:


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 112

More and more people reach advanced age. But for many, disability

makes life a burden. Yet even when life is no longer desired, or

consciously experienced, medicine can now prolong it. Although still

fallible, diagnoses have become far more reliable than in the past;

prognosis is fairly certain. Miracles--medical or religious--are rare. It is

reasonable, then, to allow physicians to actively help end life when the

patient so desires.... We should no longer ask whether assisted suicide, or

mercy killing, should be allowed, but rather under what conditions.

(Carr,1995, pp. 50-51)

Alongside, the abovementioned surrender of intellectuals to the circumstances,

the desperation of terminally ill patients who are kept alive against their wishes, had

they were not kept artificially alive, they would have died, is not less at all. The

desperation could be understood by the deaths of Rev. Henry Van Dusen and his wife,

Elizabeth. Several years ago, the Rev. Henry Van Dusen and his wife, Elizabeth, both

of them in pain and with no prospect of recovery, joined in a suicide pact. The deaths

were front-page news in The New York Times and most other newspapers because

Van Dusen was president of Union Theological Seminary and one of the most

respected theologians in the world. In a suicide note, Elizabeth Van Dusen wrote:

There are too many helpless old people who, without modern medicine, would have

died, and we feel God would have allowed them to die when their time had come"

(Carr, 1995, pp. 50-51).


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 113

As indicated above, the terminally ill patients whose death is unnecessarily

prolonged are unfortunate cases of mishandlement of advanced medical technology.

The terminally ill patients whose recovery is not possible would have rather died

naturally, had they not artificially kept alive. Furthermore, it is evident that a need for

active euthanasia stems from the misuse of medical technology itself. The question

arises about those terminally ill patients whose recovery is unattainable and there is

no cure for them; are such patients suitable subjects for euthanasia, whether active or

passive,; the researchers answer is of denial. Because, they are not subject to either

killing, active euthanasia, or letting die, passive euthanasia. Because, passive

euthanasia is not letting die therefore it is not euthanasia.

3.6.2. Passive Euthanasia is not Euthanasia / Letting Die

The passive euthanasia, on Rachels's formulation, is defined as terminating or

withholding or withdrawing the treatment and which eventually leads to the death of

a person. The definition can be confusing that if ordinary medical treatment which

can benefit a patient is withdrawn, withheld or terminated, to researchers

understanding that kind of action is also active euthanasia. Rachels has also

misunderstood passive euthanasia in these terms; according to Rachels, passive

euthanasia means letting die. The statement of AMA is somehow very careful

understanding of the case, it states explicitly killing of patient is prohibited and such

formulation can be easily classified as active euthanasia and on the other side it states

that extraordinary treatment can be terminated if such treatment is not helpful. The

case therefore if treated as passive euthanasia deserves a careful definition: that


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 114

passive euthanasia is withholding, withdrawing or terminating medical treatment

from those patients to whom such treatment is useless or extraordinary. On this

understanding the passive euthanasia is not euthanasia it is just that the death works

its way. As an illustration, Daniel Callahan (1992) gives the following interesting

comment:

[I]t confuses reality and moral judgment to see an omitted action as having the

same causal status as one that directly kills. A lethal injection will kill both a

healthy person and a sick person. A physician's omitted treatment will have no

effect on a healthy person. Turn off the machine on me, a healthy person, and

nothing will happen. It will only, in contrast, bring the life of a sick person to

an end because of an underlying fatal disease. (Pp.52-55)

Therefore, the researcher maintains that passive euthanasia as widely known as

letting die is misrepresentation of the actual scenario in which a patient takes course

to his final exit without prolonging the process of his dying by using life sustaining

high technology and unaffordable burdens of medical care and artificial means of

maintaining biological processes. Similarly, when a patients condition is such that it

is not reasonable to hope that any medical procedures or treatments will save his life,

a failure to implement the procedures or treatments is not euthanasia. If the person

dies, this will be as a result of his injuries or disease and not because of his failure to

receive treatment (Gay-Williams, 1979/1989, pp.97-98).

The real and actual case of euthanasia is only active euthanasia. Active

euthanasia is killing a terminally ill patient to put end to his suffering. The point is
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 115

that is there really a need for such action on the part of a doctor, the simple

understanding of the case is negative. The negation of such a need is backed by

reasons: (1) a terminally ill person whose dying process is prolonged by life

sustaining medical technology and extraordinary means is most of the time thought to

be subject of active euthanasia, to avoid involvement of euthanasia such a person

should not be kept alive by life sustaining and extraordinary means against his wish ,

if the suggestion is followed there will not arise any need of actively killing such a

person and death will happen naturally due to illness, therefore active euthanasia will

be avoided. The cases which are most of the time illustrated to be subject of active

euthanasia are the cases actually mishandled by medical technology (2) the other

reason is that even if extraordinary medical treatment is terminated and life sustaining

equipments are disconnected , there is possibility of pain and suffering therefore

active euthanasia can put end to such a pain, however the case is not so that only

option of active euthanasia can put end to the problem, such persons suffering and

pain can be controlled by medicine and palliative care , the medication besides

soothing the pain may shorten life as a side effect, but such side effects are not

intended they are by-products , therefore the option of active euthanasia can be

avoided.

In short, if passive euthanasia means letting die , then there is no difference

between killing and letting die: because if a curable patient is not treated medically

such negligence is not different from killing. On the contrary, if passive euthanasia

means discontinuing useless and extraordinary medical care from an incurable patient

such termination of medical care is neither killing nor letting die. Therefore, on this
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 116

formulation passive euthanasia is not euthanasia. The question arises then who are the

subjects of active euthanasia; the researcher response is that none but those whose

death is prolonged, those who would have died naturally if not mishandled by

extraordinary, useless, and futile medical technology.

3.6.3. Active Euthanasia is Mishandling of those whose Death is Prolonged

The need for active euthanasia, if there is any need, which the researcher

thinks that there is not, is actually a consequence of mans mishandling the natural

laws within the medical sciences. The actual natural law of medicine is that the

living ought never to be treated as if they were dying, nor the dying as if they were

living( Vaux, 1988/ 1989, p.32). The law has been adversely affected by the misuse

of advanced medical technology. The crucial shortcoming in Rachelss thought is that

he tries to find the solution for mishandled patients to stop their suffering, but,

deliberately, ignores the causes of such suffering. He has no suggestions to doctors

not to modify nature and he has not made any criticism against that and on that base

he argues that death should be also made in an unnatural way. The problem as such

creates a dilemma for more nature loving people that how could they allow doctors to

modify nature and then plead for nature to run as unhindered. The proper way is that

to get it right in the beginning and it will be right in the end. And if we get it wrong in

the beginning then we have to commit another wrong in the end to make it look better,

we cannot get it right in the end when the whole matter is based on a wrong and

mistaken foundation. The mishandling of patients by employing advanced medical

technology is succinctly shown by Kenneth L. Vaux (1988/ 1989) as follows:


Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 117

In recent years the qualities that morally distinguished the living from the

dying have been blurred. With our life-prolonging techniques and

medications, we have transformed death; we have taken it out of the acute,

natural, and non interventional mode and made it more into a chronic,

contrived, and manipulated phenomenon. Deaths as inevitable as Debbie's

have been protracted by a range of interventions, including chemotherapy

(disrupting the cellular-pathogenic process), analgesia (altering the release

of natural body endorphins and narcotics), the administration of

intravenous fluids and nutrients, and hospitalization itself. Logically and

emotionally, we cannot intervene at one phase and then be inactive at

another, more painful phase. We cannot modify nature and then plead that

nature must be allowed to run its unhindered course. (p.32)

As indicated above, the need for active euthanasia is the one artificial. The

doctors at one phase start prolonging death and at the point when the prolongation

becomes costly on all fronts such as suffering and financial expenses then disposal of

the patient in an unnatural way becomes eminent.

