Sei sulla pagina 1di 448

ts

;'

i^inf'-

Ml'

''"'

T'|.'';i
t^Jrr*-*''

*!''V-

/''

=-

m'J;^-;

;>(t?fr,fitk,

',

'

.,\

%'p

'

;^'^

>

,.

'

'-:

.-HI''

'

!:"

<

':

'

I>

Digitized by the Internet Archive


in

2011 with funding from


University of Toronto

http://www.archive.org/details/socratessocraticOOzell

AUTHORISED ENGLISH TRANSLATION


OF

BE. ZELLBE'S

WOEK

ON THE

PHILOSOPHY OF THE GREEKS


The

PRAE-SOOBATIO SCHOOLS,
Being a History of Greek Philosophy from the Earliest Period
to the

Time

sanction.

of

SOCKATES.

Crown

Translated with the Author's

8vo.

[In pre;paration.

II

SOCRATES and

the

Translated by the Eev.

Crown

revised.

SOCRATIO SCHOOLS.

Oswald

J.

Keichel, M.A.

New Edition,

8vo. price lOs. Qd.

Ill

ARISTOTLE

and

ELDER

the

PERI-

PATETICS.
Translated with the Author's sanction.

Crown

8vo.

[In preparation.
IV

The STOICS, EPICUREAITS, and SCEPTICS.


Translated by the Rev.

Oswald

J.

Eeichel, M.A.

Crown Svo

price 14s.

PLATO

and the

OLDER ACADEMY.

Translated by Sarah Fbances Alleyne and Alfbed Goodwin,


M.A. Fellow and Lecturer of Balliol College, Oxford. Crown
Svo. price IBs.

London,

LONGMANS &

CO.

Lately published, in cro-wn 8vo. price I85.

PLATO AND THE OLDER ACADEMY.


Translated with the Author's sanction from the

German

of

EDUARD ZELLER,

D.

ALLEYNE

By SARAH FEANCES

and

ALFRED GOODWIN,

M.A.

Fellow and Lecturer of Balliol College, Oxford.

THE ACADEMY.
The compliment of translation is well deserved by the patient
erudition and masterly arrangement of the original, which is an indispensable aid to the readers of Plato and Aristotle. Of this translation
'

it can be said that in all essential respects


equivalent of Zeller's book.'

it

may

be relied on as an

EDUCATIONAL TIMES.
The work must become indispensable

to the student of Plato.


It
consists of sixteen chapters, in which Plato's life, the order of his writings, the character of his Philosophy, his Physics, his Ethics, and his
'

Religion are treated with great detail and minuteness. It is, of course
impossible in these pages to do more with so vast a work not vast,
however, in bulk, being a book of 600 pages than to call attention to
it, and, if possible, to give some idea of its style.'

SATITRDAY REVIEW.
departments Dr. Zeller's book is both comprehensive
and trustworthy. He seems to have said the last word on Greek philosophy and his volumes are among those monuments of nineteenthcentury German research which make one wonder what will remain for
the scholars of the twentieth century to do. He brings to his task the
two essential qualities vast learning, and the power of moving at
pleasure in the rarefied atmosphere of abstractions
It is evident
that jNIr. Goodwin, to whom this part of the undertaking fell, had no
sinecure in his work of translation and verification.
He has gone
bravely through with it, however, and both his work and that of Miss
Alleyne, who translated the text, leave almost nothing to be desired.'

In

all its

'

This

is

GUARDIA]>3".
Eduard Zeller's Plato und

a translation of Dr.

die dltere

work

of great value to students of Plato, but hitherto only


The text has been admirably
in part accessible to English readers.
translated by Miss Alleyne, who has proved herself fully competent to
deal with the philosophical terminology of the German original, and to
execute a translation which does not, like some translations, proclaim
itself as such by an un-English structure of its phrases and sentences.
Copious notes and references have been added by Mr. Goodwin, Fellow
of Balliol College, who shares with Miss Alleyne the responsibility of
the work. The value of Dr. Z.sller's work has been amply acknowledged
by Professor Jowept in the Preface to the second edition of his Plato
and this translation of it will be a great boon to many students of
Plato who (as its Authors suggest in their Preface) are less familiar with
Akade'tnie, a

German than with Greek.

London,

LONGMANS &

CO.

SOCEATEg

LONDON
IMilNTIiD BY
SPOTTLSWOODE AND CO., XEW-STUEET SQUAUE
AND PARLIAMENT STREET
:

OOLS
N SLATED

FROM miE

Tli/RD

GERMAN EDITION OF

D^ E.^'ZELLER
BY

OSWALD

J.

REICHEL,

B.C.L.

& M.A.

VICAR OP SPERSHOLT, BERKS

.SECOXD

AND ENTIRELY NEW ED[TION

LONDON

LONGMANS, GREEN, AND


1877

All

iijh Is

rttirr Cfii

CO.

>;

INSTITUTE OF

TORONTO

^^mmi STUDIES

5,

CANADA.

^A2 301S32

PEEFACE
In offering to the English reader a
that part of

new

edition of

Dr Zeller's Philosophie der Griechen

which treats of Socrates and the imperfect Socratic


Schools, the translator
culties of the task

is

not unaware of the

which he has undertaken.

on the one hand, such a translation be too


reader

may

find it

more

difficult to

diffi-

For

if,

literal, the

understand than

the original, and expend a labour in disentangling


the thread of a sentence which were better spent in

grasping

its

meaning.

much freedom be

If,

on the other hand, too

allowed, the charge

may be

justly

preferred, that the rendering does not faithfully re-

present the original.

The present

translator has en-

deavoured to steer a middle course between these

two extremes, aiming at reproducing the meaning of

Dr Zeller's work,
where

it

whilst reducing

the sentences,

seemed necessary, by breaking them up.

In

order to avoid inaccuracies, he has once more care-

PREFACE.

vi

fully

gone over the whole,

so that

as a second edition is really a

what

new

is

now offered

translation

from

the third Grerman edition.

The

writer

been able to

is

realise his

find it a

work of

imperfectly he has

own standard

but believing that there

who

how

well aware

is

of excellence

a large class of students

toil to

read

Dr Zellek's work

in the original, he submits this attempt to

their wants, soliciting for

Glenfriaes, Torquay

May,

1877.

it

a gentle criticism.

meet

CONTENTS
PART

I.

THE GENERAL STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

CHAPTER

I.

THE INTELLECTUAL DEVELOPMENT OF GREECE IN


THE FIFTH CENTURY B.C.
PAGE

Introduction.
A.

B.

The problem proposed to philosophy

The problem solved by

political events

1.

Political unsettledness

2.

Athens a centre of union

The problem solved by literature


1.

jEschylus Sophocles

The Tragedians.
pides

Simonides

2.

Didactic Poetry.

3.

The Historians. Herodotus


Comed)^ Aristophanes

Euri-

4.

Bacchylides Pin21

dar

C.

Thucydides

The problem solved by new forms of religious worship

.^7

24

29
.

32

CONTENTS.

viii

CHAPTER

II.

CHARACTER AND PROGRESS OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY


IN THE FIFTH CENTURY B.C.
I'AGK

A. Distinction of Socratic

from pre-Socratic Philosophy

1.

Knowledge substituted

2.

Study of conceptions substituted for study of


nature

for tradition

...

2.

Definition of a conception
Theory of conceptions expanded

2.

>y

.40
4j

.42

C. Distinction of Socratic
1.

38
on

B. Importance of the doctrine of conceptions


1.

38

from post- Aristotelian Philosophy


to be possible
Morality not pursued independently

Knowledge believed

...

43
44
45

D. The Socratic Philosophy developed


1.

Socrates

2.

Plato

3.

Aristotle

4.

Difficulty caused

i-.
'

'48

'

...

by Socratic Schools

PART

j^q

50

II.

.SOCRATES.

CHAPTER

III.

THE LIFE OF SOCRATES.


A.

Youth and early training

B. Active life

....

59

'
.

ei

CONTENTS.

CHAPTER

ix

TV.

THE CHARACTER OF SOCRATES.

....
....

PAGE
70

.....
.....

82

A. Greatness of the character of Socrates


B.

Greek peculiarities in his character

C.

Prominent features in his character

D.

The

^aiii6viov

1.

False views of the

2.

Kegarded by Socrates as an oracle


Limited in its application
Correct view of the Saifxdfiop

ii.

4.

hai}x6viov

CHAPTER

74
77

82
84

90

94

98

Y.

SOURCES AND CHARACTERISTICS OF THE

PHILOSOPHY OF SOCRATES.
A.

Xenophon and Plato considered

B. General point of
G.

as authorities

104

view of Socrates

Theory of knowledge of conceptions considered

.109

D. Moral value of this theory

113

E. Its subjective character

116

CHAPTER

YI.

THE PHILOSOPHICAL METHOD OF SOCRATES.


A.

Knowledge

B. Search for

of ignorance the first step

knowledge the next

Eros and

Irony
C.

121

Formation of conceptions the third step

124
.

128

CONTENTS.

CHAPTER

yil.

SUBSTANCE OF THE TEACHING OF SOCRATES


A. The subject-matter restricted to Ethics
B. Virtue

is

knowledgethe leading thought

ETHICS.

PAGE
134

of the

Socratic Ethics
C.

140

The Good and Eudaemonism


knowledge about the Good

1.

Theoretically Virtue

2.

Practically the

3.

Inconsistency of Socratic Morality

is

Good determined by custom

147

or

utility

148

.151

.....

D. Particular Moral Eolations


1. Personal independence

160
161
163

2.

Friendship

3.

The State

165

4.

Universal philanthropy

I70

CHAPTEE

VIII.

SUBSTANCE OF THE TEACHING OF SOCRATES, CONTINUED.


NATURE GOD MAN.

A.

View

of

Nature

172

God and the Worship of God


Language about the Gods taken from popular use
God conceived as the Keason of the world
The Worship of God

B. Notion of
1.

2.
3.

C.

Dignity and Immortality of

XENOPHON AND PLATO.

175
175

176
I77

man

CHAPTER

78

IX.

SOCRATES AND THE SOPHISTS.

1.

Xenophon as an authority
Xenophon in harmony with Plato and

2.

Schleiermacher's objections refuted

A. Value of

B. Importance of Socrates for the age in


C. Relation of Socrates to the Sophists

Aristotle
.

which he lived

181

183

185
187

CONTENTS.

CHAPTER

xi

X.

THE TRAGIC END OF SOCRATES.


A. Circumstances connected with his trial and death
1.

2.
3.
4.

PAGE

The Accusation
The Defence
The Sentence
His Death

B. Causes

which led to

193
196
198

200

his sentence

202

1.

The Sophists innocent

2.

Personal animosity only partially the cause

3. Political party-feeling only partially involved


4.

........

202
205
210

The teaching of Socrates generally believed to be


dangerous

213

220

C. Justification of the sentence

2.

Unfounded charges brought against Socrates


The views of Socrates subversive of old views

226

3.

Eolation borne by his views to cot emporary views

231

4.

Result of his death

235

1.

authority

political

PART

life

religion

220

of
.

III.

THE IMPERFECT FOLLOWERS OF SOCRATES.

