Sei sulla pagina 1di 239

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847HTL.

3D

i [11] 23.11.2013 10:53AM

Phase Theory
Phase Theory is the latest empirical and conceptual innovation in syntactic theory
within the Chomskyan generative tradition. Adopting a crosslinguistic perspective, this book provides an introduction to Phase Theory, tracing the development
of phases in minimalist syntax. It reviews both empirical and theoretical arguments in favor of phases, and examines the role phases play at the interface
with semantics and phonology. Analyzing current phasehood diagnostics,
it applies them in a systematic fashion to a broad range of syntactic categories,
both phases and non-phases. It concludes with a discussion of some of the more
contentious issues in Phase Theory, involving crosslinguistic variation with
respect to phasehood and the dynamic versus static nature of phases.
Barbara Citko is Associate Professor of Linguistics at the University of
Washington.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847SER.3D

ii

[22] 23.11.2013 10:44AM

Research Surveys in Linguistics


In large domains of theoretical and empirical linguistics, the needs of scholarly
communication are directly comparable to those in analytical and natural sciences.
Conspicuously lacking in the inventory of publications for linguists, compared to
those in the sciences, are concise, single-authored, non-textbook reviews of rapidly
evolving areas of inquiry. The series Research Surveys in Linguistics is intended to
ll this gap. It consists of well-indexed volumes that survey topics of signicant
theoretical interest on which there has been a proliferation of research in the last two
decades. The goal is to provide an efcient overview of, and entry into, the primary
literature for linguists both advanced students and researchers who wish to move
into, or stay literate in, the areas covered. Series authors are recognized authorities on
the subject matter, as well as clear, highly organized writers. Each book offers the
reader relatively tight structuring in sections and subsections, and a detailed index for
ease of orientation.
Previously published in this series
A Thematic Guide to Optimality Theory, John J. McCarthy
The Phonology of Tone and Intonation, Carlos Gussenhoven
Argument Realization, Beth Levin and Malka Rappaport Hovav
Lexicalization and Language Change, Laurel J. Brinton and Elizabeth Closs Traugott
Dening Pragmatics, Mira Ariel
Quantication, Anna Szabolcsi
Word Order, Jae Jung Song

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847TTL.3D

iii [33] 23.11.2013 10:36AM

Phase Theory
An Introduction

BARBARA CITKO
University of Washington

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847IMP.3D

iv

[44] 23.11.2013 10:52AM

University Printing House, Cambridge CB2 8BS, United Kingdom


Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York
Cambridge University Press is part of the University of Cambridge.
It furthers the Universitys mission by disseminating knowledge in the pursuit of
education, learning and research at the highest international levels of excellence.
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781107040847
Barbara Citko 2014
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception
and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,
no reproduction of any part may take place without the written
permission of Cambridge University Press.
First published 2014
Printed in the United Kingdom by MPG Printgroup Ltd, Cambridge
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication data
Citko, Barbara, 1970
Phase theory : an introduction / Barbara Citko.
pages cm. (Research surveys in linguistics)
ISBN 978-1-107-04084-7 (hardback)
1. Phraseology 2. Minimalist theory (Linguistics) 3. Grammar,
Comparative and general Syntax. 4. Generative grammar. I. Title.
P326.5.P45C48 2014
415dc23
2013040516
ISBN 978-1-107-04084-7 Hardback
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of
URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication,
and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain,
accurate or appropriate.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847TOC.3D

v [56] 23.11.2013 10:44AM

Contents

Acknowledgments
List of abbreviations

page vii
viii
1

Introduction
1

1.1
1.2
1.3
1.4
2

The Minimalist Program

General architecture
External and Internal Merge
Features
Agree

7
10
14
20

Introducing phases

23

2.1
2.2
2.3
2.4
2.5
2.6

23
27
29
31
41
46

Merge over Move preference


Motivating phases
Phasehood properties
Phase Impenetrability Condition
Multiple Spell-Out
Feature Inheritance

Phasehood diagnostics

58

3.1
3.2
3.3
3.4

58
60
66
67

Anatomy of a phasehood diagnostic


PF diagnostics
LF diagnostics
Syntactic diagnostics

71

Classic phases

4.1 CPs as phases


4.2 vPs as phases
4.3 DPs as phases
5

71
91
108

Other ph(r)ases

124

5.1 PrPs as phases


5.2 PPs as phases
5.3 AppIPs as phases

124
137
151
v

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847TOC.3D

vi

[56] 23.11.2013 10:44AM

vi

Contents

Variation in phasehood

161

6.1 Dynamic phases


6.2 Crosslinguistic variation
6.3 Non-simultaneous phases

161
168
177

Phases and the interfaces

185

7.1 Phases and PF


7.2 Phases and LF

185
199

Summary

205

References
Index

207
223

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847ACK.3D

vii [77] 23.11.2013 11:51AM

Acknowledgments

First, I would like to thank the many cohorts of students who took my graduate
syntax classes at the University of Washington. The idea for this book came from
you and all the questions you asked (that I may or may not have had answers to
at the time). I hope next time I will! I also want to thank all my colleagues in
the Department of Linguistics for creating an intellectually stimulating work
environment, and especially my fellow syntacticians, Edith Aldridge, Karen
Zagona and Julia Herschensohn, for encouragement and support, especially in
the nal stages of the project; and Toshi Ogihara for very kindly answering all my
last-minute semantic questions.
Portions of this book were written at the Whiteley Writing Center, a wonderful writing oasis (on an island!), which I thank for the good writing vibes. Some
parts were written when I was a visiting scholar at the Department of Linguistics
and Philosophy at MIT in the Fall of 2011. I thank the department for the
welcoming atmosphere it creates for all its visitors, and for all the inspiring
classes, talks and conversations I had while I was there. In particular, I would
like to thank David Pesetsky, Sabine Iatridou and Shigeru Miyagawa for their
openness and interest in my research. I also want to thank Andrew Winnard
and the whole editorial team at Cambridge University Press for their patience
and guidance throughout the project, Alexander Sugar for help proong the
manuscript and Brent Woo for help with the index.
Given that the literature on phases in syntactic theory is vast and evergrowing, it is impossible to do justice here to all the phenomena that bear on all
the issues surrounding phases, to all the literature on phases and to all the
researchers working on phases. I alone remain responsible for any omissions or
misinterpretations.
Last but not least, I thank my husband Randy for his support and perspective.
I dedicate this book to the memory of Icarus.

vii

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847LOA.3D

viii

[810] 23.11.2013 10:46AM

Abbreviations

The following list includes not only abbreviations used in this book but also the
abbreviations often used in the primary literature on phases.

ACC
ACD
ATB
AUGB
AUX
BPS
C
CHL
CAUS
C-I
CP
DNS
DP
ECM
EM
EPP
ERG
FEM
FI
FIFA
FIFB
FL
FP
G
H

phi-features
phonological component
semantic component
Accusative
Antecedent-Contained Deletion
across the board
approaching UG from below
Auxiliary
Bare Phrase Structure
Case
Computation of Human Language
Causative
conceptualintentional
Complementizer Phrase
Derivation of Narrow Syntax
Determiner Phrase
Exceptional Case Marking
External Merge
Extended Projection Principle
Ergative
Feminine
Feature Inheritance
Feature Inheritance from Above
Feature Inheritance from Below
language faculty
Functional Projection
Goal
Head

viii

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847LOA.3D

ix [810] 23.11.2013 10:46AM

List of abbreviations

HTA
IC
iF
IM
INTER
INDEF
iwh
LA
LBE
LCA
LDA
Lex
LF
LI
MASC
MOM
MSO
N
NEUT
NMLZ
NOM
NPI
NS
NSL
NSR
NUM
P
PART
PF
P-feature
PH
PIC
PL
PLA
PP
PrP
PST
Q
QP
QR
RNR
RP
SA

High Tone Anticipation


Interface Condition(s) or the Inclusiveness Condition
Interpretable Feature
Internal Merge
Interrogative
Indenite
interpretable wh-feature
Lexical Array
Left Branch Extraction
Linear Correspondence Axiom
Long-Distance Agree
Lexicon
Logical Form
Lexical Item
Masculine
Merge over Move
Multiple Spell-Out
Numeration
Neuter
Nominalizer
Nominative
Negative Polarity Item
Narrow Syntax
Null Subject Language
Nuclear Stress Rule
Number
Probe
Participle
Phonological Form
Periphery Feature
Phase
Phase Impenetrability Condition
Pair List or Plural
Properly Local Agreement
Prepositional Phrase
Predication Phrase
Past
Question or Interrogative
Quantier Phrase
Quantier Raising
Right Node Raising
Relator Phrase
Single Answer

ix

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847LOA.3D

SG
SM
SMT
S-O
SOR
SOT
T
TNP
TP
uF
uQ
val
VIR
vP
VPE

x [810] 23.11.2013 10:46AM

List of abbreviations

Singular
Sensorimotor
Strong Minimalist Thesis
Spell-Out
Subject to Object Raising
Sequence of Tense
Tense
Traditional Noun Phrase
Tense Phrase
uninterpretable or unvalued feature
uninterpretable Q feature
Feature Value
Virile
verb Phrase
VP Ellipsis

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847INT.3D

1 [16] 23.11.2013 10:49AM

Introduction

This research survey combines an introduction to Phase Theory with an assessment of the state of the art in Phase Theory. The term Phase Theory refers to a set
of theoretical innovations in post-2000 minimalism (Chomsky 2000, 2001, 2004,
2005, 2008).1 One of the core ideas in minimalism is the idea that the language
faculty is an optimal solution to the constraints imposed on it by the two cognitive
systems with which it interacts: the system of thought and the articulatory
perceptual system. What Phase Theory adds to this picture is the idea that the
language faculty interacts with these two cognitive systems at very specic points
during the syntactic derivation, and, consequently, that syntactic derivations are
constructed in chunks referred to as phases.2 In most general terms, phases
cannot be accessed by the narrow syntax once they are transferred to the
interfaces.
My goal in this survey is to combine an introduction to a given issue within
Phase Theory with an overview of the existing research on this issue (and an
assessment thereof), giving the reader a sense of what is fairly settled upon and
what is still under debate.3 The fact that there is lot of research that relies on
phases shows a need for a survey that situates phases in current syntactic theory,
introduces the technical details of Phase Theory, synthesizes the existing research

Chomsky in his writings is very careful about distinguishing a program from a theory, emphasizing
the programmatic nature of minimalism (see in particular Boeckx 2006 for a more detailed
discussion of this distinction). Chomsky does not use the term Phase Theory in his early writings
on phases but does so more recently: One goal of Phase Theory is to provide the mechanisms to
distinguish copies from repetitions, as straightforwardly as possible (Chomsky 2012: 3).
The resulting model is also sometimes referred to as a Multiple Spell-Out (MSO) model. The idea of
Multiple Spell-Out goes back to Uriagereka (1999) (see also Uriagereka 2012 for a fuller, booklength exposition).
There are a number of monographs, volumes and collections that focus on various aspects of Phase
Theory, which I build on and am intellectually indebted to (see, among others, Frascarelli 2006,
Gallego 2010, 2012, Grohmann 2009a, 2009b, 2009c, McGinnis & Richards 2005, and the individual
contributions in the two issues of Linguistic Analysis 33, guest-edited by Kleanthes Grohmann).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847INT.3D

2 [16] 23.11.2013 10:49AM

Introduction

on phases (pointing out issues that might be still contentious), outlines directions
for future research, and, last but not least, standardizes the notation.
Even though many (though not all) syntacticians (explicitly or implicitly)
assume the concept of a phase, there seems to be less of a consensus regarding
many of the most fundamental properties of phases, such as those listed in (1).
(1) a. How do we dene phases?
b. What categories count as phases?
c. Do the same categories count as phases with respect to semantic and phonological considerations?
d. Are phases dynamic or static?
e. Is there any crosslinguistic variation with respect to phasehood?
f. How do phases interact with the interfaces?

The fundamental question to answer before we can even begin to address


some of the questions listed above is in what sense a syntactic theory that assumes
phases is more adequate (in a descriptive, explanatory, or beyond-explanatory
adequacy kind of sense) than a syntactic theory that does not assume phases.4
This is the question we will be coming back to throughout the book. In the
remainder of this introduction, I provide a brief summary of each chapter.
Chapter 1 The Minimalist Program provides an overview of the core aspects
of the Minimalist Program. It outlines the general architecture of the minimalist
grammar, and lays the groundwork for the discussion in the following chapters by
focusing on the concepts that will be crucial to the understanding of phases, such
as the distinction between interpretable and uninterpretable features and the
concept of Spell-Out. This chapter is not meant as an introduction to (or survey
of ) minimalist syntax; however, readers less familiar with minimalism will nd
all the necessary concepts, terms and mechanisms introduced in this chapter.
Chapter 2 Motivating phases turns to phases themselves. It introduces the
concept of a phase, situating phases in the context of current minimalist
approaches to syntactic dependencies, and asking if syntactic theory with phases
is more adequate than a theory without phases, or a theory in which all phrases are
phases. This chapter also gives a historical perspective on phases, and addresses
some of the criticisms that have been levied in the literature against them, such as
Boeckx & Grohmanns (2007) critique of phases as barriers in disguise.
Even though the idea of a cycle, which is conceptually related to a phase, goes
back to the early days of generative grammar, the current concept of a phase rst
appeared in Chomskys (2000) Minimalist Inquiries, where phases (to be more
specic, lexical subarrays associated with phases) were introduced as a solution
to a problem arising from the so-called Merge over Move principle. Since then,
4

Following Chomsky (2004), I take beyond explanatory adequacy to refer to the why-questions about
language, captured by the following quote: In principle, then, we can seek a level of explanation
deeper than explanatory adequacy, asking not only what the properties of language are but also why
they are that way. (Chomsky 2004: 105).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847INT.3D

3 [16] 23.11.2013 10:49AM

Introduction

much research has focused on dening phases and formulating independent


phasehood diagnostics. The denitions of phases I survey in this chapter are
listed in (2).5
(2) a. Phases are propositional objects.
b. Phases are convergent objects.
c. Phases are objects interacting with the interfaces.
d. Phase heads are loci of uninterpretable features.
e. Phases are predication structures.
f. Phases are phrases.

From a diagnostic perspective, perhaps the most important aspect of Phase


Theory is the so-called Phase Impenetrability Condition, which deems a portion
of a phase impenetrable or inaccessible to operations from the outside. This
chapter also surveys the various versions of the Phase Impenetrability
Condition proposed in the literature, focusing on the empirical predictions they
make, and ways to unify them (see Mller 2004, Richards 2004, 2011, among
others). The Phase Impenetrability Condition is tightly linked to the concept of
Multiple Spell-Out, which I also elaborate on in this chapter, sorting through the
logical possibilities of how Multiple Spell-Out can proceed, i.e. spelling out to the
two interfaces at different points in the derivation, for example. Finally, this
chapter introduces the concept of Feature Inheritance, as developed by Chomsky
(2008) and Richards (2008), which is a logical consequence of dening phase
heads as hosts of uninterpretable features. If uninterpretable features are a
property of phase heads, the only way non-phase heads can get them is via
Feature Inheritance.
Chapter 3 Phasehood diagnostics turns to the many diagnostics that have
been proposed in the literature, a subset of which will serve as the basis for the
discussion of specic phases (CPs, vPs, DPs, PPs etc.) in the chapters that follow,
and the arguments in favor of (or against) these categories being phases. A
common thread in many existing characterizations of phases is that they should
exhibit a certain amount of independence and coherence at the interfaces. This,
however, only raises the question of what it means for a given category (a
candidate for a phase) to be semantically or phonologically independent and
coherent. Furthermore, are there any phasehood diagnostics that do not fall neatly
into either of the two groups (PF versus LF diagnostics): purely syntactic or
purely morphological diagnostics? Given such rather vague existing characterizations of phases, this chapter focuses on the more tangible questions that can be
(and have been) asked to establish the phasehood of a given category, which I list
in (3) below. It examines these questions with a critical eye towards establishing
genuine phasehood diagnostics, and avoiding those that might instead be diagnosing something other than phasehood (such as constituency or phrasal status).
5

See also Boeckx (2006), Boeckx & Grohmann (2007), Den Dikken (2007) and Gallego (2010) for a
discussion of these different views of phases, and of the problems some of them raise.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847INT.3D

4 [16] 23.11.2013 10:49AM

Introduction

(3) a. Is XP a domain for feature valuation?


b. Is X the locus of uninterpretable features?
c. Does X trigger Spell-Out?
d. Is XP a phonological domain?
e. Can the complement of X be elided?
f. Can XP be moved?

The Phase Impenetrability Condition also gives rise to a number of tangible


phasehood diagnostics, coming mostly from the realm of successive cyclic
movement through the edge of the phase, which in turn can be diagnosed by
afrmative answers to the following questions:
(4) a. Can the moved element be interpreted at the edge of the phase?
b. Can the moved element be pronounced at the edge of the phase?
c. Can the moved element leave something behind at the edge of the phase?

The discussion of phasehood diagnostics also raises the question of whether there
is any crosslinguistic variation with respect to phasehood. This is the issue which
I come back to in Chapter 6. While variation with respect to whether a given
language has phases or not seems highly unlikely and implausible, given the
conceptual arguments in favor of having phases to begin with (such as reducing
computational load and being independently motivated by the interfaces), it is
certainly possible for languages to differ with respect to what categories count as
phases.
Chapter 4 Classic phases discusses in detail three categories that are commonly assumed to be phases CPs, vPs and DPs and applies the diagnostics
established in Chapter 3 to these categories.6 The phasehood status of CP is
relatively easy to establish: the evidence in favor of successive cyclicity from the
literature on A-bar dependencies is typically taken as evidence for CPs being phases
(see, for example, Lahne 2008 for an illuminating overview). The evidence includes
phenomena like wh-copying (Felser 2004, Manetta 2010, McDaniel 1989, among
many others), scope marking (Dayal 1996, Lutz Mller & von Stechow 2000,
Stepanov 2000, among others), complementizer agreement (Carstens 2003,
Carstens & Diercks 2011, Haegeman 1992, Haegeman & Van Koppen 2011,
Zwart 1993, 1997), wh-quantier stranding (McCloskey 2000, 2001), reconstruction (Barss 1986, 2001) and left branch extraction (Wiland 2010). The evidence in
favor of vPs being phases is similar in spirit. This chapter also reviews the debate on
whether unaccusative and passive vPs constitute phases, as argued for by Legate
(2003), and against by Den Dikken (2006a). While many of the facts that are
typically deemed to bear on the issue of C or v being a phase head might be given
6

The discussion in Chapters 4 and 5 is a sequence of case studies. There are other categories that are
conspicuously absent from the discussion (APs, AdvPs, various functional projections in the left
periphery of a clause) whose phasehood we might wonder about. I thank Kleanthes Grohmann for
raising this issue.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847INT.3D

5 [16] 23.11.2013 10:49AM

Introduction

alternative explanations that do not necessarily rely on movement through the


specier of CP or vP, such accounts typically still posit a relationship between C
(endowed with uninterpretable features of the requisite sort) and the wh-pronoun in
its domain. This also points towards C being a phase head, given that only phase
heads are assumed to be the loci of uninterpretable features. More generally, I hope
to show in this chapter that phase-theoretical accounts have the advantage of
establishing connections between sets of facts that otherwise remain isolated and
require independent explanations. For example, why should complementizer agreement phenomena and locality restrictions on movement involve C? Or why would
Austronesian extraction restriction and constraints on parasitic gap formation be
sensitive to the properties of little v? Granting these projections a privileged
syntactic status (namely, the status of a phase) brings us closer towards understanding why syntactic phenomena should cluster around them.
The idea that DP might be a phase as well, explored by Matushansky (2005),
Hiraiwa (2005) and Svenonius (2004), among others, should not come as a
surprise, given the many structural and interpretive parallels between CPs and
DPs, discussed in the literature going back to the very early days of generative
grammar. However, since CPs contain other phases (namely vPs), an interesting
question is whether DPs contain other phases as well. In order to tackle this
question, this chapter also addresses the internal structure of DPs, motivating the
need for DP-internal projections such as NumberP, PersonP or ClassierP, and
asking which of them, if any, might be phases as well.
Chapter 5 Other ph(r)ases turns to categories whose phasehood status is
somewhat more controversial, and still debated in the literature: Predication
Phrases, Prepositional Phrases and Applicative Phrases. All of them have been
argued to constitute phases (see, for example, Abels 2003, Radkevich 2010 on
PPs as phases and McGinnis 2001 on Applicative Phrases as phases); yet they are
not considered to fall into the widely accepted phasehood canon. What makes
these categories somewhat more controversial is that many other questions about
them have to be answered rst before their phasehood can be entertained. For
example, if phasehood is a property of functional categories, the question that
needs to be resolved for prepositions is whether they are functional or lexical (or
both or neither, depending on the preposition).
Chapter 6 Variation in phasehood takes up the issue of whether there is any
crosslinguistic variation with respect to phasehood. There are two questions to
consider here: the question of whether non-phase heads can acquire phasehood
status in the course of the derivation (and conversely, whether phase heads can
lose their phasehood status in the course of the derivation), and the question of
whether different categories can count as phases with respect to phonological and
semantic considerations. The former scenario (a head becoming a phase or
ceasing to be a phase) has been argued to arise as a result of head movement
(Phase Extension of Den Dikken 2007 or Phase Sliding of Gallego 2010). The
latter scenario (a category being a PF phase but not an LF phase or vice versa) has
been explored by Marui (2005) as a way to handle total reconstruction and

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847INT.3D

6 [16] 23.11.2013 10:49AM

Introduction

covert movement and by Felser (2004) to handle wh-copying. This chapter also
addresses crosslinguistic variation with respect to phasehood: if phases are
dynamic and head movement can extend phasehood, a certain amount of variation will come from independent considerations (such as the presence or absence
of certain types of head movement). Variation in phasehood can also follow from
variation in lexical inventories.
Chapter 7 Phases at the interfaces examines the roles phases play at the
interfaces, putting them in the more general context of the syntaxphonology and
syntaxsemantics interface. With respect to the PF interface, it focuses on the
questions of whether phases (or Spell-Out domains) are relevant and substantive
phonological units, and how these phasal or Spell-Out units are manipulated by
phonology. This chapter examines the role phases play in determining linear
order (see Fox & Pesetskys (2005) Cyclic Linearization) and nuclear stress (see
Adger 2007, Kahnemuyipour 2003, 2004, 2005, Kratzer & Selkirk 2007, among
others).
The potential evidence for the signicance of phases at the syntaxsemantics
interface comes not only from phenomena like scope ambiguities (on the assumption that Quantier Raising is constrained by phasehood) and the propositional
status of phases both of which feature prominently as phasehood diagnostics
but also from the idea that the boundary between vP and CP phasal domains
corresponds to the distinction between nuclear scope and restrictive domain in the
tripartite quanticational structure, as proposed explicitly by Biskup (2009a).
Chapter 8 Summary provides a brief summary and conclusion.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

7 [722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

1
The Minimalist Program

1.1 General architecture


The current chapter offers a birds eye view of the Minimalist Program. It is not
meant as a comprehensive introduction (or a thorough overview) of minimalism. Rather, its goal is to give readers less familiar with minimalism the
necessary and sufcient background to follow the discussion of phases in
the rest of this book. For the sake of clarity, the technical terms that I will be
referring to throughout the book will be given in bold when they are rst
introduced. For a more thorough textbook-style introduction to minimalism, I
refer the interested reader to Adger (2003) and Hornstein, Nunes and Grohmann
(2005) and the references therein.
What came to be known as the Minimalist Program was articulated explicitly
in the early nineties with the publication of works such as Chomskys (1991)
Some Notes on Economy of Derivation and Representation, and his (1993) A
Minimalist Program for Linguistic Theory, both of which later became two of
the four chapters of Chomskys (1995) The Minimalist Program. As Chomsky
emphasizes in his writings, minimalism is grounded in the Principles and
Parameters model, which gave us the beginnings of an understanding of which
properties of language are universal (and perhaps unique to it), and which ones
are subject to crosslinguistic variation. This, in turn, led to deeper questions,
which are at the core of minimalist theorizing nowadays. These are questions that
go beyond explanatory adequacy, alluded to above, such as the question of why
language is the way it is. Computational efciency and interface conditions play a
central role, as stated succinctly in the following quote from Beyond
Explanatory Adequacy.
(1) Its [the Minimalist Programs, B.C.] task is to examine every device (principle,
idea, etc.) that is employed in characterizing languages to determine to what
extent it can be eliminated in favor of a principled account in terms of general
conditions of computational efciency and the interface condition [emphasis
mine, B.C.] that the organ must satisfy for it to function at all.
(Chomsky 2004: 106)

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

8 [722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

The Minimalist Program

This is also clear in Chomskys discussion of the so-called three factors in


language design and three types of conditions in language acquisition (see
Chomsky 2005 in particular). These are listed in (2ac), and they help determine how a child gets from the initial state (S0) of linguistic competence to
the nal state: the fully formed adult state of linguistic competence. (2b) are
the interface conditions, and (2c) are the general properties of efcient
computation.
(2) a. unexplained elements of S0
b. IC (the principled part of S0)
c. general properties (Chomsky 2004: 106)

The minimum that the language faculty (FL) has to accomplish is to interface
with language-external systems. The two external systems in question are
the sensorimotor (SM) system and the conceptual-intentional (C-I) system.
The conditions imposed by these two external systems are referred to as
Legibility Conditions, Bare Output Conditions or Interface Conditions
(IC).1 The Strong Minimalist Thesis (SMT), given in (3), states that language
is designed to interface with the external systems in an optimum way.2
(3) The substantive thesis is that language design may really be optimal in some
respects, approaching a perfect solution to minimal design specications.
(Chomsky 2000: 93)

The general architecture of the language faculty is as follows. Language has three
components: Narrow Syntax (NS), the phonological component and the
semantic component .3 For the most part, we will be concerned here with
Narrow Syntax and its computational processes.
Each derivation starts with a set of lexical items which are manipulated in the
course of the derivation by the syntactic operations Merge and Agree. I will discuss
these two operations in more detail in Sections 1.2 and 1.4, respectively. The
lexical item is, strictly speaking, a bundle of features, not a primitive syntactic
object (hence the quotes).4 This set of lexical items is called a Lexical Array (LA)
and is represented as an unordered set. A Lexical Array augmented by information
1
2

To the best of my knowledge, these terms are used interchangeably.


The formulation of the Strong Minimalist Thesis in Minimalist Inquiries (which is the one given in
(3)) is slightly different from the one Chomsky gives in Beyond Explanatory Adequacy, where he
formulates it as in (i):
(i) The set of unexplained elements of S0 is empty. (Chomsky 2004: 106)

S0 refers to the genetically determined initial state in the process of language acquisition, which is
what UG provides.
There is no PF or LF cycle and thus there are no PF or LF operations. The terms are used to refer to
PF or LF representations. The terms PF interface and LF interface are used to refer to the interface
with SM or C-I systems, respectively.
This assumes something like the Late Vocabulary Insertion model of Distributed Morphology of
Halle & Marantz (1993) and much later work.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

9 [722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

General architecture

on how many times each lexical item is selected from the lexicon is called a
Numeration (N). This information is represented by the subscripts. In simple
cases, Numerations and Lexical Arrays are equivalent, as shown in (4bc).
(4) a. Icarus likes nuts.
b. LA = {Icarus, likes, nuts, v, T, C}
c. N = {Icarus1, likes1, nuts1, v1, T1, C1}

The two diverge when a single item is used more than once in a given derivation,
as in the infamous example given in (5a).5
(5) a. Buffalo buffalo Buffalo buffalo buffalo buffalo Buffalo buffalo.
(Pinker 1994: 2006, crediting Annie Senghas)
b. LA = {Buffalo, buffalo, buffalo, C, v, T}
c. N = {Buffalo3, buffalo2, buffalo2, C2, v2, T2}

However, one does not need to resort to exotic examples of this sort to show how
Lexical Arrays and Numerations differ; relatively simple sentences with any level
of embedding make the same point:
(6) a. Icarus thinks he likes nuts.
b. LA = {Icarus, thinks, he, likes, nuts, v, T, C}
c. N = {Icarus1, thinks1, he1, likes1, nuts1, v2, T2, C2}

The output of a Narrow Syntax derivation is a pair of representations <PHON,


SEM>, which is accessed by the two interfaces dened above: the SM and the C-I
interface. The derivation converges if the two representations satisfy the conditions imposed by the two interfaces; otherwise it crashes.6 For a given representation to meet the Interface Conditions simply means it has to be legible to the
external systems; hence the term Legibility Conditions. The question of what it
means to be legible at a given interface is not trivial. A common and intuitively
correct understanding of this concept of legibility is the following: an expression
is legible at a given interface level (PF or LF) only if it consists of features that can
be interpreted by the language-external systems: the SM and C-I system, respectively. But, of course, making convergence contingent on the presence of features
that can only be interpreted at the interfaces raises an obvious question of what
features the two interfaces can interpret. It seems quite plausible to assume that
5

Its notoriety comes from lexical ambiguity, of which it provides a very extreme illustration, not from
the distinction between a lexical array, which in this case contains distinct lexical items buffalo (i.e.
the proper name Buffalo, the common noun buffalo, and the less commonly used transitive verb to
buffalo meaning to bully) and the Numeration that includes multiple occurrences of each of them.
The following paraphrase helps distinguish the different meanings of buffalo:
(i) The buffalo from Buffalo that (another) buffalo from Buffalo bullies himself bullies (yet another)
buffalo from Buffalo.

See, however, Frampton & Gutmann (2002) for a proposal that syntax only generates convergent
derivations, and Preminger (2011) for a proposal that having unvalued features does not always lead
to a crash.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

10

[722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

10

The Minimalist Program

the SM interface can interpret features having to do with linear order (if such
exist), syllable structure, prosodic structure or intonation. The C-I interface, on
the other hand, should be able to interpret features having to do with scope,
quantication, referentiality, specicity, propositional status etc. Neither interface
can interpret formal features, such as structural case features or categorial features. Since features play such a major role in minimalism and there are quite a
few contentious issues surrounding them, we will devote an entire section to them
(Section 1.3).
The three basic operations that manipulate lexical items selected from the
lexicon are External Merge, Internal Merge and Agree. These three, in conjunction with a more detailed discussion of features, are the focus of the next three
sections.

1.2 External and Internal Merge


Recursion, the property of language that allows smaller units to combine
iteratively to form larger units forming hierarchically structured objects, and
displacement, the property that gives us the intuition that syntactic objects can
surface in one position but be understood as belonging in another position, are
two very fundamental (perhaps the most fundamental) properties of language.
Chomsky (2004) distinguishes two kinds of Merge, External Merge (EM) and
Internal Merge (IM), to capture these two fundamental phenomena. External
Merge is the basic concatenation operation responsible for recursion in language.
It takes two objects (such as X and Y in (7a), which have been rst selected
from the Numeration), and combines them into one bigger object, as shown in
(7b).7 External Merge is a recursive operation; one of these two objects could
7

Elsewhere, I have argued that Merge can also create structures in which a single object can end up
shared between two objects, referring to this type of Merge as Parallel Merge (see Citko 2011b and
the references therein), illustrated in (iii). Parallel Merge combines the properties of External
Merge and Internal Merge. Before Merge takes place, Z and YP are disjoint (as in External Merge)
but Z merges with a subpart of YP (as in Internal Merge).
(i) Merge X and Y, Project Y

YP
Y

XP

(ii) (Parallel) Merge X and Z, Project Z

YP
Y

ZP
XP

Chomsky (2007) excludes such a possibility on the grounds that it requires new operations and
conditions on what counts as a copy, hence additional properties of UG (Chomsky 2007: 8, note 10).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

11

[722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

External and Internal Merge

11

itself be the output of a prior Merge operation, as shown in (7d), where the
complex object that is the output of (7b) merges with Z.8
(7) a. Select X and Y from the Numeration
b. Merge X and Y

X
X

c. Select Z from the Numeration


d. Merge Z with X

Z
Z

X
Y

Following Chomsky (1994), I assume a bare-bones approach to phrase structure, referred to as Bare
Phrase Structure (BPS), in which the X-bar status of a given projection (in particular, whether it is a
head (X0), a phrase (XP) or an intermediate projection (X0 )) is not a primitive of the theory, as it can
always be derived from the structure in which it appears. Thus a head is an element that is not a
projection of another element of the same type. It can (but it does not have to) project further. A
phrase is an element that does not project any further. Again, it can, but it does not have to, be a
projection of another element of the same type. The representations in (7ad) are BPS representations; the ones in (i) and (ii) are their more traditional X-bar theoretical counterparts, with the ones in
(ib) and (iib) simplied in that they lack vacuous intermediate projections.
(i)

a. XP

b.
X

X
(ii)

a.

XP
X

YP

YP

ZP

b.
Z

ZP
Z

XP

XP
X

YP

X
X

YP

Even though I will be using representations of the kind given in (ib)(iib) throughout this book,
mostly for familiaritys sake, I do assume a BPS approach throughout. The advantages of such an
approach are twofold. First, it allows a given element to be simultaneously a head and a phrase,
something that the behavior of clitics suggests has to be allowed in the grammar. Y in (7b) and (7d) is
such an element; it is a head because it is not a projection of another Y and it is a phrase because it
does not project any further. Second, BPS dispenses with vacuous intermediate projections, a
welcome move from the perspective of the Strong Minimalist Thesis (SMT).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

12

[722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

12

The Minimalist Program

The output of External Merge could also be represented in set notation. (8a) is
equivalent to (7b) and (8b) to (7d).
(8) a. {X, {X, Y}}
b. {Z, {Z, {X, {X, Y}}}}

It is standard to assume that the result of Merge also has to have a label, bolded in
(8ab) above.9 The label is determined by one of the two merged elements; other
options would violate the Inclusiveness Condition (IC), which prohibits the introduction of new elements in the course of the derivation. Any label other than X or Y
in (8a) (and other than Z and X in (8b)) would be a violation of this condition.
Chomsky (1995) discusses two other logical possibilities. In a set consisting of two
elements (such as X and Y in (8a)), the label could also be the intersection of X and Y
or the union of X and Y. However, he excludes the rst option on the grounds that the
intersection in many cases is a null set. The second option is excluded because
the union of X and Y is contradictory if X and Y differ in features, as is the case when
one is N and the other V, for example. This leaves us with only one option: either for
X or Y to project as the label. The question of which of the two it is, or the even more
fundamental question of whether labels are necessary at all, is far from being settled.
A common and fairly intuitive idea is that the object which has its selectional feature
checked as a result of Merge is the object that determines the label. For example,
when a verb or a preposition merges with a noun, this verb (or preposition) has its
selectional feature satised via the Merge operation. This means that the label is
going to be determined by this verb or preposition.10,11 Many existing labeling
algorithms make reference to selection; the one from Cecchetto & Donati (2010),
given in (9) below, is a representative example:12

10

11

An interesting issue is whether all the features of X determine the label, or only a subset thereof.
While it seems clear (and commonly assumed) that categorial features (N, V, D etc.) are part of the
label, what other features need to project is somewhat less clear (see Citko 2008a, 2011b,
Cecchetto & Donati 2010, Donati & Cecchetto 2011, for a discussion of this and related issues).
Things get a little more complicated if c-selection is removed from our syntactic toolkit, as
Chomsky suggests in Beyond Explanatory Adequacy (2004).
Chomsky (2008) proposes a different labeling algorithm, given in (i) below, which does not make
reference to selection.
(i) In {H, }, H a lexical item (LI), H is the label.
If is internally merged to forming {, }then the label of is the label of {, }
(Chomsky 2008: 145)

12

Other examples similar in spirit, as also noted by Cecchetto & Donati (2010) and Gallego (2010)
include those proposed by Adger (2003), Pesetsky & Torrego (2006) and Boeckx (2008b):
(i) The head is the syntactic object which selects in any Merge operation. (Adger 2003: 91)
(ii) If and merge, some feature F of must probe F on . (Pesetsky & Torrego 2006)
(ii) The label of {, } is whichever of or probes the other, where the Probe = Lexical Item whose uF
gets valued. (Boeckx 2008b: 96)

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

13

[722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

External and Internal Merge

13

(9) The label of a syntactic object {, } is the feature(s) that act(s) as a Probe of the
merging operation creating {, }. (Cecchetto & Donati 2010: 245)

Chomsky (2004) considers the possibility that the grammar requires no labels
whatsoever (see also Collins 2002, Gallego 2010, Seely 2006, among others).13
While intuitively appealing from the perspective of the Strong Minimalist
Thesis, eliminating labels raises some non-trivial issues, such as how
selection or relativized minimality works. I will not discuss these issues here
(as they strike me as tangential to the issue of phases. Instead, I refer the
interested reader to Citko (2008a, 2011b) and the references therein for
relevant discussion, pointing to the conclusion that labels are not dispensable.
One argument often adduced against the existence of labels comes from the
Inclusiveness Condition. However, if a label is simply a copy of the features of
one of the two merged elements (or more likely, of a subset of its features),
inclusiveness is not violated.
Internal Merge, which as Chomsky suggests in Beyond Explanatory
Adequacy (2004) is a very natural way to capture movement, is similar to
External Merge in that it takes two objects and combines them to form one larger
object. The only difference is that one of these two objects is already part of the
other one (hence the term Internal Merge). (10) below provides an illustration; Y
undergoes Internal Merge with X or, to use more traditional terminology, moves
to the specier of X.
(10) Internal Merge of X and Y14

a.

X
Y

b.
X

X EPP Y

X
X
X EPP

The label in Internal Merge structures is determined by the element that drives
movement. In (10ab), for example, it is some feature of X that drives movement
of Y to its specier. I assume that the feature in question is the EPP feature, which
is checked by this movement. Checking is marked by a strikethrough. In what
13

14

However, Chomsky (2013) seems to depart from this conclusion, and points out a number of cases
in which the lack of labels forces movement. This suggests that in other (non-movement) cases,
labels have to be in principle available.
(10a) represents movement (Internal Merge in our terms) in a familiar Copy and Merge notation,
whereas (10b) does so in a way that reects the term Internal Merge perhaps a little more
directly. Both are BPS-style representations. Strictly speaking, the movement illustrated here
(i.e. movement of a complement to a specier of the same head) might be banned by independent
anti-locality principles, which I discuss in more detail in Chapters 4 and 5.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

14

14

[722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

The Minimalist Program

follows, I use the term valuation to refer what used to be known as checking and
reserve the term checking for Extended Projection Principle (EPP) feature
checking, the only remnant of checking in the current system.
The third operation that plays a crucial role in minimalist syntax is Agree.
Since it is an operation that affects features, let me digress briey and discuss
features rst. This is the focus of the next section, which dicusses syntactic
features and the role they play in Narrow Syntax.

1.3 Features
Examples of syntactic features that populate syntactic literature include categorial features (such as N features or V features), case features, -features
(gender, number, person), EPP features, wh-features, and Q features, among
others. Features play a crucial role in minimalism in that they drive syntactic
operations.
Features come in two guises: Interpretable Features (iF) and
Uninterpretable Features (uF). Chomsky (2001, 2004) reduces the distinction
between these two types to feature valuation. Uninterpretable features are simply
features that enter the derivation unvalued, whereas interpretable ones are the
ones that come with inherently specied feature values:
(11) An uninterpretable feature F must be distinguished somehow in LEX from
interpretable features. The simplest way, introducing no new devices, is to
enter F without value: for example, [uNumber]. That is particularly natural
because the value is redundant, determined by Agree. (Chomsky 2004: 116)

I will use the following notation to distinguish these two types, where val stands
for feature value.
(12) a. Interpretable feature: iF[val] (e.g. iT[past], i[3sg, masc])
b. Uninterpretable feature: uF[ ] (e.g. uCase[ ], u[ ])

In Minimalist Inquiries (2000), Chomsky takes the presence of uninterpretable


features to be an imperfection from the perspective of the Strong Minimalist
Thesis, since the existence of such features is not forced by Bare Output
Conditions. Interestingly, though, he takes this imperfection to be linked to
another imperfection in the system: movement. Uninterpretable features drive
movement. Perhaps these devices [uninterpretable features, B.C.] are used to
yield the dislocation property (Chomsky 2000: 121). The fact that these two
imperfections are related is somewhat suspect, and it opens up the possibility
that they might not be imperfections after all. This is indeed the view Chomsky
takes in Beyond Explanatory Adequacy, where he takes movement to be
Internal Merge.
The concept of interpretability assumed here is a relative notion in that
it refers to interpretability with respect to one of the two (or perhaps both)
interfaces: the C-I interface and the SM interface. Being interpretable at a given
interface means containing features that this interface can interpret. For example,

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

15

[722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

Features

15

it seems plausible to assume the C-I interface can interpret features that have
some semantic import; examples of such features might be features involving
tense (past, present, future (and null, on some accounts)), aspect, quantication or
-features (person, number and gender). The SM interface, on the other hand,
can interpret features that are relevant for articulation. This allows us to distinguish features that are interpretable at a given interface from features which the
interface cannot interpret: a feature is interpretable at a given interface if it makes
a distinction between two representations at this interface.15,16 Svenonius
(2007a) (see also Adger & Svenonius 2011 for relevant discussion) puts it
succinctly as follows:
(13) A feature F is an X feature iff F can constitute a distinction between two different
X representations.(Svenonius 2007a: 375)

Crucially, a given feature is not inherently interpretable or uninterpretable.


It can be interpretable in one position but not in another, or at one interface but
not the other. This, in turn, depends on what lexical item the feature in question
is a feature of. Perhaps the most straightforward illustration comes from the
domain of -features. These features are typically taken to be interpretable
on nouns but not interpretable on verbs, which reects the intuition that verbs
agree with nouns and not vice versa. One way to think about it is that nouns are
selected from the Numeration inherently specied for these features. Verbs,
however, are selected from the Numeration unspecied. The following examples
from Polish, a language with grammatical gender distinctions, provide an
illustration.17 In (14), the noun papuga parrot is lexically specied as a

15

16

This view of interpretable features bears some resemblance to distinctive features, not an unwelcome result. Distinctive features in phonology are features that distinguish between two phonological representations. By analogy, we could think of features that are interpretable at the C-I
interface as distinctive semantic features.
Svenonius also makes the following distinction between module-internal features (for example,
syntax-internal features) and interface features (for example, syntaxsemantics features). Features
that have no semantic import at all, such as class features, or arguably EPP features, provide good
examples of syntax-internal features.
(i) For any F, and any modules X and Y,
a. F is an X-internal feature iff F is an X feature and not a feature of any other module.
b. F is an X-Y interface feature iff F is an X feature and a Y feature. (Svenonius 2007a: 375)

17

On one view, any syntax-internal feature is an uninterpretable feature. Svenonius, however,


gives uninterpretable features a narrower denition: uninterpretable features for him are
those features that are not translated or interpreted in the mapping from one module to
another.
I use English glosses for the sake of clarity. Also, the use of actual lexical items in the Numeration is
misleading. Since, in this case, the verb enters the derivation with its inectional features unvalued,
it is more accurate to think of the Numeration as consisting of feature bundles and the derivation as
manipulating these feature bundles. The use of small caps is meant to capture this intuition.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

16

[722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

16

The Minimalist Program

third-person singular feminine noun; the presence of third-person singular feminine agreement on the verb, however, is a result of run-of-the-mill subjectverb
agreement.18 In (15), on the other hand, the noun ptak bird is specied as a thirdperson singular masculine noun and the verb agrees with it.
(14) a. Papuga

siedziaa
parrot.3SG.FEM sit.PST.3SG.FEM
A parrot sat on a tree.

na
on

drzewie.
tree

na
on

drzewie.
tree

[Polish]

b. N = {PARROTi[3SG.FEM], . . ., SITu[ ], }
(15) a. Ptak

siedzia
bird.3SG.MASC sit.PST.3SG.MASC
A bird sat on a tree.

b. N = {BIRDi[3SG.MASC], . . ., SITu[ ], }

The idea that -features are always interpretable on nouns has sometimes been
questioned in the relevant literature. We have seen above (note 18) that number
might be different from other features in this respect. Legate (2002, 2012) also
raises some issues for the way Chomsky characterizes the distinction between
interpretable and uninterpretable features, pointing out that it is not clear in what
sense gender features in languages with non-natural gender are semantically

18

Number is different from person and gender. For most nouns, gender specication is inherent and
invariant; the Polish noun ksika book is always third person feminine but it can be either singular or
plural. This suggests that number might not be inherent to the noun itself in the same way person and
gender are. One way to implement it is to think of Number as being uninterpretable on the noun but
interpretable on a higher Number head, as shown in (i) (see Danon 2011 for a more concrete proposal).

DP

(i)

NumP
NP

NumiNum[val]

NiPers[val]
iGen[val]
uNum[ ]

However, there do exist nouns that can be either feminine or masculine (such as natural gender
marked nouns in (ii)), or nouns that are always singular or plural (such as so-called pluralia tantum
nouns in (iii)).
(ii) aktor/aktorka

actor/actress

lekarz/lekarka

male doctor/female doctor

pilot/pilotka

male pilot/female pilot

(iii) spodnie
nozyczki

pants
scissors

Since little hinges on this distinction as far as the specics of Phase Theory are concerned, I will
abstract away from it in what follows.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

17

[722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

Features

17

interpretable. Consider, for example, the noun book: in Russian it is feminine, in


French masculine, and in German neuter, as shown in (16ac).
(16) a. eta
this.3SG.FEM
b. un
a.3SG.MASC
c. ein
a.3sg.NEUT

kniga
book3SG.FEM
livre
book.3SG.MASC
Buch
book.3SG.NEUT

[Russian]
[French]
[German]

The mismatches between syntactic number and semantic number (discussed


by Munn 1999, for example) raise similar issues. A noun like group or committee is syntactically singular but semantically plural. Does this mean that
its interpretable number feature is singular or plural? Given that interpretability
in this case refers to the semantic interface, it seems that it should be plural, but
then the question is why (at least in American English) it determines singular
verb agreement. So perhaps a better distinction is between inherently/lexically
specied features (which may or may not map into semantically relevant features
but which can provide values to other features) and those that receive their
specication in the course of a syntactic derivation.
The idea that the same feature can be interpretable in one location
but uninterpretable in another one raises the question of whether every interpretable feature has an uninterpretable counterpart and vice versa: whether every
uninterpretable feature has an interpretable counterpart. For features such
as -features, the answer to both questions seems to be yes. -features, as
we saw above, are interpretable on nouns but uninterpretable on verbs. What
about other features? Tense features (i.e. past, present, future) have to be interpretable somewhere; the question is where and what their uninterpretable
counterparts are. It is generally assumed that the ComplementizerTense complex provides tense information; this suggests that tense features are interpretable on these heads in spite of the fact that in many languages these
features are realized on verbs, as pointed out by Pesetsky & Torrego (2007).
If tense is interpreted on T and it needs an uninterpretable counterpart, the
tense feature on the verb comes to mind as its uninterpretable counterpart, as
shown in (17).
(17) TiT[PST]

walkeduT[PST]

A slightly different explanation (but not one that is incompatible with tense
feature on the verb being uninterpretable) comes from Pesetsky and Torregos
(2001) work on case. In their view, Nominative case is an instance of an uninterpretable T feature on the subject:
(18) TiT[PST]

DPuT[NOM]

In a similar spirit, Svenonius (2002) reanalyzes the Accusative case feature as an


uninterpretable Aspect feature (uAsp). Support for such a reanalysis comes from
languages like Turkish or Finnish (see En 1991, Kiparsky 1998, Megerdoomian

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

18

[722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

18

The Minimalist Program

2000, among others), in which Accusative case marks aspectual notions such as
delimitedness or specicity:
(19) a. Ali

[Turkish]

(20) a. Matti

[Finnish]

bir
kitab
ald.
Ali one book.ACC bought
A book is such that Ali bought it.
b. Ali
bir
kitap
ald.
Ali
one
book
bought
Ali bought some book or other.
luk-i
kirja-t
(tunni-ssa).
Matti-SG/NOM read-PST/3SG book-PL-ACC (hour-INESS)
Matti read the books (in an hour).
b. Matti
luk-i
kirjo-j-a
(tunni-n).
Matti-SG/NOM read-PST/3SG book-PL-PART (hour-ACC)
Matti read books (for an hour). (Megerdoomian 2000: 31617)

The mechanism responsible for valuing unvalued features is called Agree.


Since Agree is the subject of the next section, for now all we need to know
is that Agree values uninterpretable features. I use the notation in (21) to
capture this distinction. Val stands for any feature value complex, empty
brackets signify the lack of value, and lled brackets signify valued
features. The only two possibilities are valued interpretable features and unvalued uninterpretable features; other combinations, to which I turn shortly,
would be contradictions in terms.
(21) a. valued/interpretable features: iF[val]
b. unvalued/uninterpretable features: uF[ ]

Uninterpretable features have to be valued in the course of the derivation. If


there are only two types of features, uninterpretable/unvalued and interpretable/valued, providing a value to an uninterpretable feature will make it
indistinguishable from a feature that was interpretable (i.e. it had a value)
to begin with. Furthermore, if unvalued features need to be deleted by the
time of Transfer to the interfaces, there is no way to know which features
need to be deleted, as they are all valued by the time of Transfer. This gives
rise to the following paradox, discussed by Epstein & Seely (2002), Richards
(2008) and Chomsky (2008), among others. Uninterpretable features cannot
be interpreted by the interfaces, so they have to be deleted by the time they
reach the interfaces. However, since they might have a phonetic reex (such
as the presence of subjectverb agreement as a reex of an uninterpretable feature on T or overt case morphology as a reex of an uninterpretable case
feature), they must be transferred to the phonological component before they
get deleted. This is not a problem, however, if feature valuation, Transfer and
deletion happen at the same point during the derivation. This point in the
derivation is determined by phase heads. Thus the solution to the timing
paradox provides an indirect argument in favor of phases. Since we have not
said much about phases yet, I will defer a more complete discussion of the

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

19

[722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

Features

19

interaction between feature valuation, Transfer and deletion till the next
chapter. To preview, we will see there that feature valuation and deletion
have to happen simultaneously at the point of Transfer to the interfaces. There
is thus no need for the derivation to keep track of which features entered the
derivation valued and which ones did not.
As pointed out by Pesetsky & Torrego, Chomskys reasoning for equating
interpretability with valuation has to do with the fact that Narrow Syntax
lacks the look-ahead property to determine whether a given feature is going
to be interpretable at the interface or not. It is important to note that the timing
issue alluded to here only arises if we equate uninterpretability with lack
of value; if uninterpretable features remain uninterpretable throughout the derivation, the issue does not arise. Indeed, this equivalence has also been questioned
in the literature. Pesetsky & Torrego (2007) and Bokovi (2011), for example,
argue that valuation and interpretability should be taken as independ ent of
each other. This allows feature combinations that were contradictory if
feature interpretability amounts to valuation. The new possibilities are bolded
in (22).
(22) Types of features
uF[val]
iF[val]
uF[ ]
iF[ ]

an uninterpretable and valued feature


an interpretable and valued feature
an uninterpretable and unvalued feature
an interpretable and unvalued feature (cf. Pesetsky & Torrego 2007)

For Pesetsky & Torrego (2007), tense on the verb is valued in the lexicon
(which, they argue, is plausible given the fact that quite often tense surfaces on
the verb).19 It is nevertheless uninterpretable and remains so throughout the
derivation. The tense feature on the T head, on the other hand, is interpretable
but unvalued:
(23) a. TiT[ ]
b. TiT[PST]

walkeduT[PST]
walkeduT[PST]

There are thus two plausible candidates for what an uninterpretable T feature
might be: a tense feature on the verb or a Nominative case feature on the
noun. Furthermore, Pesetsky & Torrego argue that such a dissociation of interpretability and valuation also removes the need for two types of features
on interrogative complementizer heads and wh-phrases. Complementizer
heads in wh-questions are typically thought to require two types of features: the
feature that marks the clause as interrogative (essentially Chengs (1991) typing

19

I am simplifying Pesetsky and Torregos system somewhat. For them, feature valuation is feature
sharing of the kind proposed by Frampton and Gutmann (2000), for example. Instead of (23), they
suggest (i), in which [2] is the value. The number 2 has no signicance, it just marks the same
feature value in both locations:
(i) TenseiT[2]

walkeduT+past[2]

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

20

[722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

20

The Minimalist Program

feature) and the feature that drives a wh-element to the specier of


the interrogative clause. The two are typically referred to as a Q-feature and a
wh-feature, respectively; the complementizer has an interpretable Q feature (iQ
feature) and an uninterpretable wh-feature (uwh-feature). A wh-phrase in
its scope, on the other hand, has an interpretable wh-feature feature (iwh)
and an uninterpretable Q feature (uQ).20 Agree, as shown in (24), ensures
valuation of both unvalued features, the uninterpretable wh-feature of C and
the uninterpretable Q feature of the wh-phrase.
(24) a. CiQ, uwh[ ]
b. C iQ, uwh[val]

WHiwh,uQ[ ]
WHiwh,uQ[val]

This is a proliferation of interrogative-type features. For Pesetsky and Torrego, C


has an interpretable unvalued Q feature and the wh-phrase has its uninterpretable
valued counterpart. As shown in (25), there is only one type of feature (Q feature),
and wh is its value.
(25) a. CiQ[ ]
b. CiQ[wh]

WHuQ[wh]
WHuQ[wh]

1.4 Agree
The discussion in the previous section relied on the assumption that Agree is an
operation responsible for valuing unvalued features.21 In this section, we turn to
the details of the Agree mechanism. Following the general consensus in the eld,
I will capitalize Agree when I use it in this technical sense and distinguish it from
the descriptive terms agreement or agrees with, used quite broadly in the
literature.
For Agree to be possible, the following conditions have to hold (cf. Chomsky
2000: 1223).
(26) a. The Probe and the Goal have to be active, where being active means having
uninterpretable/unvalued features.
THE ACTIVITY CONDITION

20

21

Some sources take C to have an interpretable wh-feature and an uninterpretable Q feature, and the
wh-phrase to have an uninterpretable wh-feature and an uninterpretable Q feature. This seems to be
a terminological rather than a substantive difference.
Chomsky describes Agree as an operation responsible for deleting uninterpretable features under
matching:
(i) The erasure of uninterpretable features of probe and goal is the operation we called Agree.
(Chomsky 2000: 122)

Feature deletion is distinct from feature valuation, which raises the question of whether we have been
mistaken in taking Agree to be responsible for feature valuation. I do not believe so. As we will see in
Section 2.6, if valuation and deletion happen simultaneously (at the phase level), there is no incompatibility here.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

21

[722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

Agree

21

b. The features of the Probe and Goal have to match, where matching refers to
feature identity.
THE MATCHING CONDITION
c. The Goal has to be inside the domain of the Probe, where the domain of the
Probe is its sister.
THE DOMAIN CONDITION
d. The Goal has to be in a local relationship, where locality is closest ccommand.
THE LOCALITY CONDITION

When all these conditions are met, the unvalued features get valued (and deleted).
A typical conguration satisfying all four conditions is given in (27). Agree
is indicated by a dotted line (a convention I am going to employ throughout
the book). Agree is typically assumed to be impossible if both the Probe and
the Goal have only unvalued features.22
(27)

a.
PuF[

b.
AGREE

GiF[val], uF[

PuF[val]
GiF[val], uF[val]

A very straightforward illustration comes from Nominative case licensing,


which in current terms reduces to valuation of the uninterpretable Case feature
(uC[ ], or uT[ ] in Pesetsky & Torregos system). Nominative case is assumed to be
a reex of the Agree relationship between a nite T (which, in current terms,
means it has a valued/interpretable tense feature and an unvalued set of features) and a subject in the domain of T, which has a valued set of -features
and an unvalued Case feature, as represented schematically in (28) for a past tense
T and a third-person singular subject. Agree provides values to the uninterpretable features on both; in (28b) there are no unvalued features left.
(28) a. Tu[ ], iT[pst]
b. Tu[3sg.fem] iT[pst]

DPi[3sg.fem], uC[ ]
DPi[3sg.fem], uC[Nom]

For Chomsky, Agree is a binary relationship, involving a single Probe and a


single Goal. However, others have argued that Agree does not have to be binary
and that it also can involve one Probe undergoing Agree with multiple Goals or
multiple Probes undergoing Agree with a single Goal. Hiraiwa (2001) dubs this
type of Agree Multiple Agree, focusing specically on the scenarios in which a
single Probe (T in this case) agrees simultaneously with two (or more) Goals (two
DPs in the case at hand):
(29) a. Tu[ ], iT[val] DPi[val], uC[ ] DPi[val], uC[ ]
b. Tu[val] iT[val] DPi[val], uC[val] DPi[val], uC[val]

22

Some researchers allow such non-standard Agree (see Adger 2003: 169, for example).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C01.3D

22

22

[722] 23.11.2013 11:50AM

The Minimalist Program

In my own work on Parallel Merge structures (see Citko 2011b for the most
complete exposition), I argued in favor of the other possibility: the possibility of a
single Goal agreeing simultaneously with multiple Probes:
(30) a. Tu[ ], iT[val]
Tu[ ], iT[val]
b. Tu[val], iT[val] Tu[val], iT[val]

DPi[val], uC[ ]
DPi[val], uC[val]

Since the issue of whether Agree is a binary operation or not does not bear
directly on any aspect of Phase Theory, I will not elaborate on it further here,
and I refer the interested reader to the works cited above (and the references
therein) for data, evidence and further discussion. The one thing about Agree
that is relevant to Phase Theory concerns the locality conditions on Agree; in
particular the issue of whether Agree is possible across phase boundaries. This
is the issue we come back to in Section 2.4, which focuses on the Phase
Impenetrability Condition.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

23

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

2
Introducing phases

2.1

Merge over Move preference1

This chapter introduces the concept of a phase, providing both theoretical and
empirical motivation for it. To the best of my knowledge, the term rst appeared
in Chomskys (2000) Minimalist Inquiries, where phases (to be more specic,
lexical subarrays associated with phases) were introduced as a solution to a
problem arising from the Merge over Move (MOM) principle. The concept of
a phase, however, builds on many prior principles involving locality domains:
cycles, barriers, islands, to name a few.
Let us start by looking at the Merge over Move Principle in more detail. What
it says is that, all things being equal, Merge is preferred over Move.2 Consider the
following contrast involving a raising predicate be likely, modeled upon
Chomskys (2000) (non-parrot) examples:
(1) a. There are likely to be many parrots at the clay lick right now.
b. *There are likely many parrots to be at the clay lick right now.

Without the MOM principle, it is impossible to explain the ungrammaticality of


(1b). The crucial step in its derivation is the one illustrated in (2b), where the next
step has to involve checking the EPP feature of T.
(2) a. N = {there, T, are, likely, to, be, many, parrots, at, the, clay lick, right, now}
b. [TP toEPP be many parrots i[3pl],uC[ ] at the clay lick right now]

See also Hornstein Nunes & Grohmann (2005) for a very lucid overview of the rationale behind the
Merge over Move principle. The logic of the presentation here mirrors theirs. See, however,
Castillo, Drury & Gohmann (2004) for a discussion of some issues MOM raises and ways to
resolve these issues.
Chomsky points out that MOM could be derived from more general economy principles, if Move is
a more complex operation than Merge, consisting of Copy and Merge. It is not clear, however, if the
logic survives when Move is treated as a variant of Merge, i.e. Internal Merge. There is no sense in
which Internal Merge is more complex than External Merge.

23

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

24

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

24

Introducing phases

We have a choice here: the EPP feature of T can be checked either by merging
the expletive there in [Spec,TP] or by moving the DP many parrots there.
However, only one of these choices leads to a convergent derivation. If
we move many parrots to [Spec,TP], the derivation proceeds as follows:
(3) a. Move [DP many parrots] to [Spec,TP], checking the EPP feature of T

TP
DPi[3pl],uC[ ] T
many parrots T
to EPP

VP

be many parrots at the clay lick right now


b. Merge [TP many parrots to be at the clay lick right now] with the adjective likely

AdjP
Adj
likely

TP
DP i[3pl],uC[

many parrots

T
to EPP

VP
be many parrots at the clay lick right now

c. Merge [AP likely many parrots to be at the clay lick right now] with the verb are
VP
V
are

AdjP
Adj
likely

TP
DPi[3pl],uC[

many parrots

T
to EPP

T
VP

be many parrots at the clay lick right now

d. Merge [VP are likely many parrots to be at the clay lick right now] with T
Move are to T
Agree between T and [DP many parrots]

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

25

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Merge over Move preference

25

TP
T EPP,u[3pl] VP
are
V
AdjP
are
Adj
TP
likely
DPi[3pl],uC[Nom] T
many parrots T
to EPP

VP

be many parrots at the clay lick right now


e. Merge the expletive there with [TP are likely many parrots to be at the clay lick
right now], checking the EPP feature of T

TP
T

there

TEPP,u[3pl] VP
are
V
AdjP
are
Adj
TP
likely
DPi[3sg],uC[Nom] T

VP
many parrots T
to EPP
be many parrots at the clay lick right now
f. There are likely many parrots to be at the clay lick right now.