The above problem which shows the role of advanced medical technology in

worsening the condition of dying people, can be well illustrated by the most famous

and well documented cases debated in the history of euthanasia: Karen Quinlan,

Nancy Cruzan, and Terri Schiavo. The 21-year-old Karen Ann Quinlan collapsed at a

party after swallowing alcohol and the tranquilizer Valium on 14 April 1975. Doctors

saved her life, but she suffered brain damage and lapsed into a "persistent vegetative
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 118

state." She remained in a coma for almost 10 years in a New Jersey nursing home

until her death in1985 (Koop, 1976/ 1989b, pp. 33-42). Like Karen Ann Quinlan,

Nancy Cruzan became a public figure after entering a persistent vegetative state. A

1983 auto accident left Cruzan permanently unconscious and without any higher

brain function, she was kept alive only by a feeding tube and steady medical care.

The Cruzans stopped feeding Nancy in December of 1990, and she died later the

same month (Crigger, 1990. p. 38). On 25 February 1990, 26-year-old Terri Schiavo

suffered severe brain damage when her heart stopped for five minutes. Schiavo spent

the following years in rehabilitation centers and nursing homes but never regained

higher brain function. In 1998 her husband, Michael Schiavo, filed a legal petition to

have Schiavo's feeding tube removed, saying that his wife had told him before her

medical crisis that she would not want to be artificially kept alive in such a situation.

After long court battle, in March of 2005 Schiavo's feeding tube was removed, and

after two weeks without food and water, Schiavo died of dehydration on 31 March

2005.( Schiavo Case, 2007, p. 43060). These cases vividly show that how the death

of these people was prolonged for years and how they were kept alive by artificial

means either in a coma or in a persistent vegetative state. The unfortunate situation of

these terminally ill patients is very clearly stated by John J Paris (1997):

We have come to believe that the "miracles" of modern medicine are able

not only to defeat disease but to conquer death. With the rise of

technological medicine, lives that once were beyond rescue can now be

saved. Sometimes, however, that success comes at too great a price: a life

of suffering, pain and despair. Patients like Karen Ann Quinlan or Nancy
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 119

Cruzan may now lie trapped by a halfway technology, one that can ward

off death but not restore health, in a situation worse than death itself--an

endless prolongation of their dying. (pp. 11-14)

There was not such a need to use medical technology to prolong the process of

death the mostly it happens almost at the will of the physician (Koop, 1976/ 1989a,

p.72) and such persons could have died easily in a natural way than becoming the

problematic. The biological and moral hazard which advanced medical technology

has brought seems unresolved problem to many and the same thinking is behind those

who favor active euthanasia. The reason which they give behind their stand point is

that since misuse of medical technology has created the problem, therefore it is

unavoidable to surrender to the consequences. The problem with this argument is that

instead of correcting the use of medical technology these people while feeling

helpless before the use of medical technology, favor the active euthanasia. Gerald A.

Larue (1989 ) has drafted the following statement on the same lines. He says:

We acknowledge that techniques developed by modern medicine have been

beneficial in improving the quality of life and increasing longevity, but they

have sometimes been accompanied by harmful and dehumanizing effects.

We are aware that many terminally ill persons have been kept alive against

their will by advanced medical technologies, and that terminally ill patients

have been denied assistance in dying. In attempting to terminate their

suffering by ending their lives themselves or with the help of loved ones not

trained in medicine, some patients have botched their suicides and brought
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 120

further suffering on themselves and those around them. We believe that the

time is now for society to rise above the archaic prohibitions of the past and

to recognize that terminally ill individuals have the right to choose the time,

place, and manner of their own death. (p. 160)

As mentioned above, the Gerald A. Larues statement, it is quite evident that

those patients who are treated as the subjects of active euthanasia are actually those

case who are medically mishandled. The problem which seems is that cases which

deserve to be treated as cases which should be left on their own and intervened

fruitlessly and instead of life, death is being prolonged and once the case becomes

problematic the active euthanasia is being sought. The researcher thinks that instead

of reasoning for active euthanasia, it would be far better to reason against the

inappropriate use of medical technology. If biomedical acts of life extension become

acts of death prolongation, we may force some patients to outlive their deaths, and we

may ultimately repudiate the primary life-saving and merciful ethic itself (Vaux,

1988/1989, p.32).

In light of all the above details, the researcher thinks that AMAs statement on

euthanasia is valid. The statement makes a distinction between intentionally killing

and withholding extraordinary medical treatment. Moreover, the AMAs position

implies that the patients should not be intentionally killed and extraordinary medical

treatment can be withdrawn or withheld by the permission of the patient or the

hopeless condition of the patient by the permission of his legal guardians.

Furthermore, the above findings also lead to the conclusion that Rachelss
Critique of Rachelss Thought on Euthanasia 121

categorization of active and passive euthanasia into killing and letting die is a

false dichotomy. Rachels gives two choices to terminally ill patients: either killing or

letting die, and prefers killing to letting die. Whereas the researcher thinks that both

of these choices killing and letting die are irrelevant. The researcher, in light of the

above details, thinks that there is only one choice: (I) to stop prolongation of death

by the excessive and misuse of advanced medical technology, (II) to allow

termination of extraordinary medical care from terminally dying persons and, (III) to

allow use of pain medication by following legitimate procedures.


CHAPTER FOUR

Conclusion

This research demonstrates that James Rachelss defense of active euthanasia is

conceptually, theoretically, practically, and normatively unjustifiable. Rachelss

position on euthanasia is widely known as libertarian approach in contrast to the

traditional doctrine of euthanasia (TDE) or conventional doctrine of euthanasia (CDE).

The American Medical Associations (AMAs) position is in favor of the traditional

doctrine. The traditional doctrine makes a distinction between active and passive

euthanasia and prohibits the first and allows the latter. Whereas, Rachelss approach

debunks the distinction and treats passive euthanasia unnecessary and painful; and

prefers the active euthanasia. Rachels attempts to support his position by three ways: (1)

by developing a set of concepts, (2) by dissolving the distinction between active and

passive euthanasia, and (3) by arguing for active euthanasia. Furthermore, he proposes

a proposal on the legalization of active euthanasia.

In the outset of this research a clear understanding of euthanasia is sought by

analyzing a bunch of various definitions of euthanasia. The study shows that there are

two different usages of the term, euthanasia: narrow construal of euthanasia, which

refers to mercy killing or active euthanasia; and broad construal of euthanasia, which

refers to both active and passive euthanasia. Rachels adopts the broad construal of

euthanasia, and includes suicide and assisted suicide within his definition. Rachelss

definition is unacceptable, conceptually unjustifiable, and most confusing, because it

violates all the demarcations between euthanasia, suicide, assisted suicide, and
Conclusion 123

physician assisted suicide. Contrary to Rachels, the researcher agrees only with the

narrow construal of euthanasia, i.e. active euthanasia. The researchers definition of

euthanasia is: intentionally causing a terminally ill persons death by performing an

action. The definition is based on the facts that: (1) the death is caused by an agent

(human) instead of the subject (the patient), (2) the causing of death is intentional, (3)

the death is caused either by the request of the subject or the state of being of the subject

to make it different from a pure homicide (4) the death is caused by commission or

action and (5) the subject is terminally ill. As a result, passive euthanasia is expunged

from the definition because euthanasia means the intentional, mercy killing; and in

passive euthanasia intentional killing is not part of the withholding or withdrawing the

unnecessary and extraordinary medical treatment. Therefore, the researchers

definition includes only active euthanasia mercy killing as euthanasia. The definition

excludes: suicide, assisted suicide, physician-assisted suicide and passive euthanasia.

