Sei sulla pagina 1di 7

See

discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/6901899

Why We Must Leave Our Organs to Others

Article in The American Journal of Bioethics August 2006


DOI: 10.1080/15265160600755839 Source: PubMed

CITATIONS READS

18 67

1 author:

D. Micah Hester
University of Arkansas for Medical Sciences
60 PUBLICATIONS 153 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE

Available from: D. Micah Hester


Retrieved on: 03 September 2016
InFocus Article

Why We Must Leave Our Organs


to Others
D. Micah Hester, University of Arkansas for Medical Sciences

Organ procurement presents several ethical concerns (from what constitutes acceptable crite- Keywords
ria for death to issues involved in specifically designating to whom an organ can be given), but organ
none is more central than the concern for what are appropriate means for acquiring organs.
transplant
The following discussion attempts a different perspective on the issue of organ procurement
procurment
by arguing that, rather than appealing to our charitable consciences or our pocketbooks, re-
linquishing our organs after death in this day and age is, in fact, obligatory for most people. obligation

Each of us is pressed by the growing demand for our organs should we die rightly, and that respect
desperate need has risen to such a level that not to release our organs for transplantation would
constitute a serious moral wrong.

Organ procurement presents several ethical con- need for heart transplantation (Ad Hoc Committee
cerns (from what constitutes acceptable criteria for 1968). With the implementation of the Pittsburgh
death to issues involved in specifically designat- protocol in the late 1980s, development of the non-
ing to whom an organ can be given), but none is heart-beating criteria (i.e., donation after cardiac
more central than the concern for what are appro- death) has been gaining not uncontroversial support
priate means for acquiring organs. For more than in order to help with the supply of lungs, kidneys
three decades now, the call to procure organs to use and livers (Arnold and Younger 1993; Arnold et al.
in transplantation has markedly grown louder, but 1995). Analogously, some argue that it is morally
supply simply has not kept up with demand. acceptable for surrogates to offer organs on behalf of
This fact is well known, and the statistics, although patients in a persistent vegetative state (Koppelman
often recounted, remain quite telling. According to 2003).
the United Network for Organ Sharing (UNOS) However, while these value-laden processes may,
as of May 2006, approximately 92,000 patients in fact, identify morally acceptable biological con-
are candidates for organ transplantation (e.g., more ditions for procurement, that identification pro-
than 66,000 for kidneys alone). This is more than vides no guarantee that patients (or their fami-
a 100% increase from 10 years ago. At the same lies/surrogates) will, in reality, allow organs to be
time, only about 28,000 transplant operations were made available for transplantation. Thus, rather
performed in 2005 (e.g., approximately 16,000 kid- than trying to identify such conditions, the most
ney transplants), and these numbers represent only common and public mode of addressing the pro-
about a 40% increase from 10 years ago (UNOS curement issue has been through direct appeals to
website). the populace at-large, and such strategies have tra-
In response, various strategies have been pro- ditionally taken one of two lines. The most widely
posed to aid in the task of increasing procurement accepted approach to raising the procurement rate
rates. Initially focusing on suitable conditions for has been an appeal to charity (e.g., Murray 1986;
the procurement of organs, groups began investi- Fox and Swazey 1992), and this model undergirds
gating neurological standards for death to supplant all legally sanctioned procurement in the United
the traditional cardiopulmonary understanding. For States.1 Organ donation (the very term bespeaks
example, the 1968 Harvard Ad Hoc Committee
developed its well known whole-brain death cri- 1. Still under a charity model, but employing a state-
teria in reaction not only to the rise of various car- sponsored incentive, in 2005 the state of Utah passed
a law giving tax credit for expenses incurred by liv-
diopulmonary technologies but also to demand for a ing donors, and had previously passed a law giv-
medically, morally and legally acceptable definition ing 30-day leave to state employees who donate (see
of death that would aid in supplying the nascent http://www.idslife.org/news-145i.php).