Interestingly, nothing seems to go wrong with this derivation, yet the result
(example (3f)) is ungrammatical. The uninterpretable features are all checked
and/or valued, the Numeration is exhausted, and locality is respected. This is
where the Merge over Move (MOM) principle comes in: the step in (3a) violates
MOM, as we are moving the DP many parrots to [Spec,TP] rather than merging
the expletive there. If we merge the expletive there rst, the derivation proceeds
as schematized in (4) instead, leading to the grammatical (4f).
(4) a. Merge there with [TP to be many parrots at the clay lick right now], checking the
EPP feature of T

TP
there

T
toEPP

VP

be many parrotsi[3pl],uC[ ] at the clay lick right now

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

26

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

26

Introducing phases

b. Merge [TP there to be many parrots at the clay lick right now] with the adjective
likely

AdjP
Adj
likely

TP
there

T
toEPP

VP

be many parrotsi[3pl],uC[ ] at the clay lick right now


c. Merge [AdjP likely there to be many people present] with the verb are

VP
V
are

AdjP
Adj
likely

TP
T

there
T
toEPP

VP
be many parrots[3pl],uC[ ] at the clay lick right now

d. Merge the [VP are likely many parrots to be at the clay lick right now] with the
matrix T
Agree between T and many parrots
Move are to T
TP
Tu[pl],EPP VP
are
V
are

AdjP
Adj
TP
likely
T
there
T
to EPP

VP

be [DP many parrots i[3pl],uC[Nom]] at the clay lick right now

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

27

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Motivating phases

27

e. Move the expletive there to [Spec,TP], checking the EPP feature of T

TP
there

Tuj[3pl],EPP VP
are
V
AdjP
are
Adj
TP
likely
there
T
T
to EPP

VP

be many parrots[3pl],uC[Nom] at the clay lick right now


f. There are likely to be many parrots at the clay lick right now.

2.2 Motivating phases


Now, with a basic grasp of the Merge over Move principle, let us look at slightly
more complex examples, such as (5).
(5) There is a strong likelihood that many parrots will be at the clay lick right now.

Since its Numeration, given in (6a) below, contains an expletive, the prediction is
that (5) should be ungrammatical, since at the stage given in (6b), according to
MOM, the Merge of there should win out over the Move of many parrots.
(6) a. N = {there, is, a, strong, likelihood, that, many, parrots, will, be, at, the, clay lick,
right, now}

b.

TP
T
T
VP
willu[3sg]EPP
be many parrots i[3pl],uC[Nom]t be at the clay lick right now

c.

TP

there

T
willu[3sg]EPP

VP
be many parrotsi[3pl],uC[Nom] be at the clay lick right now

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

28

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

28

Introducing phases

If that happens, however, the derivation is going to run into problems when the
matrix T is merged. Raising of there from the subject position of the embedded
nite clause to the matrix subject position, which results in (7), is unmotivated;
hence ruled out by economy.
(7) * Therei is a strong likelihood that ti will be many parrots at the clay lick right now.

The solution to this problem relies on the intuition that at the point in the
derivation when the EPP feature of the embedded T needs to get checked
(which is immediately upon the Merge of T), the expletive there is not available.
In Minimalist Inquiries, Chomsky implements it in terms of so-called subarrays.
(8) Suppose we select LA as before . . . Suppose further that at each stage of the
derivation a subset LAi is extracted, placed in active memory (the work space),
and submitted to the procedure L. When LAi is exhausted, the computation may
proceed if possible. Or it may return to LA and extract LAj, proceeding as before.
(Chomsky 2000: 106)

Crucially, only when a given subarray has been exhausted can the next subarray
be accessed, which can be thought of as a form of cyclicity in lexical access. With
lexical arrays in place, the Numeration becomes a more structured object, which
instead of being a set (as in (9a)), is a set of sets (as in (9b)). These subsets are the
subarrays we have just learned about.
(9) a. N = { a, b, c, d, e, f }
b. N = { {a, b},{c, d},{e, f} }

Now, the choice between Merge and Move (and the preference for Merge) arises
only if the relevant subarray contains both the expletive and the potentially
movable DP. What this means for our problematic example (5) above is that the
Merge over Move principle does not apply since the expletive there and the DP
people are in two different subarrays, as shown in (10).
(10) N = { {there, is, a, strong, likelihood}, {that, many, parrots, will, be, at, the, clay
lick, right, now } }

The only way to check the EPP feature of T is thus to move many people to [Spec,
TP], which will eventually lead to the grammatical string (11b).
(11) a.

TP
DP i[3pl],uC[Nom] T
many parrots

T EPP u[3pl] VP
will
be many parrots at the clay lick right now

b. There is a strong likelihood that many parrots will be at the clay lick right now.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

29

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Phasehood properties

29

Given the focus of this book on phases, the question is: what is the relationship between subarrays (the need for which arises from problems relating to the
MOM principle) and phases? In Minimalist Inquiries, this relationship is fairly
straightforward. Chomskys characterization of phases is simply in terms of
subarrays:
(12) A phase of a derivation is a syntactic object derived . . . by choice of LAi.
(Chomsky 2000: 106)

Such a characterization of phases only raises the question of how lexical subarrays (LAi) are chosen. Otherwise, the argument is circular: phases are determined relative to subarrays, and subarrays are determined relative to phases. To
avoid such circularity, we need an independent way to characterize phases (or
subarrays). This is the focus of the next section.

2.3 Phasehood properties


In Minimalist Inquiries, Chomsky characterizes phases as natural syntactic
objects, relatively independent in terms of interface properties (2000: 106).3
The C-I interface requires phases to be complete from a semantic perspective. In
Chomskys words, a phase is the closest syntactic counterpart to a proposition:
either a verb phrase in which all theta roles are assigned or a full clause
including tense and force (2000: 106). Chomsky thus assumes that CPs are
phases, as are transitive and unergative vPs, but TPs, unaccusative and passive
vPs are not.4 What distinguishes verb phrases that are not phases from the ones
that are is the fact that they lack external arguments. It is not clear, however, in
what sense the argument structure of unaccusative or passive verbs is less
complete than the argument structure of transitive verbs; since the external
argument is not selected, there is no real sense in which it is missing. We could
only make this case by comparing the two, but such cross-derivational comparisons introduce non-signicant complications into the grammar (as pointed out
by Epstein 2007, for example). Furthermore, such a comparison is not always
available, as shown by the following contrasts:
(13) a. The ship sank.
b. The captain sank the ship.

Chomsky actually describes subarrays in those terms in Minimalist Inquiries, but this seems to be a
better characterization of phases. A subarray is a set, so it cannot be a syntactic object that can have
the semantic type of a proposition or be movable, for example. A phase, on the other hand, being a
hierarchically organized object, can have these properties.
Even though Chomsky does not explicitly address the phase status of verb phrases involving
ditransitive verbs, it seems reasonable to group them with transitive ones. I will come back to
them in Chapter 5.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

30

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

30

Introducing phases

(14) a. The sailor died.


b. *The captain died the sailor.

By analogy, one could also make a case that unergative verbs are not complete in
terms of their argument structure (because they lack an internal argument which
can sometimes be realized (as in (15b)), or that many transitive verbs are not
complete in terms of their argument structure because they have double object
counterparts, as shown in (16b).
(15) a. John ran.
b. John ran a race.
(16) a. John baked a cake.
b. John baked Mary a cake.

There are other characterizations of phases that do not rely on propositional


status or completeness. I list them in (17).
(17) a. Phases are convergent objects.
b. Phases are objects that determine points of Transfer.
c. Phase heads are the loci of uninterpretable features.

Chomsky (2000) rejects the idea of characterizing phases in terms of convergence


on the grounds that it would require a considerable look-ahead, thus negating
whatever advantages of reducing computational complexity phases were meant
to afford. We have seen above that dening phases in terms of the interfaces is
appealing. One way to make it more concrete is to take phases to be objects that
determine points of Transfer to the two interfaces. As we will see in the next
section, seeing phases in this light provides a very natural way to understand the
so-called Phase Impenetrability Condition (PIC), a powerful locality
constraint.
A slightly different view to think of phases is by looking at the properties of
phase heads. On this view, articulated as (17c), phase heads are more powerful,
syntactically speaking, than non-phase heads. Their syntactic prowess comes
from the fact that they are the loci of uninterpretable features, and as such, they
trigger syntactic operations. In simple terms, they are the syntactic engines of
every derivation. Chomsky is not very explicit on this point in Minimalist
Inquiries, but (18) below does imply that phase heads trigger syntactic operations (and are subject to strong cyclicity). From here, it is not a huge leap to
assume that phase heads are the only triggers.5

This is different from the issue of whether the phase head itself can be a target of operations from
outside the phase (as opposed to the issue of whether the phase head can trigger any operations). The
Phase Impenetrability Condition, the focus of the next section, determines how much of a given
phase is accessible from the outside.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

31

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Phase Impenetrability Condition

31

(18) The head of a phase is inert after the phase is completed, triggering no further
operations. (Chomsky 2000: 107)

The idea of phase heads being the loci of uninterpretable features is often viewed
as a denitional property of phase heads. This is the view articulated explicitly by
Gallego (2010), Legate (2012) and Miyagawa (2011), among others, whose
formulations are given in (19ac).
(19) a. Uninterpretable features signal phase boundaries. (Gallego 2010: 151)
b. A C/v possessing an unvalued -feature in the numeration is a phase head.
(Legate 2012: 239)
c. Case identies phase heads. (Miyagawa 2011: 1273)

2.4 Phase Impenetrability Condition


From an empirical perspective, perhaps one of the most important aspects
of Phase Theory is the so-called Phase Impenetrability Condition
(PIC), which deems a portion of the phase impenetrable (inaccessible) from
outside of the phase. In this section, we rst examine the various versions of
PIC that have been proposed in the literature, focusing on the different
empirical predictions they make. Next, we turn to the empirical coverage
of PIC, particularly the issue of whether it governs all syntactic operations
or only a subset thereof (i.e. only Move/Internal Merge or both Move and
Agree).
What counts as phase-external can vary depending on the specic formulation of PIC, and, as we will see in this section, different versions of PIC differ with
respect to how long in the derivational history the interior of the phase is
accessible. All of them refer to the same general conguration, given in (20a)
below, in which Z and H, given in bold, are phase heads, and there is a non-phase
head X between them. This conguration corresponds to a clausal structure in
(20b) in which C and v are phase heads and T is not.
(20) a. [ZP Z . . . [XP X [HP [ H YP ] ] ] ] (cf. Chomsky 2001: 13)
b. [CP C . . .[TP T [vP DP [v VP ] ] ] ]

Let us start with the original version of PIC, from Chomskys (2000) Minimalist
Inquiries.
(21) Phase Impenetrability Condition
In phase with head H, the domain of H is not accessible to operations
outside , only H and its edge are accessible to such operations.
(Chomsky 2000: 108)

According to (21), as soon as HP is complete, the complement of H is spelled out.


HP is complete when H no longer projects. Being inaccessible in this context

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

32

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

32

Introducing phases

means if there are any features that are unvalued (or unchecked), they are going to
remain so. The general conguration PIC refers to is shown in (22a), and applied
to a more concrete clausal conguration in (22b); HP/vP is the phase (with H/v
being a phase head), YP/VP is the Spell-Out domain, and H/v and its specier
constitute the phase edge. In (22ab), as well as in the tree diagrams that follow,
the spelled-out portions are faded.6
(22) a.

PHASE
XP
X

HP

H
H

YP

SPELL-OUT DOMAIN

EDGE

b.

PHASE

TP
T

vP
DP

VP

SPELL-OUT DOMAIN

EDGE

Thus the only way something can move out of the Spell-Out domain is if it gets to
the phase edge rst. This is how the Phase Impenetrability Condition, in conjunction with (23) which states that phase heads have the requisite features to
trigger movement forces movement out of the phase to proceed through the
phase edge.7
(23) The head H of phase Ph may be assigned an EPP-feature.
(Chomsky 2000: 109)

We will review the evidence in favor of movement proceeding through phase


edges in Chapter 4 and, to a lesser extent, Chapter 5. For now, sufce it to note
that such evidence exists, and it involves well-known diagnostics of successive
cyclic movement (i.e. reconstruction, partial wh-movement, agreement, quantier

I borrow the convention from Hornstein, Nunes Grohmann (2005). They, however, use it to mark
checked features rather than spelled-out domains.
The EPP feature is also sometimes referred to as the P-feature (Periphery feature) (see Chomsky
2000: 144, note 5).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

33

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Phase Impenetrability Condition

33

oat, to name a few). If, for example, a wh-phrase in a long-distance question passes
successive-cyclically through the edge of vP or CP (the edge being there because of
the extra EPP (or P) feature, as per (23)), we should be able to see evidence of it
having passed through that edge. This is illustrated schematically in (24).
(24) [CP WH [C C . . . [vP WH [v v . . . [CP WH [C C . . . [vP WH v [VP V WH ] ] ] ] ] ] ] ]

As briey mentioned above, there are at least two major versions of the Phase
Impenetrability Condition: one from Chomskys (2000) Minimalist Inquiries
and the other one from Chomskys (2001) Derivation by Phase. The two are
juxtaposed in (25ab). I will refer to the two versions as a Strong PIC and a Weak
PIC, or PIC1 and PIC2, respectively (following Chomsky 2001, Mller 2004,
Richards 2011, among others, who also provide a more detailed discussion of the
differences between them).8
(25) a. The domain of H is not accessible to operations outside HP
[emphasis mine, B.C.]; only H and its edge are accessible
to such operations.
STRONG PIC/PIC1
b. The domain of H is not accessible to operations at ZP
[emphasis mine, B.C.]; only H and its edge are accessible to
such operations.
WEAK PIC/PIC2
(Chomsky 2001: 1314)

The two denitions differ with respect to when the domain of the phase head H
becomes inaccessible: as soon as HP is complete versus at the point the next
phase head (Z) is merged. Thus the two versions impose different restrictions
on how long (in derivational terms) the elements inside the complement
domain (complement of H) can be probed. If the phase HP is directly dominated by Z (another phase head), the two versions of PIC are empirically
equivalent. Both state that at the level of ZP, only the edge of H (i.e. H itself, its
speciers and adjuncts) are accessible to Z. However, the two versions of PIC
diverge in their empirical consequences in congurations of the kind given in
(26a) below, where there is a non-phase head between the two phase heads Z
and H (and corresponding phrases), given in bold.
8

Mller (2004), however, argues in favor of a yet different type of PIC, given in (i) below, which he
dubs PIC3, in which movement proceeds through the edge of every phrase (and in which every
phrase is thus a phase). I take here the more restrictive (and the more standardly assumed)
approach to phasehood, in which only some phrases are phases. I also refrain from digressing
into a detailed comparison of PIC3 with its predecessors, I refer the interested reader to Mllers
work instead.
(i) Phrase Impenetrability Condition (PIC3)
The domain of a head X of a phrase XP is not accessible to operations outside XP; only X and its
edge are accessible to such operations.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

34

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

34

Introducing phases

(26) a.

XP
X

HP

PHASE 1

H
H

YP

SPELL-OUT DOMAIN

EDGE

b.

ZP
Z

PHASE 2

XP
X

HP

PHASE 1

H
H

SPELL-OUT DOMAIN

YP

The two versions of PIC also make different predictions with respect to what X
can agree with in (26ab). Under PIC1, X cannot agree with YP (or anything
inside YP), since YP is spelled out as soon as X is merged, as shown in (26a).
Under PIC2, however, X can agree with YP since YP is not spelled out until Z is
merged, as shown in (26b).
A concrete illustration comes from the relationship between T and a direct
object. According to PIC1, T cannot agree with DP, as shown in (27). According
to PIC2, T can undergo such an Agree relationship, since the complement of v
becomes inaccessible only at the next phase level, the CP level, as shown in
(28b). The two versions of PIC do not differ in their predictions regarding Agree
between T and the elements at the edge of vP (the external argument, shifted
object if present, and the v head itself ).
(27)

TP
Tu[ ]

v
Agree between T
and DP blocked

vP
VP

SPELL-OUT DOMAIN

...DPi[val],uC[

]...

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

35

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Phase Impenetrability Condition

(28) a.

35

TP
Tu[val]

vP

VP

Agree between T
and DP possible

b.

DPi[val],uC[val]

CP
C

TP
Tu[val]

vP

VP

SPELL-OUT DOMAIN

...DPi[val],uC[val]...

The reason to believe that this type of Agree should be possible comes from
languages that allow so-called quirky Nominative objects. On the assumption
that Nominative case is a result of Agree between a nite T and the object in
question, VP cannot be spelled out before Agree takes place. This is thus an
argument in favor of PIC2 over PIC1. Illustrative examples from Icelandic and
Polish are given in (29ab), respectively.9, 10
(29) a. Henni hfu
leist
eir.
her.DAT had.3PL bored.at they.NOM
She had found them boring. (Sigursson 2002: 692)
b. Marii
podobaa sie ta
ksiazka.
Maria.DAT please
REFL
Maria liked this book.
9

this

[Icelandic]

[Polish]

book.NOM

It is clear that T, rather than some unorthodox form of v, values Nominative case on the object,
given that in Polish it remains Nominative under negation. If v were involved in valuing the case of
the (Nominative) object, we would expect Genitive case instead (so-called Genitive of Negation)
under negation. This is what happens obligatorily with Accusative objects:
(i) Marii
Maria.DAT

nie

podobaja

sie

kwiaty/*kwiatw.

not

please

REFL

owers.NOM/*GEN

[Polish]

Maria is not pleased with the owers.


(ii) Maria
Maria.NOM

nie

lubi

kwiatw/*kwiaty.

not

likes

owers.GEN/ACC

Maria does not like owers.


10

Many of the examples with Dative subjects and Nominative objects involve so-called psych-verbs,
which is interesting in itself but does not change the fundamental insight about case valuation (see
Belletti & Rizzi 1988 for a classic early account of psych-verbs, and Pesetsky 1995 and Landau
2010, among many others, for more recent ones).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

36

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

36

Introducing phases

Abstracting away from the non-trivial issue of how Agree can take place
across a Dative experiencer in such a conguration, Agree between T and DP is
only possible under PIC2; under PIC1,VP is spelled out as soon as T is merged. A
similar issue arises in expletive constructions; if the associate of the expletive
bears Nominative case and if v in this case is also a phase head (a somewhat
controversial assumption, as we will see in Chapter 5), the example in (30) also
requires Agree between T and the VP internal argument, schematized in (30).11,12
(30) a. There arrived a train.
b. [CP C [TP there T u[3sg] [vP [v [VP arrived [DP a train]i[3sg],uC[Nom] ] ] ] ] ]

Again, if the VPs are spelled out as soon as T is merged, the case feature on the
associate of the expletive cannot be valued.
Richards (2011) argues that the differences between the two versions of PIC
are reducible to which subarray contains T. He contrasts two general approaches
to phasehood, which he dubs the subarrays approach versus all-powerful head
approach, and argues in favor of the subarray-based one (see, however, the
discussion in Section 2.2 above). Since in principle T could belong either to the
subarray headed by C or to the one headed by v, depending on which of
the two it is, the effect is either PIC1 or PIC2.
(31) a. N= { {C, T},{v, V} }
b. N = { {C},{T,v},{V} }

STRONG PIC/PIC1
WEAK PIC/PIC2

However, given the empirical problems associated with PIC1 (as well as the
inherent circularity in dening phases in terms of subarrays and subarrays in
terms of phases), it is not clear why we would ever need both versions.
Richards (2011) points out that PIC1 might be preferable conceptually, as
PIC2 increases the search space, thus increasing computational complexity
11

The assumption that the associate is Nominative seems problematic in light of the examples
involving pronouns, such as the one in (i), in which the case of the associate is Accusative rather
than Nominative. This led Belletti (1988) and Lasnik (1992) to a different proposal, relying on socalled partitive case. Interestingly though, even in such cases the associate determines agreement,
as shown by the contrast between (ii) and (iii).
(i) There arrived him/*he.
(ii) There arrives him.
(iii) There arrive them.

12

The so-called transitive expletive constructions, such as the one in (i) from Icelandic, are not a
problem, since the Nominative argument is at the phase edge, as shown in (ii).
(i) a
there

boruu

sennilega

margir

jlasveinar

bjgun.

ate

probably

many

Christmas.trolls

the.sausages

[Icelandic]

Many Christmas trolls probably ate the sausages.(Bobalijik & Jonas1996: 230)
(ii) [CP C [TP there T u[3pl] [vP [DP many Christmas trolls]i[3pl]uC[Nom] [v [VP eaten [DP the sausages] i[3pl]
uC[Acc]]

]]]]

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

37

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Phase Impenetrability Condition

37

(see also Mller 2004). Richards also notes, together with Bokovi (2002),
Abels (2003), Matushansky (2005), Boeckx & Grohmann (2007) and Epstein
(2007) among others, that there is a mismatch between what is a phase and what
is transferred to the interfaces. Phases are identied by their heads, but it is the
complement of the phase head that gets transferred to the interfaces. Richards
system avoids this problem. For him, the phase conceived in terms of subarrays
is the Spell-Out unit.
An important question about the Phase Impenetrability Condition, which
has been given a fair amount of attention in the literature on phases, is
whether all syntactic mechanisms are subject to it or constrained by it. The
two most relevant syntactic mechanisms (arguably, the only two) are Move/
Internal Merge and Agree. The discussion so far implies that they both
have to obey PIC. However, this conclusion is not uncontroversial (see, for
example, Bokovi 2003, 2007, Bhatt 2005 for claims to the contrary).
Bokovi, based on data of the following sort, argues that Agree into nite
clauses is possible, and, consequently, that Agree cannot be subject to PIC.
In what follows, we will refer to this type of Agree as Long Distance Agree
(LDA).
(32) nan qlilu lnrk -nin-et [iqun -rtm v-nen-at qora-t]. [Chukchee]
he-INSTR regrets-3-PL
that 3SG-lost-3-PL
reindeer-PL(NOM)
He regrets that he lost the reindeers.
(Bokovic 2003: 57, citing Inenlikj & Nedjalkov 1973)

In (32), the matrix verb is plural. Since the only plural element in the clause is
the embedded object, Bokovi takes this to indicate the presence of an Agree
relationship between the matrix v and the embedded object. This leaves us with
the question of whether such LDA is universally possible, or subject to parametric variation. Bokovi takes the latter view, attributing the difference
between languages like Chukchee and ones like English to the presence or
absence of -features on CP. If CPs have -features, which he takes to be the
case in English, LDA is impossible (presumably, due to intervention effects, as
a violation of Attract Closest).
The phenomenon of LDA crossing a nite CP boundary is also attested in
Tsez, another language Bokovi discusses. His analysis, however, departs
from Polinsky & Potsdam (2001), from whom he draws his data. (33a) illustrates what Polinsky and Potsdam dub Properly Local Agreement (PLA);
(33b) illustrates the LDA pattern we are interested in here. Polinsky and
Potsdam, arguing against specierhead-based accounts of agreement in general, reanalyze LDA as involving covert topic movement. The element triggering agreement moves to the edge of the embedded clause, from which it is
accessible to Agree with the matrix V-v complex. In (33a), the verb agrees with
the embedded clause. In (33b), which is an example of LDA, the verb agrees
with the embedded object.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

38

38

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Introducing phases

(33) a. enir
[ua magalu
bacrui] r-iyxo.
[Tsez]
mother [boy bread.III.ABS ate].IV
IV-know
The mother knows [the boy ate the bread].
The mother knows the boy ate the bread.
b. enir
[ua magalu
bacrui] b-iyxo.
III-know
Mother [boy bread.III.ABS ate]
The mother knows [the boy ate the bread].
The mother knows the boy ate the bread. (Polinsky & Potsdam 2001: 584)

Another language that allows LDA is Hindi. As in Tsez, in HindiUrdu


long-distance agreement appears to be optional, as shown by the examples in
(34ab), which Bhatt attributes to Mahajan (1989). The difference in agreement correlates with a difference in interpretation. Following Mahajan, Bhatt
takes the relevant factor to be specicity for HindiUrdu, whereas Polinsky
and Potsdam take it to be topic-hood for Tsez. Irrespective of what the difference is, the availability of LDA in languages like HindiUrdu or Tsez suggests
that there must be some factors that (in some languages) allow Agree not to
obey PIC.
(34) a. Ram-ne [rotii
khaa-nii]
chaah-ii.
Ram-ERG bread.FEM eat-INF.FEM want-PFV.FEM.SG
Ram wanted to eat bread.
b. Ram-ne [rotii
khaa-naa]
chaah-aa.
Ram-ERG bread.FEM eat-INF.MASC want-PFV.MASC.SG
Ram wanted to eat bread. (Bhatt 2005: 761)

[HindiUrdu]

HindiUrdu is slightly different from the Chukchee and Tzez data we have just
seen in that LDA is only possible into innitival clauses, which leads Bhatt to
correlate LDA with restructuring. It also leads him to dissociate case from
agreement; in LDA examples, the embedded object agrees with the matrix verb
but does not get case from it.13
A slightly different version of the Phase Impenetrability Condition, which also
allows LDA into embedded CPs, comes from Landaus work on control (see also
witkos 2010a, b).14 In a series of works, Landau develops a theory of control, often
referred to as Agree-based Calculus of Control (see Landau 1999, 2000, 2003,
2008), in which the interpretation of PRO is determined by what it undergoes Agree

13

14

In order to account for Hindi LDA, Bhatt (2005) also reformulates Agree (dubbing it AGREE). His
version of AGREE differs from the standard Agree in that it allows the Goal to have no unvalued
features. In standard Agree cases, having unvalued features (uCase features in most cases we
have seen in this section) was a denitional characteristic of a Goal; this was the property that
made it active.
This is slightly different from the issue of Agree being exempt from PIC. Here we are dealing with
PIC being reformulated in a way that allows certain elements to agree with outside others their
phase (without being at the phase edge).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

39

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Phase Impenetrability Condition

39

with. In Landaus system, the relationship between PRO and its controller is
mediated via Agree, but, crucially, not necessarily Agree between PRO and its
controller. Rather, he proposes two mechanisms of control, which correlate with the
distinction between Partial and Exhaustive control.15 The difference between
the two types of control, which Landau convincingly argues are both subspecies
of Obligatory Control, is illustrated by the contrast between the example in
(35a), illustrating Partial Control, and the one in (36a), illustrating Exhaustive
Control. The former allows a mismatch in plurality between a (singular) controller
(i.e. matrix subject) and a plural embedded PRO. The plurality of PRO, which
Landau indicates by the subscript 1+, is evidenced by the fact that it is possible with
distributive predicates like gather, meet or do something together. Both Exhaustive
and Partial Control involve a number of Agree relationships. Interestingly though,
neither involves a direct Agree relationship between the controller and PRO. In
Partial Control cases, such as the one in (35a), none of the three Agree relationships
violates PIC.
(35) a. Maria1 preferred [PRO1+ to go for a walk together].

b.

TP
DP

T
vP

Maria
v

VP

preferred

CP
C

TP

T C PRO

T
T

vP

PRO go for a walk together

However, the Agree Landau posits for Exhaustive Control is different and it does
involve Agree across a CP boundary, in violation of the Phase Impenetrability
Condition. This is the Agree between the matrix T and the PRO in the embedded
[Spec,TP] position.

15

The distinction between Exhaustive and Partial Control is a matter of lexical selection. Some verbs
are inherently specied as selecting Partial Control complements, whereas others are specied as
selecting Exhaustive Control complements.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

40

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

40

Introducing phases

(36) a. Maria1 managed [PRO1 to go for a walk].

b.

TP
T

DP
T1

vP
v

Maria

VP

v
managed

CP
C

TP
T

PRO
T

vP
PRO go for a walk

On standard assumptions about PIC, as soon as v is merged, the embedded TP


is spelled out, the result of which is that anything inside this TP will not be
accessible to further operations.16, 17
vP

(37)

VP
managed

CP

TP
T

PRO
T

vP
PRO go for walk

Thus, in order to allow Agree between T and PRO in such cases, Landau modies
the Phase Impenetrability Condition. He does not take the route Bokovi took
(essentially exempting Agree from PIC). Instead, he allows Agree into the
complement domain under certain circumstances, namely when the Goal in this

16

17

The only difference between subject and object control in both Exhaustive and Partial Control
cases is that the rst Agree relationship is between v and the object (rather than T and the subject).
As far as PIC is concerned, the same problem arises: the Agree between v and PRO in Partial
Control cases also violates it.
Or even earlier if we assume the earlier version of PIC, on which the complement of a phase head
becomes inaccessible as soon as the next head is merged, which in this case is the matrix V.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

41

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Multiple Spell-Out

41

Agree operation is interpretable (or more accurately, has interpretable features).


Landaus version of PIC is given in (38).
(38) In a structure [. . .X. . . [YP . . .Z. . .] ], where YP is the only phase boundary between
X and Z, Z is accessible to X.
a. only at the head or edge of YP, if Z is uninterpretable;
b. anywhere in the YP phase, if Z is interpretable. (Landau 2000: 69)

The possibility of Agree not being subject to the PIC raises a very fundamental question concerning the relationship between Transfer and PIC.
Implicit in the discussion so far has been the assumption that the reason the
complement of a phase head becomes inaccessible at a certain point in the
derivation (i.e. when the next phase head is merged) is the fact that it has been
transferred to the interfaces. From this perspective, Agree that violates PIC,
which would be Agree after Transfer, should never be possible. But is the
conclusion that PIC determines Transfer a logical necessity? Could it be that
PIC determines locality but not Transfer? For the proposals we discussed in
this section, PIC determines both Transfer and locality. This, however, is only
one possibility. Another possibility would be to assume that in certain cases
(such as the cases of LDA considered here), Transfer to the interfaces is simply
delayed. This would keep the concept of Transfer intact, in that once an object
is transferred, it is no longer visible to syntactic processes such as Merge,
Move or Agree, but would allow delayed Transfer, the possibility we will
discuss in more detail in Chapter 6.18

2.5 Multiple Spell-Out


The concept of Multiple Spell-Out was implicit in the discussion of the Phase
Impenetrability Condition in the previous section, where we saw that different
versions of PIC make different predictions with respect to how long in the
derivation the complement of a phase head is accessible. The most straightforward explanation for why this should be the case is that at a given point, this
complement is not accessible to the syntax because it is no longer part of the
syntax; it is transferred to the two interfaces. The technical term used to
describe this moment is Transfer; however, it is often referred to as SpellOut, even though technically speaking Spell-Out refers only to transfer to
the SM interface. To the best of my knowledge, there is no analogous term to
describe transfer to the C-I interface. Interpret-Out is a term that comes to mind,
but, admittedly, it does not have the same intuitive appeal as Spell-Out. I will
thus follow the eld and perpetuate the misconception in referring to Transfer
as Spell-Out. This terminological note aside, it is clear that given PIC and the

18

This is essentially what Richards (2012) does by taking Spell-Out to occur when the complement of
a phase head contains only interpretable features.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

42

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

42

Introducing phases

fact that (most) derivations contain more than one phase, Spell-Out is going to
occur more than once per derivation. In this respect, phase-theoretical syntax
constitutes a major departure from its predecessors (minimalist and preminimalist alike), where there was only one point at which syntax could
communicate with phonology and semantics. The difference is illustrated
schematically in (39) and (40).
(39)

SINGLE SPELL-OUT

C-I

SM

(40)

MULTIPLE SPELL-OUT

C-I

SM

C-I

SM

C-I

SM

Logically speaking, the Transfer to each interface could happen at different times
(the Non-Simultaneous Spell-Out of Marui 2005, for example), as shown
below.19
(41)

SM
C-I
SM
C-I
SM
C-I

A variant of the general non-simultaneous approach would be to allow


Multiple Spell-Out to apply only to one of the two interfaces, as illustrated in
(42a) and (42b), respectively.
(42) a.

SM
SM
SM

C-I
19

Since there is only one point of Transfer under the so-called inverted T (or Y) model illustrated in
(39), non-simultaneous Transfer was not an option.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

43

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Multiple Spell-Out

43

b.
C-I
C-I
C-I

SM

Even though Chomsky leans towards maintaining the LF and PF integrity of


phases, there is nothing that would exclude such non-simultaneous scenarios on
principled grounds. Since this is nevertheless not something that is standardly
assumed, I will abstract away from Non-Simultaneous Spell-Out for now, and
come back to it in Chapter 6.
The concept of Multiple Spell-Out goes back to Uriagereka (1999) (see,
however, Uriagereka 2012 for a fuller exposition). The details of Uriagerekas
Multiple Spell-Out, however, are different from the Multiple Spell-Out that
became standard in Phase Theory, in which phase heads determine when SpellOut takes place, and the complement of a phase head is what gets spelled out. For
Uriagereka, non-complements are spelled out rst and become giant lexical
compounds (Uriagereka 1999: 256), whose terms become unavailable to further
syntactic operations. For example, speciers are spelled out before complements,
as shown schematically in (43). This can explain, for example, why extraction
from subjects is more constrained than extraction from complements. If the
specier is spelled out, nothing can move out of it.20
XP

(43)

YP
Y

X
ZP X

WP

With the concept of Multiple Spell-Out in mind, let us look at how the
theoretical pieces we have seen so far come together. The example we will look
at is given in (44a); its Numeration, given in (44b), contains two phase heads,
indicated in bold. This means that that there are two subarrays, each containing
one phase head. If DP is a phase a possibility which I abstract away from until
Chapter 4 the Numeration will be (44c) instead.
(44) a. Parrots like nuts.
b. N = { {C1, T1}, {Parrots1, v1, like1, D2, nuts1} }
c. N = { {C1, T1}, {D1, parrots1}, {v1, like1}, {D1, nuts1} }

20

It also helps reconcile Bare Phrase Structure with Kaynes (1994) Linear Correspondence Axiom.
If the specier becomes one big lexical item, it is not an issue that its subparts are not ordered with
respect to the elements in the rest of the structure.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

44

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

44

Introducing phases

The relevant features are given in (45), and the derivation proceeds along the lines
given in (46):
(45) CiForce[Decl]
TiT[pres], u[ ],EPP
DuC[ ]
parrotsi[3pl]
vu[ ]
nutsi[3pl]
(46) a. Merge D with nuts

DPi[3pl], uC[
D uC[

nutsi[3pl]

b. Merge like with [DP nuts]

VP
like

DPi[3pl], uC[
DuC[ ]

nutsi[3pl]

c. Merge VP with v
Agree between v and DP21
vP

vu[3pl]

VP

like

DPi[3pl]uC[Acc]
DuC[Acc]

nutsi[3pl]

d. Move (Internal Merge) like to v

v
v
like vu[3pl] like

V
DPi[3pl], uC[Acc]
DuC[Acc]

21

nutsi[3pl]

The Agree between v and the direct object results in v getting its -features valued by the
object. This Agree is realized overtly in languages in which verbs agree with both subjects and
objects.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

45

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Multiple Spell-Out

45

e. Merge [NP parrots] with D

DPi[3pl], uC[
DuC[

parrotsi[3pl]

f. Merge [DP parrots] with [vP like nuts]

vP
DPuC[

],i[3pl]

VP

D parrots v
like vu[3pl] like

DPi[3pl], uC[Acc]
DuC[Acc]

nutsi[3pl]

g. Merge T with vP
Agree between T and [DP parrots]
TP

TEPP,u[3pl]

vP

DPuC[Nom],i[3pl]
D

parrots v

VP

like vu[3pl] like

DPi[3pl],uC[Acc]
DuC[Acc]

nutsi[3pl]

h. Move (Internal Merge) [DP parrots] to [Spec, TP],


checking the EPP feature of T

TP
T

DPuC[Nom],i[3pl]

DuC[Nom] parrotsi[3pl] TEPP,u[3pl] vP


DP
D

parrots v
like vu[3pl] like

VP
DPi[3pl],uC[Acc]
DuC[Acc]

nutsi[3pl]

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

46

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

46

Introducing phases

i. Merge C with TP, Transfer VP to SM and C-I

CP
C

TP
DPuC[Nom],i[3pl]

DuC[Nom] parrotsi[3pl] TEPP,u[3pl]

vP
v

DP
D

parrots v

VP
DPi[3pl], uC[Acc]

like vu[3pl] like


D

nuts

j. Transfer CP to SM and C-I

2.6 Feature Inheritance


This section illustrates perhaps the most straightforward (and perhaps
expected, given the discussion in the previous sections) implementation of
the idea that phase heads are the driving force behind each derivation. One way
to implement it is to assume that only phase heads are the locus of uninterpretable features. This might not seem like a big departure from what we
have seen so far, but it does have one important consequence when taken at
face value. If all uninterpretable features start their derivational lives on
phase heads, non-phase heads can either have no uninterpretable features
whatsoever, or they can acquire uninterpretable features from phase heads in
the course of the derivation. The latter scenario is what Feature Inheritance
(FI) refers to. Generally speaking, the idea is that phase heads have uninterpretable features but non-phase heads can inherit them in the course of the
derivation. This, in addition to maintaining the intuition that the ability to
host uninterpretable features is a prerogative of phase heads, avoids the conclusion that T is a phase head, or that T has no uninterpretable features at all.
Either conclusion about T is both empirically and conceptually problematic.
T heads, which we normally do not think of as phase heads, must have the
uninterpretable -features that allow them to undergo Agree with the
subjects in their domains. T heads are also assumed to have EPP features.
The EPP feature is an odd feature in the taxonomy of features we have so
far, which takes features to be either interpretable or uninterpretable; EPP
functions as an uninterpretable feature but it has no interpretable counterpart.
One possibility is to assume that EPP is the only uninterpretable/formal
feature that has no place on the valued/unvalued spectrum. An alternative is

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

47

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Feature Inheritance

47

to assume that it is not the same kind of feature as all other features, and is more
of a second-order feature in the Adger & Svenonius (2011) sense. If we treat
EPP as a second-order feature, it becomes less of a mystery that it lacks an
interpretable counterpart.22
Taking T to be a phase head instead would also cause both conceptual and
empirical problems. Conceptually, TPs are not complete or independent at the
interfaces in the same sense that CPs are. Empirically, if TP were a phase, we
would encounter similar problems to the ones we encountered in the previous
section with the earlier version of PIC, so-called PIC1. If T were a phase head,
however, the same problems would arise even with PIC2 in place. In particular,
Agree between T and a VP-internal object (which is what is needed in (47a))
would never be possible:
(47) a. Henni hfu
leist
eir.
her.DAT had.3PL bored.at they.NOM
She had found them boring. (Sigursson 2002: 692)

b.

[Icelandic]

TP
Tu[

Agree between T
and DP blocked

vP
VP
...DPi[val], uC[ ]...

If T inherits its uninterpretable -features from C, we can reconcile the idea that
phase heads are hosts of uninterpretable features with the idea that T undergoes
Agree with the subject (and sometimes with the object), thus valuing the unvalued/uninterpretable features of both.
A corollary of the claim that phase heads have uninterpretable features is the
claim that derivations are evaluated at phase levels. Independent evidence in
favor of this claim comes from locality considerations. The idea that locality is
evaluated at phase levels eliminates the need for equidistance, which arose from a
locality violation in run-of-the-mill wh-questions. A simple formulation of equidistance is given in (48).23
22

23

Adger (2003) treats EPP as a D-feature. This is a bit of an oversimplication given that other
elements besides DPs can check it.
The original formulation of the equidistance principle (from The Minimalist Program) is given
below:
(i) If , are in the same minimal domain, they are equidistant from . (Chomsky 1995: 184)

See Chomsky (1995: 17780) for a detailed explanation of what counts as a minimal domain.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

48

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

48

Introducing phases

(48) Terms of the edge of HP are equidistant from probe P.

(Chomsky 2001: 27)

At the point in the derivation illustrated in (49b), Agree between T and the subject
is blocked by the intervening wh-object. The movement of the subject over the
intervening wh-object is also blocked by its presence. Equidistance, which made
speciers of the same head equidistant from any higher Goal, was essentially a
stipulation to allow such movement (or Agree) to take place.
(49) a. What do parrots like?

b.

CP

TP
TEPP,u[ ]

vP

whati[3sg], uC[Acc]
Agree between T
and subject
blocked

parrotsuC[

vP
],i[3pl]

vEPP

VP

like

what

If locality is evaluated at the T level (as is unavoidable if T is a phase), and if


equidistance is not available, Agree between T and the subject is not possible.
This Agree, however, is not a locality violation if locality is evaluated at the
C level and, more generally, if operations happen simultaneously at the phase
level. What this means is that Agree between T and the subject, movement
of the subject to [Spec,TP], and movement of the object from [Spec,vP] to
[Spec,CP] happen simultaneously at the phase level.24 Thus there is no sense in
which the subject moves across the object, or T undergoes Agree with the
subject across the object. The copy of the wh-object does not intervene because
only entire chains can intervene, and in (50) only one link of the chain does.
This argument from intervention also leads Chomsky (2004) to conclude that

24

The equidistance principle was set against a different theoretical backdrop, with Agreement
projections still in place, and before the emergence of concepts like Probe, Goal and Agree. The
basic logic behind it has not changed, though.
The idea that all operations take place simultaneously at the phase level also removes the
countercyclicity in Holmbergs Generalization; the verb had to move to T before the object
could undergo object shift. Chomsky (2001) addresses the countercyclic nature of head movement, which together with other problematic aspects of head movement (such as the fact that
the moved head does not c-command its trace and is subject to different locality conditions than
other types of movement) led him to suggest that head movement is phonological.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

49

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Feature Inheritance

49

wh-phrases cannot remain in [Spec,vP] and that the landing site of overt object
shift cannot be [Spec,vP], either.25
(50)

CP
C

CiForce[Q], EPP TP
T

Ti[3sg],
uC[Acc] vP
x
whati[3sg], uC[Acc] vP
parrotsuC[Nom ],i[3pl]

vEPP

VP
like

what

Feature Inheritance thus provides a concrete way of implementing the idea that
operations happen simultaneously at the phase level. If uninterpretable -features
of T start out on C and get inherited by T from C, there is simply no way for T to
have these features before C is merged.
This is what Chomsky (2008) proposes. Richards (2008) argues that Feature
Inheritance is obligatory and deduces its obligatoriness (as stated in (51)) from
the interplay of the two independently motivated principles, Value-Transfer
Simultaneity (given in (52a)) and the formulation of the Phase Impenetrability
Condition (given in (52b)).26
(51) Feature Inheritance
uF must spread from edge to nonedge (i.e. from C to T, v* to V, etc.)
(Richards 2008: 567)
(52) a. Value-Transfer Simultaneity
Value and Transfer of uFs must happen together.
b. Phase Impenetrability Condition
The edge and nonedge (complement) of a phase are transferred separately.
(Richards 2008: 5668)

25

26

Chomsky states explicitly that no clear case of stranding in Spec-v is known (Chomsky 2004:
123). This conclusion might be too strong, in light of the data to be discussed in Section 4.2 of
Chapter 4, which does seem to suggest that stranding sometimes is possible in the intermediate
[Spec,vP] position.
Strictly speaking, (52b) is a consequence of PIC not PIC itself.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

50

50

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Introducing phases

First, Richards argues that feature valuation and Transfer have to happen at the
same time. The relative timing of these two operations is something that we
have not been explicit about so far. Uninterpretable features (being uninterpretable, thus by denition not readable by the interfaces) have to be deleted by
the time of Transfer. However, if feature interpretability reduces to feature
valuation, with uninterpretable features being simply unvalued (and interpretable features valued), unvalued features that were valued during the derivation
via Agree become indistinguishable from features that were valued to begin
with. In essence, uninterpretable features become indistinguishable from
interpretable features. Thus, once they are valued there is no way to know
that they have to be deleted (unless they come with I acquired my value
versus I was born with my value tags, a somewhat speculative solution, to say
the least). The problem disappears if feature valuation and feature deletion
happen simultaneously.27 This is precisely what Feature Inheritance allows.
There are nevertheless some nontrivial questions that Feature Inheritance
raises, listed in (53).
(53) a. Do all uninterpretable features have to be inherited?
b. Can other features (besides -features) be inherited?
c. Can a non-phase head inherit its uninterpretable features from a phase head
below it?

Interpretable features, being inherently associated with lexical elements, do not


get inherited. Given the logic above, there is also no reason why interpretable
features would need to be inherited; they never get deleted.
While there is a growing consensus in minimalist theory that non-phase
heads (such as T or V) lack formal features and can only get them from phase
heads via the process of Feature Inheritance (see Chomsky 2008, Richards
2004, 2008, 2011, among others), the precise mechanism behind Feature
Inheritance remains somewhat elusive. Given Richards reasoning above
about the timing of feature valuation, Transfer and deletion, the only possible
answer to (53a) is yes. However, there is a growing body of evidence showing
that under certain circumstances -features can remain on C, or wh-features can
be inherited by T, which suggests that Feature Inheritance perhaps does not
have to be obligatory.
Well-known cases of complementizer agreement of the kind found in
Germanic or Bantu languages (discussed by Carstens 2005, Carstens & Diercks
2011, Diercks 2011, Haegeman 1992, among many others) has been taken to
mean that -features can remain on C (or be present on both C and T). In (54a) the

27

This is also a point Epstein & Seely (2002) make. The conclusion they draw is different. In order to
ensure that feature valuation and Spell-Out happen simultaneously, they propose Spell-Out
happens whenever feature valuation happens.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

51

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Feature Inheritance

51

complementizer agrees with the embedded subject, in (54b) it agrees with the
matrix subject, and in (54c) the verb moved to C agrees with the wh-phrase in
the specier of CP.
(54) a. Kpeinzen dan-k (ik) morgen
goan.
[West Flemish]
I.think
that-I (I)
tomorrow go
I think that Ill go tomorrow. (Carstens 2005: 222, citing Haegeman 1992)
b. Alfredi ka-bol-el-a
baba-ndu a-li
ba-kha-khil-e.
[Lubukusu]
1Alfred 1S-said-AP-FV 2-person 1-that 2S-FUT-conquer
Alfred told the people that they will win. (Diercks 2011: 1)
c. Bik
bi--ks-l-
bbo bkulu
mwm mu-mwlo? [Kilega]
8what 8CA-A-give-PERF-FV 2that 2woman 1chief 183village
What did those women give the chief in the village? (Carstens 2005: 220)

A somewhat lesser known case of complementizer agreement comes from Slavic


languages. The Polish example in (55) shows that the complementizer agrees
with the embedded pro subject in Number and Person features.28
Chce
zeby-s
cie skonczyli.
want.1SG that-2PL
nish.PST.PL.MASC
I want you to nish.

(55)

28

The complementizer agreement is different from the so-called oating inection (discussed
by Booij & Rubach 1987, Embick 1995, Franks & Baski 1999, among many others),
illustrated in (i).
(i) My-smy
we-AUX.1PL

wyjechali

Wrocawia

rano.

leave.PART.VIR.PL

from

Wrocaw

morning

We left Wrocaw in the morning. (Migdalski 2006: 231)

Unlike oating inection, complementizer agreement is obligatory. Compare the grammatical


unoated variant of (i) in (ii) with the ungrammatical unoated variant of (55) in (iii).
(ii) Rano
morning

wyjechali-s
my

Wrocawia

leave. PART.VIR.PL-AUX.1PL

from

Wrocaw

We left Wrocaw in the morning. (Migdalski 2006: 230)


(iii) *Chce
zeby skonczyli-s
cie.
want.1SG

that

nish.PST.PL.MASC

I want you to nish.

Second, not only complementizers can host oating inection:


(iv) Ty

to

widziaes

you

it

saw

(v) Tys

to

widzia.

(iii) Ty

tos

widzia

this

saw

you

You saw it. (Embick 1995, citing Dogil 1987)

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

52

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

52

Introducing phases

A slightly different argument in favor of C being able to keep its -features


comes from the work of Ouali (2008) on Berber. Ouali (2008) discusses three
logical possibilities concerning the distribution of uninterpretable -features on C
and T heads and argues that all three are attested. To use his terminology, C can
donate its -features to T (which is the standard scenario), keep its features or share
its features with T. The three possibilities are illustrated in (56ac).
(56) a.
b.
c.

DONATE:
SHARE:
KEEP

C
Cu
Cu

Tu
Tu
T

The latter two options are the ones that are problematic if Feature Inheritance is
obligatory.29 Ouali attributes the so-called anti-agreement effect in Tamazight
Berber, illustrated in (57) below, to the ability of C to not pass the uninterpretable -features to T (the KEEP option given in (56c)). The anti-agreement effect
refers to the fact that in examples involving subject extraction, subjectverb
agreement is blocked. The data below provide a concrete illustration. (57a) is
the base example showing that verbs typically agree with subjects, (57b) shows
that this is impossible if the subject is wh-moved, and (57c) shows that in such
cases the non-agreeing participial form surfaces (hence the term antiagreement).
(57) a. thamttut thla
araw.
woman
3SF.see.PERF boys
The woman saw the boys.
b. *mani thamttut ag
thla
araw.
which woman
COMP
3SF.see.PERF boys
Which woman saw the boys?
c. mani thamttut ag
lan
araw.
which woman
COMP
see.PERF.PART boys
Which woman saw the boys? (Ouali 2008: 164)

[Tamazight Berber]

Ouali argues that in (57b) T does not inherit any -features from C, and, as a
result, subjectverb agreement is impossible.
Another plausible case of C keeping its uninterpretable -features comes
from Legates (2011) analysis of subject-initial orders in V2 languages.
Legate refers to it as under-inheritance, but it is equivalent to Oualis KEEP option.
What is interesting about subject-initial V2 clauses is that the subject behaves as
if it were in an A (rather than A-bar) position, in spite of the fact that it occupies
the [Spec,CP] position. The evidence that the [Spec,CP] subject position is an Aposition comes from reconstruction effects. Legate presents the following contrast from Dutch, due to Craenenbroeck & Haegeman (2007), to show that the

29

Ouali also argues that the three options are ordered with respect to each other, but nothing here
hinges on this argument.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

53

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Feature Inheritance

53

movement of the subject bleeds Principle C reconstruction. (58a) constitutes a


Principle C violation if the pronoun t it is coindexed with the R-expression
lemmeken lamb. Such coindexation is possible in (58b), which shows that the
moved subject does not have to reconstruct.
(58) a. Nou
ein-t*i/j den aaigeneir van t
lemmekeni zelf
muutn
now
has-it the owner
of the lamb
himself must
doewtuun.
kill
Now the owner of the lamb has had to kill it (not the lamb) himself.
b. Den aaigeneir van t
lemmekeni ein-ti/j zelf
muutn doewtuun.
the owner
of
the lamb
has-it himself must kill
The owner of the lamb has had to kill it (possibly the lamb) himself.
(Craenenbroeck & Haegeman 2007: 173)

Furthermore, Legate derives under-inheritance from a form of economy: the


sequence of operations in which C rst donates its -features to T, and the subject
raises to [Spec,TP] only to subsequently raise to [Spec,CP] is less economical
than the scenario in which T never inherits -features from C and the subject
raises to [Spec,CP] directly.30
The prediction that feature valuation and feature deletion (therefore Transfer,
if deletion is part of Transfer) have to happen simultaneously and, consequently,
that feature deletion is obligatory (see the discussion of Richards 2008 above)
only arises if feature interpretability reduces to feature valuation. However, as we
saw in Chapter 1, this equivalence has been questioned in the literature (see
Bokovi 2011, Pesetsky & Torrego 2007, among others). If we abandon the
equivalence between uninterpretable and unvalued features, and allow uninterpretable features to remain uninterpretable throughout the derivation and thus be
marked for deletion with no further stipulations, the need for obligatory Feature
Inheritance disappears.
The cases of Feature Inheritance discussed so far involve a lower non-phase
head inheriting uninterpretable features from a phase head above it. This is a
countercyclic process, but perhaps the countercyclicity does not matter so much if
derivations are evaluated at phase levels. It does, however, raise the question of
whether in addition to this type of Feature Inheritance, which we might call
Feature Inheritance from Above (FIFA), the standard cases of a non-phase
head inheriting its features from a higher phase head, schematized in (59ab)),
there exists Feature Inheritance from Below (FIFB), by means of which a nonphase head can inherit its features from a lower phase head (matrix V from
30

Interestingly, as pointed out by Richards (2011), PIC2 (the weaker version) is informulable with
Feature Inheritance in place. If the Merge of C is what triggers the Spell-Out of VP, the
Nominative object becomes inaccessible when C is merged. However, T does not inherit its
uninterpretable -features, which are the features that allow it to undergo Agree with the object,
until C is merged.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

54

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

54

Introducing phases

embedded C or T from v, as in (60ab)), yielding the following four possibilities,


with arrows indicating directionality of Feature Inheritance.
(59)

a.

CP
C

TP

FIFA

Tu
b.

vP
VP

Vu

(60)

a.

VP

FIFB

CP

Vu

b.

TP
Tu

vP
v

The question now is whether the two FIFB options in (60) are theoretically
possible and empirically justied. There does not seem to be anything that
excludes them on theoretical grounds; if anything, they seem conceptually
more plausible if we pursue the analogy between Feature Inheritance and movement. The FIFA options in (59a) and (59b) would be the options corresponding to
lowering movement operations and the FIFB options would correspond to standard (upwards) movement operations. Nevertheless, let me end with a piece of
speculation concerning the potential empirical support for (60a). Perhaps this
is what happens in Subject-to-Object Raising (SOR) / Exceptional Case
Marking (ECM) congurations, where the matrix V inherits uninterpretable
features from the embedded C, in addition to inheriting them from the matrix v.
The latter option was suggested by Chomsky (2008). On either account, SOR
targets [Spec,VP]; however, FIFB might provide a new take on the old puzzle of
why some languages allow SOR and others, such as Polish (as shown in (61ab)),
do not (see Bokovi 1997, Dziwirek 2000, Kayne 1981, Lasnik 1998, Rooryck
1997, among others, for a discussion of crosslinguistic variation with respect to
SOR).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

55

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Feature Inheritance

(61) a. *Maria
uwaza
Jana
byc
madrym.
Maria.NOM considers Jan.ACC be.INF smart.INSTR
Maria considers Jan to be smart.
b. *Maria spodziewa sie Jana
byc
na czas.
Maria
expects
REFL
Jan.ACC be.INF on time
Maria expects Jan to be on time.

55

[Polish]

This could only work on an independent assumption that control and ECM
clauses are categorically non-distinct and both are CPs (see, for example,
Bokovi 1997 and Pesetsky 1991). This seems problematic given the defective
tense of ECM clauses (see Stowell 1981 and Martin 1996, among others). But
maybe this defective nature of CP is what motivates FIFB. This is not what
happens in control clauses, whose CPs bear irrealis tense. Perhaps more generally, this is impossible in Slavic languages, whose CPs are more temporally
independent than their English counterparts, as evidenced, for example, by the
lack of Sequence of Tense (SOT) (see Khomitsevich 2007 for a recent discussion
of SOT in Russian, and Lasnik 1998 on the connection between tense and the lack
of ECM, also in Russian).
Let me conclude this chapter with a concrete illustration of how exactly
Feature Inheritance affects Narrow Syntax. In particular, let us look at how the
derivation of the example (44) above, repeated below as (62a), changes with
Feature Inheritance in place. There are two cases of Feature Inheritance to
consider: T inherits its uninterpretable -features from C, and V inherits its
uninterpretable -features from v. What is signicant is that a number of
processes happen simultaneously at phase levels (the steps (63c) and (63h)).
These are: Feature Inheritance, Agree (and feature valuation), movement and
Transfer.
(62) a. Parrots like nuts.
b. N = { {C1, T1}, {parrots1, v1, like1, D2, nuts1} }
(63) a. Merge D with nuts

DPi[3pl], uC[
DuC[

nutsi[3pl]

b. Merge like with [DP the nuts]


VP
like

DPi[3pl], uC[

DuC[ ]

nutsi[3pl]

c. Merge [VP like nuts] with v


V inherits u-features from v

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

56

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

56

Introducing phases

Agree between V and DP

vP
vu[

VP

likeu[3pl]

DPij[3pl], uC[Acc]

DuC[Acc]

nutsij[3pl]

d. Move (Internal Merge) like to v

v
v

v likeu[3pl]

like

DPi[3pl], uC[Acc]

DuC[Acc]

nutsi[3pl]

e. Merge [NP parrots] with D

DPi[3pl], uC[
DuC[

parrotsi[3pl]

f. Merge [DP parrots] with [V P like nuts]


vP
DPuC[

],i[3pl]

D parrots

v
VP

likeu,[3pl] v like

DPi[3pl], uC[Acc]
DuC[Acc] nutsi[3pl]

g. Merge T with vP

TP
T

vP

DPuC[
D

],i[3pl]

parrots v

like v

VP
like

DPi[3pl], uC[Acc]
D

nuts

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C02.3D

57

[2357] 23.11.2013 11:49AM

Feature Inheritance

57

h. Merge C with TP, Transfer VP to PF and LF


T inherits u-features and the EPP feature from C31
Agree between T and [DP parrots]
Move (Internal Merge) [DP parrots] to the specier of TP
DP checks the EPP feature of T

CP
Cu[3pl]

TP

DPuC[Nom],i[3pl] T
D parrots

TEPP,u[3pl] vP
DPuC[Nom],i[3pl] v

parrots v

VP
DPi[3pl], uC[Acc]

like vu:val like


D

nuts

j. Transfer CP to PF and LF

In sum, we have seen the motivation for phases stemming from the Merge over
Move principle, as well as reviewed the existing characterizations of phases (e.g.
phases dened in terms of subarrays versus phases dened in terms of the properties of phase heads). We have also seen how the introduction of phases changes the
overall architecture of the grammar in that it results in Multiple (and potentially
Non-Simultaneous) Spell-Out and how the property of phase heads as the loci of
uninterpretable features leads to Feature Inheritance. Throughout this chapter, we
have assumed that certain types of vPs and CPs (and perhaps DPs) are phases,
without providing much evidence for this assumption, and without applying concrete
diagnostics to these categories. This is what we turn to in the next two chapters. In
Chapter 3, we discuss various diagnostics that have been suggested in the literature to
determine the phasehood of a given category, with an eye towards determining
which of these diagnostics are real, and which ones are not. The diagnostics
established in this chapter will serve as the basis for the discussion of specic phases
in the chapters that follow.

31

I assume that the EPP feature of T is also inherited from C. This is not uncontroversial, but it seems
innocuous in the case at hand, where TP is dominated by C and where C does not need any EPP
features of its own. More interesting are cases in which TP is not dominated by C but nevertheless
has an EPP feature, as in the successive cyclic raising example in (i), and cases in which both C and
T have an EPP feature, as in the object wh-question in (ii).
(i) Parrots seem to be likely to like nuts.
(ii) What do parrots like?

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C03.3D

58

[5870] 23.11.2013 11:45AM

3
Phasehood diagnostics

3.1 Anatomy of a phasehood diagnostic1


A common characterization of phases, which we alluded to in previous sections
(Section 2.3 in particular), is their independence at the interfaces. Thus, to
determine if a given XP is a phase, we need to ask the two questions in (1).
(1) a. Is XP semantically independent?
b. Is XP phonologically independent?

This, however, only restates the question of how to determine if XP is a phase as


the question of what it means to be independent at the PF or LF interface, and,
more importantly, how this independence can be diagnosed. The bulk of the
discussion in the current chapter is devoted to making these questions more
concrete and establishing more tangible phasehood diagnostics.
Alternatively, we can dene phases by extension (by simply listing them)
and this is essentially all we have been doing so far, merely alluding to
independence at the interfaces as a possible factor. The categories we have
been assuming to be phases are vPs, CPs and possibly DPs. This is hardly an
optimal way to proceed, as it raises the obvious question of why these three
categories, as opposed to any other logically possible subset of syntactic
categories, should count as phases. A more desirable way to proceed is to
dene phases by intension, establishing independent diagnostics. The following alternative, often employed in the literature, comes to mind: if we know that
categories X, Y are phases (but Z is not), and we establish that X and Y share
properties p1 and p2 (which is what distinguishes them from Z), we can
conclude that properties p1 and p2 are phasehood diagnostics, and apply these
diagnostics to other categories to determine their phasehood. However, this
method also has its drawbacks. For one thing, it relies on having some a priori
1

I borrow the title of this section from the title of chapter 1 of Levin & Hovavs (1995) book
Unaccusativity: At the SyntaxLexical Semantics Interface, which is The anatomy of a diagnostic:
the resultative construction.