CHAPTER

XI.

THE SCHOOL OF SOCRATES POPULAR PHILOSOPHY.


XENOPHON j<:scniNES.
A. School of Socrates

236

B.

Xenophon

239

C.

^schines

245

D. Simmias and Cebes

246

CONTENTS.

xii

CHAPTEK

XII.

THE MEGARIAX AND THE ELEAN-ERETRIAN SCHOOLS.


The Megarians

PAGJi

A. History of the School

249

B. Their Doctrine
1.

2.

255

and Becoming
The Good
Being-

C. Eristic
1.

2.

264

Euclid
Eubulides

.........
.....

4.

Alexinus
Diodorus on

5.

Philo.

3.

Motion Destruction the

Pogsible

The Possible Hjrpothetical sentences


Meaning of words
Stilpo. Subject and Predicate
the Good Cvnic
,

6.

259
262

268
269
273

........

Morality

The Elean-Eretrian

265
268

275

School.

A. History of the School

279

B. Doctrine of the School

281

CHAPTER

XIII.

THE CYNICS.
A. History of the 0311108

.......

B. Teaching of the Cynics


1.

2.

C.

.......

Depreciation of theoretical knowledge


Logic

Negative conditions

2.

Positive side

3.

Wisdom and

Good and Evil

3Q2
.

Virtue
Folly

291
291

295

Cynic theory of Morality


1.

284

301

3Xq
.

313

CONTENTS.

Xlll

....

D. Practical results of Cynic teaching


1.
2.

E.

314

Renunciation of Self
Renunciation of Society. Family Life Civil Life

.....

Modesty

3.

PAGK

31.5

311>

Renunciation of Relig-ion

327

Cynic influence on Society

331

CHAPTER

XIV.

THE CYRENAICS.
A. History of the Cyrenaics

.337

B. Teaching of the Cyrenaics


1.

2.
3.

4.
5.

344

General position
Feelings the only object of knowledge
Pleasure and pain
The Highest Good
Modified form of the extreme view
.

34g
.

.'.".!
.

C. Practical Life of the Cyrenaics

2.

E.

The

2.

Theodorus
Hegesias

3.

Anniceris

35f>

361

369

......

375

Relation of their philosophy


Points of resemblance

later Cyrenaics

1.

347
352
354

....

D. Relation of their teaching to Socrates


1.

369

376
3jg

.......

3gQ
383

CHAPTER XV.
RETROSPECT.
A. Inconsistencies of the imperfect Socratic
Schools

B. These Schools

more closely related

to Socrates than to

the Sophists
C.

Importance of

J'^^^^^

tliese

386

3g-

Schools

389
'.
.

393

PAET

I.

THE GENERAL STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

CHAPTER

I.

THE INTELLECTUAL DEVELOPMENT OF GREECE IN


THE FIFTH CENTURY.

The

intellectual life of

Oreece had reached a point

towards the close of the


choice lay before

it

fifth

century, in which the

of either giving

up philosophy

altogether, or attempting a thorough transformation

upon a new

basis.

wholly extinct

The

but

all

older schools were not indeed

dependence in their systems

had been shaken, and a general disposition to doubt


had set in. From the Sophists men had learnt
to
everything in question to attack or defend
with equal readiness every opinion. Belief in
the
call

truth of
laws,

human

had been

ideas, or in the
lost.

validity of moral

Not only

enquiries respecting
nature, which had engaged the attention of
thinkers
for upwards of a century and a half,
had become
distasteful,

place to a

expression
0.

but even philosophy

itself

had given

mere superficial facility of thought and


and the acquisition of attainments useful

chap.
^

STATU OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

1
Chap.
I.

Prohlem
proposedto
2)hilosophy
in the fifth
century.

only for the purposes of social


of things naturally

life.

Yet

this state

suggested the need of a

new

method, which would avoid the defects and one-

more cautious
treatment of scientific questions. The way thereto
had not only been indirectly prepared by the clearing away of previous speculation, but the very
instrument of research had been sharpened by the
quibbles and subtleties of sophistry ample material,
too, for the erection of a new structure lay to hand
sidedness of previous systems by a

Moreover,

in the labours of preceding philosophers.

by the practical turn which the Sophistic enquiries


had taken, a new field of research was opened up, the
more careful cultivation of which gave promise of a

Would a
creative genius be forthcoming, able to make use of
these materials, and to direct thought into a new

rich harvest for speculative philosophy.

channel?

Before this question

stood at the time


A. The
prohlem
solved by
political
events.

(1) Political

unsettledness.

when

philosophy

Grreek

Socrates appeared.

by the
course which political circumstances, moral life, and
general culture had taken. Between these and philo-

The answer was determined

sophy the connection

is

in great part

at all times close

in the case of the Sophistic teaching,

it

yet lately,

had been

The most sweeping


more than ever apparent.
changes had taken place in the fifth century in
Never has a nation had a more rapid or
Greece.
miore brilliant career of military glory in union with

Yet never has


First came the great
that career been sooner over.
deeds of the Persian war, then the rich bloom of art

high culture than had the Greeks.

':

ILLUSTRATED BY POLITICS.
of the age of Pericles
internal

conflict

which

following immediately that

Chap.
'

wasted the strength and

prosperity of the free states of Greece in unhallowed

domestic quarrels, which sacrificed anew the indepen-

dence so hardly won from the foreigner, undermined


her freedom, threw her moral notions into confusion,

and irretrievably ruined the character of her people.


A progress which elsewhere required centuries was in
her case compressed within a few generations.
the pulse of national

life

When

beats so fast, the general

must be exposed to a quick and susceptible


change and when so much that is great happens in
spirit

so short a time,

an abundance of ideas

up, awaiting only a regulating

hand

is

sure to crop

to range

them-

selves into scientific systems.

Of

greatest importance for the future of philo-

(2)

sophy was the position won by Athens since the close


of the Persian war.

u}iion

a common brotherhood had dawned


upon the Hellenes with a force unknown before.
All that fancy had painted in the legend of the
Trojan war seemed to be realised in actual history
sciousness of

Hellas standing as a united nation opposed to the

The headship of this many-membered body


had fallen in the main to Athens, and herewith that
city had become the centre of all intellectual movements, 'the Prytaneum of the wisdom of Greece.'
East.

the fm-ther development of philosophy.

No

So called by Hippias in Plato, Prot. 337, D.


B 2

doubt

and

^*i^^'^y-

In that great conflict the con-

This circumstance had a most beneficial effect on

Athens

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.


Chap.
I.

tendency may be noticed in the several schools to come


forth from their isolation it maybe seen in the natural
;

philosophers of the fifth century that an active interchange of thought was being carried on between the

East and theWest of Grreece and now that the Sophists


had begun to travel from one end to the other of the
;

Hellenic world, to carry to Thessaly the eloquence of


Sicily, to Sicily the doctrines of Heraclitus, these
various sources of culture could not fail gradually to
flow together into one mighty stream. Still it was of
great importance that a solid bed should be hollowed

out for this stream and

its course directed towards a


This result was brought about by the rise
of the Attic philosophy.
After that, in Athens, as

fixed end.

the

common

centre of the Grrecian world, the various

lines of pre-Socratic enquiry

had met and

crossed,

Socrates was able to found a more comprehensive


philosophy; and ever afterwards Grreek philosophy

continued to be so firmly tied to Athens, that down


to the time of the New Academy that city was the
birthplace of all schools historically important.

was even their

last place of refuge before

It

the final

extinction of ancient philosophy.


B.

The

lyrohlem
solved hy
literature.

The

(1)
tragedians.

To make clear, by means of the literary remains


we possess, the change which took place in the Greek
mode of thought during the fifth century, and to
estimate the worth and extent of the contributions
yielded to philosophy by the general culture of the
time, the

appealed

great Athenian tragedians

to.

For tragedy

is

may

be

first

better suited than any

other kind of poetry to arouse ethical reflection, to

ILLUSTMATED

BY

TRAGEDIANS.

pourtray the moral consciousness of a people,


and to
express the highest sentiments of which
an age,

Chap.

or

at least individual prominent spirits


in an age, are
capable.
Every deeper tragic plot rests on the conflicting calls of duty and interest.
To make clear

'

the origin of the plot, to unfold the


action psychologically, to produce the general
impression intended,
the poet must bring these two points of
view before us,
allowing each to advocate its cause in
lively speech
and counter-speech he must go into the
analysis of
moral consciousness, weigh what is right and
what

is

faulty in

human

action,

and expose

it

to view.

As

a poet he will do this, always having


regard to the
particular case before him. Still, even
this

he cannot
do without comparing one case with another,
without
going back to general experience, to the
generally
received

notions

short, to general

respecting right

and wrong in
moral conceptions. Hence tragic

poetry must always give a lasting


impetus to scientific speculation on moral
conduct and its laws,
affording,
itself,

too,

for

such reflection ample

material

and that to a certain extent already prepared,

and inviting partly use, partly correction.


Moreover,
masmuch as moral convictions were in the case of
^

the Greeks, as in the case of other


nations, originally
bound up with religious convictions, and
inasmuch
as this connection particularly affects
tragedy owing
to the legendary subjects with
which it deals, it
'

On

this 'point

compare the

excellent remarks of
Hist, of Greece, P. II.

Grote,
c.

67,

vol.

viii.

137, ed.

1870'

vii. 7,

ed 1872

vol

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.


Chap,

follows that all that has been said respecting the

connection between tragedy and principles of morality


applies also to the connection between tragedy
principles of theology

and

nay more, in exactly the

same way tragedy must busy itself with the nature


and state of men whose deeds and fate it depicts.
In all these respects a most decided and thorough
change in Grreek thought may be observed in the
three

generations, whose character finds

such

fit-

ting expression in the three successive tragedians,


iEschylus, Sophocles, and Euripides.

Without going

so far as to attribute to the poets themselves every

word which they put into the mouths of

their heroes,

the general tone of their sentiments may be


gathered partly from their general treatment of the
still

materials, partly

from their individual utterances,

with no lack of certainty.


{a)

Ms-

chylm.

an earnestness of purpose, a
depth of religious feeling, an overwhelming force and
majesty, worthy of a man of ancient virtue, who had
In ^schylus there

is

himself taken part in the great battles with the


At the same time there is a something
Persians.

and violent about him, which a time of heroic


deeds and sacrifices, of mighty capabilities and inbitter

spiriting results, could neither soften

dispense with.

The

down nor yet

spirit of his tragedies is that of

an untamed, masculine mind, seldom moved by


softer feelings, but spell-bound by reverence for the
gods, by the recognition of an unbending moral
order, by resignation to a destiny from which there
is

no escape.

Never were the Titan-like defiance of

ILLUSTRATED BY TRAGEDIANS.
unbridled strength, the wild fury of passion and

Chap.

might of fate, the paroxysms of


divine vengeance, more thrillingly painted than by
^schylus. At the bottom of all his sentiments lies
frenzy, the crushing

reverence for the divine powers

'____

yet these are grouped

almost monotheistically together, in his vast vision,

almighty power.

as one

will always

notice of

comes

men

What Zeus

to pass, even

says happens

though

it

his

escape the

no mortal can do aught against his

none can escape the decision of heaven, or


rather of destiny,^ over which Zeus himself is powerless.'*
In face of this divine power man feels himself

will

weak and frail


shadow of smoke

his

thoughts are fleeting as the

his life

like a picture

is

which a

That man mistake not his


that he learn not to overrate what is
that he be not indignant with the Grods

sponge washes out.^


position,

human ,^
when

in affliction,^ that his

mind

soar not too high,

that the grain of guilt planted by pride grows to a

harvest of tears,-

glowing words,

such

flashes

is

the teaching which, with

on us in every page of the

poet.

