Sei sulla pagina 1di 38

Three Factors in Language

Design
Noam Chomsky
The biolinguistic perspective regards the language faculty as an organ
of the body, along with other cognitive systems. Adopting it, we
expect to find three factors that interact to determine (I-) languages
attained: genetic endowment (the topic of Universal Grammar), experi-
ence, and principles that are language- or even organism-independent.
Research has naturally focused on I-languages and UG, the problems
of descriptive and explanatory adequacy. The Principles-and-Param-
eters approach opened the possibility for serious investigation of the
third factor, and the attempt to account for properties of language in
terms of general considerations of computational efficiency, eliminat-
ing some of the technology postulated as specific to language and
providing more principled explanation of linguistic phenomena.

Keywords: minimalism, principled explanation, Extended Standard


Theory, Principles-and-Parameters, internal/external Merge, single-
cycle derivation, phase

Thirty years ago, in 1974, an international meeting took place at MIT, in cooperation with the
Royaumont Institute in Paris, on the topic of biolinguistics, a term suggested by the organizer,
Massimo Piattelli-Palmarini, and the title of a recent book surveying the field and proposing new
directions by Lyle Jenkins (2002).1 This was only one of many such interactions in those years,
including interdisciplinary seminars and international conferences.
The biolinguistic perspective began to take shape over 20 years before in discussions among
a few graduate students who were much influenced by developments in biology and mathematics
in the early postwar years, including work in ethology that was just coming to be known in the
United States. One of them was Eric Lenneberg, whose seminal 1967 study Biological Foundations
of Language remains a basic document of the field. Many of the leading questions discussed at
the 1974 conference, and in the years leading up to it, remain very much alive today.
One of these questions, repeatedly brought up in the conference as one of the basic questions
to be asked from the biological point of view, is the extent to which apparent principles of
language, including some that had only recently come to light, are unique to this cognitive system
or whether similar formal arrangements are found in other cognitive domains in humans or

This article is expanded from a talk presented at the annual meeting of the Linguistic Society of America, 9 January
2004. Thanks to Cedric Boeckx, Samuel David Epstein, Robert Freidin, Lyle Jenkins, Howard Lasnik, and Luigi Rizzi,
among others, for comments on an earlier draft.
1
The conference, titled A Debate on Bio-Linguistics, was held at Endicott House, Dedham, Massachusetts,
2021 May 1974, and organized by the Centre Royaumont pour une science de lhomme, Paris.

Linguistic Inquiry, Volume 36, Number 1, Winter 2005


122
2005 by the Massachusetts Institute of Technology 1
2 NOAM CHOMSKY

other organisms. An even more basic question from the biological point of view is how much of
language can be given a principled explanation, whether or not homologous elements can be
found in other domains or organisms. The effort to sharpen these questions and to investigate
them for language has come to be called the Minimalist Program in recent years, but the
questions arise for any biological system and are independent of theoretical persuasion, in linguis-
tics and elsewhere. Answers to these questions are fundamental not only to understanding the
nature and functioning of organisms and their subsystems, but also to investigating their growth
and evolution. For any biological system, language included, the only general question that arises
about the program is whether it can be productively pursued or is premature.
In these remarks, I will try to identify what seem to me some of the significant themes in
the past half-century of inquiry into problems of biolinguistics and to consider their current status.
Several preliminary qualifications should be obvious. One is that the picture is personal; others
would no doubt make different choices. A second is that things often seem clearer in retrospect
than at the time, so there is some anachronism in this account, but not I think too much. A third
is that I cannot even begin to mention the contributions of a great many people to the collective
enterprise, particularly as the related fields have expanded enormously in the years since the 1974
conference.
The biolinguistic perspective views a persons language as a state of some component of
the mind, understanding mind in the sense of eighteenth-century scientists who recognized
that after Newtons demolition of the only coherent concept of body, we can only regard aspects
of the world termed mental as the result of such an organical structure as that of the brain
(Joseph Priestley). Among the vast array of phenomena that one might loosely consider language-
related, the biolinguistic approach focuses attention on a component of human biology that enters
into the use and acquisition of language, however one interprets the term language. Call it the
faculty of language, adapting a traditional term to a new usage. This component is more or
less on a par with the systems of mammalian vision, insect navigation, and others. In many of
these cases, the best available explanatory theories attribute to the organism computational systems
and what is called rule-following in informal usagefor example, when a recent text on vision
presents the so-called rigidity principle as it was formulated 50 years ago: if possible, and
other rules permit, interpret image motions as projections of rigid motions in three dimensions
(Hoffman 1998:169). In this case, later work provided substantial insight into the mental computa-
tions that seem to be involved when the visual system follows these rules, but even for very
simple organisms, that is typically no slight task, and relating mental computations to analysis
at the cellular level is commonly a distant goal.
Adopting this conception, a language is a state of the faculty of language, an I-language, in
technical usage.
The decision to study language as part of the world in this sense was regarded as highly
controversial at the time, and still is. A more careful look will show, I think, that the arguments
advanced against the legitimacy of the approach have little force (a weak thesis) and that its basic
assumptions are tacitly adopted even by those who strenuously reject them, and indeed must be,
even for coherence (a much stronger thesis). I will not enter into this interesting chapter of
THREE FACTORS IN LANGUAGE DESIGN 3

contemporary intellectual history here, but will simply assume that crucial aspects of language
can be studied as part of the natural world, adopting the biolinguistic approach that took shape
half a century ago and that has been intensively pursued since, along different paths.
The language faculty is one component of what the cofounder of modern evolutionary theory,
Alfred Russel Wallace, called mans intellectual and moral nature: the human capacities for
creative imagination, language and symbolism generally, mathematics, interpretation and record-
ing of natural phenomena, intricate social practices, and the like, a complex of capacities that
seem to have crystallized fairly recently, perhaps a little over 50,000 years ago, among a small
breeding group of which we are all descendantsa complex that sets humans apart rather sharply
from other animals, including other hominids, judging by traces they have left in the archaeological
record. The nature of the human capacity, as some researchers now call it, remains a considera-
ble mystery. It was one element of a famous disagreement between the two founders of the theory
of evolution, with Wallace holding, contrary to Darwin, that evolution of these faculties cannot
be accounted for in terms of variation and natural selection alone, but requires some other
influence, law, or agency, some principle of nature alongside gravitation, cohesion, and other
forces without which the material universe could not exist. Although the issues are framed differ-
ently today within the core biological sciences, they have not disappeared (see Wallace 1889:
chap. 15, Marshack 1985).
It is commonly assumed that whatever the human intellectual capacity is, the faculty of
language is essential to it. Many scientists agree with paleoanthropologist Ian Tattersall, who
writes that he is almost sure that it was the invention of language that was the sudden and
emergent event that was the releasing stimulus for the appearance of the human capacity in
the evolutionary recordthe great leap forward as Jared Diamond called it, the result of some
genetic event that rewired the brain, allowing for the origin of modern language with the rich
syntax that provides a multitude of modes of expression of thought, a prerequisite for social
development and the sharp changes of behavior that are revealed in the archaeological record,
also generally assumed to be the trigger for the rapid trek from Africa, where otherwise modern
humans had apparently been present for hundreds of thousands of years (Tattersall 1998:2425;
see also Wells 2002). Tattersall takes language to be virtually synonymous with symbolic
thought. Elaborating, one of the initiators of the Royaumont-MIT symposia, Francois Jacob,
observed that the role of language as a communication system between individuals would have
come about only secondarily, as many linguists believe (1982:59), perhaps referring to discus-
sions at the symposia, where the issue repeatedly arose, among biologists as well. In the 1974
conference, his fellow Nobel laureate Salvador Luria was the most forceful advocate of the view
that communicative needs would not have provided any great selective pressure to produce a
system such as language, with its crucial relation to development of abstract or productive
thinking (Luria 1974:195). The quality of language that makes it unique does not seem to be
so much its role in communicating directives for action or other common features of animal
communication, Jacob continued, but rather its role in symbolizing, in evoking cognitive im-
ages, in molding our notion of reality and yielding our capacity for thought and planning,
through its unique property of allowing infinite combinations of symbols and therefore mental
4 NOAM CHOMSKY

creation of possible worlds, ideas that trace back to the seventeenth-century cognitive revolution
(1982:59). Jacob also stressed the common understanding that answers to questions about evolu-
tion in most instances . . . can hardly be more than more or less reasonable guesses (1982:
31).
We can add another insight of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century philosophy: that even
the most elementary concepts of human language do not relate to mind-independent objects by
means of some reference-like relation between symbols and identifiable physical features of the
external world, as seems to be universal in animal communication systems. Rather, they are
creations of the cognoscitive powers that provide us with rich means to refer to the outside
world from certain perspectives, but are individuated by mental operations that cannot be reduced
to a peculiar nature belonging to the thing we are talking about, as Hume summarized a century
of inquiry. Those are critical observations about the elementary semantics of natural language,
suggesting that its most primitive elements are related to the mind-independent world much as
the internal elements of phonology are, not by a reference-like relation but as part of a considerably
more intricate species of conception and action. It is for reasons such as these, though not clearly
grasped at the time, that the early work in the 1950s adopted a kind of use theory of meaning,
pretty much in the sense of John Austin and the later Wittgenstein: language was conceived as
an instrument put to use for various human purposes, generating expressions including arrange-
ments of the fundamental elements of the language, with no grammatical-ungrammatical divide,
each basically a complex of instructions for use (see Chomsky 1955, hereafter LSLT).2
If this much is generally on the right track, then at least two basic problems arise when we
consider the origins of the faculty of language and its role in the sudden emergence of the human
intellectual capacity: first, the core semantics of minimal meaning-bearing elements, including
the simplest of them; and second, the principles that allow infinite combinations of symbols,
hierarchically organized, which provide the means for use of language in its many aspects. Accord-
ingly, the core theory of languageUniversal Grammar (UG)must provide, first, a structured
inventory of possible lexical items that are related to or perhaps identical with the concepts that
are the elements of the cognoscitive powers, sometimes now regarded as a language of
thought along lines developed by Jerry Fodor (1975); and second, means to construct from
these lexical items the infinite variety of internal structures that enter into thought, interpretation,
planning, and other human mental acts, and that are sometimes put to use in action, including
the externalization that is a secondary process if the speculations just reviewed turn out to be
correct. On the first problem, the apparently human-specific conceptual-lexical apparatus, there
is important work on relational notions linked to syntactic structures and on the partially mind-
internal objects that appear to play a critical role (events, propositions, etc.).3 But there is little
beyond descriptive remarks on the core referential apparatus that is used to talk about the world.
The second problem has been central to linguistic research for half a century, with a long history
before in different terms.

2
For later discussion, see among others Chomsky 1966, 2001b, McGilvray 1999, Antony and Hornstein 2003.
3
For insightful review and original analysis, see Borer 2004a,b.
THREE FACTORS IN LANGUAGE DESIGN 5

The biolinguistic approach adopted from the outset the point of view that C. R. Gallistel
(1997) calls the norm these days in neuroscience (p. 86), the modular view of learning:
the conclusion that in all animals, learning is based on specialized mechanisms, instincts to
learn (p. 82) in specific ways. We can think of these mechanisms as organs within the brain
(p. 86), achieving states in which they perform specific kinds of computation. Apart from ex-
tremely hostile environments (p. 88), they change states under the triggering and shaping effect
of external factors, more or less reflexively, and in accordance with internal design. That is the
process of learning (Gallistel 1997, 1999), though growth might be a more appropriate
term, avoiding misleading connotations of the term learning. The modular view of learning
of course does not entail that the component elements of the module are unique to it: at some
level, everyone assumes that they are notthe cellular level, for exampleand the question of
the level of organization at which unique properties emerge remains a basic one from a biological
point of view, as it was at the 1974 conference.
Gallistels observations recall the concept of canalization introduced into evolutionary and
developmental biology by C. H. Waddington over 60 years ago, referring to processes adjusted so
as to bring about one definite end result regardless of minor variations in conditions during the
course of the reaction, thus ensuring the production of the normal, that is optimal type in the face
of the unavoidable hazards of existence (Waddington 1942). That seems to be a fair description of
the growth of language in the individual. A core problem of the study of the faculty of language
is to discover the mechanisms that limit outcomes to optimal types.
It has been recognized since the origins of modern biology that such constraints enter not
only into the growth of organisms but also into their evolution, with roots in the earlier tradition
that Stuart Kauffman calls rational morphology (1993:35).4 In a classic contemporary paper,
John Maynard Smith and associates trace the post-Darwinian reformulation back to Thomas
Huxley, who was struck by the fact that there appear to be predetermined lines of modification
that lead natural selection to produce varieties of a limited number and kind for every species
(Maynard Smith et al. 1985:266).5 They review a variety of such constraints in the organic world
and describe how limitations on phenotypic variability are caused by the structure, character,
composition, or dynamics of the developmental system, pointing out also that such develop-
mental constraints . . . undoubtedly play a significant role in evolution though there is yet little
agreement on their importance as compared with selection, drift, and other such factors in shaping
evolutionary history (p. 265). At about the same time, Jacob wrote that the rules controlling
embryonic development, almost entirely unknown, interact with other constraints imposed by
general body plan, mechanical properties of building materials, and other factors in restricting
possible changes of structures and functions in evolutionary development (1982:21), providing
architectural constraints that limit adaptive scope and channel evolutionary patterns (Erwin
2003:1683). The best-known of the figures who devoted much of their work to these topics are

4
For comment in a linguistic context, see Boeckx and Hornstein 2003. For more general discussion, see Jenkins
2000.
5
For review of some of these topics, see Stewart 1998.
6 NOAM CHOMSKY