58

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C03.3D

59

[5870] 23.11.2013 11:45AM

Anatomy of a phasehood diagnostic

59

division of syntactic categories into phases and non-phases. Furthermore, not


all common properties of phases will work as diagnostics. For example, it
seems to be the case that all phases are maximal projections, but we do not think
of being a maximal projection as a phasehood diagnostic, since the common
view is that not all maximal projections are phases (see, however, Epstein &
Seely 2002, 2006, Lahne 2008, Mller 2004, 2011 for proposals that all phrases
are indeed phases).2 A natural alternative, which all the proposals surveyed so
far assume, is that only a certain well-dened subset of syntactic categories
constitutes the set of phases. Now the question is which subset, and what
exactly distinguishes this subset from its complement (the set of non-phases).
There are many logical possibilities that come to mind; one is that only
phrases headed by core functional heads constitute phases. However, conceptually it is not clear why things should work this way, as opposed to the other
way around. Why couldnt all phrases headed by lexical categories
constitute phases instead? Neither approach seems to yield correct empirical
results, with either TP being problematically classied as a phase if we take
all functional categories to be phase heads, or VPs and NPs being problematically classied as phases (and CP and vP as non-phases) if we take the opposite
route. So what is it that CPs and vPs have in common that they do not share with
TPs? A trivial answer is that things would go terribly wrong if a different set of
categories were phases. A more promising path to pursue is to establish
independent phasehood diagnostics, based on what the interfaces need phases
to be, and apply these diagnostics to test whether a given syntactic category is a
phase or not.
Since phasehood is often characterized in terms of interface considerations,
the diagnostics tend to be classied into two major groups: LF diagnostics
and PF diagnostics, each relating to the two interfaces. Some researchers, such
as Matushansky (2005), divide phasehood diagnostics into more types,
adding a separate class of syntactic (or morphosyntactic) diagnostics to the
two interface-based ones. It would be preferable on conceptual grounds if we
were able to diagnose phases by appealing only to interface-based considerations, but ultimately it is an empirical question of whether there are some
phasehood diagnostics that are purely syntactic. The answer depends on the
somewhat murky issue of where the boundary between syntax and semantics or
phonology lies. Furthermore, it is not always easy to tell whether a given
diagnostic is a true syntactic diagnostic, as opposed to being a syntactic reex
of a semantic diagnostic. The classication is harder for some potential
2

I do not think anyone would question the idea that all phases have to be maximal projections, since
maximal projections have the level of independence and completeness that non-maximal projections do not have. However, the question of whether something would go wrong at the interfaces if
phases were not maximal projections, or if phases were not always maximal projections, is
ultimately an empirical question. But allowing non-maximal projections to be phases would devoid
phases of completeness associated with phasehood.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C03.3D

60

60

[5870] 23.11.2013 11:45AM

Phasehood diagnostics

diagnostics than for others. For example, being a domain for nuclear stress
assignment would be a fairly straightforward example of a PF diagnostic,
whereas being propositional would count as a solid case of an LF diagnostic.
But some are harder to classify. For example, is being a target for Quantier
Raising (QR) or reconstruction a semantic or a syntactic diagnostic? This
depends on whether we think of QR (or reconstruction) as a semantic or a
syntactic process, and we know that there are different views on this matter.
Similarly, if ellipsis is a diagnostic, should it count as a PF, LF or a syntactic
diagnostic? Surely, ellipsis has an effect on both pronunciation and interpretation, and depending on whom we ask, it is treated as either a PF process (literal
deletion) or an LF process (reconstruction of missing material at LF).
Difculties in classication notwithstanding, I will proceed on the assumption that phasehood diagnostics can indeed be subdivided into three types:
syntactic, semantic and phonological, with the caveat that sometimes the
distinctions between the three types might be less than perfect. I will thus
not attach too much importance to this classication and leave open the
possibility that the same diagnostic can belong to more than one group, and,
for example, be both a syntactic and a semantic diagnostic. It is not even
clear whether the issue of classication is a substantive, as opposed to a
terminological issue. After all, does it really matter whether a given diagnostic
is a PF, LF or a syntactic phasehood diagnostic, as long as it is a reliable
phasehood diagnostic?
The two more concrete questions we can ask about phases concern the
properties of phase heads. If phases are syntactic engines, to borrow
Richards (2011) term, the following questions come to mind:
(2) a. Does X trigger Spell-Out?
b. Is X the source of uninterpretable features?

The answer to (2a) will help us diagnose the PF and LF status of phase; if phase
heads determine Spell-Out, the domain that is spelled out is a domain that will
feed phonology and semantics. We might therefore expect both phonological and
semantic processes to apply to this domain. Sections 3.2 and 3.3 will thus be
devoted to PF and LF phasehood diagnostics, respectively. The afrmative
answer to (2b), on the other hand, will help us uncover syntactic diagnostics; if
only phase heads are inherently endowed with uninterpretable features, then they
are going to trigger operations that rely on these features. This will lead us to
concrete syntactic diagnostics in Section 3.4.

3.2 PF diagnostics
This section focuses on the questions of what it means for a phase to be
independent at PF, what it means for a phase head to trigger Spell-Out, and
more importantly how we know that a phase is PF independent or has

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C03.3D

61

[5870] 23.11.2013 11:45AM

PF diagnostics

61

triggered Spell-Out. Below is a list of PF phasehood diagnostics that are often


discussed (or alluded to) in the literature on phases. The ones in (3ab),
discussed explicitly by Matushansky (2005), speak to PF independence,
whereas the ones in (3cd) speak to the ability of phase heads (and only
phase heads) to determine Spell-Out.
(3) a. Can XP be isolated?
b. Can XP be moved?
c. Does XP (or X) determine phonological domains?
d. Can the complement of X be elided?

Perhaps the most natural potential PF diagnostic is the one in (3a), involving
phonetic isolability. Simply put, according to this diagnostic, if XP can stand
alone (and function as a response to a question, for example), XP is a phase. The
diagnostic in (3b) says that if a given XP can be moved (by processes like
fronting of any kind, extraposition, clefting etc.), it should count as a phase.
However, these are standard constituency tests (as any introductory syntax
textbook can conrm), so a much larger number of categories pass as phases
according to this diagnostic. Matushansky (2005) also notes that the ability to
be isolated or undergo movement does not seem to be a very reliable phasehood
diagnostic (although she nevertheless applies it to DPs).3 The reason why we
might be tempted to think of it as such is that taking phonetic independence to
be a property of phases has an intuitive appeal. However, both isolability and
movement are broader characteristics of phrases, or perhaps of constituents
even more generally. Thus, example (4a) shows that DPs can stand alone as
sentence fragments. However, the examples in (4bf) show that many other
phrases can do so as well.
(4) a. What did Mary study?
a. [DP Western philosophy]
b. How many tests did Mary take to become a doctor?
b. [NumP Two]
c. Where did Mary go?
c. [PP To Cambridge]
d. What does everyone believe?
d. [CP That the earth is at]
e. What did Tom try?
e. [CP To be a good syntactician]
f. What color is this page?
f. [AP White]

Matushansky also considers extraposition, clefting and though-movement as PF phasehood diagnostics. She starts of by comparing TPs, CPs and vPs, and then applies the same diagnostics to test
DPs for phasehood.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C03.3D

62

62

[5870] 23.11.2013 11:45AM

Phasehood diagnostics

Similarly, many phrases may function as pivots (bracketed in (5)) in pseudocleft


constructions, which is also a sign of isolability.4
(5) a. What Mary read was [DP Chomskys Syntactic Structures].
b. What Tom wondered was [CP whether Pluto is a planet].
c. Where Tom went was [PP to the store].
d. *What Tom seemed was [TP to be a hero].
e. *How many books Tom read was [NumP ve].
f. *What color was Toms new car was [AdjP yellow].

Since different types of verb phrases have been claimed to differ in terms of their
phasehood status (something we will discuss in detail in Section 4.2 of
Chapter 4), I am going to keep them distinct for the purposes of the (putative)
diagnostics considered here.
(6) a. What Mary did was [vP read Chomskys Syntactic Structures]
b. What John did was [vP/VP arrive late].
c. *What John did/was [vP/VP given a book].

UNERGATIVES
UNACCUSATIVES
PASSIVES

The examples in (7ag) show that quite a few types of phrases can undergo
movement:
(7) a. [DP This new movie], we all admired.
b. [PP To this store], John went after the meeting.
c. [TP To become a top syntactician], Mary is very likely.
d. [CP To become a top syntactician], John really wanted.
e. [CP That the earth is not at], nobody doubts.
f. *[AdjP Interesting], we read books.
g. *[NumP Five], we read books.

All three verb phrase types under consideration here behave alike in this respect:
(8) a. [vP Read Chomskys new manuscript], all linguists should.
b. [vP/VP Arrive at the station], the train should have by now.
c. [vP/VP Eaten by sharks], nobody wants to be.

UNERGATIVES
UNACCUSATIVES
PASSIVES

And the examples below make a similar point with respect to Right Node Raising
(RNR):5
(9) a. John read and Bill reviewed [DP a new article on RNR].
b. John knows and Bill believes [CP that syntactic phases exist].

A reasonable question to ask is what type of derivation pseudoclefts involve; in particular whether
they involve movement of the pivot. Derivational details notwithstanding, it is clear that there is a
pause before the pivot of the pseudocleft, which is suggestive of some degree of phonetic
independence. Similar considerations apply to Right Node Raising.
See also Bokovi (2002) for a discussion of RNR (of TPs in particular) as an argument against
treating isolability as a diagnostic.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C03.3D

63

[5870] 23.11.2013 11:45AM

PF diagnostics

63

c. John should and Bill wont [vP read a new article on RNR].
d. John should but Bill wont [vP/VP arrive on time].

However, RNR seems to be a very permissive diagnostic, given that RNR can
even apply to subwords:6
(10) a. My analysis over and your analysis under-generates.
b. Ex and current smokers have high blood pressure.
c. Sheila likes pre- and post-colonial architecture. (Barros & Vicente 2010: 9)

This shows that isolability (the ability to stand alone and the ability to undergo
movement) is not a very reliable diagnostic. It is also not clear that there are any
reasons to expect that movement or the ability to stand alone should count as
phasehood diagnostics to begin with. There is nothing in the way syntactic
derivations proceed under phase-theoretical assumptions that should make us
believe that only phases should be able to undergo syntactic movement, or that
only phases should be able to stand alone. For example, we could conclude from
the grammaticality of sentence fragments of the kind given in (11b) that AdjP are
phases. But we could also conclude that they involve a more complex (phasal)
structure with some portion deleted (namely (11c)). Needless to say, this makes
the diagnostic vacuous, unless we have a clear sense of what it means for a given
string to stand alone.
(11) a. What color is the sky today?
b. [AdjP Grey].
c. [CP it is grey]

Phase Theory also does not seem to make any predictions about the movability of a given constituent. It only makes predictions about the movement
path (namely, the Phase Impenetrability Condition states that movement out of
a phase is possible only if it proceeds through the phase edge). Thus, even
though both the ability to stand alone and the ability to function as a unit for the
purposes of movement seem like reasonable and intuitive ways to understand
phonetic independence, there is nothing in the theory that leads to such a
prediction; the conditions imposed by the interfaces do not lead to a prediction
that only phases should be able to move or stand alone. However, the ability of
phase heads to determine Spell-Out does lead to two concrete diagnostics: one
having to do with determining phonological domains and the other one having
to do with ellipsis.
If phase heads determine Spell-Out, they should also determine domains for
indisputably PF-related processes, such as nuclear stress assignment (and, arguably, linear order). We will discuss this in more detail in Chapter 7, where we
focus on the syntaxphonology interface and the role phases play at this interface.
For now, sufce it to note that given the role phase heads play in determining
6

This is only a counterexample if Right Node Raising involves movement.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C03.3D

64

[5870] 23.11.2013 11:45AM

64

Phasehood diagnostics

Spell-Out, we expect them to be involved in determining phonological domains.


Crucially though, saying that phases might be relevant in determining phonological domains is not necessarily equivalent to saying that phases are the
relevant phonological domains. Furthermore, such phonological domains serve
as useful (direct or indirect) phasehood diagnostics only if they can be established
independently.
Yet another potential PF-related diagnostic comes from the domain of ellipsis.
It is a well-documented fact that elided strings have to be licensed in a sense that
is somewhat debatable (but not directly relevant to our purposes), and that only
certain types of heads can license ellipsis (see Chung, Ladusaw & McCloskey
1995, Hankamer & Sag 1976, Lobeck 1995, Merchant 2001, Sag 1976, Zagona
1988, among many, many others). What is relevant for our purposes is that Phase
Theory does seem to make a concrete prediction about ellipsis. In particular, if we
take ellipsis to be a PF phenomenon (and thus something that happens at SpellOut or after Spell-Out), it is only natural to link ellipsis to phases and assume that
only phase heads can license ellipsis. This is the view on ellipsis that has been
taken by Craenenbroeck 2010, Gengel 2007, 2009, Holmberg 2001, Rouveret
2012, among others.7 The following examples provide an illustration; what is
elided in each case is the complement of a phase head, the complement of C in
sluicing, the complement of v in VP Ellipsis (VPE) and the complement of D in
nominal ellipsis. In all of these examples, the phase head is in bold and the
missing constituent is indicated by a symbol.8
(12) a. A parrot ew somewhere but I dont know where [CP C [TP ] ].
b. A macaw ate a nut and a cockatoo did [vP v [VP ] ], too.
c. Parrots like Randys biscuts but they prefer [DP Barbaras D [NP ] ].
7

This is not to say that being a complement of a phase head is sufcient to license ellipsis. Rouveret
(2012), for example, proposes the licensing condition in (i) to capture crosslinguistic variation with
respect to VPE.
(i) Licensing Condition on VPE
VPE is available in a given structure if, and only if, vs uninterpretable [tense] feature is valued at
the v-level.

He argues that in some languages, the tense feature is valued at the v level, whereas for others it is
valued at the T level.
This view of ellipsis does raise questions about other ellipsis types, such as gapping, pseudogapping, Right Node Raising or argument ellipsis, which do not readily lend themselves to being treated
as involving deletion of a complement of a phase head. For some of them, there are alternative
treatments that do not involve ellipsis. For example, Right Node Raising has been reanalyzed in a
multidominant fashion (see Citko 2011a, b and the references therein), and gapping has been argued
to involve ATB movement (see Johnson 2000, 2009). Logically speaking, it could also be the case
that ellipsis is not directly linked to Spell-Out, and, consequently, the grammar has to include some
process directly responsible for ellipsis that goes beyond spelling out the complement of a phase
head as null. Aelbrecht (2009), for example, argues explicitly against the claim that only phase
heads can license ellipsis.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C03.3D

65

[5870] 23.11.2013 11:45AM

PF diagnostics

65

This is not the only view of ellipsis that has been proposed within the connes
of Phase Theory. Bokovi (to appear) argues that either complete phases or
complements of phase heads can be elided. To illustrate with a concrete example,
he argues, following ener & Takahashi (2009), that (13b) involves ellipsis of a
complete noun phrase, since it allows for both a strict and sloppy reading, the
latter being characteristic of ellipsis.9
(13) a. Taroo-wa sannin-no sensei-o
Taro-TOP
three-GEN teacher-ACC
Taro respects three teachers.
b. Hanako-mo e sonkeisiteiru.

sonkeisiteiru.
respects

[Japanese]

Hanako-also
respects
(Lit.) Hanako respects e, too.
(Bokovic to appear: 22, citing Sener & Takahashi 2009: 3)

Possessors, particles and quantiers can escape ellipsis, which Bokovi takes to
mean that complements of phase heads can also be elided. Interestingly, he notes
that when both a quantier and a possessor is present, the quantier can escape
ellipsis but the possessor cannot:
(14) *B sensei-wa hotondo-no Ziroo-no tikoku-o
yurus-anakat-ta.
Prof. B-TOP
most-GEN
Ziro-GEN tardiness-ACC forgive-NEG-PST
Prof. B didnt forgive most of Ziros tardiness.
(Bokovic to appear 28, citing Takahashi 2001)

This is related to an independent claim that phases are dynamic in that the highest
projection in a given extended projection constitutes a phase. In (14), the highest
projection is the QP hosting the quantier most. This is the projection that
constitutes a nominal phase. The possessor occupies a specier of a lower
(non-phasal) head. In Bokovis theory, (14) is ungrammatical because it
involves ellipsis of a complement of a complement of a phase head. We will
discuss the possibilities of phases being dynamic in more detail in Chapter 6. For
now, let me conclude the discussion of PF diagnostics by listing the questions that
survived the scrutiny of this section; positive answers to these questions classify a
given constituent as a PF phase. I do so in (15); the answers to (15b) and (15c)
establish the answer to (15a).
(15) a. Does X trigger Spell-Out?
b. Does XP constitute (or determine) a prosodic domain?
c. Can the complement of X be elided?

See, however, Merchant (2013) for a discussion of some issues with considering sloppy identity a
reliable diagnostic of ellipsis.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C03.3D

66

66

[5870] 23.11.2013 11:45AM

Phasehood diagnostics

3.3 LF diagnostics
A common characterization of phases is that, in addition to being independent at
PF, they should also be independent at LF. What this means is that they should be
interpretable and complete in some semantically relevant sense. However, as
often pointed out, it is not very clear what it means to be complete in a semantic
sense. Furthermore, what counts as complete can mean different things depending on the category. One possibility, explored by Matushansky (2005), would be
to equate semantic completeness with being saturated; in other words, being of
type e or t. From this perspective, only elements of type e (individuals) or type t
(truth values) would be phases. Thus only certain types of DPs would be phases:
proper names (being of type e), but not quantied DPs (being of type <<e,t >,t>).
On the Generalized Quantier theory, no DP would ever be a phase, since all DPs
are of the unsaturated type <<e,t >,t>, as also noted by Matushansky (2005).
Furthermore, even if we take semantic saturation to be a viable diagnostic, it is not
going to be a reliable one, given that the semantic type of a given constituent can
change if something moves out of it.
Chomsky often refers to a slightly different kind of completeness: the
kind associated with a complete argument structure. However, it is not clear
that an unaccusative verb is any less complete than an unergative one; both
require only one argument, yet Chomsky only treats unergative (and transitive)
vPs as phases. Treating unergatives as hidden transitives with a hidden object,
along the lines of Hale & Keyser (1993), provides a possible solution to this
problem.
There are other (perhaps more concrete) diagnostics that are arguably also
semantic, which I list in (18). One has to do with reconstruction, and the other one
with QR. Classifying them as semantic is somewhat controversial, since they
both have to do with overt movement out of XP, which is undeniably a syntactic
process. However, since they deal with the interpretation of elements moving out
of phases, it seems innocuous enough to treat them as semantic (or both syntactic
and semantic).
(16) a. Can an element moving through the edge of XP be interpreted at the edge of
XP?
b. Is XP a target for Quantier Raising?

Another potential LF phasehood diagnostic comes from existential closure


and the distinction between nuclear scope and the restrictive clause. It has been
proposed that the quanticational partition of the clause into nuclear scope and
restrictive clause corresponds to the distinction between a vP and a CP phase10
(see Butler 2005, Biskup 2009a, Carnie & Barss 2006, among others). Since it is

10

Butler also takes a TP to be a phase.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C03.3D

67

[5870] 23.11.2013 11:45AM

Syntactic diagnostics

67

not clear that this is a general diagnostic that can be applied to test the phasehood
of other categories, I will not rely on it here as a diagnostic, but will come back to
it in Section 7.2, which deals with the syntaxsemantics interface and the role
phases play at that interface.
Quantier Raising might seem odd as a phasehood diagnostic, given the
classic view that QR targets TPs, non-phases on standard assumptions (see May
1977, 1985, for example). There are, however, many independent factors
involved (such as semantic type compatibility, economy or locality considerations), which make it impossible for QR to target many phrases, but the availability of QR in cases where these factors do not intervene does help us establish
that movement can target the edge of a given a category, a property associated
with phases. Bruening (2001), for example, argues that QR is subject to economy
in that it targets the closest constituent of the right semantic type (type t). Thus, vP
is always going to be the closest semantically appropriate QR landing site for vPinternal quantiers. This can explain clause-boundedness of QR; since vP is
always closer than a CP, CP is never a potential landing site, and successive
cyclic movement from the edge of the embedded vP to the edge of matrix vP
would be banned by the Phase Impenetrability Condition. Thus PIC, as shown by
Cecchetto (2004), can explain clause-bounded nature of QR. Simply put, if QR
could target CPs, there would be no way to explain it. QR should be able to take
place successive-cyclically, the way wh-movement takes place.

3.4 Syntactic diagnostics


The Phase Impenetrability Condition, which we discussed in detail in Section 2.4
above, and which is repeated in (17) below, gives rise to a number of very tangible
diagnostics. Since, for the most part, this class of diagnostics involves syntactic
movement (which may or may not have semantic effects), it is only natural to
treat them as syntactic.
(17) a. [ZP Z . . . [XP X [HP [ H YP ] ] ]
b. The domain of H is not accessible to operations at ZP [emphasis mine, B.C.];
only H and its edge are accessible to such operations. (Chomsky 2001: 14)

The question is whether movement out of XP has to proceed through the edge of
XP. I will refer to this property of phases as the edge property.11 This general
question can be broken up into more specic questions about the effects of such
movement, listed in (18).12
11

12

This is slightly different from perhaps the more typical usage of the term edge property, which
takes it to be the feature that triggers movement to the edge.
These are familiar from the vast literature on successive cyclic movement (see Boeckx 2003,
2008a, Felser 2004 and the references therein, for more detailed discussion of successive cyclic
movement, and Lahne 2008 in particular for a discussion of these (and other) diagnostics in the
context of Phase Theory).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C03.3D

68

68

[5870] 23.11.2013 11:45AM

Phasehood diagnostics

(18) a. Can the moved element be interpreted at the edge of XP?


b. Can the moved element be pronounced the edge of XP?
c. Can the moved element strand anything the edge of XP?

It may well be the case that some of these diagnostics are phonological and
some are semantic, or that they cannot be classied as falling neatly into one
(or the other) class. As we saw above, deciding whether a given diagnostic is a
PF, LF or a syntactic diagnostic might not matter for all practical intents and
purposes as long as we assume phase integrity, take the same categories to
count as both PF and LF phases, and take Transfer to PF and LF to occur at the
same time. This is not uncontroversial; we alluded to the possibility of nonsimultaneous Transfer/Spell-Out in Section 2.5, and we will discuss it in more
detail in Chapter 6.
There are two other diagnostics that do not seem to be easily classiable
as either PF or LF diagnostics, as they do not capitalize on the idea that
phases are independent at the interfaces. Both have to do with uninterpretable
features. If phase heads drive syntactic computation, and uninterpretable
features are the syntactic engines, uninterpretable features have to be associated with phases. Thus the questions in (19ab) can also be used to diagnose
phases.
(19) a. Is XP a domain for feature valuation?
b. Is X the source of uninterpretable features?

If phase heads are the only locus of uninterpretable features, and as such, they
literally drive syntactic computation, the only way a non-phase head such as T or
V can acquire uninterpretable feature is through Feature Inheritance. We have
seen above (in Section 2.3) that in many accounts, being the locus of uninterpretable features is in fact the denitional property of phases. Recall the Phase
Condition of Gallego (2010), repeated below.
(20) Phase Condition
Uninterpretable features signal phase boundaries. (Gallego 2010: 151)

One might object to the phasehood diagnostics we have discussed in this


chapter on the grounds that they involve certain circularity. We have established a set of diagnostics of the following form: if X and Y share property p,
they are phases. However, it could just as well be the case that having property
p is a consequence of being a phase rather than a diagnostic of it. I do not think
I will be able to resolve this potential issue here; I will proceed on the
assumption that property p is a phasehood diagnostic if property p is associated with phasehood.
One important syntactic phenomenon that might seem to be conspicuously
absent from the discussion of phasehood diagnostics (or phases in general) in this
book is island effects. This is not to say that Phase Theory is not concerned with
island effects, and it goes without saying Phase Theory would be incomplete at

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C03.3D

69

[5870] 23.11.2013 11:45AM

Syntactic diagnostics

69

best without an account of islands that is complete with its basic tenets. And
islands have indeed received a fair amount of attention in phase-theoretical
literature (see, for example, Mller 2011 and Gallego 2010 for specic proposals
on how certain islands can be derived). However, since our focus here is on
introducing Phase Theory and justifying phases themselves, an adequate discussion of islands from a phase-theoretical perspective, which merits a book-length
discussion of its own, would take us too far astray.13 Let me nevertheless comment briey on the status of islands in Phase Theory.
Locality, which is captured by means of the Phase Impenetrability Condition, is
an important aspect of Phase Theory but, strictly speaking, there is no direct
correlation between islandhood and and phasehood. This makes islands not very
useful for the purposes of diagnosing phases. First, it is not simply the category of a
given phrase (CP versus TP, or DP versus NP) that determines whether it is an island
or not. For example, only certain types of CPs and DPs are islands, namely interrogative CPs and denite DPs. Appealing to a lled edge position (lled [Spec,CP]
position and a lled [Spec,DP] position in these two cases) is not going to be helpful,
since adding an extra specier to a phase head is always an option, and a lled
specier does not always lead to island violation (as also pointed out by Boeckx &
Grohmann 2007). For example, a lled [Spec,vP] does not make that vP an island.
All Phase Theory says is that movement out of phases has to proceed through phase
edges; it does not say that movement out of phases (or non-phases, for that matter) is
impossible. Furthermore, as we know, the answer to the question of whether a CP or
DP is an island depends on many independent factors. DP is an island only for
certain movements (in certain languages, as we will see in Chapter 4): movement of
a specier of D, for example, leads to an island violation but movement of (or from)
the complement of D only does so sometimes. Furthermore, whether DP or CP is an
island depends on what positions it occupies: if it is a complement, movement out of
it is possible, but if it is a specier or an adjunct, it is not. This is Huangs (1982)
Condition on Extraction Domains, which distinguished objects on the one hand,
from subjects and adjuncts on the other hand, by appealing to proper government, an
obsolete theoretical concept. In phase-theoretical terms, CED effects have been
derived from the Phase Impenetrability Condition, combined with certain assumptions about features and activity (see Mller 2011 and Gallego 2010 in particular).
To illustrate briey, Mller proposes that the (optional) EPP feature (edge feature in
his terms) can be added to a phase head only if the phase head is still active, where
being active means not having had all its features checked. This includes features
checked by both Internal and External Merge. Extraction from subjects is banned in
his system because the subject is the last element merged in the vP phase. This means
that the EPP feature cannot be added after the subject is merged. At that point, the v
head is no longer active because it has had all its features checked. Without that EPP
feature, movement is going to violate the Phase Impenetrability Condition. Adding
13

I refer the interested reader to Mller (2011) and Boeckx (2012) for book-length discussions of
islands specically.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C03.3D

70

70

[5870] 23.11.2013 11:45AM

Phasehood diagnostics

the EPP feature before the subject is merged is possible because the v head is still
active; this is what allows movement of the object (or out of the object). But this is
not going to help with extraction out of the subject since the subject has not been
merged yet.
Setting islands aside, let me conclude the current chapter by listing the
three types of diagnostics, as they are the ones that will be used as the basis of
the discussion in the next two chapters, where we look at specic categories and
determine whether they pass as phases according to these diagnostics. In the next
chapter (Chapter 4), we will look at three classic phases CPs, vPs and DPs
whose phasehood status is fairly well established in the literature on phases.
(21) PF phasehood diagnostics
a. Does X trigger Spell-Out?
b. Does XP determine phonological domains?
c. Can the complement of X be elided?
(22) LF phasehood diagnostics
a. Can an element moving out of XP be interpreted in the edge position?
b. Is XP a target for Quantier Raising?
(23) Syntactic phasehood diagnostics
a. Can an element moving out of XP be pronounced (partially or completely) at the
edge?
b. Can an element moving out of XP strand anything at the edge?
c. Is XP a domain for feature valuation?
d. Is X the source of uninterpretable features?

We have alluded above to alternative approaches to phases, such as Bokovi


(to appear), Mller (2004), or Den Dikken (2007), which rely on (or require)
different sets of diagnostics, and end up with different categories counting as
phases. While these alternatives do avoid problems with imprecise characterizations of phases, they often raise questions of their own. For Bokovi, for
example, all lexical categories (Vs, Ns, Ps and As) project phases. However, for
him it is not necessarily the case that every V, N, P or A head is a phase head.14 Its
phasehood is determined relative to the context in which it appears (see also
Bobaljik & Wurmbrand 2005) in that the highest projection in the extended
domain of each lexical category is a phase. This can yield to a fair amount of
crosslinguistic variation if languages differ in terms of how extended their
extended projections are. For Epstein & Seely (2002, 2006), Lahne (2008) and
Mller (2004, 2011), all phrases are phases, which leads to a very different view
of successive cyclic movement. For Den Dikken, whose proposal we will discuss
in more detail in Chapter 6 (Section 6.1), the denitional characteristic of a phase
is the subjectpredicate conguration.
14

This is different from proposals that claim that every phrase is a phase (as suggested by Mller
2004, for example).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

71

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

4
Classic phases

4.1 CPs as phases


This section reviews the evidence pointing towards CPs being phases. Most of
it involves well-known (and often discussed) evidence that long-distance whmovement takes place in a successive-cyclic fashion through intermediate [Spec,
CP] positions (see, for example, Boeckx 2008a, Felser 2004, Lahne 2008 and the
references therein).1 What matters for our purposes is that successive-cyclic
movement targeting a certain projection can be taken as evidence in favor of
this projection being a phase. We dubbed this property of phases the edge
property.2 The questions that can help us diagnose this edge property are given
in (1). In the case at hand, the edge refers to the edge of CP, namely the [Spec,CP]
position.3
(1) a. Can an element moving out of CP be pronounced at the edge of CP?
b. Can an element moving out of CP strand anything at the edge of CP?
c. Can an element moving out of CP be interpreted at the edge of CP?

In this section we will also look at the properties of the C head, particularly its
featural makeup (whether it has any uninterpretable features and whether it
1

Many of the phenomena I discuss in this chapter are also discussed by these authors, and are
generally well-known from the literature on successive cyclic movement. Lahne (2008), for
example, also discusses reconstruction, agreement, quantier oat, partial movement and whcopying. Her conclusions, however, are different from the conclusions reached here, as she takes
all phrases to be phases. Felser (2004) focuses on partial movement and wh-copying. Legate (2003)
discusses reconstruction, parasitic gaps, QR and nuclear stress assignment (focusing on vPs rather
than CPs).
However, there is more to establishing whether a CP (or any other category) is a phase than
establishing whether it has the edge property, and we have seen many phasehood diagnostics
that do not make reference to edges. We will discuss non-edge diagnostics in this section
as well.
The title of Lahnes (2008) dissertation Where There Is Fire There Is Smoke captures the spirit of
the diagnostics considered here; we are looking for the smoke.

71

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

72

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

72

Classic phases

triggers Spell-Out). Both of these properties are associated with phase heads only.
We will defer the discussion of CPs as potential phonological domains till
Chapter 7.
Perhaps the most straightforward illustration of the edge property comes from
the domain of long-distance wh-movement of the kind represented schematically
in (2). In such congurations, the wh-phrase moving out of the lowest CP has to
pass through (at the very least) each [Spec,CP]. For now, we will not worry about
whether it has to pass through any other positions; this is the issue we turn to in
the next section.
(2) [CP WH [C C [TP

[CP WH [C C [TP [CP WH [C C [TP WH ] ] ] ] ] ] ] ] ]

Even though the claim that long-distance wh-movement proceeds in such


successive-cyclic fashion is hardly controversial, the why-question (i.e.
the motivation for movement to the intermediate positions) is somewhat less
understood; the Phase Impenetrability Condition offers the rst glimpse into this
why-question. If both C and v are phase heads, as I hope to convince the reader by
the end of Section 4.2, this is the only way a wh-phrase can get from the
embedded clause to the matrix [Spec, CP]. Crucially, this is different from
the question of what features drive this movement, the question I set aside for
the time being. Thus, in a simple case such as the one in (3a) below, represented
schematically in (3b), the embedded TP is spelled out when the matrix v is
merged. Thus, if the wh-pronoun does not move to [Spec,CP] in the embedded
clause, it will not be accessible either to the matrix v or C (via PIC), as shown in
(3b). Movement to the specier of the embedded vP is not indicated in this
diagram, but the same logic applies: the complement of v is spelled out when C
is merged, so the only way for the wh-phrase to avoid Spell-Out is to move to
[Spec,vP].
(3) a. What does Jan think Piotr read?
b.
vP

v
v
V

TP Spell-Out

CP
C

TP
... WH...

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

73

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

CPs as phases

73

There are a number of ways to tell that wh-movement does indeed target the
edge of CP. Perhaps the simplest one is to look at what happens if the edge is
lled. And, indeed, unless a language has some other strategy (such as the
availability of multiple speciers), the result is ungrammatical and constitutes a
familiar example of a wh-island violation:
(4) a. *What did you think [CP when Jan devoured what when]?
b. *This is the book which Jan wondered [CP who wrote which].
c. *How did you wonder [CP who xed the sink how]?

Interestingly, languages can vary in whether they obey the Wh-Island Condition,
as noted by Rizzi (1982) for Italian and by Rudin (1988) for Bulgarian, for
example. The examples in (5ab) show that in these languages movement from
wh-islands does not result in ungrammaticality.
mi
domando che
storie abbiano
(5) a. tuo fratello, a cui
your brother, to whom myself ask.1SG which stories have.3PL

raccontato. [Italian]
told

your brother, to whom I wonder which stories they told (Rizzi 1982: 50)

oveka, kojto
b. C
the man who.REL

ne znae
NEG

kakvo kazvat

know.2S what

ce

kupil

[Bulgarian]

say.3PL that has bought

The man who you dont know what they say that he bought.

(Rudin 1988: 452)

The common explanation for Bulgarian is that its CPs allow multiple speciers,
as evidenced by the well-known the fact that Bulgarian (along with other Slavic
languages) is a multiple wh-fronting language.4 From a phase-theoretical perspective, what such languages teach us is that a phase edge can contain multiple
speciers (at least in those languages in which all wh-phrases move to [Spec,CP],
such as Bulgarian and Romanian).5 This explanation, however, is not going to
work for Italian, which is not a multiple wh-fronting language, and, to make
things even more intriguing, is not even a language that allows English-style
multiple wh-questions with one of the wh-phrases in situ, noted by Calabrese
(1984) and discussed more recently by Stoyanova (2008).6 The classic account of
the grammaticality of wh-island violations in Italian is that of Rizzi (1982); it
4

The literature on multiple wh-fronting is vast, starting with Wachowiczs (1974) observation that
there are indeed languages that can front all their wh-phrases overtly, and Rudins (1988) seminal
work on the distinction between two types of multiple wh-fronting languages, which, in most
general terms, differ with respect to whether they treat all the fronted wh-pronouns alike or
privilege the highest one. See also Boeckx & Grohmann (2003), Bokovi (2002b) and Richards
(2001), among others, for more recent proposals and renements of the early empirical
generalizations.
We have already seen that v, another candidate for a phase head, also allows multiple speciers. There is
a stage in the derivation in which the subject is in the inner specier and the object in the outer one.
Stoyanova also includes Somali, Irish and Berber in her discussion of languages with no multiple
wh-questions, and attributes the lack of multiple wh-questions to the existence of a unique focus
position in such languages.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

74

74

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

Classic phases

involves parameterization of bounding nodes, and, consequently, of the


Subjacency Condition itself. If in Italian, a CP (rather than a TP) counts as a
bounding node that is relevant for subjacency, the movement of the wh-phrase a
cui in (5a) above would cross only one bounding node. An explanation along
these lines, however, is somewhat anachronistic, and perhaps more gravely
incompatible with the claim that crosslinguistic variation is limited to features of
individual lexical items, sometimes referred to in the literature as the Borer
Chomsky Conjecture.7
Leaving wh-islands and subjacency aside, let us turn to other wellestablished arguments in favor of movement proceeding through the specier
of CP, and thus, indirectly, in favor of CPs being phases. A fair amount
comes from reconstruction effects; situations in which the moved element is
interpreted in a lower position than the position in which it is pronounced (see
Barss 1986, 2001, Fox 1999, 2000, Lebeaux 2009 and the references therein).8
On a syntactic approach to reconstruction, in which reconstruction amounts to
the interpretation of a lower copy, the only way a wh-phrase can be interpreted
in an intermediate [Spec,CP] position is if it passed through this position,
leaving a copy behind. Consider in this light example (6): the presence of
multiple wh-copies gives rise to multiple potential interpretations, involving
different antecedents. If the copy in the specier of CP1 is the one that is
interpreted, the most local potential binder for the anaphor is going to be
Piotr. If it is the highest copy instead (the one in the specier of CP2), the
most local potential binder is going to be Jan. And if it is the lowest one, the
most local potential binder is going to be Adam.

On a methodological note, it is worth noting that what looks like the same phenomenon can have
very different explanations from language to language.
The phenomenon of reconstruction is quite complex; there are many factors that play a role, such as
the differences in reconstruction possibilities between A and A-bar movement, arguments and
predicates, and questions and relative clauses, to name just a few. The very assumption that
reconstruction is a syntactic mechanism is far from being uncontroversial. There is also a possibility
that different binding principles might exhibit reconstruction behavior. For example, Lebeaux
(2009) argues that Binding Principles A, B and C apply at different points in the derivation (contra
the standard minimalist view, on which they all apply at LF only), and that the negative principles
(Principles B and C) have to apply throughout the derivation while the positive principle (Principle
A) applies at LF. As he himself admits, examples of the following sort are a problem, as before
movement they violate Principle C. He resorts to a kind of late insertion mechanism to avoid such
problems.
(i) John seems to himself to like cheese.

Since my goal here is not to argue for a specic analysis of binding, I will abstract away from these
controversies. All that matters for our diagnostic purposes here is that reconstruction be a syntactic
mechanism, indicating the presence of a lower copy.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

75

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

CPs as phases

75

(6) Jan4 asked [CP2 [which picture of himself2,3,4]1 Piotr3 thought [CP1 which picture of
himself1 that Adam2 liked [which picture of himself2,3,4]1.

Fox (1999, 2000) looks at slightly more complex cases to establish that
in successive cyclic movement contexts, wh-pronouns can be interpreted in
intermediate [Spec,CP] positions. Building on the work of Lebeaux (1994)
and Heycock (1995), he looks at the interaction of scope reconstruction with
Binding Principle C, and concludes that reconstruction feeds Principle C. In
cases where reconstruction would lead to a Principle C violation, reconstruction
is blocked. Fox examines successive cyclic movement cases in which the whphrase undergoing movement contains both an R-expression and a bound
pronoun.9 The pronoun, in order to receive a bound variable interpretation,
has to be c-commanded by the quantied expression that binds it. The
R-expression, on the other hand, cannot be c-commanded by the pronoun
coindexed with it. In the conguration given in (7a) there exists a position
(indicated by ) in which the wh-phrase can be c-commanded by the quantied
DP but not by the pronoun. This is not an option in (7b), as reconstruction to
either of the two available positions will result in a Principle C violation.10
(7) a. [which. . . pronoun1. . . r-expression2] . . ..QP1 pronoun2 . . . * . . .
b. [which . . . pronoun1 . . . r-expression2] . . . pronoun2 . . .*. . . QP1 . . .*. . .
(Fox 1999: 173)

The actual examples are given in (8ab). In (8a), the wh-phrase can be interpreted
in the intermediate [Spec,CP] position (indicated by t), in which the pronoun he1
will be bound by every student, but the R-expression Ms. Brown will not be
bound by she2. In (8b), on the other hand, this is not an option; reconstruction
even to the intermediate position (t) will yield a Principle C effect. This is only
possible if movement takes place through the edge of CP, which in turn is only
possible on current assumptions if CP is a phase.
(8) a. [Which (of the) paper(s) that he1 gave to Ms. Brown2] did every student1 hope t
that she2 will read t?
b. *[Which (of the) paper(s) that he1 gave to Ms. Brown2] did she2 hope t that
every student1 will revise t? (Fox 1999: 173, citing Lebeaux 1990)

This suggests the derivation in (9) (rst pass) for long-distance movement.
The questions that we will come back to are whether there are any other
intermediate landing sites, and what exactly drives the movement to the intermediate [Spec,CP] positions. For now, let us assume the answer to the latter
question is some uninterpretable feature with the EPP property.

10

Foxs goal, however, is to establish that Principle C applies at LF, rather than to argue for the
phasehood of CPs.
The star here indicates a position to which reconstruction will result in a Principle C violation.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

76

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

76

Classic phases

(9) a. Who does she think John saw?


b.

b.

CP

whoiwh[wh]

CiForce[Q],uwh[wh],EPP TP
DPuC[Nom] T
shei[3sg]T u[3sg],EPP vP
she

v
v

VP

think vu[3sg] think

CP
who

CiForce[Decl],EPP

TP

DPuC[Nom]
D

Johni[3sg]Tu[3sg],EPP vP
John

v
v

saw vu[3sg] saw

VP
whoiwh[wh]

Another well-known range of arguments in favor of successive cyclic movement taking place through the specier of CP comes from kinds of questions
in which the wh-phrase with a matrix scope can either be pronounced in the
embedded [Spec,CP] or leave something behind in this position. There are a
number of such cases to consider, illustrated below in pseudo-English. (10a)
is allowed only in some varieties of English, (10b) in childs English, and
(10c) and (10d) not at all. In all of them, the scope of the wh-phrase who
or which movie is in the matrix [Spec,CP]; however, the embedded [Spec, CP]
contains some portion of it (in the form of the stranded quantier or the nominal),
the wh-phrase itself (in case of the partial wh-movement construction) or its copy.
(10) a.
b.
c.
d.

wh-quantier stranding
[CP who did John think [CP who all Bill saw who all]
[CP who did John think [CP who Bill saw who]
wh-copying
[CP what did John think [CP who Bill saw who]
partial wh-movement
[CP which movie did John think [CP which movie Bill saw which movie]
split wh-movement

Now, let us turn to some actual data, starting with the phenomenon dubbed whquantier oat by McCloskey (2000) in the varieties of English he refers to
as West Ulster English. What distinguishes West Ulster English dialects from
standard English is that they allow the quantier all to be associated with a whpronoun (as shown in (11a)), and more interestingly for our purposes allow
the quantier to be separated from the wh-pronoun, as shown in (11b). In this
respect, these varieties differ from standard English, which only allows quantier
oat under A-movement, thus providing a nice window into the inner workings
of successive cyclic wh-movement.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

77

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

CPs as phases

77

(11) a. What all did you get for Christmas?


[West Ulster English]
b. What did you get all for Christmas? (McCloskey 2000: 58)

Crucially, in long-distance questions, the quantier can appear in the intermediate [Spec,CP] positions (as in (12a)), in addition to being stranded in
its base position (as in (12b)), or pied-piped all the way to the matrix [Spec,
CP] (as in (12c)).
(12) a. What did he say all (that) he wanted?
b. What did he say (that) he wanted all?
c. What all did he say (that) he wanted t? (McCloskey 2000: 61)

McCloskey adopts Sportiches (1988) analysis of quantier oat, in which the


position of the oated quantier can only mean one of two things: that the
element undergoing movement has started in the position of a oated/stranded
quantier or that it has moved through this position.11 McCloskey further
assumes that the quantier occupies the D position, and that the wh-pronoun
moves to the specier of DP rst before moving out of the DP, thus stranding
the quantier. Such movement suggests that DPs might also be phases, a
possibility I discuss in detail in Section 4.3 of this chapter. We might wonder,
however, if the movement in (13) violates antilocality (See Grohmann 2003,
Abels 2003), which prevents movement of a complement of a given phrase to
the specier of the same phrase; the rationale is that such movement violates
economy, not by virtue of being too long (one could not think of a shorter
movement, in fact) but by virtue of being too short, hence unmotivated. I do not
think this is a major blow to the analysis presented here, given the evidence that
DP structure is much more elaborate than the picture in (13a) might suggest. I
will not belabor this point here, as DP phasehood (and consequently, DP
internal structure) is the main focus of Section 4.3. The addition of a single
projection between D and N, shown in (13b), will make the movement of NP
to the specier of DP legitimate from the standpoint of antilocality. Now the
wh-pronoun what is not moving from the complement of one head to the
specier of the same head.12

11

12

The stranding analysis is by no means the only analysis of quantier oat. Alternatives include
treating the oated quantier as an adjoined adverbial of sorts. I refer the interested reader to
Bobaljik (2003) and the references therein for further discussion. The claim that quantiers can be
stranded in their base positions is also not uncontroversial. Bokovi (2004a), for example, argues
that stranding in thematic positions is impossible.
Abels version of antilocality is different from Grohmanns. Grohmann (2003, 2011) divides clause
structure into what he dubs prolic domains (theta domain, case/agreement domain, operator
domain) and argues that movement within the same domain (as opposed to movement across
domains) is illegitimate.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

78

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

78

Classic phases

(13) a.

DP
D

whati
D
all

b.

ti

DP
D

whati
D
all

XP
X

ti

We might ask here whether quantiers are the only elements that can be stranded
in intermediate landing sites. Two other phenomena come to mind: preposition
stranding and what we might call nominal stranding. Felser (2004), following
Du Plessis (1977), shows that Afrikaans, for example, allows P-stranding in
intermediate positions. The availability of such intermediate P-stranding would
have to be parameterized, as not all languages that in principle allow P-stranding
allow it in intermediate positions. English, for example, does not, as noted by
Postal (1972) and illustrated in (14ab).13 How to achieve such parameterization
(in a way that attributes it to some lexical property of some lexical item rather than
simply stating it as a general parameter), however, is not a trivial matter. If
stranded prepositions undergo reanalysis (as suggested, for example, by
Hornstein & Weinberg 1981), one way to explain why preposition stranding in
intermediate [Spec,CP] positions is not allowed would be to assume that the
requisite reanalysis is blocked across a CP boundary and to parameterize the
reanalysis itself.
(14) a. *Who/Whom do you believe to Mary thinks Joan talked?
b. *Who/Whom do you believe Mary thinks to Joan talked? (Postal 1972: 213)

Both quantier stranding and preposition stranding are amenable to a nonstranding analysis, in which the entire wh-phrase moves but part of it is
pronounced in [Spec,CP] and part in the pre-movement site, as illustrated
schematically in (15a) for preposition stranding and (15b) for quantier stranding. This does not affect the point made here, which is that movement targets
[Spec,CP].

13

Postal himself uses the ungrammaticality of such examples to argue against successive cyclic
movement, which is not the point I am making here.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

79

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

CPs as phases

79

(15) a. [CP To who [C C [TP . . . [CP to who [C C [TP . . . to who] ] ] ] ] ]?


b. [CP All what [C C [TP . . . [CP all what [C C [TP . . . all what] ] ] ] ] ]?

The mechanism illustrated here, referred to in the literature as distributed deletion


or scattered deletion, has also been employed to handle various types of discontinuous noun phrases (see Fanselow & avar 2002 and the references therein),
illustrated in (16) and (17) for Polish with the two parts of the split/discontinuous
DP given in italics.14 Distributed deletion is particularly appealing for cases of what
would otherwise have to involve non-constituent movement, such as the ones
given in (17), in which what is pronounced in the fronted position is the preposition
followed by the wh-determiner (to the exclusion of the complement of D).
(16) a. Kolorowe Maria zobaczya papugi.
colorful
Maria saw
parrots
Maria saw colorful parrots.
b. Papugi Maria zobaczya kolorowe.
parrots Maria saw
colorful
Maria saw colorful parrots.
c. Ile
Maria naliczya papug?
how.many Maria counted parrots
How many parrots did Maria count?

[Polish]

(17) a. O
australijskich Maria czytaa papugach.
about Australian
Maria read
parrots
Maria read about Austrialian parrots.
b. O
papugach Maria czytaa australijskich.
about parrots
Maria read
Australian
c. O
jakich
Maria czytaa papugach?
about what.kind Maria read
parrots
What kind of parrots did Maria read about?

Perhaps the most extreme example of a wh-pronoun leaving something


behind in intermediate movement sites comes from a construction referred to
in the literature as wh-copying (see Felser 2004, Lahne 2008 and the references
therein), in which a complete copy of the wh-phrase is pronounced in each [Spec,
CP] on the wh-pronoun movement path. Representative examples from Felsers
work are given in (18ad).
(18) a. Wen glaubst Du, wen sie getroffen hat?
Who think
you who she met
has
Who do you think she has met? (Felser 2004: 544)
14

[German]

The idea that copies can be pronounced in a discontinuous manner is related to the idea that under
some (fairly restricted) circumstances, pronunciation of a lower copy is forced in languages with overt
movement of the relevant kind. This is the case when the pronunciation of the higher copy would lead
to a PF violation (see Franks 1998, Bokovi 2002b and the references therein).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

80

80

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

Classic phases

b. Waarvoor dink julle waarvoor werk ons?


[Afrikaans]
Wherefore think you wherefore work we
What do you think we are working for?
(Du Plessis 1977: 725; Felser 2004: 544)
c. Kas
o Demri
mislenola
kas
i Arfa
dikhla?
[Romani]
Whom
Demir
think
whom
Arifa
saw
Who does Demir think Arifa saw?
(McDaniel 1989: 569 note 5; Felser 2004: 544)
d. Who do you think who is in the box?

[Child English]
(Thornton 1990: 204)

The Copy Theory of Movement provided a simple explanation of this construction: wh-copying could be thought of as copying with no subsequent
deletion. While there are many non-trivial questions that wh-copying raises
(especially given that movement is no longer thought to be a simple copying
operation), what matters most for our purposes is the evidence for movement
through [Spec,CP] that it provides. First, how to motivate movement through
all the intermediate positions? This is the question Felser dubs the triggering
question. This is the question that arises for all cases of successive-cyclic
movement (not just wh-copying). Second, what allows the embedded CP to
converge in spite of the fact that it seems to contain copies with unvalued
features? After all, only one copy (the highest one) determines the scope of the
wh-question and values the uninterpretable wh-feature (or Q feature) on C. This
is what Felser calls a convergence question. And third, what allows multiple
copies to be pronounced. This is the linearization question. If copies count as
identical elements with respect to linearization, the result is going to violate the
Linear Correspondence Axiom (LCA) of Kayne (1994), which prohibits structures in which the same element both c-commands and is c-commanded by
itself.15 Any account of wh-copying, phase-theoretical or not, must answer
these questions. The convergence question and the linearization question might
appear to be non-distinguishable, but they are actually quite distinct. The
convergence question focuses on why the Spell-Out of a wh-phrase with
some of its uninterpretable features unchecked/unvalued does not violate Full
Interpretation. Note that the wh-phrase does not get its uQ feature valued/
checked till it undergoes Agree with the matrix C (which is the C that bears
the corresponding iQ feature and marks the scope of the wh-question). Felser
solves the convergence problem in the following way. First, she assumes,
following a long line of research going back at least to Katz & Postal (1964)
on the morphosyntax of wh-pronouns, that they can be decomposed into the
15

Even though the specics of the LCA in its original formulation are incompatible with Bare Phrase
Structure theory, the idea behind it (the idea that linear order is not a syntactic primitive) is very
much minimalist in spirit (see, however, Chomsky 1995 and Kayne 2010 for different ways to
make the LCA compatible with BPS).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

81

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

CPs as phases

81

quanticational part (the wh-part) and the indenite part. Second, she posits
that the two parts can be pronounced in a discontinuous manner, akin to what
saw above in discontinuous DPs (see the Polish examples in (16) and (17)).
We also alluded to it being a possible analysis for preposition stranding and whquantier stranding. In a copying construction, in a way that is similar to split
wh-questions, the indenite part is pronounced in the embedded [Spec,CP] and
the quanticational part is pronounced in the specier of the matrix [Spec,CP].
It just happens to be the case that the two parts sound the same, so to speak, in
the languages under consideration here, namely in those that allow wh-copying.
A derivation incorporating this insight, including only the relevant features for
the sake of simplicity, is given in (19).16
(19)

CP
whoiWH,iINDEF

C
C

TP
you

T
T

Spell-Out whoiWH

vP

you

v
v

VP

think v think CP
whoiWH,iINDEF C
C

TP
John

vP

Spell-Out whoiINDEF

John

v
v

VP

saw v saw

whoiWH,iINDEF

Partial wh-movement (also referred to in the literature as scope marking) is


similar to wh-copying in that there is a wh-element in both the matrix and
embedded [Spec,CP]. However, the two wh-elements are distinct; the scope of
the wh-phrase is marked by the so-called scope marker (typically a default whpronoun), and the contentful wh-phrase is in the embedded [Spec,CP]. The

16

This also leads Felser to argue for a convergence-based view of phases. In (29), the uninterpretable wh-feature of the wh-pronoun is not going to be checked until the wh-pronoun reaches the
matrix [Spec,CP]. This suggests that the embedded CP cannot be spelled out before this feature is
valued.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

82

82

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

Classic phases

literature on scope marking is vast; see, among others, Bruening (2004), Dayal
(1993), Felser (2004), Horvath (1997), Lahne (2008), Lutz, Mller & von
Stechow (2000), Manetta (2010), McDaniel (1989), Stepanov (2000) and the
references therein. The examples below, in which both the real wh-phrase and the
scope marker are given in bold, provide an illustration.
(20) a. Was glaubt Hans [mit wem
Jacob jetzt spricht]? [German]
what believe Hans with whom Jacob now talks
Who do you think Maria has spoken with? (cf. McDaniel 1989: 569)
b. Jak myslisz
[co
Maria zrobi]?
[Polish]
how think.2SG what Maria do.3SG
What do you think Maria will do?
c. Kak vy
dumaete, [kogo ljubit
Ivan]?
[Russian]
how you think.2PL whom love.3SG John
Who do you think John loves? (Stepanov 2000: 1)
d. Mit
gondolsz, [hogy kit
ltott
Jnos]?
[Hungarian]
who.ACC saw.3SG John.NOM
what.ACC think.2SG that
Who do you think that John saw? (Horvath 1997: 510)

We might be tempted to analyze scope marking in a way that is similar to partial


wh-movement, with the wh-pronoun being spelled-out in a distributed fashion
across the main and the embedded [Spec, CP]. However, the two wh-elements in
a scope-marking construction do not lend themselves to a partition along the
indenite/quanticational divide of the kind we saw in (19). As Felser also points
out, assimilating the two constructions along these lines would leave a number of
well-documented differences between them unaccounted for. For example, whcopying is restricted to simple wh-pronouns such as who or what but impossible
with complex wh-phrases such as which book. No such restriction is present in
scope marking.17, 18 There is also no sense in which the scope marker, which is
the wh-word what in some languages, and interestingly, how in Slavic languages,
is a complete copy (or a partial one) of the real wh-pronoun. It is thus more
typical to think of the scope marker as an independent element (perhaps an
expletive of sorts, as suggested by McDaniel 1989, for example). The scope
marker can either be inserted directly in the matrix [Spec,CP], as shown schematically in (21a), or start out in the embedded [Spec,CP] and move to the matrix
[Spec,CP], as shown in (21b). In both cases, the scope marker is capitalized. The

17
18

Interestingly, Felser reports that some speakers accept wh-copying with prepositional phrases.
Felser discusses other differences as well, such as the ability to conjoin two embedded clauses
and their compatibility with verbs like seem. What matters for our purposes is the fact that both
partial wh-movement and wh-copying provide evidence for movement through the embedded
[Spec,CP].

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

83

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

CPs as phases

83

latter option is favored by Mahajan (1996) for Hindi and by Stepanov (2000) for
Polish and Russian.
(21)

a.

CP
C

WHATiwh[wh]

CiForce[Q],uwh[wh],EPP

CP
who iwh

CiForce[Decl], uwh[wh]EPP

TP

who iwh

b.

CP
C
CiForce[Q],uwh[wh],EPP

DP
WHATiwh
whoiwh

CP
C
CiForce[Decl], uwh[wh]EPP

TP

whoiwh

The existence of so-called agreeing complementizers also provides quite a


convincing argument for successive-cyclic movement through the edge of CP,
and thus indirectly for CPs being phases. The well-known case of Irish, due to
McCloskeys seminal work on the topic, provides a nice illustration. Irish has
different types of complementizers, which some researchers analyze as verbal
particles (a point of contention that goes beyond the scope of this chapter). The
one relevant for our purposes is the one glossed as aL, which appears in whextraction contexts. More importantly, it also appears in every intermediate
[Spec,CP] in long-distance wh-extraction contexts:19

19

In addition to relative clauses and wh-questions, which are perhaps the two best-known cases, we
see the same complementizer in equative clauses, comparative clauses and clefts (see McCloskey
2001 for examples and a detailed analysis).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

84

84

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

Classic phases

(22) a. an ghirseach a
ghoid na siogai.
[Irish]
the girl
aL stole the fairies
the girl that the fairies stole away
b. rud
a
gheall
tui
a
dheanfa.
thing aL promised you aL do.COND-S2
something that you promised that you would do (McCloskey 2001:678)

Complementizer agreement is also found in other languages (Germanic and


Bantu, most notably), and we saw some examples of it in Chapter 3, in the context
of the discussion of Feature Inheritance. The relevant examples are repeated in
(23) and (24) below. The pattern generalizes widely across the Bantu language
group; Carstens reports on a study of over seventy languages that show similar
agreement. In (23), the verb is in C and it agrees in noun class with the whpronoun in the specier of CP.20
(23)

Bik
bi--ks-l-
bbo bkulu
mwm
8what 8CA-A-give-PERF-FV 2that 2woman 1chief
What did those women give the chief in the village?

mu-mwlo?
[Kilega]
183village
(Carstens 2005: 220)

In long-distance questions, both the matrix and the embedded verb agree with the
wh-pronoun in class. This also shows that the wh-phrase has passed through the
embedded [Spec, CP].
(24)

Bik
bi--tnd-l
bna
bi--gl-l
nina-b?
8what 8CA-A-say-PERF 2child 8CA-A-buy-PERF mother-their
What did the children say their mother had bought?
(Carstens 2005: 247)

The issue of how to account for such complementizer agreement phenomena is


somewhat contentious in the literature. For some researchers, such as
Kinyalolo (1991), it is a reex of spechead agreement. McCloskey (2002)
analyzes the Irish complementizer aL as a realization of C with an operator
feature and an EPP feature. Carstens (2005), however, analyzes agreeing
complementizers in terms of Agree between a C head endowed with uninterpretable -features and a wh-element in its scope. Either way, complementizer
agreement provides evidence that C is a Probe having uninterpretable features,
thus a phase head.
The two types of uninterpretable features that we considered in this section
were uninterpretable wh-features and uninterpretable -features, capturing whmovement and complementizer agreement phenomena, respectively. It is certainly true that non-phase heads such as T can have uninterpretable features
(uninterpretable -features being an obvious example), but, as we saw in
Chapter 2 (Section 2.6), non-phase heads can only have uninterpretable features

20

Crosslinguistically, complementizer agreement is not limited to wh-extraction contexts. The point


that matters for our purposes is that it is possible in those contexts.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

85

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

CPs as phases

85

if they inherit them from phase heads above. Such Feature Inheritance is not a
very likely option for C, especially in matrix contexts, where there is no head
(phase or non-phase) dominating it. And in embedded contexts, where C is
typically dominated by a non-phase head such as a V or an N, the presence of
uninterpretable features on C is highly indicative of C being a phase head. The
phenomenon of complementizer agreement (illustrated above with Bantu, West
Germanic and, in a slightly different form, Slavic data) also suggests that the
uninterpretable -features do not have to be obligatorily inherited by T, and that
languages can vary in whether these features stay on C (yielding complementizer
agreement) or migrate down to T (yielding subjectverb agreement). These are
two of the three options proposed by Ouali (2008): SHARE and KEEP, given in
(25ab). If C shares its features with T, the result is both complementizer agreement and subject verb agreement. If C keeps its features, the result is just
complementizer agreement.
(25) a. Cu
b. Cu

Tu SHARE
T KEEP

In all the cases of complementizer agreement under consideration here,


the same set of -features is taken to be responsible for subjectverb
agreement and for complementizer agreement. This claim has recently
been challenged by Haegeman & Van Koppen (2011), who argue for
dissociating the two, based on the fact that in (26), for example, the
complementizer agrees with the rst member of the conjunct, but the verb
agrees with the entire conjunction phrase.
(26)

Ich dink de-s


[toow en
Marie] kump.
[Limburgian]
I
think that-2SG you.SG and Marie come.PL
I think that you and Marie will come.
(Haegeman & Van Koppen 2011: 3)

Leaving complementizer agreement aside, let us turn to the last piece of


evidence in favor of CPs being phases. Given that complements of phase heads
undergo Spell-Out, the fact that the complement of C can undergo ellipsis is also
evidence in favor of CPS being phases. This is what happens in sluicing constructions. On the most straightforward account of this construction (see
Merchant 2001 and the references therein for arguments in favor of such an
account), sluicing involves movement of the wh-phrase moves to [Spec,CP],
followed by deletion of the TP, as schematized in (27).
(27) I know Maria likes someone but I dont Know [CP whoi [C C [TP Maria likes ti ] ] ]

Let us briey consider two of his arguments. One involves a crosslinguistic


correlation between the ability to strand prepositions in sluicing constructions and the ability to strand prepositions in run-of-the-mill wh-questions.
English, for example, allows preposition stranding in both cases, as shown
in (28ab).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

86

86

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

Classic phases

(28) a. I know that Maria talked to someone but I dont know [CP whoi [TP Maria talked
to ti].
b. Whoi did Maria talk to ti?