Not even ^schylus, however, was able

to grasp

these ideas in their purity, or to rise above the contradiction which runs not only through Grreek tragedy,

but through the whole of the Grreek view of


'

Suppl. 598

Agamemnon,

H85.
;

On

1327.

Niobe, Fr. 155, (154).


Fragm. 369 Dindorf. Stoha-us. Serm, 108, 43, attributes
the words to Euripides.
6

Prometh. 550.
^ Pers. 93
Fragm. 299 Dindorf (352 Nauck.).
*
Prometh. 511.
* Fragm. 295
Agam.
(390)
^

life.

'

p^j-g^

320.

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE,


Chap,

the one hand, even he gives utterance to the ancient


belief in the envy of heaven, which is so closely con-

nected with the peculiarity of natural religion


ness lurks under the rudest health
fortune,

when

it

man

bears

sick-

the wave of

highest on

its crest,

man on whom

breaks on a hidden reef; would the

fortime smiles escape ruin, he must voluntarily throw

away a part of what he has


even fate itself ordains
guilt, when bent on utterly destroying a family.^
On
the other hand, ^schylus never tires of insisting on
the connection between guilt and punishment. Not
;

only in the old stories of Niobe and Ixion, of the


house of Laius and of that of Atreus, does he paint

with telling touches the unavoidable natm^e of divine


vengeance, the mischief which follows in the wake
of pride, the never-dying curse of crime

but also in

the unexpected result of the Persian expedition he


sees a higher hand, visiting with punishment the
self-exaltation of the great

king, and the insults

offered to the gods of Grreece.

according to his deeds


in piety without guile

though

it

may

God

Man must

suffer

him who

blesses

lives

and pride, but vengeance,^

be slow at

the transgressor of right;

first,

suddenly overtakes

some Dike

strikes

down

with a sudden blow,^ others she slowly crushes from


generation to generation the curse of crime gathers
;

strength, likewise virtue and happiness


Agam. 1001
compare the
story of Poly crates in Herodo;

tus,

iii.

40.

Niobe, Fr. 160


PlatOy Kep. 380, A.
2

blamed by

descend on

Agam. 1563

Choeph. 309

Fr. 282.

Eumen. 530

Choeph.

Agam.

Fr. 283.

61.

750.

I
i

ILLUSTRATED BY TRAGEDIANS.
children and children's children

the Furies rule over

the destiny of men, avenging the fathers' sins on the


sons,'

sucking the criminal's life-blood, stealthily

him the snares


madness, pursuing him with punishment down to

clinging to his feet, throwing round


of

Thus severely and clearly through all


the plays of ^schylus runs the thought of divine
justice and of implacable destiny.
All the more remarkable on that account is the
vigour with which the poet breaks through the fetters
the shades.2

which this view of the world imposes.

In the Eumenides, these moral conflicts, the play of which


^schylus can so well pourtray,^ are brought to a satis-

Olympic Groddess appeasing


of vengeance, and the severity of the

factory issue, the bright

the dark spirits

ancient bloodthirsty Justice yielding to

human

kind-

In the Prometheus, natural religion as a whole


celebrates its moral transfiguration ; the jealousy of
ness.

the gods towards mortals

mercy

is

seen to resolve itself

Zeus himself requires the aid of the


Wise One, who, for his kindness to men, has had to
feel the whole weight of his wrath
yet, on the other
hand, the unbending mind of the Titan must be
into

and Zeus' rule of might be changed by


willing submission into a moral rule.
What the
softened,

poet places in the legendary past


history

of

his

is

own time and of

in reality the

his

own mind,

^schylus stands on the boundary line between two


periods of culture, and the story he tells of the miti'

Eum.
Eum.

830.
264, 312.

566.

Choeph.

896:

Eum.

198.

Chap.
^'

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

1^

Chap,
'-

g-ation of ancient justice,

and of the new rule of the

was repeated in another way, the sternness of

Grods,

the

generation of Marathon giving place to the


cheerful beauty of the age of Pericles.
the

I'o

Q)) Sophoek\^.

new age Sophocles has

of this

spirit

given the most fitting expression. Agreeing as he


does in principle with his predecessor, his poems,
nevertheless, convey a very different impression.

The

keynote of the poetry of Sophocles is likewise reverence for the Gods, whose hand and laws encompass

human

life.

fortune

From them come

all

things, even mis-

their never-decaying

power no mortal can


withstand
nothing can escape its destiny ^ from
their eyes no deed and no thought can be hid ^ their
^

no one transgress.

mere human power, dare


Men, however, are weak and

mere shadows

or dreams, a very nothing, capable

eternal laws,^ created by no

frail,

No

only of a passing semblance of happiness.^


mortal's life

happiest

death

from misfortune,^ and even the


cannot be called happy before his

free

is

man

nay, taking

all

things into account, which

the changing day brings with

it,

the

number of woes,
all must
saying, Not to

the rarity of good fortune, the end to which

come,

it

were well to repeat the old

have been born

is

to die as soon as

wisdom
1

is,

the best

may

be.'

Ajax, 1036 Trach. 1278.


Antig. 604, 951
Fr. 615.
;

3
4

Electra, 657.
(Ed. Rex, 864 Ant. 450.
Ajax, 125; (Ed. E. 1186;
;

and the next best

is

The^ highest practical

therefore, to control the wishes, to


;

lot,

'

mode-

Fr. 12, 616, 860.


Ant. 611
Fr. 530.
' (Ed.
E. Trach. 1, 943
532, 583.
(gd. Col. 1215.
;

Fr.

BY

ILLUSTRATED

TRAGEDIANS.

rate the desires, to love justice, to fear

That

resigned to fate.

above

self

man

is

man

human measure,

moderate

lot,

God, to be

Ciim'.

should not exalt him-

only the modest

that

acceptable to the Grods,^ that

to seek a higher instead

11

it

absurd

is

of being content with a

that arrogance hurries on to sudden

destruction, that Zeus hates the vaunts of a boastful

tongue,^ all this Sophocles shows by the example of

men who have been hurled from


fortune, or who have been ruined by
He,

overbearing.

too, is

summit of

the

recklessness

and

impressed by the thought

of the worth of virtue

and of divine retribution. He


knows that uprightness is better than riches, that
loss is better than unjust gain, that heavy guilt
heavy punishment, but that piety and virtue
are worth more than all things else, and are rewarded
entails

not only in this world, but in the next


declares that it

more important

is

he even

to please those in

He

the next world than those in this.^

is

more-

over convinced that all

wisdom comes from the Gods,


and that they always conduct to what is right,^ albeit

men may never

He

cease from

them

learning and

striving

commit their griefs to


who from heaven above looks down and orders
things, and to bear what the Gods send with

after

it.^

bids

to

Zeus,
all

and in

resignation,^

this

Ajax, 127, 758


(Eel. Col.
1211
Fr. 320, 528.

(Ed. R. 873 Ant. 127.

Fr.
18, 210, 1<J6;
1440.

Philoc.

belief

is

neither puzzled

^ Fr. 834, 227, 809, 865


in
the unintelligible 06ia riyi^pci
probably there is a eeiauoTpa.
;

'

Fr. 731, 736.


Eiec. 174
Fr. 523, 862.
;

Ant. 71.

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

12

Chap,
'.

by the good fortune of many bad men, nor yet by


the misfortunes of many good ones.^
The same thoughts had inspired the poetry of
^schylus, and yet the spirit of the drama of Sophovery different one from his.
Sophocles can
show a higher artistic execution, a fuller dramatic
cles is a

handling, a more delicate delineation of the inner


life, a more careful unravelling of action from
characters

and of characters by means of

actions, a better

proportioned beauty, a clearer and more pleasing


language ; whereas for tempestuous force, for wild
exultation, for majestic view of history, ^schylus is

Nor

unrivalled.

the moral platform of the two


tragedians quite the same. Both are penetrated with
is

reverence for the divine powers; but in ^schylus


this reverence is combined with a horror which has
first to be set aside, and with an antagonism
which

has to be overcome before


trustful resignation

can come up to the

it

and the

blissful

The power

piety of Sophocles.

^schylus much harsher, because


the character of those

Zeus

is

whom

peace of the

of fate seems with


less

called for by

reaches

the reign of
;
a reign of terror, mitigated only by degrees,
it

and man must perish

if

relations with him.^

Both poets celebrate the victory

of moral order over

the victory
struggles.

is

the Deity enter into too close

human

; but in iEschylus
preceded by severer and more dreadful

self-will

Moral order works, with him,

'

Fr. 104.

Compare the character

lo in
of

the

as a stern

Prometheus, espe-

cially v. 887, &c.

ILLUSTRATED

md

BY

TRAGEDIANS.

fearful power, crushing the refractory

13

whereas,

Niih Sophocles, it completes its


jertainty

work with the quiet


of a law of nature, awakening rather
pity

human weakness than

or

terror. That conflict of the


bloodthirsty justice with the new, round
which
heEumenides of ^schylus play, Sophocles has left

)ld

him

)ehind; with

justice

from the very beginharmoniously united with mercy, and the most

ling,

is,

-ccursed of all mortals finds in the


leus

reconciliation at last.

'

different order

(Edipus ColoHis heroes, too, are of


'

from those of his predecessor.

In

Eschyius moral opposites are so hard,


that human
epresentatives of them do not suffice him
hence he
;

rings the Grods themselves into the


battle-field
:eus and the Titans, the daughters
of Night and

the

enizens of

Olympus

whereas the tragedy of Sopholes moves entirely in the world


of men.
The former
eals by preference with violent
natures and unconrolled passions

what

epict

is

the strong point of the latter

noble, self-contained, tender

is

to

strength

by him generally coupled with dignity,


pain with
Jsignation.
Hence his female characters are so
1

)ecially successful.
3stra,
s

repulsiveness.

ays
3t

Eschyius paints in a Clytcemthe demoniacal side of woman's nature


in all

Sophocles in an Antigone pourpure womanhood, knowing ' how to love,


but

to hate,'

and putting even hatred

iroism of her love.


es sets before us

to

shame by the

In short, the poetry of Sophothe sentiments of an epoch and a


>

Ant. 523.

Chap.
^'

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

14

Chap,

people which having, by most successful

'

happy use of

to a

its

human

nature and

cheerful spirit, to prize

powers, and so to fame and

position, enjoys existence,

look on

efforts, risen

its

and which has learned to


all

that belongs to

in a

it

greatness, to mitigate its

by wise resignation, to bear its weaknesses,


to control its excesses by custom and law. From him, as
sufferings

;'

from no other poet, the idea is gathered of a beautiful


natural agreement between duty and inclination, between freedom and order, which constitutes the moral

ideal of the Grreek world.