DArcy Thompson and Alan Turing, who took a very strong view on the central role of such
factors in biology. In recent years, such considerations have been adduced for a wide range of
problems of development and evolution, from cell division in bacteria to optimization of structure
and function of cortical networks, even to proposals that organisms have the best of all possible
brains, as argued by computational neuroscientist Christopher Cherniak (1995:522).6 The prob-
lems are at the border of inquiry, but their significance is not controversial.
Assuming that the faculty of language has the general properties of other biological systems,
we should, therefore, be seeking three factors that enter into the growth of language in the indi-
vidual:
1. Genetic endowment, apparently nearly uniform for the species, which interprets part of
the environment as linguistic experience, a nontrivial task that the infant carries out
reflexively, and which determines the general course of the development of the language
faculty. Among the genetic elements, some may impose computational limitations that
disappear in a regular way through genetically timed maturation. Kenneth Wexler and
his associates have provided compelling evidence of their existence in the growth of
language, thus providing empirical evidence for what Wexler (to appear) calls Lenne-
bergs dream.
2. Experience, which leads to variation, within a fairly narrow range, as in the case of other
subsystems of the human capacity and the organism generally.
3. Principles not specific to the faculty of language.
The third factor falls into several subtypes: (a) principles of data analysis that might be used in
language acquisition and other domains; (b) principles of structural architecture and developmental
constraints that enter into canalization, organic form, and action over a wide range, including
principles of efficient computation, which would be expected to be of particular significance for
computational systems such as language. It is the second of these subcategories that should be
of particular significance in determining the nature of attainable languages.
Those exploring these questions 50 years ago assumed that the primitive step of analysis of
linguistic experience would be feature-based phonetic analysis, along lines described by Roman
Jakobson and his associates (see Jakobson, Fant, and Halle 1953). We also tried to show that
basic prosodic properties reflect syntactic structure that is determined by other principles, including
crucially a principle of cyclic computation that was extended much more generally in later years
(see Chomsky, Halle, and Lukoff 1956). The primitive principles must also provide what George
Miller called chunking, identification of phonological words in the string of phonetic units. In
LSLT (p. 165), I adopted Zellig Harriss (1955) proposal, in a different framework, for identifying
morphemes in terms of transitional probabilities, though morphemes do not have the required
beads-on-a-string property. The basic problem, as noted in LSLT, is to show that such statistical

6
See also Laughlin and Sejnowski 2003, Cherniak et al. 2004, and Physics News Update 2001 reporting Howard,
Rutenberg, and de Vet 2001.
THREE FACTORS IN LANGUAGE DESIGN 7

methods of chunking can work with a realistic corpus. That hope turns out to be illusory, as has
recently been shown by Thomas Gambell and Charles Yang (2003), who go on to point out that
the methods do, however, give reasonable results if applied to material that is preanalyzed in
terms of the apparently language-specific principle that each word has a single primary stress. If
so, then the early steps of compiling linguistic experience might be accounted for in terms of
general principles of data analysis applied to representations preanalyzed in terms of principles
specific to the language faculty, the kind of interaction one should expect among the three factors.
In LSLT, it was assumed that the next step would be assignment of chunked items to syntactic
categories, again by general principles of data analysis. A proposal with an information-theoretic
flavor was tried by hand calculations in that precomputer age, with suggestive results, but the
matter has never been pursued, to my knowledge. Surely what are called semantic properties
are also involved, but these involve nontrivial problems at the most elementary level, as mentioned
earlier. The assumption of LSLT was that higher levels of linguistic description, including mor-
phemes, are determined by a general format for rule systems provided by UG, with selection
among them in terms of a computational procedure that seeks the optimal instantiation, a notion
defined in terms of UG principles of significant generalization. Specific proposals were made
then and in the years that followed. In principle, they provided a possible answer to what came
to be called the logical problem of language acquisition, but they involved astronomical calcula-
tion and therefore did not seriously address the issues.
The main concerns in those years were quite different, as they still are. It may be hard to
believe today, but it was commonly assumed 50 years ago that the basic technology of linguistic
description was available and that language variation was so free that nothing of much generality
was likely to be discovered. As soon as efforts were made to provide fairly explicit accounts of
the properties of languages, however, it became obvious how little was known, in any domain.
Every specific proposal yielded a treasure trove of counterevidence, requiring complex and varied
rule-systems even to achieve a very limited approximation to descriptive adequacy. That was
highly stimulating for inquiry into language, but it also left a serious quandary, since the most
elementary considerations led to the conclusion that UG must impose narrow constraints on
possible outcomessometimes called poverty of stimulus problems in the study of language,
though the term is misleading because this is just a special case of basic issues that arise universally
for organic growth.
A number of paths were pursued to try to resolve the tension. The most successful turned
out to be efforts to formulate general principles, attributed to UGthat is, the genetic endow-
mentleaving a somewhat reduced residue of phenomena that would result, somehow, from
experience. Early proposals were the A-over-A Principle, conditions on wh-extraction from wh-
phrases (relatives and interrogatives), simplification of T-markers to base recursion (following
observations by Charles Fillmore) and cyclicity (an intricate matter, as shown in an important
paper of Robert Freidins (1978) and insightfully reviewed in a current paper of Howard Lasniks
(to appear) which shows that many central questions remain unanswered), later John Robert
Rosss (1967) classic study of taxonomy of islands that still remains a rich store of ideas and
observations to explore, then attempts to reduce islands to such properties as locality and structure
8 NOAM CHOMSKY

preservation, and so on. These approaches had some success, but the basic tensions remained
unresolved at the time of the 1974 conference.
Within a few years, the landscape had changed considerably. In part this was because of
great progress in areas that had hitherto been explored only in limited ways, including truth- and
model-theoretic semantics and prosodic structures. In part it was the result of a vast array of new
materials from studies of much greater depth than previously undertaken, and into a much wider
variety of languages, much of it traceable to Richard Kaynes work and his lectures in Europe,
which inspired far-reaching inquiry into Romance and Germanic languages, later other languages,
also leading to many fruitful ideas about the principles of UG. About 25 years ago, much of this
work crystallized in a radically different approach to UG, the Principles-and-Parameters (P&P)
framework, which for the first time offered the hope of overcoming the tension between descriptive
and explanatory adequacy. This approach sought to eliminate the format framework entirely, and
with it, the traditional conception of rules and constructions that had been pretty much taken over
into generative grammar. That much is familiar, as is the fact that the new P&P framework led
to an explosion of inquiry into languages of the most varied typology, yielding new problems
previously not envisioned, sometimes answers, and the reinvigoration of neighboring disciplines
concerned with acquisition and processing, their guiding questions reframed in terms of parameter
setting within a fixed system of principles of UG with at least visible contours. Alternative paths,
variously interrelated, were leading in much the same direction, including Michael Brodys highly
illuminating work (1995, 2003). No one familiar with the field has any illusion today that the
horizons of inquiry are even visible, let alone at hand, in any domain.
Abandonment of the format framework also had a significant impact on the biolinguistic
program. If, as had been assumed, acquisition is a matter of selection among options made available
by the format provided by UG, then the format must be rich and highly articulated, allowing
relatively few options; otherwise, explanatory adequacy is out of reach. The best theory of lan-
guage must be a very unsatisfactory one from other points of view, with a complex array of
conditions specific to human language, restricting possible instantiations. The only plausible
theories had to impose intricate constraints on the permissible relations between sound and mean-
ing, all apparently specific to the faculty of language. The fundamental biological issue of princi-
pled explanation could barely be contemplated, and correspondingly, the prospects for serious
inquiry into evolution of language were dim; evidently, the more varied and intricate the conditions
specific to language, the less hope there is for a reasonable account of the evolutionary origins
of UG. These are among the questions that were raised at the 1974 symposium and others of the
period, but they were left as apparently irresoluble problems.
The P&P framework offered prospects for resolution of these tensions as well. Insofar as
this framework proves valid, acquisition is a matter of parameter setting and is therefore divorced
entirely from the remaining format for grammar: the principles of UG. There is no longer a
conceptual barrier to the hope that the UG might be reduced to a much simpler form, and that
the basic properties of the computational systems of language might have a principled explanation
instead of being stipulated in terms of a highly restrictive language-specific format for grammars.
Within a P&P framework, what had previously been the worst theoryanything goesmight
THREE FACTORS IN LANGUAGE DESIGN 9

be within the realm of conceivability at least, since it is no longer refuted instantly by the fact
that it renders acquisition impossible. Returning to the three factors of language design, adoption
of a P&P framework overcomes a difficult conceptual barrier to shifting the burden of explanation
from the first factor, the genetic endowment, to the third factor, language-independent principles
of data processing, structural architecture, and computational efficiency, thereby providing some
answers to the fundamental questions of biology of language, its nature and use, and perhaps
even its evolution.
As noted by Luigi Rizzi (pers. comm.), whose comments I paraphrase here, abandonment
of the construction-based view of earlier (and traditional) work had further consequences for the
biolinguistic program. In the earlier framework, not only rules but also UG principles were ex-
pressed in terms of grammatical constructions (islands, specified-subject and other constraints
on operations, Emondss structure-preserving hypothesis, filters, etc.), all inherently specific to
language, without even remote counterparts in other biological systems. Within the P&P frame-
work, the basic computational ingredients are considerably more abstract (locality, minimal search,
basic recursion, etc.), and it becomes quite reasonable to seek principled explanation in terms
that may apply well beyond language, as well as related properties in other systems.
As noted, the third factor subsumes two kinds of principles: (a) data processing, and (b)
architectural/computational-developmental constraints. Consider the first category. Within the
general P&P framework, language acquisition is interpreted in terms of parameter setting; an
acquisition theory would seek to set forth the mechanisms used to fix parameter values. That
requires some understanding of what the parameters are, and how they are organized, perhaps
into a hierarchic structure with each choice of value setting limits on subsequent choices. The
most far-reaching approach of this sort that I know of is Mark Bakers (2001). A somewhat
different approach, also within the P&P framework, is suggested by Charles Yang (2002). Devel-
oping suggestions of Thomas Roepers, Yang proposes that UG provides the neonate with the
full array of possible languages, with all parameters valued, and that incoming experience shifts
the probability distribution over languages in accord with a learning function that could be quite
general. At every stage, all languages are in principle accessible, but only for a few are probabilities
high enough so that they can actually be used. He provides interesting empirical evidence in
support of this approach, which carries very early proposals about general data-processing princi-
ples to a new plane of sophistication.
Consider next language-independent principles of structural architecture and computational
efficiency, the subcategory of the third factor in the design of any biological system that might
be expected to be particularly informative about its nature. With the conceptual barriers imposed
by the format framework overcome, we need no longer assume that the means of generating
structured expressions are highly articulated and specific to language. We can seriously entertain
the possibility that they might be reducible to language-independent principles, whether or not
there are homologous elements in other domains and organisms. We can, in short, try to sharpen
the question of what constitutes a principled explanation for properties of language, and turn to
one of the most fundamental questions of the biology of language: to what extent does language
approximate an optimal solution to conditions that it must satisfy to be usable at all, given
10 NOAM CHOMSKY

extralinguistic structural architecture? These conditions take us back to the traditional characteriza-
tion of language, since Aristotle at least, as a system that links sound and meaning. In our terms,
the expressions generated by a language must satisfy two interface conditions: those imposed by
the sensorimotor system SM and by the conceptual-intentional system C-I that enters into the
human intellectual capacity and the variety of speech acts.
Let us put aside the possibility that the linkage to sound is a secondary one, for reasons
mentioned and in the light of recent discoveries on modality-independence of language. We can
regard an explanation of properties of language as principled insofar as it can be reduced to
properties of the interface systems and general considerations of computational efficiency and
the like. Needless to say, these external conditions are only partially understood: we have to
learn about the conditions that set the problem in the course of trying to solve it. The research
task is interactive: to clarify the nature of the interfaces and optimal computational principles
through investigation of how language partially satisfies the conditions they impose, not an un-
familiar feature of rational inquiry. Independently, the interface systems can be studied on their
own, including comparative study that has been productively underway. And the same is true of
principles of efficient computation, applied to language in recent work by many investigators
with important results (see, e.g., Collins 1997, Epstein 1999, Epstein et al. 1998, Frampton and
Gutmann 1999). In a variety of ways, then, it is possible to both clarify and address some of the
basic problems of the biology of language.
It is perhaps worth recalling that the intuition that language is well designed relative to
interface conditions has been a valuable heuristic for many years. The search for some reasonable
notion of simplicity of grammars goes back to the earliest exploration of generative grammar
in the late 1940s. It has also proven very useful over the years to ask whether apparent redundancy
of principles is real, or indicates some error of analysis. A well-known example is passive forms
of exceptional Case-marking constructions, which seemed at one time to be generated by both
raising and passive transformations. Dissatisfaction with such overlapping conditions led to the
realization that the transformations did not exist: rather, just a general rule of movement, which
we can now see to be a virtual conceptual necessity. More recent work suggests that such appar-
ently language-specific conditions as Jean-Roger Vergnauds Case Filter and its descendants may
be reducible to virtual conceptual necessity as well, in this case, interpretability of constructions
at the interface, topics reviewed and elaborated recently by Freidin and Vergnaud (2001). Through-
out, the guiding intuition that redundancy in computational structure is a hint of error has proven
to be productive and often verified, suggesting that something deeper is involved, a topic opened
to more direct investigation as conceptual barriers were removed within the P&P framework.
To proceed further, for concreteness, consider the Extended Standard Theory (EST), now
often called the Y-model, which was modified and improved extensively as it was reconstructed
within the P&P frameworkthough I should perhaps stress again that the minimalist questions
to which I am now turning arise within any theoretical orientation. In the early 1990s, Howard
Lasnik and I published a sketch of our own best understanding of UG in these terms (Chomsky
and Lasnik 1993). Taking that as a point of departure, let us ask to what extent its assumptions
THREE FACTORS IN LANGUAGE DESIGN 11

can be revised or eliminated in favor of principled explanation in terms of interface conditions