The American Journal of Bioethics, 6(4): W23W28, 2006 ajob W23


Copyright 
c Taylor & Francis Group, LLC
ISSN: 1526-5161 print / 1536-0075 online
DOI: 10.1080/15265160600755839
The American Journal of Bioethics

charity), in this sense, has been characterized as a sciences or our pocketbooks. Instead, as intimated
precious and vital gift to be made from one person to by Caplan (1992, 156157) and addressed directly
another. It is considered, in the language of ethics, to by Nelson (2003a), the following argues that re-
be supererogatorybeyond our moral obligations, linquishing our organs after death in this day and
but highly laudable. The metaphor has even taken age is, in fact, obligatory for most people. Each of us
root in public policy with the development of the is pressed by the growing demand for our organs
Uniform Anatomical Gift Act (19721987), to en- should we die according to acceptable procurement
courage (and protect) donors and donations. standards, and that desperate need has risen to such
The most vocal alternative strategy has been a level that not to release our organs for transplanta-
one of commodificationan economic appeal or tion (an admittedly awkward phraseLoewy 1996)
market-based model, as it were (e.g., Lachs 1979; would constitute a serious moral wrong.3
Annas 1984; Gill and Sade 2002; Cherry 2005; The focus of this article is primarily
Kishore 2005). While not legally accepted in the theoreticalby which is meant that the argument
United States,2 it has been argued (primarily on contained herein relies on a moral logic. Whereas
liberaleven libertarianautonomy basis) that many articles on organ procurement begin with a
monetary incentives should be offered to potential concern about the need to increase procurement
donors. Though it eventually reversed its policy, rates (and it is agreed that this is a serious prac-
India (as one example) has allowed for the use of tical concern), the argument that follows does not
monetary incentives, but the argument has never primarily aim to increase procurement. It may, in
won the day in the United States (Wilkinson and fact do so, but the central purpose of the argument
Garrad 1996; Cohen 2002; Goya et al. 2002). Each is to ground our procurement practices on the surest
side in this debate has put forth strong reasons why moral footing possible. To do so, the argument be-
the other fails as an acceptable strategy to procure gins from a basic assumption about ethical theory
organs, but ultimately, neither puts forth sufficient and the moral lifenamely, that we are obligated
support for its own position. Both sides fundamen- to do what we can to save seriously endangered lives
tally miss the moral point because both sides im- when we can do so without risking anything of sig-
plicitly and falsely accept that organ procurement nificant value to us.4 Without accepting this as-
must be the result of a voluntary and supereroga- sumption, the argument that follows will rest inse-
tory act. However, as will be argued, the call to re- curely its own ethical moorings.
linquishing organs upon our deaths begins as what Granting the previous assumption about
some would call a prima facie or even ordinary obli- the moral life, then, the first premise is
gation, and what has also been referred to as a de straightforwardnamely, saving a life is a good
facto obligation. As others have pointed out, charity which is worthy of pursuit. Unless circumstances
is morally weak, and requires little of us and others dictate that undue harm or potential harm (whether,
(Caplan 1992, 156). This article, in kind, argues for in the case of transplants, to the recipient or the per-
a stronger moral claim, one that becomes further son from whom the organ is procured) would result
strengthened as this de facto claim quickly becomes from life-saving measures, attempts at saving some-
a de jure (i.e., moral) obligationthat is, as it be- one who would foreseeably die otherwise is a moral
comes a final moral good worthy of our pursuit, in good.
the face of no significant and comparable obligation
or loss to ourselves on our deaths (cf. James 1891; 3. Having said this, however, I leave open the question of
Dewey 1926). public policy for further debate. The legal and strategic
The following, then, will attempt to refocus the questions of whether and how the state should require the
relinquishing of organs on death is importantly distinct,
issue away from an appeal to our charitable con- and while I believe our liberal democracy rightly demands
that we allow the moral choice to be real, whatever are
the legal/strategic implications of my position, the moral
2. Relatedly, the South Carolina legislature passed a question must be answered first.
law in 2004 allowing living donors a tax deduc- 4. In fact, any viable conception of what we owe to each
tion and giving surviving family of deceased donors other must recognize this basic obligation. Although
a tax credit. The bill was vetoed by the gov- the phrase is from the deontologically-minded Thomas
ernor. (see http://www.scstatehouse.net/sess115 2003- Scanlon (2000), some version of this simple moral point
2004/bills/5085.htm). Further, other proposed ethical can be found in other deontologists such as Ross (2003),
incentives can be found in but adding what has been utilitarians such as Mill (1975) and Singer (1972), and
called ethical incentives Delmonico et al. 2002 and even pragmatists such as James (1891), among many
Steinberg 2004. others.