{c)

Euri-

jm es.

Only some four Olympiads later comes Euripides.


Yq^ what a remarkable change in ethical tone and
As an artist,
view of life is apparent in his writings

is

Euripides

is far

too fond of substituting calculations

for the spontaneous

cal reflection for

of particular

outcome of the

poet's

mind,

admiring contemplation.

criti-

By means

scenes of an exciting and terrifying

by chorus-songs often loosely connected


with the action of the play, by rhetorical declama-|
tion and moralising, he seeks to produce an effect
character,

which might be gained in greater purity and depth


from the unison of the whole. That harmony between
the moral and the religious life which commended
itself so

may

agreeably to us in Sophocles,

be seen in

^
I'

a state of dissolution in the plays of the younger

Not that he

poet.

religious thoughts.

is

deficient in

He knows

moral maxims

full well

and|";;

that piety

and the virtue of temperance are the best things for


man that he who is mortal must not be proud of
advantages nor despair in misfortune that he can do
;

'

ILLUSTRATED

BY

TRAGEDIANS.

iry

nothing without the Gods that in the long run the


?ood man fares well and the bad fares ill; that
a
modest lot is preferable to fitful greatness ^ that the
;

poor man's fear of


tatious sacrifices

God is worth more than


of many a rich man that
;

:ntelligence are better

the ostenvirtue and

than wealth and noble

birth.'^

He discourses at length of the benefits conferred by


;he Gods on men ^ he speaks right
well of their
;

ighteous

and almighty

human

)ack

rule,^

and he even traces

guilt to their will.^

However numerous such


writings,

lis

still

expressions may be in
they do not contain the whole of

view of the world, neither

lis

iarity of his

is the ethical pecupoetry to be found in them.


Euripides

sufficient

las

appreciation

Qorally beautiful,

to

of

what

great

is

be able to paint

it

when

omes before him in a true and telling manner.

Bacch. 1139. lo Schl. Hip1100. Kirchh.


Fr. 77,

'

olyt.

257, 305, 355, 395, 507, 576,


942, 1014,
1016,
1027

21,

^^^?r*

o^^

Fr. 329, 53, 254, 345, 514,

1
,o^
buppi.
1J7.

Troad 880
Hel. 1442.
ompare tlie concluding verses
r

tins piece, wliich also occur


the end of the Andromache

id Lacchie. Fr. 797, 832, 875,

fV6

it

For

that, as a pupil of philosophers,^ as a kindred


spirit

11

0,

and

i.o-r

Th?'?if
.V anIhe testimony of^ the

ents respecting the connecon between Euripides and


naxagoras has been quoted in

Zei.j.krs Pliilosopliie der Griechen, vol. i. 790, 3.


For the
traces thereof, which are princi pally found in some

oAhe

fragments,
compare
lUntu^o^s
Euripides
Restitut
10^' 118, 139.
Anaxagorasi
however, does not, like Euripides, make Earth and Ether
but Air and Ether come first
after tlie original mixino-of all
things.
The well-know^ii and

beautiful passage (Fragment


902) commending the investi'^^'^ contemplates with
innocence the eternal order of

-^'''^'^''

immortal nature,
Anaxagoras.
7.

is

referred to

Compare

Younger men,

also Fr
like Prodicu^

Chap.

^__

STATE OF CVLTUBE IN GREECE.

16

Chap,
\

to the better Sophists, he is too far

removed from the

older lines of thought to be able to give himself

and with full conviction to the traditional


and morality. His sober understanding feels
the improbability and unseemliness of many legends,
and the artistic spirit has not such an exclusive hold
freely
faith

on him that he can overlook this for the sake of the


embody, or for their poetic worth. The

ideas they

fortunes of

men

do not seem to

him

to be directly

the revelation of a higher power, but rather to be

proximately the result of natural causes, of calculation, of caprice,

and of accident.

appear wavering.

ciples

authority

is

admitted,

If,

still

Even moral

prin-

on the whole, their

the poet cannot conceal

from himself that even an immoral course of conduct


has much to say in its defence.
The grand poetic
way of contemplating the world, the moral and religious

way

of looking at

to a sceptical tone, to a

setting

forth

of

plain

brought the Eumenides,


antiquity, yet with

human

life,

has given place

decomposing

reflection, to a

natural
all in

most

^schylus

facts.

the uncouth guise of

fearful effect,

on

to the

whereas the Electra of Euripides says to her


brother, or rather the poet himself says, that they
stage

are

mere

geneia

fancies of his imagination.^

WTiilst Iphi-

flects

preparing to sacrifice the captives, she rethat the goddess herself cannot possibly require

this

sacrifice,

and

is

Socrates,

and that the story of the

Euripides

been their pupil.

may have known,

feast

ofi

but cannot have^

Orest. 248, 387.

BY

ILLUSTRATED
Tantalus

is

a fable.^

TRAGEDIANS.

Likewise in the Electra

tragic chorus doubts as to the

17
2

the

wonder of the change

the course of the sun.

In

In the Troades,^ Hecuba


the story of the judgment of Paris, and exthe assistance of Aphrodite in carryino-

riuestions

plains

off

Helen to
^he

mean

the attractive beauty of Paris.


In
Bacchse,^ Teiresias gives an insipid,
half-natural

explanation of the birth of Bacchus.-^


The Gods,
lays Euripides,^ have no needs,
and therefore

the

tories

which impute to them human passions cannot

Even the general notions of divine


engeance give him offence. This he will not
regard

)0ssibly

be true.

a punishment for particular acts, but


rather as a
miversal law.^
In other instances, the actions and
ommands of the Gods are held up to blameblame,
-s

the most part, not called for by the


character
f the acting persons and go
unpunished in the
3quel, so that it necessarily appears
as the poet's
w'n conviction whence he concludes
at one
30, for

time

lat

man need

not disturb himself because of his


lults, since the Gods commit the
same at another
me, that the stories about the Gods
cannot be
;

ue.

The prophetic

art is held in equally low estima-

on by Euripides.

The opportunity

Iphig. Taur. 372.

that

;
3
^

'

seized in the

God

cares only for great


leaving unimportant
f^l'P^^^'
things to chance.

ofio"
,':,.^*

vxag. M)\).
Here. Fur. 1328.

Orest. 277.
339, 654.

Fr.

508, with which the


ring (Fr. 964) is connected,
'

is

409'

Here Fur 1301

Hpro
Here.

^^^v
Fur.

Chap.
}'

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

28

Chap.
^'

Helen,

to prove,

that

it is all

and

rites,

lie

on highly rationalistic grounds,

and

With

deceit.^

however, belief in the

No

thoroughly interwoven.

these legends

Gods

most

is

wonder, therefore, that

the poet often puts into the mouths of his heroes

statements respecting the

existence of the

Grods,

which would sound more natural coming from Protagoras than from men and women of the legendary
Tal thy bins raises the question whether there
past.
"

are

Grods, or

whether Chance guides

things

all

^
;

another doubts their existence,'' because of the unjust


distribution of good

and bad fortune

Hecuba

in

her prayer wonders what the deity really is, whether


Zeus, or natural necessity, or the spirit of mortal
beings

Hercules and Clytsemnestra leave

it

open

even the
whether there are Gods, and who Zeus is
Ether is explained to be Zeus.^ So much at least
these utterances prove that Euripides had wandered
;

far

away from the ancient

ing that he

is

sincere

faith in the Gods.

when he

Allow-

says that only a fool

can deny the deity and give credence to the deceitful


assertions of philosophy respecting what is hidden,
still his attitude appears to have been prepondera-

and

critical

towards the popular

tingly

sceptical

faith.

Probably he allowed that there was a God

743.
Sophocles,

1033,
Antig.
makes Cleon attack the prophet, but his accusations are
refuted by the sequel. Not so
with Euripides.
3 Hel. 484.
* Fr. 288
compare Fr. 892.
2

Troad. 877.
Here. Fur. 1250
1034; Orestes, 410,
5

fragment

of

'

Iph. Aul.

and the

Melanippe

483.

fe
;

Fr. 935, 869.


Fr. 905, 981.

Fr.

ILLUSTRATED
certainly he

notions

TRAGEDIANS.

19

attached

no value to the legendary


the dods; holding that the

respecting

essence of

BY

God

could not be known, and


assuming
the oneness of the divine nature either
by glossing
"
over or by plainly denying the ruling
Pantheism.
Nor did the popular ideas respecting the
i

state

death fare better at his hands.


Naturally
enough, he makes use of them when
a poet can use
them, but then it is also said, that we
know not how
it is with another life, we
only follow an unfounded
opinion.
In several places Euripides
expresses the
opinion,^ pointing partly to
Orphic-Pythagorean traditions, and partly to the
teaching of Anaxagoras
md Archilaus,3 that the spirit returns at
death
after

to

)he

ether whence

it

came

'

)pen question, whether at

apparently leaving

it

an

or to what extent,
consciousness belongs to the soul
when united with
-he ether.^
That the sphere of
all,

morals did not

11

Fr. 904 says the ruler of


things IS now called Zeus,

ow Hades, which would point


D

the opinion tiiat the popular

Dr

the one

God

Helios and

.polio ai-e

Identified (Fr. 781,


1) according to the tradition
ilippolyt. 192.

Compare

Zeller^s

8%t'
S^'Atr'
430, 822
846.

Philoso-

'^''' ' PP-

J8,

/Suppl. 532, the genuineness


xth, Hel. 1012 M.836.
'He says in the Helen The
nl ot the dead no longer lives,
It yet It has an eternal con:

sciousness
(yt,d,a-n
after it has^ unked

^eduaro.^

with

tl

immortal Ether
From th^
he deduces the belief in retr (Fr. 689, compare Fr 452
8S()^
whether on the whole life ^s
not a death and death a
life

Troades, 638, it
the dead m'an

is

stated ihnt

feelit ei
an unborn child; in Fr.'
536 that he is a nothin- earth
'
and a shade; Fr 734 anrpp
is

^ike

tality

of fame;
and in the
Heraclid. 591, he leaves it nn
open questionVhet her tL c
lad
have feelings or not

Chap.

^__

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

20

Chap,
'

remain unaffected by these doubts

may

be gathered

from the general character of his tragedies more


definitely than from those particular utterances which

some measure

in

sufficed to give offence

The

cotemporaries.^

tragic

movement

even to his

in Euripides,

unlike that conflict of moral forces which ^schylus

and Sophocles knew how to depict with such deep


feeling, lies

rather

in

personal

ments, and experiences.

arrange-

passions,

His heroes have not that

makes them types of a whole


most cases, that higher necessity,

ideal character which


class.

Hence, in

which

called

for

our admiration in the

^schylus and Sophocles,

case

not active in the de-

is

velopment of the Euripidean drama, but the


result is

of

final

brought about by some external means,

by divine interposition or by some human

either

cunning.