and general principles.
The EST/Y-model postulates three internal linguistic levels in addition to the interface levels:
D-Structure, S-Structure, and LF. A linguistic level is postulated to host specific operations. Thus,
D-Structure is the locus of lexical insertion and projection to X-bar constructions; S-Structure is
the point of transfer of the computation to the sound interface, and the transition from overt to
covert operations; LF is the output of overt and covert operations, and the input to the mapping
to the meaning interface. Three internal levels require five operations, each assumed to be cyclic:
the operations forming D-Structures by the cyclic operations of X-bar theory from selected items
from the lexicon; the overt syntactic cycle from D- to S-Structure, the phonological/morphological
cycle mapping S-Structure to the sound interface, the covert syntactic cycle mapping S-Structure
to LF, and formal semantic operations mapping LF compositionally to the meaning interface.
The similarity of the overt and covert cycles was recognized to be problematic as soon as the
framework was developed 35 years ago, but the problem is in fact much broader: there are five
cycles operating in rather similar fashion. One crucial question, then, is whether internal levels,
not forced by interface conditions, can be eliminated, and the five cycles reduced to one. If
possible, that would be a substantial step forward, with many consequences.
One natural property of efficient computation, with a claim to extralinguistic generality, is
that operations forming complex expressions should consist of no more than a rearrangement of
the objects to which they apply, not modifying them internally by deletion or insertion of new
elements. If tenable, that sharply reduces computational load: what has once been constructed
can be forgotten in later computations, in that it will no longer be changed. That is one of the
basic intuitions behind the notion of cyclic computation. The EST/Y-model and other approaches
violate this condition extensively, resorting to bar levels, traces, indices, and other devices, which
both modify given objects and add new elements. A second question, then, is whether all of this
technology is eliminable, and the empirical facts susceptible to principled explanation in accord
with the no-tampering condition of efficient computation.
Other questions arise about the variety of operationsphrase structure, transformations,
reconstruction, and so on; about the crucial reliance on such notions as government that seem to
have no principled motivation; and about many principles that are hard even to formulate except
in terms specific to the language faculty. The general question is, How far can we progress in
showing that all such language-specific technology is reducible to principled explanation, thus
isolating the core properties that are essential to the language faculty, a basic problem of biolinguis-
tics?
An elementary fact about the language faculty is that it is a system of discrete infinity. Any
such system is based on a primitive operation that takes n objects already constructed, and con-
structs from them a new object: in the simplest case, the set of these n objects. Call that operation
Merge. Either Merge or some equivalent is a minimal requirement. With Merge available, we
instantly have an unbounded system of hierarchically structured expressions. The simplest account
of the Great Leap Forward in the evolution of humans would be that the brain was rewired,
12 NOAM CHOMSKY

perhaps by some slight mutation, to provide the operation Merge, at once laying a core part of
the basis for what is found at that dramatic moment of human evolution, at least in principle;
to connect the dots is no trivial problem. There are speculations about the evolution of language
that postulate a far more complex process: first some mutation that permits two-unit expressions
(yielding selectional advantage in overcoming memory restrictions on lexical explosion), then
mutations permitting larger expressions, and finally the Great Leap that yields Merge. Perhaps
the earlier steps really took place, but a more parsimonious speculation is that they did not, and
that the Great Leap was effectively instantaneous, in a single individual, who was instantly en-
dowed with intellectual capacities far superior to those of others, transmitted to offspring and
coming to predominate, perhaps linked as a secondary process to the SM system for externalization
and interaction, including communication as a special case. At best a reasonable guess, as are all
speculations about such matters, but about the simplest one imaginable, and not inconsistent with
anything known or plausibly surmised. In fact, it is hard to see what account of human evolution
would not assume at least this much, in one or another form.7
Similar questions arise about growth of language in the individual. It is commonly assumed
that there is a two-word stage, a three-word stage, and so on, with an ultimate Great Leap Forward
to unbounded generation. That is observed in performance, but it is also observed that at the early
stage the child understands much more complex expressions, and that random modification of
longer oneseven such simple changes as placement of function words in a manner inconsistent
with UG or the adult languageleads to confusion and misinterpretation. It could be that un-
bounded Merge, and whatever else is involved in UG, is present at once, but only manifested in
limited ways for extraneous reasons (memory and attention limitations and the like)matters
discussed at the 1974 symposium and now possible to formulate more explicitly, for example,
in the frameworks developed by Wexler and Yang, already mentioned.8
Suppose, then, that we adopt the simplest assumption: the Great Leap Forward yields Merge.
The fundamental question of biology of language mentioned earlier then becomes, What else is
specific to the faculty of language?
Unless some stipulation is added, there are two subcases of the operation Merge. Given A,
we can merge B to it from outside A or from within A; these are external and internal Merge,
the latter the operation called Move, which therefore also comes free, yielding the familiar
displacement property of language. That property had long been regarded, by me in particular,
as an imperfection of language that has to be somehow explained, but in fact it is a virtual
conceptual necessity;9 some version of transformational grammar seems to be the null hypothesis,

7
For discussion in a broader framework, see Hauser, Chomsky, and Fitch 2002; and for intriguing extensions, see
Piattelli-Palmarini and Uriagereka, to appear.
8
Rizzi (to appear) argues that performance restrictions interact with UG principles: inconsistency with the target
language in early production is grammatically based, with parameters fixed and principles observed, but performance-
driven until the production system matures. The logic is similar to that of Gambell and Yang (2003) and Wexler (to
appear).
9
Options that come free may, of course, not be used, for example, in invented symbolic systems that keep to
external Mergepossibly because they do not have to make use of the edge properties that are typically discourse-related.
THREE FACTORS IN LANGUAGE DESIGN 13

and any other mechanisms, beyond internal Merge, carry a burden of proof. Assuming the no-
tampering condition that minimizes computational load, both kinds of Merge to A will leave A
intact. That entails merging to the edge, the extension condition, which can be understood in
different ways, including the tucking-in theory of Norvin Richards (2001), which is natural
within the probe-goal framework of recent work, and which can also be interpreted to accommo-
date head adjunction.
The no-tampering condition also entails the so-called copy theory of movement, which leaves
unmodified the objects to which it applies, forming an extended object. As movement operations
began to emerge with improvements of the more intricate LSLT framework, it was assumed that
they must compound movement and deletion, because of the general architecture of the system.
In the EST/Y-model architecture, that was unnecessary, but since there did appear to be clear
effects of the position left by Move, it was assumed that the operation leaves a trace, a new object
coindexed with the moved element; thus, the objects subject to the operation are modified, and
new entities are introduced, violating elementary conditions of optimal computation. That was
an errormine in this case. Neither indexing nor the notion of traces is required if we adopt the
simplest assumptions: the copy theory. An important additional gain is that rules of reconstruction
can be eliminated, and the phenomena can be accounted for more effectively, as has been shown
in a great deal of recent work.
Move leaves a copy, perhaps several, all transmitted to the phonological component. If
language is optimized for communicative efficiency, we would expect all to be spelled out: that
would overcome many of the filler-gap problems faced by processing models. If language is
optimized for satisfaction of interface conditions, with minimal computation, then only one will
be spelled out, sharply reducing phonological computation. The latter is the case, one of many
reasons to suspect that speculations of the kind mentioned earlier about language design and
evolution are on the right track. Which one is spelled out? There are several ideas about that.
The most convincing seems to me Jon Nissenbaums (2000), in phase-theoretic terms to which
I will return. At the phase level, two basic operations apply: transfer to the interface, and Merge,
either external or internal. If internal Merge precedes transfer, movement is overt; otherwise, it
is covert. If movement is covert, transfer has already spelled out the lower copy; if overt, the
choice is delayed to the next phase. Zeljko Boskovic (2001) has pointed out that there should be
an exception to such minimal computation if the phonetic interface requires partial spell-out of
a copy, and he has produced interesting examples. To take a different one discovered by Idan
Landau (to appear), VP-fronting in Hebrew sometimes leaves the V behind, namely, when it has
to satisfy what Lasnik called the Stranded Affix Filter, a phonetic condition on affixes.10 If
these are the only exceptions, then syntactic and phonological computation are optimally efficient
in this regard, at least.
The two kinds of Merge appear to correlate closely with interface properties, capturing much
of the dual aspect of semantics that was becoming clearer in the 1960s in work of Ray Jackendoff

10
Landaus formulation is somewhat different.
14 NOAM CHOMSKY

(1969), Peter Culicover (1970), Lyle Jenkins (1972), and others, sometimes expressed in terms
of deep and surface interpretation. External Merge correlates with argument structure, internal
Merge with edge properties, scopal or discourse-related (new and old information, topic, etc.).
The correlation is not perfect, at least on the surface, but close enough to suggest that apparent
violations should fall under broader principles. For external Merge, these go beyond argument
structure associated with substantive categories, and they presumably include functional categories
of the kind coming to light in a variety of inquiries, notably the very fruitful cartography projects
(Cinque 2002, Rizzi 2004, Belletti 2004). Possibly such apparent exceptions as morphological
identification of typical edge properties involve covert Move, also matters studied in current work.
External Merge yields the base structures of the EST/Y-model and earlier proposals.
Since structures are constructed in parallel, there is no locus of lexical insertion. Accordingly,
the notion of D-Structure is not only superfluous, but unformulable, a more far-reaching and
desirable result. If base structures require nothing more than Merge, bar levels can also be elimi-
nated, extending ideas of Naoki Fukui (1986) and Margaret Speas (1986) to full bare phrase
structure. Proceeding further, along lines to which I will briefly return, S-Structure and LF seem
to be unformulable as well, leaving us with just the interface levels, the optimal outcome.
The specifier-complement distinction loses independent significance, except in that the com-
plement of a head H should be the only domain accessible to operations driven by H, by conditions
of minimal search, the core property of c-command, but barring m-command and specifier-head
relations (unless the specifier is a head, hence a possible probe), a strong and controversial
empirical consequence of minimal search. Complement and specifier are just notations for
first-Merge and later-Merge. Banning of multiple specifiers requires stipulation, hence empirical
justification. The empirical evidence seems to me to leave the null hypothesis viable, maybe
supported, though the issue is very much alive.
Each syntactic object generated contains information relevant to further computation. Opti-
mally, that will be captured entirely in a single designated element, which should furthermore be
identifiable with minimal search: its label, the element taken to be projected in X-bar-theoretic
systems. The label, which will invariably be a lexical item introduced by external Merge, should
be the sole probe for operations internal to the syntactic object, and the only element visible for
further computations. We would hope that labels are determined by a natural algorithm, perhaps
even by methods as far-reaching as those that Chris Collins (2002) has proposed in his label-free
analysis. Again, these optimal possibilities are explored extensively in recent work by many
researchers, along different though related paths.
Note that labels, or some counterpart, are the minimum of what is required, on the very
weak assumption that at least some information about a syntactic object is needed for further
computation, both for search within it and for its external role. Labeling underlies a variety of
asymmetries: for example, in a head-XP construction, the label will always be the head, and the
XP a dependency; for substantive heads, an argument with a semantic role that it assigns.
Therefore, such asymmetries need not be specified in the syntactic object itself, and must not be,
because they are redundant. A head-complement structure is a set, not an ordered pair. There are
many similar cases.
THREE FACTORS IN LANGUAGE DESIGN 15

One asymmetry imposed by the phonetic interface is that the syntactic object derived must
be linearized. Optimally, linearization should be restricted to the mapping of the object to the
SM interface, where it is required for language-external reasons. If so, then no order is introduced
in the rest of the syntactic computation: the narrow syntax and the mapping to the C-I interface.
That has been a research objective for the past 25 years at least, ever since Tanya Reinharts
(1979) work on c-command, and it seems at least a plausible conclusion, though the consequences
are quite restrictive and inconsistent with some of the most interesting work: papers by Danny
Fox and Jon Nissenbaum on quantifier raising, antecedent-contained deletion, and late Merge of
adjuncts, to mention some current examples (Fox 2002, Fox and Nissenbaum 1999). But I think
there is reason to suspect that the simplest possibility can be maintained. How syntactic objects
are linearized is also a lively topic. An early proposal is the head parameter, perhaps general,
perhaps category-dependent. A different approach is based on Kaynes Linear Correspondence
Axiom, which has inspired a great deal of productive work, including Kaynes (to appear) discov-
ery of surprising gaps in language typology, and accounts for them. Other ideas are also being
explored. A desideratum, throughout, is that the conclusion introduce few assumptions, optimally
none, that cannot be reduced to the interface requirement and conditions of computational effi-
ciency.
If linear order is restricted to the mapping to the phonetic interface, then it gives no reason
to require the basic operation Merge to depart from the simplest form. As noted, many asymmetries
can be derived from configurations, from properties of lexical items, and from the independently
needed principles of labeling, so need nothence should notbe specified by the elementary
operation that forms the configuration. If that is universal, then the basic operation will be the
simplest possible one: unstructured Merge, forming a set.
There may beI think issome reason to introduce an asymmetrical operation, for adjuncts,
basically serving the function of composition of predicates. The most elementary choice is an
ordered pair, which, at some point, must be simplified to a set for the purposes of linearization.
Simplification optimally should be at the point of Spell-Out, that is, transfer to the two interfaces.
Adopting this assumption, we can derive at least some, maybe all, of the intricate properties of
reconstruction of adjuncts explored by Robert Freidin, Henk van Riemsdijk and Edwin Williams,
David Lebeaux, and others since (Chomsky 2004).
It might be useful to allay some misgivings that appear in the technical literature. With
minimal technical apparatus, a syntactic object X with the label A can be taken to be the set
A, X, where X itself is a set Z, W. If A happens to be one of Z, W, then the set A, X has
the formal properties of an ordered pair, as Norbert Wiener pointed out 90 years ago; that is, it
will have formal properties of the pairs constructed for adjuncts.11 That has been wrongly assumed
to be problematic. It isnt. The possibility of giving a set-theoretic interpretation of ordered pairs,
along Wieners lines, has no bearing on whether ordered pairs are formal objects with their own