On the other hand, Polish (patterning together with other Slavic languages in this
respect) disallows preposition stranding in both sluicing and wh-constructions, as
shown in (29ab):21
(29) a. *Wiem,
ze
Maria
rozmawiaa z
kims,
[Polish]
know.1SG that Maria
talk.PST.3SG with
someone
ale
nie wiem
[CP kimi
[TP Maria rozmawiaa z ti] ].
but
not know.1SG whom
Maria talked
with
I know that Maria talked to someone but I dont know whom?
b. *Kimi Maria rozmawiaa z
ti?
with
Maria talk.PST.3SG with
Who did Maria talk to?

This led Merchant to the following generalization:


(30) A language L will allow preposition stranding under sluicing iff L allows preposition stranding under wh- movement. (Merchant 2001: 92)

Case provides further evidence in favor of a deletion account. The case of the
fronted wh-pronoun is the case it is assigned within the elided clause. In (31a) it is
Instrumental not Nominative. This also provides an argument against an analysis
of sluicing that derives it from a cleft (illustrated in (31b)), which would incorrectly predict Nominative case instead:
(31) a. Maria zainteresowaa sie czyms,
ale nie wiem
czym/*co.
Maria got.interested REFL something.INSTR but not know.1SG what.INSTR/*NOM
Maria got interested in something but I dont know what.
b. Maria zainteresowaa sie czyms,
ale nie wiem co
Maria got.interested REFL something.INSTR but not know.1SG what.NOM
to
jest
czym
Maria
sie zainteresowaa.
it
is
what.INSTR Maria
REFL get.interested.PST.1SG.
Maria got interested in something but I dont know what (it is that Maria got
interested in).

This concludes our discussion of CPs as phases. The table in (32) summarizes the
behavior of CPs (and C heads) with respect to the phasehood diagnostics
established in Chapter 3.

21

See, however, Szczegielniak (2008) and Stjepanovic (2008) for some interesting counterexamples
to this correlation, from Polish and Serbo-Croatian, and Sato (2011) for similar evidence from
Indonesian.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

87

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

CPs as phases

87

(32) CPs as phases


Diagnostic question

Answer Evidence

Does C trigger Spell-Out?

Yes

Can the complement of C be elided?


Can an element moving out of CP be
interpreted in [Spec,CP]?
Can an element moving out of CP be
pronounced (partially or completely) in
[Spec,CP]?

Yes
Yes

VP-internal elements
inaccessible
sluicing
reconstruction

Yes

preposition stranding
(subject to crosslinguistic
variation)
quantier stranding
wh-copying
scope marking

Is CP a domain for feature valuation?

Yes

Is C the source of uninterpretable


features?

Yes

nite CPs as domains for


Nominative case valuation
u-features
uwh-features

Let me conclude this section with a brief comparison of CPs with TPs with
respect to the same diagnostics. So far, we have assumed TPs not to be phases, but let
us see if the behavior of TPs with respect to the diagnostics actually conrms this
assumption. If TPs were phases (and T heads were phase heads), we would expect a
number of things from them. First, we would expect T heads to trigger Transfer/
Spell-Out. This would put limits on Agree (since on standard assumptions, no Agree
is possible into spelled out constituents). For example, if both T and v were phase
heads in (33a), VP would contain an object whose case feature could not be valued.
(33) a. Piotrowi podobaja sie te
Peter.DAT please
REFL
Peter likes these owers.

b.

kwiaty.
owers.NOM

[Polish]

TP
T
Tu [ ], EEP

vP

DP

v
VP

v
V

DPuC[

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

88

88

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

Classic phases

Second, we would expect ellipsis to be able to target vP. While Merchant does
analyze pseudogapping as vP ellipsis, this could be due to the fact that T might have
inherited whatever features make it a licensor for vP ellipsis from C. Thus we are
only going to look at cases in which T is not dominated by (a nite) C, and it could
not have inherited any features from it. Raising innitives (both subject to subject
raising and exceptional case marking) are a case in point. Unlike control innitives,
they are assumed to be TPs, not CPs. Evidence to support this distinction comes
from tense considerations. Stowell (1982) argues that raising innitives are nonnite and non-tensed (i.e. involve a T[-nite, -tensed]), whereas control innitives are
non-nite but tensed (i.e. involve a T[-nite, +tensed] ). The tense of an embedded
control innitive clause is interpreted as unrealized or future with respect to the
tense of the matrix clause. By contrast, the tense of an embedded raising innitive
clause is interpreted as simultaneous with respect to the tense of the matrix clause.
This is shown by the contrast in (34). In (34a), the time of parrots ying in the
rainforest is typically understood to be future with respect to the time of their desire
to do so. In (34b), on the other hand, the two events (my expectation and the event
of parrots ying) are understood to be simultaneous.
(34) a. Parrots want to y in the rainforest.
b. I expect parrots to y in the rainforest.

If being tensed is a property of a C-T complex (rather than of T alone), this


contrast receives a natural explanation: there is a C head in (34a) but not in (34b).
ECM innitives (and raising innitives more generally) are thus good diagnostic
cases, as there is independent evidence that they do not involve a CP layer (so
Feature Inheritance is not a confounding factor).
If T were a phase head, we would expect it to be able to license ellipsis by
itself. The fact that raising and ECM innitives do not license VP ellipsis, as
shown in (35ab), suggests that T is not a phase head.22
(35) a. *I expect cockatoos to be funny but I dont consider blue-headed macaws to .
b. *Cockatoos are able to y but kakapos dont appear to .

The next diagnostic concerns successive-cyclic movement. If TP were a


phase, we would expect wh-movement to target the edge of TP (in addition to
targeting the edges of other phases), and the derivation of the wh-question in
(36a) to proceed as in (36b) not (36c).
(36) a. What do parrots eat?
b. [CP WHi [C C [TP ti [TP parrotsj [vP ti [ tj [v v [VP eat ti]]]]]]]]
c. [CP WHi [C C [TP ti [TP parrotsj [vP ti [ tj [v v [VP eat ti]]]]]]]]

Investigation of such cases, however, is not very illuminating, as the intermediate


copy in [Spec,TP] is so close to the nal copy. For example, interpreting the copy in
22

See Lobeck (1995) for a classic account of the factors which determine which heads do (and which
ones do not) license ellipsis.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

89

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

CPs as phases

89

the [Spec,TP] position is indistinguishable from interpreting the copy in [Spec,CP].


Wh-movement in successive-cyclic raising contexts, however, is more informative.
Here, the question is whether movement proceeds as in (37b) or (37c).
(37) a. Which parrots appear to be likely to nest soon?
b. [CP WHi [TP ti [TPappear[TP ti [TPto be likely [TP ti [TP ti] ] ] ] ] ] ]
c. [CP WHi [TPappear [TP ti to be likely [TP ti] ] ] ]

Abels (2003) argues against wh-movement proceeding as in (37a), uniformly


targeting all the TP edges (hence the term he uses, uniform paths). His crucial
contrast is given in (38). If wh-movement took place through the edge of TP, we
would expect both (38a) and (38b) to be grammatical.
(38) a. Which pictures of himselfi did it seem to Johni that Mary liked?
b. *Which pictures of himselfi did Mary seem to Johni to like? (Abels 2003: 30)

The reason (38a) is grammatical is that which pictures of himself can be interpreted in the intermediate position (bolded in (39)), in which John is the closest
binder for the anaphor himself contained within the wh-trace/copy:
(39) [CP Which pictures of himselfi [C0 did [TP it seem to Johni [CP ti that [TP Mary liked ti
]]]]]?

However, if wh-movement targeted intermediate [Spec, TP] positions, we would


expect (38b) to be equally grammatical, with the anaphor himself also bound by
John in the intermediate (bolded) position:
(40) *[CP Which pictures of himselfi [C0 did [TP Mary seem to Johni [TP ti [TP to like ti ]]]]]?

This indicates that TP cannot be a phase, since wh-movement cannot proceed


through its edge.
A related question concerns A-movement. The question is whether A-movement
takes place through intermediate embedded [Spec,TP] positions (as in (41a)), or
movement in one step (as in (41b)).23 Such examples are often brought to bear on the
issue of the status of EPP in the grammar. If T were a phase head (and EPP were the
uninterpretable feature by assumption only associated with phase heads), we would
expect any movement out of TP to have to proceed through the edge of TP.
(41) a. The parrots appear to be likely to nest soon.

23

b.

[TP The parrotsi appear [TP ti to be likely [TP ti to nest soon] ] ]

c.

[TP The parrotsi appear [TP to be likely [TP ti to nest soon] ] ]

PIC does not discriminate between A-bar and A-movement. The fact that passive movement does
not target the [Spec,vP] as an intermediate landing site does show that passive vPs are not phases, or
at least the same kinds of phases as active vP. This is the point I discuss in the next section.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

90

90

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

Classic phases

Epstein & Seely (2006) and Grohmann, Drury & Castillo (2000) argue explicitly
against A-movement proceeding in a successive-cyclic fashion. Many of their
arguments are quite theoretical in nature, involving the general status of EPP in
the grammar, or the nature of chains formed by this movement. Empirical
considerations of the familiar kind, such as binding of quantier stranding,
however, do seem to suggest that A-movement takes place through the intermediate speciers of TP.24 Consider the following example:
(42) a. Johni seems to Mary to appear to himselfi to be ill.
b. *Mary seems to Johni to appear to himselfi to be ill.
(Grohmann, Drury & Castillo 2000: 160)

If John and Mary moved directly from their thematic positions, as shown in
(43ab) below, there would be no way to account for this contrast. In both
cases, they would be moving from the positions in which they do not bind the
anaphor.
(43) a. Johnj seems to Maryi [TP to appear to himselfi [TP to be tj ill] ]
b. *Maryj seems to Johni [TP to appear to himselfi [TP to be tj ill] ]

Successive-cyclic derivation, on the other hand, can capture this contrast; in


(43b), schematized in (44b), there is a copy of the matrix subject Mary in the
intermediate subject position, which causes a Principle A violation:
(44) a. Johnj seems to Maryi [TP tj to appear to himselfi [TP tj to be tj ill] ]
b. *Maryj seems to Johni [TP tj to appear to himselfi [TP tj to be tj ill] ]

Quantier stranding, also discussed by Grohmann, Drury & Castillo (2000),


shows that movement proceeds through the embedded specier of TP, which is
one of the positions in which the quantier can be stranded:
(45) a. The parrots appear all to be ready to nest soon.
b. The parrots appear to all be ready to nest soon.
c. The parrots all appear to be ready to nest soon.

Bokovi (2002a) also presents evidence in favor of intermediate landing sites


in raising congurations. In addition to the quantier oat and Condition A data of
the kind discussed above, he discusses variable binding (following Lebeaux 1991
and Nunes 1995). In (46a), reconstruction to the position necessary for variable
binding results in a Principle C effect. In (46b), on the other hand, there exists a
position (the intermediate specier of TP position) in which the pronoun his can be
bound by every man without the R-expression his mother being bound by her.
(46) a. *[Hisi mothersj bread]k seems to herj [TP tk to be known by every mani [TP tk to
be tk the best there is.]]

24

Grohmann, Drurg & Castillo (2000) attribute this observation to David Pesetsky, who in turn
credits Danny Fox. They themselves do not take it to indicate successive cyclic movement.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

91

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

vPs as phases

91

b. [Hisi mothersj bread]k seems to every mani [TP tk to be known by herj [TP tk to be
tk the best there is.]] (cf. Bokovic 2002: 180)

The table in (47) summarizes the behavior of TPs with respect to phasehood
diagnostics.
(47) TPs as phases
Diagnostic Question

Answer Evidence

Does T trigger Spell-Out?

No

Can the complement of T be elided?

No

Can an element moving out of TP be


interpreted in [Spec,TP]?
Can an element moving out of TP be
pronounced (partially or completely) in
[Spec,TP]?
Is TP a domain for feature valuation?

No

Is T the source of uninterpretable


features?

Yes

No
No

Agree between T and


Nominative object would be
impossible
lack of VP ellipsis with ECM/
raising verbs
no reconstruction in successive raising contexts
quantier stranding in
[Spec,TP]
no Nominative case in nonnite contexts
no -feature agreement
(unless T is dominated by a
nite C)

4.2 vPs as phases


In this section, we examine the status of vPs with respect to the phasehood
diagnostics we established in Chapter 2 and applied to CPs in the previous
section. The diagnostics, relativized to vPs, are repeated in (48).
(48) a. Does v trigger Spell-Out?
b. Can the complement of v be elided?
c. Can an element moving out of vP be interpreted at the edge of vP?
d. Is vP a target for Quantier Raising?
e. Can an element moving out of vP be pronounced (partially or completely) at the
edge of vP?
f. Can an element moving out of vP strand anything at the edge of vP?
g. Is vP a domain for feature valuation?
h. Is v the source of uninterpretable features?

We will examine different types of vPs, distinguishing those selecting an external


argument (transitive and unergative ones) from those not selecting one (passive
and unaccusative ones). The question of whether passive and unaccusative vPs
are phases relies on the not uncontroversial assumption that there is a vP layer in
such clauses to begin with. We know that passive and unaccusative verbs differ
from transitive and unergative ones in that they (i) do not value Accusative case,

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

92

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

92

Classic phases

and (ii) do not select an external argument. This is Burzios Generalization, which
becomes easy to account for if there are no vPs in passives and unacccusatives.
However, irrespective of whether passives and unaccusatives involve the structures in (49b) and (50b) (with a vP) or the structures in (49c) and (49c) (with no
vP), the question of whether they constitute phases is still valid. It just becomes a
question about passive and unaccusative VPs rather than vPs.
(49) a. Tom arrived.

b.

TP
T
Tu [

],iT[pst], EPP

vP
VP

c.

V
arrived

TP

DPi [3sg,masc],uC[

Tom

T
Tu [

],iT[pst], EPPVP

V
arrived

DPi [3sg,masc],uC[

Tom

(50) a. Tom was chosen.

b.

TP
T
Tu [
was

], iT[pst], EPP

vP
VP

v
V
chosen

DPi [3sg,masc], uC[


Tom

c.

TP
T
Tu [
was

], iT[pst], EPP

V
chosen

VP
DPi [3sg,masc], uC[
Tom

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

93

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

vPs as phases

93

Let us rst look at the properties of v heads in order to determine whether v is the
locus of uninterpretable features and whether v determines Spell-Out.
The answer to the rst question seems fairly straightforward, at least for
transitive (and unergative) vPs. The idea that in transitive clauses v is responsible
for structural Accusative case and that the Agree relationship between v and the
object in its domain, shown in (51ab), values Accusative case is standard, and I
will not dwell on it here.
(51)

a.

vP
vu [

VP

V
read

DPi [3sg],uC[

a book

b.

vP
VP

vu [3sg]
V
read

DPi [3sg], uC[Acc]


a book

We also know that the complement of v can be elided; this is VP Ellipsis


(VPE), perhaps one of the best-studied ellipsis types. As we saw in Chapter 3, if
phase heads determine points of Transfer, VPE can be thought of as a null SpellOut of the complement of v.
(52) a. Mary talked to Bill and Tom did, too.

b.

CP
C

TP
Tom

Tu [3sg], EP vP
did

VP

SPELL-OUT DOMAIN

talk to Bill

Since v in this case is empty, we might wonder why ellipsis couldnt target vP
instead. Merchant (2008) shows that VPE is indeed deletion of a VP (and not a vP),

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

94

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

94

Classic phases

based on the fact that it allows voice mismatches in which the antecedent clause is
active and the elided clause is passive or vice versa.25
(53) a. This problem [VP1 was to have been looked into], but obviously nobody did
[VP2 look into this problem].
PASSIVE VP1 /ACTIVE VP2
b. The janitor must [VP1 remove the trash] whenever it is apparent that it
should [VP2 be removed].
ACTIVE VP1 /PASSIVE VP2
(cf. Merchant 2008: 169)

Merchant accounts for the availability of such mismatched examples by assuming that v (which includes voice information) is not included in the elided portion,
which is what allows the v head in the antecedent clause to be passive and the one
in the elliptical clause to be active, as shown in (54).
(54)
&P
&
CP

but

CP
C

vP

vP

vivoi[pass] VP
look_into

nobody
DP

this problem

vivoi[act]

VP

look into this problem

The edge diagnostics, which helped us determine whether movement out of a


phase has to proceed through the phase edge, were perhaps the most fruitful
diagnostics in the discussion of CPs as phases, so let us apply them to vPs. If vPs
are phases, successive cyclic movement would have to proceed as in (55b), rather
than proceeding as in (55a), resulting in two extra copies, given in bold.
(55) a. [CP WH [C C [TP . . . [CP WH [C C [TP . . .WH . . . ] ] ] ] ] ]
b. [CP WH [C C [TP [vP WH [v v . . . [CP WH [C C [TP [vP WH [v v . . .WH . . . ]]]]]]]]]]
25

If pseudogapping, as Merchant (2008) argues (based on the fact that unlike VPE it does not allow
voice mismatches), is vP (rather than VP) ellipsis, the generalization that only complements of
phase heads allow ellipsis breaks down. Bokovi argues that in pseudogapping cases, it is not a v
but a higher (verbal) projection that is a phase head, which makes vP ellipsis the ellipsis of the entire
phase head. Bokovis relativized approach to phases is something we will discuss in more detail
in Chapter 6.

95

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

vPs as phases

95

A related question is whether [Spec,vP] is ever the nal (as opposed to the
intermediate) landing site for wh-movement, as shown in (56a) for a monoclausal wh-question and in (56b) for wh-movement that spans across clausal
boundaries.
(56) a. [CP [C C [TP[vP WH [v v . . . [VP . . .WH . . . ]]]]] ]
b. [CP [C C [TP[vP WH [v 0 v . . . [CP WH [C0 C [TP [vP WH [v 0 v . . .WH . . . ]]]]]]]]]]

This is one way to think about so-called short wh-movement, overt whmovement to a clause-medial position. The examples in (57ae) provide an
illustration: this is how Jayaseelan (2001) analyzes Malayalam, Aldridge
(2010) archaic Chinese, Manetta (2010) HindiUrdu, and Citko (2010) a subset
of wh-questions in Polish.26, 27 It is also a plausible way to think of Hungarian
wh-questions.
(57) a. nin-ne aar aTiccu?
[Malayalam]
you-ACC who beat.PST
Who beat you? (Jayaseelan)
b. Wu shei qi?
Qi
tian
hu?
[Archaic Chinese]
I
who deceive deceive Heaven Q
Who do I deceive? Do I deceive Heaven?
(cf. Aldridge 2010: 2, from Analects 9)
c. Hamid-ne kya: par.ha:?
[HindiUrdu]
Hamid-ERG what read
What did Hamid read?(Manetta 2010: 4)
d. Co
Ewa komu
daa?
what.ACC Ewa who.DAT gave
What did Ewa give to whom?(Citko 2010: 46)
e. Jnos kit
mutatott
be Marinak?

[Hungarian]

John who.ACC introduced PRT Mary.to


Who did John introduce to Mary? (Cable 2008: 3)

26

The idea that Polish wh-movement can target a clause medial position goes back to Dornisch
(1998), who also points out that this medial position has to be an A-bar position, based on the fact
that it licenses parasitic gaps:
(i) Za

co

by

Piotr

kogoi

wyrzuci

nie

Piotr

who

throw.out

not

wysuchawszy pgi

przedtem?

listen.PART
before
For what would Peter throw out whom without having listened to? (Dornisch 1998: 160)
for

27

what

COND

However, many researchers working on Hungarian take this position to be a more specic focusdesignated projection (see, for example, Kiss 1987). Cable (2008), however, argues against this
position.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

96

96

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

Classic phases

In successive-cyclic movement contexts, there are a number of ways we


could diagnose the presence of these extra copies. While I am not aware of any
cases in which all the copies are realized (as in (58a)), there are cases in which the
copies surface in [Spec,vP] (as in (58b)).28
(58) a. [CP WH [C C [TP [vP WH [v v . . . [CP WH [C 0 C [TP [vP WH [v 0 v . . .WH . . . ]]]]]]
b. [CP WH [C C [TP[vP WH [v v . . . [CP WH [C 0 C [TP [vP WH [v 0 v . . .WH . . . ]]]]]]

We saw above that Manetta (2010) analyzes wh-movement in HindiUrdu


as targeting the [Spec,vP] position. In this respect, she contrasts Kashmiri (a
language in which C is the phase head responsible for wh-movement) with
HindiUrdu (a language in which v head is the phase head responsible for whmovement). However, since HindiUrdu is an SOV language, (57c) above in
itself is not evidence for wh-movement targeting [Spec,vP] position, as it is also
compatible with the wh-pronoun never leaving its initial position. The example in
(59), however, is incompatible with the in-situ analysis, as the wh-phrase originates in the embedded clause.29
(59) Sita-ne kis-ko
soca:
ki
Ravi:-ne dekha:?
Sita-ERG who-ACC thought that Ravi-ERG saw
Who did Sita think that Ravi saw? (Manetta 2010: 1)

HindiUrdu also has a wh-scope-marking construction, in which the scope


marker is at the edge of the matrix vP and the real wh-phrase remains
inside the embedded clause, as shown in (60ab)). (60b) also shows that
such expletive wh-elements appear in every clause separating the clause
containing the real wh-phrase and the clause in which the wh-phrase gets its
scope.30
(60) a. Sita-ne kya: soca:
ki
Ravi:-ne kis-ko
dekha:? [HindiUrdu]
Sita-ERG EXPL thought that Ravi-ERG who-ACC saw
Who did Sita think that Ravi saw? (Manetta 2010: 1)
b. Ra:m-ne kya: soca: ki Ravi:-ne kya: kaha: ki kon sa a:dmi: a:ya:?
Ram-ERG EXPL thought that Ravi-ERG EXPL said that which man came
Which man did Ram think that Ravi said came? (Manetta 2010: 24)

28

Example (59) could also involve the derivation in (i), in which there are no deleted copies in the
speciers of CP, just Agree between C heads and the wh-phrases in [Spec,vP]:
(i) [CP [C C [TP[vP WH [v v . . . [CP [C C [TP [vP WH [v v . . .WH . . . ]]]]]]

29

30

Manetta also gives independent evidence to argue against the claim that HindiUrdu is a wh-in-situ
language, coming from adverb placement, for example. The preverbal position that the wh-word
occupies is also a generalized focus position, something which is also the case in other languages
with this type of short wh-movement.
Manetta describes the scope marker kya: as a minimal wh-word.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

97

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

vPs as phases

97

In principle, the difference between languages like English or Kashmiri, in which


wh-phrases surface at the edge of the CP phase, and languages like HindiUrdu,
in which they surface at the edge of the vP phase, could mean one of the following
two things: either wh-movement proceeds through the edge of CP in some
languages but through the edge of vP in others, or movement uniformly proceeds
through the edges of both CP and vP, but languages choose which copies to
pronounce. The rst possibility is reminiscent of Rackowski & Richards (2005),
who argue, based primarily on data from Tagalog, that long-distance movement
proceeds directly from the embedded [Spec,vP] to the matrix [Spec,vP]. In
Tagalog, as in other Austronesian languages, we see morphological reexes of
this movement in the form of verbal agreement: the extracted element agrees with
the verb. In (61) what gets extracted is the indirect object, and we see the dative
agreement marker on the verbal complex.31
(61)

Sino ang b-in-igy-an ng lalaki ng buluklak? [Tagalog]


who ANG ASP-give-DAT CS man CS ower
Who did the man give the ower to? (cf. Rackowski & Richards 2005: 587)

The differences between languages in which wh-movement targets the edge of


CP and the languages in which it targets the edge of vP could mean that C is a
phase head in some languages but v is in others, and, more generally, that
phasehood could be subject to parametric variation. We will discuss the latter
possibility in more detail in Chapter 6.32 This, however, is neither the route that
Manetta takes to explain the difference between Kashmiri and HindiUrdu, nor
the one Rackowski and Richards take to explain the difference between Tagalog
and English.
The morphological evidence from Tagalog in (61) parallels in spirit the
morphological evidence we used in the previous section to establish that C is a
phase head. There we looked at complementizer agreement phenomena; here
we are looking at what might be called v-agreement phenomena. This vagreement is indeed what we nd in Austronesian languages (see, among
others, Chung 1994, 1998, Lahne 2008 on Chamorro, Sato 2012 on Malay/
Bahasa Indonesia, Rackowski & Richards 2005 and Aldridge 2005 on
Tagalog). We saw above that the verb agrees with the moved wh-phrase.

31

32

The Tagalog-specic glosses used in these examples are:


CS case
ANG subject, topic, pivot marking
Rackowski and Richards actually generalize their claim to English-type languages, and argue that
even in such languages, wh-movement proceeds from the embedded [Spec,vP] to the matrix [Spec,
vP]. This leaves all the evidence in favor of wh-movement proceeding through the edge of [Spec,
CP] in need of an alternative explanation. While not impossible (and Rackowski and Richards do
offer some insightful suggestions), it does raise some non-trivial questions.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

98

98

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

Classic phases

Conversely, arguments that do not agree with the verb cannot be extracted. This
is the well-known extraction restriction of Austronesian syntax. Aldridge
attributes it to the Phase Impenetrability Condition: if movement out of a
phase proceeds through the phase edge, only elements at the edge can undergo
further movements.
Let us look at a couple of other examples. Chung (1994) analyzes
wh-agreement in Chamorro as agreement with a trace. The wh-agreement
morphology is sensitive to the case of the moved element, which, among other
things, leads her to conclude that wh-agreement is not a reex of C agreeing with
a wh-phrase in its specier. The contrast between (62a) and (62b) provides an
illustration. When the wh-trace is Nominative, the wh-agreement is realized as
the inx -um-; when it is objective (or oblique), it is realized as -in-.
(62) a. Humllum si Maria [na ha-pnak si Juan i
ptgun].
AGR.assume Maria
COMP AGR-spank Juan
the child
Maria assumes that Juan spanked the child.

[Chamorro]

b. Hayi hinaloma si Maria [ t pumnak t i


ptgun]?
who? WH.assume Maria
WH.spank
the child
Who does Maria assume spanked the child? (Chung 1994: 1)

A slightly different, yet related, illustration comes from Indonesian, in which


the morphological marking involves the deletion of the active voice prex
men-. Sato (2012) analyzes this as a reex of the wh-phrase moving through
the edge of vP, where it checks the uninterpretable D-feature of v. This is what
blocks the insertion of the active voice prex and forces the insertion of a null
one instead. What is crucial for our purposes is that the deletion of the menprex marks the path site.
(63) a. Siapai yang Bill (*mem)-beritahu ibu-nya
[CP yang ti *(men)-cintai Fatimah]?
who
that Bill AV-tell
mother-his that
AV-love
Fatimah
Who does Bill tell his mother that loves Fatimah?
b. Apai
yang Ali (*mem)-beri ti kepada Fatimah?
to
Fatimah
what that
Ali AV-give
What did Ali give to Fatimah? (Sato 2012: 34, citing Cole & Hermon 1998: 2312)

Yet another way to establish the edge property of vPs is to look at stranding
possibilities. The question here is whether quantiers, prepositions or nominals
can ever be stranded in [Spec, vP] positions, the same way they can in [Spec,CP]
positions.
(64) a. [CP WH [C C [TP . . . [vP WH all [v v . . . [VP . . .WH . . . ] ] ] ] ] ]
b. [CP WH [C C [TP. . . [vP P WH [v v . . . [VP . . .WH . . . ] ] ] ] ] ]
c. [CP which [C C [TP. . . [vP which NP [v v . . . [VP . . .WH . . . ] ] ] ] ] ]

McCloskey shows that West Ulster English, a language that allows quantier
stranding in intermediate [Spec,CP] positions (as we saw in the previous section),
disallows analogous stranding in [Spec,vP] positions.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

99

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

vPs as phases

99

(65) a. *Whati did he tell all him (that) he wanted ti?


[West Ulster English]
b. *What did he tell all his friends/Mickey (that) he wanted t?
(McCloskey 2001:63)

Preposition stranding yields similar results. It should not come as a surprise that
prepositions in English cannot be stranded in [Spec,vP] positions, given that
English does not allow P-stranding in [Spec,CP] positions either:
(66) Whoj did John [vP [PP to tj]i talk ti ] ]?

We saw, however, in Section 4.1 above that Afrikaans does allow P-stranding in
the intermediate [Spec,CP]. However, as noted by Rackowski & Richards (2005),
it does not allow stranding at the edge of vP:
(67) *Wat dink julle [vP oor dink die bure
stry
ons]? [Afrikaans]
what think you about think the neighbors argue we
What do you think the neighbors think we argue about?
(Rackowski & Richards 2005: 593)

Some evidence in favor of nominal-stranding in the specier of v comes from


languages that allow Left Branch Extraction (LBE). Wiland (2010) shows that
in Polish, one such language, the stranded nominal marks the movement path.
Thus, the fact that it can be stranded in [Spec,vP] (either in simple or longdistance questions) shows that movement does indeed proceed through the
specier of vP.33
(68) a. [CP Jaki [TP Pawe [vP samochd [VP
what
Pawe.NOM car.ACC
What car did Pawe buy for his wife?

kupi
bought

swojej
his.DAT

zonie t]]]]?
wife.DAT

b. %[CP Jaki [TP Maria [vP


samochd myslaa, [CP t ze Pawe [vP t kupi
what
Maria.NOM car.ACC
thought
that Pawe.NOM bought
swojej
zonie t]]]]]?
his.DAT
wife.DAT
What car did Maria think Pawe bought his wife? (cf. Wiland 2010: 3356)

So far we have seen mixed results regarding the pronunciation of the whpronoun (or its remnant) at the edge of vP. On the one hand, we have seen
that it can be the site of the wh-copy in HindiUrdu, that it can be the landing
site of wh-movement in languages like Hungarian, and that the nominal can be
stranded in this position in languages with Left Branch Extraction like Polish.
On the other hand, we have seen that the wh-related quantier all cannot be
stranded in this position and that prepositions cannot be stranded in this
position. I do not take these to be a fatal blow; both phenomena are known to
be sensitive to prosodic factors, which could inuence the grammaticality of

33

The % symbol indicates speaker variation. I nd this example perfectly acceptable.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

100

100

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

Classic phases

(65) or (66), as claimed explicitly by McCloskey (1998) with respect to whquantier stranding in West Ulster English. Furthermore, if P-stranding
requires reanalysis, it is also conceivable that such reanalysis is only possible
if the verb is in a certain relationship with the stranded preposition, and the
specier of vP is simply not such a position.
Let us now turn to the evidence for vPs being phases on the interpretative side.
Here the question is whether the wh-phrase can be interpreted at the edge of vP
even if it is not its ultimate resting place. The evidence that bears on this issue
comes from various types of reconstruction effects (see Agero-Bautista 2001,
Fox 1999, 2000, Lahne 2008, Legate 2003 among others).
The reconstruction argument is very similar in spirit to the argument made
in Section 4.1 to establish reconstruction into the intermediate [Spec,CP]
position. The relevant conguration is similar to the congurations we considered in the previous section (where we established that wh-movement targets
[Spec,CP] in a successive-cyclic manner). This time, however, the reconstruction site we are interested in is the edge of vP, not CP. The examples in (69)
provide evidence that wh-movement does indeed proceed through this edge. In
all of them, the fronted wh-phrase contains a bound pronoun and an Rexpression. They are all grammatical because there exists a reconstruction
site, marked with a checkmark, below the quantier and above the pronoun.
This is the edge of the vP.34
(69) a. [Which of the books that he1 asked Ms. Brown2 for] did every student1 __ get
from her2 * ?
b. [Which (of the) paper(s) that he1 wrote for Ms. Brown2] did every student1 __
get her2 * to grade? (Fox 1999: 175)

If we reverse the position of the quantier and the pronoun, as in (70) below, the
results become ungrammatical because there is no reconstruction site such that
Principle C is obeyed and the variable is bound; interpreting the wh-phrase in the
specier of the matrix vP results in a Principle C violation and a lack of variable
binding.
(70) a. *[Which of the books that he1 asked Ms. Brown2 for] did she2 * give every
student1 * ?
b. *[Which (of the) paper(s) that he1 wrote for Ms. Brown2] did she2 get * get
every student1 * to revise? (Fox 1999: 174)

A similar argument, due to Agero-Bautista (2001), comes from the availability


of the so-called Pair List (PL) readings in wh-questions with quantiers. The
34

Den Dikken (2006a) raises the possibility that the reconstruction site could also be the edge of TP
(thus providing an argument in favor of TPs being phases). It is not clear whether the moved whphrase could be tucking in below the subject. He also points out that the argument relies on the
assumption that reconstruction is the only way to get the bound variable reading. This does seem to
be the simplest assumption.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

101

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

vPs as phases

101

crucial assumption that this argument relies upon is that in questions containing a
universal quantier, the wh-phrase has to be interpreted in a position in which it is
c-commanded by the quantier. Thus, the distribution of PL readings in such
questions will help us determine possible reconstruction sites. The baseline
contrast is given in (71ab). In (71a) the PL interpretation is possible because
the wh-pronoun can reconstruct to a position below the quantied subject. In
(84b) there is no such position; hence the PL reading is not available. The only
available reading is Single Answer (SA) reading.
(71) a. Who do you think everyone saw __ at the rally? SA, PL
b. Who __ thinks everyone saw you at the rally? SA, *PL
(Agero-Bautista 2001: 142)

Augero-Bautista shows that the availability of PL readings in the Fox-style


examples points towards [Spec,vP] as a reconstruction site, and is thus consistent
with the conclusions that Fox drew based on Principle C and variable binding
data. Consider in this light the contrast in (72). In (72a), the only possible
interpretation is a SA interpretation. This implies lack of reconstruction, as
reconstruction to any site would result in a Principle C violation. In (72b), on
the other hand, reconstruction to a position below the quantier is a possibility
(and, consequently, a PL reading becomes available), since a potential Principle C
violation is not a factor.
(72) a. [Which (of the) books that John asked Ms. Brown2 for ] did
she2 give every student * ? SA, *PL
b. [Which (of the) books that John asked her2 for] did Ms.
Brown2 ___ give every student * ? SA, PL (Agero-Bautista 2001: 145)

Yet another well-known argument comes from the domain of parasitic gaps. It
relies on a particular account of parasitic gaps, namely one that involves complex
predicate formation, defended in most detail by Nissenbaum (2000), who in turn
builds on Larsons (1988) insights. Such an analysis, Nissenbaum shows, is only
possible if the wh-movement licensing the parasitic gap moves through the edge
of vP. (73) below illustrates the conguration necessary for parasitic gap formation, with irrelevant details omitted.35

35

I refer the interested reader to Nissenbaums work (and the references therein) on how such an
account captures the properties typically associated with parasitic gaps, listed in (i) (and to the
contributions in Culicover & Postal (2000) for a discussion of some counterexamples to these
generalizations). Nissenbaum himself notes, for example, that covert movement can license
parasitic gaps in multiple wh-questions if the overtly moved wh-phrase also licenses a parasitic gap. Null operators might seem suspect and there are quite a few of alternative accounts
that do not involve null operators (or complex predicates, for that matter). See Hornstein &
Nunes (2002) for a sideward movement account, and Kasai (2007) for a multidominant
account.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

102

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

102

Classic phases

(73)
CP
which paper C
did

TP
T

Johni
T

vP

which paper

vP1

vP2
John file which paper

PP
OPi without PRO reading ti

(cf. Nissenbaum 2000, Larson 1988)

The interpretation Nissenbaum assigns to the relevant nodes is given in (74ac).


(74) a. vP2: e. x. there is an event e of John ling x.
b. PP: e. .x. there is no subevent of e such that it is the reading of x by PRO.
c. vP1: ex. there is an event e of John ling x and there is no subevent e of e
such that e is the reading of x by PRO.

The null operator movement inside the adjunct PP forms a predicate, and movement of the wh-phrase to the edge of vP2 forms a predicate out of this vP. Thus,
only if vP2 contains a trace of the moved wh-phrase, the vP and PP can combine
yielding a complex (conjoined) predicate via predicate modication. This predicate can subsequently apply to the wh-pronoun. If vP didnt contain a trace of the
wh-phrase, it could not combine with the adjunct containing the parasitic gap,
because it would not be of the right semantic type.
Antecedent-Contained Deletion (ACD) provides yet another argument in
favor of movement targeting the edge of vP. This time, the movement in question
is Quantier Raising (see also Bruening 2001 for arguments that vP can be the
target for QR). The issue is how to avoid the so-called innite regress in cases of
VP ellipsis in which the antecedent VP contains the missing VP (hence the term
Antecedent-Contained Deletion). Consider a simple example in (75a). It contains
a missing VP (indicated by ). The only VP that could help us recover the content

(i) The antecedent of a P-gap must be in A-bar position.


(ii) A P-gap is licensed only at S-structure.
(iii) The antecedent of a P-gap must be an NP.
(iv) The true gap cannot c-command the P-gap
(v) The P-gap is in a chain with the antecedent of the true gap. (Culicover 2001: 65)

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

103

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

vPs as phases

103

of the missing one is the one containing the missing VP, namely saw every movie
Tom did. This leads to innite regress.36
(75) a. Bill saw every movie Tom did [VP ]
b. Bill saw every movie Tom did [see every movie Tom did [VP ]]
c. Bill saw every movie Tom did [see every movie Tom did [see every movie Tom
did [VP ]]
d. Bill saw every movie Tom did [see every movie Tom did [see every movie Tom
did [see every movie Tom did [VP ]]]]

QR solves the innite regress in the following way.37 First the quantied object
undergoes QR, as in (76b). In this particular example, it does not matter whether
QR targets vP or TP. Bruening (2001) argues in favor of the former option based
on economy considerations: adjunction to vP involves shorter movement than
adjunction to TP, and is thus more economical. Second, the missing VP gets
copied, as in (76c).
(76) a. Bill saw every movie Tom did [VP ]
b. [TP Bill [vP [DP every movie Tom did [VP ]]i [vP v [VP saw ti] ] ] ]
c. [TP Bill [vP [DP every movie Tom did [VP saw ti]]i [vP v [VP saw ti] ] ] ]

QR
COPY VP

Legate (2003) ingeniously solves the question of why QR could not always
target the matrix TP (as is perhaps more standardly assumed) by making the
quantied element a Negative Polarity Item (NPI), or by making the subject
quantied and testing if the subject can have wide scope with respect to the

36

Copying just see every movie, as in (i) below, is not an option, as this string is not a constituent;
irrespective of the specics of the structure (complementation versus adjunction) and derivation
(raising versus deletion) for relative clauses, the string saw every movie Tom did is a constituent, but
saw every movie is not.
(i) Bill saw every movie Tom did [VP see every movie]
(ii)

VP
V
saw

DP
D
every

NP
NP

37

CP

movie Tom did [VP]


See, among others, Larson & May (1990), Kennedy (1997) for QR-based accounts of ACD, and
Baltin (1987), Hornstein (1994) for non-QR based alternatives, which rely on movement to a case
position or extraposition instead.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

104

104

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

Classic phases

QR-ed object. The rst case is illustrated by (77), modeled upon Legates
examples. In (77a), the only way to resolve innite regress without moving
the NPI out of the scope of negation is to adjoin any movies that Tom did to vP,
as shown in (77b), and then copy the missing VP, as shown in (77c).
(77) a. Bill didnt [VP1 see [DP any movies that Tom did [VP2 ]]]
b. Bill didnt [vP [DP any movies that Tom did [VP2 ]]i [vP [VP1 see ti]]]
c. Bill didnt [vP [DP any movies Tom did [VP1 see ti]]i [vP [VP1 see ti]]]

QR
COPY

VP

Likewise, in (78a), the way to ensure that some linguist maintains wide scope
over every paper Bill did is to adjoin the latter to vP, as shown in (78b).
(78) a. Some linguist [VP1 read [DP every paper Bill did [VP2 ]]]
b. Some linguist [vP [DP every paper Bill did [VP2 ]]i [vP [VP1 read ti]]]

QR

c. Some linguist [vP [DP every paper Bill did [VP1 read ti]] [vP [VP1 read ti]]]
COPY

VP

All the examples and arguments discussed in this section involved vPs
containing transitive and unergative verbs. For Chomsky, such vPs are complete in terms of their argument structure, whereas their passive and unaccusative counterparts are defective, which leads him to conclude that they are not
phases. This conclusion, however, has been challenged by Legate (2003), who
applies by now familiar diagnostics to argue that vPs headed by passive and
unaccusative verbs are phases. And, interestingly, the conclusion she reaches is
that with respect to these diagnostics, unaccusative and passive verb phrases
behave the same way as transitive and unergative ones do. This, in principle,
could mean one of two things: the diagnostics are ill-conceived (and are
perhaps tests for something else); or that passive and unaccusative verb phrases
are phases as well, contrary to Chomskys view. As I alluded to at the very
beginning of this section, the issue is independent of the issue of whether
passive and unaccusative verb phrases have a vP or not. The presence of v in
these structures seems pretty innocuous, but perhaps this is the reason to be
suspicious of its existence; since it does not value Case and does not select an
external argument, it might be dispensable in the same way that Agreement
projections became dispensable in the mid nineties (see Chomsky 1995, for
example). However, there might be independent reasons in favor of having v
projections in every verbal structure. This is the view taken by Marantz (2007),
who argues explicitly that phase heads are responsible for providing categorial
status to categoryless roots. On this view, associated with the Distributed
Morphology view of the lexicon, such category-neutral roots acquire their
verbal (or nominal) status only by virtue of merging with an appropriate light
functional head (a verbal v or a nominal n, for example). This leaves us with the

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

105

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

vPs as phases

105

structures in (79b) and (80b) as the only possible structures. What is at issue
here is not so much the VP versus vP status of passive and unaccusative verbal
projections, but the phase versus non-phase status of such verbal projections,
be they VPs or vPs. The most signicant (and syntactically most visible)
consequence of treating VP/vP as a phase is that passive (or unaccusative)
movement will proceed through the phase edge, as shown below. This
could also be taken as an argument in favor of the presence of the v head,
as movement of the complement of V to the specier of V would violate
antilocality, which, as we saw above, prohibits movements that are too short.
However, movement from a complement of v to the specier of vP would not
constitute a violation of antilocality.

(79) a. Tom arrived.

b.

TP
T
TiT[pst] u[3sg],EPP vP
vP
VP

v
V
arrived

DPi[3sg],uC[Nom]
Tom

c.

TP
T
TiT[pst] u [3sg],EPP VP
V
V
arrived

DPi [3sg],uC[Nom]
Tom

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

106

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

106

Classic phases

(80) a. Tom was chosen.


b.

TP
T
TiT[pst] u[3sg], EPP vP
was
vP
VP

V
chosen

DPi[3sg], uC[Nom]
Tom

c.

TP
T
TiT[pst] u [3sg], EPPVP
V
V
chosen

DPi [3sg], uC[Nom]


Tom

Most of Legates arguments come from phenomena that diagnose the presence of
this extra movement step. The logic of the argument is familiar by now; if the whpronoun moved to the edge position, we should nd some evidence of this movement either on the phonological side (in the form of a stranded quantier, a copy or
an expletive wh-phrase), or on the semantic side (in the form of scope reconstruction, for example). In (70) above, we saw evidence for movement through [Spec,vP]
coming from the interaction of Principle C reconstruction and variable binding.
Those examples all involved transitive or ditransitive verbs like get, read or ask. We
also saw that in all those cases, there was evidence for reconstruction to the vP edge
position, which was a position that allowed for a bound variable interpretation
without inducing a Principle C effect. Parallel passive examples are given in
(81ab); they also show that reconstruction to the edge of vP has to be possible.38
(81) a. [CP [At which of the parties that hei invited Maryj to]k was [TP every mani [vP ti
introduced to herj * ] ] ]?
b. [CP [At which of the parties that hei invited Maryj to] was [TP shej [vP * introduced
to every mani * ] ] ]? (Legate 2003: 507)
38

I refer the reader to Legates paper for parallel data involving unaccusative verbs. And to Den
Dikkens (2006a) response for a discussion of some issues stemming from Legates proposal.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

107

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

vPs as phases

107

We also saw above that the edge of vP can be a landing site for Quantier Raising.
The examples involved Antecedent-Contained Deletion (ACD) with an NPI to
ensure that QR does not target the matrix TP. If it did, the NPI would no longer be
licensed. The grammaticality of such examples showed that there has to be a QR
site below negation, which makes the edge of vP a plausible candidate. Legate
shows that passive vPs behave the same way. Example (82a), modeled on
Legates example, provides evidence. It shows that QR has to target vP; if it
targeted a TP instead, the negative polarity item would be outside the scope of
negation.
(82) a. The movie wasnt [VP1 seen by [DP anyone that wanted to [VP2 ]]]
b. The movie wasnt [ [ anyone that wanted to [
vP DP
VP2 ]]i [vP [VP1 see ti]]]

QR

c. The movie wasnt [vP [DP anyone that wanted to [VP2 see ti]]i [vP [VP1
seen by ti]]]
COPY VP

Legate also brings forth nuclear nuclear stress as an argument in favor of passive
and unaccusative vPs being phases. I defer the discussion of nuclear stress (and
the question of how phases may play a role in the distribution of nuclear stress) till
Chapter 7.
Before moving on to DPs, let me summarize the behavior of various types of
verb phrases with respect to various types of phasehood diagnostics.
(83) vPs as phases

Diagnostic
Is vP a domain for feature
valuation?
Is v the locus of uninterpretable features?
Does movement out of vP
proceed through the edge?
Is the complement of v a
Spell-Out domain?

Transitive Unergative Passive Unaccusative


vPs
vPs
vPs
vPs
Yes

Yes

No

No

Yes

Yes

No

No

Yes

Yes

Yes

Yes

Yes

Yes

No

No

The evidence that transitive and unergative vPs are phases is quite strong;
they behave as phases with respect to the diagnostics established in Chapter 3.
The evidence in favor of passive and unaccusative vPs being phases is somewhat less unequivocal, however. They do not trigger Spell-Out but they do
require movement to proceed through the phase edge. This is the reason why
they are sometimes referred to as weak phases, and thus distinguished from
strong (transitive and unergative) vP phases.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

108

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

108

Classic phases

4.3

DPs as phases

In this section, we turn to the phase status of DPs. There are two in principle
independent, questions to ask. One is whether DPs themselves are phases, and
the other one is whether DPs contain other phases. The latter question arises
especially in the context of the many well-documented similarities between noun
phrases (be they DPs or NPs) and clauses (be they TPs or CPs). If CPs contain other
phases (vPs, whose phasehood we established in the previous section), it may be the
case that DPs contain phases as well.
The well-documented similarities between DPs and CPs involve argument
structure, agreement and case morphology, and extraction possibilities. See
Bernstein (2001a) for a succinct summary (and Abney 1987, Chomsky 1970,
Hiraiwa 2005, Szabolcsi 1983, among many, many others, for the original
observations). In many languages, possessors and subjects bear the same case.
A classic illustration comes from Szabolcsis (1983) work on Hungarian; she
shows that in Hungarian DP-internal possessors and clausal subjects bear the
same (Nominative) case:
(84) a. (a) Mari-
the Mary-NOM
Marys guest

vendg-e-
guest-POSS-3SG

b. Mari-
alud-t-
Mary-NOM
sleep-PAST-3SG
Mary slept. (Szabolcsi 1983: 8990)

The distinction between A and A-bar positions, familiar from a clausal domain, is
operative inside DPs as well. Valois (1991), Szabolcsi (1983) and Tellier (1988),
among others, show that the specier of DP is an A-bar position, providing an
escape hatch for movement, and Bernstein (2001b) shows that there is a DP-internal
focus position.39 We will look at some of their evidence shortly. For now, sufce it
to note that given the many similarities between noun phrases and clauses, it is not
unreasonable to expect DPs to be phases, paralleling CPs in this respect.40
The answer to the question of whether DPs contain phases, and if so, what
these DP-internal phases might be, depends largely on what the internal structure
of DPs is. So before delving into DP phasehood, let us digress into DP-internal
syntax. There are a number of DP-internal projections that have been proposed
over the years, mainly to accommodate all the DP-internal elements, and to
capture the relative ordering of these elements as well as the crosslinguistic

39

40

On a related note, there is also interesting evidence that CP and DP-internal movements can be
equally impaired in agrammatism (see, for example, Rausch, Butchert & De Bleser 2005 for a case
study involving a German agrammatic aphasic).
Chomsky initially did not include DPs in the list of phases, but suggests this as a possibility in later
writings.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

109

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

DPs as phases

109

variation with respect to this ordering (see Alexiadou, Haegeman & Starrow 2007,
Bernstein 1993, 2001a, 2008, Cinque 2002, Ritter 1992, 1993, Valois 1991,
Zamparelli 1996, among many, many others). Svenonius (2007b), based on a
crosslinguistic study of the ordering of articles, demonstratives, plural markers,
classiers, numerals and adjectives, arrives at the following hierarchy:
(85) Dem > Art > Num > unit > Pl/sort > Adj > n > N

Below are some of the more common nominal functional projections posited to
accommodate these elements; others include Kase Phrase (Bittner & Hale 1996),
Quantier Phrase, Person Phrase, and Demonstrative Phrase.41
(86) a. Number Phrase (NumP) (Ritter 1992)
b. Gender/Classier Phrase (GenP/ClassP)42 (Picallo 1991)
c. Possessive Phrases(PossP) (Valois 1991)
d. nP

I will henceforth assume the following (somewhat streamlined) DP structure:43


DP

(87)

D
D

PossP
Poss
Poss

NumP
Num
Num

nP
n
n

41

42

43

NP

The list gets bigger if we assume that nouns of different semantic types project different structures.
Zamparelli (1996) adds Kind Phrases, Predicative Phrases and Strong DPs to the inventory of
nominal projections.
See, however, Ritter (1993) for an argument that there is no syntactic Gender projection, and
gender can be either part of the Number head or the Noun head itself.
This hierarchy abstracts away from the relative position of different types of adjectives with respect
to each other and with respect to other DP-internal elements. If adjectives occupy speciers of
functional heads, the structures will get exponentially more complex (see Scott 2002, Cinque 2010,
Laenzlinger 2005, Bernstein 1994 for some representative accounts). An example hierarchy, based
on Scott (2002), is given in (i). For him, this adjectival hierarchy reects the hierarchy of heads
licensing them, making the internal structure of DP quite elaborate.
(i) Ordinal > Cardinal > Subject Comment > Evidential > Size > Length >Height >
Speed > Depth > Width > Temperature > Wetness > Age > Shape > Color > Nationality/Origin >
Material

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

110

110

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

Classic phases

With these brief remarks on DP-internal structure as background, we can


apply to DPs the diagnostics we established during our discussion of CPs and vPs
in the previous sections. They are given in (88ai).44
(88) a. Is DP a domain for feature valuation?
b. Is D a source of uninterpretable features?
c. Does movement out of DP proceed through the edge of DP?
d. Can an element moving out of DP be interpreted at the edge of DP?
e. Can an element moving out of DP be pronounced at the edge of DP?
f. Can an element moving out of DP strand anything at the edge of DP?
g. Is DP a target for Quantier Raising?
h. Does D trigger Spell-Out?
i. Can the complement of D be elided?

Some of the diagnostics are subsumed by others; the way we can tell whether
movement out of DP proceeds through the edge of DP is by looking at reconstruction (is there a copy in this position?), ordering (can a copy be pronounced in
this position?), stranding (can something be stranded at this position?). Similarly,
the way we can tell whether D triggers Spell-Out is by looking at DP-internal
ellipsis and stress assignment.
The discussion of DPs as phases in this section is to a large extent informed by
Matushansky (2005), who discusses the behavior of DPs with respect to many of
the diagnostics listed in (89), and concludes that since DPs behave as phases with
respect to some diagnostics (PF diagnostics) but not with respect to others (LF
diagnostics), the behavior of DPs does not bode well for phases (Matushansky
2005: 179).
Two of the diagnostics in (88) involve uninterpretable features: only phase
heads can be inherent hosts of uninterpretable features (although non-phase heads
can inherit them), and only phases can be domains for feature valuation. I take it
to be uncontroversial that DPs have case features, and at least for structural case,
that these case features are uninterpretable.45 However, the uninterpretable case
features on DPs are different from the uninterpretable -features on C and v
heads. An uninterpretable Case feature is not a feature that makes DP (or its head)
a Probe, which is what we saw with uninterpretable -features on v or C heads.46
Instead, an uninterpretable case feature of a DP makes it an active Goal.
This brings us to the next question, the question of whether DPs are (or
contain) domains for feature valuation. There is evidence that DPs can contain a
44

45

46

The list of questions is ordered slightly differently to reect the order of presentation in this
section.
This is independent of whether a case feature is analyzed as a sui generis feature (uC[ ] feature, as
we have assumed throughout) or an uninterpretable counterpart of some other interpretable feature
(uT[ ] for Nominative case and uAsp[ ] for Accusative case, the possibility we alluded to in
Section 1.3).
Strictly speaking, a phrase (as opposed to a head) cannot be a Probe.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

111

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

DPs as phases

111

separate case domain, which suggests that either a D (or some DP-internal head)
has to be the source of this case. Genitive case is a prime example. We can see it
even in a very morphologically impoverished language like English, if we take
the preposition of to be a marker of genitive case (see Chomsky 1986, for
example). A more straightforward illustration comes from Slavic languages, in
which descriptively speaking nouns assign Genitive case (so-called adnominal
genitive), as illustrated below with Polish data. In (89a) the adnominal genitive is a
possessor, but this genitive is not limited to possessors, as shown in (89bd).
(89) a. ksiazka
studenta
book.NOM student.GEN
a students book
b. artyku
profesora
article.NOM
professor.GEN
an article (written) by a professor
c. kon
wysokiej klasy
horse.NOM high.GEN class.GEN
a high-class horse
d. objecie
wadzy
assumption.NOM power.GEN
assumption of power
e. kawaek
chleba
piece.NOM bread.GEN
a piece of bread

[Polish]
POSSESSOR

AGENT

ATTRIBUTE

THEME

PARTITIVE

(Swan 2002: 3302)

Another illustration comes from the domain of numerals. Slavic numerals higher
than ve are also case assigners; the lower ones (one, two, three, four) agree in
case with their complements (as shown in (90a)), and only get Genitive case if the
entire DP gets Genitive case, as shown in (90b) with respect to the so-called
Genitive of negation. The higher numerals, on the other hand, assign Genitive
case (the so-called Genitive of quantication) to their complements, as shown in
(91a). Not surprisingly, this Genitive case stays Genitive under negation.47

47

This pattern is only found in structural case contexts. The situation changes in lexical case contexts:
(i) Jan

zainteresowa

sie

dwoma

jezykami

sowianskimi.

Jan

got.interested

REFL

two.INSTR

languages.INSTR

Slavic.INSTR

Jan got interested in two Slavic languages.


(ii) Jan

zainteresowa

sie

szescioma

jezykami

sowianskimi.

Jan

got.interested

REFL

six.INSTR

languages.INSTR

Slavic.INSTR

Jan got interested in six Slavic languages.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

112

112

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

Classic phases

(90) a. Przeczytaam jedna/dwie/trzy/cztery ksiazki.


read.1SG
one/two/three/four.ACC books.ACC
I read one/two/three/four books.
b. Nie przeczytaam
jednej/dwch/trzech/czterech
not read
one/two/three/four.GEN
(91) a. Przeczytaam piec/szesc/siedem ksiazek.
read
ve/six/seven.ACC
books.GEN
I read ve/six/seven books.
b. Nie przeczytaam
pieciu/szesciu/siedmiu
not read
ve/six/seven
I didnt read ve/six/seven books.

ksiazek.
books.GEN

ksiazek.
books.GEN

The distribution of adnominal genitive case thus suggests that there has to be a
distinct case domain within DP, and is compatible with some DP-internal head
(like the Num head) being the source of this genitive case.
A different argument, also pointing towards DPs being self-contained
domains, comes from binding.48 Well-known examples of the kind given in
(92) show that only certain types of DPs (namely the ones that contain possessors) count as domains for binding. This raises the possibility that maybe only
certain types of DPs are phases (or strong phases), the possibility we considered
in the last section regarding different types of vPs.
(92) a. *Johni likes [Marys descriptions of himselfi].
b. Johnj likes [Marysi descriptions of herselfi].
c. Johni likes these descriptions of himselfi.

The contrast in (93ab), due to Chomsky (1986), is also compatible with this
view if DPs can contain a PRO possessor/subject, which is coindexed with the
matrix subject in (93a) but not in (93b).
(93) a. The childreni heard [PROi stories about each otheri]
b. The childreni heard [PROj stories about themi]

48

This argument builds on Quinolis (2008) proposal that binding is determined cyclically at a phase
level. His focus, however, is on CPs and vP as binding domains, rather than DPs. While a full
review of his arguments goes beyond the scope of this chapter, he does show, for example, that
Huangs (1993) predicate fronting cases, such as the one given in (i), receive a natural explanation
if binding is determined derivationally and vPs, being phases, constitute binding domains.
(i) [CP [vP t1 criticize himself1/*2] John2 never thought [tvp that [Bill1 would tvP] ] ]

Quinoli also uses the ambiguity of examples like (ii) to argue against TPs being binding domains
(and phases). If TP were a binding domain, anaphoric interpretation would be xed at the
embedded TP level.
(ii) Johnj wonders which pictures of himselfi/j Billi saw. (Quinoli 2008: 313)

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

113

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

DPs as phases

113

The next set of diagnostics refers to what we called above the edge property.
Here, the question is whether movement from a DP has to proceed through the
edge of DP. We know that movement out of a phase has to proceed through the
edge of a phase. In cases of other phases, we looked at reconstruction, Quantier
Raising, various types of stranding, copying and agreement phenomena to
determine movement paths. For independent reasons, however, not all of them
will be applicable to DPs. For example, since DP-internal elements often agree in
-features and case (due to whatever mechanism underlies case concord), it is not
a surprise that they will continue to agree if a subpart of DP gets extracted. This is
shown in (94ac) for Polish. (94a) shows that DP-internal elements agree, and
(94bc) show that movement preserves this agreement. Thus, agreement on
extracted elements is not going to tell us whether movement took place through
the specier of DP or not.
(94) a. Jan przeczyta ciekawa
ksiazke
.
Jan read
interesting.3SG.FEM.ACC book.3SG.FEM.ACC
Jan read an interesting book.
b. Ciekawa
i
Jan przeczyta [DP ti ksia
zke].
interesting.3SG.FEM.ACC Jan read
book.3SG.FEM.ACC
c. Ktrai
Jan przeczyta [DP ti ksia
zke]?
which.3SG.FEM.ACC Jan read
book3SG.FEM.ACC
Which book did Jan read?

[Polish]

The fact that movement from a DP is blocked if the specier of DP is lled might
be taken as evidence that movement does indeed have to proceed through the
edge of DP.
(95) *Whoi did Jan like Marias picture of ti?

However, the ungrammaticality of examples of this kind, as pointed out by


Matushansky (2005), is part of a larger phenomenon, more likely linked to
specicity than deniteness. First, a D head lled by a denite article also blocks
movement, and so does one lled by an indenite article (as long as the noun
phrase in question is interpreted as specic). Second, not all denite noun phrases
block extraction.49, 50
(96) a. *Whoi did Jan like the picture of ti?
b. *Whoi did Jan like a specic/particular/certain picture of ti?
c. Whoi did Jan take the best picture of ti?

49
50

These examples are modeled on Matushanskys examples.