W24 ajob July/August 2006, Volume 6, Number 4


Why We Must Leave Our Organs

Second, the use of organ transplantation is a own negative side-effectsboth physiological and
medically and ethically appropriate means to saving psychological (Brown and Parfrey 1999)but also
a life. On the whole transplants have proven to be reduces transplant success rates as well (Mange et al.
relatively safe surgeries that extend the lives of those 2001).
who have them, and transplants do so without grave Fifth, the most complex premise remains: Dead
harm to either the transplant patients themselves or persons have no embodied countervailing interests
to others. As such transplantation has demonstrated that could trump the vital interests of potential
that it is not simply a case of the technological im- transplant patients. Bodies, although significant
perative running amok, but a socially positive use symbols of the life once inhabiting them, have no
of ingenuity and technology in medicine. need for the organs that remain after death. The
Similarly, my third premise should be easily question raised, then, is what harm could be done
accepted: Namely, those who await organ trans- to now-dead persons if organs are taken without di-
plantation must rely on othersphysicians, nurses, rect consent? Aristotle and others have noted that
benefactors, and most importantly, donors. It may it is still possible to be harmed after ones death.
seem trivial, but it is worth emphasizing that trans- The question, then, is whether any potential harms
plant patients cannot fulfill their needs without could be serious enough to affect the powerful obli-
someone else coming through for them. Also, in most gation to save a life. Nelson (2003a), for one, does
cases, patients find themselves in need of a trans- not think so, which follows from both beneficence
plant through no moral failing of their own. It and what Nelson calls the easy rescue (118120).
cannot be denied that nutrition, lifestyle and per- In a brief commentary, Nelson notes that fastid-
sonal choice can lead to heart disease, cirrhosis and iousness about ones dignity, which might pre-
other organ-compromising disease. As such, some clude them from consenting to life-saving acts, is
imply (if not claim outright) that, for example, al- not morally supportablehis argument turning on
coholics require liver transplants because of their the virtually costless nature of certain kinds of
moral failure to stop excessive drinking (Moss and life saving acts like organ release over-and-against
Siegler 1991; Kluge 1994). Of course, the impor- the clearly beneficial nature of organ transplantation
tance of volition implied here cannot be minimized. (2003b, 14).
It seems false to say that eating habits are strictly Of course, some groups believe that the removal
willful acts or that excessive drinking is primar- of organs from a dead person can itself be a form of
ily a chosen avocation. There is ample evidence, disrespect. These claims are often made in light of
for example, that many, if not most, alcoholics de- larger value-systems, such as religious beliefs. For
velop as a consequence of genetic and environmen- example, though most religious organizations ac-
tal factors beyond their own decisive control; also, cept donation as charitable, none require it (e.g.,
diets routinely fail even in the face of willful deter- Kunin 2005); at the same time some groups, such as
mination. Even if psychological and moral factors the orthodox Jews, strict Jehovahs Witnesses, some
can be brought to bear to pronounce negatively on Amish, and Confucians (cf. Lam and McCullough
some potential recipients, surely the medical situa- 2000), have particular reluctances, and still others
tions many patients find themselves in do not con- such as the Shinto in Japan find the dead body im-
tain such morally questionable circumstances and, pure and thus find procurement and transplantation
even when they do, genetic and biological factors at inherently troubling (Cooper and Taylor 2000).
least mitigate some degree of moral responsibility. Such claims, however, seem difficult to support,
Further, many of these concerns would affect allo- even for long-standing religious institutions, in the
cation, rather than procurement, decisions. Fourth, face of deep moral concerns for potentially dying
it is clear that the demand for organs is high, and persons. The extent to which the body is symbolic
those organs are vital to the patients who need them. of the person should not be discounted, but even a
Transplantation fulfills a basic and important good well-established belief system that claims that only
to those who receive the organs. Every year, approx- whole-bodied persons can gain glory in an after-
imately over 6,000 people on the UNOS waiting life must address the question of what shape a
list die still waiting for a transplant. Many others body must be in and why. Does heart disease, for
wait in various stages of deteriorating health for up- example, constitute an unclean bodily form, and if
wards of 5 years or more. At the same time tens of not, which cellular and functional apparatus must
thousands of kidney patients, in particular, must be present and which need not be? Of course, it
go through dialysis, which not only produces its could be claimed that even raising the question