11
The standard Wiener-Kuratowski definition of ordered pair is slightly different, Howard Lasnik points out, taking
a, b a, a, b. Wieners original proposal was more complex.
16 NOAM CHOMSKY

properties, primitive objects for mental computation that are distinct from sets, including those
indicating label.
Without further stipulations, external Merge yields n-ary constituents. Particularly since
Kaynes (1981) work on unambiguous paths, it has been generally assumed that these units are
mostly, maybe always, binary. If so, we would like to find a principled explanation. For internal
Merge, it follows from elementary conditions of efficient computation, within the probe-goal
framework, though precisely how this works raises interesting questions, with considerable empiri-
cal bite. For external Merge, one source could be conditions of argument structure imposed at
the C-I interface. Another possibility has been suggested by Luigi Rizzi (pers. comm.), in terms
of minimization of search in working memory.
The most restrictive case of Merge applies to a single object, forming a singleton set. Restric-
tion to this case yields the successor function, from which the rest of the theory of natural numbers
can be developed in familiar ways. That suggests a possible answer to a problem that troubled
Wallace over a century ago: in his words, that the gigantic development of the mathematical
capacity is wholly unexplained by the theory of natural selection, and must be due to some
altogether distinct cause (1889:467), if only because it remained unused. One possibility is that
the natural numbers result from a simple constraint on the language faculty, hence are not given
by God, in accord with Kroneckers famous aphorism, though the rest is created by man, as he
continued. Speculations about the origin of the mathematical capacity as an abstraction from
linguistic operations are not unfamiliar. There are apparent problems, including apparent dissocia-
tion with lesions and diversity of localization, but the significance of such phenomena is unclear
for many reasons (including the issue of possession vs. use of the capacity). There may be
something to these speculations, perhaps along the lines just indicated, which have the appropriate
minimalist flavor.
On very weak assumptions about efficient computation, there should be no linguistic levels
beyond those that are imposed by interface conditions: that is, the interface levels themselves. In
fact, it is not even obvious that these exist. Thus, one can imagine, say, a computational process
that sends parts of generated objects to the SM systems in the course of derivation (say, certain
but not all phonetic properties), not just at its final stage; and the same on the meaning side.
Though such proposals have never been explored, to my knowledge, they could turn out to be
correct. Beyond this, however, we would like to determine whether all internal levels are dispensa-
ble, with the five cycles of the EST/Y-model reduced to onebetter still unformulable, as D-
Structure is. That will follow if computation relies solely on Merge, perhaps pair- as well as set-
Merge, yielding syntactic objects that, at some point in the derivation, are transferred to the two
interfaces: transfer to the sound interface is often called Spell-Out. Let us call the syntactic
objects that are transferred phases. Optimally, once a phase is transferred, it should be mapped
directly to the interface and then forgotten; later operations should not have to refer back to
what has already been mapped to the interfaceagain, a basic intuition behind cyclic operations.
We therefore hope to be able to establish a Phase Impenetrability Condition, which guarantees
that mappings to the two interfaces can forget about what they have already done, a substantial
THREE FACTORS IN LANGUAGE DESIGN 17

saving in memory. Whether that is feasible is a question only recently formulated, and barely
explored. It raises many serious issues, but so far at least, no problems that seem insuperable.
If these general ideas are on the right track, then all internal levels are unformulable, hence
dispensable in the strongest sense. We are left with only the interface levels, and the five cycles
of the EST/Y-model are reduced to a single one, based on Merge. The cyclic properties of the
mappings to the interface follow without comment. Pure cyclic computation is also required for
the simplest account of uninterpretable features. Their values are redundant, determined by an
Agree relation with interpretable features. They should therefore be unvalued in the lexicon, and
when assigned a value, must be treated as what Juan Uriagereka (1998) calls a virus: eliminated
as soon as possible, hence at the phase level, where they are transferred to the phonological
component for possible phonetic realization but eliminated from the syntactic derivation and from
transfer to the semantic interface to avoid crash. That is again an immediate consequence of
phase-based computation.12
The topic of uninterpretable features has moved to center stage since Vergnauds proposals
concerning Case theory 25 years ago, and particularly in the past few years. Vergnauds original
thesis that such elements as structural Case may be present even when not spelled out has received
considerable empirical support. A very strong version of the thesis holds that inflectional features
are in fact universal, ideas developed particularly by Halldor Sigursson (2003) as part of an
extensive analysis of the role of these features, including Case, in speech events, and their fine-
grained syntactic analysis.
Since the copy of a moved element remains, it is in principle accessible for higher syntactic
computations (much as it can be accessed more globally at the meaning interface, under reconstruc-
tion). How deeply is such access allowed? Evidence so far is meager, but as far as I know, it
never goes beyond one phase. We find examples of this, for example, with Icelandic quirky Case:
a phase-internal nominative object can agree with an external inflection. The example is interesting
and merits further inquiry, because it appears to undermine a possible phase-theoretic explanation
for some of Vergnauds account of subjects that cannot appear where Case cannot be assigned,
namely, that they are invisible because they are in the interior of a phase that has already been
passed. In the Icelandic case, the object is not invisible, though the Phase Impenetrability Condi-
tion, which prevents any tampering with an earlier phase, blocks extraction. A different account,
based on a richer variety of linguistic materials and some different assumptions, has been proposed
by Andrew Nevins (2004).
What objects constitute phases? They should be as small as possible, to minimize computa-
tional load. For reasons mentioned earlier, they should at least include the domains in which
uninterpretable features are valued; agreement features apart from nouns and structural Case for
nouns. There is evidence, which I will not review here, that these domains are CP and vP (where
v is small v that introduces full argument structure, transitive, or experiencer verbal structures)
and that these are the only phases in the core clausal structures. Perhaps phases also include DP,

12
See Chomsky 2001a. A consequence is the Earliness Principle of David Pesetsky and Esther Torrego (2001).
18 NOAM CHOMSKY

as is worked out by Peter Svenonius (2003), developing further the parallels between DP and
CP. Keeping to CP and vP, the objects derived have a skeletal structure in which C and v are
the labels driving internal operations and relevant to external Merge, and are also the points of
feature valuation (as is a virtual necessity) and transfer. If so, a number of properties have a
unified account. A possible speculation is that the more elaborate structures revealed by the
cartographic inquiries are based on linearization of features in these labels, and possibly labels
closely linked to them (as in the C-T connection).
The phases have correlates at the interfaces: argument structure or full propositional structure
at the meaning side, relative independence at the sound side. But the correlation is less than
perfect, which raises questions.
This computational architecture, if sustainable, seems to be about as good as possible. S-
Structure and LF are no longer formulable as levels, hence disappear along with D-Structure, and
computations are reduced to a single cycle. It should be that all operations are driven by the
designated element of the phase, the phase head C, v. That should include internal Merge. But
a problem arises, discovered by Julie Legate (2003): there are reconstruction sites at smaller
categories, though movement cannot stop there but must move on to the phase head that drives
the operation. A solution to the conundrum is developed by Cedric Boeckx (2003) in a slightly
different framework, adapting ideas of Daiko Takahashis (1994). In brief, the phase head drives
the Move operation, but it proceeds category by category, in a manner occasionally suggested
for other reasons, until it reaches a point where it must stop. That is usually the phase head,
though there can be an exception, namely, if the phase head assigns its uninterpretable features
to the head it selects. Thus, the phase head C may be the locus of agreement, selecting T and
assigning it (unvalued) -features, so that when raising of DP driven by C-agreement reaches
the TP level, its uninterpretable features are valued and it is frozen, unable to proceed further.
That yields many of the properties of the Extended Projection Principle (EPP) and, if generalized,
also yields interesting empirical consequences that would carry us too far afield. But partial
movement is impossible phase-internally in other cases; in particular, we can overcome the annoy-
ing lack of structures of the form *There seems a man to be in the room, without the apparatus
that has been proposed to account for the gap, which generalizes to the specifier of participial
phrases and other such constructions. In a somewhat different framework, Jan Koster (2003) has
developed the interesting idea that V-movement to T is partial movement to C, the true locus
of Tense, analogous to the partial wh-movement in German discussed by Henk van Riemsdijk
(1983) and Dana McDaniel (1989).
Internal Merge seems to be driven in part at least by uninterpretable features of the phase
head, as a reflex of probe-goal matching. Insofar as that is true, it carries us part of the way
toward a principled explanation for why languages should have uninterpretable features at all.
But it is not clear how far. For example, there is considerable evidence for successive-cyclic
movement through phase edges, but for A -movement it is unclear whether there is independent
motivation for the features that would be required to formulate the operations within this frame-
work. It may be that phase heads have an edge feature, sometimes called an EPP-feature (by
extension of the notion EPP) or an occurrence feature OCC (because the object formed is an
THREE FACTORS IN LANGUAGE DESIGN 19

occurrence of the moved element in the technical sense). This edge feature permits raising to the
phase edge without feature matching. Similar questions arise for A-movement, particularly in
languages where EPP is satisfied by a nonnominative element, as in locative inversion, which
may agree with T, as in Bantu, though not in English, though there is reason to doubt that locative
inversion involves A-movement to subject in English. Mark Baker (2003) suggests a parameter
distinguishing Bantu from Indo-European in this respect, with interesting empirical consequences,
and it is possible that his conclusions extend to apparent attraction to T by a D-feature in Slavic
and Japanese-type languages, along lines developed by James E. Lavine and Robert Freidin (2002)
and by Shigeru Miyagawa (2004). It seems possible that the variety of cases might fall under a
probe-goal framework with T parameterized somewhat along the lines that Baker suggests, but
keeping to -feature probe-goal matching with or without the requirement that the goal be active,
that is, with unvalued Case; or, along lines that Miyagawa develops extensively, with Focus
playing the role of agreement in some class of languages. If the phase heads have both agreement
features (or Focus features) and edge features, then we would expect both to apply simultaneously.
That assumption directly yields some curious phenomena about intervention effects discussed by
Ken Hiraiwa (2002) and by Anders Holmberg and Thorbjorg Hroarsdottir (2003), and also an
account of some apparent exceptions to the Subject Island Condition. We move here well into
the terrain of open problemsa vast terrain.
I have barely touched on the rich range of inquiries with these general motivations in the
past few years, and now in progress. One broad-ranging summary, with many new ideas and new
empirical materials, is Cedric Boeckxs recent book Islands and Chains (2003). It seems reason-
ably clear that there has been considerable progress in moving toward principled explanation that
addresses fundamental questions of the biology of language. It is even more clear that these efforts
have met one primary requirement for a sensible research program: stimulating inquiry that has
been able to overcome some old problems while even more rapidly bringing to light new ones,
previously unrecognized and scarcely even formulable, and enriching greatly the empirical chal-
lenges of descriptive and explanatory adequacy that have to be faced.

References
Antony, Louise M., and Norbert Hornstein, eds. 2003. Chomsky and his critics. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell.
Baker, Mark. 2001. The atoms of language. New York: Basic Books.
Baker, Mark. 2003. Agreement, dislocation, and partial configurationality. In Formal approaches to function
in grammar, ed. by Andrew Carnie, Heidi Harley, and MaryAnn Willie, 107132. Amsterdam: John
Benjamins.
Belletti, Adriana, ed. 2004. The cartography of syntactic structures. Vol. 3, Structures and beyond. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Boeckx, Cedric. 2003. Islands and chains: Resumption as stranding. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Boeckx, Cedric, and Norbert Hornstein. 2003. The varying aims of linguistic theory. Ms., University of
Maryland, College Park.
Borer, Hagit. 2004a. Structuring sense. Vol. 1, In name only. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Borer, Hagit. 2004b. Structuring sense. Vol. 2, The normal course of events. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
20 NOAM CHOMSKY

Boskovic, Zeljko. 2001. On the nature of the syntax-phonology interface. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Brody, Michael. 1995. Lexico-Logical Form: A radically minimalist theory. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Brody, Michael. 2003. Towards an elegant syntax. London: Routledge.
Cherniak, Christopher. 1995. Neural component placement. Trends in Neuroscience 18:522527.
Cherniak, Christopher, Zekeria Mokhtarzada, Raul Rodriguez-Esteban, and Kelly Changizi. 2004. Global
optimization of cerebral cortex layout. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science online, 13
January 2004 (print version 27 January 2004, 101(4):10811086).
Chomsky, Noam. 1955. Logical structure of linguistic theory (LSLT). Ms. Parts of 1956 revision published
in New York: Plenum, 1975, and Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985.
Chomsky, Noam. 1966. Cartesian linguistics. New York: Harper & Row.
Chomsky, Noam. 2001a. Derivation by phase. In Ken Hale: A life in language, ed. by Michael Kenstowicz,
152. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam. 2001b. New horizons in the study of language and mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Chomsky, Noam. 2004. Beyond explanatory adequacy. In The cartography of syntactic structures. Vol. 3,
Structures and beyond, ed. by Adriana Belletti. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chomsky, Noam, Morris Halle, and Fred Lukoff. 1956. On accent and juncture in English. In For Roman
Jakobson, compiled by Morris Halle and others, 6580. The Hague: Mouton.
Chomsky, Noam, and Howard Lasnik. 1993. The theory of principles and parameters. In Syntax: An interna-
tional handbook of contemporary research, ed. by Joachim Jacobs, Arnim von Stechow, Wolfgang
Sternefeld, and Theo Vennemann, 506569. Berlin: de Gruyter. Reprinted in Noam Chomsky, The
Minimalist Program, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995.
Cinque, Guglielmo, ed. 2002. The cartography of syntactic structures. Vol. 1, Functional structure in DP
and IP. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Collins, Chris. 1997. Local economy. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Collins, Chris. 2002. Eliminating labels. In Derivation and explanation in the Minimalist Program, ed. by
Samuel David Epstein and T. Daniel Seely, 4264. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell.
Culicover, Peter. 1970. Syntactic and semantic investigation. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.
Epstein, Samuel David. 1999. Un-principled syntax: The derivation of syntactic relations. In Working mini-
malism, ed. by Samuel David Epstein and Norbert Hornstein, 317345. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
Epstein, Samuel David, Erich M. Groat, Ruriko Kawashima, and Hisatsugu Kitahara. 1998. A derivational
approach to syntactic relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Erwin, Douglas. 2003. The Goldilocks hypothesis. Science 302 (5 December 2003):16821683.
Fodor, Jerry. 1975. Language of thought. New York: Crowell.
Fox, Danny. 2002. Antecedent-contained deletion and the copy theory of movement. Linguistic Inquiry 33:
6396.
Fox, Danny, and Jon Nissenbaum. 1999. Extraposition and scope: A case for overt QR. In Proceedings of
the 18th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. by Sonya Bird, Andrew Carnie, Jason
D. Haugen, and Peter Norquest, 132144. Somerville, Mass.: Cascadilla Press.
Frampton, John, and Sam Gutmann. 1999. Cyclic computation, a computationally efficient minimalist syntax.
Syntax 2:127.
Freidin, Robert. 1978. Cyclicity and the theory of grammar. Linguistic Inquiry 9:519549.
Freidin, Robert, and Jean-Roger Vergnaud. 2001. Exquisite connections: Some remarks on the evolution of
linguistic theory. Lingua 111:639666.
Fukui, Naoki. 1986. A theory of category projection and its applications. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cam-
bridge, Mass. Revised version published as Theory of projection in syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, and Stanford, Calif.: CSLI Publications, 1995.
THREE FACTORS IN LANGUAGE DESIGN 21