The reasons behind not considering passive euthanasia as euthanasia is due to: (1) the

death is natural, and not artificial (2) the death is not caused by action of any agent. The

suicide, assisted suicide, and physician assisted suicide are excluded due to: (1) the

death is not caused by an agent other than the subject. The very integral factor of the

notion of euthanasia is being killed by some agent (person) instead of the subject.

The historical sketch of euthanasia as detailed in this research shows that

problem of euthanasia has a long history of philosophical discussion; however, most of

the discussion revolves around the issue of suicide. The late twentieth century shows a

divide between suicide and euthanasia. Both these subjects become separate along with

their subject matter and arguments; although there is an unavoidable overlap between
Conclusion 124

them. The peculiarity of euthanasia is because of its relatedness to medical profession

and legal issues. The issue of euthanasia in its essential relation is practically connected

with medicine; it has brought the medical profession in question. The defenders of

active euthanasia suggest to redefine the profession not only as life saving but also as

life taking. Similarly, the issue has brought in debate the rights, duties, and autonomy

of both terminally ill patients and physicians. Due to the crucial touch of euthanasia to

medical profession the American Medical Association (AMA) announced its position

on the issue of euthanasia. The AMAs statement prohibited the intentional termination

of the life of one human being by another, mercy killing and allowed the cessation of

the employment of extraordinary means to prolong the life of the body when there is

irrefutable evidence that biological death is imminent. Rachelss interpretation of the

statement is that it supports passive euthanasia and opposes active euthanasia. Rachels

understands by active euthanasia killing and by passive euthanasia letting die.

Contrary to Rachels, the researcher disagrees on such categorization. The researcher

thinks that the statement refers to narrow construal euthanasia. Because, the cessation

of the extraordinary means of medical treatment does not amount to letting die.

Therefore, Rachelss interpretation is both conceptually and practically unjustifiable.

The chapter two of this research deals with Rachelss thought on euthanasia in

a detailed form. The ideas are grouped in three categories: conceptual framework,

arguments for absolution of the distinction between active and passive euthanasia, and

arguments for active euthanasia including the proposal on legalization of active

euthanasia, respectively. Rachels is a moral, utilitarian philosopher; while elaborating

his thought on euthanasia, he refers directly and indirectly to his conceptual framework
Conclusion 125

which permeates all of his arguments. Rachelss conceptual framework deals with

three distinctions: (1) biological and biographical life, (2) killing and letting die, and (3)

ordinary and extraordinary medical treatment. Rachels attempts to show that there is

morally no difference between active and passive euthanasia and where passive

euthanasia is appropriate, active should be allowed too. He challenges CDE for several

reasons: (1) active euthanasia is in many cases more humane that passive euthanasia, (2)

the conventional doctrine leads to decisions concerning life and death on irrelevant

grounds, (3) the doctrine rests on a distinction between killing and letting die that itself

has no moral importance, and (4) the most common arguments in favor of the doctrine

are invalid. Furthermore, Rachels explicitly supports active euthanasia. Rachels states

three main arguments: (1) the argument from mercy; (2) the argument from the best

interest and the golden rule; and (3) the argument from autonomy. And finally, he

proposes a modest proposal for the legalization of active euthanasia.

The criticism of Rachelss thought on euthanasia is the subject of chapter three.

The research analyzes Rachelss thought in accordance and order of the preceding

chapter. The chapter in argumentative and critical ways shows how Rachelss claims

are unjustifiable on all fronts: conceptual, theoretical, practical, and normatical.

The researcher criticizes the conceptual framework which comprises of

distinctions, and demonstrates that it has various problems which are reasonably not

enough to support the soundness of Rachelss position and that of arguments which

mainly draw on such distinctions.


Conclusion 126

Rachelss first distinction, biological and biographical life, holds that biological

life is ethically unimportant, whereas biographical life is important and relevant.

Rachelss support for active euthanasia is largely based on the distinction. The research

shows that the distinction does not provide a valid foundation or criteria for the

permissibility of active euthanasia. The distinction is rather inadequate due to: (1)

reductive fallacy oversimplification; (2) slippery slope and (3) inconsistency with the

main arguments of Rachels. The distinction commits reductive fallacy, because it

reduces human person to some functions and therefore divides a human entity into a

human being or biological life and human person or biographical life. The research

shows that such distinction is possible conceptually and not physically. The distinction

is both conceptually and practically unjustifiable: conceptually because it implies that

besides terminally ill patients, many persons like mentally ill and retarded, drug and

alcohol addicts, patients with Parkinson's and Alzheimer's diseases, and the comatose

are not persons; and practically because the distinction entails the consequences which

hardly seem to escape being the easy target of slippery slope; it leads to permissibility

of not only voluntary active euthanasia, but non-voluntary and involuntary as well,

because if having just a biological life without biographical life is a valid criterion

for euthanasia then the consent of terminally ill becomes irrelevant. Therefore, the

distinction defines a human person in way which is not coherent with the main

arguments of Rachels such as best interest and golden rule argument and argument

from autonomy, which are based on patients consent and autonomy. Therefore, the

distinction becomes irrelevant to Rachelss main arguments for active euthanasia.

Nevertheless, the distinction if restricted to painful and suffering terminally ill patients
Conclusion 127

who are kept alive by artificial means makes some sense, however, in such a case

killing actively is not the only option, the extraordinary treatment can be terminated.

Therefore, such a distinction deserves to be shunned in face of its inadequacy.

Rachelss second distinction, killing and letting die, maintains that there is

morally no distinction between killing someone and letting someone die. Rachelss

killing means active euthanasia and letting die passive euthanasia; therefore active

and passive dichotomy is a distinction without difference. The distinction pervades his

arguments from mercy and bare difference. Rachels illustrates his point by a

hypothetical example of Smith and Johns; Smith kills his cousin and Johns watches his

cousin die without extending any affirmative assistance. The research shows that the

distinction is: (1) irrelevant, (2) extraneous to the medical profession, and

methodologically degressive. The irrelevance of the distinction to euthanasia is that it

is not the case that doctors let the patient. The AMAs statement actually holds that if

the medical treatment seems extraordinary and unbeneficial, in such a case the patient

has choice to refuse the treatment. The future of such a patient remains to be seen in the

future, and the possibility of patients recovery is a matter of probability. Therefore, the

distinction is theoretically unjustifiable. Furthermore, the distinction extraneous to the

medical profession because omissions of ordinary care are as punishable as affirmative

misdeeds in a patient physician relationship. The distinction may be somehow

defensible in outside care taking professions where affirmative assistance may not be

required; however a physician's omission of readily available treatment is the textbook

definition of professional malpractice. Furthermore, the acceptance of the distinction

within the medical profession grows mistrust and suspicion between the patient and the
Conclusion 128

doctor and leads to abuse, slippery slope and vulnerability of patients. Therefore, the

distinction is practically, and normatively unjustifiable. From the point of development

and progress in medical history the distinction is methodologically degressive. There is

possibility that those patients who are suffering from deadly diseases will be killed and

the efforts needed to help such cases will not be spent. Therefore, it removes the skeptic

nature of scientific methodology which is progressive; as a result, the distinction

becomes practically unjustifiable.

Rachelss third distinction, ordinary and extraordinary medical treatment,

dissolves the distinction; the distinction is endorsed in AMAs statement and has

proponents such as Thomas Sullivan. Rachels claims that the distinction is useless and

senseless. He argues that there is no demarcation between ordinary and extraordinary

and it is sometimes permissible to omit ordinary treatments. The research shows that

the distinction as held in AMAs statement is valid and useful. The research shows that

the distinction is evolutionary and progressive. Technologically, medicine has

advanced so quickly that older understanding of the distinction seems obsolete. What

might have been considered extraordinary care a few years ago is now so commonplace

as to be called ordinary. As a matter of fact, the distinction between ordinary and

extraordinary depends on the prudence, experience, and expertise of a physician; it is

like the legal criterion of 'the reasonable man' and the criterion works in a rough and

ready way at the practical level. Therefore, it is in essence a practical matter; therefore

Rachelss claim on the issue is practically and conceptually unjustifiable. Rachelss

additional claim is that instead of debating ordinary and extraordinary medical

treatment, physicians should decide whether the life in question to be prolonged. The
Conclusion 129

claim is normatively unjustifiable because the benefit of the care to the patients health

condition is what is a real matter a doctor should be concerned about; deciding the life

and death for the patient puts the physician in an unwarranted prerogative role which is

problematic due to legal complexities, rights, duties, and autonomy. Such a judgmental

role is also prone to abuse and corruption. The doctors role is not to assess the value or

worth of the patient but that of the treatment.