Valois (1991) makes a similar point based on French data, showing that demonstratives in French
(which he takes to occupy [Spec,DP] positions) block not only movement but also negative
polarity item licensing and parasitic gap licensing. However, similar caveats apply.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

114

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

114

Classic phases

More generally, as discussed by Davies & Dubinsky (2003), for example,


extraction from English DPs is a fairly complex phenomenon, sensitive to factors
like the semantics of the selecting verb, argument structure and incorporation
possibilities, rather than just a lled versus empty specier position. Furthermore,
it is not clear what aspect of Phase Theory (or the Phase Impenetrability
Condition) leads to the expectation that movement from a phase is impossible
if the specier of that phase head is lled. We might think that extraction from
CPs proceeds in this fashion; this is the standard way to account for wh-island
effects. However, a C head occupied by an interrogative complementizer also
results in ungrammatical extraction, so a lled specier cannot be the only culprit.
We also know that there are languages that do not show wh-island effects, which
(at least for some of them) is attributed to the availability of multiple [Spec,CP]
positions. Thus it is not unreasonable to expect the same parametric option to be
available for DPs. Likewise, a lled specier does not block movement out of the
vP. If it did, nothing would ever be able to move out of transitive vPs, since the
specier is lled by the external argument. This also shows that adding an extra
(non-thematic) specier must be an option. These considerations do not support
the conclusion that a lled phase edge necessarily blocks extraction out of that
phase.
There is, however, a fair amount of crosslinguistic evidence pointing towards
movement out of DPs proceeding through DP edges. Szabolcsis work on
Hungarian DPs provides perhaps the best-known argument in favor of the
specier of DP providing an escape hatch for movement out of DPs. First,
Szabolcsi shows that Hungarian has two types of possessors, differing in case
and position relative to the determiner. One follows the determiner and is marked
with Nominative case, as shown in (97a). The other one precedes the determiner
and is marked with Dative case, as shown in (97b).
(97) a. a
the

Mari-
Mary-NOM

b. Mari-nak
Mary-DAT

a
the

vendg-e-
guest-POSS-3SG
vendg-e-
guest-POSS-3SG (Szabolcsi 1983: 8991)

Furthermore, Szabolcsi shows that the specier of DP is a landing site for DPinternal operators and that this DP-internal movement turns the entire DP into an
operator:
(98) a. *(a) ki-
vendg-e-
the who-NOM guest-POSS-3SG
whose guest
b. ki-nek
a
vendg-e-
who-DAT the guest-POSS-3SG
whose guest (Szabolcsi 1983: 91)

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

115

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

DPs as phases

115

Thus, only wh-phrases that are dative-marked possessors can undergo further
movement, as shown by the following contrast with respect to topicalization.
(99) a. Pter-neki, csak
Peter-DAT only

Mari
Mari

ltta [DP ti
saw

a
the

kalap-jt]
hat-POSS.3SG.ACC

b. *Peter-i csak Mari ltta [DP ti a


kalap-jt]
Peter-NOM only Mari saw
the hat
As for Peter, only Mari saw his hat.
(Gavruseva 2000:750, citing Szabolcsi 1994: 205)

The availability of a DP-related escape hatch position could then be what


accounts for the contrast between languages that allow possessor extraction and
those that do not. This is the line of thought taken by Gavruseva (2000), who
contrasts Hungarian, Tzotzil and Chamorro (languages that allow possessor
extraction) with Germanic languages, which overwhelmingly do not allow it.
More specically, she links the availability of possessor extraction to strong
(possessor) agreement.51 In this respect, her account is the opposite (as she herself
points out) of that of Uriagereka (1988), Corver (1990), Bokovi (2005, 2009),
which links the availability of Left Branch Extraction (of which possessor
extraction is perhaps the best-known type) to the lack of a D projection. For
these researchers, the evidence for the lack of D projection, in turn, comes from
the lack of overt articles. Gavruseva, on the other hand, posits a DP shell-like
structure akin to the one given in (100), and takes possessor extraction to proceed
in two steps: movement to the specier of the lower DP is linked to case and
agreement, and movement to the specier of the higher DP is linked to a strong
operator or Q features. This higher specier position is the escape hatch position
necessary for possessor extraction.52 In her analysis, the higher [Spec,DP] position is an A-bar position corresponding to [Spec,CP] in the clausal domain,
whereas the lower one is an A position, corresponding to [Spec, TP]. In our
terms, the higher D head could be thought of as a phase head endowed with both
operator features and case/agreement features. I will call this head a light d head,
to make it analogous to a v head dominating a VP, but nothing hinges on this

51

52

Gavruseva also discusses Aissens (1996) analysis of Tzotzil, in which regular possessives appear
postnominally, but wh-possessors can appear pre-nominally. Aissen analyzes it as movement of a
wh-possessor to [Spec,DP].
The question of whether movement out of DPs proceeds through the specier of DP is different
from the question of whether the edge of DP can be the nal landing site. Hungarian dative
possessors suggest that it can indeed be a landing site. English DP inversion structures of the kind
given in (i) have also been analyzed in this way (see Valois 1991, for example).
(i) How big a nut can a parrot eat?

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

116

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

116

Classic phases

terminological choice. If d is a phase head the lower head (D head in (100)) could
inherit its uninterpretable -features.
(100)

dP
d
duOp[

], u [ ]

DP
D
D

NP

The licensing of parasitic gaps was an important edge diagnostic in the


discussion of vPs as phases. For DPs, the two questions to consider are: (i) does
the empty operator target the [Spec,DP] position, and (ii) can the wh-movement
licensing the parasitic gap proceed through [Spec,DP]? With respect to the rst
question, Emonds (2001) argues that the empty operator inside the gerund adjunct
clause moves to [Spec,DP], based on the fact that the status of gerund-internal
parasitic gap examples worsens if the specier of DP is lled:53, 54
(101) a. Which paintings could she scrutinize without (*the owner/*the owners)
bringing to the gallery?
b. These are the dishes you should leave out instead of (*John/*Johns)
putting away. (Emonds 2001: 93)

However, since the behavior of the empty operator in these parasitic gap examples is similar in this respect to the behavior of wh-phrases undergoing overt
movement (as evidenced by the contrast in (102ab)), it might also be the case
that the issue is not a lled versus empty [Spec,DP] position but other factors
(specicity, deniteness etc.):55
(102) a. What did John enjoy showing off at the party?
b. What did John enjoy Marys showing off at the party? (Emonds 2001: 104)

In our discussion of parasitic gaps in vPs, we focused on the wh-movement


licensing the parasitic gap, not the empty operator movement inside the constituent
containing the parasitic gap. And we saw that movement to the edge of vP, repeated
in (103a) was necessary in order for the parasitic gap to be possible (otherwise the

53
54

Only the variants without s are from Emonds 2001.


Engdahl, however, considers examples parallel to (101b) to be grammatical:
(i) Which boy did Marys talking to pg bother t most? (Engdahl 2001: 69)

55

Valois (1991), following Tellier (1988), also analyzes nominal parasitic gaps as involving empty
operator movement to the specier of DP.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

117

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

DPs as phases

117

result is a semantic type mismatch when the adjunct combines with the vP). An
analog in the DP domain would involve wh-movement from a DP internal position
to the edge of DP licensing a DP internal parasitic gap, as shown in (103b).
(103)

a.

CP
WHj
vP
WHj

vP
Adjunct

vP
tj

b.

OPiti

CP
WHj
DP
DP

WHj
DP

Adjunct

tj

OPiti

Common examples in which the parasitic gap is DP-internal, such as (104a), are
not going to be relevant, as they are licensed by another DP-external gap.
However, (104b) is the right conguration; it involves real extraction from
DP, licensing a parasitic gap inside the adjunct relative clause.
(104) a. Marys the kind of woman OPi that [DP people who meet pg] usually end up
inviting ti into their homes.
b. *Whoi did Mary [DP tell a story about ti [CP that really impressed pg] ]?
(Matushansky 2005: 168)

While I agree with Matushanskys judgment regarding (104b), the reasons for its
degraded status might be non-syntactic in nature. (105) below, involving an
analogous conguration, improves markedly:
(105) Whoi did Mary take [DP pictures of ti [CP that werent that attering to pg ] ]?

The next edge diagnostic concerns Quantier Raising. Here the question is
whether the edge of DP can be a landing site for QR. To determine that, let us look
at cases of complex DPs containing two quantiers to see if the lower quantier
can take scope over the higher one without scoping outside the DP. Discussion of
such cases abounds in the literature (see Charlow 2009, Larson 1985, May 1977,

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

118

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

118

Classic phases

Sauerland 2005, among many others). Consider the example in (106). The most
felicitous reading for it is the inverse scope reading, in which every team scopes
over one member.
(106) [DP One member of every team] won an MVP (Most Valuable Player) award.

A more complex example is given in (106). Its most natural reading is one in
which the relative scope of the three quantiers is the mirror image of their linear
ordering. This reading can naturally be paraphrased as There is a large California
city in which every freeway has some exits that are badly constructed.
(107) [Some exits from every freeway in a large California city] are badly constructed.
(Larson 1985: 1)

The issue is whether inverse scope in such cases is the result of the lower
quantier adjoining to DP or moving out of DP and adjoining to TP, as shown
in (108ab) respectively.
(108) a.

TP
DP
DPi

DP

vP

every state two delegates from ti

b.

TP
DPi

TP

every state DP
two delegates from ti T

T
vP

The availability of the bound variable reading in (109) suggests the latter
possibility; however, given Kaynes denition of c-command, both adjuncts
and speciers (which are indistinguishable for him) can c-command out of DPs
containing them.
(109) Someone from every city despises it. (Larson 1985: 1, citing May 1977)

However, if inverse scope were the result of movement of the lower quantier to a
TP-adjoined position (as opposed to a DP-adjoined position), we would expect
the scope of the lower quantier to be independent of the scope of the higher
quantier in cases involving yet another (DP-external this time) quantier.
Larson (1985) also discusses such cases, concluding that the scope of the lower
quantier is dependent on the higher one. To illustrate with a concrete example,
in (110), every city can have scope over two politicians, but only if someone has

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

119

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

DPs as phases

119

scope over two policitians. This is unexpected if every city could move out of DP
and adjoin to TP directly.
(110) Two politicians spy on someone from every city. every city> someone > 2
politicians (Larson 1985: 5)

The literature on inverse scope centers around the issue of whether DP is a scope
island or not, with examples of the kind given in (110) suggesting that it is.56
However, this issue is independent of the issue at stake here, which is the issue of
whether the edge of DP is a landing site for QR. And the fact that every city can
scope over someone does suggest that QR can target the edge of DP. This brings
us to the question of whether QR can ever target a DP-internal position. If so, it
might suggest the presence of another DP-internal phase. The following example,
from Matushansky, shows that there has to be such a site; the quantier a/any
foreign country has to undergo QR in order to be interpreted. But at the same
time, being a Negative Polarity Item, it has to remain within the scope of the
negative quantier no.
(111) No student from a/any foreign country was admitted.
(Matushansky 2005: 168)

Thus the edge diagnostics do show that DPs are phases and possibly contain other
phases. We also saw evidence that DPs are case and binding domains, which is
also compatible with DPs being phases. What is left is the semantic status of DPs
(are they semantically complete in the same way CPs and vPs are?) and their
phonological status (do D heads determine Spell-Out?). Let us discuss these
questions in turn. For CPs and vPs, the criterion of semantic completeness had
to do with their propositional status and full argument structure. The obvious
parallelism between CPs like Romans destroyed the city and DPs like Roman
destruction of the city suggests that DPs are complete in the requisite sense.
Matushansky, however, interprets semantic completeness slightly differently,
focusing of semantic types instead. The question of whether DPs are semantically
complete, as she points out, is complicated in view of the fact that DPs come in
different semantic guises, with referential DPs being of type e, quantied DPs of
type <e, <e,t>>, and predicative DPs of type <e,t>. If we take completeness to be
saturation, only referential DPs are complete, and on the Generalized Quantier
Theory (which treats all DPs as generalized quantiers), no DPs would ever be
semantically complete.

56

Sauerland (2005) argues that DP is not a scope island (see also Marui 2009, Charlow 2009 for
relevant discussion), based on the fact that examples of the kind given in (i) allow the interpretation
in which the most deeply embedded quantier these two countries can scope over want and
someone.
(i) Mary wants to marry someone from these two countries. (Sauerland 2005: 306)

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

120

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

120

Classic phases

The next set of diagnostics involves Spell-Out. If D is a phase head, we expect


its complement to be able to undergo ellipsis. The result is a pretty ubiquitous
ellipsis type, dubbed N anaphora (or N deletion) by Jackendoff (1977), illustrated in (112ab).
(112) a. John wanted to read the dossiers of famous linguists, and/but he succeeded
in reading Morriss/yours/these/one/none/some/many/three __.
(Jackendoff 1977: 115)
b. The students attended the play but most/some/all/each/two __ went home
disappointed. (Lobeck 1995: 42)

Interestingly, however, there are a number of restrictions on NP ellipsis (see


Lobeck 1995 and the references therein). Only some determiner-like elements
can license NP ellipsis, namely the quantiers all, each, some, both, many, few,
numerals, possessives and plural demonstratives. By contrast, the quantier
every, denite and indenite articles and singular demonstratives do not license
ellipsis. For Lobeck, the crucial factor involved in the licensing of ellipsis (not
just NP ellipsis but also VP ellipsis and sluicing, the two other types she
considers) is what she dubs strong agreement. Strong agreement refers to
morphological strength, which Lobeck takes to be dening agreement in a
productive number of cases (Lobeck 1995: 51). Lobeck also shows that DPinternal heads such as Number heads can license ellipsis. The evidence comes
from examples containing more than one DP internal element, such as the ones
in (113ac).
(113) a. My sisters two boys are wild, but Johns two __ are really quite well-behaved.
b. Many students enrolled in the class, but the few __ who dropped it later said
it was too difcult.
c. Although all twelve __ did well in the class, only two students got As.
(Lobeck 1995: 712)

If we take the higher element to occupy either the specier of DP or its head, and
the lower one to occupy either the specier of NumP or its head (as in (114),
adapted from Lobeck 1995: 87), these case will involve ellipsis of the complement of the Num head, thus pointing towards Num being a phase head as well.
(114)
DP
Possessor
D
all
both
these
s

D
NumP
Num
Num
six/few

NP

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

121

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

DPs as phases

121

Lobecks work in many respects builds on Jackendoff (1977), who distinguishes


two types of NP speciers, differing in the level of attachment (N versus N in
his terms). The structure in (115) below translates his insights into the more
current structure (see Jackendoff 1977: 105 for the original one).
(115)

DP
Fred
D
the
both
those
which

D
NumP
Num
Num
many
few
several

NP
dwarfs

A potential problem for the idea that D heads trigger Spell-Out involves
case. It is well known that in a language like Polish, which marks case
morphologically, DP internal elements usually (but not always, see the discussion of adnominal genitive or genitive of quantication above) agree in case.
This is the familiar phenomenon of concord, which involves not only case, but
gender, number and person features as well (cf. Danon 2011, Carstens 2000
and the references therein for a detailed discussion of concord from a more
crosslinguistic perspective).
ta
ciekawa
ksiazke.
[Polish]
read.1SG this.3SG.FEM.ACC interesting.3SG.FEM.ACC book.3SG.FEM.ACC
I am reading this interesting book.
b. Nie przeczytam
tej
nudnej
ksiazki.
not read.PERF.1SG this.3SG.FEM.GEN boring.3SG.FEM.GEN book.3SG.FEM.GEN
I will not read this boring book.

(116) a. Czytam

The simple question, raised by Matushansky (2005), is how case spreads onto all
the DP-internal elements if D is a phase head. In more technical terms, the
question is what the uninterpretable case feature (uC feature) is a feature of.
The logical possibilities to consider are: the uC feature could be a feature of D
(percolating to DP), N, or both, as illustrated in (117ac) for an uC feature of a
direct object.57

57

The latter two options are compatible with the idea that only phase heads can have uninterpretable
features, as N can inherit its features from D. See the discussion of Feature Inheritance in Chapter 2
(Section 2.6).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

122

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

122

Classic phases

(117)

a.

vP
v
vu [

VP

DP
DuC [

b.

NP

vP
v
vu [

VP

DP

V
D

c.

NP
NuC [

vP

v
vu [

VP

DP
DuC [

NP
NuC [

Each of these options raises questions. If we assume the structure in (117a), the
question is how case spreads downwards to N. If NP (being a complement of the
phase head D) is spelled out, the question about (117b) is how case spreads
upwards to D. And, nally, if we assume the structure in (117c), the question is
how v can value uninterpretable case feature on two elements simultaneously. If it
values uC feature of D rst, then this D head with a valued case feature might act
as an intervener, and block Agree between v and N. We could appeal to Hiraiwas
(2001) Multiple Agree mechanism, which allows a single Probe to undergo
Agree with multiple Goals. However, in typical cases of Multiple Agree, the
two Goals are in the same Spell-Out domain. If D is a phase head, its complement
NP is spelled out as soon as the next phase head (v in the case at hand) gets
merged. This would also result in the uC feature on N being unvalued.
Matushansky (implicitly) assumes the option in (117a), pointing out that it is
not clear how case gets onto the N head, if NP gets spelled out when the v head
is merged. But it does seem reasonable to assume that case spreads DP

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C04.3D

123

[71123] 23.11.2013 11:48AM

DPs as phases

123

internally via an agreement or concord mechanism (see Baker 2008b, Carstens


2000, among others, for explicit proposals), perhaps taking place in the postsyntactic component.
This concludes our discussion of DPs as phases and the table below summarizes the behavior of DPs with respect to the phasehood diagnostics established in
Chapter 3.
(118) DPs as Phases
Diagnostic

Evidence

Is DP a domain for feature valuation?


Yes adnominal Genitive
Is D the locus of uninterpretable features? Yes genitive case
Does movement out of DP proceed through Yes parasitic gaps
constraints on movement out
the edge?
of DPs

Does D determine Spell-Out?


Is DP a binding domain?
Can D serve as a Probe?
Can QR target the edge of DP?

Yes
Yes
Yes
Yes

N ellipsis
picture noun phrases
genitive case
inverse scope

The next chapter examines the idea of extending the idea of phasehood to
three other categories, all of which have been argued to be phases. The three are:
Predicatation Phrases (PrPs), Prepositional Phrases (PPs) and Applicative
Phrases (ApplPs). The discussion in this chapter will be somewhat more speculative for two reasons. First, the very existence of two of the three categories is
not uncontroversial. A PrP structure is not the only possible structure for small
clauses (see Citko 2011c for an overview of possibilities), and an Applicativetype structure is certainly not the only structure that has been proposed for double
object constructions. While the very existence of PPs is fairly settled, there are
quite a few of unsettled matters regarding the types, structure, and lexical vs.
functional status of prepositions.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

124

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

5
Other ph(r)ases

5.1 PrPs as phases


In this section, we turn to the idea that there is a relationship between predication and phasehood. There are two possible ways to look at this relationship.
One is to rst expand the inventory of functional projections to include a
Predication Phrase (PrP), as proposed by Bowers (1993), and, next, to take
the head of PrP to be a phase head, in addition to the other heads whose
phasehood we established in the previous chapter: C, v and D heads. A very
different view, due to Den Dikken (2006), is to essentially abandon the standard
characterization of phases, and, instead, to take the subjectpredicate relationship to be a denitional characteristic of phases. For Den Dikken, whenever
there is a predication relationship, there is a phase.1, 2 I focus here on the
former, more specic view, which is that Predication Phrases are phases, as
argued for explicitly by Bowers (2002), Harves (2002), Matushansky (2000)
and Tanaka & Yokogoshi (2010), among others.
For Bowers, all predication relationships are mediated by a Pr head; simple
transitive clauses also include a PrP in addition to the usual functional projections, some phasal and some not. I take a more modest view and assume that a
Pr head is only present when it needs to be: when there is no other functional
head to relate the subject and the non-verbal predicate (see also Svenonius
1994 for a similar view). Small clauses are a case in point. In both matrix and
embedded contexts, Pr heads the small clause.

Den Dikken differs from Bowers in that he assumes that predication relationships can be mediated
by a number of functional categories (which he collectively refers to as relators), rather than a
predication-specic functional category.
See also Carnie & Barss (2006) for a slightly different view. For them, phases have to contain some
predicative element, a single argument, and a temporal operator that situates the predicate and
argument in time and space.

124

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

125

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

PrPs as phases

125

(1) a. Icarus is a parrot.

b.

TP
T
T
is

PrP
DP

Pr

Icarus

Pr

DP
a parrot

(2) a. I consider parrots smart.

b.

TP
T
T

vP
v

VP
consider

PrP

DP
parrots Pr

Pr
AdjP
smart

The Predication Phrases in both cases are certainly semantically complete since
they contain a predicate with all its arguments. This is the behavior we expect of
phases. Tanaka & Yokogoshi (2010) also bring forth general architectural considerations as an argument in favor of Predicatation Phrases being phases. For
them, treating PrP as a phase ts in well with the conguration of phases
envisaged by Chomsky (2001): F-XP, where a functional category F selects a
substantive category XP, e.g. C-TP and v-VP (Tanaka & Yokogoshi 2010: 26).
However, it is not clear what exactly they mean by substantive category. A TP
does not seem more substantive than a CP, both being functional. We have also
seen some issues for the characterization of phases as semantically complete;
what counts as complete may vary from category to category. Therefore, let us
look at more concrete diagnostics, listed in (3), to determine the phasehood of
PrPs. These are the same diagnostics we used in previous chapters to determine
the phasehood of other categories.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

126

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

126

Other ph(r)ases

(3) a. Is PrP a domain for feature valuation?


b. Is Pr the source of uninterpretable features?
c. Does Pr trigger Spell-Out?
d. Does movement out of PrP proceed through the edge of PrP?

And to tell whether movement out of PrP proceeds through the edge of PrP, we
will ask the more specic questions in (4).
(4) a. Can an element moving out of PrP be interpreted in the edge position?
b. Can QR target PrP?
c. Is stranding at the edge of PrP possible?

Many languages have what can be referred to as a predicative case, i.e. case
assigned to predicate nominals that cannot be attributed to a default case mechanism or a case agreement mechanism (see Matushansky 2008 and the references
therein for a typological overview of case patterns on predicates). To illustrate with
one concrete example, predicate nominals are marked with Instrumental case in
Slavic languages like Polish or Russian, as shown in (5a) and (5b), respectively.3
jest studentka/*studentka.
Maria.NOM is
student.INSTR/*NOM
Maria is a student.
ego
durakom/*duraka.
b. Ja scitaju
I
consider him.ACC fool.INSTR/*ACC
I consider him a fool. (Bailyn & Citko 1999: 19)

(5) a. Maria

[Polish]

[Russian]

Bailyn & Rubin (1991) propose that the Pr head heading the small clause is
responsible for Instrumental case assignment. In phase-theoretical terms, their
claim can be restated as a claim about the Pr head valuing the uninterpretable case
feature on the predicate as Instrumental. This is only possible if Pr is a phase head.
It can value case, which means that it has to have uninterpretable features which
make it an active Probe, and since it is not a complement of a phase head (in (1b)
PrP is a complement of T and in (2b) of V), it could not have inherited its
uninterpretable features from a phase head above it. There is also no (other)
Instrumental nominal in either sentence with which the predicate could agree, and
there are no reasons to consider Instrumental case to be default, even if we grant
the existence of default case in general.
Interestingly, in Russian (and to a much lesser degree in Polish), predicate
nominals can also be marked with Nominative case, as shown in (6ab). This
alternation (Instrumental versus Nominative) is a very well-documented case
alternation in Slavic linguistics (see Bailyn & Citko 1999, Citko 2008b, Harves
2002, Matushansky 2000, Pereltsvaig 2007, Richardson 2007, among many

This is not the only option. I turn to the other option, predicates marked with Nominative case,
shortly.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

127

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

PrPs as phases

127

others), and, roughly speaking, it correlates with a difference in interpretation


along the individual versus stage-level dimension.
byl
ucitel.
[Russian]
brother.NOM was teacher.NOM
(My) brother was a teacher (by nature).
b. Brat
byl
ucitelem.
brother.NOM was teacher.INSTR
(My) brother was a teacher (for a certain period of time).
(Bailyn & Citko 1999: 30)

(6) a. Brat

Interestingly, if the head of the PrP is lled by an overt predicator (such as the
particle za as in the examples below), the predicate nominal is no longer
Instrumental. Instead, it agrees with the DP it is predicated of: in (7ab) the
adjective is predicated of the direct object and both are Accusative.
(7) a. Uwazam

Marie
za
I.consider Maria.ACC as
b. Ja prinimaju ego
I
take
him.ACC
I consider him as a fool.

madra
studentke/*madra studentka.
clever.ACC student.ACC/*INSTR
za duraka/*durakom.
as fool.ACC/*INSTR
(Bailyn & Citko 1999: 22)

[Polish]
[Russian]

Likewise, in Polish copular sentences, the Instrumental case disappears in the


presence of the demonstrative-like element to, often characterized as a pronominal copula. When it is present, either in addition to or instead of the verbal copula
by be, both the subject and the predicate are Nominative (see Citko 2006,
2008b for a more detailed discussion of this pattern):
(8) Maria
to
( jest)
Maria.NOM DEM is
Maria is a student.

studentka.
student.NOM

In phase-theoretical terms, the fact that Pr head is involved in Instrumental


case assignment means that it contains uninterpretable -features that make it a
Probe capable of valuing case on its complement, as shown in (9ab):
(9) a.

TP
T
Tu:[3sg],EPP

PrP

DPuC:[Nom],i:[3sg] Pr
Maria

Pru:[3sg]

DPuC:[Instr],i:[3sg]
a student

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

128

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

128

Other ph(r)ases

b.

TP
T
Tu:[1sg],EPP

vP

DPuC:[Nom],i:[1sg] v
I

VP

vu:[3sg]
consider

PrP

DPuC:[Acc],i:[3sg]
Maria

Pr

Pru:[3sg]

DPuC:[Instr],i:[3sg]
a student

The fact that the Pr head can lose its ability to value Instrumental case suggests
that it can lose its uninterpretable -features, and, consequently, stop being
a phase head.4 The fact that neither the pronominal copula to nor the
prepositional predicator za as agrees with the subject or the predicate is
consistent with Pr lacking -features. Instead, predicate nominals agree in
case with the subject of predication, and end up either with Nominative
case (by Multiple Agree with T) or with Accusative case (by Multiple Agree
with v):
(10) a.

TP
T
T u:[3sg],EPP

PrP

DP uC:[Nom],i:[3sg] Pr
John

Pr

DPuC:[Nom],i:[3sg]
a student

The insight that a lled Pr head loses the ability to assign Instrumental case is due to Bailyn & Citko
(1999), who capture it under a slightly different (non-phase-theoretical) set of assumptions. The
insight is reminiscent of the classic account of passive morphology as absorbing Accusative case
(see Baker, Johnson & Roberts 1989).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

129

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

PrPs as phases

b.

129

vP
vu:[3sg],EPP VP
consider

PrP

DPuC:[Acc],i:[3sg] Pr
John

Pr

DPuC:[Acc],i:[3sg]
a student

The ability of Pr to value Instrumental case (or the lack thereof) has been shown
to correlate with the possibility of extracting the complement of a Pr head. The
contrast in (11ab), discussed in Citko (2006, 2008b), shows that copular clauses
with Nominative and Instrumental predicates behave differently with respect to
movement: Instrumental predicates can undergo wh-movement, but Nominative
ones cannot. Russian behaves similarly in this respect, as discussed by
Matushansky (2000) and Harves (2002), among many others.5
(11) a. Kimi
chcesz,
zeby Maria bya ti?
who.INSTR want.2SG COMP Maria was
Who do you want Maria to be?
b. *Ktoi
chcesz,
zeby Maria (to) bya ti?
who.NOM want.2SG COMP Maria DEM was
Who do you want Maria to be?

[Polish]

This contrast has also been accounted for by taking the Pr head selecting an
Instrumental predicate (but not one selecting a Nominative predicate) to be a
phase head.6 Matushansky (2000) and Harves (2002) analyze Russian in a
similar way; however, for them the relevant difference between the two types
of Pr heads is the difference between defective and non-defective phase heads,
rather than phase versus non-phase heads. What both types of accounts
share is the insight that the extraction asymmetry between Nominative and
Instrumental predicates is due to the presence of an EPP feature on the phasal

The Polish complementizer eby is a subjunctive complementizer, selecting past tense complements (see Tomaszewicz 2012 for a recent discussion of its many interesting properties). The
reason I use subjunctive clauses here is that for some speakers, extraction out of indicative clauses
is degraded.
The idea that there are two variants of the same head, one phasal and one not, is not new. This is a
common way to think of v heads, for example. In Section 5.3 of this chapter, we will look at two
types of applicative heads, which also vary in terms of phasehood.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

130

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

130

Other ph(r)ases

Pr head, which allows the Instrumental wh-predicate to move to the outer edge
of PrP, as shown in (12).7
(12) Structure of (11a)
CP
C
C

TP
T
Tu:[3sg],EPP

PrP
PrP
DPuC:[Nom],i:[3sg] Pr
Maria

Pru:[3sg],EPP

DPuC:[Instr],i:[3sg]
who.INSTR

If Pr lacked the EPP feature, the wh-predicate would not be able to move past
the subject, as is the case with Nominative predicates. This movement would
be blocked either by the Phase Impenetrability Condition if Pr remains a phase
head, or by the presence of the intervening subject either in [Spec,PrP] or
[Spec,TP] if Pr is no longer a phase head. The two options are given in (13a)
and (13b), respectively. In (13a), the subject intervenes and C cannot undergo
Agree with the wh-phrase.8 In (13b), the Merge of C (the next phase head up)
triggers the Spell-Out of the complement of Pr (the nominal predicate). Since it
is impossible to prevent a phase head from having an EPP feature in a nonspeculative way, I will not pursue this option any further.

Note that the movement of the Instrumental DP from the complement of Pr head to its (outer)
specier is a violation of antilocality. This is not a problem if Instrumental DPs involve a richer
structure, in which what moves is not a complement of the phase head but a complement of a
complement of phase head).
This conguration is very similar to the conguration involving object wh-movement out of
simple transitive clauses. It is important to note that the reason movement is not allowed in (13a)
is not PrP not being a phase, as movement out of non-phases is certainly possible. The reason is
the intervention of the subject. One might wonder why the subject, not being a wh-phrase itself,
blocks wh-movement. This I take be similar to the cases we saw in Section 2.6, in which the whobject in the outer [Spec,vP] blocked Agree between T and the subject.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

131

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

PrPs as phases

(13)

131

CP
C
C

TP
T
Tu:[3sg],EPP

PrP
PrP
DPuC:[Nom],i:[3sg] Pr
Maria

Pr

DPuC:[Nom],i:[3sg]
who.NOM

b.
CP
C
C

TP
T
Tu :[3sg],EPP

PrP

DPuC:[Nom],i:[3sg] Pr
Maria

Pru :[3sg]

DPuC:[Nom],i :[3sg]
who

The claim that what allows wh-extraction of Instrumental predicates is Pr


being a phase head seems in conict with Tanaka & Yokogoshis (2010)
proposal that it is the phase status of Pr that prevents (certain types of)
inversion in English small clauses. They argue that English small clauses
historically went from being headed by a lexical category (the predicate) to
being headed by a functional category (the Pr head). They further argue that
with the emergence of Pr as a phase head, the inversion of the kind illustrated in
(14) became impossible.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

132

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

132

Other ph(r)ases

(14) *I consider smart Maria.

Tanaka & Yokogoshi attribute the ungrammaticality of (14) to the Phase


Impenetrability Condition, arguing that the predicate cannot move because it is
within the Spell-Out domain of Pr. However, the argument only works on the
stronger version of the Phase Impenetrability Condtion (PIC1), on which the
complement of Pr is spelled out as soon as the next head up is merged, as shown
in (15a). Under the assumptions of PIC2, the later and the more empirically
adequate of the two, the complement of Pr is not spelled out until v (the next
phase head up) is merged. Thus, movement of the predicate should in principle be
possible, as shown in (15b). The congurations schematized here are very similar
to the conguration involving Agree between T and a quirky Nominative object,
which was excluded by PIC1 but allowed by PIC2.
(15) a.

VP
V

PrP
Pr

Maria
Pr

AdjP
smart

b.

vP
v

VP
V
V

PrP
Maria

Pr
Pr

AdjP
smart

Furthermore, we do not want to exclude all cases of predicate inversion, which


a PIC2-based account would do. The contrast in grammaticality between the
so-called predication copular clause in (16a) and the specicational one in (16b)
is often attributed to inversion around the copula (e.g. Moro 1997 and much later
work):

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

133

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

PrPs as phases

133

(16) a. Maria is my best friend.


b. My best friend is Maria.

On Tanaka & Yokogoshis assumptions, this should not be allowed. The


movement in (17ab) is similar to the movement in (15ab). However, given
PIC2, the complement of Pr does not get spelled out until C is merged, which
allows either the subject or the predicate to move to [Spec,TP], as shown in
(17ab).9
(17) a.
CP
C

TP
T
T

PrP
DP

Pr

Maria Pr

DP
my best friend

b.

CP
C

TP
T
T

PrP
DP
Maria Pr

Pr
DP
my best friend

The difference in extraction possibilities between Instrumental and


Nominative predicates in Slavic is different in spirit from the evidence we used
in Chapter 4 to argue that movement out of CPs, vPs and DPs has to proceed
through their respective edges. There, the issue was not whether extraction was
possible (we saw that it was), but whether movement had to proceed through the
edge of the presumed phase. One of the ways we could tell was by looking at

The timing becomes problematic with Feature Inheritance in place.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

134

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

134

Other ph(r)ases

whether movement could strand a quantier or a nominal (in cases of split


constituents) at the edge of the phase. Let us now apply the same logic to PrPs.
The grammaticality of the examples in (18ab) shows that the subject of the
Predicate Phrase can move stranding all, but it does not necessarily show that it
has to move through the edge of PrP.
(18) a. I consider the students all smart.
b. The cat regards the kids as all hopeless cases. (cf. Starke 1995: 242)

We have seen that in Polish a language that allows Left Branch Extraction the
position of the nominal can mark the movement path. The grammaticality of
(19a), then, is also consistent with the nominal being stranded in its underlying
position (shown in (19b)) or in the matrix object position (shown in (19c)), so it
does not tell us much about movement through the edge of PrP.10
(19) a. Ktrego
which.ACC

uwazasz

studenta

za

najlepszego

skadniowca?

consider.2SG

student.ACC

as

best.ACC

syntactician.ACC

[Polish]

Which student do you consider to be the best syntactician?

b. [CP which student [TP you

[vP which student

[vP consider [VP which student [PrP

which student [Pr as [DP the best syntactician]]]]]]]]

c. [CP which student [TP you

[vP which student

[vP consider [VP which student [PrP

which student [Pr as [DP best syntactician]]]]]]]]

Extraction from the predicate position will thus be more telling. If movement
proceeds as schematized in (20ab), we should expect that the nominal can be
strandable in the bolded outer [Spec,PrP] position.
(20) a. [CP WH [TP [vP WH v [VP [PrP WH [PrP SUBJECT [Pr Pr [ WH]]]]]]]]
b. [CP WH [TP [PrP WH [PrP SUBJECT [Pr Pr [ WH ]]]]]]

Since the subject moves from the specier of PrP in both cases (to the matrix
[Spec,VP] position in (20a) and to the matrix [Spec,TP] in (20b)), the surface
congurations we end up with are as shown in (21ab), which again makes it
difcult to distinguish some of these cases from cases in which the moving
wh-predicate strands something in its base position.
(21) a. [CP WH [TP [vP WH v [VP SUBJECTi [PrP WH [PrP ti [Pr Pr [ WH ]]]]]]]]
b. [CP WH [TP SUBJECTi [PrP WH [PrP ti [Pr Pr [ WH ]]]]]]

The examples below provide an illustration. (22a) is a baseline example. The


contrast between (22b) and (22c) shows that the predicate can only be extracted
if it pied-pipes the prepositional predicator za as, which I am treating as the

10

I do not have information on the status of the following examples in Irish English. However, if they
are acceptable, a similar caveat applies to them; the nominal could be stranded in situ or in the
matrix object position.
(i) Who do you consider all smart?

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

135

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

PrPs as phases

135

head of PrP.11 (22d) and (22e) show that the nominal can be stranded. (22d) is
compatible with the nominal being stranded in its underlying position. However,
in (22e) the matrix subject remains inside PrP (as evidenced by the position of the
adverbial), which makes the outer specier of PrP the most likely culprit for the
position of the stranded nominal.
(22) a. Uwazam
Marie
za najlepsza przyjacike.
consider.1SG Maria.ACC as best.ACC
friend.ACC
I consider Jan to be (my) best friend.
b. Za jakai
przyjacike uwazasz
Marie
ti?
as what.ACC friend.ACC
consider.2SG Maria.ACC
c. *Jakai
przyjacike uwazasz
Marie
za ti?
what.ACC friend.ACC
consider.2SG Maria.ACC as
What kind of friend do you consider Maria to be?
d. Za jakai
uwazasz
Mariej [PrP tj przyjacike ]?
as what.ACC consider.2SG Maria.ACC
friend.ACC
What kind of friend do you consider Maria to be?
uwazasz
po
tym [PrP [ti przyjacike]k [PrP Marie tk ] ]?
e. Za jakai
as what.ACC consider.2SG after this
friend.ACC
What kind of friend do you consider after this Maria to be?

Maria.ACC

Similar considerations apply to copular sentences. (23a) is the baseline example.


(23b) shows that wh-movement from the predicate nominal is possible. (23c)
shows the noun ssiada neighbor can be stranded by wh-movement. However,
in this case it is stranded in its underlying position (the complement of Pr head),
not at the phase edge. (23d), however, does show that it can also be stranded at the
edge of PrP.
(23) a. Maria jest przyjacika naszego sasiada.
Maria is
friend.INSTR our.GEN
neighbor.GEN
Maria is our neighbors friend.
b. Czyjego
sa
siadai
Mariaj jest [PrP tj [Pr Pr [DP przyjacika ti]]]?
whose.GEN neighbor.GEN Maria is
friend.INSTR
c. ?Czyjegoi Mariaj jest [PrP tj [Pr Pr [DP przyjacika [DP ti sasiada]]]]?
whose.GEN Maria is
friend.INSTR
neighbor.GEN
d. Czyjegoi
Mariaj jest [PrP [ti sasiada]k [PrP tj [PrPr[DP przyjacika tk ]]]]?
whose.GEN Maria is
neighbor.GEN
friend.INSTR
Whose neighbor is Maria a friend of?

11

This does not seem to have anything to do with za as being prepositional (and Polish disallowing
P-stranding), as the English as resists stranding as well, as pointed out by Emonds (1985), for
example:
(i) ??Who do you consider John as?

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

136

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

136

Other ph(r)ases

In cases of other phases (vPs and DPs in particular), we also looked at Quantier
Raising to determine whether movement proceeds through the phase edge. Let us
now apply this diagnostic to PrPs. Ambiguity of examples like (24) below is not
directly relevant; the surface scope reading is in principle compatible with the
quantied predicate nominal remaining in its surface position, and the inverse scope
reading is compatible with the lower of the two quantiers adjoining to TP.
(24) Everyone is someone.

EVERYONE

>

SOMEONE, SOMEONE

>

EVERYONE

However, the rst option disappears if quantied elements need to QR for independent semantic reasons even if this movement does not establish a new scopal
relationship. Then someone will have to move in both cases, and it will have to
move to the closest position of type t, as is commonly assumed in the literature on
QR (see Bruening 2001, for example). In copular constructions such as (24), the
closest category of the right semantic type to which someone could adjoin is PrP.12
Negative Polarity Licensing also suggests that PrP is a potential QR site. In
(25), for example, anyone has to undergo QR for semantic reasons, and it has to
remain within the scope of negation to be licensed as a Negative Polarity Item.
Thus the only possible QR site is the PrP adjoined position.
(25) a. John isnt anyone.
b. [TP Johnj [T isnt [PrP anyonei [PrP tj [Pr Pr ti ]]]]]

Antecedent-Contained Deletion points towards the same conclusion.


(26) a. John isnt [anyone Bill is ]
b. [TP Johnj [T isnt [PrP [anyonei Bill is ]i [PrP tj [Pr Pr ti ]]]]]

The last diagnostic we will consider involves the ability of Pr heads to determine
Spell-Out. One way to diagnose this is by looking at whether the complement of
Pr can be deleted. Here, however, the evidence is somewhat inconclusive. The
grammaticality of (27a) does not necessarily involve deletion of the complement
of the Pr head, and the ungrammaticality of (27b) seems to be related to a more
general ban on as stranding illustrated in (27c):
(27) a. John is my best friend but Bill isnt .
b. *Mary considers Bill as her best friend and Ann considers Mike as .
c. *Whoi does Mary consider Bill as ti?

This concludes our discussion of PrPs as potential phases. The table in (28)
provides a brief summary of the main ndings in this section. We saw that the
evidence for the phasehood of PrPs is less unequivocal than the evidence for the
12

These cases are different from the cases of frozen scope in examples of the kind given in (i),
discussed by Hornstein (1995), Den Dikken (2007), among others, which show that the smallclause-internal elements cannot scope out of the small clause.
(i) Someone considers every parrot endangered.
SOMEONE

SOMEONE

>

EVERY PARROT,

*EVERY

PARROT

>

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

137

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

PPs as phases

137

phasehood of other categories, and that different types of PrPs behave differently
with respect to some of the diagnostics. Nevertheless, I hope to have established
in this section that at least some languages have PrPs that do behave like phases
with respect to most phasehood diagnostics.
(28) PrPs as phases
Diagnostic Question

Answer Evidence

Is Pr the source of uninterpret- Yes


able features?
Does movement out of PrP
Yes
have to proceed through the
edge of PrP?
Can QR target PrP?

Yes

Can the complement of Pr be


deleted?
Is PrP semantically complete
(propositional)?

No

5.2

Yes

Instrumental case on Slavic


predicates
contrast with respect to extraction
between Instrumental and
Nominative predicates
possibly stranding in [Spec,PrP]
scope, Antecedent-Contained
Deletion
no stranding of overt predicators
PrP consists of a subject and a
predicate

PPs as phases

The category we focus on in this section, with an eye towards determining its
phase status, is a Prepositional Phrase. What makes determining the phasehood of
PPs somewhat more elusive than determining the phasehood of CPs or vPs is the
fact that there are quite a few background issues that have to be settled before we
can even gure out whether PPs are phases. We rst need to establish: (i) are
prepositions functional or lexical?, (ii) what is the internal structure of PPs?,
(iii) do different types of PPs have different structure?13, 14 Thus a fair amount of
the discussion in this section will revolve around these background questions.
This is not to say that these questions do not matter for other phasal categories; the
answers to them, however, seem relatively more settled and less controversial.
13

14

Perhaps an even more fundamental question is what prepositions are to begin with, as the line
distinguishing them from case particles or verbal particles is not always clear. It is not even clear if
all languages have prepositions, which, if we establish that prepositions are phases and that some
languages lack prepositions, would bear directly on one of the more general issues concerning
phases under consideration here, namely the issue of whether there is any crosslinguistic variation
with respect to phasehood. Typically, however, the issue is whether a given category such as
ApplP or DP counts as a phase in a given language, which is different from the issue of whether a
given language might lack a potentially phasal category.
See Cinques Mapping Spatial PPs: An Introduction in Cinque & Rizzi (2010) for a very
illuminating review of these (as well as a host of other) issues.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

138

138

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

Other ph(r)ases

The logical possibilities concerning the phasehood of PPs, all of which have
been defended in the literature, are given in (29).
(29) a. Prepositional phrases are phases
(Bokovic 2004b, Drummond, Hornstein & Lasnik 2010, Kayne 1999, 2004)
b. Prepositional phrases are not phases (Den Dikken 2010)
c. Prepositional phrases in some languages are phases (Abels 2003)

In order to determine the phasehood of PPs, we will look at the familiar


diagnostics:
(30) a. Is PP a domain for feature valuation?
b. Is P a source of uninterpretable features?
c. Does P trigger Spell-Out?
d. Does movement out of PP proceed through the edge of PP?

And, as in the previous cases, we will look at reconstruction, stranding and QR to


see whether movement proceeds through the edge of PP:
(31) a. Can an element moving out of PP be interpreted in the edge position?
b. Can QR target PP?
c. Is stranding at the edge of PP possible?

First, however, let us digress a bit into the background issues alluded to above: the
functional versus lexical status of prepositions, as well as the structural differences between different types of prepositions. These are directly relevant for the
following reason: if only functional categories are capable of being phases,
whether or not PPs are phases might depend on whether prepositions are functional or lexical.15 And if different types of PPs involve different structures, we
might expect only certain types of PPs to be phases.
The assumption that only functional categories are capable of being phases
has been implicit throughout the discussion in this book. Being a functional
category, however, would not make a very useful phasehood diagnostic, as the
implication goes only one way: while all the phase heads we have encountered so
far are functional, not all functional heads are phase heads. Examples of uncontroversially functional heads that are not considered to be phasal include (but are
not limited to): Tense heads, Aspect heads or various functional heads within the
(extended) nominal domain.
Prepositions have always straddled the lexical/functional divide, which
reects the fact that different types of prepositions might behave differently
with respect to some of the criteria distinguishing lexical from functional categories. For some researchers, prepositions are essentially lexical (but may be
dominated by a functional layer) (e.g. Den Dikken 2010, Jackendoff 1977); for
15

The view that some or all prepositions are lexical (thus non-phasal) is compatible with the idea that
they are dominated by some P-related phasal functional head (little p perhaps, by analogy to a little
v dominating VP), as is sometimes suggested.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

139

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

PPs as phases

139

others, they are functional (e.g. Baker 2003, Emonds 1985, Grimshaw 1991,
Kayne 2004); and yet for others some prepositions are lexical and others functional (e.g. Abraham 2010, Van Riemsdijk 1998, 1990, Yadroff 1999)16
Abney (1987) characterizes functional elements as belonging to closed
lexical classes, lacking descriptive content and being phonologically and morphologically dependent. Even though there are more prepositions than articles
or conjunctions, the number of prepositions in English, to choose a familiar
example, is much smaller than the number of nouns or verbs (less than a
hundred, according to most estimates).17 Prepositions also pattern with other
functional categories with respect to the remaining criteria: they tend to be
phonologically and morphologically dependent, they do not undergo derivational processes, they often cliticize, and they tend to lack descriptive content.18 Baker (2003) also notes that they cannot be incorporated, which he
attributes to the Proper Head Movement generalization, a generalization that
makes it impossible to move from a functional head to a lexical one (see Baker
2003: 306).
A slightly different host of arguments in favor of treating prepositions as functional and/or phasal comes from the parallelism between prepositions and other
(uncontroversially) functional heads, most notably C heads. This is what Emonds
(1985), Kayne (1999) and Abels (2003), among others, do. Complementizers often
develop from prepositions, with the English preposition for or the Romance de/di
serving as good examples.19

16

17

18

19

Strictly speaking, Van Riemsdijk treats prepositions as belonging to the so-called semi-lexical
category.
Baker lists English as having around fty prepositions, and points out that in some languages, the
class of prepositions is really small: Mohawk has four simple adpositions, Edo three and Chichewa
three or ve (depending on the criteria used). However, small does not mean closed.
Psycholinguistic evidence also seems to points towards treating prepositions as functional. Froud
(2001), as reported by Cinque (2010), shows that they pattern with functional categories in aphasia
studies. Frederici (1982), as reported by Muysken (2008), shows that with respect to some types of
speech errors, prepositions pattern with lexical classes, but with respect to others they pattern with
other (functional) categories.
Emonds (1985) actually treats complementizers as prepositions. Kaynes (1999) main arguments
in favor of treating prepositions and complementizers alike comes from the fact that both can act as
Probes and attract phrases to their speciers. More specically, he argues that prepositional
complementizers (such as di in (i)) do not form a constituent with their clausal complements.
Instead, the main verb merges with the innitival clause and the prepositional complementizer di is
merged later. It attracts the innitive clause to its specier. Next, it moves to a higher head, which
subsequently attracts the VP to its specier:
(i) Gianni
John

ha

tentato

di

cantare.

has

tried

di

sing.INF

John has tried to sing. (Kayne 1999: 51)

[Italian]

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

140

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

140

Other ph(r)ases

Interestingly, with respect to some of the criteria for distinguishing lexical


from functional categories, (at least some) prepositions behave like lexical
categories. For example, borrowed prepositions do exist, which casts doubt
on the claim that prepositions constitute a closed class. Yadroff (1999: 61) gives
the following examples: vis-a-vis, circa, via, per, qua. Van Riemsdijk (1998)
also argues that prepositions do not constitute a purely closed lexical class, as
new prepositions can be added to the lexicon. He gives upcreek from here as an
example of a prepositional phrase coinage (Van Riemsdijk 1998: 17), and takes
the fact that prepositions can participate in derivation, as evidenced by the
forms like ofsh, inner, to also argue against their functional nature. Abney
(1987) notes that prepositions can appear in compounds but other functional
categories cannot.
Given the mixed nature of the evidence in favor of prepositions being lexical
or functional, with some diagnostics pointing in one direction and others in the
other, an obvious possibility to consider is that prepositions are a mixed category,
with some prepositions being lexical and others functional. This is suggested, for
example, by Van Riemsdijk (1990, 1998), Yadroff (1999), Yadroff & Franks
(2001), Cinque (2010) and Abraham (2010).20, 21 Yadroff (1999) provides a very
systematic discussion of the differences between the two types, based on the data
from Russian. Functional prepositions tend to be unstressed, monosyllabic and
polysemous (due to the more abstract meaning). Lexical prepositions, on the
other hand, are more complex: they tend to be stressed, polysyllabic (often
polymorphemic) and have a more concrete (hence xed) meaning. Cinque
(2010) also points out that in some languages only functional prepositions assign
case. The table in (32) provides examples of the two types from Polish; I refer the
reader to Yadroff (1999: 65) for the Russian counterparts.
(32) Functional versus lexical prepositions in Polish
Functional prepositions
bez
za
z
na
od

20

21

without
behind
with, from, out of
on
from

Lexical prepositions
miedzy
zamiast
powyzej
poza
podczas

between/among
instead of
above
except
during

To be accurate, Yadroff argues that there is no such thing as a preposition in Universal Grammar
(Yadroff 1999: 26). For him, functional prepositions occupy a functional slot within the extended
projection of N/D (Yadroff 1999: 162). Yadroff & Franks (2001) take a similar view, arguing that
prepositions are an epiphenomenon: functional prepositions arise through ssion of a functional
projection dominating NP, and lexical prepositions are bleached lexical categories.
Abraham (2010) argues that the two types are merged in different positions: lexical prepositions are
merged high and serve as Probes, and grammatical ones are merged low.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

141

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

PPs as phases

141

Lexical prepositions can be stressed and are often morphologically complex (for
example, podczas during morphologically consists of pod under and czas
time).
The upshot of the discussion so far is that at least some prepositions are
functional. On the assumption that only functional heads are phase heads, we
might expect only these prepositions to be phase heads. However, the existence
of two types of prepositions is also consistent with all PPs being phases, if lexical
prepositions are not phase heads but are dominated by functional heads that are.
Before turning to this possibility, let me introduce another distinction: the
distinction between locative and directional prepositions, as this distinction is
often correlated with a difference in structure. Many prepositions are ambiguous
and can be either locative or directional, depending on the context. This is shown
in (33ab).
(33) a. The statue sat on/under/behind the table.
b. John put the statue on/under/behind the table.

LOCATIVE
DIRECTIONAL

P
P

As is well documented in the literature, many languages disambiguate the two


uses by means of case. The contrast in polish between the a and b examples in
(34)(36) shows that the same preposition can assign two different cases, depending on whether it is used in a locative or a directional sense.
(34) a. Jan jest na wakacjach.
Jan is
on holidays.LOC
Jan is on vacation.
b. Jan pojecha na wakacje.
Jan went
on holidays.ACC
Jan went on vacation.
(35) a. Kot jest pod
stoem.
cat is
under table.LOC
The cat is under the table.
b. Kot uciek pod
st.
cat ran
under table.ACC
The cat ran under the table.
(36) a. Kon
jest za
potem.
horse is
behind fence.LOC
The horse is behind the fence.
b. Kon
pobieg za
pot.
horse ran
behind fence.ACC
The horse ran behind the fence.

[Polish]

One way to think about it is too assume that directional prepositions are
structurally more complex than locative ones, and that perhaps directional
prepositions are literally built from locative ones. Structural implementations

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

142

142

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

Other ph(r)ases

of this general idea range from very simple ones as in (37a) to cartographically
rich ones as in (37b).22
(37) a. [PP Pdir[PP Ploc DP]]
b. [CP(Place) (er) [C(Place) [DegP(Place) (two meters) [Deg(Place) [PlaceP (er) [Place [PP (P)
[AgrP pronouns Agr [PP (P) DP]]]]]]]]] (cf. Koopman 2000: 61)

With this as background, we can turn to the phasehood diagnostics. As we apply


them, we will distinguish lexical from functional prepositions and directional from
locative ones, to see if these differences correlate with differences in phasehood.
We already saw that both locative and directional prepositions can value case
(Accusative versus Locative in Polish); so, according to this diagnostic, both
behave like phase heads. The ability to value case also does not seem to
distinguish between lexical and functional prepositions. (38a) is an example
with the functional preposition za behind, and (38b) is an example with the
lexical preposition poza except. The two assign the same (Locative) case:
(38) a. Jan
wyszed za
Jan.NOM left
behind
Jan left after Maria.

22

Maria.
Maria.LOC

Many proposals build on this basic insight, proposing a ner-grained structure in which there are a
number of projections dominating PP, the speciers of which provide landing sites for PP-internal
movement of pronouns and adjunction sites for different types of measure phrases. Koopmans
structure in (37b) is one example. Other representative examples, which also distinguish structurally locative from directional prepositions, are given in (iii).
(i) [PPStat (at) [DPplace [AxPartP under [PP P [NPplace the table [PLACE]]]]]] (Cinque 2010: 5)
(ii) [DirP (DegP) Dir [LocP (DegP) Loc [DP N/CP]]] (cf. Biskup 2009b: 22)

Den Dikken (2010) takes Koopmans structure as a starting point but modies it substantially. For
him, both locative and directional prepositions are lexical categories that project an extended
functional layer, similarly to what other lexical categories do. Thus, verbs, nouns and prepositions
all have a C-like projection, a Deixis-like projection and an Aspect-like projection. The precise
nature of this projection varies depending on the nature of the head.
(iii) a. [CP C[FORCE] [DxP Dx[TENSE] [AspP Asp[EVENT] [VP V ]]]]
b. [CP C[DEF] [DxP Dx[PERSON] [AspP Asp[NUM] [NP N ]]]]
c. [CP C[SPACE] [DxP Dx[SPACE] [AspP Asp[SPACE] [PP P ]]]] (Den Dikken 2010: 100)

Radkevich (2010) also posits a more exploded structure for PPs, in which the core P-meaning
(Path, Location) can be dominated by three levels of functional projections, subject to
crosslinguistic variation. While there is no variation with respect to the availability of the core
structure and all languages have the locative/directional complex, Radkevich shows that languages
can differ with respect to how much functional structure they allow in PP. The diagnostics
Radkevich uses to diagnose the level of functional structure involve the compatibility of PPs
with measure phrases, the availability of quantier oat, and the behavior of PPs in a given
language with respect to binding.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

143

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

PPs as phases

b. Wszyscy poza
Maria
all
except Maria.LOC
Everyone except Maria left.

143

wyszli.
left

So according to the ability to value cases, all prepositions pass as phase heads.
Prepositions can also show agreement. The following examples from Scottish
Gaelic, due to Adger & Ramchand (2003), show that prepositions agree in
deniteness with their complements:
(39) a. ri
tidsear
with.INDEF teacher
with a teacher
b. ris
an tidsear
with.DEF the teacher
with the teacher (Adger & Ramchand 2003: 348)

[Scottish Gaelic]

The next host of diagnostics concerns extraction from PPs. There are two
questions to consider here. One is whether movement out of PPs is possible at all
(especially movement of the complement of P, which gives rise to preposition
stranding), and the other one is whether movement proceeds through the edge of
PP (or some other functional head within the extended P projection). If the answer
to both is yes, the P head is a phase head.
Preposition stranding is considered to be typologically a rare phenomenon. Van Riemsdijk (1978) is quite explicit about not allowing any
crosslinguistic variation with respect to extraction out of PPs, taking all PPs
to be islands, and allowing extraction out of PPs only under exceptional
circumstances:
(40) It is impossible to relate X, Y in the structure
Xi [P [P Y ] ] Xj
unless (a) Y = r-pronoun
(b) Y = modifying clause
(c) Y = motional postposition (Van Riemsdijk 1978: 159)

For Van Riemsdijk, movement out of PP is possible if that PP has a special


escape hatch position, which he dubs the R-position in Dutch (the position to
which so-called R-pronouns move) and the COMP position in English.
R-pronouns (which are lexically marked +R because they contain the /r/
phoneme) are locative forms, such as daar there er there, ergens somewhere, waar where (see Van Riemsdijk 1978: 40).23 The R-rule inverts the
R-pronoun with the preposition, which Van Riemsdijk analyzes as movement
of the pronoun to [Spec,PP].
23

Van Riemsdijk also points out that English has R-forms, such as therewith, whereby, hereafter.
These, however, are more restricted and typically frozen.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

144

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

144

Other ph(r)ases

(41) a. Ik had eri


niet op ti gerekend.
I
had there not on
counted
I had not counted on it. (cf. Van Riemsdijk 1978: 192)

[Dutch]

b.
PP
P

eri
P

ti

The same R-rule is operative with wh-pronouns, and accounts for the contrast in
grammaticality between (42a) and (42b). In (42a), the R-rule applies rst and
P-stranding is allowed, whereas in (42b), the R-rule does not apply and
P-stranding is disallowed.
(42) a. Waari heb
je
[PP ti op ti] gerekend?
where have you
on
counted
What did you count on?
b. *Wiei heb
je [PP op ti ] gerekend?
who
have you
on
counted
Who did you count on? (Van Riemsdijk 1978: 1357)

[Dutch]

From the perspective of Van Riemsdijks theory, movement of R-pronouns in


Dutch and, more generally, the ability to strand prepositions is more of an exception
than the rule.24, 25 Van Riemsdijks evidence that movement proceeds through the
edge of PP comes from the fact that movement is blocked if the edge is lled:
(43) *Waari heeft zij
er
vaak over ti gesproken?
where
has
she there often about
spoken
What has she often spoken about there? (Van Riemsdijk 1978: 211)

This is very similar to some of the evidence we discussed in Section 4.3


showing that movement out of DPs is blocked if the specier of DP is lled.
There, however, we saw that the issue was more likely a semantic deniteness
effect than a syntactic constraint on movement. In cases of PPs, however,
deniteness is not a factor.
24

Preposition stranding, even in a language like English, which allows it in principle, is not without
exceptions. As also pointed out by Van Riemsdijk, prepositions like during, despite or notwithstanding resist it. Others require it:
(i) a. *As what is this house famous?
b. What is this house famous as? (Emonds 1985: 276)

25

Strictly speaking, Van Riemsdijk allows two distinct mechanisms to permit preposition stranding:
reanalysis for pseudopassives and movement through the escape hatch for wh-movement.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

145

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

PPs as phases

145

Even though movement proceeds through this intermediate position, a


wh-phrase cannot remain there, as shown in (44a). Interestingly, it can do so
under sluicing, as shown in (44b), in a process referred to as swiping (see
Craenenbroeck 2010 and the references therein).26
(44) a. Who read [PP whati [P about ti ] ]?
b. John talked about something but I dont know [PP whati [P about ti ] ].

The ability to strand prepositions (or the lack thereof) does not seem to distinguish between lexical and functional prepositions or locative and directional
ones. In English all four types in principle allow it:
(45) a. Whati were you thinking of ti?
b. Whati were you hiding under ti?
c. Whati was the statue resting against ti?
d. Whoi were you running towards ti?

FUNCTIONAL
LEXICAL
LOCATIVE
DIRECTIONAL

P
P
P
P

And in a language like Polish, which disallows P-stranding, all four types
disallow it, as shown in (46ad). The pied-piped counterparts of (46ad) are all
perfectly well formed.
(46) a. *Kimi
rozmawiaas z ti?
who.LOC talk.PST.2SG
with
Who did you talk to?
b. *Kogoi posaas
Jana
zamiast ti?
who.GEN send.PST.2SG Jan.ACC instead.of
Who did you send Jan instead of?
c. *Jakich wakacjachi
Jan
by
na ti?
what.LOC vacation.LOC Jan.NOM was on
What kind of vacation was Jan on?
d. *Jakie
wakacjei
Jan
pojecha na ti?
what.ACC vacation.ACC Jan.NOM went
on
What vacation did Jan go on?

FUNCTIONAL

LEXICAL

LOCATIVE

DIRECTIONAL

The availability of preposition stranding is only one part of a more general


issue of whether extraction from PPs is allowed, and, if so, whether it has to
proceed through the specier of PP. Abels (2003) Stranding Generalization
disallows on principled (economy-based) grounds movement of an entire
complement of a phase head to the specier of the same phase head. Such
movement would have to target the edge (i.e. the specier of the phase

26

The fact that swiping is only allowed in sluicing constructions led Craenenbroeck (2010) to a
different analysis of (44b), in which the entire PP moves to [Spec,CP] rst, and, next, the whpronoun moves to the specier of a higher CP in a CP shell-like structure:
(i) [CP whati [C C [CP [PP about tj]i [C C [TP ti ] ] ] ]

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

146

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

146

Other ph(r)ases

head) rst, which Abels argues is too short: it does not establish any new
relationship between H and XP, since the two are already in a very local
relationship.
(47)

HP
H
XP

H EPP

For Abels, movement that does not stop at the edge of HP is also not an option, as
it is a violation of the Phase Impenetrability Condition. Whether the specier of
HP is lled or not should not matter, as an extra optional specier is in principle
allowed.27
(48)

ZP

Z
Z

HP
(YP)

H
H

XP

The ban on movement in (48) does not take into account the distinction
between the two versions of PIC, which, interestingly, make different predictions in this case. In particular, PIC1 disallows any movement of XP (or out of
XP), as XP is spelled out as soon as HP is complete (namely when the next
head Y is merged):
(49)

ZP
Z
Z

HP
(YP)

H
H

XP
Spell-Out domain

27

This depends of whether the lled specier is an A or A-bar position. A specier of vP occupied by
a subject does not block wh-movement out of vP, but a specier of CP occupied by a wh-phrase
does block wh-movement of another wh-phrase out of this CP.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

147

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

PPs as phases

147

But PIC2 does not spell out XP until the next phase head is merged. Thus, it
allows XP in (50a) to move to a higher specier position without stopping at the
edge of HP, as long as this higher specier position is not a specier of a phase
head. Spell-Out does not occur until later, as shown in (50b).
(50) a.