Gallistel, C. R. 1997. Neurons and memory. In Conversations in the cognitive neurosciences, ed. by Michael
S. Gazzaniga. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Gallistel, C. R. 1999. The replacement of general-purpose learning models with adaptively specialized
learning modules. In The cognitive neurosciences, ed. by Michael S. Gazzaniga. 2nd ed. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
Gambell, Thomas, and Charles Yang. 2003. Scope and limits of statistical learning in word segmentation.
Ms., Yale University, New Haven, Conn.
Harris, Zellig S. 1955. From phoneme to morpheme. Language 31:190222.
Hauser, Marc D., Noam Chomsky, and W. Tecumseh Fitch. 2002. The faculty of language. Science 198:
15691579.
Hiraiwa, Ken. 2002. Multiple Agree. Paper presented at the 25th GLOW Colloquium, Utrecht.
Hoffman, Donald. 1998. Visual intelligence. New York: Norton.
Holmberg, Anders, and Thorbjorg Hroarsdottir. 2003. Agreement and movement in Icelandic raising con-
structions. Lingua 113:9971019.
Jackendoff, Ray. 1969. Some rules of semantic interpretation in English. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cam-
bridge, Mass.
Jacob, Francois. 1982. The possible and the actual. New York: Pantheon.
Jakobson, Roman, Gunnar Fant, and Morris Halle. 1953. Preliminaries to speech analysis. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
Jenkins, Lyle. 1972. Modality in English syntax. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.
Jenkins, Lyle. 2000. Biolinguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kauffman, Stuart. 1993. The origins of order. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kayne, Richard. 1981. Unambiguous paths. In Levels of syntactic representation, ed. by Robert May and
Jan Koster, 143183. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Kayne, Richard. To appear. Anti-symmetry in Japanese. In Variation and universals in biolinguistics, ed.
by Lyle Jenkins.
Koster, Jan. 2003. All languages are tense second. Ms., University of Groningen.
Landau, Idan. To appear. Chain resolution in Hebrew V(P) fronting. Syntax.
Lasnik, Howard. To appear. Conceptions of the cycle. In Wh-movement on the move, ed. by Lisa Lai-Shen
Cheng and Norbert Corver. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Laughlin, Simon, and Terrence J. Sejnowski. 2003. Communication in neuronal networks. Science 301 (26
September 2003): 18701874.
Lavine, James E., and Robert Freidin. 2002. The subject of defective T(ense) in Slavic. Journal of Slavic
Linguistics 10:251287.
Legate, Julie Anne. 2003. Some interface properties of the phase. Linguistic Inquiry 34:506516.
Lenneberg, Eric. 1967. Biological foundations of language. New York: Wiley.
Luria, Salvador. 1974. Transcript of remarks at A Debate on Bio-Linguistics, a conference organized by
the Centre Royaumont pour une science de lhomme, Paris, held at Endicott House, Dedham, Mass.,
2021 May 1974.
Marshack, Alexander. 1985. Hierarchical evolution of the human capacity. New York: American Museum
of Natural History.
Maynard Smith, J., R. Burian, S. Kauffman, P. Alberch, J. Campbell, B. Goodwin, R. Lande, D. Raup,
and L. Wolpert. 1985. Developmental constraints and evolution. Quarterly Review of Biology 60:
265287.
McDaniel, Dana. 1989. Partial and multiple wh-movement. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 7:
565604.
McGilvray, James. 1999. Chomsky: Language, mind, and politics. Cambridge: Polity.
Miyagawa, Shigeru. 2004. On the EPP. In Proceedings of the EPP/Phase Workshop, ed. by Martha McGinnis
22 NOAM CHOMSKY

and Norvin Richards. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, Department of
Linguistics and Philosophy, MITWPL.
Nevins, Andrew. 2004. Derivations without the Activity Condition. In Proceedings of the EPP/Phase Work-
shop, ed. by Martha McGinnis and Norvin Richards. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT, Department of Linguistics and Philosophy, MITWPL.
Nissenbaum, Jon. 2000. Investigations of covert phrase movement. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge,
Mass.
Pesetsky, David, and Esther Torrego. 2001. T-to-C movement: Causes and consequences. In Ken Hale: A
life in language, ed. by Michael Kenstowicz, 355426. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Physics News Update. 2001. American Institute of Physics Bulletin of Physics, News Number 570, December
21, 2001, reporting study by M. Howard, A. D. Rutenberg, and S. de Vet, Physical Review Letters,
31 December 2001.
Piattelli-Palmarini, Massimo, and Juan Uriagereka. To appear. In Variation and universals in biolinguistics,
ed. by Lyle Jenkins.
Reinhart, Tanya. 1979. Syntactic domains for semantic rules. In Formal semantics and pragmatics for
natural language, ed. by Franz Guenthner and Siegfried J. Schmidt, 107130. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Richards, Norvin. 2001. Movement in language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Riemsdijk, Henk van. 1983. Correspondence effects and the Empty Category Principle. In Studies in genera-
tive grammar and language acquisition, ed. by Y. Otsu et al., 516. Tokyo: International Christian
University.
Rizzi, Luigi, ed. 2004. The cartography of syntactic structures. Vol. 2, The structure of CP and IP. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Rizzi, Luigi. To appear. On the grammatical basis of language development. In Handbook of comparative
syntax, ed. by Guglielmo Cinque and Richard Kayne. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ross, John Robert. 1967. Constraints on variables in syntax. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.
Published as Infinite syntax!. Norwood, N.J.: Ablex, 1986.
Sigursson, Halldor. 2003. Meaningful silence, meaningless sounds. Ms., Lund University.
Speas, Margaret. 1986. Adjunctions and projections in syntax. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, Mass.
Stewart, Ian. 1998. Lifes other secret. New York: Wiley.
Svenonius, Peter. 2003. On the edge. Ms., University of Troms.
Takahashi, Daiko. 1994. Minimality of movement. Doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut, Storrs.
Tattersall, Ian. 1998. The origin of the human capacity. New York: American Museum of Natural History.
Uriagereka, Juan. 1998. Rhyme and reason. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Waddington, C. H. 1942. Canalization of development and the inheritance of acquired characters. Nature
150:563565.
Wallace, Alfred Russel. 1889. Darwinism. London: Macmillan.
Wells, Spencer. 2002. The journey of man: A genetic odyssey. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Wexler, Kenneth. To appear. Lennebergs dream: Learning, normal language development and specific
language impairment. In Variation and universals in biolinguistics, ed. by Lyle Jenkins.
Yang, Charles. 2002. Knowledge and learning in natural language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Department of Linguistics and Philosophy


32-D840
MIT
Cambridge, Massachusetts 02139
chomsky@mit.edu
This article has been cited by:

1. John Zerilli. 2017. Against the system module. Philosophical Psychology 1-16. [CrossRef]
2. David Adger. 2017. Restrictiveness matters. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review . [CrossRef]
3. Charles Yang, Silvina Montrul. 2017. Learning datives: The Tolerance Principle in monolingual
and bilingual acquisition. Second Language Research 33:1, 119-144. [CrossRef]
4. Kaori Takamine 240, . [CrossRef]
5. Simona Mancini, Ileana Quiones, Nicola Molinaro, Juan A. Hernandez-Cabrera, Manuel
Carreiras. 2017. Disentangling meaning in the brain: Left temporalinvolvement in agreement
processing. Cortex 86, 140-155. [CrossRef]
6. Padraic Monaghan. 2017. Canalization of Language Structure From Environmental Constraints:
A Computational Model of Word Learning From Multiple Cues. Topics in Cognitive Science 9:1,
21-34. [CrossRef]
7. Charles Yang, Stephen Crain, Robert C. Berwick, Noam Chomsky, Johan J. Bolhuis. 2017. The
growth of language: Universal Grammar, experience, and principles of computation. Neuroscience
& Biobehavioral Reviews . [CrossRef]
8. GEOFFREY SAMPSON. 2016. Rigid strings and flaky snowflakes. Language and Cognition 8:04,
587-603. [CrossRef]
9. Kari Kinn. 2016. Referential vs. non-referential null subjects in Middle Norwegian. Nordic
Journal of Linguistics 39:03, 277-310. [CrossRef]
10. Padraic Monaghan, Caroline F. Rowland. 2016. Combining Language Corpora With
Experimental and Computational Approaches for Language Acquisition Research. Language
Learning . [CrossRef]
11. Ermenegildo Bidese, Federica Cognola, Manuela Caterina MoroniIntroduction 1-22. [CrossRef]
12. Anna Maria Di SciulloBiolinguistic investigations on the Language Faculty vii-xviii. [CrossRef]
13. Anna Maria Di Sciullo, Calixto Aguero-BautistaThe biolinguistics program 3-40. [CrossRef]
14. Ljiljana Progovac. 2016. A Gradualist Scenario for Language Evolution: Precise Linguistic
Reconstruction of Early Human (and Neandertal) Grammars. Frontiers in Psychology 7. .
[CrossRef]
15. AMY ROSE DEAL. 2016. Person-based split ergativity in Nez Perce is syntactic. Journal of
Linguistics 52:03, 533-564. [CrossRef]
16. Laura Domnguez, Glyn HicksSynchronic change in a multidialectal Spanish community 53-72.
[CrossRef]
17. Reinhard Blutner, Peter beim Graben. 2016. Quantum cognition and bounded rationality.
Synthese 193:10, 3239-3291. [CrossRef]
18. M. Rita Manzini, Leonardo M. Savoia. 2016. Enclisis/Proclisis Alternations in Romance:
Allomorphies and (Re)Ordering. Transactions of the Philological Society . [CrossRef]
19. Yen-Hui Audrey LiFacilitating language learning 33-58. [CrossRef]
20. J. Carlos Acua-Faria. 2016. Opportunistic processing of language. Language Sciences 57, 34-48.
[CrossRef]
21. Carlos Gelormini-Lezama, David Huepe, Eduar Herrera, Margherita Melloni, Facundo Manes,
Adolfo M. Garca, Agustn Ibez. 2016. The Overt Pronoun Constraint Across Three Dialects
of Spanish. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 45:4, 979-1000. [CrossRef]
22. Abdulkhaliq Alazzawie. 2016. An agree-based account of Standard Arabic nominal clauses.
Ampersand . [CrossRef]
23. Shir Hofstetter, Naama Friedmann, Yaniv Assaf. 2016. Rapid language-related plasticity:
microstructural changes in the cortex after a short session of new word learning. Brain Structure
and Function . [CrossRef]
24. Cedric Boeckx. 2016. The language-ready head: Evolutionary considerations. Psychonomic
Bulletin & Review . [CrossRef]
25. Maggie Tallerman. 2016. Can the integration hypothesis account for language evolution?. Journal
of Neurolinguistics . [CrossRef]
26. Haojie Li. 2016. On College English Teaching in China from the Perspective of MP in Generative
Grammar Theory. Journal of Language Teaching and Research 7:4, 724. [CrossRef]
27. Edison Barrios. 2016. Simple is not easy. Synthese 193:7, 2261-2305. [CrossRef]
28. Koji Fujita. 2016. On the parallel evolution of syntax and lexicon: A Merge-only view. Journal
of Neurolinguistics . [CrossRef]
29. Ivn Ortega-SantosFocus-related Operations at the Right Edge in Spanish 7, . [CrossRef]
30. Jinghua Zhang. 2016. Cross-linguistic Variations of pro Licensing Conditions. Journal of
Language Teaching and Research 7:3, 499. [CrossRef]
31. Bill Thompson, Simon Kirby, Kenny Smith. 2016. Culture shapes the evolution of cognition.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 113:16, 4530-4535. [CrossRef]
32. . 2016. Agreement Phenomena in Agreement-less Languages. Studies in Linguistics null:39,
315-335. [CrossRef]
33. Chris Collins, Edward Stabler. 2016. A Formalization of Minimalist Syntax. Syntax 19:1, 43-78.
[CrossRef]
34. Mario SaltarelliMarsican deixis and the nature of indexical syntax 399-413. [CrossRef]
35. Jennifer Culbertson, Simon Kirby. 2016. Simplicity and Specificity in Language: Domain-
General Biases Have Domain-Specific Effects. Frontiers in Psychology 6. . [CrossRef]
36. Devereaux Kennedy. 2016. Games People Play: Strategy and Structure in Social Life. Social
Epistemology 30:1, 67-88. [CrossRef]
37. John A. Hawkins. 2016. The emergence of grammar in a language-ready brain. Physics of Life
Reviews . [CrossRef]
38. Cem BozahinNatural Recursion Doesnt Work That Way: Automata in Planning and Syntax
95-112. [CrossRef]
39. Antonino Pennisi, Alessandra FalzoneIntroduction 1-4. [CrossRef]
40. Antonino Pennisi, Alessandra FalzoneChomsky and Biolinguistics 7-13. [CrossRef]
41. Antonino Pennisi, Alessandra FalzoneThe Last Chomsky and the Evolutionary Perspective
15-29. [CrossRef]
42. Sam Wolfe. 2016. A comparative perspective on the evolution of Romance clausal structure.
Diachronica 33:4, 461-502. [CrossRef]
43. Alessandro G. Benati, Benedetta BasileTheoretical and Pedagogical Views on the Role of
Grammar Instruction 7-38. [CrossRef]
44. Lorenzo Vitral. 2016. Lmergence de la biolinguistique et ses consquences pour la thorie
linguistique. Histoire Epistmologie Langage 38:2, 117-136. [CrossRef]
45. Brian Hok-Shing Chan. 2015. Portmanteau Constructions, Phrase Structure, and Linearization.
Frontiers in Psychology 6. . [CrossRef]
46. Anke Assmann, Doreen Georgi, Fabian Heck, Gereon Mller, Philipp Weisser. 2015. Ergatives
Move Too Early: On an Instance of Opacity in Syntax. Syntax 18:4, 343-387. [CrossRef]
47. Martin B.H. Everaert, Marinus A.C. Huybregts, Noam Chomsky, Robert C. Berwick, Johan J.
Bolhuis. 2015. Structures, Not Strings: Linguistics as Part of the Cognitive Sciences. Trends in
Cognitive Sciences 19:12, 729-743. [CrossRef]
48. , Sungshim Hong. 2015. Remarks on English Non-Restrictive Relative Clauses. Korean
Journal of English Language and Linguistics 15:4, 639-662. [CrossRef]
49. Maria Kambanaros, Kleanthes K. Grohmann. 2015. Grammatical Class Effects Across Impaired
Child and Adult Populations. Frontiers in Psychology 6. . [CrossRef]
50. Roberta DAlessandro, Tobias Scheer. 2015. Modular PIC. Linguistic Inquiry 46:4, 593-624.
[Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF] [PDF Plus]
51. Simon Fitzpatrick. 2015. Nativism, Empiricism, and Ockhams Razor. Erkenntnis 80:5, 895-922.
[CrossRef]
52. Melanie Green, Chris H. Reintges. 2015. Syntactic conditions on special inflection: Evidence
from Hausa and Coptic Egyptian. Lingua 166, 127-154. [CrossRef]
53. Yadgar Karimi. 2015. Remarks on Ergativity and Phase Theory. Studia Linguistica n/a-n/a.
[CrossRef]
54. Andreas TrotzkeRethinking Syntactocentrism 225, . [CrossRef]
55. Denis Bouchard. 2015. Brain readiness and the nature of language. Frontiers in Psychology 6. .
[CrossRef]
56. Malin Hager, Natascha Mller. 2015. Ultimate attainment in bilingual first language acquisition.
Lingua 164, 289-308. [CrossRef]
57. Pedro Guijarro-Fuentes, Katrin Schmitz. 2015. The nature and nurture of heritage language
acquisition. Lingua 164, 239-250. [CrossRef]
58. Alexandra BeytenbratCase in Russian 70, . [CrossRef]
59. Chris Collins, Andrew Radford. 2015. Gaps, ghosts and gapless relatives in spoken English.
Studia Linguistica 69:2, 191-235. [CrossRef]
60. Werner Abraham. 2015. Strong modality and truth disposability in syntactic subordination: What
is the locus of the phase edge validating modal adverbials?. Studia Linguistica 69:2, 119-159.
[CrossRef]
61. Bridget D. Samuels. 2015. Can a bird brain do phonology?. Frontiers in Psychology 6. . [CrossRef]
62. Adriana Belletti, Maria Teresa GuastiThe Acquisition of Italian 57, . [CrossRef]
63. Victoria Eugenia Mateu. 2015. Object Clitic Omission in Child Spanish: Evaluating
Representational and Processing Accounts. Language Acquisition 22:3, 240-284. [CrossRef]
64. Christina Behme, Vyvyan Evans. 2015. Leaving the myth behind: A reply to Adger (2015).
Lingua 162, 149-159. [CrossRef]
65. . 2015. On Desirable Research Methods in Generative Linguistics. Studies in Linguistics
null:36, 215-244. [CrossRef]
66. Elliot Murphy. 2015. Labels, cognomes, and cyclic computation: an ethological perspective.
Frontiers in Psychology 6. . [CrossRef]
67. Doo-Won Lee. 2015. English Counterparts of Causative Verb Cwu and Benefactive Suffix Verb
(a/e) Cwu Constructions. The Jungang Journal of English Language and Literature 57:2, 267-291.
[CrossRef]
68. Csaba Plh, Ottilia BorossDarwinism as a Decryption Key for the Human Mind 1-16. [CrossRef]
69. Andrew Radford, Eiichi Iwasaki. 2015. On Swiping in English. Natural Language & Linguistic
Theory 33:2, 703-744. [CrossRef]
70. David Embick, David Poeppel. 2015. Towards a computational(ist) neurobiology of language:
correlational , integrated and explanatory neurolinguistics. Language, Cognition and Neuroscience
30:4, 357-366. [CrossRef]
71. Abdul-Hafeed Ali Fakih. 2015. Wh-questions in Hodeidi Arabic: A Phase-based Approach.
Theory and Practice in Language Studies 5:4, 773. [CrossRef]
72. Kent Johnson. 2015. Notational Variants and Invariance in Linguistics. Mind & Language 30:2,
162-186. [CrossRef]
73. Doo-Won Lee. 2015. Causative Cwu-Constructions Revisited. Studies in Linguistics null:35,
227-246. [CrossRef]
74. Vitor A. Nbrega, Shigeru Miyagawa. 2015. The precedence of syntax in the rapid emergence
of human language in evolution as defined by the integration hypothesis. Frontiers in Psychology
6. . [CrossRef]
75. Miki Obata, Samuel Epstein, Marlyse Baptista. 2015. Can crosslinguistically variant grammars
be formally identical? Third factor underspecification and the possible elimination of parameters
of UG. Lingua 156, 1-16. [CrossRef]
76. Bradley Larson. 2015. Minimal search as a restriction on Merge. Lingua 156, 57-69. [CrossRef]
77. Cecile De Cat, Ekaterini Klepousniotou, R. Harald Baayen. 2015. Representational deficit or
processing effect? An electrophysiological study of noun-noun compound processing by very
advanced L2 speakers of English. Frontiers in Psychology 6. . [CrossRef]
78. Brian Agbayani, Chris Golston, Toru Ishii. 2015. Syntactic and prosodic scrambling in Japanese.
Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 33:1, 47-77. [CrossRef]
79. Mara C. Parafita Couto, Virginia C. Mueller Gathercole, Hans Stadthagen-Gonzlez. 2015.
Interface strategies in monolingual and end-state L2 Spanish grammars are not that different.
Frontiers in Psychology 5. . [CrossRef]
80. JohnA. HawkinsTypological Variation and Efficient Processing 215-236. [CrossRef]
81. William O'GradyAnaphora and the Case for Emergentism 100-122. [CrossRef]
82. Elisa Di Domenico, Cornelia Hamann, Simona MatteiniIntroduction xi-xxvi. [CrossRef]
83. Patrick C. Trettenbrein. 2015. The grammar in Universal Grammar: A biolinguistic
clarification. Questions and Answers in Linguistics 2:1, 1-10. [CrossRef]
84. Martin DaviesKnowledge (Explicit, Implicit and Tacit): Philosophical Aspects 74-90. [CrossRef]
85. Manfred BierwischGenerative Grammar 871-878. [CrossRef]
86. Hiroki NaritaEndocentric Structuring of Projection-free Syntax 218, . [CrossRef]
87. 2014. Developments in the acquisition of Wh-interrogatives in Cypriot Greek. Linguistic
Variation 14:1, 69-108. [CrossRef]
88. 2014. Linguistic variation and micro-cues in first language acquisition. Linguistic Variation 14:1,
26-45. [CrossRef]
89. 2014. Introducing socio-syntax and language acquisition. Linguistic Variation 14:1, vii-xii.
[CrossRef]
90. 2014. Specific language impairment in Cypriot Greek: Diagnostic issues. Linguistic Variation
13:2, 217-236. [CrossRef]
91. 2014. Introducing language development and impairment. Linguistic Variation 13:2, vii-xii.
[CrossRef]
92. R. Slabakova, T. L. Leal, J. Liskin-Gasparro. 2014. We Have Moved On: Current Concepts and
Positions in Generative SLA. Applied Linguistics 35:5, 601-606. [CrossRef]
93. Magdalena Sztencel. 2014. Conditionality in individual minds: An argument for a wholly
pragmatic approach to utterance interpretation. Lingua 152, 81-97. [CrossRef]
94. Cedric Boeckx, Evelina Leivada. 2014. On the particulars of Universal Grammar: implications
for acquisition. Language Sciences 46, 189-198. [CrossRef]
95. Elizabeth Ritter, Martina Wiltschko. 2014. The composition of INFL. Natural Language &
Linguistic Theory 32:4, 1331-1386. [CrossRef]
96. Antonio Fbregas, ngel J. Gallego. 2014. Morphological variation in Spanish. Lingua 151,
97-119. [CrossRef]
97. Gillian Ramchand, Peter Svenonius. 2014. Deriving the functional hierarchy. Language Sciences
46, 152-174. [CrossRef]
98. Maggie Tallerman. 2014. No syntax saltation in language evolution. Language Sciences 46,
207-219. [CrossRef]
99. Javier Gutirrez-Rexach, Sandro Sessarego. 2014. Morphosyntactic variation and gender
agreement in three Afro-Andean dialects. Lingua 151, 142-161. [CrossRef]
100. Jim Wood, Halldr rmann Sigursson. 2014. Let Causatives and (A)symmetric dat-nom
Constructions. Syntax 17:3, 269-298. [CrossRef]
101. James Griffiths, Anik Liptk. 2014. Contrast and Island Sensitivity in Clausal Ellipsis. Syntax
17:3, 189-234. [CrossRef]
102. . 2014. Jakobsons Translation Typology Revisited: Situated Cognition and Its Translative
Nature. The Journal of Translation Studies 15:3, 331-375. [CrossRef]
103. Christopher S. Butler, Francisco Gonzlvez-GarcaExploring Functional-Cognitive Space 157, .
[CrossRef]
104. Louise Barrett, Thomas V. Pollet, Gert Stulp. 2014. From computers to cultivation:
reconceptualizing evolutionary psychology. Frontiers in Psychology 5. . [CrossRef]
105. Ianthi Maria Tsimpli. 2014. Early, late or very late?. Linguistic Approaches to Bilingualism 4:3,
283-313. [CrossRef]
106. Samuel David Epstein, Hisatsugu Kitahara, T. Daniel Seely. 2014. Labeling by Minimal Search:
Implications for Successive- Cyclic A-Movement and the Conception of the Postulate Phase.
Linguistic Inquiry 45:3, 463-481. [Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF] [PDF Plus]
107. Kent Johnson. 2014. Methodology in generative linguistics: scratching below the surface.
Language Sciences 44, 47-59. [CrossRef]
108. Laurent Dekydtspotter, Claire Renaud. 2014. On second language processing and grammatical
development. Linguistic Approaches to Bilingualism 4:2, 131-165. [CrossRef]