As noted earlier, Rachels argues against the traditional doctrine (TDE) or

conventional doctrine on euthanasia (CDE) which is also called standard view, which

according to Rachels makes a distinction between active , killing, and passive letting

die euthanasia and prohibits active and allows passive. This view, on Rachelss

understanding, is upheld by the American Medical Association. Rachelss arguments

are aimed against AMAs position exclusively. The research shows that Rachelss

active-passive categorization of AMAs statement is a mistaken interpretation. The

statement prohibits intentional killing of terminally ill patients and allows the cessation

of extraordinary medical treatment. Rachels gives four arguments against AMAs

position and which on his formulation render the distinction between active and

passive euthanasia morally absurd. Therefore, his conclusion is that where passive

euthanasia is allowed, active euthanasia should be permitted but preferred too. The

research demonstrates the invalidity of Rachelss arguments, therefore the research

leads to invalidity of the establishment of the validity of active euthanasia on the basis

of the permissibility of so called passive euthanasia. Furthermore, the research shows

that Rachelss claim of equating active and passive euthanasia morally is theoretically

unjustifiable.
Conclusion 130

Rachelss first claim is that often active euthanasia seems more humane than

passive and therefore active euthanasia should not be only permitted but preferred too.

Rachelss reinforces his position in mercy argument. Rachelss position is based on the

suffering of terminally ill patients and that on his view such suffering can be eliminated

by active euthanasia. The research shows two main responses to Rachelss claim which

render his argument invalid.

The first response is that Rachels argues against CDE on the basis not included

in the AMAs statement. According the AMAs statement, CDE is not based on

suffering and no consideration is included on methods which produce less or more

suffering. Therefore, Rachelss argument against AMAs position is irrelevant. The

second response is made if Rachelss argument is taken against CDE on the basis of

suffering although not considered in AMAs statement. Even though, the research

forwards the reasons which render Rachelss argument unimportant, irrelevant, and

inadequate. There are two main reasons against Rachelss claim.

The first reason is that, allowing euthanasia would risk killing people who

could otherwise have had years of more life. The case from the practical point goes

against the active euthanasia, because recovery is a probability. Furthermore, the active

euthanasia in the case leads to fallacy: appeal to future. Because the defender of active

euthanasia takes the death of the patient granted. Therefore, Rachelss claim is

practically and normatively indefensible. The second reason is that modern advanced

medical technology has the most developed treatment to control the pain or suffering of

terminally ill patients. From the practical point of view suffering is irrelevant to the
Conclusion 131

issue of euthanasia due to advances in palliative care and pain medication. Therefore

active euthanasia seems undesirable. The other important notion which is connected

with suffering is the conception of the nature of suffering itself. The suffering can be

physical and it can be also mental or psychological. If suffering becomes the basis for

the permissibility of active euthanasia, then many patients who are not terminally ill

but psychologically suffering or non-terminally ill, will be subjects of euthanasia as

well. Therefore, suffering as itself is an inadequate reason for permissibility of active

euthanasia. Furthermore, suffering is actually about the attitude; it extends into

metaphysical questions about the nature of human happiness and of what constitutes a

meaningful life. On the whole, Rachless position is conceptually and practically

indefensible.

However, while it may be true any terminally ill patient might, for very good

reasons, no longer wish to prolong his or her life. These cases are cited in Rachelss

works also. However, the reason which renders such a position invalid is that the cases

are of patients who are being kept alive by extraordinary means; their death is being

prolonged due to inappropriate use of advanced medical technology. The point is that if

a person could not be cured by ordinary treatment, providing extraordinary treatment to

such a patient when death is foreseen would only create suffering. Unfortunately,

Rachels has missed this point in his works. However, Rachels argues that there are still

patients, their death is foreseen and instead of killing them they are left to die and their

dying process takes days and weeks in suffering. He therefore argues that such patients

could have been better off by active euthanasia by putting end to their suffering. The

research argues against it by two reasons. The first is that pain medication and
Conclusion 132

palliative care has made suffering irrelevant. The second reason is that those patients

who are terminally ill and their life may be miserable due to the pain which is caused by

illness, for such patients, double doctrine effect (DDE) opens the way and avoids any

need of active euthanasia. On the whole, Rachelss claim of killing a patient is

practically unjustifiable because in light of above reasons there appears no need of

killing a terminally ill patient.

Rachelss second claim is that the conventional view makes life-and-death

decisions on irrelevant grounds therefore the conventional view, CDE, is not true.

Rachels claims that those irrelevant grounds are killing and letting die; and

according to him the relevant ground should be elimination of suffering. The research

shows that the relevant grounds in CDE are the killing and termination of extraordinary

medical care. The elimination of suffering is not included; its irrelevance is shown in

the preceding arguments. Rachelss claim against CDE is theoretically unjustifiable.

Furthermore, irrelevance of killing and letting die is already shown earlier in the

criticism of the conceptual framework, and its irrelevance is further shown in the

criticism of the following claim .

Rachelss third claim is that there is no moral difference between doings and

refraining, therefore wherever refraining is allowed doing should be permitted too; in

other words, wherever passive euthanasia is allowed active should be allowed too.

Rachels attempts to demonstrate that active and passive distinction is without any

difference. The research shows that Rachelss argument is invalid due to four reasons:

(1) irrelevance to AMAs statement; (2) differences between the cases because of
Conclusion 133

intentionality, causality, and agency; (3) straw man fallacy, (4) and weak analogy.

The first reason is that the argument is irrelevant to AMAs statement which

does not make any distinction between killing and letting die, therefore Rachelss

argument against the statement is irrelevant. The second reason is that in active

euthanasia killing is intended whereas death in passive euthanasia happens naturally

without any intention. Furthermore, closely connected is the legal distinction between

ignorance of law and ignorance of fact. In legal judgments of the actions intentions are

considered; a crime committed intentionally receives greater punishment than the same

act done unintentionally. Moreover, causation and agency also makes the cases

different: in active euthanasia the cause is lethal injection and the agency is a physician,

whereas in passive euthanasia the cause and agency are the underlying disease. The

third reason is that Rachels makes very superficial and shallow claim that if a patient is

dying and could be in fact cured and doctor leaves such a patient without care and such

a patient dies and in the case killing and letting die would make no difference. This

reason is very irresponsible and subject to fallacies such as straw man fallacy, missing

the point, and equivocation; because terminating ordinary medical care when the

patient is potentially able to recover is not the subject matter of active euthanasia or

passive euthanasia. The fourth reason is that Rachelss illustration of Smith and Johns

in support of his argument commits fallacy of weak analogy, the cases are not

analogous. Because, the distinction between active and passive euthanasia lies in the

patients autonomy and ability to refuse treatment. Due the above reasons, Rachelss

claim becomes theoretically unjustifiable, because active and passive are distinctly

different.
Conclusion 134

Rachelss fourth claim is that often heard argument for the conventional view,

which states is that in passive euthanasia doctor does nothing whereas in active doctor

is the cause of death, is unsound. Because, the doctor does something, he lets the

patient die. Rachels repeats his straw man fallacy as in preceding claim; the research

shows that it is the underlying disease which causes the death, not the doctor. Therefore,

Rachelss claim becomes theoretically unjustifiable.