YP
Y
Y

H
(YP)

H
H

b.

XP

ZP
Z

YP
Y

XPi
Y

HP
(YP)

H
H

ti
Spell-Out domain

This predicts the existence of languages that might allow preposition stranding
with A movement but not with A-bar movement. These are languages in which
the following contrast would hold:28
(51) a. J O H N W A S
b. *WHOi D I D

T A L K E D A B O U T ti.
W E T A L K A B O U T ti?

However, Abels is very explicit about it being not an attested pattern.


(52) All languages that allow P-stranding under A-movement, i.e. pseudopassivization, also allow P-stranding under A-movement. (Abels 2003: 230)

28

I use small caps here to indicate that these are hypothetical/pseudo-English examples.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

148

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

148

Other ph(r)ases

The grammatical (51a) involves precisely the conguration in (53), in which


movement targets a specier position which is lower than the (phase) head that
determines Spell-Out:29
(53)

CP
C

TP

Johni
T

vP
VP

v
V

PP
P

ti
Spell-Out domain

Another prediction of the Stranding Generalization (and the account of preposition stranding that relies on it), examined in detail by Abels, concerns
extraction from as opposed to of the complement of the P head. This is
allowed: (54), for example, involves movement of the PP ber welches
Thema about which topic from the complement of the PP headed by malnach
after.
(54) ber welches Themai hast du mich noch [PP malnach ti ] einem Buch gefragt?
about which
topic
have you me again after
a
book asked
Which topic did you ask me about a book on again? (Abels 2003: 211)

Furthermore, if some prepositions are more complex than others (for example, if directional prepositions are more complex than locative ones), we might
expect to nd cases in which locative prepositions can be stranded but directional
ones cannot. This does not seem to be the case either in P-stranding or non-Pstranding languages.
The next diagnostic concerns binding: can PPs be domains for binding?
Interestingly, as often noted, different types of prepositions do behave differently in this respect (see Bring 2005, Chomsky 1986, Radkevich 2010,
Reinhart & Reuland 1993, among many others). For example, PPs headed by
prepositions like near or apart from can constitute a distinct binding domain,
but PPs headed by prepositions like about or with do not.30, 31
29
30
31

The passive v-V complex, irrespective of whether it is a phase or not, does not determine Spell-Out.
The examples are from Reinhart & Reuland (1993); I have added the indices and bolding.
Radkevich (2010) notes a fair amount of crosslinguistic variation in this respect and shows
that languages that allow coindexed pronouns inside PPs have more functional structure than
languages that do not. PPs in Polish, Czech and Russian are structurally impoverished, and

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

149

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

PPs as phases

149

(55) a. Maxi saw a gun near himselfi/himi.


b. Luciei counted ve tourists in the room apart from herselfi/heri.
(56) a. Maxi speaks with himselfi/*himi.
b. Luciesi joke about herselfi/*heri (Reinhart & Reuland 1993: 661)

A related diagnostic concerns stranding and the question of whether the


quantier all or a nominal in a split constituent can be stranded at the edge of PP.
West Ulster English, which we know allows quantier stranding under whmovement (see McCloskey 2000 and the discussion of CPs as phases in
Chapter 4), is a good language to look at. The evidence is mixed at best.
McCloskey shows that it is possible to strand all in the specier of the prepositional complementizer for:
(57) Who did you arrange all for your mother to meet at the party?
(McCloskey 2000: 70)

However, while stranding is ne in PPs in principle (see (58)), it is impossible in


the [Spec,PP] position (see (59)).
(58) a. ?Who did you talk to all (at the party)?
b. ?Who was he laughing at all?
(59) a. *Who did you talk all to?
b. *What were you laughing all at? (McCloskey 2000: 65?)

Bokovi (2004b) links the availability of PP-internal quantier stranding,


which is slightly different from the quantier stranding given in (58) above,
as the nominal remains inside the PP (or its extended projection), to the
availability of object shift. English, which disallows both, differs in this
respect from Icelandic, which allows both. Bokovi also argues that both
are subject to the same restrictions: both quantier stranding and object
shift, for example, are excluded in periphrastic constructions and with
indenite objects.
(60) a. *John the booksi/themi read ti.
b. *John talked the books/them about ti.

lack the functional layer that would allow them to count as a separate binding domain. SerboCroatian and Slovak, on the other hand, behave like English; they allow the coreferential
pronoun inside the PP, which suggests more structure, and potentially a clausal boundary.
(i) Mariai
Maria

poozya

bron

koo

siebiei/*nieji.

put

gun

near

herself/her

[Polish]

Maria put a gun near herself.


(ii) Maria
Maria

poloila

zbran

blizko

sebai/?neji.

put

gun

near

herself/her

Maria put a gun near herself. (Radkevich 2010: 126)

[Slovak]

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

150

150

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

Other ph(r)ases

(61) a. Halldr lasj


bkurnari ekki tj ti.
Halldor read the.books not
Halldr didnt read the books.
b. ?g talai (i gaer)
vi
stdentanai

[Icelandic]

alla ti.
I
talked yesterday with the-students all
Lit. I talked yesterday with all the students. (cf. Bokovic 2004b: 102)

The simplest derivation that would yield (61b) is the one in (62), in which the NP
simply moves to [Spec,PP], and the quantier is stranded in D.32
(62) a. [PP with [DP all students]]
b. [PP studentsi [P with [DP all ti ]]]
c. [pP with [PP studentsi [P t [DP all ti]]]]

However, a more complex derivation is also possible, in which stranding does


indeed happen in [Spec,PP].33
(63) a. [PP with [DP all the students]]
b. [PP all the studentsi [P with ti ]]
c. [FP the studentsj [PP [all tj]i [P with ti ]]]
d. [pP withk [FP the studentsj [PP [all tj]i [P tk ti ]]]]

The last two diagnostics we will consider involve Quantier Raising and
ellipsis. If QR can target PP, we have extra evidence that movement can
proceed through the edge of PP. However, PPs are not of the right semantic
type to serve as the target for QR. If the complement of P can undergo ellipsis,
we have evidence that P can determine Spell-Out. Here, the evidence also
suggests that P heads cannot license ellipsis, but it is reducible to independent
factors. Thus, the ungrammaticality of (64a) in Polish is due to the lack of
preposition stranding. And the ungrammaticality of (64b) in English, a language with preposition stranding, could be due to the lack of argument ellipsis
in English.
(64) a. *Jan zadzwoni do Marii a
Piotr poszed do .
Jan
phoned
to Maria and Piotr went
to
Jan called Maria and Piotr went to see her.
b. *John talked about a holiday in Paris and Bill dreamt about .

[Polish]

As we can see, neither QR nor ellipsis provides an argument in favor of PPs being
phases.

32

33

The derivation in which students moves to [Spec,DP] stranding all in D is excluded as a violation
of antilocality.
This is more in line with Bokovis actual derivation, given in (i). For Bokovi, however, there
are extra steps involved, as he disallows stranding in thematic positions:
(i) [PP withj [OP studentsi tj [AgrpP [all ti] tj [PP tj ti(cf.
]]]] Bokovic 2004b: 108)

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

151

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

ApplPs as phases

151

This concludes our discussion of PPs as phases. The behavior of PPs with
respect to phasehood diagnostics is mixed, as summarized in the following table.
(65) PPs as phases
Diagnostic Question

Answer Evidence

Is P the source of uninterpret- Yes


able features?
Is PP a domain for feature
Yes
valuation?
Does movement out of PP
have to proceed through the
edge of PP?

Yes

Can QR target PP?


No
Can the complement of P be No
deleted?
Can PP be a binding domain? Yes

structural prepositional cases


Locative versus Accusative case on
complements of directional versus
spatial prepositions
blocked by lled edge position quantier stranding in [Spec,PP] (subject to
crosslinguistic variation), ungrammaticality of preposition stranding (subject
to crosslinguistic variation)
PP is not the right semantic type
ungrammatical in languages that lack
argument ellipsis
with certain prepositions

5.3 ApplPs as phases


In this section, we turn to the idea, due to McGinnis (2001), that certain types of
double object constructions are phases. This idea relies on the assumption that
in a double object construction, the relationship between the direct and the
indirect object is mediated by a functional head called an applicative head (see
Pylkknen 2008 and the references therein for arguments in favor of such an
analysis):34

34

There are many alternative structures for double object constructions, and many issues surrounding
double object constructions, which I will abstract away from here. For example, the relationship
between the two objects in a double object construction is in principle independent from the issue
of what the relationship is between the so-called double object and dative constructions (expressed
by means of the preposition to in English). More specically, the issue is whether the two sentences
in (i) and (ii) are related transformationally or not.
(i) Jan gave Piotr a cookie.
(ii) Jan gave a cookie to Piotr.

I refer the interested reader to Green (1974) and Oehrle (1976) for some early diagnostics and
observations about the differences between the two. To illustrate briey, double objects are
infelicitous with locations (as shown in (iiab)) and imply a successful transfer of possession

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

152

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

152

Other ph(r)ases

(66)

ApplP
IO

Appl
Appl

DO

This straightforwardly captures the fact that the indirect object c-commands the direct
object, as can be shown by applying the familiar Barss & Lasnik (1986) c-command
diagnostics, which I will refrain from doing here. The structure in (66) also captures
the fact that in some languages, the applicative head is realized overtly, as shown by
the following examples from Bukusu (a northeastern Bantu language).35
(67) a. n-a-keend-el-a
omu-xasi.
1SS-tense-walk-APP-FV CL1-woman
I walked for the woman.
b. n-a-ar-ir-a
e-nyuungu luu-saala
1SS-tense-break-APP-FV CL9-pot
CL11-stick
I broke the pot with the stick.
c. wanjala e-er-er-a
en-goxo
e-yaywa
Wanjala 3sS.tense-kill-APP-FV CL9-chicken CL9-axe
Wanjala killed the chicken with the axe. (Peterson 2007: 7)

[Bukusu]

Pylkknen distinguishes two types of applicative structures, which she refers to


as high and low applicatives.36 This distinction is empirically motivated by the
fact that applicative constructions can behave differently from language to
language, and, furthermore, that different types of applicatives can behave differ-

(either literal or metaphorical). Thus (iiib) implies that the students successfully mastered Polish;
no such implication is present in a DP PP frame.
(ii) a. Maria sent a book to Warsaw.
b. #Maria sent Warsaw a book.
(iii) a. Maria taught Polish to the students.
b. Maria taught the students Polish.

35

36

In languages that allow both orders of the two objects, the issue of some contention is which of the
objects is basic and which one derived (see Miyagawa & Tsujioka 2004 for a discussion of
Japanese, and Bailyn 2009 and Dyakonova 2007 for a discussion of Russian). See also the brief
discussion of dative shift in Chapter 6.
The applicative head can convey a large number of meanings: benefactive, malefactive, instrumental, locative and comitative meanings, among others. Other types of applicative markers,
discussed by Peterson (2007), include prioritive ones (which indicate that the action was completed
before a given object) or relinquitive ones, which indicate that the action was accomplished without
the (applied) object.
See also Marantz (1993) for the idea that different types of applicative heads might occupy different
levels, even in a language like English.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

153

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

ApplPs as phases

153

ently even within a single language. The differences involve transitivity restrictions, compatibility of an applicative structure with static verbs and the ability for
a depictive modier to modify the indirect object:
(68) High versus low applicatives

possible with intransitive verbs


possible with stative verbs
possible for depictive modiers to modify indirect object

High
applicatives

Low
applicatives

*
*
*

According to these diagnostics, English lacks high applicatives. First, it disallows


applicative objects with intransitive verbs, such as the unergative run or the
unaccusative die.
(69) a. *Maria ran Jan.
b. *Maria died Jan.

They are not implausible semantically as applicatives; (70a) could be a benefactive and (70b) a malefactive:
(70) a. Maria ran for the benet of Jan.
b. Maria died to the detriment of Jan.

Second, English disallows applicative objects (indirect objects) with stative verbs
like hold. This is illustrated by the ungrammaticality of (71a), whose intended
interpretation is the one in (71b).
(71) a. *I held Maria the door.
b. I held the door for Maria.

And, third, English disallows the indirect object to be modied by depictives:


(72) *I gave Mariai the book curiousi

In a language with high applicatives, all three applicative sentence types are
possible. Pylkknen applies these diagnostics to a variety of languages; below I
illustrate with data from Luganda.
(73) a. Mukasa ya-tambu-le-dde
Katonga.
Mukasa 3SG.PAST-walk-appl-PAST Katonga
Mukasa walked for Katonga.
b. Katonga ya-kwaant-i-dde
Mukasa ensawo.
Katonga 3SG.PAST-hold-APPL-PAST Mukasa bag
Katonga held the bag for Mukasa. (Pylkknen 2008: 20)

[Luganda]

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

154

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

154

Other ph(r)ases

c. Nd-o-shum-el-a
Katonga o
neta.
1SG-PAST-work-APPL-FV Katonga 3SG tired
I worked for Katonga while he was tired. (Pylkknen 2008: 32)

Pylknnen derives the differences between the two types of applicatives from
either structural or interpretative considerations. First, she establishes a different structure for high and low applicatives. In a high applicative structure,
given in (74) below, the direct object is the complement of the verb, and the
indirect object is the specier of a high applicative head (which itself takes a
VP as a complement). A high applicative head establishes a relationship
between the indirect object and the event described by the VP containing the
direct object:
(74)

ApplP
IO

Appl
Appl

VP
V

DO

In a low applicative structure, the asymmetric relationship between the indirect


and direct object remains the same in that the indirect object c-commands the
direct one; however, this relationship is more direct. The Applicative Phrase, with
the indirect object as its specier and the direct object as its complement, is a
complement of the verb:
VP

(75)
V

ApplP
IO

Appl
Appl

DO

Pylknnen argues that the differences illustrated above follow from this difference in structure. Given that the low applicative head takes a direct object as its
complement and the indirect object as its specier, the ungrammaticality of
applicative structures in which the direct object is missing becomes a matter of
lexical selection; in the English examples in (69ab) above the selectional
requirements of the applicative head are not satised. Since in a high applicative structure, the applicative head selects the VP, it does not matter if this VP is
transitive or not.
The next two differences between high and low applicatives, namely the fact
that only high applicatives are compatible with static verbs and allow the indirect
object to be modied by a depictive phrase, follow from the semantics of the two
types of applicative heads.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

155

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

ApplPs as phases

155

So far, nothing we have said about the two types of applicatives has any
bearing on their phasal status, as the diagnostics distinguishing the two types
are independent of the diagnostics that distinguish phase heads from non-phase
heads. However, McGinnis (2001) argues that high applicatives differ from
low applicatives in that the high applicative head is a phase head but a low one
is not. As such, it can have the EPP feature, which allows movement of the
direct object over the indirect one. What this captures nicely is the distinction
between languages in which only the higher of the two objects (the indirect
object) can passivize, and languages in which either the direct or the
indirect objects can passivize. The examples in (76ab) show that Bukusu is
of the latter type: in benefative applicatives, either object can undergo passive
movement:37
(76) a. omu-xasi
a-kul-il-w-a
sii-tabu
nee-wanjala.
[Bukusu]
CL1-woman
3SS-buy-APP-PASS-FV CL7-book by-Wanjala
The woman was bought the book by Wanjala.
b. sii-tabu
sy-a-kul-il-w-a
omu-xasi
(?nee-wanjala).
CL17-book
CL7S-tense-BUY-APP-PASS-FV
CL1-woman
by-Wanjala
The book was bought for the woman (?by Wanjala). (Peterson 2007: 8)

From a purely locality-centric perspective, this pattern is surprising; if the two


objects stand in an asymmetric relationship with respect to each other, only the
higher one should be able to passivize. McGinnis attributes the ability of either
object to passivize to the fact that the direct object moves to the (outer) specier of
the ApplP head rst. From this position, it is going to be closer than the indirect
object to T for the purposes of passivization. Passivization of the direct object
instead (illustrated in (77b)) would constitute a standard locality violation,
irrespective of how locality is implemented (Attract Closest, Minimal Link
Condition, Shortest Link).38

37

38

The language McGinnis focuses on is Kinyarwanda, another Bantu language in which either object
can in principle passivize. In this language (as in many Bantu languages), different types of
applicatives behave differently with respect to passivization. For example, in locative applicatives,
only the locative argument can passivize.
McGinnis speculates that perhaps more generally the difference in phasal status of the two types
of applicatives is due to the fact that a sister of a VP can head a phase only if it has an argument in
its specier. This correctly distinguishes high applicatives from the low ones, but it does not
seem to be a general fact about phase heads; for example, it is not the case that C heads only
constitute phases if the specier of CP is lled. Perhaps this is due to the fact that the specier of
CP is not a thematic position, which would mean that McGinniss generalization could be
restated as a statement that the sister of VP counts as a phase head only if it selects an external
argument. If, however, passive and unaccusative vPs are phase heads, as argued by Legate
(2003) (whose arguments we reviewed in Section 4.2), this might not be the right characterization, either.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

156

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

156

Other ph(r)ases

(77) a. High applicative


TP
T
Tu:[

], EPP

ApplP
ApplP

DOi
IO

Appl
VP

ApplEPP
V

ti

b. Low applicative
TP
DOi

T
VP
V

ApplP
Appl

IO
Appl

ti

Movement of the direct object to the outer specier of the ApplP (over the indirect
object), which is analogous to what we have seen above in a high applicative
structure, can be ruled out in two in principle independent ways. We could
appeal to the idea that the low applicative head, being a non-phase head, does not
have the EPP feature, which is the feature driving the movement of the direct
object to the outer specier.39 Alternatively, we could appeal to antilocality,
which is what Jeong (2006) does.
We have seen above what allows passivization of direct objects in high
applicatives. We have yet to see what allows passivization of indirect objects; if
39

Feature Inheritance is not an option either, since a low applicative phrase is dominated by a nonphase head (the V head).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

157

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

ApplPs as phases

157

the direct object were always to move across the indirect object, passivization of
the direct object should be the only possibility. We could either assume that the
direct object does not move to [Spec, ApplP], which implies that the EPP feature
on the high applicative head is optional (not an unreasonable assumption), or that
it does move, but that it does so in a tucking-in fashion, below the indirect object,
the latter option being the one favored by McGinnis.40 These two possibilities are
schematized in (78ab).
(78) a.

TP
IO

T
T
ApplP
Appl

ti
Appl

VP
V

b.

DO

TP
T

IOi
T

ApplP
ti

ApplP
DOj

Appl
ApplEPP
V

VP
tj

So far, the discussion in this section has established that high and low applicatives differ with respect to extraction, and that passivization of the lower
object in a high applicative proceeds through the edge of the ApplP. The
extraction diagnostic thus distinguishes between low and high applicatives,

40

Equidistance is a logical possibility, too. However, since equidistance became obsolete with
Feature Inheritance in place, I will not elaborate on it here.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

158

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

158

Other ph(r)ases

but it is not clear that other diagnostics do. For example, the Appl head is
implicated in case valuation in both high and low applicatives.41
To complete the discussion of high Applicative Phrases as phases, let us apply
the remaining phasehood diagnostics to high applicatives. Polish is a language
which, according to Pylkkanens diagnostics, has high applicatives (see Citko
2010, 2011b for a more detailed discussion). Dyakonova (2007) makes a similar
point about Russian, and the Polish examples below are based on her Russian ones.
(79) a. Bede wam
spiewac i
tanczyc.
[Polish]
be.FUT you.DAT sing.INF and dance.INF
I will sing and dance for you.
b. Siedzisz mi
na sukni.
sit.2SG
me.DAT on dress
Youre sitting on my dress.
c. Maria odebraa
nam
klucze juz
troche pijanym.
Maria took.away us.DAT keys
already bit
tipsy.INSTR
Maria took away the keys from us (while we were) already a bit tipsy.

Direct objects can be passivized, which implies movement through the outer
specier of ApplP. The ungrammaticality of (80b) is unexpected in a high
applicative structure, but receives an independent explanation based on case:
indirect object is dative and dative objects do not passivize, something I discuss in
detail in Citko (2011b).42
(80) a. Ksiazkai zostaa wysana Marii ti
(przez
book.NOM became sent
Maria.DAT by
A book was sent to Maria
b. *Mariai
zostaa wysana ti ksiazke.
Maria.NOM became sent
book.ACC
Maria was sent a book.

Jana).
Jan.ACC

Either object can be wh-moved:


(81) a. Komui
Jan
wysa ti ksiazke?
who.DAT Jan.NOM sent
book.ACC
Who did Jan send a book to?
b. Coi
Jan
wysa ti? Marii
Maria.DAT
what.ACC Jan.NOM sent
What did Jan send Maria?

41

42

This is something we have not discussed in a lot of detail here. But it is quite standard to assume that
the Applicative head values the case feature of the indirect object (often as dative).
Even though the dative indirect object cannot move, it could still act as an intervener (of a defective
kind), so similar considerations apply.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

159

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

ApplPs as phases

159

When both move, the ordering is free, which is not a surprising fact for a language
with no superiority effects:
(82) a. Coi
komuj
Jan
wysa tj ti?
what.ACC who.DAT Jan.NOM sent
What did Jan send to whom?
b. Komuj
coi
Jan
wysa tj ti?
who.DAT what.ACC Jan.NOM sent
What did Jan send to whom?

I assume the underlying order is one in which the indirect object precedes the
direct one, even though this is an issue of some controversy in the literature on
Slavic double object constructions (see, for example, Bailyn 2009 and
Dyakonova 2007 for opposing views on this matter). This implies that the whmovement of the direct object is always going to proceed through the edge of
ApplP, and that the structure of (83a) is that of (83b).
(83) a. Coi
Jan
wysa Marii ti?
what.ACC Jan.NOM sent
Maria.DAT
What did Jan send to Maria?
b. [CP whati [TP Jan [vP sent [ApplP ti [ApplP Maria [VP ti ]]]]]]

The edge of ApplP may also be the shifted position for scrambled orders in
which the direct object precedes the indirect one:
(84) a. Jan wysa ksiazkei Marii ti.
Jan sent
book.ACC Maria.DAT
Jan sent a book to Maria.
b. [TP Jan [vP sent [ApplP a booki [ApplP Maria [VP ti]]]]]

What is relevant for our purposes is the fact that a complex wh-phrase moving
through the edge of ApplP can strand a nominal in that position:
(85) a. Ilei
Jan
wysa ksiazek
Marii ti?
how.many.ACC Jan.NOM sent
books.GEN Maria.DAT
How many books has Jan sent Maria?
b. [CP how.many [TP Jan [vP sent [ApplP how.many books [ApplP
Maria [VP how.many books]]]]]]

Ellipsis of the complement of the high applicative head is also possible:43


43

The fact that the English example in (i) does not readily allow the interpretation in (ii) is thus
consistent with English Applicative Phrases not being phases.
(i) John sent Maria letters and Peter Eve.
(ii) John sent Maria letters and Peter sent Eve letters.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C05.3D

160

[124160] 23.11.2013 11:35AM

160

Other ph(r)ases

(86) a. Jan
wysa Marii
listy,
a
Piotr
Ewie.
Jan.NOM sent
Maria.DAT letters.ACC and Piotr.NOM Ewa.DAT
Jan sent Maria letters and Peter (sent letters to) Eve.
b. [TP Piotr.NOM [vP [ApplP Ewa.DAT [Appl Appl [VP sent letters ]]]]]

The behavior of (high) Applicative Phrases with respect to phasehood diagnostics is summarized in (87).
(87) High ApplP as phases
Diagnostic Question

Answer Evidence

Is Appl the source of uninterpretable


features?
Does movement out of ApplP have to
proceed through the edge of ApplP?

Yes

Does Appl determine Spell-Out?

Yes

Yes

Dative case on indirect


objects
Passivization of direct
objects, discontinuous
nominals
VP ellipsis in high
applicatives

More generally, we have seen in this chapter how extending phasehood to


three new categories (Predication Phrases, Prepositional Phrases and certain
types of Applicative Phrases) fares. The results are somewhat more mixed.
In the next chapter, we turn to variation in phasehood, which, broadly speaking, refers to the idea that the status of a given category as a phase might vary not
only from language to language but also within a single language. There are a
couple of possibilities to consider. One is that a given head can acquire (or lose)
its phasehood status in the course of the derivation. This will be the topic of
Section 6.1, where I focus on proposals like those of Gallego or Den Dikken, for
whom head movement (of a phase head to a non-phase head dominating it) can
result in what would otherwise be a non-phase head becoming a phase head. The
second type of variation concerns crosslinguistic variation. Such variation could
arise trivially if a language lacks a given category (which is considered universally to be a phase). We have seen some instances of this scenario already. For
example, applicatives count as phases only in languages that have high applicatives. There are other cases to consider, as we will see in Section 6.2 of next
chapter. And the last type of variation, which is referred to in the literature as nonsimultaneous phasehood, will be the topic of Section 6.3.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

161

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

6
Variation in phasehood

6.1

Dynamic phases

This chapter focuses on the idea that the phase status of a given category
can change throughout the derivation. This is very different from the view
that has been implicit throughout this book, which is that phasehood, once
xed, remains constant. The ideas we will examine in this chapter allow
categories to become phases or stop being phases. Such a dynamic
approach to phasehood has been articulated most explicitly by Den Dikken
(2007) and Gallego (2010), and in what follows, I focus on their
proposals. What they share is the basic idea that a non-phase head can become
a phase head under certain well-dened circumstances. Where they differ is in
the details of implementation, as well as in their fundamental assumptions
about the nature of phases. For both Den Dikken and Gallego, the process
responsible for the variability of the phase status of a given head is head
movement. Both thus rely on head movement being a syntactic movement, as
opposed to a post-syntactic PF movement. Den Dikken, whose formulation is
given in (1), refers to this process as Phase Extension, and Gallego refers to it as
Phase Sliding.
(1) Phase Extension
Syntactic movement of the head H of a phase to the head X of the node
dominating extends the phase up from to ; loses its phasehood in the
process, and any constituent on the edge of ends up in the domain of the derived
phase as a result of Phase Extension. (Den Dikken 2007: 1)

According to (1), HP is a phase in (2a). However, after it moves to X in (2b), it


stops being a phase, and XP becomes a phase instead. What changes is not just the
status of XP and HP; the edge of the phase and the Spell-Out domain also get
adjusted accordingly. In (2b), HP will eventually become the Spell-Out domain,
but not until the phase is complete and the next head is merged (on PIC1) or the
next phase head up is merged (on PIC2).

161

{DESKTOP}/9781107040847C06.3D

162 [161184] 23.11.2013 12:21PM

162

Variation in phasehood

(2)

a.

XP
PHASE
X

HP
ZP

H
YP

SPELL-OUT DOMAIN

EDGE

PHASE

b.

XP
WP

X
X

HP

EDGE

SPELL-OUT DOMAIN
ZP

H
H

YP

Logically speaking, it is also possible for the lower head not to lose its phase
status. On this scenario, we end up with two phase heads (X and H), two edges
(circled below), and two Spell-Out domains:
(3)

XP
X

WP

HP

SPELL-OUT DOMAIN 2
ZP

H
H

YP

SPELL-OUT DOMAIN 1

There are two arguments against adopting the scenario in (3), in which a phase
head moves up to another phase head and keeps its phase status. First, it
is incompatible with the assumption that every phase head has to dominate a
non-phase head, as argued by Richards (2008), whose reasoning we reviewed in
the section on Feature Inheritance in Chapter 2 (Section 2.6). Second, it will not
allow Agree between X and YP, which as we will see shortly was Den
Dikkens main empirical motivation for Phase Extension.
Phase Extension is not the only innovation in Den Dikkens system. As
we saw earlier, his denition of a phase also departs crucially from the
standard denition. For Den Dikken, it is neither propositionality, nor complete
argument structure, nor being the locus of uninterpretable features that denes a
phase. For him, what denes a phase is a subjectpredicate conguration. Such

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

163

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

Dynamic phases

163

congurations (and only such congurations) constitute inherent phases. Others


(i.e. non-subjectpredicate congurations) can become phases only as a result of
Phase Extension.1 Den Dikken (2007: 27) considers the classic criteria for
phasehood, such as semantic and phonological independence, being the loci of
uninterpretable features and EPP features, contrasting his dynamic approach with
Chomskys static approach. Den Dikkens approach is both stronger and weaker
than Chomskys. On the one hand, there are some categories which count as
phases given Chomskys diagnostics (or, perhaps to put it in more accurate terms,
given the elds understanding of Chomskys diagnostics), but which do not
always count as phases on Den Dikkens diagnostics. A CP is a good example: for
Den Dikken it can only become a phase by extension.2 On the other hand, some of
the structures that Den Dikken analyzes as predication structures (and thus
phases) are not typically considered to be phasal. Given the conclusions of
Section 5.3, English double object structures are a case in point.
Since the concept of Phase Extension is in principle independent of redening
phases as predication structures, I will consider Phase Extension on its own merits.
Den Dikken illustrates how Phase Extension works (and why it is necessary)
with three well-documented types of inversion structures, illustrated in (4)(6):
predicate inversion, locative inversion and dative shift. In all of them, the subject
and the predicate are given in italics, with the b examples being the inverted variants.
(4) a. Spixs Macaw is the worlds rarest parrot
b. The worlds rarest parrot is Spixs macaw.
(5) a. All the parrots ew up the river.
b. Up the river ew all the parrots.
(6) a. Leslie gave each parrot a piece of fruit
b. Leslie gave a piece of fruit to each parrot

As we saw in Chapter 2, such an understanding of phases relies on an independent understanding of


predication; something which is the focus of his earlier work (Den Dikken 2006b). The list in (ivii)
provides examples of the kinds of structures that Den Dikken (2006b) considers to be predication
structures. While many of them can be pretty straightforwardly analyzed as such, it is not completely
clear whether we would want to treat all of them as phases.
(i) I have [SUBJECT a parrot] for [PREDICATE a friend]
(ii) [SUBJECT Parrots], [PREDICATE I really admire]
(iii) I gave [SUBJECT a nut] to [PREDICATE a parrot]
(iv) I put [SUBJECT the parrot] on [PREDICATE its perch]
(v) [SUBJECT Parrots screech] [PREDICATE loudly].
(vi) [PREDICATE the monster] of [SUBJECT a parrot]
(vii) [SUBJECT Mary]s [PREDICATE parrot]

If CP is not a phase, wh-movement through (or to) [Spec,CP] can only take place if there is v-T-C
movement; something that happens universally at LF, Den Dikken argues.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

164

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

164

Variation in phasehood

I will focus here on copular constructions, since we have devoted a fair amount of
attention to them in the previous chapter. The PrP structure presented there
is different from Den Dikkens structure, but it is consistent with his assumptions that the relationship between the subject and the predicate is mediated by
a functional projection. On Den Dikkens assumptions, all the b examples in (4)
(6) involve inversion of the predicate around the subject, as illustrated in (7ab):
(7) a. Spixs Macawi is [PrP ti [Pr Pr the worlds rarest parrot] ].
b. The worlds rarest parroti is [PrP Spixs Macaw [Pr Pr ti] ].

A similar inversion mechanism applies to locative inversion and dative shift cases,
the only difference being that the functional head mediating the relationship between
the subject and the locative PP in (5ab) or the two objects in (6ab) is different.3
Den Dikken argues that in all of them, the relationship between the subject and the
predicate is mediated by a functional category he refers to as a relator, which projects
its own phrase, the Relator Phrase (RP). In the cases at hand, the RP is dominated
by an FP (where FP stands for any phrase headed by a functional head F). In copular
clauses, RP and FP stand for PrP and TP, respectively:
(8)

FP(TP)
F/T

RP(PrP)

SUBJECT

R(Pr)

R(Pr)

PREDICATE

Den Dikkens main theoretical argument in favor of Phase Extension involves the
following issue: if RP (TP) in (9) is a phase, how is it possible for the functional
head F(T) to establish an Agree relationship with the predicate, and, consequently, for the predicate to move to [Spec,TP]?
(9)

FP/TP
F(T)
F/T

RP(PrP)

SUBJECT

R(Pr)

R(Pr)

PREDICATE

We might wonder whether dative shift (which in Den Dikkens terms is inversion around the
preposition to) is compatible with the approach to double object verbs advocated in Section 5.3
above, which relied on the presence of an applicative head. While this is not the approach Den
Dikken takes, nothing in principle would prevent the inversion from taking place around the
applicative head.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

165

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

Dynamic phases

165

If, however, R raises to F, as shown below, then RP stops being a phase and F
(with R adjoined to it) becomes one. Now, on Den Dikkens assumptions, F can
undergo Agree with the predicate; the complement of the derived phase head (i.e.
RP) is not spelled out until FP is merged with a higher head.
(10)

FP(TP)
F/ T

RP(PrP)
R(Pr)

SUBJECT

R(Pr)

PREDICATE

Note, however, that predicate inversion in (9) is only a problem if the


complement of the phase head R, the predicate itself, is spelled out as soon as
the phase is complete, i.e. when F is merged. This is what the earlier version
of PIC, referred to as PIC1 throughout this book, mandated. However, if F is not a
phase head (as is the case if F is T), the domain of the lower phase head R is
not spelled out till the next phase head, C in this case, is merged. Thus, under
the assumptions of PIC2, Agree between F and the complement of R in (9) (as
well as movement of the complement of R to the specier of TP) should be
possible, unless F is independently shown to be a phase head. For Den Dikken,
however, Phase Extension is what allows movement of the predicate to the edge
of the derived phase.4
FP/TP

(11)
PREDICATEi

F/ T

F/ T
RP(PrP)
SUBJECT

R(Pr)

R(Pr)

ti

Now the (original) subject of PrP becomes part of the Spell-Out domain when a
higher head is merged:5

Den Dikken relies on equidistance in order to explain why the subject in the specier of RP does not
intervene.
In order to rule out the derivation in which the subject moves to the edge of FP rst, Den Dikken
appeals to a ban against adjunction to empty categories.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

166

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

166

Variation in phasehood

(12)

HP(CP)
H(C)

FP/ TP

PREDICATEi

F/ T

F/ T
RP(PrP)
R(Pr)

SUBJECT

R(Pr)

ti

Phase Extension can not only explain what allows the predicate to move
to [Spec,FP], but also why the postverbal subject (the original subject in [Spec,
RP]) cannot move. The immobility of postverbal subjects in inverted copular
constructions, illustrated in (13ab), is well documented in the literature (see Den
Dikken 2006, Moro 1997, 2000, among others). On the Phase Extension account,
the ungrammaticality of the b examples is a consequence of the structure and
derivation in (11), where the original subject is buried inside the Spell-Out
domain of the derived phase head T.6
(13) a. Which parroti do you think is ti the worlds rarest parrot?
b. *Which parroti do you think the worlds rarest parrot is ti?
(14) a. Which parrotsi do you think ti ew up the river?
b. *Which parrotsi do you think up the river ew ti?

Let me conclude this section with a brief comparison of Den Dikkens Phase
Extension with Gallegos Phase Sliding. Phase Sliding is similar in spirit, but
it relies on a different (more standard) denition of a phase, and it applies to
a different empirical domain. Gallego shares Den Dikkens misgivings
about interface-based criteria for distinguishing phases from non-phases, suggesting a need for a denition of phases that does not rely on the interface diagnostics.

Den Dikken extends this reasoning to DPs, and takes the ban on extraction out of specic noun
phrases of the kind illustrated in (i) to be a consequence of a DP becoming a phase by extension due
to the raising of the relator head (the head mediating the relationship between picture of who and
maria) to D, as shown schematically in (iiac). After Phase Extension, the wh-phrase who is
buried inside the complement of the derived phase headed by the complex head D with an R
head adjoined to it. Since DP is an argument, adjunction to it is blocked by assumption.
(i) Whoi did Jan see Marias picture of ti?
(ii) a. [RP picture of who R Maria]
b. [DP R+D [RP picture of R Maria] ]
c. [DP Mariais R+D [RP picture of ti] ]

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

167

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

Dynamic phases

167

He treats the interface behavior of phases as a consequence of phasehood rather


than a diagnostic of phasehood. However, he also points out problems with Den
Dikkens predication-based denition of phases, proposing instead the familiar by
now denition based on the presence of uninterpretable features:
(15) Phase Condition
Uninterpretable features (uFF) signal phase boundaries. (Gallego 2010: 51)

Gallego thus does not redene phases; he still takes core phases to be CPs and vPs,
and he shares with Den Dikken the idea that head movement can extend phases.
His empirical focus is on v to T movement, and the contrast between Romance
languages (Spanish and Catalan primarily) and English in this respect. He frames
his discussion in more general terms, suggesting that Phase Sliding could be what
distinguishes Null Subject Languages (NSLs) from non-Null Subject Languages.
I illustrate his proposal below with data from Polish, also a NSL. As is well known,
NSLs differ from non-NSLs in that they do not show that-trace effects:
(16) a. Ktoi Jan chce, zeby ti przeczyta ten
who Jan wants COMP
read
this
Who does Jan want to read this poem?
b. *Whoi do you think that ti read this poem?

wiersz?
poem

[Polish]

The classic account of this contrast is to attribute the grammaticality of (16a) to


the fact that the subject moves from a postverbal position so there is no that-trace
conguration whatsoever. This is what Gallego does as well, relying on Pesetsky &
Torregos (2001) treatment of the Nominative case feature as an uninterpretable
Tense feature on the DP (uT[ ]), and allowing case to be valued in situ in NSLs.7
This also allows him to account for the obligatory presence of the complementizer
in embedded clauses in NSLs:8
(17) a. John knows (that) Mary wrote this poem.
b. Jan wie
*(ze) napisaa Maria ten
Jan knows
that wrote
Maria this
Jan knows that Maria wrote this poem.

wiersz.
poem

[Polish]

For Pesetsky & Torrego (as well as for Gallego), these two facts are related. C has
an uninterpretable T feature, which can be checked either by the complementizer that or by the movement of the subject, which also has the uT feature
(namely, its Nominative case feature). With Phase Sliding, the subject (being
inside vP) is spelled out as soon as C is merged, as shown in (18).9 The subject
thus cannot move to [Spec,CP] to check the uT feature of C, which is what
happens in English, according to Pesetsky & Torrego. What forces the presence
7

8
9

This suggests that T in NSLs either has no EPP feature, or that its EPP feature is checked by verb
movement to T, as proposed, for example, by Alexiadou & Anagnostopoulou (2001).
A postverbal position is not the neutral position for subjects in Polish.
Gallego thus assumes the weak PIC (PIC2), in contrast to Den Dikken.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

168

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

168

Variation in phasehood

of the complementizer is the need for the uT feature of C to be checked. In


languages like English, the subject (which moves to [Spec,TP]) remains accessible and can go on and move to [Spec,CP] to check Cs uT feature. Note,
however, that it would also remain accessible in [Spec,vP] with no Phase
Sliding in place.
CP

(18)
CuT [

TP

TiT [val]

vP

SUBJECTUT[NoM]

v
DP

This concludes our discussion of dynamic phases. While the proposals we


looked at in this section are quite programmatic in nature, the very idea that
phasehood is dynamic and might be affected by independent factors (such as the
presence or absence of head movement) is quite appealing. It also opens up
the possibility that phasehood may be subject to crosslinguistic variation, which
we will explore in the next section.

6.2 Crosslinguistic variation


Crosslinguistic variation with respect to phasehood has already been raised as
a possibility in this book. In Section 5.2 above, for example, we saw proposals,
most notably Abels (2003), that allow PPs to be phases in some languages (i.e.
languages that disallow preposition stranding) but not in others (i.e. languages
that allow preposition stranding). Chomskys own writings on phases do
not seem to leave much room for crosslinguistic variation. Certainly, if the
conceptual motivation for phases comes from the fact that they reduce computational complexity, we would expect phases to be universal. However,
conceptual considerations lead us only to the expectation that the existence of
phases is universal, not that their identity is universal. One question we need to
ask before entertaining the possibility of crosslinguistic variation with respect to
phasehood any further is whether the diagnostics we developed in Chapter 3
(both interface-based diagnostics and syntactic diagnostics) allow for crosslinguistic variation, and if so, how such crosslinguistic variation might come
about. We saw that one of the core criteria for phasehood was independence at
the interfaces. This, in turn, was diagnosed by things like propositional status or
full argument structure (on the LF side), or the ability to determine Spell-Out (on
the PF side). If propositional status or full argument structure is an LF diagnostic
of phasehood, then there does not seem to be a lot of room for crosslinguistic
variation. It is not clear what it would mean for a given category (i.e. CP or vP) to

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

169

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

Crosslinguistic variation

169

be propositional in some languages but not in others, or for a transitive verb


phrase to be complete in terms of its argument structure in some languages but not
in others. LF diagnostics thus point towards a more static and crosslinguistically
stable approach to phasehood. PF diagnostics, however, seem somewhat more
exible: if isolability or movability is a PF diagnostic, we might expect to nd
some variation with respect to PF phasehood. However, we saw in Chapter 3 that
isolability is not a reliable phasehood diagnostic.10
Setting the diagnostics aside, there are (at least) three different ways, listed in
(19ac), in which crosslinguistic variation in phasehood can arise. I will consider
them in turn in the rest of this section.
(19) a. A language lacks a category which is a phase head in other languages.
VARIATION AS LEXICAL GAP

b. Independent factors create an illusion of crosslinguistic variation with


VARIATION AS EPIPHENOMENON
respect to phasehood.
c. A given category may be a phase in some languages but not in others.
VARIATION AS PARAMETRIC SETTING

The rst possibility is for a given language to simply lack a category that is
considered to be a phase universally. The second one might be a misnomer,
since, technically, there is no variation on this view. Independent factors can
affect phases in ways that ultimately lead to different categories behaving like
phases in different languages.11 The third option is to simply assume that
variation in phasehood does occur, and posit a parameter to capture this variation
accordingly.
A straightforward illustration of the rst option (and not unexpected,
given the discussion in Section 5.3) comes from the domain of double
object constructions. We saw that only certain types of applicative heads
are phase heads (i.e. so-called high applicative heads), which can explain why
passivization of either the higher (i.e. the indirect) object or the lower (i.e. the

10

11

We also saw in Chapter 3 that phase heads determine Spell-Out. Crosslinguistic variation with
respect to what heads determine Spell-Out (and thus are phase heads) would thus have consequences for determining case valuation domains and ellipsis types. And both are places in the
grammar where we do nd some crosslinguistic variation. Logically speaking, however, crosslinguistic variation with respect to ellipsis could mean one of two things: either that the inventory of
phase heads (which are the heads that license ellipsis of their complements) can vary from language
to language, or that ellipsis is not a reliable phasehood diagnostic either.
Processes like Phase Extension or Phase Sliding can endow new heads with phasehood characteristics,
without changing the denitional characteristics of phases. As a result of Phase Extension, TP can be a
phase in one language but not in another. For Den Dikken, similar considerations apply to CPs: a CP
can only be a phase if a phase head moves to it. On this view, there is no (or very little) crosslinguistic
variation with respect to what categories count as inherent phases. Gallego (2010), in fact, is quite
explicit about not making the claim that there is crosslinguistic variation with respect to phasehood.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

170

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

170

Variation in phasehood

direct) object is possible in high applicative constructions.12 We also saw that the
existence of high applicatives in a language can be independently established by
the behavior of its applicatives with respect to three diagnostics, due to Pylkknen
(2008): compatibility with intransitive verbs, compatibility with stative predicates, and the ability for the indirect object to be modied by a depictive phrase.
What allowed passivization of the lower object was the EPP feature on the high
applicative head, as proposed by McGinnis (2001), something that we took to be
possible only if the high Applicative head is a phase head.13
A common place to look for variation with respect to phasehood is in the
domain of noun phrases (or determiner phrases), given the long line of research
on the crosslinguistic validity of the DP Hypothesis. The logic of the argument
is very simple: if DPs are phases (as we saw in Section 5.2), and if some
languages lack DPs (as is often argued for languages with no overt articles),
12

13

We also saw in Section 5.1 above that Slavic languages like Polish or Russian have two types of
Predication Phrases, one of which is a phase head and one is not. This makes it quite plausible that some
languages might lack the Pr head that is a phase head and only allow the one that is not. English might
seem like a plausible candidate for such a language: predicate nominals do not receive a designated
predicative case. However, unlike Slavic PrPs with Nominative predicates, they do allow extraction.
In principle, there could be another way for a high Applicative head to acquire its EPP feature,
without necessarily being a phase head. Given that high applicatives are dominated by a vP, the
high Applicative head could also acquire its uninterpretable features via Feature Inheritance, by
analogy to T inheriting its uninterpretable features from C. However, strictly speaking, this would
not be a case of Feature Inheritance, but rather of feature spreading (since v has to retain its
uninterpretable features), and it would also have to be possible with passive vPs. The two options
are also hard to distinguish empirically, since in both cases we end up with uninterpretable features
on both v and Appl heads:
(i)

vP
vu [

], (EPP)

ApplP
Appl

IO
Applu [

], (EPP)

V
(ii)

VP
DO

V AND

APPL

AS PHASE HEADS

vP
vu [

], (EPP)

ApplP

IO
Applu [

Appl
], (EPP)

VP
DO

V AS PHASE HEAD SHARING U-FEATURES WITH

APPL

HEAD

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

171

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

Crosslinguistic variation

171

such languages are predicted to lack one phase when compared to languages with
overt articles. This is the case that I will focus on in what follows.
Bokovi (2005, 2009, to appear) revives the idea that languages can vary with
respect to how much nominal structure they project: languages with overt articles
project their nominals Traditional Noun Phrases (TNPs), in Bokovis terms
up to DP, whereas languages with no articles projects their TNPs only up to NP.
However, the claim that the lack of overt articles implies the lack of a DP projection
is far from uncontroversial; see Citko (2010), Pereltsvaig (2007), Progovac (1998),
Rappaport (2001), Rutkowski (2002) and Rutkowski & Progovac (2005), among
many others, for a defense of the universality of the DP Hypothesis.14
14

A complete discussion of the arguments in favor of (and against) the Universal DP Hypothesis
would take us too far astray here and is somewhat tangential to the issue of crosslinguistic variation
in phasehood. Let me nevertheless mention a couple of potential issues for the Parametrized DP
Hypothesis. While languages at the core of the debate (Slavic languages like Polish, SerboCroatian or Russian) lack overt articles, they do have other elements that are typically analyzed
as D heads: demonstratives, possessive pronouns and quantiers, as shown in (iac).
(i) a. z
with

ta

papuga

this.3SG.FEM.INSTR

parrot.3SG.FEM.INSTR

[Polish]

with this parrot


b. z

moja

papuga

with

my.3SG.FEM.INSTR

parrot.3SG.FEM.INSTR

with my parrot
c. z
kazda
papuga
with

every

parrot.3SG.FEM.INSTR

with every parrot

Bokovi analyzes such elements essentially as adjectives, based on the fact that they show the
same agreement with the nouns they modify as adjectives do. He also points out that they can cooccur with each other and that some of them can appear in predicative positions:
(ii) ta
this
(iii) Ta
this

moja

papuga

my

parrot

[Polish]

papuga

jest

moja.

parrot

is

my

This, however, is not a convincing argument unless we have independent evidence that DP-internal
concord is limited only to adjectives.
A different argument against treating TNPs as Noun Phrases (as opposed to Determiner Phrases)
comes from contrasts of the following kind, which can be attributed to the fact that pronouns
occupy D positions (see Progovac 1998, Rutkowski 2002, for example). The contrast between (iii)
and (iv) shows that pronouns have to follow nominal modiers like sam alone. This follows
nicely from an analysis in which pronouns either occupy a D position to begin with, or raise to it.
(iii) Ona
she

sama

przysza

na

zebraine.

alone

came

to

meeting

She alone came to the meeting.

[Polish]

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

172

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

172

Variation in phasehood

Following Uriagereka (1988) and Corver (1990, 1992), Bokovi links


the grammaticality of Left Branch Extraction, well documented in Slavic literature and illustrated in (20) with data from Polish, to the lack of a DP projection.15
(20) a. Ilei
papugi jedza ti orzechw?
how.many parrots eat
nuts.GEN
How many nuts do parrots eat?
b. Jakiei
papugi najbardziej lubia ti
what.kind.of parrots best
like
What kind of nuts do parrots like best?
c. Swiezei papugi lubia ti orzechy.
fresh
parrots like
nuts
Parrots like fresh nuts.

orzechy?
nuts

It might be tempting to attribute the grammaticality of LBE to DP not being a


phase. However, it is not generally the case that movement out of phases is
impossible. What is generally the case (and what we have seen throughout this
book) is that movement out of a phase has to proceed through the phase edge,
whereas movement out of a non-phase is not subject to such a restriction. It
would also have the unwanted consequence of imposing similar restrictions
on movement of complements from DPs. This is not to say that parameterizing
the phasehood of DP is not a logical possibility. The crucial point here is that it
is not a possibility that is going to yield the right empirical results with respect
to LBE, a point made very explicitly by Bokovi.16
(iv) *?Sama

ona

przysza

na

zebranie.

alone

she

came

to

meeting

She alone came to the meeting.


15

16

The fact that there are languages that allow violations of the Left Branch Condition was noted by
Ross (1967).
Bokovi also points out that such an explanation will not explain why LBE violations sometimes
emerge, for example, when extraction takes place from the left branch of the complement of the
noun.
(i) *Cijei
whose

je

on

vidio [NP [N

prijatelja [NP ti

majke]]]?

is

he

seen

friend

mother

[Serbo-Croatian]

Whose mother did he see a friend of? (Bokovic 2005: 8)

While the equivalent of (i) in Polish is also degraded, it improves markedly if the Genitive precedes
the head noun:
(ii) ?*Czyjeji

Jan

zobaczy

przyjaciela ti

matki?

whose

Jan

saw

friend

mother

Whose mother did Jan see a friend of?


(iii) Czyjeji

Jan

zobaczy ti

matki?

przyjaciela

whose

Jan

saw

mother

friend

Whose mother did Jan see a friend of?

[Polish]

{DESKTOP}/9781107040847C06.3D

173 [161184] 23.11.2013 12:21PM

Crosslinguistic variation

173

Bokovi considers a number of other phase-based explanations of the contrast


between English-type and Serbo-Croatian-type languages briey, but ends up
rejecting them all. If DP is a phase, one way to exclude Left Branch Extraction of
adjectival modiers (which is the type of LBE that Bokovi focuses on) is to
assume that D cannot have an extra escape hatch. He rejects this assumption on the
grounds that it would rule out any movement from DP, not just movement from the
left branch. He further modies it by allowing D to have an extra specier position,
but deems movement from an adjoined NP position (the position for adjectives) to
be too short (via a form of antilocality of the kind proposed by Abels 2003). This
would rule out movement of adjoined APs, but it is not clear how it would rule out
movement of other left branch elements. Demonstratives and determiners are a case
in point; they are already at the edge of DP (so antilocality would not be able to
explain why they cannot move out of DP).
Since our focus here is not on the specics of LBE, or even on the issue
of whether Slavic noun phrases are noun phrases or determiner phrases, I will
not dwell on the specics of Bokovis account. In short, he settles on the
parameter concerning the position of adjectives to distinguish languages that
allow LBE from the ones that do not. In English-type languages (languages with
no LBE), adjectives are heads taking NP as complements (see (21a)), whereas in
Serbo-Croatian-type languages (languages that allow LBE), they are adjuncts
(see (21b)). Given this structural distinction, in languages like English, LBE
would have to involve non-constituent movement.17
(21) a.

DP
AdjP

D
Adj

NP

LANGUAGES WITH NO LBE

b.
NP
AdjP

NP

LANGUAGES WITH LBE

To try and settle the question of whether DPs are phases in languages with no
articles, let us apply to them the same diagnostics we applied to English DPs in
Section 4.3. As usual, I will use Polish to illustrate. The examples below show
that with respect to these diagnostics, Polish Traditional Noun Phrases (be they
DPs or NPs) behave like phases. First, they contain heads that are capable of
valuing so-called adnominal Genitive case:
(22) a. kawa
Jana
coffee.NOM Jan.GEN
Jans coffee
17

[Polish]

LBE, being a fairly straightforward case of A-bar movement, could not be easily reanalyzed as
head movement, which could in principle be possible out of the structure in (21a).

{DESKTOP}/9781107040847C06.3D

174 [161184] 23.11.2013 12:21PM

174

Variation in phasehood

b. kawa
dobrego
coffee.NOM good.GEN
good quality coffee

gatunku
quality.GEN

Second, Polish TNPs are domains for the valuation of uninterpretable features.
DP-internal concord provides evidence:
(23) a. Jan zobaczy piekna

zielona
papuge.
[Polish]
Jan saw
beautiful.3SG.FEM.ACC green.3SG.FEM.ACC parrot.3SG.FEM.ACC
Jan saw a beautiful green parrot.

b. Piekna
zielona
papuga
green.3SG.FEM.NOM parrot.3SG.FEM.NOM
beautiful.3SG.FEM.NOM
przeleciaa
Janowi
nad
over
ew
Jan.DAT
A beautiful green parrot ew over Jans head.

gowa.
head

Third, demonstratives and numerals determine Spell-Out, as evidenced by the


following nominal ellipsis types:
(24) a. Ja wezme tego .
I
take
this.3SG.MASC.ACC
I will take this one.
b. Ja wezme tych
I
take
these.3PL.MASC.ACC
I will take these two.

[Polish]

dwch
two.3PL.MASC.ACC

And fourth, DP-internal inverse scope is also possible, which shows that the edge
of DP can be a target for QR. The inverse scope reading is the most natural
reading for the following example.
(25) Dwch senatorw z
kazdego miasta bedzie na tym zebraniu.
two
senators
from every
city
will.be at this meeting
Two senators from every city will be at the meeting.

Logically speaking, there are two conclusions we can draw from the
behavior of Polish TNPs. One is that Polish noun phrases are DPs and behave
accordingly (thus supporting the Universal DP Hypothesis), and the other
one is that in some languages NPs can be phases as well (thus supporting the
Parameterized DP Hypothesis). Bokovi (to appear) argues for the latter,
relativized approach to phasehood, in which the highest projection is a phase
(see also Bobaljik & Wurmbrands 2005 work on relativized domains). If in
a given language TNPs are NPs, then NP is going to be a phase; if TNPs are
DPs, then DP is going to be a phase; and if TNPs are KPs, then KP is going
to count as a phase, as shown schematically in (26ac). What is impossible is
the situation illustrated in (25d), in which TNPs are KPs but a DP counts as a
phase.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

175

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

Crosslinguistic variation

(26) a.

VP
V

b.
NP

VP
V

c.
DP

175

VP

d. * VP

V
NP

KP
K

V
DP

KP
K

NP

DP
D

NP

phases

Bokovis proposal is interesting in that it only indirectly attributes crosslinguistic variation in phasehood to lexical variation (e.g. the presence or absence
of a D projection in a language). It does, however, show that a different inventory
of categories might yield differences in phasehood. This is what distinguishes his
proposal from others considered in this section: the number of phases remains the
same, only their identity changes.
This brings us to the third option for variation in phasehood, which simply
attributes it to variation in parameter setting. This is what Abels (2003) proposes
in order to explain crosslinguistic variation with respect to preposition stranding.
For Abels, such variation is simply due to the different settings of the following
parameter:18
(27) Parameter 1: [+/] P is a phase head. (Abels 2003: 233)

A more general question that a proposal like Abels raises is whether such a
parameter is a plausible parameter on theoretical grounds. If the phasehood of P is
subject to crosslinguistic variation, we would expect the phasehood of other
phase heads to be subject to similar parametric variation. More generally then,
the question is whether the parameter in (28), which I will call the Phasehood
Parameter, is a plausible parameter. X in (28) ranges over the categories that we
have seen to be phase heads.
(28) [+/] X is a phase head.

(where X = C, v, D, P, Appl, Pr)

Of course, the answer to this question hinges on many other, more


general questions concerning parameters, such as what exactly parameters
are, what is the locus of parametric variation in the grammar, and how to best
state parameters. These are not questions to which I can do justice here; for very
18

Capitalizing on the same intuition, Bokovi offers a slightly different take on the difference
between P-stranding and non P-stranding languages. In particular, he attributes this difference to
the possibility that PPs in languages that allow P-stranding project more structure than PPs in
languages that disallow P-stranding.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

176

176

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

Variation in phasehood

relevant and illuminating discussion, I refer the reader to Biberauer et al.


(2010), Biberauer (2008) and the references therein. The common minimalist
assumption concerning parameters is that they reside in the lexicon as features
of individual functional heads. This assumption is sometimes referred to as the
BorerChomsky conjecture, which attributes crosslinguistic variation to the
differences in featural make-up of functional heads.19
Being a phase head, if it is a feature at all, is not a feature of the same kind
as other syntactic features we know: wh-features, case features, EPP features or features. So it seems that a parameter like (27) is not a parameter that can be stated
in a way that is compatible with this view of parametric variation. However, there
are views of phase heads that are more amenable to phasehood being subject to
parametric variation. If, however, all there is to being a phase head is the ability to
bear uninterpretable features (as proposed explicitly by Gallego 2010, for example), the parameter in (29a) could easily be restated as (29b).20, 21
(29) a. [+/] X is a phase head.
(where X = C, v, D, P, Appl)
b. [+/] X is the locus of uninterpretable features.
(where X = C, v, D, P, Appl)

However, allowing such a parameter into the grammar raises a number


of questions. For example, are all phases subject to similar crosslinguistic variation? More specically, are there any languages in which C is not a phase head or v
is not a phase head? This is ultimately an empirical question, but I take it to be a
telling fact that, to the best of my knowledge, we have not stumbled upon such
languages. Given the properties associated with the phase head C, it is hard to
imagine a language in which C is not a phase head. This would have to be a
language in which CPs are not propositional, a language that lacks sluicing, a
language in which the C-T complex does not value Nominative Case, or a language
in which successive cyclic movement does not proceed through [Spec,CP].
We have only scratched the surface of the issues concerning crosslinguistic variation in phasehood. There are many others to consider, such
as whether variation in phasehood is something that might change over
time. And if so, what would it mean for a given head to lose or acquire phasal
status?

19

20

21

The name BorerChomsky conjecture refers to Borers seminal work on parametric variation
(Borer 1984) and Chomskys endorsement of it, and the term itself is attributed to Baker (2008a).
To be fair, Baker himself has a different take on the nature of parameters, and argues explicitly in
favor of so-called macro-parameters, which cannot easily (if at all) be stated as features of
individual functional heads.
As we saw in the earlier chapters, for Gallego uninterpretable formal features are the key formal
criterion of phasehood.
Feature Inheritance thus muddies the picture somewhat, as (29b) can only refer to heads that can
inherently count as bearers of uninterpretable features (as opposed to heads that get to inherit them).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

177

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

Non-simultaneous phases

177

6.3 Non-simultaneous phases


In this section, we turn to the possibility that there might be a mismatch between
what counts as a phase with respect to phonological considerations and what counts
as a phase with respect to semantic considerations. This would mean that a given
constituent could be a PF-only phase, an LF-only phase, both a PF and LF phase or
neither a PF or LF phase. I alluded to these possibilities in Chapter 2, where we
looked at Multiple Spell-Out, as well as in Chapter 3, where we looked at phasehood diagnostics, distinguishing between PF and LF diagnostics. We also saw that
the same constituent can pass as a phase with respect to one set of diagnostics
but not with respect to others. This was, for example, Matushanskys (2005)
conclusion about the phase-theoretical status of DPs: she argued that they are PF
phases but not LF phases. All these possibilities are consistent with the general
architecture of the grammar in Phase Theory. In fact, the concept of Multiple SpellOut, which is at the core of Phase Theory, only raises the question of whether
Transfer to each interface could happen at different points in the derivation. And,
as we will see in this section, there are reasons to believe that it can. And, if fact,
quite a few researchers have either argued for such Non-Simultaneous Spell-Out
explicitly (see Cecchetto 2004, Felser 2004, Marui 2005, 2009, for example)
or assumed it implicitly. In what follows, I will use the term Transfer rather than
Spell-Out, and to avoid using the term Spell-Out to describe transfer to the semantic
interface.
The standard scenario we have been assuming throughout is for Transfer to
PF and LF to happen simultaneously, as shown in (30) for a simple clause with
two phase heads (C and v).22
(30) Simultaneous Transfer
CP
C

TP
DP

PF2, LF2

T
T

vP
v

ti

VP

v
V

22

PF1 LF1
DP

For the sake of clarity, I only mark the rst two cases of Transfer in the diagrams that follow.
Technically speaking, the edge of the CP phase gets transferred separately. PF1 stands for the rst
Transfer to PF, and LF1 for the rst Transfer to LF.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

178

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

178

Variation in phasehood

There are different ways to think of what a Non-Simultaneous Multiple


Transfer might be. One is to allow Multiple Transfer to apply only to one of the
two interfaces (with Single Transfer to the other interface), as illustrated in (31a)
and (31b), respectively. The cases we will look at in the rest of this section will
involve these two options.
(31) a. Multiple Transfer to PF, Single Transfer to LF

CP
C

TP
DP

T
T

PF2

LF1

VP

PF1

vP
v

ti

v
V

DP

b. Multiple Transfer to LF, Single Transfer to PF

CP
C

TP
DP

LF2

PF1

vP

ti

VP

v
V

LF1
DP

One could also imagine scenarios in which there are Multiple Transfers to
both PF and LF, but one is delayed with respect to the other. This might be the
case if the CP in (31a) or (31b) were embedded and Transfer to both interfaces
proceeded simultaneously once the embedded CP is complete.23

23

There is also another possibility, which I will not consider here: for Transfer to be totally
asynchronic.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

179

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

Non-simultaneous phases

179

Now that we have seen that Non-Simultaneous Multiple Transfer is conceptually plausible, we can turn to the question of how a grammar with it
compares to a grammar without it. More specically, we turn to the empirical
motivation for Non-Simultaneous Multiple Transfer.
What Non-Simultaneous Transfer is particularly well designed to handle is
a situation in which a given element is phonologically visible, so to speak,
in one position but semantically visible in another one. Marui argues that
Non-Simultaneous Transfer is what happens in cases of reconstruction (in
which a moved element is interpreted lower than it is pronounced) and covert
movement (in which a seemingly unmoved element is interpreted higher
than it is pronounced), illustrated in (32a) and (32b), respectively. In (32a),
we are interested in the non-specic reading of the indenite a Kenyan, which
can be paraphrased as It is likely that some Kenyan (or other) will win the
marathon. And in (32b), we are interested in the inverse scope reading, in
which the object every problem has wide scope over the subject some student
and we are not necessarily talking about one smart student. Both are ambiguous
and also allow interpretations in which the scope of the relevant elements
parallels their relative order.24
(32) a. A Kenyan is likely to win the marathon.
b. Some student solved every problem.