Thus,

rich

as

he

may

be

in

poetic

beauties, successful in painting individual characters,

human life and human


many of the speeches and

experienced in knowledge of
weaknesses, thrilling in
scenes in his tragedies

yet most undeniably he has

come down from the moral and

artistic

height of his

two great predecessors, by introducing into tragedy


habits of inward reflection, of studied effect, and of
artificial

As

language, which Agatho with his dainty

yKaxra-'
for instance
?/
Hippol. 607, or
&c.
the language of Eteocles in
Phoen. 504:, 525, that men will
do anything for power, and
even commit crimes for a
throne or that of the old man
in lo 1051, that it befits the
fortunate man to shun wrong,
'

llnufioKe,

but that all means of vengeance


are lawful in case of injury,
It is true Euripides does not
give these as his own sentiments.
Yet even his cotemporaries noticed their resem-i
blance to the moral teaching
of the Sophists.

ILL USTRA TED

B Y BIBA CTIC POETR Y.

elegance, and Critias with his sophistic


were not slow to follow.'

21

moralising,

Chap.
l.

Cotemporary

with ^schylus, or even a little


before him, the poets Epicharmus,
Simonides, and
Pindar, flourished:
soon after him

(2)
^^^'

m^.
I^^^'V-

Bacchylides.

The first of these, Epicharmus, it has


been shown
in an earlier work,^ takes
a rational view of the
world, and entertains clear notions
on morals, and
theology, thanks to his knowledge
of philosophy.
Bimonides,3 so far as his views can be
gathered from
scattered fragments, appears

mainly to insist on that


noderation and self-restraint which
result from a
jonsideration of human weakness and
frailty.
Our
ife is full

ain

swiftly it

asily lost

ect

of toils

by

and cares its fortune is uncerhurries away; even prudence Ms


too

men

and unstable

he best

man

erity.

is

() Simo''''^''''

their hardly-won virtue is imper-

it

changes with circumstances

whom the Oods bestow prosman must not be looked for;

he on

faultless

nough to find one moderately

righteous.^^

The same

ein of feeling is

found in Bacchylides, on whom


escended the mantle of Simonides. He
knows that
one is altogether happy, that few are
spared some
eavy changes of fortune, and bursts,
yet not alone,
ito the complaint
'
Not to have been

born were'

happiest

le

lot.'^

Hence the highest

\Zellcr's
Geschichte
der
ulosophie, Part I. p. 925, and
mck. Trag. Frag. 599.
^ Zeller's
Philosopliie
der
eichen. Part

I.

p.

427 (Ger-

m).
'

Called by later writers, as

practical

well as by ^schvlus a Dopt of


the good old
^^n^r^j^/i.,
Clouds, 1352.
^
Fr 32 3fi ^s qo ^^
c~
^
Fr.' 42

Ue 'ISL

'

6
^

'

Yx. 5.
Fr. 1,2 3 21,

'

(i)

Bac-

'-'^''J^^'^<^''

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

22

Chap,
'_

mind, in equanimity, in a
contentment with the present, and absence of care
At the same time he shares the
for the future J

wisdom

his

consists, in

conviction that

man

can discover what

is

right,

that Zeus, the all-seeing ruler of the world,

is

and
not

blame for the misfortunes of mortals.^ These


are the same sentiments as in the older moral poets,
without any noticeable change in the moral platto

form.^
(6-)

Fin-

more peculiar and more powerful,

spirit far

and more nearly akin to ^schylus, finds utterance


At the bottom of Pindar's
in the poems of Pindar.
as of that of ^Eschylus, lies a

view of the world,

most exalted notion of the


nothing

for

is

Him

deity.

He

is

the

all ;"^

all

bestows success or

law, which governs mortals and immortals,

Grod

Zeus governs

impossible.

things according to his will


failure

'

accomplishes

its

are the deeds of

Nor

purposes with mighty hand.^

men

hid from the all-seeing eyes of

Only beautiful and noble traits can be attrihe who accuses it of human
buted to the deity
Such being the
vices cannot escape punishment.^
God."^

(Trach. 1278) ovSej/ tovtuv H ti


Zei;s, to express, All depends

Fr. 19.
Fr. 29.

Zeller, Part

fJ^h

I. p.

llivhapos

upon God.

90.

Clemens, Stromat.
avriKpvs

v.

610:
elirwv,

Fr. 119;

Nem.

Although

Fr. 146.

to give the
words beginning t/ as a quotalion, it seems hardly likely
that they can have stood in

'

01.

Tt

9^6$

8ti

rh

irav.

Clement appears

Pindar. Perhaps Pindar used


the words dehs rh irav in the
same sense that Sophocles said

Pyth.

ii.

49,

88;

iii.

28

x. 29.

i.

64

Pyth.

ix. 42.
^ 01.
i.
28, where, with a
curious combination of credulity and rationalism, the story
of the feast of the Gods in the
house of Tantalus is declared

'

BY DIDACTIC

ILLUSTRATED

exalted position of God,

On

attitude.

fold

the

related to that of the

the race of Gods


the

is

man

POETRY.

occupies thereto a two-

one hand he has a nature

Gods

one

the race of men,^

is

another, yet both descend from

same mother; hence

in nature

and

spirit

are not altogether unlike immortals.

hand, looking at their power, there


difference,^ for changeful is

sorrow

lie for

23

our

lot,

us ever near together.^

On

the other

an

is

mortals

infinite

and joy and


True wisdom,

therefore, consists in not transgressing the

what

is

bounds of
Gods for all that is
taking with contentment what they bestow.

human,

good, in

in looking to the

'Seek not to be a God,' exclaims the poet: mortality becomes mortals


he who soars to heaven will,
like Bellerophon, have a precipitate fall.^
Only
where God leads is blessing and success ^ in His
;

hand

rests the issue of our labour, according as it is

determined by
virtue

destiny.^'

and knowledge

From

the deity comes

all

and doubtless for this very


being a gift of God, natural talent is
placed by Pindar far above all acquirements, and
tlie creative spirits on whom it has been bestowed,
above all other spirits, as the eagle of Zeus is above
;

reason, as

to be a fable, the occasion for

which

was supplied by the


carrying off of Pelops by Poseidon.
'
This, rather than the identity of both sexes, must be the
meaning- of the words av^pwv
%v e^wv yevos
men form a race
by themselves, the Gods form
another different therefrom.
^

Nem.

According to
Frag. 108, the soul, the fUuAov
-

vi. 1.

alCivos, comes from God alone,


and proves its higher nature
during the sleep of the body in

prophetic dreams.
^
oi_ ^^^ 3q
Yx. 210.
^
01. v. 24; Isthm.
.

14;

v.

vii. 42.
^

Fr. 85,

stands for

where probably

l\yth. xii. 28.

OL

Fr. 118.

eV

es.

ix. 28,

103

Pyth.

i.

41

Chap.
^^

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

"24

Chap.
I.

We

the croaking ravens.^

what Grod
whatever

must resign ourselves to

disposes, content ourselves with our lot,

Strive not against

it be.

God

bear His

yoke without kicking against the pricks


yourself to circumstances
sible

seek not what

in all things observe moderation

adapt

impos-

is

beware of

envy, which deals the strongest blow to those most

highly placed

Nay more,

these

counsels, he

greater weight to

give

to

are the counsels of the poet.^

moral

his

not unfrequently appeals to a future

retribution, of the wicked as well as of the good,

sometimes following

herein

the

received

notions

respecting Tartarus, Elysium, and the islands^ of

the blest,

at

belief in the

other

times connecting therewith a

migration of

souls.^

In the main,

Pindar's platform, both religious and moral,

is

not

different from that of ^schylus, albeit the thought

of divine vengeance does not stand out with

him

in

such tragic guise.


(3) Historians.
(a) Herodotus.

Would we

see this

view of

life

in transition to

the later form, no better example can be selected

than Herodotus. This friend of Sophocles, in writing


history,
01.

25

iii.

ii.

often allows himself to


86

ix.

100

Nem.

i.

40.

2 Pyth. ii. 34, 88


iii. 21, 59,
103; xi. 50; Fr. 201.
3 01.
ii.
56; Fr. 106, 120.
Fr. 108 seems only to presuppose the current notions, with
this difference, that a more
intense life is attributed to
souls in Hades than was the
view of Homer and the mass
of the people.
Fr. 109 is pro;

be guided by the

bably interpolated
Alexandrian Jew.
"

Fr. 110, 01.

ii.

68.

by some
Accor-

ding to the latter passage, in


which Pindar is m.ost explicit,
reward or punishment follows
in Hades.
Some few distinguished men are allowed to
return to life, and may, by a
threefold life of
innocence,
enjoy the higher bliss on the
islands of the blessed.

ILLUSTRATED BY HISTORIANS.

He

of olden times.

notions

2o

admits the rule of

divine providence in the order of nature,^ and equally


fortunes of men, and especially in

the

clearly in

punishment, which overtakes the guilty, even though


he have acted in the excess of an excusable passion.^

Popular forms of worship are honoured by him,^


knowing as he does that every nation likes its own
rites best

with

only a

Credulous,

disdain.''

to relate, in all

phecies,^

good

says,

can treat these

he

too,

is,

so

far

as

wonders and pro-

faith, divers

among them some

Even

kind.

madman, he

of the most extraordinary

an antique type, affected

his piety is of

with that fear of the divine powers which

is

so

peculiarly suited to natural religion, where the ex-

men

altation of Grods above

but

essentia] difference,

Man
his

is

not destined to

life

may

better for a

man than

jealous of

Her.

iii.

Mi. 120;

He who

life.^

129;

is

quite

111.

vi.

84;

vii. 133.

^^,

in
*

205;

For this reason he hesitates


to utter the names of Egyptian
Gods in a context which might
desecrate them, ii. 86, or to
speak of Egyptian mysteries.
^

it

even

is

is

not

in prosperity

lot of

men,

is

in-

by the envy of the Deity, which,

108.
iv.

nay

privileges, will not brook a

its

All this

rival.'^

before

doubt whether death

imagination soars above the

variably struck

viii.

more physical than moral.


enjoy perfect good fortune
is

be called happy

a general matter for

'

not conceived of as an

exposed to changes innumerable

is

death no one

or

is

mortal

agreement with the


12,57;

vii.

viii. 37,

65;

ix.

100.
Here belong the propliecies of Bakis and Musajus,
viii.

77

ix. 43,

respecting the

genuineness of which he entertains no doubt,

''

i.

ii.

On

31.

the Qiiov (pBovepov, conf.


iii. 40
vii. 10, 5, 46.

32. 34

Chap.
I.

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

26
CHAr.

spirit,

_J

Grreece.

For

which breathes through the older poetry of

Herodotus neither can nor will


conceal from us the fact that he is the son of an
epoch, in which thought has already begun to shake
all that,

the foundations of a simple faith. Notwithstanding


the naivete with which he tells many a wonder ;i there
are times

when he cannot

the impulse to exaway the marvels of legend, either referring

plain

resist

them

to natural causes in the rationalising spirit of


the Sophists, or at least mentioning such explana-

given by others with approval.


Thus the
wanderings of lo and the rape of Europa are ex-

tions

plained at the very beginning of his work to mean


the carrying off by pirates of these two royal
daughters.
In the story of Gryges the wonderful

power of

his ring

is

referred

to

a very

common

The prophetic doves of Dodona turn into


Egyptian priestesses.^
The Egyptian stories re-

trick.2

specting Paris and Helena are preferred to those of


Homer, and the general tradition of the Greeks/ on

grounds

far

removed from ancient poetry.