109. Doo-Won Lee. 2014. A Feature-based Approach for Addressee Honorification. The Jungang
Journal of English Language and Literature 56:2, 205-229. [CrossRef]
110. Ana Maria Martins. 2014. How much syntax is there in metalinguistic negation?. Natural
Language & Linguistic Theory 32:2, 635-672. [CrossRef]
111. Robert Truswell. 2014. Book review. Lingua 143, 52-55. [CrossRef]
112. J. Carlos Acua-Faria, Enrique Meseguer, Manuel Carreiras. 2014. Gender and number
agreement in comprehension in Spanish. Lingua 143, 108-128. [CrossRef]
113. Jae-Young Shim. 2014. Phase-head Initiated Structure Building: Its Implications for Feature-
Inheritance, Transfer and Internal Merge. Studies in Generative Grammar 24:2, 455-474.
[CrossRef]
114. D. M. Gomez, I. Berent, S. Benavides-Varela, R. A. H. Bion, L. Cattarossi, M. Nespor, J.
Mehler. 2014. Language universals at birth. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 111:16,
5837-5841. [CrossRef]
115. Thomas J. Hughes, J. T. M. Miller. 2014. Lexicalisation and the Origin of the Human Mind.
Biosemiotics 7:1, 11-27. [CrossRef]
116. Richard L. Lewis, Andrew Howes, Satinder Singh. 2014. Computational Rationality: Linking
Mechanism and Behavior Through Bounded Utility Maximization. Topics in Cognitive Science
6:2, 279-311. [CrossRef]
117. Gereon Mller. 2014. A local approach to the Williams Cycle. Lingua 140, 117-136. [CrossRef]
118. Juan UriagerekaRegarding the Third Factor 363-391. [CrossRef]
119. Norbert Hornstein, William IdsardiA program for the Minimalist Program 9-34. [CrossRef]
120. Hedde ZeijlstraOn the uninterpretability of interpretable features 109-128. [CrossRef]
121. Laurice Tuller, Hlne Delage. 2014. Mild-to-moderate hearing loss and language impairment:
How are they linked?. Lingua 139, 80-101. [CrossRef]
122. Violeta Demonte, Olga Fernndez-SorianoChapter 8. Evidentiality and illocutionary force
217-252. [CrossRef]
123. Hamid OualiMultiple agreement in Arabic 121-134. [CrossRef]
124. Tobias ScheerMuta cum liquida in the light of Tertenia Sardinian metathesis and compensatory
lengthening Latin tr > Old French Vrr 77-100. [CrossRef]
125. Anna Maria Di SciulloMinimalism and I-Morphology 267-286. [CrossRef]
126. Manfred BierwischThe role of arbitrariness from a minimalist point of view 392-415. [CrossRef]
127. George Walkden. 2014. Charlotte Galves, Sonia Cyrino, Ruth Lopes, Filomena Sandalo and
Juanito Avelar. Parameter theory and linguistic change . Diachronica 31:1, 150-157. [CrossRef]
128. Giuseppe LongobardiTheory and experiment in parametric minimalism: The case of Romance
negation 217-262. [CrossRef]
129. Koenraad Kuiper, Jacqui NokesThe Minimalist Program 176-213. [CrossRef]
130. Tomohiro Fujii. 2013. Interpreting Thematic Relations Cyclically. Syntax 16:4, 311-323.
[CrossRef]
131. Yuval Marton. 2013. Cylons, Gaylons and Gay Grammar:. AI & SOCIETY 28:4, 553-557.
[CrossRef]
132. Jeong-Shik Lee. 2013. Some Asymmetries in Perception Verb Construction in Korean. Studies
in Generative Grammar 23:4, 677-707. [CrossRef]
133. . 2013. Non-determinism and the Derivational Null Hypothesis. Studies in Generative
Grammar 23:4, 709-726. [CrossRef]
134. M.C. Popa, L.J.M. Rothkrantz, P. Wiggers, C. Shan. 2013. Shopping behavior recognition using
a language modeling analogy. Pattern Recognition Letters 34:15, 1879-1889. [CrossRef]
135. Ljiljana Progovac. 2013. Non-sentential vs. Ellipsis Approaches: Review and Extensions.
Language and Linguistics Compass 7:11, 597-617. [CrossRef]
136. . 2013. The Evolution of Human Language from the Biolinguistic Perspectives. The Journal
of Studies in Language 29:3, 571-591. [CrossRef]
137. Stephen Crain. 2013. Whats parsing got to do with it?. Linguistic Approaches to Bilingualism 3:3,
301-307. [CrossRef]
138. Ccile De Cat. 2013. Beyond the first step. Linguistic Approaches to Bilingualism 3:3, 308-311.
[CrossRef]
139. Cedric Boeckx, Evelina Leivada. 2013. Entangled Parametric Hierarchies: Problems for an
Overspecified Universal Grammar. PLoS ONE 8:9, e72357. [CrossRef]
140. Keir Moulton. 2013. Not Moving Clauses: Connectivity in Clausal Arguments. Syntax 16:3,
250-291. [CrossRef]
141. Adam Szalontai, Katalin Csiszar. 2013. Genetic insights into the functional elements of language.
Human Genetics 132:9, 959-986. [CrossRef]
142. Tobias Scheer. 2013. Why phonology is flat: the role of concatenation and linearity. Language
Sciences 39, 54-74. [CrossRef]
143. Reinhard Blutner, Peter beim Graben. 2013. The (virtual) conceptual necessity of quantum
probabilities in cognitive psychology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36:03, 280-281. [CrossRef]
144. Anna Maria Di Sciullo, Stanca Somesfalean. 2013. The Definite Determiner in Romanian: A
Biolinguistic Perspective. Australian Journal of Linguistics 33:2, 121-139. [CrossRef]
145. Sungshim Hong. 2013. Feature-based Honorifics and Politeness in English and Korean at a
Syntax-Pragmatics Interface. Studies in Generative Grammar 23:2, 199-219. [CrossRef]
146. Jeong-Shik Lee. 2013. Replies to Chung (2012): On Pre- vs. Post-verbal Asymmetries in Korean.
Studies in Generative Grammar 23:2, 171-198. [CrossRef]
147. Elly van Gelderen. 2013. Null Subjects in Old English. Linguistic Inquiry 44:2, 271-285.
[Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF] [PDF Plus]
148. Roumyana Slabakova. 2013. Adult second language acquisition. Linguistic Approaches to
Bilingualism 3:1, 48-72. [CrossRef]
149. Ken Ramshj Christensen, Johannes Kizach, Anne Mette Nyvad. 2013. The processing of
syntactic islands An fMRI study. Journal of Neurolinguistics 26:2, 239-251. [CrossRef]
150. JOY PHILIP. 2013. (Dis)harmony, the Head-Proximate Filter, and linkers. Journal of Linguistics
49:01, 165-213. [CrossRef]
151. Ken Ramshj Christensen, Johannes Kizach, Anne Mette Nyvad. 2013. Escape from the Island:
Grammaticality and (Reduced) Acceptability of wh-island Violations in Danish. Journal of
Psycholinguistic Research 42:1, 51-70. [CrossRef]
152. Chao-Ting Tim Chou. 2013. Unvalued interpretable features and topic A-movement in Chinese
raising modal constructions. Lingua 123, 118-147. [CrossRef]
153. SHIGERU MIYAGAWA. 2013. STRONG UNIFORMITY AND <i>GA/NO</i>
CONVERSION. ENGLISH LINGUISTICS 30:1, 1-24. [CrossRef]
154. Jeong-Shik Lee. 2012. Plural Marker -tul and Its Structural Implication. Studies in Generative
Grammar 22:4, 753-776. [CrossRef]
155. Halldr rmann Sigursson. 2012. Case variation: Viruses and star wars. Nordic Journal of
Linguistics 35:03, 313-342. [CrossRef]
156. Jeffrey Keith Parrott. 2012. Introduction: Case variation and change in the Nordic languages.
Nordic Journal of Linguistics 35:03, 213-218. [CrossRef]
157. Satu ManninenGenerative Grammar . [CrossRef]
158. Takuma Torii, Takashi HashimotoBlending defined on difference, and an implementation using
dynamical approach 896-901. [CrossRef]
159. . 2012. Recursion and Human Language from the Biolinguistic Perspectives. The Journal of
Studies in Language 28:3, 579-598. [CrossRef]
160. . 2012. English Raising Constructions: SOA and Phase-based EPP. The Journal of Studies in
Language 28:3, 479-501. [CrossRef]
161. Gerald P. BerentSign Language-Spoken Language Bilingualism and the Derivation of Bimodally
Mixed Sentences 351-374. [CrossRef]
162. William Haddican, Anders Holmberg. 2012. Object movement symmetries in British English
dialects: Experimental evidence for a mixed case/locality approach. The Journal of Comparative
Germanic Linguistics 15:3, 189-212. [CrossRef]
163. Mirko Grimaldi. 2012. Toward a neural theory of language: Old issues and new perspectives.
Journal of Neurolinguistics 25:5, 304-327. [CrossRef]
164. William O'Grady. 2012. Three factors in the design and acquisition of language. Wiley
Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science 3:5, 493-499. [CrossRef]
165. Myung-Kwan Park. 2012. Passivization, Structural Case and A'-movement in Double Object
Constructions of American and British English. Studies in Generative Grammar 22:3, 647-663.
[CrossRef]
166. Edgardo Brigatti. 2012. Viability of an elementary syntactic structure in a population playing
naming games. Physical Review E 86:2. . [CrossRef]
167. K. M. Petersson, P. Hagoort. 2012. The neurobiology of syntax: beyond string sets. Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 367:1598, 1971-1983. [CrossRef]
168. Caroline Lyon, Chrystopher L. Nehaniv, Joe Saunders. 2012. Interactive Language Learning by
Robots: The Transition from Babbling to Word Forms. PLoS ONE 7:6, e38236. [CrossRef]
169. George Walkden. 2012. Against inertia. Lingua 122:8, 891-901. [CrossRef]
170. Jeong-Shik Lee. 2012. Resurrecting Sluicing from Clefting. Studies in Generative Grammar 22:2,
359-390. [CrossRef]
171. YVES ROBERGE. 2012. On the distinction between preposition stranding and orphan
prepositions. Bilingualism: Language and Cognition 15:02, 243-246. [CrossRef]
172. Nathalie Gontier. 2012. Selectionist Approaches in Evolutionary Linguistics: An Epistemological
Analysis. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 26:1, 67-95. [CrossRef]
173. . 2012. Toward a Syntax without T. Korean Journal of Linguistics 37:1, 47-67. [CrossRef]
174. Jeong-Shik Lee. 2012. Speculations on Typological Variation from a Third Factor Perspective.
Studies in Generative Grammar 22:1, 77-112. [CrossRef]
175. Edith Aldridge. 2012. Antipassive and ergativity in Tagalog. Lingua 122:3, 192-203. [CrossRef]
176. Kim,Yeon-Seung. 2012. Against the Movement Analysis of Gapping Constructions. The Journal
of Studies in Language 27:4, 649-671. [CrossRef]
177. . 2012. A Review of the Anti-Locality of Movement Dependencies. Studies in Generative
Grammar 22:1, 135-155. [CrossRef]
178. . 2012. : . Studies in Generative Grammar 22:1, 113-134.
[CrossRef]
179. Keun-Won Sohn. 2012. Probing in Move: Single or Multiple?. The Journal of Studies in Language
27:4, 693-714. [CrossRef]
180. Ellen Brandner. 2012. Syntactic Microvariation. Language and Linguistics Compass 6:2, 113-130.
[CrossRef]
181. K. Pastra, Y. Aloimonos. 2012. The minimalist grammar of action. Philosophical Transactions of
the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 367:1585, 103-117. [CrossRef]
182. Halldr rmann Sigursson. 2012. Minimalist C/case. Linguistic Inquiry 43:2, 191-227.
[Abstract] [Full Text] [PDF] [PDF Plus]
183. Iris Berent, Wilson Colin, Gary F. Marcus, Douglas K. Bemis. 2012. On the Role of Variables
in Phonology: Remarks on Hayes and Wilson 2008. Linguistic Inquiry 43:1, 97-119. [Abstract]
[Full Text] [PDF] [PDF Plus]
184. . 2012. On Wh-Asymmetries in Korean Interrogatives. Studies in Linguistics null:22, 1-20.
[CrossRef]
185. Wolfram HinzenThe Emergence of Complex Language 243-263. [CrossRef]
186. Marcello BarbieriOrganic Codes and the Origin of Language 445-473. [CrossRef]
187. Charles H. Smith. 2012. Natural selection: A concept in need of some evolution?. Complexity
17:3, 8-17. [CrossRef]
188. Kheline FP Naves, Adriano A Pereira, Slawomir J Nasuto, Ieda PC Russo, Adriano O Andrade.
2012. Assessment of inter-examiner agreement and variability in the manual classification of
auditory brainstem response. BioMedical Engineering OnLine 11:1, 86. [CrossRef]
189. Kheline F. P. Naves, Adriano A. Pereira, Slawomir J. Nasuto, Ieda P. C. Russo, Adriano O.
Andrade. 2012. Analysis of the variability of auditory brainstem response components through
linear regression. Journal of Biomedical Science and Engineering 05:09, 517-525. [CrossRef]
190. Alexander Clark, Shalom LappinComputational Learning Theory and Language Acquisition
445-475. [CrossRef]
191. Christopher CherniakNeural wiring optimization 361-371. [CrossRef]
192. Christina Behme. 2011. Language Universals. Philosophical Psychology 24:6, 867-871. [CrossRef]
193. Marcello Barbieri. 2011. Origin and Evolution of the Brain. Biosemiotics 4:3, 369-399. [CrossRef]
194. J. E. Cannon, S. R. Easterbrooks, P. Gagne, J. Beal-Alvarez. 2011. Improving DHH Students'
Grammar Through an Individualized Software Program. Journal of Deaf Studies and Deaf
Education 16:4, 437-457. [CrossRef]
195. 2011. Chomskyan (R)evolutions. Australian Journal of Linguistics 31:3, 377-386. [CrossRef]
196. Jeong-Shik Lee. 2011. Rethinking Split Questions in Korean. Studies in Generative Grammar
21:3, 409-437. [CrossRef]
197. . 2011. Language Faculty and Biolinguistics. The Journal of Studies in Language 27:2,
373-391. [CrossRef]
198. Halldr rmann Sigursson. 2011. On the New Passive. Syntax 14:2, 148-178. [CrossRef]
199. Miki Obata, Samuel David Epstein. 2011. Feature-Splitting Internal Merge: Improper
Movement, Intervention, and the A/A Distinction. Syntax 14:2, 122-147. [CrossRef]
200. . 2011. Reanalysis of Locality and Optional Movement in the Survive Framework. Studies in
Generative Grammar 21:2, 215-236. [CrossRef]
201. Shigeru Miyagawa. 2011. Genitive subjects in Altaic and specification of phase. Lingua 121:7,
1265-1282. [CrossRef]
202. Halldr rmann Sigursson. 2011. Conditions on Argument Drop. Linguistic Inquiry 42:2,
267-304. [Abstract] [PDF] [PDF Plus]
203. John Collins. 2011. Innateness, canalization, and the modality-independence of language: A reply
to Griffiths and Machery. Philosophical Psychology 24:2, 195-206. [CrossRef]
204. JOHN COLLINS. 2011. Impossible Words Again: Or Why Beds Break but Not Make. Mind
& Language 26:2, 234-260. [CrossRef]
205. . 2011. Case and case particles. Journal of Korean Linguistics null:60, 233-263. [CrossRef]
206. ngel J. Gallego. 2011. Successive cyclicity, phases, and CED effects*. Studia Linguistica 65:1,
32-69. [CrossRef]
207. Morten H. Christiansen, Florencia Reali, Nick Chater. 2011. Biological Adaptations for
Functional Features of Language in the Face of Cultural Evolution. Human Biology 83:2, 247-259.
[CrossRef]
208. Kay Gonzlez-Vilbazo, Luis Lpez. 2011. Some properties of light verbs in code-switching.
Lingua 121:5, 832-850. [CrossRef]
209. References 217-233. [CrossRef]
210. LILIANE HAEGEMAN, TERJE LOHNDAL. 2011. Introducing the Minimalist Program to
students of English. English Language and Linguistics 15:01, 149-172. [CrossRef]
211. Acrisio Pires, Jason Rothman, Ana Lcia Santos. 2011. L1 acquisition across Portuguese dialects:
Modular and interdisciplinary interfaces as sources of explanation. Lingua 121:4, 605-622.
[CrossRef]
212. TERJE LOHNDAL. 2011. Freezing effects and objects. Journal of Linguistics 47:01, 163-199.
[CrossRef]
213. Shane Nicholas Glackin. 2011. Universal grammar and the Baldwin effect: a hypothesis and some
philosophical consequences. Biology & Philosophy 26:2, 201-222. [CrossRef]
214. Celia Jakubowicz. 2011. Measuring derivational complexity: New evidence from typically
developing and SLI learners of L1 French. Lingua 121:3, 339-351. [CrossRef]
215. Keun-Won Sohn. 2011. Deriving Tags in Split Questions: Deletion and pro. The Journal of
Studies in Language 26:4, 857-877. [CrossRef]
216. Laurice Tuller, Hlne Delage, Ccile Monjauze, Anne-Galle Piller, Marie-Anne Barthez. 2011.