LIKELY
EVERY PROBLEM

>

>

A KENYAN

SOME STUDENT

Marui is careful about distinguishing cases like (32a), in which the entire
constituent reconstructs (total reconstruction cases), from cases in which only a
part of it does (partial reconstruction cases), and focusing on the former. The latter
is what happens with wh-movement, in which the operator part is interpreted in
its scopal position and the remainder reconstructs.
The early Transfer to LF (illustrated in (31b) above) gives rise to a situation
in which a moving element is interpreted earlier than it is pronounced.
This could be a general way to think about all cases of semantically vacuous
overt movement, of which (32a) above was one example. Another plausible
example comes from cases of scrambling which are (arguably) semantically
vacuous (see Bokovi & Takahashi 1998, Saito 2003, among many others).25
Consider the following contrast. (33a) is the unscrambled variant, (33b) shows
that the wh-pronoun can be scrambled out of the embedded CP; the scrambled
variant is nevertheless interpreted as an indirect question. Saito takes it to
mean that it has to undergo total reconstruction; if there were a trace (or copy)

24

25

Marui puts both of these cases in the more general context of attested mismatches between form
and meaning. He points towards idioms as another common example of a mismatch between
phonological and semantic units: they function as one unit semantically but multiple units
phonologically.
See, however, Bailyn (2001), Miyagawa (1997), for example, for a different take on scrambling.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

180

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

180

Variation in phasehood

left in the matrix clause position, the result would be a violation of the Proper
Binding Condition, the condition that requires traces to be bound.26
(33) a. John-ga

[CP Mary-ga dono hono-o


yonda ka] siritagatteiru. [Japanese]
which book-ACC read
Q
want.to.know
John-NOM Mary-NOM
John wants to know which book Mary read.

b. ?Dono hon-oi John-ga


[CP Mary-ga ti yonda ka] siritagatteiru.
what-ACC
John-NOM
Mary-NOM read
Q
want.to.know
John wants to know which book Mary read. (cf. Saito 2003: 484)

In a grammar with Multiple Non-Simultaneous Transfer, such cases of scrambling can be analyzed as involving Transfer to LF before Transfer to PF. In
(33b) the embedded vP phase containing the wh-pronoun nani-o what is
transferred to LF at a lower phase level.27 However, its phonological features
will still be accessible, since Transfer to PF has not occurred yet. This means
that the pronoun is going to be interpreted low no matter where it ends up
surfacing.
Reconstruction under A-movement of the kind illustrated in (32a) above is
different though. Sauerland & Elbourne (2002) analyze such movement as PF
movement, which, strictly speaking, would not involve reconstruction of any
type. We might be tempted to analyze such cases in a way parallel to vacuous
scrambling as also involving Transfer to LF before Transfer to PF. This is the
derivation Marui argues explicitly for, a derivation in which the indenite
subject (a Kenyan in (32a)) is transferred to LF before it is transferred to PF.
However, given that we are dealing with a raising construction, the only two
(non-DP) phases are the vP associated with the embedded verb phrase win the
marathon and the CP associated with the matrix clause, both circled in (34)
below. In (34), all three copies of the indenite subject a Kenyan are in the same
domain (the complement of the matrix C) and get transferred at the same stage.
This does not change even if verb phrases headed by verbs like seem or be likely
(or passive and unaccusative verb phrases in general) are phases; they are
thought to be weak phases; weak in that they do not trigger Transfer to the
interfaces.28

26

27

28

This is not to say that all cases of scrambling are semantically vacuous in this way. In the literature
on Japanese scrambling, it is standard to distinguish long-distance and short-distance scrambling,
and assume radical reconstruction (or some process akin to it) only for the long-distance cases.
The question is whether this necessarily means that the embedded phase has to be an LF phase but
not a PF phase, and whether there is any independent evidence for treating it as such.
This is not a problem for Marui, who treats non-nite TPs as LF phases but not PF phases. I do
not think this conclusion is generally warranted for raising TPs, and is incompatible with the
assumptions about phases defended here. Raising TPs are not complete in the requisite sense; they
are not capable of valuing Nominative case, for example.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

181

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

Non-simultaneous phases

(34)

181

CP
C

TP
T

DPuC[Nom]

a Kenyani [3sg] Tu [3sg],EPP vP


AP

v
likely

TP

DP

a Kenyani [3sg] Tu [3sg],EPP vP

DP
a Kenyani [3sg]

VP
win the marathon

The intuition is clear; either the copy below or above the predicate be likely
gets interpreted. Depending on which one it is, we either get the reconstructed
or the non-reconstructed interpretation. However, this seems to be more a case
of Transfer targeting different features differently (PF features versus LF
features) than Transfer happening at different points in the derivation. Thus,
the interpretation of the lower copy does not seem to have much to do with
Transfer to the two interfaces happening non-simultaneously, given the
assumption that phase heads determine the points of Transfer and the complement of a lower phase head is transferred to the interfaces when a higher
phase head is merged.29
Another illustration of Non-Simultaneous Transfer, which we alluded to
above, comes from the domain of Quantier Raising. The idea here is that QR
(and perhaps covert movement more generally) involves Transfer to PF before
Transfer to LF. In (32b), repeated below as (35a), there are two Transfer domains,
with copies of the quantied object every problem present in both. Given that
every problem is pronounced low but interpreted high, it is reasonable to assume

29

The issue of reconstruction under A-movement (or the lack thereof) is quite a thorny issue. It is only
allowed with certain elements (indenites contrast in this respect with universal quantiers, for
example). That is why the mechanism that is used to capture it is sometimes different from the
mechanism used to capture A-bar reconstructions. It has been given many different accounts:
quantier lowering by May (1977, 1985); covert insertion of an expletive there by Boeckx (2001),
PF movement by Sauerland & Elbourne (2002) (see Iatridou & Sichel 2011 for a recent proposal
teasing the different complicating factors apart).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

182

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

182

Variation in phasehood

that it the lowest copy is transferred to PF during the rst PF cycle. In the diagram
that follows I indicate quantication type with subscripts on the relevant DPs.30
(35) a. Some student solved every problem.

b.

CP
C

TP
DP

TP

DP

PF2

T
T

vP
LF1
DP

vP

DP

v
PF1

VP

v
V

DP

The concept of Non-Simultaneous Transfer we have focused on so far in this


section is conceptually related to the concept of Delayed Spell-Out, due to
Bachrach & Katzir (2009). For consistencys sake, I will refer to it here as
Delayed Transfer. Delayed Transfer, as the name implies, allows Transfer to
skip a phase. In cases of Non-Simultaneous Transfer we have seen above,
Transfer to one interface is delayed, but, in principle, delay could affect both
interfaces. This is what Bachrach & Katzir (2007, 2009) argue happens in a
construction known as Right Node Raising (RNR), an example of which is
given in (36).
(36) Leslie recommended and Terry watched a new documentary on Australian
parrots.

Bachrach & Katzir assume a multidominant structure for RNR, in which the RNR
element is literally shared between the two conjuncts, as shown in (37a).31
Furthermore, they argue that the italicized string a new documentary on
Australian parrots is not spelled out when (and where) we would expect it to
be spelled out, namely inside the embedded vP at the time when that embedded vP
is spelled out. Instead, it is spelled out during the next Spell-Out cycle, above the
coordination level.

30

31

Marui treats these cases slightly differently, deriving the effects of QR from DPs being PF phases
but not LF phases.
See Citko (2011a,b and the references therein) for a defense of such structure for RNR, and for a
more general discussion of multidominance in the grammar.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

183

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

Non-simultaneous phases

(37)

a.

183

CP
C

&P
&
and

TP
Terryi

TP
Lesliei

vP

T
T

vP

ti

ti

VP

VP

Transfer 1
recommended

watched DP
a new documentary on Australian parrots

b.

CP
&P

&
and

TP
T

Terryi
T

Transfer 2
TP
T

Lesliei
T

vP
ti

v
v

vP
ti

VP

recommended

v
v

VP
watched

DP

a new documentary on Australian parrots

For Bachrach & Katzir, Transfer can only affect completely dominated
constituents, which is what allows the shared element to escape early (or standard, perhaps more accurately) Transfer; in (37ab) it is not completely dominated by either VP.32 Such a multidominant structure for RNR (coupled with
Delayed Transfer) can explain why the shared element (often referred to as the
pivot in the literature on RNR) has to be right-peripheral; otherwise the result
would be a linearization contradiction, with the pivot both preceding the verb
watched and following it, in violation of the antisymmetry requirement on linear
order.33 It also captures (and reconciles) two seemingly irreconcilable properties

32
33

The rst node that completely dominates the shared DP is the &P node.
Since neither linearization of multiply dominated structures or constraints on RNR are our primary
focus here, I will refrain from digressing into the details and refer the reader to the literature on the

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C06.3D

184

184

[161184] 23.11.2013 11:05AM

Variation in phasehood

of RNR: the fact that it is impervious to islands (as noted by Wexler & Culicover
1980 and discussed in much later literature on RNR) and the fact that the pivot
can scope over material inside both conjuncts.34 These two properties come
together, somewhat paradoxically, in (38). The lack of an island violation implies
a non-movement analysis but the wide scope interpretation for the pivot implies a
movement analysis.35
(38) John knows [someone who speaks __ ], and Bill knows [someone who wants to
learn __], every Germanic language.
( > , > )
(Sabbagh 2007: 367)

On Bachrach & Katzirs proposal, the pivot is transferred only when it becomes
fully integrated into the structure (where full integration amounts to complete
dominance), which is when the two conjuncts are combined to form a coordinate
phrase. Only then will the pivot be fully dominated (by the &P node). It means
that it will only incur island violations from this point on (hence the grammaticality of (37)) and that it will be interpreted in this high position (hence wide
scope for the pivot).
Even though the concept of Delayed Transfer illustrated here is different from
the concept of Non-Simultaneous Transfer, the two are alike in that they constitute departures from the standard Multiple Transfer architecture. I take this
exibility to be a welcome consequence of Phase Theory, rather than a potential
issue for it, given the facts it can capture. In the next chapter, we turn to the
relationship between syntax and phonology on the one hand, and syntax and
semantics on the other hand, and we will look at this relationship from the
perspective of Phase Theory. We will examine the evidence in favor of phases
being (or determining) both phonological and semantic domains, focusing on the
following questions: (i) how do phases affect linearization, (ii) how do phases
affect prosodic structure?, and (iii) how do phases affect interpretation?

34

subject (see, for example, Citko (to appear) for a handbook-style overview of these (and related)
issues surrounding RNR and the references therein for the details of the specic accounts of RNR).
The contrast below between the a examples, involving run-of-the-mill wh-movement, and the b
examples, involving RNR, provides an illustration:
(i) a. *Whati did Leslie wonder [WH-ISLAND when Terry saw ti]?
b. Leslie asked [WH-ISLAND when John directed ti] and Terry asked [WH-ISLAND when Bill saw ti ] a new
documentary on Australian parrotsi.
(ii) a. *What does Leslie know [COMPLEX DH-ISLAND someone who directed ti]?
b. Leslie knows [COMPLEX DP-ISLAND someone who directed ti] and Terry knows [COMPLEX DP-ISLAND someone who
saw ti] a new documentary on Australian parrots.

35

Covert movement is not an option here since it would have to be covert Across-the-Board (ATB)
movement of the pivot, and covert ATB movement is generally disallowed (see Bokovi & Franks
2000 and Citko 2000, 2005, among others, for data and analysis).

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

185

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

7
Phases and the interfaces

7.1 Phases and PF


The focus of this section is on the relationship between phases (and/or Spell-Out
domains) and PF. Given that phase heads determine Transfer (in that domains of
phase heads get transferred to the two interfaces, sometimes non-simultaneously,
as we saw in the previous section), it is not unreasonable to assume that phases
will play a role in PF processes. In fact, many researchers point out that the theory
of the syntaxphonology mapping in which phases or Spell-Out domains constitute phonological domains is the null hypothesis (see, among others, Adger
2007, Dobashi 2003, Ishihara 2003, 2007, Kahnemuyipour 2003, 2004, 2005,
Kratzer & Selkirk 2007, Pak 2008, Samuels 2011, Scheer 2012). For the two
core phases CPs and vPs, the relevant phonological units on the null hypothesis
would be TPs and VPs.
The very idea that there is a principled mapping between syntactic domains
and phonological domains is by no means novel (or original) to Phase Theory,
and I cannot do justice here to the vast literature on the subject of the syntax
phonology interface; I refer the interested reader to Elordieta (2008) and the
references therein for a thorough overview of this interface instead.
Perhaps the most relevant PF fact about language is linear order. If linearization is not part of Narrow Syntax (as made explicit by Kaynes 1994 Linear
Correspondence Axiom), and if linear order is established at Spell-Out (as seems
reasonable given what Spell-Out is), and if Spell-Out happens phase by phase,
linearization will happen phase by phase, too. This is what the title of Fox &
Pesetskys (2005) Cyclic Linearization paper, the gist of which I give below,
refers to. The claim that linear order is established at Spell-Out, in a cyclic
fashion, as expected in a Multiple Spell-Out architecture, is only one part of
their proposal. The other part is the proposal, which they refer to as Order
Preservation, that the ordering established within one Spell-Out domain cannot
be changed in subsequent Spell-Out domains. Future Spell-Out domains can add
information but not delete or change previously established information (see
Fox & Pesetsky 2005: 6). Fox & Pesetsky consider the following scenario to

185

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

186

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

186

Phases and the interfaces

illustrate how Order Preservation works. In (1) below, there is a single Spell-Out
domain (D1) consisting of three elements, X, Yand Z. The ordering statements for
this domain D1 are given in (1b).
(1) a.
X
Y
Z

b. Ordering statements within D1: X >Y, Y > Z

If another element is merged outside D1, it will be linearized in the next


domain (D2).
(2) Merge
D2

D1
X
Y
Z

Given the Order Preservation Principle, a number of things could happen next;
crucially, however, the relative order of elements established within D1 cannot
change.1 This means that X, being at the edge of D1, can freely move out of D1.
After movement, it will still precede all the elements within D1.
(3) a. Move X

D2
Xi

D1

ti
Y

b. Ordering within D1: X>Y, Y>Z


c. Ordering within D2: X > , > D1

See, however, Richards (2007) for a proposal that phase-internal movements are order preserving
but transphasal movements are not.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

187

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

Phases and PF

187

The ordering created at the next Spell-Out domain (D2) does not change the
ordering previously established, it merely adds new orderings to the ones established at D1. This is how Fox & Pesetsky derive the fact that movement from a
given domain has to proceed through the edge of that domain. If, on the other
hand, movement from D1 takes place from a non-left-edge position, as in (4a), the
new linearization statements are going to contradict the previously established
ones. Here both precedes Y (by virtue of preceding D1, which includes Y) and
follows Y (due to Y having moved out of D1).
(4) a. Move X

D2
Y1

D1

X
ti

b. Ordering within D1: X>Y, Y>Z


c. Ordering within D2: Y > , > D1 >Y

However, if it is essentially PF that rules it out, as Fox & Pesetsky point out, we
expect to nd ways to x it. And this is indeed what happens. If both X and Y
move but their relative order is preserved, the new linearization statements are not
going to contradict the previously established ones.2
(5) a. Move X and Y

D2
Xj
Yi

D1

tj
ti

b. Ordering within D1: X>Y, Y>Z


c. Ordering within D2: X > Y, Y > , > D1

This is how Fox & Pesetsky derive Holmbergs Generalization, illustrated by the
contrast in (6). This contrast shows that the object can undergo object shift only if
the verb has shifted even further and the order of the two is preserved:

Ellipsis is another way to rescue a structure in which a non-nal element moves out of a domain D.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

188

[185204] 23.11.2013 12:19PM

188

Phases and the interfaces

(6) a. [CP

Jag kysstej hennei inte [VP tj ti].


[Swedish]
I
kissed her
not
jag hennei inte [VP kysste ti].
b. *[CP. . . att
...
that I
her
not
Kissed (cf. Fox & Pesetsky 2005: 17)

In the grammatical (6a), this is what happens. The ordering established at the CP
level does not contradict the ordering established at the VP level:
(7) a. Ordering within VP: KISSED > HER
b. Ordering within CP: I > KISSED, KISSED > HER, HER > NOT, N O T >

VP

However, in the ungrammatical (7b), the ordering established at the CP level does
contradict the ordering established at the VP level: henne precedes kysste at the
CP level but follows it at the VP level.
(8) a. Ordering within VP: K I S S E D > H E R
b. Ordering within CP: THAT > I, I > H E R ,

HER

> NOT,

NOT

> VP H E R >

KISSED

Fox & Pesetskys Cyclic Linearization proposal establishes a direct link between
Spell-Out domains and linearization domains. It is not clear, however, what in their
system prevents the object from moving to the edge of VP rst, in which case it
could continue to move to the next Spell-Out domain with the verb remaining within
VP without violating the Order Preservation Principle. The relationship between
Fox & Pesetskys Spell-Out domains and phases (or complements of phase heads) is
also not quite transparent. Given that vP is a phase, the Spell-Out domain should be a
VP, which is consistent with their proposal. However, on standard assumptions
about phases and successive cyclic movement, movement takes place through the
edge of a phase (vP) not through the edge of the Spell-Out domain (VP).
In the rest of this chapter, I will be concerned with the relationship between
phases (or Spell-Out domains) and phonological domains, and the issue of
whether phases correspond to (or help determine) phonological domains. If so,
what are these phonologically relevant domains, and what phonological processes apply to them?
The commonly assumed prosodic units are listed in (9) (see Nespor & Vogel
1995: 11). The question is which of them correspond to Spell-Out domains. Since
phases correspond to larger chunks of structure, the most likely culprits are
higher-level units such as intonational phrases.
(9) a. phonological utterance
b. intonational phrase
c. clitic group
d. phonological word
d. foot
e. syllable
3

This follows from transitivity. Given that henne precedes inte and inte precedes VP (and kysste is
included within VP), henne will end up having to precede kysste.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

189

[185204] 23.11.2013 12:19PM

Phases and PF

189

We will focus below on sentential stress (also referred to as nuclear stress), which
is a good example of a phonological process that applies to larger units and which
has been shown to be sensitive to syntactic domains. The more specic questions
about nuclear stress we will ask are:
(10) a. Do phases play a role in determining domains for nuclear stress assignment?
b. If so, does movement across phasal domains affect nuclear stress?
c. How can we account for the crosslinguistic variation (or the lack thereof) with
respect to nuclear stress?

To ground the discussion empirically, let us start with some observations


about the nature of nuclear stress and a brief summary of previous (not
necessarily phase-based) accounts. Earlier accounts, such as Chomsky &
Halles (1968), or Halle & Vergnauds (1987), often refer to directionality of
stress assignement. The rule governing the distribution of sentential stress (the
so-called Nuclear Stress Rule (NSR)) operates cyclically and takes the
element bearing the rightmost word-level stress in a given domain to project
its stress to the next level. Applied to a concrete example, the NSR yields the
following:
(11) (
(*
)
(*
)
Parrots

* )
(
* )
(* ) ( * )
like NUTS

Cinque (1993) points out both conceptual and empirical problems with
Halle & Vergnauds formulation and suggests the revision given in (12). The
crucial innovation in his proposal lies in the fact that it makes no reference
whatsoever to the directionality of stress assignment (right versus left).
(12) a. Interpret boundaries of syntactic constituents as metrical boundaries.
b. Locate the heads of line N constituents on line N + 1.
c. Each rule applies to a maximal string containing no internal boundaries.
d. An asterisk on line N must correspond to an asterisk on line N 1.
(Cinque 1993: 244)

In most general terms, nuclear stress is sensitive to the level of embedding


rather than directionality. This explains, for example, why there is not as
much crosslinguistic variation with respect to sentential stress as there is with
respect to word stress. It also explains why there is not as much crosslinguistic
variation with respect to sentential stress as there is with respect to word
order (as noted by Cinque 1993, Kahnemuyipour 2004 and the references
therein). To illustrate, in simple transitive sentences, the direct object is the

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

190

[185204] 23.11.2013 12:19PM

190

Phases and the interfaces

element that bears nuclear stress irrespective of the word order type involved
(SVO, SOV or VSO):4
(13) a. John read a BOOK.
b. Ali
KETAAB
ye
Ali
a
book
Ali bought a book.

SVO
[Persian]

xarid.
bought

c. Chuala
Seonag
CALUM.
heard
Seonag
Calum
Seonag heard Calum (Kahnemuyipour 2004: 12)

SOV
[Scottish Gaelic]

Other factors, however, do play a role. For example, as often noted, unaccusative
and unergative verbs behave differently: with unergative verbs, stress can fall
either on the verb or on the subject (see Kahnemuyipour 2004, Selkirk 1995,
Zubizaretta & Vergnaud 2005 and the references therein). With unaccusative
verbs, on the other hand, only the subject can bear nuclear stress:
(14) a. The PARROT is screeching.
b. The parrot is SCREECHING.
(15) a. The PARROT disappeared.
b. *The parrot DISAPPEARED.

Not surprisingly, passives pattern with unaccusatives in this respect.


(16) My BIKE was stolen. (Legate 2003: 513)

NSR is a cyclic rule: stress is assigned cyclically (domain by domain) and the
highest stress within a given domain projects to the next level. Furthermore, the
contrast between the a and be examples in (1719), due to Bresnan (1971), who
attributes the rst pair to Newman (1946), suggests that the stress assigned within
one domain can sometimes survive as the highest stress if the stressed element
moves out of that domain. All the a examples involve noun complement clauses
(thus no movement from the embedded CP), whereas all b examples involve
relative clauses (which on the Head Promotion Account means that the head
moves from within the relative CP). Interestingly, the relative clause head keeps
its stress.5

This is not to say that there is no crosslinguistic variation whatsoever. Zubizarreta (1998), for
example, in order to account for the differences between Romance and Germanic languages, posits
the existence of two types of nuclear stress rules, one sensitive to selection (which she dubs
selectional nuclear stress rule) and the other one sensitive to c-command. They might interact
differently in different languages (or one of them might be absent altogether in a given language),
which is what gives rise to crosslinguistic variation.
Legate reinterprets Bresnans ndings in phase-theoretical ways and takes this to mean that movement across phases does not affect nuclear stress. Kahnemuyipour takes issue with this assertation
based on the fact that the moved wh-phrase does not keep its stress.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

191

[185204] 23.11.2013 12:24PM

Phases and PF

191

(17) a. George has plans to LEAVE.


b. George has PLANS to leave.
(18) a. Helen left directions for George to FOLLOW.
b. Helen left DIRECTIONS for George to follow.
(19) a. Mary liked the proposal that George LEAVE.
b. Mary liked the PROPOSAL that George left. (Bresnan 1971: 2589)

With this as background, let us turn to the question of how Nuclear Stress Rule
might be recast in phase-theoretical terms. A natural starting point is the hypothesis, stated in various forms in (20ad), that the Spell-Out domain of the phase is
the domain for prosodic rules like the Nuclear Stress Rule.
(20) a. The spellout domain of a phase is the prosodic domain for phrase stress.
(Kratzer & Selkirk 2007: 104)
b. On the construction of each phase, the complement of the phasal head is
Spelled Out, so it is this category that undergoes phonological rules.
(Adger 2007: 247)
c. Phonological rules apply directly to the material that is spelled out at
eachphase. (Pak 2008: 10)
d. Spell-Out domains are mapped onto prosody as MaPs. (Ishihara 2007: 144)

However, even with these proposals about the mapping between Spell-Out
domains and prosodic domains, there is still the question of how exactly NSR
applies within these domains. There are two logical possibilities. One is that
the lowest (e.g. the most deeply embedded) element within the Spell-Out
domain is prosodically the most prominent one, and the other one is that it is
the highest element within a given domain that is prosodically the most
prominent one. Interestingly, both of them have been defended in the literature,
not for different languages. This is not necessarily a contradiction. However,
depending on which route we take, we will require a different set of background assumptions.
Adger (2007) provides a very straightforward implementation of the Cinquestyle Nuclear Stress Rule in a phase-based system.6 Let us look at concrete
examples, parallel to Adgers original (parrot-free) examples.
(21) The parrot ate a nut.

Adgers implementation of it, however, does avoid some of the problems Cinque faces. To illustrate,
complex noun phrases of the following sort, as pointed out by Adger, are problematic for Cinque.
(i) [the [man [from [Philadelphia]]]]s hat. (Cinque 1993: 268, crediting Richard Kayne)

Since speciers are at the edge, they escape Spell-Out. Consequently, the noun hat can be the most
prominent element in spite of the fact that it is not the most deeply embedded constituent in this noun
phrase.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

192

[185204] 23.11.2013 12:24PM

192

Phases and the interfaces

The steps in the derivation that are relevant for determining nuclear stress
(namely Spell-Out domains) are given below. (22a) shows that the complement
of the lowest phase head (D) is spelled out when the next phase head (v in this
case) is merged.
(22)

vP
VP

v
V
ate

DP
D
a

NP
nut

At this stage, the lexical stress on the noun nut projects to the next level, as
shown in (23). Similar considerations apply to the subject the parrot. If
Spell-Out domain is the domain for stress assignment, and NSR amounts to
projecting the highest stress within the Spell-Out domain. This is actually a
departure from Adgers proposal; for him NSR applies to entire phases, and
phase edges are not included in the calculation of stress due to extrametricality.
Here, NSR applies to Spell-Out domains, which eliminates the need for
extrametricality.
(23) Spell-Out NP, apply NSR to NP
*
*
nut]

[NP

*
*
[NP parrot]

The next Spell-Out occurs when C (the next phase head up) is merged. At this
point the complement of VP, being the complement of v, is spelled out.
(24) a.

CP
C

TP
DPi

the parrot T

vP
v

ti

VP

v
V
ate

DP
D
a

NP
nut

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

193

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

Phases and PF

193

b. Spell-Out VP, Project highest stress to the next level

[VP

*
*
*
a nut]

*
ate

In the last Spell Out-cycle, the TP spelled out, and the stress on the noun nut, still
being the highest one, is projected to the next level. This correctly derives the
placement of nuclear stress on the noun nut in The parrot ate the nut.
(25)

a.

CP
C

TP
DPi

the parrot T

vP
ti

v
VP

v
V
ate

DP
D
a

NP
nut

b.

[TP

*
*
The parrot

*
ate

*
*
*
*
nut]

This algorithm can also account for the contrast between unergatives and unaccusatives. We have seen above that unaccusatives differ from unergatives in that
they only allow stress on the subject (recall the contrast between (15) and (16)
above).7 On the assumption that unaccusative vPs are not strong phases in that
they do not trigger Spell-Out, there are two Spell-Out domains, the complement
of D and the complement of C.

Crucially, Adger assumes that the unaccusative v does not trigger Spell-Out. If it did, the verb would
be the most stressed element in this domain.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

194

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

194

Phases and the interfaces

(26)

CP
C

TP
DPi

the parrot T

vP
v

VP

V
disappeared

ti

In the rst domain the stress on parrot, being the only stress (the determiner the,
being functional, is not stressed), is the one that projects to the next level, as
shown in (27a). In the second domain, the stress on parrot is still the one that
projects to the next level, being the highest stress in this Spell-Out domain, as
shown in (27b)).8
(27) a. Spell Out NP, Project stress on parrot
*
*
[NP parrot]

b. Spell Out TP, Project stress on parrot


*
*
*
[TP the parrot

*
dissappeared]

Examples involving unergatives are different, since we are dealing with


an extra Spell-Out domain, the complement of v. This means that stress on
both the subject and the predicate can project up to the next level (since they
are in distinct domains). As a result, they end up equally stressed at the
next level. This does not mean that they end up equally stressed at the
sentential level. Instead, the indeterminacy means that either can project to
the sentential level, which is how Adger derives the fact that either the subject
or the predicate can be stressed.

Legates view is different. She assumes there is a phase boundary here, and assumes that in those
cases it preserves the stress it was assigned at an earlier cycle. The reason parrot in (i) is stressed is
thus similar to the reason proposal is stressed in (ii).
(i) The PARROT disappeared.
(ii) I liked the PROPOSAL that George left.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

195

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

Phases and PF

(28) a.

195

CP
C

TP
T

DPi
D
the

NP T
parrot

vP
ti

v
v

VP
screeched

b.

*
*
*
[TP the parrot

*
*
screeched]

*
*
[TP the parrot

*
*
*
screeched]

c.

Adgers phase-based theory of nuclear stress is quite different from


Kahnemuyipours (2003, 2004, 2005) one, which also crucially relies on phases,
but which takes the elements at the edge of the Spell-Out domain to receive
highest stress. Kahnemuyipours Sentential Stress Rule is given in (29).
(29) Sentential Stress Rule
Sentential stress is assigned at the phase to the highest element (i.e. the
phonological border) of the spelled out constituent or the SPELLEE.
(Kahnemuyipour 2004: 88)

At rst glance, this seems to make wrong predictions for a language like English:
within the Spell-Out domain of a transitive v, a direct object is not the highest
element. However, it becomes one if the verb moves out of VP (or the object
moves to some higher position within this Spell-Out domain). In verb-nal
languages (of which Kahnemuyipour 2004 focuses on Persian and German),
stress falls on the direct object in simple transitive clauses, just as in English.
Kahnemuyipour accounts for it as follows; he assumes the existence of a low
aspectual projection, sandwiched between vP and VP (see MacDonald 2006,
Travis 2010 and the references therein for a justication of such a projection). He
furthermore assumes that the direct object moves to the specier of this projection, even in a language with no object shift like English. This means that the
Spell-Out domain (SPELLEE in his terms) of the phase head v is this low
aspectual projection. Thus, at the point in the derivation illustrated in (30)

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

196

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

196

Phases and the interfaces

(namely when C is merged), the complement of the lower phase head, in this case
an AspP is spelled out:
(30)

CP
TP

Subjectj

vP
tj

v
AspP

OBJECTi

Asp
Spell-Out Domain
VP

Asp
V

ti

Even though Kahnemuyipour (2004) and Adger (2007) agree that phases
are relevant to the determination of nuclear stress, we saw that they differ in the
details of implementation. For Adger, it is the element with the highest level of
stress that gets its stress augmented by one stress mark. For Kahnemuyipour,
it is structurally the highest element that does. They also differ in how they
handle the difference between sentences with passive/unaccusative verbs and
unergative ones. We have seen above how this difference can be derived in
Adgers system. For Kahnemuyipour (2004), this difference is tied to the
assumption that unaccusative vPs are not (strong) phases in that they do not
trigger Spell-Out. The only phase is the CP phase, and, consequently, the
subject being the highest element in the Spell-Out domain of C is the element
that bears nuclear stress.
Kahnemuyipours system gives rise to two straightforward predictions. First,
if the highest element moves out of what would otherwise become its Spell-Out
domain, it should lose nuclear stress. Specic objects in Persian are a case in
point; the contrast between (31a) and (31b) shows that specic objects differ from
their non-specic counterparts in that they do not receive nuclear stress.
(31) a. Ali
QAZAA
Ali
food
Ali ate food.
b. Ali
Ali

qazaa-ro
food-ACC

xord.
ate

[Persian]

XORD.

ate (cf. Kahnemuyipour 2004: 96)

Kahnemuyipour provides independent evidence that specic objects move to a


higher position. In (32a), the object is the highest element in the Spell-Out
domain of v, whereas in (32b) the verb is.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

197

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

Phases and PF

197

(32)
TP

a.

Alij

TP

b.

Alij

T
T

T
T

vP
tj

qazaa-roi

v
v

vP

QAZAA

tj

AspP
Asp

Asp

VP
xord

v
v

AspP
Asp

tj
ti

Asp

VP
XORD

ti

Second, if some (extra) element is merged higher than the non-specic direct
object (which would otherwise be the highest element inside the Spell-Out
domain, that element should bear nuclear stress. For example, if an adverb is
merged inside the Spell-Out domain, it will bear nuclear stress.
So far, we have focused in this section mostly on the Nuclear Stress Rule, and
mostly on how it works in English. However, phases and Spell-Out domains have
been implicated in a number of other phonological phenomena in a number of
other languages. Let me thus conclude this section with a couple of examples.
Paks (2008) analysis of High Tone Anticipation (HTA) in Luganda makes
crucial use of phases. HTA, illustrated in (33ab) below, is a kind a spreading in
which high tone spreads leftward across a given domain, which Pak argues is the
Spell-Out domain of a phase head. The verb and the material following it are
treated as a single domain, whereas preverbal elements belong to a separate
domain. Pak argues that preverbal elements are in the specier of C, thus by
hypothesis outside the Spell-Out domain of C.
(33) a. omulenzi a-gul-ir-a
Mukasa
kw.
1.boy
SBJ1-buy-APPL-IND
1.Mukasa 1A.coffee
The boy is buying Mukasa some coffee.
b. (mlnz) (-gl-r-
Muks
kw.
1.boy
SBJ1-buy-APPL-IND
1.Mukasa 1A.coffee
The boy is buying Mukasa some coffee. (Pak 2008: 15)

[Luganda]

McGinnis (2001) , building on Seidl (2000), shows that in Bantu languages,


high and low applicatives have different prosodic structures. In high applicatives,
the two objects belong to the same phonological domain, whereas in low applicatives, they belong to two different domains. The boundaries of phonological
domains can be diagnosed by processes like Penultimate Vowel Lengthening
(PVL) or Vowel Length Shift (VLS); both apply at the right edge of a phonological domain. What is interesting is that what counts as the right edge is
different in low and high applicatives. In (34a), which is a low applicative, the

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

198

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

198

Phases and the interfaces

two objects are in the same Spell-Out domain, whereas in (34b), which is a high
applicative, the direct object and the indirect object are in two different domains.
This follows if the Spell-Out domain of the high applicative phase head is a VP
containing the direct object but not the indirect object, which is part of the next
domain.
(34) a. [Tu-k-i-tum-ir-
omkali valin:nde.]
we-PST-T-send-APPL-FV woman
Valinande
We have just sent Valinande to the woman.
b. [Ni-mw-ndik-il-ile nu:ru:] [xti.]
SP-OP-write-APPL-FV
Nuru
letter
I wrote Nuru a letter. (McGinnis 2001: 23)

[Kinande]

[Chi-Mwhi:ni:]

Ishihara (2003, 2007) shows that in Japanese, Spell-Out domains are mapped
onto Major Phrases and that scope in Japanese cannot extend beyond Major
Phrases. The empirical support comes from the contrast, due to Miyagawa
(2003), illustrated in (35ab), showing that a universal quantier unambiguously
scopes over negation in SOV word order, but can get either wide or narrow scope
with respect to negation in an OVS word order type.
(35) a. zenin-ga sono tesuto-o
all-NOM
that test-ACC
All did not take that test.

uke-nakat-ta.
take-NEG-PST

(SOV)
*NOT>>ALL,

ALL>>NOT

b. sono tesuto-oi zenin-ga ti uke-nakat-ta.


(OSV)
that test-ACC
all-NOM
take-NEG-PST
That test, all didnt take.
NOT >> ALL, (ALL>>NOT)
(Ishihara 2007: 139, citing Miyagawa 2003: 1834)

In (37a), the subject and negation are not in the same Major Phrase, as schematized in (36):
(36) [TP ALLi

[vP ti THAT TEST NOT TOOK] ]

MaP

(SOV)

MaP

The scrambled example (36b), on the other hand, is structurally ambiguous,


and depending on the structure assigned to it, the subject and negation are in the
same Major Phrase, as in (37a), which yields the reading in which negation has
scope over the subject, or the subject and negation are in distinct domains, as
shown in (37b), which yields a reading in which the subject has scope over
negation.
(37) a. [TP THAT TESTi
MaP

[vP

NOT TOOK] ]

ALL ti

MaP

(OSV)

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

199

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

Phases and LF

b. [ THAT TEST
CP
i
MaP

[TP ALLj [vP tj ti NOT TOOK] ] ]


MaP

199

(OSV)

MaP

This concludes our discussion of the role phases play in determining phonological domains. The question we focused on is whether phonological cycles
correspond to syntactic cycles, and more importantly, given the focus of this
book, whether phases or complements of phase heads (being the Spell-Out
domains) either are the relevant phonological units or map onto the phonological
relevant units.We saw that phases and Spell-Out domains (as determined by
phase heads) help us understand PF phenomena such as linear order preservation
effects or nuclear stress assignment. We also saw that phases play a role in
determining phonological processes such as Vowel Lengthening or High Tone
Anticipation in Bantu, and that Major Phrases as determined by phases play a role
in constraining scope in Japanese. In the next (nal) section of this book, we ask
similar questions about the mapping between syntax and semantics, and the role
phases might play in that mapping.

7.2 Phases and LF


This section focuses on the question of whether phases (or complements of phase
heads) correspond to semantically relevant units, and if so, what these semantically
relevant units might be. We have seen throughout this book that semantic completeness is a commonly assumed LF phasehood diagnostic. Semantic completeness in this context refers to phases being propositional and/or complete in some
other relevant sense, for example, complete with respect to their argument structure. However, we have also seen that there are issues with both of these as
diagnostics; issues that have led researchers to propose alternative denitions of
phases giving rise to possibly different categories counting as phases. For example,
Den Dikken (2007) denes phases as subjectpredicate structures, Bokovi (to
appear) takes each phase to be the top node in an extended projection of each
lexical category, and Epstein & Seely (2002, 2006), Mller (2004, 2011) take all
phrases to be phases. While these approaches avoid the problems associated with
limiting phasehood to propositional elements, they do end up with a very different
view of what phases are. For example, for Den Dikken CPs are phases only under
certain circumstances, and for Bokovi AdjPs can be phases.
Given the ontology of semantic types where the types are t (truth value), e
(entity) (and perhaps s (intension or world)) and various combinations thereof,
the types for the categories that we have assumed to be phases are quite diverse.
Furthermore, the lack of clear distinctions between the semantic types of the
phrases listed in (38a), which are taken to be phases, and the ones in (48b), which
are not taken to be phases, shows that semantic types are not a reliable diagnostic
distinguishing phases from non-phases.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

200

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

200

Phases and the interfaces

(38) a. Phases and semantic types


Syntactic category

Semantic type

Determiner Phrase (DP)

e (proper names)
<<e,t>,t> (quantied noun phrases)
t
<<s,t>, t> (questions)
t (declaratives)
<e,t> (relative clauses)
t
<e,t>

verb Phrase (vP)


Complementizer Phrase (CP)

Predication Phrase (PrP)


Prepositional Phrase (PP)
b. Non-phases and semantic types
Syntactic category

Semantic type

Noun Phrase (NP)


Verb Phrase (VP)
Tense Phrase (TP)
Adjective Phrase (AdjP)
Adverb Phrase (AdvP)

<e,t>
<e,t>
t
<e,t>
<e,t>

Thus, a more fruitful line of inquiry into the role of phases in the syntax
semantics interface might come from the question of what semantically relevant
domains phases might correspond to. For reasons that are similar to the reasons
we discussed in the last section (which dealt with phases and PF), given how
Phase Theory and Multiple Spell-Out work, it may well be the case that it is not
phases per se that are the relevant domains, but, rather, complements of phase
heads.
Interestingly, there is an important (and independently motivated) semantic
distinction that has been argued to correlate with the boundary between vP and
CP phases. It is the distinction between the nuclear scope (the domain of
existential closure) and the restrictive clause in a tripartite quanticational structure, as proposed explicitly by Biskup (2009a) (see, however, Butler 2005,
Carnie & Barss 2006 for different implementations of the same general idea).9
This is Diesings (1992) Mapping Hypothesis, stated in (39) in phase-theoretical
terms, and illustrated in (40) in arboreal terms.

Carnie and Barsss approach to phases is slightly different, though, from the approach taken here.
They argue for a relativized approach to phases, in which each phase has a predicative element, a
single argument and a temporal operator.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

201

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

Phases and LF

201

(39) The Mapping Hypothesis10


a. Material from vP phase maps into nuclear scope.
b. Material from CP phase maps into a restrictive clause.
(40)
CP
C

Restrictive Clause
TP

DPSUBJ
T

T
vP
Nuclear Scope

DPSUBJ v
VP

v
V

DPOBJ

What is important is that the two subject positions (the thematic vP-internal
position and the EPP-related [Spec,TP] position) end up in different domains.
Diesing shows how it can explain ambiguity of bare plural subjects in sentences
of the following sort:
(41) a. Parrots are loud.
b. Parrots are intelligent.

With a stage-level predicate (such as be loud, available, present), the sentence is


ambiguous between a generic reading, on which being loud is a general property
associated with parrothood, and an existential reading, on which parrots may be
loud at a specic time (for example, before they roost for the night). However,
with an individual-level predicate (such as be intelligent, green, have yellow
beaks), the only available reading is the generic one. Diesing accounts for it by
proposing that generic bare plural subjects are interpreted in [Spec,TP], whereas
existential ones are interpreted in [Spec,vP], as shown in (42ab).11

10

Diesings original formulation, given in (i), does not make reference to phases (but to VPs and IPs
instead). This, of course, is not surprising, since her formulation predates Phase Theory by a
decade.
(i) Material VP is mapped into the nuclear scope.
(ii) Material from IP is mapped into a restrictive clause. (Diesing 1992: 10)

11

To be consistent with the analysis of small clauses assumed in this book (see the discussion in
Section 5.1), I use PrPs instead of vPs here. This does not impact upon the Mapping Hypothesis in
any way: the higher (CP) phase is the restrictive clause and the lower (PrP) phase is the nuclear
scope. In fact, this ambiguity could be seen as another argument in favor of treating PrP as phases.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

202

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

202

Phases and the interfaces

(42) a. Existential reading


CP
Restrictive Clause
C

TP

parrots

T
T

PrP
parrots

Nuclear Scope

Pr
Pr

AdjP
loud

b. Generic reading
CP
C

TP

Restrictive Clause
T

parrots
T

PrP
parrots Pr
Pr

Nuclear Scope

AdjP
intelligent

For Diesing, the position of the subject on the generic interpretation is due to
Quantier Lowering. Given the somewhat unclear current status of Quantier
Lowering, I take it to be due to the option of interpreting the lower versus the higher
copy. There is still the question of what disallows the lower interpretation with
individual-level predicates. For Diesing, this is due to the fact that these are in fact
control clauses and there is simply no subject in the PrP- (or vP-)internal position.
Similar considerations apply to objects. Diesing shows that indenite objects
are in principle ambiguous between specic (or denite interpretations) and
existential interpretations. Biskup (2009a), following Diesings insights, derives
this ambiguity from the fact that they can be interpreted either inside the domain
of existential closure (within the vP phase) or outside it (within the CP phase). In
languages like German (i.e. languages with overt scrambling), the two interpretations can be disambiguated by scrambling. In (43a), the object remains within
the vP (the domain of existential closure) and is interpreted existentially. In (43b),
on the other hand, the object has moved out of the domain of existential closure
(as evidenced by its position relative to the manner adverb immer always),
which makes the existential interpretation no longer available.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

203

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

Phases and LF

(43) a. da Otto immer Bcher ber


Wombats
that Otto always books about wombats
that Otto always reads books about wombats

203

liest
reads.

[German]

b. da Otto Bcher ber


Wombats immer liest
that Otto books about wombats always reads
that Otto always reads books about wombats (Diesing 1992: 1078)

Biskup (2009a) goes a step further, and, in addition to making the explicit
proposal that Diesings Clause Partitioning corresponds to the split between the
CP and the vP phase, also argues that the boundary between these two phases
corresponds to the information-structure distinction between topic (old information) and focus (new information), or, to use his terms, background information
and informational focus. Thus, vP-internal elements are interpreted as new
information (informational focus), whereas vP-external elements (which for
subjects implies movement to [Spec,TP], and for objects scrambling above vP)
as old information (background, topic). This is illustrated by the contrast in (44a
b). In (44a), the subject Maria, being vP-internal, is interpreted as new information. This sentence would be an appropriate response to the question Who
bought a new car? However, in (44b), being vP-external, it is interpreted as
background information. This would be a felicitous response to the question
What did Maria buy?
(44) a. Nowy samochd kupia Maria.
new
car
bought Maria
Maria bought this new car.
b. Maria kupia nowy samochd.
Maria bought new car
Maria bought a new car.

[Polish]

The structures of the two are given in (45ab), with insignicant details omitted
and/or simplied.
(45) a. Structure of (44a)
CP
C

Old Information (Topic)

TP

a new car

bought

vP

Maria

New Information (Focus)

v
v

VP
bought a new car

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C07.3D

204

[185204] 23.11.2013 10:57AM

204

Phases and the interfaces

b. Structure of (44b)
CP
C
Maria

TP

Old Information (Topic)


T

bought

vP
v

Maria
v

New Information (Focus)


VP

bought a new car

Considerations of this sort show that the boundary between vP and CP phases is
relevant not only to syntax, semantics and phonology, but also to information
structure.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C08.3D

205

[205206] 23.11.2013 10:53AM

8
Summary

In lieu of a conclusion, let me briey summarize each chapter, highlighting its


core ideas. The rst chapter served mostly as background, providing the
rationale for writing a book about phases, as well as an introduction to those
aspects of the minimalist program that are relevant to the understanding of
phases.
Chapter 2 Introducing phases motivated the need for phases, provided
the necessary historical background on phases, and reviewed the existing characterizations of phases, contrasting the views of phases dened in terms
of subarrays with the views of phases dened in terms of the properties of
phase heads. The property that played an important role throughout the book
was the ability of phase heads (and only phase heads) to be the locus
of uninterpretable features. This chapter also showed how this property led
to Feature Inheritance, the idea that non-phase heads can only acquire uninterpretable features by inheriting them from phase heads, and raised some
questions concerning the obligatory nature of Feature Inheritance. This chapter
also showed how phases change the overall architecture of the grammar in that
they allow transfer to the interfaces to happen more than once during the
derivation, perhaps even non-simultaneously, as was further explored in
Chapter 6.
Chapter 3 turned to the diagnostics that have been suggested in the
existing literature to determine the phasehood of a given category, with an eye
towards determining which of these diagnostics are real, and which ones
are only apparent. While the diagnostics discussed in this chapter were
organized into three groups, distinguishing interface diagnostics (PF and
LF diagnostics) from syntactic diagnostics (as seems common practice in the
literature on phases), I refrained from attaching too much import to a given
diagnostic being a PF, LF or a syntactic diagnostic, as it is often difcult to tell,
and the process underlying a given diagnostic might have both semantic and
phonological effects. The ones that end up playing an important role in the
discussion in subsequent chapters were: the ability of phase heads to determine
Spell-Out (as determined by ellipsis types and the effects of the Phase
205

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847C08.3D

206

206

[205206] 23.11.2013 10:53AM

Summary

Impenetrability Condition), the ability of phase heads to serve as Probes (be


the loci of uninterpretable features), and the requirement that movement out
of phases proceed through phase edges. This chapter also alluded to alternative
approaches to phases, which might rely on (or require) different sets of diagnostics, and end up with different categories counting as phases.
The next chapter (Chapter 4) turned to three core categories that are
typically assumed to be phases: CPs, vPs and DPs. It applied the diagnostics
established in the previous chapter to these three categories, and concluded
that, indeed, with respect to these diagnostics, these three categories do
behave as phases. It showed that C, v and D heads trigger Spell-Out, and can
act as Probes (and thus value uninterpretable features), and that movement out
of them proceeds through the edge (as it can trigger agreement, reconstruct to
the edge position or be blocked when the edge is lled). This chapter also
examined the issue of whether passive and unaccusative vPs are phases. Here
the evidence was somewhat less unequivocal. For example, we saw that such
vPs do not trigger Spell-Out, but they do require movement to proceed through
the edge.
Chapter 5 extended the idea of phasehood to three other categories whose
status as phases is somewhat more elusive: Predication Phrases (PrPs),
Prepositional Phrases (PPs) and Applicative Phrases (ApplPs) and applied
the diagnostics to them. It concluded that only certain types of PrPs and ApplP
are phases, and that the behavior of PPs with respect to phasehood diagnostics
is mixed.
Chapter 6 dealt with variation in phasehood, construed quite broadly, to
include both interlanguage and intralanguage variation. It examined the
question of whether phasehood can be affected by independent factors (such
as head movement), and the possibility that phasehood itself might be
subject to crosslinguistic variation. It also examined the possibility that
there might be variation in phasehood with respect to PF and LF diagnostics.
And the last chapter (Chapter 7) examined the role phases play at the
interfaces. It showed how phases can help us understand PF-related
phenomena such as linear order preservation effects or nuclear stress assignment,
as well as the mapping between phases and semantic and information structure
domains.
To conclude ever so briey, I do not aspire to have covered (or even
touched upon) all the aspects of Phase Theory in this book. There are many
questions that I raised that remain unanswered. I do, however, hope to have
shown where phases came from, what they can do, and where they are going.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

207 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

Abels, Klaus. 2003. Successive Cyclicity, Antilocality and Adposition Stranding.


Doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut.
Abney, Steven P. 1987. The English Noun Phrase in its Sentential Aspect. Doctoral
dissertation, MIT.
Abraham, Werner. 2010. Misleading Homonymies, Economical PPs in Microvariation,
and P as a Probe. In Mapping Spatial PPs, ed. G. Cinque & L. Rizzi, 26194. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Adger, David. 2003. Core Syntax: A Minimalist Approach. Oxford University Press.
2007. Stress and Phasal Syntax. Linguistic Analysis 33: 23866.
Adger, David & Gillian Ramchand. 2003. Predication and Equation. Linguistic Inquiry
34: 32559.
Adger, David & Peter Svenonius. 2011. Features in Minimalist Syntax. In The
Oxford Handbook of Minimalist Syntax, ed. C. Boeckx, 2751. Oxford University Press.
Aelbrecht, Lobke. 2009. You Have the Right to Remain Silent: The Syntactic Licensing
of Ellipsis. Doctoral dissertation, Catholic University of Brussels.
Agero-Bautista, Calixto. 2001. Cyclicity and the Scope of Wh-Phrases. Doctoral
disseration, MIT.
Aissen, Judith. 1996. Pied-Piping, Abstract Agreement, and Functional Projections in
Tzotzil. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 14: 44791.
Aldridge, Edith. 2005. Phase Theory Account of Absolutive Extraction in Tagalog. In
Perspectives on Phases, ed. M. McGinnis & N. Richards, 128. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Working Papers in Linguistics.
2010. Clause-internal Wh-movement in Archaic Chinese. Journal of East Asian
Linguistics 19: 136.
Alexiadou, Artemis & Elena Anagnostopoulou. 2001. The Subject-in-Situ Generalization
and the Role of Case in Driving Computations. Linguistic Inquiry 32: 193231.
Alexiadou, Artemis, Liliane M. V. Haegeman & Melita Stavrou. 2007. Noun Phrase in the
Generative Perspective. Berlin and New York: Mouton De Gruyter.
Bachrach, Asaf & Roni Katzir. 2007. Spelling out QR. Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung
11, ed. E. Puig-Waldmller, 6375. Barcelona: Universitat Pompeu Fabra.
2009. Right Node Raising and Delayed Spell-Out. In Interphases: Phase-Theoretic
Investigations of Linguistic Interfaces, ed. K. K. Grohmann, 283316. Oxford
University Press.

207

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

208

208 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

Bailyn, John Frederick. 2001. On Scrambling: A Reply to Bokovi and Takahashi.