When

Poseidon interposes in the Thessalian legend, he sees


the working of an earthquake,^ and remarks not
without irony, that those who believe Poseidon

wrought the earthquake, may believe he interposed


also.
Add to this that he occasionally expresses the
opinion that all

men know

equally

'

i-

60.

ii

1-

8.

vii. 129.

ii.

56.

120.

little

about

'

the'

..i

ILLUSTRATED BY HISTORIANS.
(iods,^

and

it will

27

how much doubt had

be patent,

Chap.
^'

already taken the place of the ancient faith.

In Thucydides, the next great historian, doubt


bas gone over into the matter of fact treatment of

The high moral tone of his


deny. Even in its unfinished form

no one

history.

style

will

his history of

the Peloponnesian war has all the effect of a touching

This

tragedy.

effect,

however,

secured simply

is

by a plain setting forth of historical

facts,

without

introducing the interposition of 'the Grods to explain


events.

Thucydides knows how indispensable religion

for the public

is

scription,

He

good.

how deeply he

shows, by his very de-

deplores the decay, not only

moral but religious of his country.^ Yet the rule of


the deity and of moral order in the world is only
apparent in his

Convinced that

pages by the progress of events.

human

nature

is

always the same,

he exhibits moral laws by showing


before

him

how

in the case

ruin naturally resulted from the weakness

and the passions of men, which he knows so well


and can judge so impartially.^ Nowhere is a belief
betrayed in those extraordinary occm-rences, in whicli
the hand of Grod manifests itself in Herodotus.

Where

cotemporaries

his

see

the

fulfilment of a

prophecy, he contents himself with sober

To depend on
calls
ii.

the folly of the masses


3 (Schl.).

See the well-known passages ii. 53; iii. 82.


iii. 82, 84
and in the description of the Sicilian expcdition, its moti\es and results.
=*

criticism.'*

oracles instead of using remedies, he


;

he openly expresses

vi. 15, 24,


<

is,

30

vii. 75, 87.

For instance, ii. 17, 54.


v. 103, where the Athenian
without doubt, expressing-

the writer's opinion,

(h)

Tlm-

^y^^'^''^-

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

28
Chap.

his

disapproval of

the

disastrous

superstition

I.

Nicias.^

quite as

of

In the panegyric of the dead,^ which is


much a memorial of his own spirit as of the

spirit of Pericles, there is

not a word of the legendary

history of Athens, that hackneyed

panegyrists

theme of

earlier

but instead thereof, there is a statesman's mind dealing with facts, and practical problems.
His history is a brilliant evidence of a mature judg;

ment, of high intellectual culture, of a many-sided


experience of

life,

f a calm, unimpassioned, pene-

and morally sober view of the world. It is a


work which kindles the highest respect not only for the
writer, but for the whole period, which could rear up
trating,

such a genius.

Nor yet does this work conceal the darker sides


that period.
Eead only the descriptions it gives ^

of

of

the confusion of

all moral notions in the factious


struggles of the Peloponnesian war, of the desolation
of Athens by the plague, of the decline of piety and

self-sacrifice,

of the running riot of all the selfish

passions, to be satisfied of the decay of

moral excel-

lence, even in that period of

might and culture. Beyond all question, along with this outward change of
conduct, universal convictions were shaken also in
proof of which, Thucydides puts in the mouth of
;

several

of his

and particularly of those


coming from Athens, naked avowals of the most
selfish principles, such as could only come from
the
lips of some one of the younger Sophists.
All who
have the power seek to rule no one is restrained by
speakers,

'

BY COMEDY.

ILLUSTRATED

29

considerations of right from pursuing his advantage

by hook and by crook

the rule of the stronger

the universal law of nature

judges what

states act

^"

is

bottom every one


right and honourable by his own

is

and enjoyments

interests

Chap.

at

even the best regulated

on this idea, at

least,

in their foreign rela-

These and such like utterances are put into


the mouths of Athenian popular men and ambassadors on every opportunity.^
Even those who have to
tions.

from Athenian self-seeking are in the end


hardly able to blame it.^ Have we not here moral
and political conditions keeping exact pace with the
suffer

sophistic character of philosophy

Nor were other prudent men blind


which

to the dangers (4) Th^

this course of things

however

little

counter

to

was bringing upon them, ^aZm.


they were able to control it, or to run

the spirit

of their

times.
Take, for
This poet, an enthusiastic
admirer of the good old time, as he paints it with its

example, Aristophanes.

steady

morality,

prowess,

warms

its

strict

education, its

military

and prudent administration,^


subject whenever he speaks of the days
orderly

its

to his

With implacable satire, now in the


bantering jest, now in that of bitter earnest-

of Marathon.'*

form of

he lashes the innovations which have taken the


iplace
of time-honoured institutions;
democracy
running riot with its demagogues and sycophants ^
ness,

'

^1.]

i.

76

'

iii.

40

v.

89,

105,

vi. 85.

nians, 676.
5

;.

^V o^ ,,
Clouds, 882 Knights,

!y,-

'

Wasps, 1071

the

1316.

Achar-

Wasps; Clouds,

568.

The

Sycophants are taken to task


on every opportunity

Aristo^''^''^''

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

30
Chap,

'

poetry, empty, effeminate, free-tbinking, faithless to

moral

its

idea,

sophistic

from

fallen

cultm-e

with

fruitless

its

height

artistic

its

speculations,

dangerous alike to faith and morals, the produce of


shameless quibblers, atheistic rationalisers,^ or conscienceless perverters of justice, instead of steady

and sober-minded men.

citizens

ancient

is

with him undeniably an

conviction.

and

classic

Of this

for

is

affair of personal

beauty of those passages which

still lies

what

his zeal is proof, the excitement

the praise of the olden time and


proof

Love

its

customs.

set forth

Grreater

in the general tone of his comedies.

Boastful himself, with reason, of the courage with

which he discharged his duty as a citizen against


Cleon,^ he extracts even from us the testimony of his
being an honourable

man

fighting for a principle.

Whilst warmly taking the


of innovation, he at the

poses

this

spirit

in

field

against the spirit

same time not only presup-

his

audience,

but

actually

Demagogues and sycophants he lashes yet whilst lashing them he tells


us that every place is full of them that democracy
furthers and promotes

it.

has a hundred heads, ever full of vitality; that the

Athenian people, like a childish old man, are always


the victim of the most impudent of their flatterers
that the steady

men

of the older generation are just

as eager for their judicial dues as the

whole body of

worshipful citizens are for their law-suits

Frogs Achar. 393.


Clouds Birds, 1282, 1553

Frogs, 1491.

that the

Wasps, 1029, 1284


Peace,
Achar, 959 Clouds, 542.
;

951

ILLUSTRATED BY COMEDY.

31

young champions of Spartan severity are as debauched as the demagogues


that the sovereign

Chap.
I.

people, after the re-establishment of Solon's constitution, has

gone on

as'

capriciously as

before,

only

wanting female government to complete the folly.^


Even in his plays he indulges in the arts of the
demagogue and the sycophant Socrates he slanders,
and many another as heartily as any rhetorician could
;

and to outbid those who squandered the public


property in order to bribe the people, he tells the
citizens of Athens that if things were fairly done,-"^
hey ought to receive far more than they did.
For
do

reform in religion and morals, the prospects with


him are bad. He praises the moral training of the

ancients, but observes with a smile that morality


little

home amongst

at

is

his hearers,'*

and finds the


from which his people suffered at bottom very
natural.^
Women he brings on the stage to lash
heir licentiousness
but that licentiousness he represents as so deep and so general, that there
can
hardly be hope of improvement.
He makes an onvices

slaught on the philosophers

who deny the Grods, but


comedies he gives us to understand,
(hat belief in his time rested on trembling
feet.^
Not only here and there,^ but in whole acts
and
plays, he exposes the Grods,
together with their
one of his

111

Wasps

first

Birds, 38.
Eccles. V. 456 conf. Plato,
lu;p. yiii. 563 B.
Wasps, 05o.
'

'

Clouds, 1055
Birds, 137; Frogs,
18; Knights, 1384.
;

Compare

Knights, 32.

Clouds, 369, 396, 900, 1075


Birds, 554, 1608
Eccles. 778
Plut. 123, 697.
In
the Frogs, Peace, and
the Birds.
'

';

'

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

32
Chap.
I.

with audacious recklessness, bringing them


down with rough wit to a human level and to what
priests,

is

low and

common

holding up the moral weaknesses

in which they resemble

making the world

men nakedly and minutely

of Grods, like that of

men, turn in

such a wild whirl, that neither the spectator

who

takes delight in this perverted world, nor yet the


poet, can

have

any real

respect

beings

for

who

are so readily and recklessly at the service of his

imagination.
license of

Much

comedy

of this

may

be attributed to the

yet more than enough remains

show that the poet himself, as well as his


audience, had strayed far from the ancient morality
which he so regretfully wishes to recall that his
to

fanatical devotion,

like Eousseau's

returning to a state of nature,

is

of discontent with the present,


sion

of a

The
C.
problem
,wlved hy
the new

forms of
religious
ri'orshi]).

only the outcome


only

the

romantic idea, not a sentiment

feelings.

expres-

pene-

and ruling his thought


Thus everywhere where we touch

trating his every day

and

wild dream of

life,

upon them, the age and the surroundings from which


Attic philosophy came forth appear penetrated
by a spirit of innovation, rendering it impossible for
the most decided lovers of antiquity to adhere to the
life and beliefs of their ancestors.
Amongst other signs of this change, one phenomenon deserves to be noticed, which appears about
the time of the Peloponnesian war

the

increasing!

spread of the worship of the mysteries, and of soothsaying

in

connection therewith.
Phut, 665.

Hitherto,

the

BY NEW RELIGIOUS

ILLUSTRATED

IDEAS.

reputed predictions of the older prophets had been


appealed to indeed,^ as is the wont of men, but only in

now the mischief and abuse which


was perpetrated by such appeals reached an incredible
pitch.2
To judge by the numerous allusions in the
exceptional cases

and the following generation, the


Orphic and Corybantic mysteries probably gained
at
this time both ground and supporters.^
Such an
writers of this

extension, however, was an innovation in

more than

one respect.

Looking at it from an outside point of


view, it was one thing to seek counsel from
public
and make use of ancient rites naturalised
from time immemorial in fixed spots a very
differoracles

Herod, viii. 7
ix.
437,
mentions prophecies of Bakis
and Musasus respecting the

to the polemic of Euripides.


8 Amongst others,
Philolaus

Persian war.
2 This is particularly
evident
in Aristophanes, who loses no
opportunity of lashing the prophets. Not to mention cursory
attacks, as in Clouds, 330
Birds, 521
in Knights, 109,

(Phasdo, 69, C. Eep. ii. 363, C.