July/August 2006, Volume 6, Number 4 ajob W25


The American Journal of Bioethics

against such belief systems employs a kind of a The previous argument above makes a strong
category error that reduces bodily integrity merely moral claim, one typically avoided (if not dispar-
to biological processes rather than utilizing spiri- aged) in the transplantation ethics literature. How-
tual language and concepts. Of course, there is a ever, one remaining practical matter concerns the
stronger argument to be madenamely, any spir- very real existence of fear that organ procurement al-
itual or philosophical value system that leads to ready occurs under questionable circumstance, and
failure of ethical duties to others in your society that the medical establishment supports the has-
should be help accountable for the moral weak- tening of death in order to procure organs. Soci-
nesses that follow. Respect and disrespect are paid ological research has already shown that such a
to persons/moral agents, not to bodies per se. In fear exists within the current system. In particu-
the face of the need for healthy organs for living lar, African-American physicians have long argued
human beings, spiritual concepts that champion a that organ conscription or even presumed consent
spiritual notion of bodily integrity over helping oth- policies would heighten an already complex atti-
ers survive seems misguided. Instead, procurement tude of distrust (cf. Jacob Arriola 2005) within the
from dead bodies should be championed as no vio- African-American community towards medicine
lation of what respect is due to formerly embodied (Robeznieks 2004). The particularly strong moral
persons, but instead the fulfillment of ones moral stance of the previous argument could be seen as
duty. ratcheting up the conditions that lead to such fear
Lastly, it may be useful to emphasize the pre- all the more with the view that if organ removal is
vailing limiting factor employed throughout this morally required, then coercive measures to har-
articlenamely, while some demands on us would vest organs might be more common, such as inap-
require the loss of a significant good in order to be propriately withholding treatment in order to se-
fulfilled, relinquishing cadaveric organs requires no cure death sooner.
such loss. The previous argument, thus, is delim- This concern, along with concerns of those who
ited by a practical factnamely, the current dangers hold that organ retrieval after death is spiritually
of surgery and the vital character of our organs to disrespectful, will strike many as a significant prob-
our own well being, weaken the force of both the lem for the argument on practical/policy grounds,
second and fifth premises, leaving live donations as primarily because this societys liberal democratic
a supererogatory act. Further, as Truog (2005) has valuing of autonomy and personal safety requires
argued, cadaveric organs should be regarded as a the use of a certain level of decisional latitude in
societal resource, not as personal property. Nelson decisions that affect usincluding our bodies. Of
concurs, We ought to move closer toward seeing course, strict moral logic might require a very strong
such organs as communal resources, and hence, as policy, but important social values such as auton-
routinely retrievable (Nelson 2005, 26). And while omy and safety might mitigate against strong pol-
living donor organs may become societal resources, icy precisely to leave room for those persons who
there is no debate that living individuals must con- hold the kinds of beliefs that would problemati-
sent to make them available to the pool of potential cally pit organ procurement against other strongly
recipients. At the same time, though, these facts are held values. This raises the relationship between
deeply contextual, and continual protections and moral argument and public policy. Theory devoid
techniques of surgery for live donations as well as of practical concerns is bound to fail, whereas a
further development of the socioethical landscape practical decisions without moral grounding risk
may, in the future, raise the moral stakes to the level being unethical. The given argument provides care-
of obligation even for procurement from living in- ful moral reasoning concerning organ procurement;
dividuals. Either way, concerns for surgical and gen- what must be taken up next is how such moral find-
eral health risks, as well as legitimate morally-based ings would be implemented given cultural condi-
property claims, do not apply in cadavers, creating tions operative in the United States.
a heightened moral requirement. Thus, while the argument morally grounds the
Thus, without need to draw out the logical con- obligation to relinquish our organs after death, the
clusion, given the basic moral assumption as well concerns of those who find organ removal after death
as the stated premises and conditions concerning disrespectful have implications for how to deal with
organ transplantation and procurement, each of us this moral obligation in public policy. In other
has a moral obligation to relinquish our organs for words, it might seem to follow that because organ
transplantation on our deaths. release has been shown to be an ethical obligation,