The research, after criticizing the conceptual framework, and Rachelss

arguments against CDE, criticizes Rachelss direct arguments for active euthanasia.

The research shows that Rachelss arguments for active euthanasia are three types: (1)

argument based on biological and biographical distinction, (2) arguments based on

CDE by dissolving the distinction between active euthanasia and passive euthanasia;

these two types can be classified as indirect arguments; and (3) direct arguments for

active euthanasia. These direct arguments are: (1) argument from mercy, (2) argument

from the best interests and golden rule, and (3) argument from autonomy. And finally,

he proposes a modest proposal on the legalization of active euthanasia. The research

shows that Rachelss argument for active euthanasia are interconnected in a way that

no argument stands on its own to support his position. His first argument from mercy

shows the problem of pure utilitarianism, to remove such a difficulty, he moves to best

interest argument, where he feels helpless and turns to the golden rule argument and the

golden rule argument ultimately depends on autonomy. Autonomy becomes

problematic and more problematic by his legislation proposal on active euthanasia.


Conclusion 135

Rachelss first argument from mercy is not different from his first argument

against CDE. Rachelss position is that it is cruel and inhumane to refuse the plea of a

terminally ill person that his or her life be ended to avoid unnecessary suffering and

pain. Allowing such a person to terminate his or her life is an act of mercy. As noted

earlier, the research demonstrates the reasons which render Rachelss argument

unimportant, irrelevant, and inadequate.

Rachelss second argument is from the best interests and golden rule. In short,

the argument holds that if active euthanasia promotes the best interest of everyone

concerned, and violates no one's rights, then it should be is morally acceptable. He

further uses Kantian categorical imperative that if we like euthanasia applied to us, we

should like it to be applied to others.

The research demonstrates three reasons which render the argument invalid.

They are: (1) the argument is based on subjective moral judgment, failing the

universalization test; (2) it may not be in my own best interests or in the best interests

of others for me to die; and (3 the argument is based on indefensible autonomy.

The research demonstrates that the best interest and golden rule arguments are

based on subjective moral judgment, therefore the arguments fail the morally

universalization test and become subject of partiality. The relevance of

universalization test is due to Rachelss acceptance of categorical imperative. In short,

if a person takes anything in his own interest, it does not guarantee that such an act

would be desirable to other people. Similarly, not everything people would wish to

have done to them is morally appropriate. Some terminally ill patients may like to be
Conclusion 136

killed, but their wishes are not enough to establish a moral rule, because they are

pointing to their own pain as a justification for carving out an exception to the general

legal and moral rule against intentionally killing the innocent. Furthermore, the

research by referring to various studies establishes the fact that even approval of some

terminally ill patients for active euthanasia is due to treatable depression; and because

of other factors the approval of such patients turn out to be a matter of completion

instead of free autonomous wish. Moreover as the research mentioned earlier the

relation of categorical imperative, Rachelss understanding of Kant turns out to be a

misinterpretation. Because, Kant argued that taking ones own life was inconsistent

with the notion of autonomy, properly understood. Autonomy, in Kants view, does not

mean the freedom to do whatever one wants, but instead depends on the knowing

subjugation of ones desires and inclinations to ones rational understanding of

universally valid moral rules. According to Kant, our rational wills are the source of

our moral duty, and it is therefore a kind of practical contradiction to suppose that the

same will can permissibly destroy itself. Given the distinctive worth of an autonomous

rational will, suicide is an attack on the very source of moral authority. Therefore, due

to these reasons, Rachelss claim of killing a terminally ill patient on the basis of the

best interest and golden rule becomes normatively and theoretically unjustifiable.

Rachelss third argument is from autonomy. Rachelss conception of

biographical life entails that a human being is autonomous; therefore, if a person

autonomously chooses to end his or her life then it is morally permissible. Rachels also

supports his position by the of analogy to the law of suicide; since it is not unlawful for

a person to commit or attempt to commit suicide, therefore such a person should be


Conclusion 137

able to seek the assistance of others in achieving this end. Importantly, the argument

from autonomy stands as the foundation of Rachelss thesis which according to him is

based on the golden rule and the best interest argument.

The research demonstrates that argument from autonomy fails to claim the

sufficient support to substantiate a pro-position for the approval of active euthanasia.

The related reasons are: (1) invalidity of civil rights claim; (2) weak analogy between

suicide and euthanasia; (3) unwarranted influence of patients autonomy on doctors

autonomy; and (4) unattainable autonomy of the terminally ill patients.

The first reason is that civil rights claim from right of property and right to

death is invalid. Because, our selves are not sufficiently distinct from our bodies to

make ownership of the body; and it does not seem to follow from having a right to life

that a person has a right to death. The second reason is that Rachelss commits fallacy

of weak analogy between suicide and euthanasia. Because, suicide is a civil liberty,

whereas euthanasia is a civil right, there exists the important distinction between them

because suicide is an autonomous and self-regarding act, and active voluntary

euthanasia requires the involvement and assistance of a second party. Furthermore, if

the argument for active voluntary euthanasia is based on dignity of human freedom and

self-determination, then it is inconsistent to ask someone else to assist. The third reason

is that by accepting patients autonomy it will have unwarranted influence on doctors

autonomy. The creation of any right to active euthanasia tends to imply a

corresponding duty on the part of someone to become actively involved in bringing

about death. Because of the adverse consequence, in the US constitutional context, the
Conclusion 138

courts have already indicated that the recognition of a constitutional right to physician

assisted suicide does not entail any duty on the part of any doctor. There is broad

agreement amongst euthanasia advocates that it would be inappropriate to impose a

duty on any person to take the life of another. Although such a duty would uphold the

autonomy of the patient who requests assistance, it is recognized that it would be an

unjustifiable interference with the autonomy of others. It is primarily to avoid the

implication of any such duty and the resulting infringement of the autonomy of other

parties that a strictly rights-based model has been widely rejected as an appropriate

basis for the legalization of active voluntary euthanasia. The fourth reason is that

autonomy of the patients is practically unattainable. Because, disease and pain

medication can cause clouding of patients mind, outside forces can influence the

patients will, furthermore the research shows that the patients who desire an early

death during a serious terminal illness are usually suffering from a treatable depressive

condition. In light of all these reasons, Rachelss claim from autonomy becomes

normatively, practically, and conceptually unjustifiable.

Rachels proposes modest proposal on the legalization of active euthanasia.

According to his proposal a physician who kills a patient would be acquitted on

proving that the patient requested so and by pleading mercy killing. Rachels claims

that under the proposal no one would be authorized to decide when a patient should be

killed. Rachels further explains that by following the proposal we would rely on the

good sense of judges and juries to separate the cases of justifiable euthanasia from the

cases of unjustifiable murder, just as we already rely on them to separate the cases of

self-defense and insanity and coercion. The research demonstrates that Rachelss
Conclusion 139

proposal on legalizing active euthanasia is problematic and after analyzing his proposal

from the legal and practical points, his proposal turns out to be impractical. The

research shows that the proposal fails to provide clear guidelines. The proposal

suggests that after mercy killing a criminal trial can acquit the physician, the

impossibility arises when the murdered person is killed and there is no one left to

follow his killing or those who follow have vested interests. The research shows that

Rachels is very naive about homicide and criminal law procedures. He suggest that

there will be no one to follow the murder case as guardians will give consent

positively, and therefore he ignores the role of the state and police . Rachels confuses

criminal trial with civil trial. The further complication arises that not many physicians

would be ready to face trials after mercy killing in absence of any guidelines and

legalized procedures. The biggest problem which the proposal fails to deal with is that

on one hand Rachels dismisses any committees which could decide the euthanasia,

whereas on the other hand he leaves the matter unto doctors that they could defend

themselves on commonsense or ignorance of fact, which gives an easy hand to a doctor

to kill people without any requirements. On the whole, Rachelss proposal is

practically unjustifiable.