364, B.
Laws, vi. 782, C), and
more particularly Euripides and
Aristophanes.
The
former
(Hippol. 949) describes Hippolytus as a pupil of Orpheus,
and (Fr. 475) introduces a
mystic, who, initiated into the
orgies of IdiBan Zeus, of Zagreus, and the Curetes, devotes
himself to an Orphic life. The

'

818,

767),

t30,

967 (comp. Lysist.


he shows what liberal use

fOleon and other demagogues


made of superstition to flatter
the self-love of the people, and
to direct its will by the socalled prophecies of Bakis.
In
Peace, 1047, he introduces a
prophet Hierocles, who, from
interested motives, opposes the
inclusion of peace, and is
evidently meant for a real
aerson; in the Birds, 959, a
arophet, who thrusts himself in
it the founding of a city,
to

Part

{Zeller,

388) and Plato

I.
;

latter not only depicts (in the


Frogs, 145, 312) the life of the

initiated and iminiliated in


Hades as rudely and vividly as
the consecrated priests do in
Plato, but also (in Peace,
374)
hints at the opinion that man
cannot die quietly without receiving initiation before death,
and (in Wasps, 119) alludes to

the custom of initiating the


sick for the purpose of healino-

;atch a trifle.

Such like phenomena may have given occasion

them.

,'J3

Chap.
I.

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE,

34
Chap,

__Jl__

ent thing to have recourse to the so-called answers


of individual prophets and to a private worship
f

without fixed locality, propagated by vagrant priests,


practised

in

confraternities,

self-constituted

and

claiming to elevate all who took part in it as the


special elect above the mass of mankind, both in this
world and in the next. What was this increasing

fondness for private worship and irregular prophecy


but a proof that the public religion was not altogether satisfactory, whilst

it

contributed at the same

Looking

time to intensify the evil?

at

its real

nature, this mystical piety has diverged from the


In it, the notions
received form of faith and life.

of the gods, flowing into each other, begin to lose


perhaps even the tendency to
their distinctness
^

may be already seen


in individuals in the fifth century, may be referred
The conception of human life and of
thereto.'^
human nature has assumed an altered character,

resolve all into pantheism, wiiich

'

'

owing to a clearer belief in immortality, introduced


by the dogmas of the migration of souls and of
1
This is more immediately
true in the case of Dionysus,

In mystic theology this God,


as the representative of the
changing life of nature, dying
in winter, reviving in spring,
was honoured under the name
Zagreus, and
Dionysus
of
treated as one of the Gods of
On this
the nether world.
account the Dionysus-mysteries
are so important for the future
To the initiated in them
life.
69, C. comp.
(^Plato, Phsedo,
Aristoph., Frogs) may be promised life in Hades with the
Gods,

among whom must

surely

be found the God in whose


service they were enlisted. At
a later time, following Heraclitus' example, Dionysus was
See
identified with Plato.
Zeller's Gesch. d. Phil. Vol.

51, 3

592,

I.

5.

Besides the extracts from


Euripides already quoted, p. 19,
fragment in
1, compare the
Clemens, Stromat. v. 603, D,
^

NaucTt, Fragm. Trag.


588, attributes in all probability to ^schylus' son EuphoZews tcniv aidrip,^ Zevs Sc
rion
yrj, Zeis r ovpavhs Zevs roi to

which

Trdyro. x^'<- '^'y^'

(VeoTeooi/,

ILLUSTRATED
future retribution

BY NEW RELIGIOUS
and even of

^
;

this

IDEAS.

change traces

may be

seen in the poetry of the time of Euripides.^


Lastly, in connection herewith an ascetic code of

morals

has come into vogue, enjoining abstinence

from animal food,^ celibacy ,Hhe avoidance of certain


defilements,^ and the wearing of white clothing.
Philosophy,

could only appropriate in an


intellectual form the general idea of this asceticism,
it is true,

the renunciation of
till

a later

all

its

what belongs
time did it embrace

external

it as

Not

a whole with

belongings,

in the system of the


Before that time came, thanks to

Neopythagoreans.

the state of intellectual


in Greece, it

to the senses.

and mental development


itself on another and a more

life

had entered

brilliant career.
'
Comp. Zellei\
388, 581, 654.

Vol.

I.

54,

2 Besides Euripides
(p. 19, 1),
Melanippides (Fr. 6 in Bergli,
Lyr. Gr. p. 982) appears to have
regarded the soul as immortal.
lo, too (Fr. 4 in Bergh, p. 464),

appro])riates the Pythagorean


belief in immortality.
reso-

lution of souls into aether may


also be implied in the popular
belief

mentioned

of

Empedocles and

Pythagoras.
*

Probably EiiHp., Fr. 884,

refers to this.
* That
this was a part of
Orphic perfection may be ga-

thered

from

typical

Euripides,

who

chastity,

reminds

of
of
chastity also occurs in Electra,
V. 254, and it is well known

Orphic virginity.

A vow

that marriage was forbidden to

many

priestesses,

though more

rarely to priests.

by Aristo-

phanes (Peace, 832), that the


dead become stars.
' See Euripid.y Hippol.
949
Fr. 475; Plato, Laws, vi. 782,
C, comparing therewith the
principles

holds up Hippolytus as a type


of an Orphic, probably only
because this despiser of Aphrodite (Hippol. 10, 101), by his

*eu7a) 7eVeo-tV t6 ^porwv koI


oh xp^/^'^rdfievos (Eu-

v^KpoQr}Ky]s

rip., Fr. 475, 16), consequently


the same KaOapeveiv airh K-fiSovs
Kal Xexovs (toucliing a corpse
or woman who has been confined), which the P^'thagorean
of Alexander
Polyhister
in
Dior/., viii. 88 requires.
Birtli
and death, for reasons closely

allied, are regarded as polluting.


Compare Eimp., Iphig.

Taur. 372; Thuc.iii. 104.

D 2

.35

Off A
I.

I'

STATE OF CULTUliE IN GREECE.

36

CHAPTEK

II.

CHARACTER AND PROGRESS OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY IN


THE FIFTH CENTURY.
Chap.

J^

of Socrates inherited from that which had


gone before it a rich treasure of religious ideas, of
moral principles, and scientific conceptions ; at the

The age

had declined at every point from the


Traditional
tone of thought and custom.

same time
earlier
lines

it

seemed now to be

had been discovered;

all

too narrow

new problems

new paths
pressed

for

ideas respecting the Grods

solution.

The legendary

and the

state after death,

had

meaning

lost all

for

the great majority of the educated ^ the very existence of the Grods had been denied by many; ancient!
;

customs had fallen into disuse


civil life, the simplicity

the orderliness

and purity of domestic

ofl

lifej

had given place to a wanton dissoluteness of conduct,'


and an unscrupulous pursuit of pleasure and profit/'
Principles subversive of all law and of all right werd
being unblushingly advocated with
approval of the younger generation.

and grandeur of the

the

The

cheerful
severity^

earlier art, the lucid beauty, th

classic grace, the self-contained dignity of the late


art,

began to resolve themselves into the study o


1

Conf. PUto, Eep.

i.

330, D.

ILLUSTRATED
mere

effect

BY PROGRESS OF PHILOSOPHY.

whilst under the influence of sophistry,

philosophy had come to disbelieve, not only in individual systems, but

also

the whole course of

in

previous enquiry, and even in the possibility of

ledge at

know-

all.

Far, however, from being exhausted hereby, the


spirit of Grreece

was only completely delivered by

the throes and struggles of the fifth century.

mental horizon was widened


ened

its

Its

thought was sharp-

views and conceptions enriched.

Its whole
had gained a new field since its sucrenowned exploits and glorious undertakings.

its

consciousness
cess in

If the meridian of classic art

and of free political


was past towards the close of this period, still
the newly-awakened culture of the understanding
life

was

full

of intellectual promise for the future

sophistry

for

had been destructive, not constructive, only

suggesting,

not accomplishing.

Some new and

thorough change was called for to satisfy not only


practical but also intellectual requirements.
Ancient
propriety of conduct, and the received philosophic
teaching having been once ousted by the altered

the times, simple return thereto became impossible.


But to despair on this account of all
spirit of

knowledge, and of

all

principles of morality, was

most

Allowing even that the received view


of both was inadequate, it by no means followed,

precipitate.

that all science,

and

morality was impossible.


On the contrary, the more the pernicious consequences of such a view were exposed, the more urgent
all

became the duty of avoiding them by a thorough

37

Chap

_L1___

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

38

transformation of

CJHAP.
_

the

whole tone of feeling and

thought, without, however, attempting the impos-

sible task of

simply restoring the past.

For this purpose some new path must be struck out.

A. Distino'

What

that path should be, a far-sighted eye could

Soaratio
from, pre-

discern with sufficient clearness by the aid of the

jMloeo-

experience of the past.

i^%-

duct had given way before the spirit of innovation,

p)'o-Soc?ntic tradi-

Socraiic ^
resting on

Knonledge.

iiiasmuch

as

it

and not on any

Traditional propriety of con^

rested

upon

instinct

and custom,

clear recognition of necessity.

He!

who would undertake a permanent restoration of moral


must found it upon
Earlier philo-|
knowledsfe.
^
^
*
sophy had been unable to satisfy the requirements
of the times, because it had been directed exclusively

Yiie

to a study of nature

because to the mass of

men

it

did not give sufficient preliminary education for the

work of life, nor to the thinking spirit any clue tc


the problem of its being and destiny. New philosophy must meet this want, must direct its attentioE
to the sphere of mind and morals, and work intc
shape the ample supply of ethical ideas underlying
Earlier sys-'
religion, poetry and received custom.
tems had succumbed before the doubts of sophistry
inasmuch as their method was too one-sided, depending too

little

on

definite conceptions respecting th(

nature and problem of knowledge to be able to with


stand a searching criticism which destroyed thei

means of each other, aud argue(


from the change and uncertainty of the phenomen;
of the senses that knowledge must be impossible

several platforms by

No

building that would last could be erected excep

ILLUSTRATED BY FROG BESS OF BHILOSOBHY.

ao

by laying the foundations deeper, except by finding

Chap.
'

some means of supplementing these several points


of view by each other, of harmonising them when
contradictory in some higher bond of union,^ and of
grasping the unchangeable essence of things amid

changing appearances.

The means wanted was sup-

plied by Dialectic, the

art of

forming conceptions,

and the result was philosophical Idealism. Thus the


knowledge of the faults and deficiencies in existing
circumstances led naturally to the turn taken by

time of Socrates.

[)hilosophy after the


ethics

Scientifi c

became necessary because of the tottering of

moral convictions

a wider enquiry, because of the

narrowness of the philosophy of nature

a critical

method, because of the contradiction of dogmatic


a philosophy of conceptions, because of the
systems
;

uncertainty of the observations of the senses

Ideal-

ism, because of the unsatisfactory nature of a materialistic

view of the world.

Precisely these features distinguish the Socratic

philosophy from that of the previous period.


pre-Socratic

simply and

philosophy was

philosophy of nature

and

to

leave

dialectical questions.

the dialectical tendency

solely

is

supreme.

and enquiries respecting

nature for

After

Socrates

His own attenvirtue.

With

rare exceptions the imperfect Socratic schools con'

Comp.

Zeller^s

Griechen, Part

I. p.

ticpUlo-

a ^^P^ *

tion was exclusively occupied with determining conceptions,

The

the transitional philosophy nature;

of the Sophists was the first


ethical

The

(2)

Phil, der
854, 860.