Linguistic Inquiry 32: 63558.
2009. Whats inside VP? New Evidence on VP Internal Structure in Russian. Paper
presented at FASL 18, Cornell University.
Bailyn, John Frederick & Barbara Citko. 1999. Case and Agreement in Slavic Predicates.
In Formal Approaches to Slavic Linguistics 7: The Seattle Meeting 1998, ed.
K. Dziwirek, H. Coates & C. Vakareliyska, 1739. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic
Publications.
Bailyn, John Frederick & Edward Rubin. 1991. The Unication of Instrumental Case
Assignment in Russian. Cornell Working Papers in Linguistics 9: 99126.
Baker, Mark C. 2003. Lexical Categories: Verbs, Nouns, and Adjectives. Cambridge
University Press.
2008a. The Macroparameter in a Microparametric World. In The Limits of Syntactic
Variation, ed. T. Biberauer, 35174. Cambridge University Press.
2008b. The Syntax of Agreement and Concord. Cambridge University Press.
Baker, Mark, Kyle Johnson & Ian Roberts. 1989. Passive Arguments Raised. Linguistic
Inquiry 20: 21951.
Baltin, Mark R. 1987. Do Antecedent-Contained Deletions Exist? Linguistic Inquiry
18: 57995.
Barros, Mathew & Luis Vicente. 2010. Right Node Raising Requires Both Multidominance
and Ellipsis. Handout from a talk given at the 34th Penn Linguistics Colloquium.
Barrs, Andrew 1986. Chains and Anaphoric Dependence. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
2001. Syntactic Reconstruction Effects. In The Handbook of Syntactic Theory, ed.
M. Baltin & C. Collins, 67096. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Barss, Andrew & Howard Lasnik. 1986. A Note on Anaphora and Double Objects.
Linguistic Inquiry 17: 34754.
Belletti, Adriana. 1988. The Case of Unaccusatives. Linguistic Inquiry 19: 134.
Belletti, Adriana & Luigi Rizzi. 1988. Psych-Verbs and -Theory. Natural Language
and Linguistic Theory 6: 291352.
Bernstein, Judy. 1993. Topics in the Syntax of Nominal Structure across Romance.
Doctoral dissertation, CUNY Graduate Center.
2001a. The DP Hypothesis: Identifying Clausal Properties in the Nominal Domain. In
The Handbook of Contemporary Syntactic Theory, ed. M. Baltin & C. Collins, 536
61. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
2001b. Focusing the Right Way in Romance Determiner Phrases. Probus 13: 129.
2008. Reformulating the Determiner Phrase Analysis. Language and Linguistics
Compass 2: 124670.
Bhatt, Rajesh. 2005. Long Distance Agreement in HindiUrdu. Natural Language and
Linguistic Theory 23: 757807.
Biberauer, Theresa (ed.) 2008. The Limits of Syntactic Variation. Amsterdam and
Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Biberauer, Theresa, Anders Holmberg, Ian Roberts & Michelle Sheehan. 2010. Parametric
Variation: Null Subjects in Minimalist Theory. Cambridge University Press.
Biskup, Petr. 2009a. The Phase Model and Adverbials. Doctoral dissertation, University
of Leipzig.
Biskup, Petr. 2009b. The Syntactic Structure of PPs. In Czech in Formal Grammar, ed.
M. Doekal & M. Zikov, 929. Munich: Lincom.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

209 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

209

Bittner, Maria & Ken Hale. 1996. The Structural Determination of Case and Agreement.
Linguistic Inquiry 27: 167.
Bobaljik, Jonathan David. 2003. Floating Quantiers: Handle With Care. In The Second
Glot International State-of-the-Article Book, ed. L. Cheng & R. Sybesma, 10748.
Berlin and New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Bobaljik, Jonathan David & Dianne Jonas. 1996. Subject Positions and the Roles of TP.
Linguistic Inquiry 27: 195236.
Bobaljik, Jonathan David & Susi Wurmbrand. 2005. The Domain of Agreement. Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory 23: 80965.
Boeckx, Cedric. 2001. Scope Reconstruction and A-Movement. Natural Language and
Linguistic Theory 19: 50348.
2006. Linguistic Minimalism: Origins, Concepts, Methods, and Aims. Oxford
University Press.
2008a. Understanding Minimalist Syntax: Lessons from Locality in Long-Distance
Dependencies. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
2008b. Bare Syntax. Oxford University Press.
2012. Syntactic Islands. Cambridge University Press.
Boeckx, Cedric & Kleanthes K. Grohmann 2003. Multiple Wh-Fronting. Amsterdam and
Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
2007. Remark: Putting Phases in Perspective. Syntax: 10: 20422.
Booij, Geert & Jerzy Rubach. 1987. Postcyclic versus Postlexical Rules in Lexical
Phonology. Linguistic Inquiry 18: 144.
Borer, Hagit. 1984. Parametric Syntax: Case Studies in Semitic and Romance Languages.
Dordrecht: Foris.
Bokovi, eljko. 1997. The Syntax of Nonnite Complementation: An Economy
Approach. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
2002a. A-Movement and the EPP. Syntax 5: 167218.
2002b. On Multiple Wh-Fronting. Linguistic Inquiry 33: 35183.
2003. Agree, Phases and Intervention Effects. Linguistic Analysis 33: 5496.
2004a. Be Careful Where You Float Your Quantiers. Natural Language and
Linguistic Theory 22: 681742.
2004b. Object Shift and the Clause/PP Parallelism Hypothesis. In WCCFL 23: Proceedings
of the 23rd West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. B. Schmeiser, V. Chand,
A. Kelleher, & A. Rodriguez, 10114. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.
2005. On the Locality of Left Branch Extraction and the Structure of NP. Studia
Linguistica 59: 145.
2007. On the Locality and Motivation of Move and Agree: an Even More Minimal
Theory. Linguistic Inquiry 38: 589644.
2009. More on the No-DP Analysis of Article-Less Languages. Studia Linguistica 63:
187203.
2011. On Unvalued Interpretable Features. In NELS 39: Proceedings of the 39th
Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society, ed. S. Lima, K. Mullin &
B. Smith, 10920. Amherst, MA: GLSA.
(To appear). Now Im a Phase, Now Im Not a Phase: On the Variability of Phases with
Extraction and Ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry.
Bokovi, eljko & Steven Franks. 2000. Across-the-Board Movement and LF. Syntax
3: 10728.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

210

210 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

Bokovi, eljko & Daiko Takahashi. 1998. Scrambling and Last Resort. Linguistic
Inquiry 29: 34766.
Bowers, John. 1993. The Syntax of Predication. Linguistic Inquiry 24: 591656.
2002. Transitivity. Linguistic Inquiry 33: 183224.
Bresnan, Joan W. 1971. Sentence Stress and Syntactic Transformations. Language 47:
25781.
Bruening, Benjamin. 2001. QR Obeys Superiority: Frozen Scope and ACD. Linguistic
Inquiry 32: 23373.
2004. Two Types of Wh-Scope Marking in Passamaquoddy. Natural Language and
Linguistic Theory 22: 229305.
Bring, Daniel. 2005. Binding Theory. Cambridge University Press.
Butler, Jonny. 2005. The Phase Structure of Tense. In Perspectives on Phases ed.
M. McGinnis & N. Richards, 6985. Cambridge, MA: MIT Working Papers in
Linguistics.
Cable, Seth. 2008. Wh-fronting in Hungarian Is Not Focus Fronting. Manuscript.
Available at Lingbuzz (lingbuzz/000674).
Calabrese, Andrea 1984. Multiple Questions and Focus in Italian. In Sentential
Complementation, ed. W. De Geest & T. Putseys, 6774. Dordrecht: Foris.
Carnie, Andrew & Andrew Barss. 2006. Phases and Nominal Interpretation. Research In
Language 4: 12732.
Carstens, Vicki. 2000. Concord in Minimalist Theory. Linguistic Inquiry 31: 31955.
2003. Rethinking Complementizer Agreement: Agree with a Case-Checked Goal.
Linguistic Inquiry 34: 393412.
2005. Agree and EPP In Bantu. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 23: 21979.
Carstens, Vicki & Michael Diercks. 2011. Agreeing How? Implications for Theories of
Agreement And Locality. Manuscript. Available at Lingbuzz (lingbuzz/001389).
Castillo, Juan Carlos, John E. Drury & Kleanthes K. Grohmann. 2009. Merge over Move
and the Extended Projection Principle: MOM and the EPP Revisited. Iberia: An
International Journal of Theoretical Linguistics 1: 53114.
Cecchetto, Carlo. 2004. Explaining the Locality Conditions of QR: Consequences for the
Theory Of Phases. Natural Language Semantics 12: 34597.
Cecchetto, Carlo & Caterina Donati. 2010. On Labeling: Principle C and Head
Movement. Syntax 13: 24178.
Charlow, Simon. 2009. Can DP Be a Scope Island? Talk given at the ESSLLI09 Student
Session.
Cheng, Lisa Lai-Shen. 1991. On The Typology of Wh-Questions. Doctoral dissertation,
MIT.
Chomsky, Noam. 1970. Remarks on Nominalization. In Readings In English
Transformational Grammar, by R. A. Jacobs & P. S. Rosenbaum, 184221.
Waltham, MA: Ginn & Co.
1986. Knowledge of Language: Its Nature, Origin, and Use. New York: Praeger.
1994. Bare Phrase Structure. Working Occasional Papers in Linguistics 5. Cambridge,
MA: MIT.
1995. The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
2000. Minimalist Inquiries: The Framework. In Step By Step. Essays on Minimalist
Syntax in Honor of Howard Lasnik, ed. R. E. A. Martin, 89155. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

211 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

211

2001. Derivation by Phase. In Ken Hale: A Life in Language, ed. M. Kenstowicz,


152. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
2004. Beyond Explanatory Adequacy. In Structures and Beyond: The Cartography of
Syntactic Structures, vol. 3, ed. A. Belletti, 10431. Oxford University Press.
2005. Three Factors in Language Design. Linguistic Inquiry 36: 122.
2007. Approaching UG from Below. In Interfaces + Recursion = Language?, ed.
U. Sauerland & H. -M. Grtner, 130. Berlin: Mouton De Gruyter.
2008. On Phases. In Foundational Issues in Linguistic Theory, ed. R. Freidin,
C. P. Otero & M. L. Zubizarreta, 13366. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
2013 The Problem of Projection. Lingua 130: 3349.
Chomsky, Noam & Morris Halle. 1968. The Sound Pattern of English. New York:
Harper & Row.
Chung, S., W. A. Ladusaw & J. McCloskey. 1995. Sluicing and Logical Form. Natural
Language Semantics 3: 23982.
Chung, Sandra. 1994. Wh-Agreement and Referentiality in Chamorro. Linguistic
Inquiry 25: 144.
1998. The Design of Agreement: Evidence from Chamorro. University of Chicago
Press.
Cinque, Guglielmo. 1993. A Null Theory of Phrase and Compound Stress. Linguistic
Inquiry 24: 23997.
2002. Functional Structure in DP and IP. Oxford University Press.
2010. The Syntax of Adjectives: A Comparative Study. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Cinque, Guglielmo & Luigi Rizzi. 2010. Mapping Spatial PPs. Oxford University Press.
Citko, Barbara. 2000. Parallel Merge and the Syntax of Free Felatives. Doctoral dissertation, Stony Brook University.
2005. On the Nature of Merge: External Merge, External Merge, and Parallel Merge.
Linguistic Inquiry 36: 47597.
2006. Copula Sentences Reconsidered. In Formal Approaches to Slavic Linguistics
14: The Princeton Meeting 2005, ed. J. E. Lavine, S. Franks, M. TassevaKurktchieva & H. Filip, 8398. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic Publications.
2008a. Missing Labels. Lingua 118: 90744.
2008b. Small Clauses Reconsidered: Not So Small and Not All Alike. Lingua 118:
26195.
2010. On the (A)Symmetric Nature of Movement: A View from Polish Wh- and
Passive Movement. In Formal Approaches to Slavic Linguistics 18: The Second
Cornell Meeting 2009, ed. C. Browne et al., 3857. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic
Publications.
2011a. Multidominance. In The Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Minimalism, ed.
C. Boeckx, 11942. Oxford University Press.
2011b. Symmetry in Syntax: Merge, Move and Labels. Cambridge University Press.
2011c. Small Clauses. Language and Linguistics Compass 5: 74863.
Cole, Peter & Gabriella Hermon. 1998. The Typology of WH Movement: WH Questions
in Malay. Syntax 1: 22158.
Collins, Chris. 2002. Eliminating Labels. In Derivation and Explanation in the
Minimalist Program, ed. S. D. Epstein & T. D. Seely. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Corver, Norbert. 1990. The Syntax of Left Branch Extraction. Doctoral dissertation,
Tilburg University.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

212

212 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

1992. Left Branch Extraction. In NELS 22: Proceedings of the 22nd Annual Meeting
of the North East Linguistics Society, ed. K. Broderick, 6784. Amherst, MA: GLSA.
Craenenbroeck, Jeroen van. 2010. The Syntax of Ellipsis: Evidence from Dutch Dialects.
Oxford University Press.
Craenenbroeck, Jeroen van & Liliane M. V. Haegeman. 2007. The Derivation of SubjectInitial V2. Linguistic Inquiry 38: 16778.
Culicover, Peter W. & Paul Martin Postal (eds.). 2001. Parasitic Gaps. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Danon, Gabi. 2011. Agreement and DP-Internal Feature Distribution. Syntax 14: 97317.
Davies, William D. & Stanley Dubinsky. 2003. On Extraction from NPs. Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory 21: 137.
Dayal, Veneeta. 1996. Locality in Wh-Quantication: Questions and Relative Clauses in
Hindi. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
1993. Scope Marking as Indirect Wh-Dependency. Natural Language Semantics 2:
13770.
Den Dikken, Marcel. 2006a. A Reappraisal of vP Being Phasal A Reply to Legate.
Unpublished manuscript, CUNY Graduate Center.
2006b. Relators and Linkers: The Syntax of Predication, Predicate Inversion, and
Copulas. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
2007. Phase Extension: Contours of a Theory of the Role of Head Movement in Phrasal
Extraction. Theoretical Linguistics 33: 141.
2010. On the Functional Structure of Locative and Directional PPs. In Mapping
Spatial PPs: The Cartography of Syntactic Structures, ed. G. Cinque & L. Rizzi,
74126. Oxford University Press.
Diercks, Michael. 2011. Against Feature Inheritance: Phase Heads Are Not Dened by
Unvalued -features. Manuscript.
Diesing, Molly. 1992. Indenites. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dobashi, Yoshihiko. 2003. Phonological Phrasing and Syntactic Derivation. Doctoral
dissertation, Cornell University.
Dogil, Grzegorz. 1987. Lexical Phonology and Floating Inection in Polish. In
Phonologica 1984, ed. W. U. Dressler, 3947. Cambridge University Press.
Donati, Caterina & Carlo Cecchetto. 2011. Relabeling Heads: A Unied Account for
Relativization Structures. Linguistic Inquiry 42: 51960.
Dornisch, Ewa. 1998. Multiple Wh-Questions in Polish: The Interactions between WhPhrases and Clitics. Doctoral dissertation, Cornell University.
Drummond, Alex, Norbert Hornstein & Howard Lasnik. 2010. A Puzzle about PStranding and a Possible Solution. Linguistic Inquiry 41: 68992.
Dyakonova, Marina. 2007. Russian Double Object Construction. ACLC Working Papers
21: 128.
Dziwirek, Katarzyna. 2000. Why Polish Doesnt Like Innitives. Journal of Slavic
Linguistics 8: 5782.
Elordieta, Gorka. 2008. An Overview of Theories of the Syntax-Phonology Interface.
International Journal of Basque Linguistics and Philology (ASJU) 42(1): 20986.
Embick, David. 1995. Mobile inections in Polish. In NELS 25: Proceedings of the 25th
Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistics Society, ed. J. N. Beckman, 12742.
Amherst, MA: GLSA.
Emonds, Joseph. 1985. A Unied Theory of Syntactic Categories. Dordrecht: Foris.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

213 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

213

2001. The Lower Operator Position with Parasitic Gaps. In Features and Interfaces in
Romance, ed. J. Herschensohn, E. Malln & K. Zagona, 85106. Amsterdam and
Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
En, Mrvet. 1991. The Semantics of Specicity. Linguistic Inquiry 22: 125.
Engdahl, Elisabet. 2001. Parasitic Gaps. In Parasitic Gaps, ed. Peter W. Culicover &
Paul M. Postal, 6997. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Epstein, Samuel. 2007. On I(nternalist)-Functional Explanation in Minimalism.
Linguistic Analysis 33: 2053.
Epstein, Samuel D. & T. Daniel Seely. 2002. Rule Applications as Cycles in a Level-Free
Syntax. In Derivation and explanation in the Minimalist Program, ed.
S. D. Epstein & T. D. Seely, 6589. Oxford: Blackwell.
2006. Transformations and Derivations. Cambridge University Press.
Fanselow, Gisbert & Damir avar. 2002. Distributed Deletion. In Theoretical
Approaches to Universals, ed. A. Alexiadou, 65107. Amsterdam and
Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Felser, Claudia. 2004. Wh-Copying, Phases, and Successive Cyclicity. Lingua 114: 54374.
Fox, Danny. 1999. Reconstruction, Binding Theory, and the Interpretation of Chains.
Linguistic Inquiry 30: 15796.
2000. Economy and Semantic Interpretation Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fox, Danny & David Pesetsky. 2005. Cyclic Linearization of Syntactic Structure.
Theoretical Linguistics 31: 146.
Frampton, John & Sam Gutmann. 2000. Agreement is Feature Sharing. Unpublished
manuscript, Northeastern University.
2002. Crash-Proof Syntax. In Derivation and Explanation in the Minimalist Program,
ed. S. D. Epstein & T. Daniel Seely, 90105. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Franks, Steven. 1998. Clitics in Slavic. Paper Presented at the Comparative Slavic
Morphosyntax Workshop. Spencer, IN.
Franks, Steven & Piotr Baski. 1999. Approaches to Schizophrenic Polish Person
Agreement. In Formal Approaches to Slavic Linguistics: The Seattle Meeting, ed.
K. Dziwirek, H. Coats & C. M. Vakareliyska, 12344. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic
Publications.
Frascarelli, Mara (ed.). 2006. Phases of Interpretation. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Frederici, Angela. 1982. Syntactic and Semantic Processes in Aphasic Decits: the
Availability of Prepositions. Brain And Language 15: 26958.
Froud, Karen. 2001. Prepositions and the Lexical/Functional Divide: Aphasic Evidence.
Lingua 111: 128.
Gallego, ngel J. 2010. Phase Theory. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
2012. Phases: Developing the Framework. Berlin and Boston: De Gruyter Mouton.
Gavruseva, E. 2000. On the Syntax of Possessor Extraction. Lingua 110: 74372.
Gengel, Kirsten. 2007. Focus and Ellipsis a Generative Analysis of Pseudogapping and
Other Elliptical Structures. Doctoral dissertation, Stuttgart University.
2009. Phases and Ellipsis. Linguistic Analysis 35: 2142.
Green, Georgia M. 1974. Semantics and Syntactic Regularity. Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press.
Grimshaw, Jane. 1991. Extended Projection. Manuscript, Brandeis University.
Grohmann, Kleanthes K. 2003. Prolic Domains: On the Antilocality of Movement
Dependencies. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

214

214 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

(ed.) 2009a. Explorations of Phase Theory: Features And Arguments. Berlin: Walter de
Gruyter.
2009b (ed.). Explorations of Phase Theory: Interpretation at the Interfaces. Berlin:
Walter de Gruyter.
2009c (ed). Interphases: Phase-Theoretic Investigations of Linguistic Interfaces.
Oxford University Press.
2011. Anti-Locality: Too-Close Relations in Grammar. In The Oxford Handbook of
Linguistic Minimalism, ed. C. Boeckx, 26090. Oxford University Press.
Grohmann, Kleanthes K., John Drury & Juan Carlos Castillo. 2000. No More EPP. In
WCCFL 19: Proceedings of the 19th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics,
ed. R. Billerey & B. D. Lillehaugen, 15366. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.
Haegeman, Liliane. 1992. Theory and Description in Generative Syntax: A Case Study in
West Flemish. Cambridge University Press.
Haegeman, Liliane & Marjo Van Koppen. 2011. Complementizer Agreement and the
Relation Between C And T. Manuscript, Ghent University and University of Utrecht.
Hale, Ken & Jay S. Keyser. 1993. On Argument Structure and the Lexical Expression of
Syntactic Relations. In The View From Building 20: Essays in Linguistics in Honor of
Sylvain Bromberger, ed. K. Hale & J. S. Keyser, 53109. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Halle, Morris & Alex Marantz. 1993. Distributed Morphology and the Pieces of
Inection. In The View From Building 20, ed. K. Hale & J. S. Keyser, 11176.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Halle, Morris & Jean-Roger Vergnaud. 1987. An Essay on Stress. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hankamer, Jorge & Ivan Sag. 1976. Deep and Surface Anaphora. Linguistic Inquiry 7:
391428.
Harves, Stephanie. 2002. Where Have All the Phases Gone? (Non-)Defective Categories
and Case Alternations in Russian. In Formal Approaches To Slavic Linguistics 10:
The Second Ann Arbor Meeting, ed. J. Toman, 97118. Ann Arbor, MI: Michigan
Slavic Publications.
Heycock, Caroline. 1995. Asymmetries in Reconstruction. Linguistic Inquiry 26: 54770.
Hiraiwa, Ken. 2001. Multiple Agree and the Defective Intervention Constraint in
Japanese. In Proceedings of HUMIT 2000, 6780. Cambridge, MA: MIT Working
Papers in Linguistics.
Hiraiwa, Ken. 2005. Dimensions of Symmetry in Syntax: Agreement and Clausal
Architecture. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
Holmberg, Anders. 2001. The Syntax of Yes and No in Finnish. Studia Linguistica 55:
14175.
Hornstein, Norbert. 1994. An Argument for Minimalism: the Case of AntecedentContained Deletion. Linguistic Inquiry 25: 45580.
1995. Logical Form. Oxford: Blackwell.
Hornstein, Norbert & Jairo Nunes. 2002. On Asymmetries between Parasitic Gap and
Across-the-Board Constructions. Syntax 5: 2654.
Hornstein, Norbert, Jairo Nunes & Kleanthes K. Grohmann. 2005. Understanding
Minimalism. Cambridge University Press.
Hornstein, Norbert & Amy Weinberg. 1981. Case Theory and Preposition Stranding.
Linguistic Inquiry 12: 5591.
Horvath, Julia. 1997. The Status of Wh-Expletives and the Partial Wh-Movement
Construction of Hungarian. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 15: 50972.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

215 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

215

Huang, Cheng-Teh James. 1982. Logical Relations in Chinese and the Theory of
Grammar. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
1993. Reconstruction and the Structure of VP: Some Theoretical Consequences.
Linguistic Inquiry 24: 10338.
Iatridou, Sabine & Ivy Sichel. 2011. Negative DPs, A-Movement, and Scope
Diminishment. Linguistic Inquiry 42: 595629.
Inenlikj, Petr I. & Vladimir Nedjalkov. 1973. Glagoly uvstva v ukotskom jazyke.
Lingvistieskie issledovanija 1972, 175203.
Ishihara, Shinichiro. 2003. Intonation and Interface Conditions. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
2007. Major Phrase, Focus Intonation, Multiple Spell-Out (Map, FI, MSO). The
Linguistic Review 24: 23.
Jackendoff, Ray. 1977. X-bar Syntax: A Study of Phrase Structure. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Jaysaseelan, K. A. 2001. IP-Internal Topic and Focus Phrases. Studia Linguistica 55:
3975.
Jeong, Youngmi. 2006. The Landscape of Applicatives. Doctoral dissertation, University
of Maryland.
Johnson, Kyle. 2000. Few Dogs Eat Whiskas or Cats Alpo. In UMOP 23: Issues
in Semantics and its Interface, ed. K. Kusumoto and E. Villalta, 5982. Amherst,
MA: GSLA.
2009. Gapping Is Not (VP-)Ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 40: 289328.
Kahnemuyipour, Arsalan. 2003. Syntactic Categories and Persian Stress. Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory 21: 33379.
2004. The Syntax of Sentential Stress. Doctoral dissertation, University of Toronto.
2005. Towards a Phase-Based Theory of Sentential Stress. In Perspectives on Phases,
ed. M. McGinnis & N. Richards, 12546. Cambridge, MA: MIT Working Papers In
Linguistics.
Kasai, Hironobu. 2007. Multidominance in Syntax. Doctoral dissertation, Harvard
University.
Katz, Jerrold J. & Paul Martin Postal. 1964. An Integrated Theory of Linguistic
Descriptions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kayne, Richard S. 1980. Extensions of Binding and Case-Marking. Linguistic Inquiry
11: 7596.
1981. On Certain Differences between French and English. Linguistic Inquiry
12: 34972.
1994. The Antisymmetry of Syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
1999. Prepositional Complementizers as Attractors. Probus 11: 3973.
2004. Prepositions as Probes. In Structures and Beyond, ed. A. Belletti, 192-X. Oxford
University Press.
2010. Why Are There No Directionality Parameters? Manuscript, New York
University.
Kennedy, Christopher. 1997. Antecedent-Contained Deletion and the Syntax of
Quantication. Linguistic Inquiry 28: 66288.
Khomitsevich, Olga. 2007. Dependencies across Phases: From Sequence of Tense to
Restrictions on Movement. Doctoral dissertation, Utrecht: LOT.
Kinyalolo, Kasangati Kikuni Wabongambilu. 1991. Syntactic Dependencies and the
SPECHead Agreement Hypothesis in Kilega. Doctoral dissertation, UCLA.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

216

216 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

Kiparsky, Paul. 1998. Partitive Case and Aspect. In The Projection of Arguments, ed.
M. Butt & W. Gueder. Stanford: CSLI Publications.
Kiss, Katalin . 1987. Congurationality in Hungarian. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Koopman, Hilda 2000. Prepositions, Postpositions, Circumpositions, and Particles: The
Case of Dutch PPs. In The Syntax of Speciers and Heads: Collected Essays of Hilda
J. Koopman, ed. H. Koopman, 20460. London: Routledge.
Kratzer, Angelika & Elisabeth Selkirk. 2007. Phase Theory and Prosodic Spell-Out: The
Case of Verbs. The Linguistic Review 24: 93135.
Laenzlinger, Christopher. 2005. French Adjective Ordering: Perspectives on DP-Internal
Movement Types. Lingua 115: 64589.
Lahne, Antje. 2008. Where There Is Fire There Is Smoke: Local Modelling of SuccessiveCyclic Movement. Doctoral dissertation, University Of Leipzig.
Landau, Idan. 1999. Elements of Control. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
2000. Elements of Control: Structure and Meaning in Innitival Constructions
Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer.
2003. Movement out of Control. Linguistic Inquiry 34: 47198.
2008. Two Routes of Control: Evidence from Case Transmission in Russian. Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory 26: 877924.
2010. The Locative Syntax of Experiencers. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Larson, Richard K. 1985. Quantifying into NP. Manuscript, Stony Brook University.
1988. Light Predicate Raising. MIT Lexicon Project Working Papers 27. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Center for Cognitive Science.
Larson, Richard & Robert May. 1990. Antecedent Containment or Vacuous Movement:
Reply to Baltin.Linguistic Inquiry 21: 10322.
Lasnik, Howard. 1992. Case and Expletives: Notes Toward a Parametric Account.
Linguistic Inquiry, 23: 381405.
1998. Exceptional Case Marking: Perspectives Old And New. In Formal Approaches
To Slavic Linguistics: The Connecticut Meeting 1997, ed. Z. Bokovi, S. Franks &
W. Snyder, 187211. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic Publications.
1999. Chains of Arguments. In Working Minimalism, ed. S. D. Epstein &
N. Hornstein, 189215. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lebeaux, David. 1990. Relative Clauses, Licensing, and the Nature of the Derivation. In
NELS 20: Proceedings of the 20th Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic
Society, ed. J. Carter, R.-M. Dechaine, B. Philip & T. Sherer, 31832. Amherst, MA:
GLSA.
1991. Relative Clauses, Licensing, and the Nature of the Derivation. In Syntax and
Semantics 25: Perspectives on Phrase Structure, ed. S. Rothstein, 20939. New
York: Academic Press.
1994. Where does binding theory apply? MS, University of Maryland, College Park.
2009. Where Does Binding Theory Apply? Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Legate, Julie Anne. 2002. Phases in Beyond Explanatory Adequacy. Manuscript.
2003. Some Interface Properties of the Phase. Linguistic Inquiry 34: 50616.
2011. Under-Inheritance. Handout of a paper presented at NELS 42, University of
Toronto.
2012. The size of Phases. In Phases, ed. A. Gallego, 23350. Berlin: De Gruyter.
Levin, Beth & Malka Rappaport Hovav. 1995. Unaccusativity: At the SyntaxLexical
Semantics Interface. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

217 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

217

Lobeck, Anne C. 1995. Ellipsis: Functional Heads, Licensing, and Identication. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Lutz, Uli, Gereon Mller & Arnim von Stechow. 2000. Wh-Scope Marking. Amsterdam
and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Macdonald, Jonathan Eric. 2006. The Syntax of Inner Aspect. Doctoral dissertation,
Stony Brook University.
Mahajan, Anoop Kumar. 1989. Agreement and Agreement Phrases. In Functional Heads
and Clause Structure, ed. I. Laka & A. K. Mahajan, 21752, Cambridge, MA: MIT
Working Papers in Linguistics.
1996. Wh-Expletives and the Syntax of Partial Wh-Movement. In Papers On Scope
Marking, ed. U. Lutz & G. Mller, 16377. University of Tbingen / University of
Stuttgart.
Manetta, Emily. 2010. Wh-Expletives in Hindi-Urdu: The vP Phase. Linguistic Inquiry
41: 134.
Marantz, Alec. 1993. Implications of Asymmetries in Double Object Constructions. In
Theoretical Aspects of Bantu Grammar, ed. S. Mchombo, 11350. Stanford: CSLI
Publications.
2007. Phases and Words. In Phases in the Theory of Grammar, ed. H. Choe, 191220.
Seoul: Dong In.
Martin, Roger Andrew. 1996. A Minimalist Theory of PRO and Control. Doctoral
dissertation, University Of Connecticut.
Marui, Franc Lanko. 2005. On Non-Simultaneous Phases. Stony Brook University.
2009. Non-Simultaneous Spell-Out in the Clausal and Nominal Domain. In
Interphases: Phase-Theoretic Investigations of Linguistic Interfaces, ed.
K. K. Grohmann, 15181. Oxford University Press.
Matushansky, Ora. 2000. The Instrument of Inversion: Instrumental Case and Verb
Raising in the Russian Copula. In WCCFL 19: Proceedings of the 19th West Coast
Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. R. Billerey & B. Lillehaugen, 10115.
Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.
2005. Going through a Phase. In Perspectives on Phases, ed. M. McGinnis &
N. Richards, 15781. Cambridge, MA: MIT Working Papers in Linguistics.
2008. Predication: A Case Study. In Studies in Formal Slavic Linguistics:
Contributions from Formal Description of Slavic Languages 6.5, ed. F. Marusic &
R. Zaucer, 21339. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.
May, Robert 1977. The Grammar of Quantication. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
1985. Logical Form: Its Structure and Derivation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
McCloskey, James. 1998. The Prosody of Quantier Stranding under Wh-Movement in
West Ulster English. Manuscript.
2000. Quantier Float and Wh-Movement in an Irish English. Linguistic Inquiry 31:
5784.
2001. The Morphosyntax of WH-Extraction In Irish. Journal of Linguistics 37:
67100.
2002. Resumption, Successive Cyclicity, and the Locality of Operations. In
Derivation and Explanation in the Minimalist Program, ed. S. D. Epstein &
T. Daniel Seely, 184226. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
McDaniel, Dana. 1989. Partial and Multiple Wh-Movement. Natural Language and
Linguistic Theory 7: 565604.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

218

218 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

McGinnis, Martha. 2001. Variation in the Phase Structure of Applicatives. Linguistic


Variation Yearbook 1: 10546.
McGinnis, Martha & Norvin Richards (eds.). 2005. Perspectives on Phases. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Working papers in Linguistics.
Megerdoomian, Karine. 2000. Aspect and Partitive Objects in Finnish. In WCCFL 19:
Proceedings of the 19th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed.
R. Billerey & B. D. Lillehaugen, 31628. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.
Merchant, Jason. 2001. The Syntax of Silence: Sluicing, Islands, and the Theory of Ellipsis.
Oxford University Press.
2008. An Asymmetry in Voice Mismatches in VP-Ellipsis and Pseudogapping.
Linguistic Inquiry 39: 16979.
2013. Diagnosing Ellipsis. In Diagnosing Syntax, ed. L. Cheng & N. Corver, 53742.
Oxford University Press.
Migdalski, Krzysztof. 2006. The Syntax of Compound Tenses in Slavic. Doctoral
dissertation, Tilburg University.
Miyagawa, Shigeru. 1997. Against Optional Scrambling. Linguistic Inquiry 28: 125.
2003. A-movement Scrambling and Options without Optionality. In Word Order and
Scrambling, ed. S. Karimi, 177200. Oxford: Blackwell.
2011. Genitive subjects in Altaic and Specication of Phase. Lingua 21: 126582.
Miyagawa, Shigeru & Takae Tsujioka. 2004. Argument Structure and Ditransitive Verbs
in Japanese. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 13: 138.
Moro, Andrea. 1997. The Raising of Predicates: Predicative Noun Phrases and the Theory
of Clause Structure. Cambridge University Press.
2000. Dynamic Antisymmetry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Mller, Gereon. 2004. Phrase Impenetrability and Wh-Intervention. In Minimality
Effects in Syntax, ed. A. Stepanov, G. Fanselow & R. Vogel, 289325. Berlin: De
Gruyter.
2011. Constraints on Displacement: A Phase-Based Approach. Amsterdam and
Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Munn, Alan. 1999. First Conjunct Agreement: Against a Clausal Analysis. Linguistic
Inquiry 30: 64368.
Muysken, Pieter. 2008. Functional Categories. Cambridge University Press.
Nespor, Marina & Irene Vogel. 1986. Prosodic Phonology. Dordrecht: Foris.
Newman, Stanley. 1946. On the Stress System of English. Word 2: 17187.
Nissenbaum, Jonathan. 2000. Investigations in Covert Movement. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
Nunes, Jairo. 1995. The Copy Theory of Movement and the Linearization of Chains in the
Minimalist Program. Doctoral dissertation, University Of Maryland.
Oehrle, Richard T. 1976. The Grammatical Status of the English Dative Alternation.
Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
Ouali, Hamid. 2008. On C-To-T Phi-Feature Transfer: The Nature of Agreement and
Anti-Agreement In Berber. In Agreement Restrictions, ed. R. Dalessandro,
G. H. Hrafnbjargarson & S. Fischer, 15980. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Pak, Marjorie. 2008. The Postsyntactic Derivation and its Phonological Reexes.
Doctoral dissertation, University Of Pennsylvania.
Pereltsvaig, Asya. 2007. The Universality of DP: A View from Russian. Studia
Linguistica 61: 5994.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

219 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

219

2007. Copular Sentences in Russian: A Theory of Intra-Clausal Relations. Dordrecht:


Springer.
Pesetsky, David. 1998. Some Optimality Principles of Sentence Pronounciation. In Is the
Best Good Enough? Optimality and Competition In Syntax, ed. P. Barbosa, D. Fox,
P. Hagstrom, M. McGinnis & D. Pesetsky, 33784. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
1991 Zero Syntax: vol. 2: Innitives. Unpublished manuscript, MIT.
1995. Zero Syntax: Experiencers and Cascades. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Pesetsky, David & Esther Torrego. 2001. T-To-C Movement: Causes And
Consequences. In Ken Hale: A Life In Language, ed. M. Kenstowicz, 355426.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
2006. Probes, Goals and Syntactic Categories. In Proceedings of the 7th Annual Tokyo
Conference on Psycholinguistics, ed. Y. Otsu, 2560. Tokyo: Hituzi Syobo.
2007. The Syntax of Valuation and the Interpretability Of Features. In Phrasal and
Clausal Architecture: Syntactic Derivation and Interpretation. In Honor of Joseph
E. Emonds, ed. S. Karimi, V. Samiian & W. K. Wilkins, 26294. Amsterdam and
Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Peterson, David A. 2007. Applicative Constructions. Oxford University Press.
Picallo, M. Carme. 1991. Nominals and Nominalizations in Catalan. Probus 3: 279316.
Plessis, Hans Du. 1977. Wh Movement in Afrikaans. Linguistic Inquiry, 8: 7236.
Polinsky, Maria & Eric Potsdam. 2001. Long-Distance Agreement and Topic in Tsez.
Natural Language & Linguistic Theory, 19: 583646.
Postal, Paul M. 1972. On Some Rules that Are Not Successive Cyclic. Linguistic Inquiry
3: 21122.
Preminger, Omer. 2011. Agreement as a Fallible Operation. Doctoral Dissertation, MIT.
Progovac, Ljiljana. 1998. Determiner Phrase in a Language without Determiners.
Journal of Linguistics 34: 16579.
Pylkknen, Liina. 2008. Introducing Arguments. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Quinoli, Carlos. 2008. Anaphora by Phase. Syntax 11: 299329.
Rackowski, Andrea & Norvin Richards. 2005. Phase Edge and Extraction: A Tagalog
Case Study. Linguistic Inquiry 36: 56599.
Radkevich, Nina. 2010. On Location: The Structure of Case and Adpositions. Doctoral
dissertation, University of Connecticut.
Rappaport, Gilbert C. 2001 Extraction from Nominal Phrases in Polish and the Theory of
Determiners. Journal of Slavic Linguistics 8: 15998.
Rausch, Philip, Frank Burchert & Ria De Bleser. 2005. Parallels in the Breakdown of CP
And DP-Internal Movement Processes in Agrammatism: A Preliminary Case Study.
Brain And Language 95: 12930.
Reinhart, Tanya & Eric Reuland. 1993. Reexivity. Linguistic Inquiry 24: 657720.
Richards, Marc. 2004. Object Shift and Scrambling in North and West Germanic: A Case
Study in Symmetrical Syntax. Doctoral dissertation, University of Cambridge.
2007. Dynamic Linearization and the Shape of Phases. Linguistic Analysis 33: 20937.
2008. On Feature Inheritance: An Argument from the Phase Impenetrability
Condition. Linguistic Inquiry 38: 56372.
2011. Deriving the Edge: Whats in a Phase? Syntax 14: 7495.
Richards, Norvin. 2001. Movement in Language: Interactions and Architectures. Oxford
University Press.
2012. Lardil Case Stacking and the Timing of Case Assignment. Syntax 16: 4276.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

220

220 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

Richardson, Kylie. 2007. Case and Aspect in Slavic. Oxford University Press.
Ritter, Elizabeth. 1992. Cross-Linguistic Evidence for Number Phrase. Canadian
Journal of Linguistics Revue Canadienne de Linguistique 37: 197218.
1993. Wheres Gender? Linguistic Inquiry, 24: 795803.
Rizzi, Luigi. 1982. Issues in Italian Syntax. Dordrecht: Foris.
Roberts, Ian & Anders Holmberg. 2010. Introduction: Parameters in Minimalist Theory.
In Parametric Variation: Null Subjects in Minimalist Theory, ed. T. Biberauer,
A. Holmberg, I. Roberts & M. Sheehan, 157. Cambridge University Press.
Rooryck, Johan. 1997. On the Interaction between Raising and Focus in Sentential
Complementation. Studia Linguistica 51: 149.
Ross, John Robert. 1967. Constraints on Variables in Syntax. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
Rouveret, Alain. 2012. VP Ellipsis, Phases and the Syntax of Morphology. Natural
Language And Linguistic Theory 30: 897963.
Rudin, Catherine. 1988. On Multiple Questions and Multiple WH Fronting. Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory 6: 445501.
Rutkowski, Pawe. 2002 The Syntax of Quantier Phrases and the Inherent versus
Structural Case Distinction. Linguistic Research 7: 4374.
Rutkowski, Pawe & Ljiljana Progovac. 2005. Classication Projection in Polish and
Serbian. In Formal Approaches to Slavic Linguistics 2004, ed. S. Franks et al.,
28999. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic Publications.
Sabbagh, Joseph. 2007. Ordering and Linearizing Rightward Movement. Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory 25: 349401.
Sag, Ivan A. 1976. Deletion and Logical Form. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
Saito, Mamoru. 2003. Derivational Approach to the Interpretation of Scrambling Chains.
Lingua 113: 481518.
Saito, Mamoru, T. H. Jonah Lin & Keiko Murasugi. 2008. N-Ellipsis and the Structure of
Noun Phrases in Chinese and Japanese. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 17: 24771.
Samuels, Bridget. 2011. A Minimalist Program for Phonology. In The Oxford Handbook
of Linguistic Minimalism, ed. C. Boeckx, 57494. Oxford University Press.
Sato, Yosuke. 2011. P-Stranding under Sluicing and Repair by Ellipsis: Why Is
Indonesian (Not) Special? Journal Of East Asian Linguistics 20: 33982.
2012. Successive Cyclicity at the Syntax-Morphology Interface: Evidence from
Standard Indonesian and Kendal Javanese. Studia Linguistica 66: 3257.
Sauerland, Uli. 2005. DP Is Not a Scope Island. Linguistic Inquiry 36: 30314.
Sauerland, Uli & Paul Elbourne. 2002. Total Reconstruction, PF Movement, and
Derivational Order. Linguistic Inquiry 33: 283319.
Scheer, Tobias 2012. Chunk Denition in Phonology: Prosodic Constituency vs. Phase
Structure. In Modules and Interfaces, ed. M. Bloch-Trojnar & A. Bloch-Rozmej,
22153. Lublin: Wydawnictwo KUL.
Scott, Gary-John. 2002. Stacked Adjectival Modication and the Structure of Nominal
Phrases. In Functional Structure in DP and IP, ed. G. Cinque, 91120. Oxford
University Press.
Seely, T. Daniel. 2006. Merge, Derivation C-Command and Subcategorization in a LabelFree Syntax. In Miminalist Essays, ed. C. Boeckx, 182220. Amsterdam and
Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Seidl, Amanda Hallie. 2000. Minimal Indirect Reference: A Theory of the Syntax
Phonology Interface. Doctoral dissertation, University of Pennsylvania.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

221 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

221

Selkirk, Elisabeth. 1995. Sentence Prosody: Intonation, Stress and Phrasing. In


The Handbook of Phonological Theory, ed. J. Goldsmith, 55069. London: Blackwell.
Sener, Serkan & Daiko Takahashi. 2009. Argument Ellipsis in Japanese and Turkish.
University of Connecticut, Storrs, and Tohoku University.
Sigursson, Halldr rmann. 2002. To Be an Oblique Subject: Russian vs. Icelandic.
Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 20: 691724.
Sportiche, Dominique. 1988. A Theory of Floating Quantiers and its Corollaries for
Constituent Structure. Linguistic Inquiry 19: 42549.
Starke, Michal. 1995. On the Format for Small Clauses. In Syntax and Semantics 28:
Small Clauses, ed. A. Cardinaletti & M. Guasti, 23769. New York: Academic Press.
Stepanov, Arthur. 2000. WH-Scope Marking in Slavic. Studia Linguistica 54: 140.
Stjepanovic, Sandra. 2008. P-Stranding under Sluicing in a Non P Stranding Language.
Linguistic Inquiry 39: 17990.
Stowell, Timothy. 1981. Origins of Phrase Structure. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
1982. The Tense of Innitives. Linguistic Inquiry 13: 56170.
Stoyanova, Marina. 2008. Unique Focus: Languages without Multiple Wh-Questions.
Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Svenonius, Peter. 1994. Dependent Nexus: Subordinate Predication Structures in English and
the Scandinavian Languages. Doctoral dissertation, University of California Santa Cruz.
2002. Case Is Uninterpretable Aspect. Paper presented at the Perspectives on Aspect
Conference, University of Utrecht. Available at www.hum.uit.no/a/svenonius/papers/
Svenonius02CUA.pdf
2004. On the Edge. In Peripheries: Syntactic Edges and their Effects, ed. D. Adger,
C. de Cat & G. Tsoulas, 26187. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
2007a. Interpreting Uninterpretable Features. Linguistic Analysis 33: 375413.
2007b. The Position of Adjectives and Other Phrasal Modiers in the Decomposition
of DP. In Adjectives and Adverbs: Syntax, Semantics, and Discourse, ed.
L. McNally & Ch. Kennedy, 1642. Oxford University Press.
Swan, Oscar. 2002. A Grammar of Contemporary Polish. Bloomington, IN: Slavica
Publishers.
Szabolcsi, Anna. 1983. The Possessor that Ran away From Home. The Linguistic Review
3: 89102.
1994. The Noun Phrase. In Syntax and Semantics 27: The Syntactic Structure of
Hungarian, ed. F. Kiefer & K. Kiss, 179274. New York: Academic Press.
Szczegielniak, Adam 2008. Islands And Sluicing in Polish. In WCCFL 27: Proceedings
of the 27th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, ed. N. Abner & J. Bishop,
40412. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.
Takahashi, Masahiko. 2011. Some Consequences of Case-Marking in Japanese.
Doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut, Storrs.
Tanaka, Tomoyuki & Azusa Yokogoshi. 2010. The Rise of a Functional Category in
Small Clauses. Studia Linguistica 132.
Tellier, Christine. 1988. Universal Licensing: Implications for Parasitic Gap
Constructions. Doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut.
Thornton, Rosalind Jean. 1990. Adventures in Long-Distance Moving: The Acquisition
of Complex Wh-Questions. Doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut.
Tomaszewicz, Barbara. 2012. The Syntactic Position of Slavic by and its Effect on
Main Clause Phenomena. In Linguistik Aktuell/Linguistics Today 190: Main Clause

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847RFA.3D

222

222 [207222] 23.11.2013 10:45AM

References

Phenomena, ed. L. Aelbrecht, L. Haegeman & R. Nye. Amsterdam and Philadelphia:


John Benjamins.
Travis, Lisa de Mena. 2010. Inner Aspect: The Articulation of VP. Dordrecht: Springer.
Uriagereka, Juan. 1988. On Government. Doctoral dissertation, University of
Connecticut.
1999. Multiple Spell-Out. In Working Minimalism, ed. S. D. Epstein & N. Hornstein,
25182. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
2012. Spell-Out and the Minimalist Program. Oxford University Press.
Valois, Daniel. 1991. The Internal Syntax of DP. Doctoral dissertation, UCLA.
van Riemsdijk, Henk. 1978. A Case Study in Syntactic Markedness: The Binding Nature of
Prepositional Phrases. Lisse: Peter De Ridder Press.
1990. Functional Prepositions. In Unity in Diversity: Papers Presented to Simon C. Dik
on His 50th Birthday, ed. H. Pinkster & I. Geene, 22942. Dordrecht: Foris.
1998. Categorial Feature Magnetism: The Endocentricity and Distribution of
Projections. Journal of Comparative Germanic Linguistics 2: 148.
Wachowicz, Krystyna A. 1974. Against the Universality of a Single Wh-Question
Movement. Foundations of Language 11: 15566.
Watanabe, Akira. 1992. Subjacency and S-Structure Movement of Wh-in-Situ. Journal
of East Asian Linguistics 1: 25591.
Wexler, Kenneth & Peter Culicover. 1980. Formal Principles of Language Acquisition.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wiland, Bartosz. 2010. Overt Evidence from Polish Left Branch Extraction for
Punctuated Paths. Linguistic Inquiry 41: 33547.
Witko, Jacek. 2010a. Movement Theory of Control and CP-Innitives in Polish. In
Movement Theory of Control, ed. N. Hornstein & M. Polinsky, 4565. Amsterdam
and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Witko, Jacek. 2010b. On Lack of Case on the Subject of Innitives in Polish. Folia
Linguistica 1: 179237.
Yadroff, Michael. 1999. Formal Properties of Functional Categories: The Minimalist
Syntax of Russian Nominal and Prepositional Expressions. Doctoral dissertation,
University of Indiana.
Yadroff, Michael & Steven Franks. 2001. The Origin of Prepositions. In Current Issues
in Formal Slavic Linguistics, ed. G. Zybatow, U. Junghanns, G. Mehlhorn, &
L. Szucsich, 6979. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.
Zagona, Karen. 1988. Proper Government of Antecedentless VP In English and Spanish.
Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 6: 95128.
Zamparelli, Roberto. 1996. Layers in the Determiner Phrase. Doctoral dissertation,
University of Rochester.
Zubizarreta, Maria Luisa & Jean-Roger Vergnaud. 2005. Phrasal Stress and Syntax. In
The Blackwell Companion to Syntax, ed. M. Everaert & H. Van Riemsdijk, 52268.
Malden, MA: Blackwell.
1998. Focus, Prosody, and Word Order. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Zwart, C. Jan-Wouter. 1993. Dutch Syntax: A Minimalist Approach. Doctoral dissertation,
Groningen: Universiteitsdrukkerij.
1997. Morphosyntax of Verb Movement: A Minimalist Approach to the Syntax of Dutch.
Dordrecht: Kluwer.

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847IND.3D

223 [223228] 23.11.2013 10:52AM

Index

Abels, Klaus, 5, 37, 77, 89, 138, 139, 145, 146,


147, 148, 168, 173, 175
Abney, Steven P., 108, 139, 140
Abraham, Werner, 139, 140
Adger, David, 6, 7, 12, 15, 21, 47, 143, 185, 191,
192, 193, 194, 195, 196
Aelbrecht, Lobke, 64
Afrikaans, 80, 99
Agree, 8, 18, 2022, 31, 34, 35, 38
Long Distance Agree, 3741
Multiple Agree, 21, 122, 128
Agero-Bautista, Calixto, 100, 101
Aissen, Judith, 115
Aldridge, Edith, 95, 97, 98
Alexiadou, Artemis, 109, 167
Anagnostopoulou, Elena, 167
antecedent contained deletion, 102104,
107, 136
antilocality, 77, 105, 156, 173
applicatives
and passive movement, 155157
high as phases, 169
high versus low, 153154
Attract Closest, 37, 155
Bachrach, Asaf, 182, 183, 184
Bailyn, John Frederick, 126, 127, 128, 152,
159, 179
Baker, Mark C., 123, 128, 139, 176, 208
Baltin, Mark R., 103
Baski, Piotr, 51
Bare Output Conditions, 8, 14
Bare Phrase Structure, 11, 43, 80

Barros, Matthew, 63
Barss, Andrew, 4, 66, 74, 124, 152, 200
Belletti, Adriana, 35, 36, 208
Berber, 73
Bernstein, Judy, 108, 109
Bhatt, Rajesh, 37, 38
Biberauer, Theresa, 176
binding, 74, 75, 90, 112, 142, 148, 149
Biskup, Petr, 6, 66, 142, 200, 202, 203
Bittner, Maria, 109
Bobaljik, Jonathan, 36, 70, 77, 174
Boeckx, Cedric, 1, 2, 3, 12, 37, 67, 69, 71,
73, 181
Booij, Geert, 51
Borer-Chomsky conjecture, 74, 176
Bokovi, eljko, 19, 37, 40, 53, 54, 55, 62, 65,
70, 73, 77, 79, 90, 91, 115, 138, 149, 150,
171173, 174175, 179, 184, 199
Bowers, John, 124
Bresnan, Joan W., 190, 191
Bruening, Benjamin, 67, 82, 102, 103, 136
Bukusu, 152, 155
Bulgarian, 73
Bring, Daniel, 148
Burzios Generalization, 92
Butler, Jonny, 200
Cable, Seth, 95
Calabrese, Andrea, 73
Carnie, Andrew, 66, 124, 200
Carstens, Vicki, 4, 50, 51, 84, 121, 123
case
Accusative, 17, 91

223

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847IND.3D

224

224 [223228] 23.11.2013 10:52AM

Index

case (cont.)
case concord, 113, 121, 174
Dative, 114
Genitive, 35, 111, 173
Instrumental versus Nominative, 126128
Locative, 142
Nominative, 17, 19, 21, 108, 167
quirky, 35, 47
valuation, 21, 121123, 127
Castillo, Juan Carlos, 90
avar, Damir, 79
Cecchetto, Carlo, 12, 13, 67, 177
Chamorro, 97, 98, 115
Charlow, Simon, 117, 119
Cheng, Lisa, 19
Chi-Mwhi:ni:, 198
Chinese, 95
Chomsky, Noam, 1, 2, 3, 7, 8, 10, 11, 12, 13, 14,
16, 18, 19, 20, 21, 23, 28, 29, 30, 31, 32, 33,
43, 47, 48, 49, 50, 54, 62, 66, 67, 74, 80, 104,
108, 111, 112, 125, 148, 163, 168, 176, 189
Chukchee, 37, 38
Chung, Sandra, 64, 97, 98, 211
Cinque, Guglielmo, 109, 137, 139, 140, 142,
189, 191
Citko, Barbara, iv, 10, 12, 13, 22, 64, 95, 123,
126, 127, 128, 129, 158, 171, 182, 184, 211
Clause Partitioning, 203
Cole, Peter, 98
Collins, Chris, 13
complementizer agreement, 4, 5051, 8385
conceptual-intentional system, 8
Condition on Extraction Domains, 69
control, 88
exhaustive, 39
obligatory, 39
partial, 39
Copy Theory of Movement, 80
Corver, Norbert, 115, 172
Craenenbroeck, Jeroen van, 52, 53, 64, 145
Culicover, Peter W., 101, 102, 184, 222
cyclic linearization, 6, 185, 188
Danon, Gabi, 16, 121
Davies, William D., 114
Dayal, Veneeta, 4, 82
Den Dikken, Marcel, 3, 4, 5, 70, 100, 106, 124,
136, 138, 142, 160, 161166, 167, 169, 199

Diercks, Michael, 4, 50, 51


Diesing, Molly, 200, 201203
distributed deletion, 79
Distributed Morphology, 8, 104
Dobashi, Yoshihiko, 185
Dogil, Grzegorz, 51
Donati, Caterina, 12, 13
Dornisch, Ewa, 95
double objects, 30, 123, 151, 159, 164, See also
applicatives
DP Hypothesis, 170171
Parametrized DP Hypothesis, 174
Universal DP Hypothesis, 171
Drummond, Alex, 138
Drury, John, 90
Dubinsky, Stanley, 114
Dutch, 144
Dyakonova, Marina, 152, 158, 159
Dziwirek, Katarzyna, 54
Elbourne, Paul, 180, 181
ellipsis, 60, 64, 65, 88, 9394, 136, 150,
159160, 169, 174
nominal ellipsis, 65, 120121
pseudogapping, 88, 94
sluicing, 85, 145
swiping, 145
verb phrase ellipsis, 64, 88, 93, 102
Elordieta, Gorka, 185
Embick, David, 51
Emonds, Joseph, 116, 135, 139, 144
En, Mrvet, 17
Engdahl, Elisabet, 116
Epstein, Samuel D., 18, 29, 37, 50, 59, 70, 90, 199
equidistance, 47, 48, 165
exceptional case marking, 5455, 88
expletive subject, 24, 36
extraction restriction, 98
Fanselow, Ginsbert, 79
Feature Inheritance, 3, 4647, 4950, 5557, 85,
88, 133, 170, 176
and Donate, 52
and Keep, 52, 85
and Share, 52, 85
from Above, 53
from Below, 53
underinheritance, 52

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847IND.3D

225 [223228] 23.11.2013 10:52AM

Index
features
EPP feature, 32, 47, 69, 75, 167
feature valuation, 18, 68, 110, 111112
interpretability versus valuation, 1920
interpretable, 14, 15
interpretable versus uninterpretable, 1415
uninterpretable, 3, 14, 18, 30, 31, 4647, 60,
110, 176
Felser, Claudia, 4, 6, 67, 71, 78, 79, 80, 81, 82, 177
Finnish, 17
Fox, Danny, 6, 74, 75, 90, 100, 101, 185, 187,
188, 219
Frampton, John, 9, 19
Franks, Steven, 51, 79, 140, 184, 209
Frascarelli, Mara, 1
Frederici, Angela, 139
French, 17
Froud, Karen, 139
Gallego, ngel J., 1, 3, 5, 12, 13, 31, 68, 69, 160,
161, 166, 167, 169, 176
Gavruseva, Elena, 115
Gengel, Kirsten, 64
German, 17, 79, 82, 108, 203
Goal, 20, 21, 22, 38, 40, 110, 122
Green, Georgia M., 151
Grimshaw, Jane, 139
Grohmann, Kleanthes, 1, 2, 3, 7, 32, 37, 69,
77, 90
Gutmann, Sam, 9, 19
Haegeman, Liliane, 4, 50, 51, 52, 53, 85
Hale, Ken, 66, 109
Halle, Morris, 8, 189
Hankamer, Jorge, 64
Harves, Stephanie, 124, 126, 129
Hermon, Gabriella, 98
Heycock, Caroline, 75, 214
Hindi-Urdu, 38, 83, 95, 96
Hiraiwa, Ken, 5, 21, 108, 122
Holmberg, Anders, 48, 64, 187, 208
Holmbergs Generalization, 48, 187
Hornstein, Norbert, 7, 23, 32, 78, 101,
103, 138
Horstein, Norbert, 136
Horvath, Julia, 82
Hovav, Malka Rappaport, 58
Huang, Cheng-Teh James, 69, 112

225

Hungarian, 82, 95, 108, 114


Iatridou, Sabine, 181
Icelandic, 35, 36, 47, 149
Inclusiveness Condition, 12, 13
Indonesian, 97, 98
interface conditions, 8
inverse scope, 118, 174
Irish, 73, 84
Ishihara, Shinichiro, 185, 191, 198
islands, 68, 7374, 184
Italian, 73
Jackendoff, Ray, 120, 121, 138
Japanese, 65, 152, 180, 198
Jayaseelan, Karattuparambil, 95
Jeong, Youngmi, 156
Johnson, Kyle, 64, 128
Jonas, Dianne, 36
Kahnemuyipour, Arsalan, 6, 185, 189, 190,
195197
Kasai, Hironobu, 101
Kashmiri, 96
Katz, Jerrold, 80
Katzir, Roni, 182, 183, 184
Kayne, Richard, 43, 54, 80, 118, 138, 139,
185, 191
Kennedy, Christopher, 103
Keyser, Jay, 66
Khomitsevich, Olga, 55
Kilega, 51, 84
Kinande, 198
Kinyalolo, Kasangati Kikuni Wabongambilu, 84
Kinyarwanda, 155
Kiparsky, Paul, 17
Kiss, Katalin ., 95
Koopman, Hilda, 142
Koppen, Marjo van, 4, 85
Kratzer, Angelika, 6, 185, 191
labels, 1213
labeling algorithm, 12
Laenzlinger, Christopher, 109
Lahne, Antje, 4, 59, 67, 70, 71, 79, 82, 97, 100
Landau, Idan, 35, 38, 39, 40, 41
Larson, Richard, 101, 102, 103, 117, 118, 119
Lasnik, Howard, 36, 54, 55, 138, 152

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847IND.3D

226 [223228] 23.11.2013 10:52AM

226

Index

Late Vocabulary Insertion, 8


Lebeaux, David, 74, 75, 90
Left Branch Condition, 172
left branch extraction, 99, 134135, 172173
Legate, Julie Anne, 4, 16, 31, 52, 53, 71, 100,
103, 104, 106, 107, 155, 190, 194
Levin, Beth, 58
Lexical Array, 8, 28
subarray, 28, 29
Limburgian, 85
Linear Correspondence Axiom, 43, 80, 185
Lobeck, Anne, 64, 88, 120, 121
locality, 21, 23, 47, 69, 155
long distance wh-movement, 7273, 75, 83, See
also successive cyclic movement
Lubukusu, 51
Luganda, 197
Lutz, Uli, 4, 82, 217
MacDonald, Jonathan Eric, 195
Mahajan, Anoop Kumar, 38, 83
Manetta, Emily, 4, 82, 95, 96, 97
Mapping Hypothesis, 200201
Marantz, Alec, 8, 104, 152
Martin, Roger Andrew, 55
Marui, Franc Lanko, 5, 42, 119, 177, 179,
180, 182
Matushansky, Ora, 5, 37, 59, 61, 66, 110, 113,
117, 119, 121, 122, 124, 126, 129, 177
May, Richard, 118
May, Robert, 67, 103, 117, 181
Mayalalam, 95
McCloskey, James, 4, 76, 77, 83, 84, 98, 99,
100, 149
McDaniel, Dana, 4, 80, 82
McGinnis, Martha, 1, 5, 151, 155, 157, 170,
197, 198
Megerdoomian, Karine, 17
Merchant, Jason, 64, 65, 85, 86, 88, 93, 94
Merge, 8
External Merge, 1012
Internal Merge, 1314
Parallel Merge, 10, 22
Merge over Move, 2, 2325
Migdalski, Krzysztof, 51
Minimal Link Condition, 155
Miyagawa, Shigeru, 31, 152, 179, 198
Moro, Andrea, 132, 166

Mller, Gereon, 3, 33, 37, 59, 69, 70, 199


multidominance, 101, 183
Munn, Alan, 17
Muysken, Pieter, 139
negative polarity item licensing, 101,
113, 136
Nespor, Marina, 188
Nissenbaum, Jonathan, 101, 102
nuclear scope, 66
nuclear stress, 60, 189191
and phases, 191193
Nuclear Stress Rule, 189, 190, 191, 195
null subject languages, 167
Numeration, 9, 28
Nunes, Jairo, 7, 32, 90, 101
Oehrle, Richard T., 151
order preservation, 185188
Ouali, Hamid, 52, 85
Pair List readings, 100
Pak, Marjorie, 185, 191, 197
parasitic gaps, 95, 101102, 113, 117
partial wh-movement, 76, 81, 82, See also scope
marking
passives and unaccusatives
and nuclear stress, 190, 193194
as phases, 104107
Pereltsvaig, Asya, 126, 171
Persian, 190, 196
Pesetsky, David, 6, 12, 17, 19, 20, 21, 35, 53, 55,
90, 167, 185, 187, 188, 219
Peterson, David A., 152, 155
Phase Condition, 68, 167
Phase Extension, 5, 161166
Phase Impenetrability Condition, 3, 4, 3134,
41, 49, 98, 130
and locality, 3741
and phasehood diagnostics, 6768
PIC1 versus PIC2, 33, 3637, 47, 132, 161
Strong PIC, 33
Weak PIC, 33
Phase Sliding, 5, 161, 166168
Picallo, M. Carme, 109
Pinker, Steven, 9
Plessis, Hans Du, 78, 80
Polinsky, Maria, 37, 38

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847IND.3D

227 [223228] 23.11.2013 10:52AM

Index
Polish, 16, 35, 51, 55, 79, 82, 83, 86, 87, 95, 99,
111, 113, 121, 126, 129, 134, 140, 141, 145,
149, 150, 158, 167, 172, 173, 174, 203
possessor extraction, 115
Postal, Paul, 78, 80, 101, 215
Potsdam, Eric, 37, 38
predication phrases, 124125
extraction from, 129131
Preminger, Omer, 9
preposition stranding, 78, 85, 86, 99, 143144,
145148, 168, 175
prepositions
directional, 141143, 145
functional, 140, 145
lexical, 140, 145
locative, 141143, 145
Probe, 12, 20, 21, 22, 48, 84, 110, 122, 126, 127,
139, 206
Progovac, Ljiljana, 171
Pylkknen, Liina, 151, 152, 153, 154, 170
quantier oat. See quantier stranding
quantier lowering, 202
quantier raising, 66, 67, 102, 107, 117119,
136, 150, 181
quantier stranding, 7677, 90, 98, 133134
Quinoli, Carlos, 112
Rackowski, Andrea, 97, 99
Radkevich, Nina, 5, 142, 148, 149
Ramchand, Gillian, 143
Rappaport, Gilbert C., 171
Rausch, Philip, 108
reconstruction, 4, 7475, 90, 100101, 106, 179
Reinhart, Tanya, 148, 149
Relator Phrase, 164
restrictive clause, 66
Reuland, Eric, 148, 149
Richards, Marc, 3, 18, 33, 36, 37, 41, 49, 50, 53,
60, 162
Richards, Norvin, 1, 73, 97, 99
Richardson, Kylie, 126
right node raising, 62, 182184
Ritter, Elizabeth, 109
Rizzi, Luigi, 35, 73, 137
Roberts, Ian, 128
Romani, 80
Romanian, 73

227

Rooryck, Johan, 54
Ross, John Robert, 172
Rouveret, Alain, 64
Rubach, Jerzy, 51
Rubin, Edward, 126
Rudin, Catherine, 73
Russian, 17, 82, 83, 126, 152
Rutkowski, Pawe, 171
Sabbagh, Joseph, 184
Sag, Ivan, 64
Saito, Mamoru, 179, 180
Samuels, Bridget, 185
Sato, Yosuke, 86, 97, 98
Sauerland, Uli, 117, 119, 180, 181
scattered deletion, 79
Scheer, Tobias, 185
scope, 184, 198199
scope marking, 4, 8183, 96
Scott, Gary-John, 109
Scottish Gaelic, 143, 190
Seely, T. Daniel, 13, 18, 50, 59, 70,
90, 199
Seidl, Amanda Hallie, 197
Selkirk, Elisabeth, 6, 185, 190, 191
semantic types, 66, 199
ener, Serkan, 65
sensorimotor system, 8
sentence fragments, 6162
sequence of tense, 55
Serbo-Croatian, 172
short wh-movement, 95
Shortest Link, 155
Sichel, Ivy, 181
Sigursson, Halldr rmann, 35, 47
Single Answer readings, 101
Slovak, 149
small clauses, 124, 131
Somali, 73
Spell-Out, 60, 61
Delayed Spell-Out, 182
Multiple Spell-Out, 1, 3, 4143, 177, 185
Non-Simultaneous Spell-Out, 43
Spellee, 195
Spell-Out domain, 32, 161, 185, 195
Sportiche, Dominique, 77
Starke, Michal, 134
Stepanov, Arthur, 4, 82, 83

{DESKTOP}NEW FOLDER//9781107040847IND.3D

228 [223228] 23.11.2013 10:52AM

228
Stjepanovic, Sandra, 86
Stowell, Timothy, 55, 88
Stranding Generalization, 145
Strong Minimalist Thesis, 8
subject to object raising. See exceptional case
marking
successive cyclic movement, 4, 32, 57, 67, 70,
7576, 78, 80, 83, 8891, 94
Svenonius, Peter, 5, 15, 17, 47, 109, 124
Swan, Oscar, 111
Szabolcsi, Anna, 108, 114, 115
Szczegielniak, Adam, 86
Tagalog, 97
Takahashi, Daiko, 65, 179
Tamazight Berber, 52
Tanaka, Tomoyuki, 124, 125, 131, 132, 133
Tellier, Christine, 108, 116
Thornton, Rosalind Jean, 80
Tomaszewicz, Barbara, 129
Torrego, Esther, 12, 17, 19, 20, 21, 53, 167
Transfer, 19, 30, 4142, 177, 180
Multiple Transfer, 178, 180
Non-Simultaneous Transfer, 179, 180, 181
Simultaneous Transfer, 177
transitive expletive, 36
Travis, Lisa, 195
Tsez, 37, 38
Tsujioka, Takae, 152
Turkish, 17

Index
Tzez, 38
Tzotzil, 115
Uriagereka, Juan, 1, 43, 115, 172
Valois, Daniel, 108, 109, 113, 115, 116
Value-Transfer Simultaneity, 49
van Riemsdijk, Henk, 139, 140, 143, 144
variable binding, 90, 100, 101, 106
Vergnaud, Jean-Roger, 189, 190
Vicente, Luis, 63
Vogel, Irene, 188
voice mismatches, 94
Wachowicz, Krystyna A., 73
Weinberg, Amy, 78
West Flemish, 51
West Ulster English, 76, 77, 99, 149
Wexler, Kenneth, 184
wh-agreement, 98
wh-copying, 4, 6, 76, 79, 8081
Wiland, Bartosz, 4, 99
Wurmbrand, Susi, 70, 174
Yadroff, Michael, 139, 140
Yokogoshi, Azusa, 124, 125, 131, 132, 133
Zagona, Karen, 64
Zamparelli, Roberto, 109
Zwart, C. Jan-Wouter, 4

Potrebbero piacerti anche