On the whole, the researcher has demonstrated throughout of this study that

Rachelss conceptual framework , his arguments against CDE , his arguments for

active euthanasia, and his proposal on the legalization of active euthanasia, are

normatively, practically, theoretically, and conceptually unjustifiable.


Conclusion 140

Equally important, are the findings of this research regarding the scrutiny into

the nature of euthanasia, its definition, origin, and solution. The research agrees only

with the narrow construal definition of euthanasia: only active euthanasia. And

suggests its prohibition. To support such a position, the research develops three

propositions: (1) prolonging of death is one of the moral hazards of advanced medical

technology; (2) the cases of passive euthanasia are the cases of the natural state of

extinction; and (3) the need of active euthanasia as defended by Rachels due to some

case studies of patients is un-unjustifiable due to two reasons: (1) that the cases are

actually mishandled by the misuse of advanced medical technology and (2) if there

are terminally ill patients in anticipation of death and living in painful state such

patients could be dealt by the use of doctrine of double effect (DDE). The research

demonstrates that AMAs statement on euthanasia is valid. In addition, the patients

should not be intentionally killed and extraordinary medical treatment can be

withdrawn or withheld by the permission of the patient or due to hopeless condition of

the patient by the permission of his legal guardians. Furthermore, Rachelss

categorization of active and passive euthanasia into killing and letting die is a false

dichotomy: Rachels gives two choices; either killing or letting die, and prefers killing

to letting die. Whereas the research demonstrates that both of these choices killing and

letting die are irrelevant. The third and only choice is to stop prolongation of death by

medical technology, to allow termination of extraordinary medical care from dying

person by following legitimate procedures, and to allow use of pain medication.

Further Research and Recommendations


Conclusion 141

The researcher would like to suggest and recommend that there is need of

further research in the field of palliative care to make it more efficient and comforting.

The further research is also needed in the area of denaturalized advanced medical

services and facilities; these services and facilities are in need of ethical evaluation

which can help in setting the proper procedures for their use. Moreover, dehumanizing

nature of advanced medical technology deserves a multidisciplinary scrutiny. There is

also an urgent need of research in the field of cross-cultural family values. The

researcher believes that there are many family values which could be learnt from the

Eastern cultures in looking after the elderly and terminally ill family members.
References

Primary Sources:

Rachels, J. (1977). Medical ethics and the rule against killing. In S. Stuart, & H.

T. Engelhardt, Jr. (Eds.), Philosophical medical ethics (pp. 63-69).

Dordrecht: Reidel.

________. (1979a). Euthanasia, killing, and letting die. In J. Ladd (Ed.), Ethical

issues relating to life and death (pp. 146-163). Oxford: Oxford University

Press.

________. (1979b). Killing and starving to death. Philosophy, 54, 159-171.

________. (1980). Euthanasia. In R. Tom (Ed.), Matters of life and death (pp.

28-66). New York: Random House.

________. (1981a). More impertinent distinctions. Biomedical Ethics, 355-359.

________. (1981b). Reasoning about killing and letting die. The Southern Journal

of Philosophy, 19, 465-473.

________. (1983). Barney Clark's key. [Electronic version]. The Hastings Center

Report, 13 (2), 17-19.

________. (1984). Euthanasia and the physician's professional commitments. The

Southern Journal of Philosophy, 22, 281-285.


References 142

________. (1986a). The permissibility of ending life. Transactions of the

American Society for Artificial Internal Organs, 32, 674-676.

________. (1986b). The end of life: Euthanasia and morality. Oxford: Oxford

University Press.

________. (1993). Killing, letting die, and the value of life. Bioethica: Revista

Interdisciplinaire, 2, 271-283.

________. (1994a). Active and passive euthanasia. In A. Norcross, & B.

Steinbock (Eds.), Killing and letting die (2nd ed., pp.112 -120). New

York, USA: Fordham University Press. (Original work published 1975)

________. (1994b). More impertinent distinctions and a defense of active

euthanasia. In A. Norcross, & B. Steinbock (Eds.), Killing and letting die

(2nd ed., pp.139 -155). New York, USA: Fordham University Press.

(Original work published 1981)

________. (2001). Killing and letting die. In Encyclopedia of ethics (Vol. 2,

pp. 947-50). New York: Routledge.

________. (2002). The value of human life. Philosophical Inquiry, 24, 3-16.

________. (2003). Euthanasia: A Rebuttal of Sullivan. Retrieved January 25, 2006

from http://www.rrcc- online.com/~harolda/onethic/ethics/module3/

rachels2.htm
References 143

Secondary Sources:

Aristotle. (1999). Nicomachean ethics (T. Irwin, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett

Publishing.

_______. (2000). Politics . Benjamin Jowett, Trans.). Retrieved January 24,

2006 from http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/politics.html

Alvarez, A. (1971). The savage god: A study of suicide . New York: Random

House.

Adams, R., et al. (1992). Physician assisted suicide and the right to die with

assistance. Harvard Law Review 105:2021-2040. Retrieved March 24,

2007 from http://www.jstor.org/pss/1341556

Admiraal, P. (1989). Justifiable active euthanasia in the Netherlands. In R. M.

Baird, & S. E. Rosenbaum (Eds.), Euthanasia: The moral issues (pp.125

129). Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Books. (Original work published

Winter 1988-89)

Aquinas , St. T. (1947). Summa theologica. (Benziger Bros. ed.). Retrieved

March 20, 2007, from http://www.assumption.edu/users/gcolvert/

summa/index.html
References 144

American Medical Association, Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs. (1992).

Deecisions near the end of life. 267 JAMA 9999, 2230-31, 2233. Retrieved

March 20, 2006, from http://jama.ama-assn.org/cgi/content/citation

/267/16/2229

Berkich , D. ( 24 March 2003 ). Rachels Arguments Against CDE. Retrieved

January 25, 2006 from http://falcon.tamucc.edu/~philosophy/courses/03-

spring/berkich/bioethics/notes/rachels_arguments_against_cde.html

Bryant, C. D. (2003). Handbook of death & dying. Michigan: University of

Michigan.

Baird, R. M. & Stuart E. Rosenbaum (ed). (1989). Euthanasia: The moral issues

Buffalo, NY: Prometheus.

British Medical Association. (2007). Withholding and withdrawing life-

prolonging medical treatment: Guidance for decision making . (3rd ed.)

Blackwell Publishing . (Original work published 1999)

Cohen-Almagor, R. (2000). Language and reality at the end of life. Journal of

Law, Medicine & Ethics, 28 (3), 267-78.

Callahan, D. (1989). Can we return death to disease? [Electronic version].

Hastings Cent Rep 1989; 19:4-6. The Hastings Center Report, 19, 52-55.

_________. (1992). When self-determination runs amok. [Electronic version].

The Hastings Center Report, 22, (2), 52-55.


References 145

Crigger , B.J. (1990). The court & Nancy Cruzan. The Hastings Center Report,

20 ( 1).

Compassion in Dying v. State of Washington Ch. No. 94-35534 (9th Cir. March

6 1996). Retrieved January 24, 2006 from http://caselaw.lp.findlaw.com/

scripts/getcase.pl?court=9th&navby=case&no=9435534&exact=1

Coleman, G. D. (1989). Assisted suicide an ethical perspective. In R. M. Baird, &

S. E. Rosenbaum (Eds.), Euthanasia: The moral issues (pp.125 129).

Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Books. (Original work published 1987)

Charlesworth , M. J. (1989). Life, death, genes, and ethics: Biotechnology and

bioethics. Crows Nest, N.S.W: ABC Enterprises for the Australian

Broadcasting.