W26 ajob July/August 2006, Volume 6, Number 4


Why We Must Leave Our Organs

we should write our laws in such a way that each of Arnold, R. M., and S. Younger (eds.). 1993. Special is-
us is legally required to donate, thus matching law sue on Ethical, psychosocial, and public policy impli-
with morality (cf. Spital 2005; Kreis 2005). How- cations of procuring organs from non-heart-beating ca-
ever, that such laws should be developed is not an davers. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 3(2).
implication to be drawn by necessity.5 Arnold, R. M., S. J. Youngner, R. Schapiro, and C.
And yet, while practical concerns like these are M. Spicer (eds.). 1995. Procuring organs for trans-
not to be ignored (and, in fact, are central to crafting plant: The debate over non-heart-beating cadaver or-
gans. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University
ethically and medically successful public policy),
Press.
the issue in this article is simply whether a moral
case for obligatory removal can be made. Certainly, Brown, E., and P. S. Parfrey. 1999. Complications of
long-term dialysis. New York, NY: Oxford University
if there is a strong case for the obligation to give or-
Press.
gans on death, then to develop ethically appropriate
means to the implications of such an argument, there Caplan, A. L. 1992. Requests, gifts, and obligations. In
If I were a rich man could I buy myself a pancreas? A. L.
would have to be careful attention paid to the details
Caplan (ed.), 145157 Bloomington, IN: Indiana Univer-
of implementation. However, the difficulty of those
sity Press.
details cannot be allowed to settle (by precluding)
Cherry, M. J. 2005. Kidney for sale by owner: Human
the question of whether we are morally obligated
organs, transplantation, and the market. Washington,
to give our organs. Thus, the moral argument for
DC: Georgetown University Press.
releasing our organs on death remains strong and
Cohen, C. B. 2002. Public policy and the sale of human
valuable. 
organ. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 12(1): 4764.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Cooper, M. L., and G. J. Taylor (eds.). 2000.
SEOPF/UNOS: Organ and tissue donation: A refer-
Given the tightly structured nature of the argu-
ence guide for clergy. Fourth edition. Richmond, VA:
ment, I take full responsibility for its possible fail- SEOPF/UNOS.
ure. However, its success is due to the aid of Drs.
Delmonico, FL, et al. 2002. Ethical Incentivesnot
Chris Hackler (University of Arkansas for Medi-
paymentFor organ donation. New England Journal
cal Sciences), Wayne Shelton (Albany College of of Medicine 346: 20022005.
Medicine), and Robert Talisse (Vanderbilt Univer-
Dewey, J. 1926. The quest for certainty. New York, NY:
sity) as well as comments of the anonymous re-
Milton, Balch and Co.
viewers. I would also like to thank my institution,
Fox, R., and J. Swazey. 1992. Spare parts: Organ re-
University of Arkansas for Medical Sciences, for its
placement in america. New York, NY: Oxford University
support of my scholarship.
Press.

REFERENCES Gill, M. B., and R. M. Sade. 2002. Paying for kid-


neys: The case against prohibition. Kennedy Institute
Ad Hoc Committee at Harvard Medical School to Ex-
of Ethics Journal 12(1): 1745.
amine the Definition of Brain Death. 1968. Report of
the Ad Hoc Committee at Harvard Medical School to Goya, M., R. L. Mehta, L. J. Schneiderman, and A. R.
examine the definition of brain death: A definition of Sehgal. 2002. Economic and health consequences of
irreversible coma. Journal of American Medical Asso- selling a kidney in India. Journal of the American Med-
ciation 105: 337340. ical Association 288(13): 15891593.
Annas, G. 1984. Life, liberty, and the pursuit of organ Gundle, K. 2005. Presumed consent: an international
sales. Hastings Center Report 14(1): 2223. comparison and possibilities for change in the United
States. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 14(1):
113118.
5. Given concerns that conscription would unduly trump
Jacob Arriola, K. R. 2005. Moving beyond attitudinal
the liberal democratic value of autonomy, presumed con-
barriers: understanding African Americans support for
sent policies might be reasonable outcomes of the moral
argument given. At the same time, arguments for pre- organ and tissue donation. Journal of the National
sumed consent have been based on the idea that we need Medical Association 97(3): 339350.
to find a morally acceptable way to get more organs to James, W. 1891. The moral philosopher and the moral
more transplant recipients (a good example is Gundle life. International Journal of Ethics 1: 330354.
2005), not that organ release is a moral obligation. In
fact, basing presumed consent policies on the idea that it Janssen, A., and S. Gevers. 2005. Explicit or presumed
will raise procurement rates may prove a weak foundation consent and organ donation post-mortem: Does it mat-
(see Janssen/Gevers 2005). ter? Medicine and Law 24(3): 575583.