Clitic pronoun production as a measure of atypical language development in French. Lingua
121:3, 423-441. [CrossRef]
217. Timothy Osborne, Michael Putnam, Thomas M. Gross. 2011. Bare phrase structure, label-less
trees, and specifier-less syntax. Is Minimalism becoming a dependency grammar?. The Linguistic
Review 28:3. . [CrossRef]
218. E. Phoevos Panagiotidis. 2011. Categorial features and categorizers. The Linguistic Review 28:3. .
[CrossRef]
219. Chris H. Reintges. 2011. High analyticity and Coptic particle syntax: A phase-based approach.
The Linguistic Review 28:4. . [CrossRef]
220. Robert Truswell. 2010. What exactly evolved?. Journal of Evolutionary Psychology 8:4, 367-373.
[CrossRef]
221. Maxwell Kadenge. 2010. Complexity in phonology: The complex consonants of simple CV-
syllables in Zezuru. Southern African Linguistics and Applied Language Studies 28:4, 393-408.
[CrossRef]
222. J. Rooryck, N.V. Smith, A. Liptak, D. Blakemore. 2010. Editorial introduction to the special
issue of Lingua on Evans & Levinson's The myth of language universals. Lingua 120:12,
2651-2656. [CrossRef]
223. Vasiliki Folia, Julia Uddn, Meinou De Vries, Christian Forkstam, Karl Magnus Petersson.
2010. Artificial Language Learning in Adults and Children. Language Learning 60, 188-220.
[CrossRef]
224. Klaus Abels, Ad Neeleman. 2010. Nihilism masquerading as progress. Lingua 120:12, 2657-2660.
[CrossRef]
225. Thomas Roeper. 2010. Interfaces, frequency, and the primary linguistic data problem. Lingua
120:11, 2538-2545. [CrossRef]
226. Theresa Biberauer, Ian Roberts. 2010. Comments on Jger Anything is nothing is something:
on the diachrony of polarity types of indefinites. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 28:4,
823-836. [CrossRef]
227. CRISTBAL LOZANO, AMAYA MENDIKOETXEA. 2010. Interface conditions on
postverbal subjects: A corpus study of L2 English. Bilingualism: Language and Cognition 13:04,
475-497. [CrossRef]
228. Tania Ionin. 2010. MEANING IN THE SECOND LANGUAGE. Roumyana Slabakova. Berlin:
Mouton de Gruyter, 2008. Pp. xi + 326. Studies in Second Language Acquisition 32:03, 502-504.
[CrossRef]
229. Nick Chater, Morten H. Christiansen. 2010. Language Acquisition Meets Language Evolution.
Cognitive Science 34:7, 1131-1157. [CrossRef]
230. Marcello Barbieri. 2010. On the Origin of Language. Biosemiotics 3:2, 201-223. [CrossRef]
231. Sung-Ho Ahn. 2010. A Case of Tense Acquisition: Is 90% Enough?. Studies in Generative
Grammar 20:3, 407-444. [CrossRef]
232. References 655-741. [CrossRef]
233. Adolfo Martn Garca. 2010. Methodological Tenets, Plausibility and Reality in Chomskyan
Biolinguistics. Linguistics and the Human Sciences 3:3. . [CrossRef]
234. Charles Whitehead. 2010. The culture ready brain. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience
5:2-3, 168-179. [CrossRef]
235. T. W. Deacon. 2010. A role for relaxed selection in the evolution of the language capacity.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 107:Supplement_2, 9000-9006. [CrossRef]
236. Charles Yang. 2010. Three factors in language variation. Lingua 120:5, 1160-1177. [CrossRef]
237. Hiroki Narita. 2010. The Tension between Explanatory and Biological Adequacy. Lingua 120:5,
1313-1323. [CrossRef]
238. 2010. Book Reviews. Australian Journal of Linguistics 30:2, 283-295. [CrossRef]
239. Daniel Gildea, David Temperley. 2010. Do Grammars Minimize Dependency Length?. Cognitive
Science 34:2, 286-310. [CrossRef]
240. Doreen Georgi, Gereon Mller. 2010. Noun-Phrase Structure by Reprojection. Syntax 13:1,
1-36. [CrossRef]
241. Kwang-Sup Kim. 2010. Is Binding Possible without C-commanding?. The Journal of Studies in
Language 25:4, 675-696. [CrossRef]
242. Jacqueline van Kampen. 2010. Typological guidance in the acquisition of V2 Dutch. Lingua
120:2, 264-283. [CrossRef]
243. Gereon Mller. 2010. On Deriving CED Effects from the PIC. Linguistic Inquiry 41:1, 35-82.
[Abstract] [PDF] [PDF Plus]
244. Howard Lasnik, Terje Lohndal. 2010. Government-binding/principles and parameters theory.
Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science 1:1, 40-50. [CrossRef]
245. John CollinsNaturalism in the Philosophy of Language; or Why There Is No Such Thing as
Language 41-59. [CrossRef]
246. David Golumbia. 2010. Minimalism is functionalism. Language Sciences 32:1, 28-42. [CrossRef]
247. Anders Holmberg. 2010. Parameters in minimalist theory: The case of Scandinavian. Theoretical
Linguistics 36:1, 1-48. [CrossRef]
248. Christopher Cherniak, Raul Rodriguez-Esteban. 2010. Information processing limits on
generating neuroanatomy: global optimization of rat olfactory cortex and amygdala. Journal of
Biological Physics 36:1, 45-52. [CrossRef]
249. Florian Schfer. 2010. On the (in-)dependency of (micro-)parameters. Theoretical Linguistics
36:1. . [CrossRef]
250. Terje Lohndal, Juan Uriagereka. 2010. The logic of parametric theories. Theoretical Linguistics
36:1. . [CrossRef]
251. Ewa Willim. 2010. On the form-function dichotomy in linguistic theory. Studia Linguistica
Universitatis Iagellonicae Cracoviensis 127:-1, 211-226. [CrossRef]
252. Jen Ting. 2010. On the climbing of the particle suo in Mandarin Chinese and its implications
for the theory of clitic placement. The Linguistic Review 27:4. . [CrossRef]
253. Myung-Kwan Park. 2009. An (impossible) excursion into matrix [Spec, vP] out of an elided
complement clause in Korean. Korean Journal of Linguistics 34:4, 895-917. [CrossRef]
254. Myung-Kwan Park. 2009. Deletion and Locality: Evidence from VP and TP Deletion in English.
Korean Journal of English Language and Linguistics 9:4, 687-715. [CrossRef]
255. 2009. Book Reviews. Language & History 52:2, 199-204. [CrossRef]
256. Hiroki Narita. 2009. Lingua 119:11, 1767-1775. [CrossRef]
257. Jan-Wouter Zwart. 2009. Relevance of typology to minimalist inquiry. Lingua 119:11,
1589-1606. [CrossRef]
258. NICOLE DEH. 2009. Clausal parentheticals, intonational phrasing, and prosodic theory.
Journal of Linguistics 45:03, 569. [CrossRef]
259. C. Lyon, Y. Sato, J. Saunders, C.L. Nehaniv. 2009. What is Needed for a Robot to Acquire
Grammar? Some Underlying Primitive Mechanisms for the Synthesis of Linguistic Ability. IEEE
Transactions on Autonomous Mental Development 1:3, 187-195. [CrossRef]
260. Guillermo Lorenzo, Vctor M. Longa. 2009. Beyond generative geneticism: Rethinking language
acquisition from a developmentalist point of view. Lingua 119:9, 1300-1315. [CrossRef]
261. Theres Grter. 2009. A Unified Account of Object Clitics and Referential Null Objects in French.
Syntax 12:3, 215-241. [CrossRef]
262. Elly van Gelderen. 2009. Renewal in the left periphery: economy and the complementiser layer.
Transactions of the Philological Society 107:2, 131-195. [CrossRef]
263. A. Powell, S. Shennan, M. G. Thomas. 2009. Late Pleistocene Demography and the Appearance
of Modern Human Behavior. Science 324:5932, 1298-1301. [CrossRef]
264. Pauli Brattico, Lassi Liikkanen. 2009. Rethinking the Cartesian theory of linguistic productivity.
Philosophical Psychology 22:3, 251-279. [CrossRef]
265. . 2009. Is v*P really a Phase?. English Language and Linguistics null:27, 23-39. [CrossRef]
266. Balzs Surnyi. 2009. Verbal particles inside and outside v P. Acta Linguistica Hungarica 56:2-3,
201-249. [CrossRef]
267. Robert Bley-Vroman. 2009. THE EVOLVING CONTEXT OF THE FUNDAMENTAL
DIFFERENCE HYPOTHESIS. Studies in Second Language Acquisition 31:02, 175. [CrossRef]
268. Roumyana Slabakova. 2009. L2 FUNDAMENTALS. Studies in Second Language Acquisition
31:02, 155. [CrossRef]
269. , . 2009. Biolinguistics and the Evolutionary Adequacy of Syntax. The Journal of Studies
in Language 25:1, 47-68. [CrossRef]
270. Morten H. Christiansen, Nick Chater, Florencia Reali. 2009. The biological and cultural
foundations of language. Communicative & Integrative Biology 2:3, 221-222. [CrossRef]
271. Angelika Kratzer. 2009. Making a Pronoun: Fake Indexicals as Windows into the Properties of
Pronouns. Linguistic Inquiry 40:2, 187-237. [Abstract] [PDF] [PDF Plus]
272. Prisca Augustyn. 2009. Uexkll, Peirce, and Other Affinities Between Biosemiotics and
Biolinguistics. Biosemiotics 2:1, 1-17. [CrossRef]
273. Donna Lardiere. 2009. Some thoughts on the contrastive analysis of features in second language
acquisition. Second Language Research 25:2, 173-227. [CrossRef]
274. Laurent Dekydtspotter, Claire Renaud. 2009. On the contrastive analysis of features in second
language acquisition: uninterpretable gender on past participles in EnglishFrench processing.
Second Language Research 25:2, 255-267. [CrossRef]
275. Robert C. Berwick. 2009. What genes can't learn about language. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences 106:6, 1685-1686. [CrossRef]
276. , Sung-Hun Kim. 2009. Linguistic Competence and Bilingual Education. The Journal of
Studies in Language 24:4, 817-838. [CrossRef]
277. N. Chater, F. Reali, M. H. Christiansen. 2009. Restrictions on biological adaptation in language
evolution. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 106:4, 1015-1020. [CrossRef]
278. ngel J. Gallego. 2009. Defective C-T in Romance. Probus 21:2. . [CrossRef]
279. Sang-soo Park. 2008. The Observance of V2 in the English Focalized Constructions. English
Language and Linguistics null:26, 269-286. [CrossRef]
280. Elly van Gelderen. 2008. Where did Late Merge go? Grammaticalization as feature economy.
Studia Linguistica 62:3, 287-300. [CrossRef]
281. M. D. Hauser, T. Bever. 2008. BEHAVIOR: A Biolinguistic Agenda. Science 322:5904,
1057-1059. [CrossRef]
282. Simin Karimi. 2008. Scrambling. Language and Linguistics Compass 2:6, 1271-1293. [CrossRef]
283. Morten H. Christiansen, Nick Chater. 2008. Language as shaped by the brain. Behavioral and
Brain Sciences 31:05. . [CrossRef]
284. Christina Behme. 2008. Languages as evolving organisms The solution to the logical problem
of language evolution?. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31:05. . [CrossRef]
285. Christina Behme, S. Hlne Deacon. 2008. Language Learning in Infancy: Does the Empirical
Evidence Support a Domain Specific Language Acquisition Device?. Philosophical Psychology 21:5,
641-671. [CrossRef]
286. Morten H. Christiansen, Nick Chater. 2008. Brains, genes, and language evolution: A new
synthesis. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31:05. . [CrossRef]
287. Amaya Mendikoetxea. 2008. Clitic impersonal constructions in Romance: syntactic features and
semantic interpretation. Transactions of the Philological Society 106:2, 290-336. [CrossRef]
288. Anna Siewierska. 2008. Introduction: impersonalization from a subject-centred vs. agent-centred
perspective. Transactions of the Philological Society 106:2, 115-137. [CrossRef]
289. Jeong-Seok Kim. 2008. Stylistic Fronting: A Syntax-Phonology Interface. Studies in Generative
Grammar 18:2, 207-227. [CrossRef]
290. eljko Bokovi. 2008. On the operator freezing effect. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory
26:2, 249-287. [CrossRef]
291. Gregory Katz. 2008. The Hypothesis of a Genetic Protolanguage: an Epistemological
Investigation. Biosemiotics 1:1, 57-73. [CrossRef]
292. William OGrady. 2008. The emergentist program. Lingua 118:4, 447-464. [CrossRef]
293. William OGrady. 2008. Innateness, universal grammar, and emergentism. Lingua 118:4,
620-631. [CrossRef]
294. Ken Ramshj Christensen. 2008. Interfaces, syntactic movement, and neural activation: A new
perspective on the implementation of language in the brain. Journal of Neurolinguistics 21:2,
73-103. [CrossRef]
295. Kwang-Sup Kim. 2008. Backward Binding and Implicit Argument. The Journal of Studies in
Language 23:4, 621-639. [CrossRef]
296. Hans Kamp, Martin StokhofINFORMATION IN NATURAL LANGUAGE 49-111.
[CrossRef]
297. Vctor M. Longa, Guillermo Lorenzo. 2008. What about a (really) minimalist theory of language
acquisition?. Linguistics 46:3. . [CrossRef]
298. Maxim I. StamenovAttention and language 1-21. [CrossRef]
299. Noam Chomsky. 2007. Book review. Artificial Intelligence 171:18, 1094-1103. [CrossRef]
300. John Collins. 2007. Linguistic Competence without Knowledge of Language. Philosophy Compass
2:6, 880-895. [CrossRef]
301. J. Collins. 2007. Meta-scientific Eliminativism: A Reconsideration of Chomsky's Review of
Skinner's Verbal Behavior. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58:4, 625-658.
[CrossRef]
302. Cedric Boeckx, Kleanthes K. Grohmann. 2007. Remark: Putting Phases in Perspective. Syntax
10:2, 204-222. [CrossRef]
303. Tuba Yarbay Duman, Glat Aygen, Nee zgirgin, Roelien Bastiaanse. 2007. Object scrambling
and finiteness in Turkish agrammatic production. Journal of Neurolinguistics 20:4, 306-331.
[CrossRef]
304. John Bolender. 2007. Prehistoric cognition by description: a Russellian approach to the upper
paleolithic. Biology & Philosophy 22:3, 383-399. [CrossRef]
305. Sjef Barbiers. 2007. Indefinite numerals one and many and the cause of ordinal suppletion. Lingua
117:5, 859-880. [CrossRef]
306. Arild Hestvik, Nathan Maxfield, Richard G. Schwartz, Valerie Shafer. 2007. Brain responses to
filled gaps. Brain and Language 100:3, 301-316. [CrossRef]
307. SAMUEL D. EPSTEIN. 2007. Physiological Linguistics, and Some Implications Regarding
Disciplinary Autonomy and Unification. Mind & Language 22:1, 44-67. [CrossRef]
308. Angelika Kratzer, Elisabeth Selkirk. 2007. Phase theory and prosodic spellout: The case of verbs.
The Linguistic Review 24:2-3. . [CrossRef]
309. 2007. Book Reviews. Folia Linguistica 41:1-2. . [CrossRef]
310. Franc Marui, Rok aucer. 2006. On the Intensional Feel-Like Construction in Slovenian: A
Case of a Phonologically Null Verb. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 24:4, 1093-1159.
[CrossRef]
311. Cedric Boeckx, Norbert Hornstein. 2006. The Virtues of Control as Movement. Syntax 9:2,
118-130. [CrossRef]
312. Idan Landau. 2006. Severing the Distribution of PRO from Case. Syntax 9:2, 153-170.
[CrossRef]
313. Jeffrey T. Runner. 2006. Lingering Challenges to the Raising-to-object and Object-control
Constructions. Syntax 9:2, 193-213. [CrossRef]
314. Maria Polinsky, Eric Potsdam. 2006. Expanding the Scope of Control and Raising. Syntax 9:2,
171-192. [CrossRef]
315. 2006. References. Syntax 9:2, 214-223. [CrossRef]
316. Peter W. Culicover, Ray Jackendoff. 2006. Turn Over Control to the Semantics!. Syntax 9:2,
131-152. [CrossRef]
317. William D. Davies, Stanley Dubinsky. 2006. The Place, Range, and Taxonomy of Control and
Raising. Syntax 9:2, 111-117. [CrossRef]
318. Livio Gaeta. 2006. How to Live Naturally and not be Bothered by Economy. Folia Linguistica
40:1part2, 7-28. [CrossRef]
319. Leslie Roulet-Amiot, Clia Jakubowicz. 2006. Production and perception of gender agreement
in French SLI. Advances in Speech Language Pathology 8:4, 335-346. [CrossRef]
320. T. Reinhart, T. SiloniCommand Relations 635-642. [CrossRef]
321. Pauli Brattico, Mikko MaattaNatural Language Parsing 158-175. [CrossRef]

Potrebbero piacerti anche