Carr, W. H. A. (1995). A right to die . [Electronic version]. The Saturday

Evening Post, 267, 50-1.

Chobli, M. (2004 ). Suicide . Retrieved January 25, 2006 from

http://plato.stanford.edu/ entries/suicide/

Dinello, D. (1994). On killing and letting die. In A. Norcross, & B. Steinbock

(Eds.), Killing and letting die (2nd ed., pp. 192197). New York, USA:

Fordham University Press. (Original work published 1971)

Donnelly, J. (1998). Suicide: right or wrong? New York: Prometheus Books.


References 146

Descartes, R. (1984). Meditations on first philosophy. In J. Cottingham; R.

Stoothoff; & D. Murdoch ( trans.) The philosophical writings of

Descartes .New York: Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge.

___________(1931). The philosophical works of Descartes . Haldane and G.

Ross (trans.). Cambridge.

Emanuel , E. J. (2000). Assisted suicide largely shunned. The Christian Century;

117, 34.

Euthanasia. (2008). In Merriam-Webster Online Dictionary.

Retrieved March 3, 2008, from http://www.merriam-

webster.com/dictionary/ euthanasia

Edelstein, J. (1943). The Hippocratic oath: Text, translation, and interpretation.

Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

Ferngren, G.B. (1989). The ethics of suicide in the renaissance and reformation.

In B. Brody (ed.), Suicide and euthanasia: Historical and contemporary

themes. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Fenigsen, R. (1989). A case against Dutch euthanasia. The Hastings Center

Report; 19. Issue: 1. [Electronic Version]

Fletcher, G. P. (1994). Prolonging life: Some legal considerations. In A. Norcross,

& B. Steinbock (Eds.), Killing and letting die (2nd ed., pp. 88 -103). New
References 147

York, USA: Fordham University Press. (Original work published 1967)

Fletcher, J. (1972). Indicators of humanhood: A tentative profile. Hastings Center

Report , 2 (5) , 1-4 . http://www.jstor.org/pss/3561570

________. (1989). Sanctity of life versus quality of life. In R. M. Baird, & S. E.

Rosenbaum (Eds.), Euthanasia: The moral issues (pp.85 97). Buffalo,

New York: Prometheus Books. (Original work published 1987)

Fried , C. (1976). Right and wrong--preliminary considerations. The Journal of

Legal Studies, 5 ( 2), 165-200.

Foot, P. (1994a). The problem of abortion and the doctrine of the double effect. In

A. Norcross, & B. Steinbock (Eds.), Killing and letting die (2nd ed.,

pp.266 -280). New York, USA: Fordham University Press. (Original

work published 1967)

______. (1994b). Killing and letting die. In A. Norcross, & B. Steinbock (Eds.),

Killing and letting die (2nd ed., pp.280 -290). New York, USA: Fordham

University Press. (Original work published 1984)

Finnis , J. (1990). Allocating risks and suffering: Some hidden traps. Cleveland.

ST. L. REV. 193, 202.


References 148

Gifford, E. (1993). Artres moriendi: Active euthanasia and the art of dying. UCLA

Law Review, 40, 1545-1583.

Gay-Williams, J. (1989). The wrongfulness of euthanasia. In R. M. Baird, & S.

E. Rosenbaum (Eds.), Euthanasia: The moral issues (pp.97 103).

Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Books. (Original work published 1979)

Gaylin, W., Kass, L.R. , Pellegrino, E.D., & Siegler, M. (1989). Doctors must

not kill. In R. M. Baird, & S. E. Rosenbaum (Eds.), Euthanasia: The

moral issues (pp.25 29). Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Books.

(Original work published 1979)

Gula, R. M. (1999a). Dying well: a challenge to Christian compassion. The

Christian Century; 116, 14, 501-5.

Gorsuch, N. M. (2000). The Right to Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia.Harvard

Journal of Law & Public Policy; 23. (3).

_______ (1999b). A different death: Euthanasia and the Christian tradition, by

Edward J. Larson; Darrel W. Amundsen. Reviewed in: The Christian

Century, 116 (14 ), p. 501-5.

Harris, J. (1994). The survival lottery. In A. Norcross, & B. Steinbock (Eds.),

Killing and letting die (2nd ed., pp.257 -266). New York, USA: Fordham
References 149

University Press. (Original work published 1975)

Hohfeld W; Cook, W.W. (Ed). (1919). Fundamental legal conceptions. New

Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Hippocrates . (2005). The oath and law of Hippocrates. The Harvard Classics,

190914. Retrieved July 3, 2007, from

http://www.bartleby.com/38/1/1.html

Hendin , H. (1997). The death debate. The Wilson Quarterly, 21.

Hendin, H., Foley, K., White, M. (1998a). Physician-assisted suicide: Reflections

on Oregon's first case. Issues in Law & Medicine, 14 (3), 243-70.

___________________________. (1998b). Oregon Death with Dignity Act.

Issues in Law & Medicine, 14 (3), 243-70. Retrieved March 3, 2008 ,

from http://www.ohd.hr.state.or.us/cdpe/chs/pas/pas.htm

Hume, D. (2004). Essays on suicide and the immortality of the soul. Kessinger

Publishing.

Hardon, J. A., S.J. (2004). Moral theology. Retrieved March 5, 2007 , from

http://www.therealpresence.org/archives/Moral_Theology/

Moral_Theology_004.htm

Irving, D. N. (1993). Scientific and philosophical expertise: An evaluation of the

arguments on "personhood". Linacre Quarterly, 60:1:18-46. Retrieved

March 2, 2006, from http://www.consciencelaws.org/Examining-

Conscience-Background/GenScience/BackGenScience06.html#01
References 150

Jacox, A., Carr, D. B., Payne, R. (1994). New clinical-practice guidelines for the

management of pain in patients with cancer. The New England Journal of

Medicine , 330 (9), 651-655.

Jonathan, B. (1994a). Whatever the consequences. In A. Norcross, & B.

Steinbock (Eds.), Killing and letting die (2nd ed., pp.167 -192). New

York, USA: Fordham University Press. (Original work published 1966)

_________. (1994b). Negation and abstention: Two theories of allowing. In A.

Norcross, & B. Steinbock (Eds.), Killing and letting die (2nd ed., pp. 230

257). New York, USA: Fordham University Press.

(Original work published 1993)

Kuhse, H. & Singer, P. (1985). Should the baby live. New York: Oxford

University Press.

Kearl , M. C. (1989) Endings: A sociology of death and dying. Oxford University

Press .

Kuhse H. (1994). Euthanasia. In P. Singer (ed.), A companion to ethics . Oxford:

Blackwell.

Kant,I. ( 1785). Fundamental principles of the metaphysic of morals. (Thomas

Kingsmill Abbott, trans.). Retrieved July 2, 2006,


References 151

From http://www.grtbooks.com/

exitfram.asp?idx=3&yr=1785&aa=KA&at=FU&ref=kant&URL=http://w

ww.constitution.org/kant/metamora.htm

Koop, C. E. (1989a). The right to die: The moral dilemmas. In R. M. Baird, & S.

E. Rosenbaum (Eds.), Euthanasia: The moral issues (pp. 69 -85).

Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Books. (Original work published 1976)

_________. (1989b). The case of Karen Quinlan. In R. M. Baird, & S. E.

Rosenbaum (Eds.), Euthanasia: The moral issues (pp. 35 -45). Buffalo,

New York: Prometheus Books. (Original work published 1976)

Kaufman, S. R. (2005). And a time to die: How American hospitals shape the end

of life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Kaveny , M. C. (1997). Assisted suicide, euthanasia and the law. Theological

studies, 58, (1).

Lichtenberg, J. (1994). The moral equivalence of action and omission. In A.