July/August 2006, Volume 6, Number 4 ajob W27


The American Journal of Bioethics

Kishore, R. R. 2005. Human organs, scarcities, and sale: Murray, T. 1986. The gift of life must always remain
Morality revisited. Journal of Medical Ethics 31: 362 a gift organ donations and biotechnology industry.
365. Discover March: 9092.
Kluge, E. J. 1994. Drawing the ethical line between or- Nelson, J. L. 2003a. Hippocrates maze. New York, NY:
gan transplantation and lifestyle abuse. Canadian Med- Rowman & Littlefield.
ical Association Journal 150(5): 745746. Nelson, J. L. 2003b. Harming the dead and saving the
Koppelman, E. 2003. The dead donor rule and the living. American Journal of Bioethics 3(1): 1315.
concept of death. American Journal of Bioethics 3(1): Nelson, J. L. 2005. Trust and transplants. American
19. Journal of Bioethics 5(4): 2628.
Kreis, H. 2005. The question of organ procurement:
Robeznieks, A. 2004. AMA backs review of pre-
beyond charity. Nephrology, Dialysis, Transplantation
sumed consent on organ donations. http://www.ama-
20(7): 13031306.
assn.org/amednews/2004/07/05/prsa0705.htm. [ac-
Kunin, J. D. 2005. The search for organs: Halachic per- cessed May 22, 2006]
spectives on altruistic giving and the selling of organs.
Ross, W. D. 2003. The right and the good. Oxford, UK:
Journal of Medical Ethics 31: 269272.
Oxford University Press.
Lachs, J. 1979. On selling organs. Forum on Medicine
Scanlon, T. M. 2000. What we owe to each other. Cam-
11: 746747.
bridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Lam, W. A., and L. B. McCullough. 2000. Influ-
Singer, P. 1972. Famine, affluence, and morality. Philos-
ence of religious and spiritual values on the will-
ophy & Public Affairs 1: 229243.
ingness of ChineseAmericans to donate organs for
transplantation. Clinical Transplantation 14(5): 449 Spital, A. 2005. Conscription for cadaveric organs for
456. transplantation: A stimulating idea whose time has not
yet come. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics
Loewy, E. 1996. Of community, organs and obligations:
14(1): 107112.
Routine salvage with a twist. Theoretical Medicine
17(1): 6174. Steinberg, D. 2005. An opting in paradigm for kidney
transplants. American Journal of Bioethics 4(4): 414.
Mange, K. C., M. M. Joffe, and H. I. Fledman. 2001. Ef-
fect of the use or nonuse of long-term dialysis on the Truog, R. 2005. Are organs personal property or a soci-
subsequent survival of renal transplants from living etal resource? American Journal of Bioethics 5(4): 14
donors. New England Journal of Medicine 344(10): 16.
726731. United Network for Organ Sharing (UNOS) website,
Mill, J. S. 1975. On liberty. London, UK: Penguin Books. www.OPTN.org. [accessed May 22, 2006]
Moss, A. H., and M. Siegler. 1991. Should alcoholics Wilkinson, S., and E. Garrard. 1996. Bodily integrity and
compete for liver transplants? Journal of the American the sale of human organs. Journal of Medical Ethics
Medical Association 265(10): 12951298. 22(6): 334339.

W28 ajob July/August 2006, Volume 6, Number 4

Potrebbero piacerti anche