Norcross, & B. Steinbock (Eds.), Killing and letting die (2nd ed., pp. 210-

230). New York, USA: Fordham University Press. (Original work

published 1982)

Larue, G. A. (1989). The case for active voluntary euthanasia. In R. M. Baird,

& S. E. Rosenbaum (Eds.), Euthanasia: The moral issues (pp. 159 -163).
References 152

Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Books. (Original work published Winter

1988-89)

Locke, J. (1894). An essay concerning human understanding. London: George

Routledge and Sons.

_______. (2001). The second treaties of government. In P. Hayden (Ed.), The

philosophy of human rights, St. Paul, MN: Paragon House.

Linacre Centre Working Party. (1982). Euthanasia and clinical practice: trends,

principles and alternatives. The Linacre Centre for Healthcare Ethics.

London. Retrieved August 27, 2007,fromhttp://www.linacre.org/lords.html

McMahan, J. (1994). Killing, letting die, and withdrawing aid. In A. Norcross, &

B. Steinbock (Eds.), Killing and letting die (2nd ed., pp.383 -421). New

York, USA: Fordham University Press. (Original work published 1993)

Murphy, J. G. (1994). Is Killing the Innocent Absolutely Immoral? In A. Norcross,

& B. Steinbock (Eds.), Killing and letting die (2nd ed., pp.197 -210). New

York, USA: Fordham University Press. (Original work published 1973)

McHugh, P. R . (1999) On death and dying [Review of the article Dying made

easy ] Commentary, 107 (5).

Mitchell , J.A. & Rae, S.B. ( 1996). The moral status of fetuses and embryos. In B.

Stetson (Ed.), The silent subject: reflections on the unborn in American

culture (pp. 19-33). Westport, CT : Praeger .

McIntyre, A. (2004). Doctrine of double effect. Retrieved January 25, 2006 from

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/double-effect/
References 153

Moreland, J. P. (1990). The life and death debate: Moral issues of our time.

Westport, CT: Praeger.

Manetta, A. A., and Wells, J. G. (2001). Ethical issues in the social worker's

role in physician-assisted suicide. Health and social work, 26 (3).

More, T. (1999). Utopia (David Wootton, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett

Publishing.

Mair, A.W. (2007). Suicide: Greek and Roman. (J. Hastings ed.,) Encyclopedia of

religion and ethics (V.12, pp. 26-30). Varda Books.

Norcross, A. & Steinbock , B . (Eds.). (1994). Killing and Letting Die. New York:

Fordham University Press.

Omar, M. (1993). Death in America. Critical Care Clinics, 9(3), G132G, 613.

Otlowski, M. (1997). Voluntary euthanasia and the common law. Oxford:

Clarendon Press.

Official Website of James Rachels. (n.d.). Biography. Retrieved February 20,

2006, from http://www.jamesrachels.org/JboBio.htm

Plato. (1980). The laws of Plato (T. L. Pangle, Trans.). New York: Basic Books.

____. (1991). The republic of Plato (A. Bloom, Trans.). New York: Basic Books.

Paris, J. J. (1997). Autonomy and physician-assisted suicide. America, 176.

11-14 .
References 154

President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and

Biomedical and Behavioural Research. .( 1983). Deciding to forego life-

sustaining treatment. A report on the ethical, medical and legal issues in

treatment decisions. Retrieved January 19, 2007, from

http://www.lib.mcg.edu/edu/drdilemma/consult/presdent.htm

Quinn, W. S. (1994). Actions, intentions, and consequences: The doctrine of

doing and allowing. In A. Norcross, & B. Steinbock (Eds.), Killing and

letting die (2nd ed., 355 -383). New York, USA: Fordham University

Press. (Original work published 1989)

Richard, F. (1989). A case against Dutch euthanasia. [Electronic version]. The

Hastings Center Report, 19, (1), 22-30.

Steinbock, B. (1994). The intentional termination of life. In A. Norcross, & B.

Steinbock (Eds.), Killing and letting die (2nd ed., pp.120 -131). New York,

USA: Fordham University Press. (Original work published 1979)

Sullivan, T. D. (1994a). Active and passive euthanasia: An impertinent distinction?

In A. Norcross, & B. Steinbock (Eds.), Killing and letting die (2nd ed.,

pp.131 -139). New York, USA: Fordham University Press. (Original work

published 1977)

___________. (1994b). Coming to terms: A response to Rachels. In A. Norcross,


References 155

& B. Steinbock (Eds.), Killing and letting die (2nd ed., pp.155 -167). New

York, USA: Fordham University Press.

Shewmon, D. A. (1989). Active voluntary euthanasia a needless Pandora's box. In

R. M. Baird, & S. E. Rosenbaum (Eds.), Euthanasia: The moral issues (pp.

129 -141). Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Books. (Original work

published 1987)

Schiavo Case. (2007). In The Columbia encyclopedia (6th ed.). New York:

Columbia University Press.

Solomon, W. D. (n.d.). Double effect. In The encyclopedia of ethics. . Retrieved

January 27, 2006 from http://www.saintmarys.edu/

~incandel/doubleeffect.html

Stetson , B. (Ed.). (1996). The silent subject: Reflections on the unborn in

American culture. Westport, CT: : Praeger.

Seneca. (1998). On the proper time to slip the cable. In J. Donnelly (Ed.),

Suicide: Right or wrong? . (pp. 35-39). New York, USA: Prometheus

Books. . (Original work published 1917)

Tooley, M. (1994). An irrelevant consideration: Killing versus letting die. In A.

Norcross, & B. Steinbock (Eds.), Killing and letting die (2nd ed., pp.103 -

112). New York, USA: Fordham University Press.


References 156

The New York State Task Force on Life and the Law. (1994). When Death is

Sought Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia in the Medical Contex . Retrieved

February 20, 2006, from

http://www.health.state.ny.us/nysdoh/consumer/patient/chap5.htm

Trammell, R. (1994). Saving life and taking life. In A. Norcross, & B. Steinbock

(Eds.), Killing and letting die (2nd ed., pp.290 -298). New York, USA:

Fordham University Press. (Original work published 1975)

The World Medical Association. (2005). Resolution on euthanasia. Retrieved

February 20, 2007, from www.wma.net/e/policy/e13b.htm

Trowell, H. C. (1973). The unfinished debate on euthanasia. London: S.C.M.

Press.

The Robert Powell Center for Medical Ethics. (n.d.). Retrieved February 20, 2006,

from http://www.nrlc.org/euthanasia/index.html#DEFINITIONS

Vaux, K. L. (1989). Debbie's dying mercy killing and the good death. In R. M.

Baird, & S. E. Rosenbaum (Eds.), Euthanasia: The moral issues (pp. 29

35). Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Books. (Original work published

1988)

Veatch , R. (1989). Death, dying, and the biological revolution: Our last quest for

responsibility. New Haven: Yale University Press.


References 157

Wicker, C. (1989). Sentenced to life In R. M. Baird, & S. E. Rosenbaum (Eds.),

Euthanasia: The moral issues (pp. 15 23). Buffalo, New York:

Prometheus Books. (Original work published April 23, 1989)

Warren, M. A. (1996). On the moral and legal status of abortion. In T.A. Mappes

& D. DeGrazia (Eds.) Biomedical ethics, 4th ed. (pp. 434-440). New

York: McGraw-Hill. Retrieved January 25, 2006 from

http://instruct.westvalley.edu/lafave/warren_article.html

Wanzer, H., Federman, DD., Adelstein, SJ. , Cassel, CK., Cassem, EH., Cranford,

RE., et al. (1990). The physician's responsibility toward hopelessly ill

patients: A second look. In J. J. Walter, & T. A, Shannon (Eds.) Quality

of life: The new medical dilemma, (pp. 282-292). Paulist Press .

(Original work published 1989)

Young, R. (2007). Voluntary euthanasia. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Retrieved February 20, 2006, from

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/euthanasia-voluntary/

Potrebbero piacerti anche