155.

In the sense given, Ihid.

I.

^Jl^^H^',
cejytions.

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

40
Chap,
II

fined themselves to the

same

field

;
'

Plato,' foundino;
fc)

his system in conceptions, completing it in morals,

forms a marked contrast to the natural philosophers,


who went before him. Even in Aristotle who treats
of physics

in

detail

and with an evident prefer-

ence for the subject, they are only a single branch


of a system, and in point of value subordinate to

metaphysics.

Such an increase of territory showed that the


whole platform of philosophy had changed.
Why
else should

thought have embraced other and more


extended materials, had it not been chano-ed in it-

and therefore no longer contented itself with


what had been before ? For the same reason the
philosophic method was a diiBferent one.
In previous
philosophy thought had dealt directly with its obself,

ley'StiTof
thisperiod
'trine tf^'

concep-

^^^^'

Systems

'^ ^^^ Socratic and post-Socratic


deals in the first place with conceptions

^^^^'

^^

it

^^^ ^^^^

^^^

objects indirectly, through the

The

of conceptions.

medium

older systems asked, without

further ado, what predicates belonged to things


instance, whether

not

what

is

real admits of

how and out of what the world

Socratic philosophy ever asks, in the

is

motion

or

The

made.

first

for

what

place,

things are in themselves according to their conception,

thinking not otherwise to obtain information

respecting their properties and conditions than by


the help of the conception of things thoroughly
mastered.^

No

conception of a thing can, however,

Compare, not to mention


other passages, the clear state*

ment in the Phgedo,

99,

Af ter

having vainly busied himself

BY PROGRESS OF PHILOSOPHY.

ILLUSTRATED
[)e

obtained, except by grouping together

its

41

various

Chap.

^ ^'
by smoothing down apparent
contradictions, by separating what is lasting from
what is changing, in a word, by that critical method, 0) Definiwliich Socrates introduced, and which Plato and Aris^conc'^i-''
totle elaborated and developed.
Former philosophers ^'^'*-

and

;ispects

liaving
\o

qualities,

gone forth from particular prominent features


and having failed

arrive at the essence of things,

l)ecause of their one-sidedness


iliat

it

was now required

the properties of an object should be taken

all

and weighed from every side, before a


judgment could be formed thereupon.
Thus the
into account

[)hilosophy of conceptions steps into the place of dog-

matism.

In this way reflection which by means


of sophistry had destroyed the older philosophy was
taken into the service of the new philosophy the

'

various aspects under

which things may be regarded,


were brought together and referred to each other but
;

not content with the negative conclusion that


our
notions cannot be true because they contain opposite
determinations, the new philosophy aimed at uniting
these opposites in one,

and showing that true science


IS not affected by contradiction,
inasmuch as it only
refers to that which unites opposites
in itself, and
excludes contradiction.
i

This pursuit of knowledge

with the enquiries of the natural pliilosophers he declares


himself convinced, that he has
only got into deeper darkness
by directing his enquiries into
things in themselves,

(rh.

fTKOTrwv

irphs

trpAyfiara tois

^Ae'TTft,;/
QfXfjLaa-i

6ura
rb.

koI eKdarr}

ruu

alaOijcrfwu ^mx^ipo)^ dTTTeadai

a,)Tcov.)ISo^Si] /moixpvt'ai etsrobs


Kdyovs Karacpvyd^ra eV e'/cetVots
<TKoire7y tuv ovtwv tt/j/ aK-hOuav
(the true essence of thino-s)
i.e. instead of irpdy^iara
xdyoi
instead of 6vra, dATj^Jm tUv

oyrwu.

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

42

through conceptions

Chap,

the

is

common

peculiarity of

the Socratic, the Platonic, and the Aristotelian philo-

'_

That the

sophy.

same bent

lesser Socratic

schools follow the:

will be seen hereafter.

If only conceptions can give true knowledge,

it'

follows that true being can only belong to that which


is

known by means

of conceptions

that

to the

is,

essence of things, as this presents itself in thought.

This essential being cannot, however, be

sought

Anaxagoras had early realised that

for in matter.

matter could only become a world by means of

spirit

then the old materialistic physics had been

since

discredited by sophistry

nothing remained but to

regard the form and purpose of things, the immaterial,


part in

them

most

as

conceptions, nay, even

essential for

determining

the,

to assign to it a true reality

underlying the appearance.

In this way the Socraticj

philosophy led logically to Idealism.


(2)

The beginnings

Theory

of concep-

^^-^^

tions ex-

of this Idealism are unmistak-,

even in Socrates.

His indifference to physical

panded hy enquiries and his preference for ethical ones prove


'piato '^and

Aristotle,

conclusively that he attributed to the inner world

much higher

value than to the outer world.

Resolve

his theory of final causes applied to nature into the,

metaphysical elements out of which


the conclusion

is

which a thing
gives

shape,

it

is

and

in

is

it

made, but the conception which

makes a thing what

more pronounced

Plato

composed

inevitable that not the material of

this accordingly represents its

Idealism

it is

it

is,

and

true nature.

that

in the school of Megara

runs through

all parts

Thi^
;

of his philo-

ILLUSTRATED BY PROGRESS OF PHILOSOPHY.

4.",

sophy side by side with a current of pre-Socratic

Even Aristotle is not

doctrines.

Chap,

faithless to this view.

'___

Whilst denying the independent existence of the


ideas,

he nevertheless asserts that reality

consists not in

matter but in form, and that the

Platonic

highest reality belongs to

On

ground he

this

spirit free

from matter.

states even in his physics, agree-

ing herein with his predecessors, that hnal causes are

Compared

higher than material causes.

with the

natural

therefore

philosophers of the pre-Socratic

period, even Aristotle

may fairly

be called an Idealist.

Starting from a consideration of nature, the preSocratic philosophy

made

it its

chief business to en-

quire into the essence and causes of external things,


for this
ties.

purpose going back to their material proper-

An

entirely different character

is

the philosophy founded by Socrates.

with the study of


Jiaitjlire

with

rather

g^git

displayed in

This begins

than the study of

ethics rather than physics.

It

aims at

of all by means of conand only in the second place naturally. It


substitutes an attitude of enquiry for dogmatic state

explaining phenomena,

first

ceptions,

Mind
now regarded as the higher element compared with
matter.
The philosophy of nature has developed
ment, idealism in the place of materialism.
is

into a philosophy of conceptions.

Not that
half of the

as yet the claim

human mind

and the end of science.


in

modern

0. Di.s^^

to be the measure of truth socnit'L


Far from reaching the sub- frompo^t-

an idealism in fact only


times the philosophy of this

jective idealism of Fichte


possible

was advanced on be-

i\an

phih-

^'^P^'J-

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

44

Chap.
II.

period

not nearly so subjective as the post- Aristo-

is

telian schools.^

In them the interests of speculation

are subordinated to those of morals

knowledge

is

regarded only as a means to virtue and liappiness;

whereas the independent value of science is fully admitted by the great philosophers of the present

To them knowledge

period.

speculation

made

is

is

an end in

the highest and noblest thing

itself;
;

action

depend upon knowledge, not knowledge


to depend upon the aims of active life.
Only a few
is

to

one-sided followers of Socrates, who, however, prove

nothing as to the general tendency, are an exception


to this rule.

{I) It still

heUeves
the attain-

ment of
knowledge
to he

pomhle.

simple belief in the possibility of knowledge


here displayed which was wanting in the post-

is

The doubts of the Sophists


are refuted, but in the mind of the philosopher
there is no need of overcoming doubt.
The problem
Aristotelian philosophy.

proposed

is.

How

can true knowledge be obtained,

in what kind of mental representations

sought,

how must the conception

No doubt

mined?

really possible.

The

is

to

the

knowledge

(e7rt(rTrj)U,Tj

8,

ri irore

rvydxvci ov
Theaetet. 145, E.)
is quite different from the doubt
;

is

Equally

are the answers to that problem.

question raised
there as to the conception of
;

is

the fundaschools
altogether

to the thinkers of this time.

them

be

be deter-

but that knowledge

later

Take for instance the The-

aetetus

it

it

search for a test

mental question of the

unknown
unknown

felt

of

must

as to the possibility of knowledge involved in the enquiry


for a standard.
2

Compare

Zeller,

duction to Part

III.

1. c.

and

Intro137.

I.

'

ILLUSTRATED BY PROGRESS OF PHILOSOPHY,


and Stoics, cut
They
short the question by practically begging it.

They did

not, as did the Epicureans

45
Chap.
'

did not, as did the Sceptics, despair of knowledge.

They did

not, as did the Neoplatonists, resort to

higher revelations.

They were content

well-regulated thought

Even

the

for

to look to

source

of

truth.

that branch of science, the independent pui'-

which was much neglected by later thinkers

suit of

physics

was

studied

in

this

epoch with success.

Socrates and the majority of his pupils

neglected

it,

but not so Plato

to a point final in the

main

may have

and Aristotle carries

for nearly

it

two thousand

If the post- Aristotelian Ethics proved at last

years.

faithless to the principles of the old Grreek morality,

partly under the influence of a world-wide extension,

partly

owing to their severance from

politics,

owing

withdrawal of the moral consciousness from

to the

the outer world, owing to a


sour asceticism
respect

is

dumb

resignation and a

the difference of epochs in this

simply seen by recalling the many-sided

sympathies of Socrates, with his cheerful enjoyment


of

life,

and his devoted attachment to

or the teaching of

his country,

Plato concerning the state, or

and society, or
the Epicurean doc-

that of Aristotle concerning virtue

the relation of the Cyrenaic to


trine of happiness.^
Is

it

true that the philosophy of this

second

(2) Dis-

period attempts in ethics to get beyond the established


^EthilT
bounds ? It supplements the propriety of custom by a

theory of morals and conscious action. It distinguishes


'

ComiD. Zellcr,

1.

c,

i.

139.

'

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

4P)

more

Chap,
TT

between the

definitely than the ordinary view

outward deed and the

It requires

intention.

what is ideal.
thrown on the meaning and motives of

rising above the life of the senses to

Light

is

moral consciousness.
taught, which

is

universal

philanthropy

is

not lost in local patriotism; and

accordingly the state

only regarded as an institu-

is

tion for the attainment of virtue and happiness, and

not as the

final

moral cause. For

all

that this period

removed from the apathy of either Stoic or


Epicurean, from the imperturbability of the Sceptic,

is far

from the asceticism of the Neoplatonist. It seeks


not to sever man in his moral activity from nature
regards virtue as the perfection of

with Aristotle

it

a natm-al gift

with Plato

of

what

is

advances from the love

sensibly beautiful, to the love of

work

for his fellowmen.

later

time

is

absent

political life.

mean between

The

is

world-citizenship of a

absent too

Even

what

requires the philosopher to

It

morally beautiful.

classic

it

is its

nationality and

in this respect,

it

holds the

a slavish surrender to the outer

world, and a narrow withdrawal therefrom.

Compared with the pre-Socratic era, the age of


Socrates is characterised by the diversion of philosophy from external nature to thought or to ideas.
Compared with the following age, it is marked by
the real character of its thought, that is, by the fact
that the thinker is not ultimately thrown back on
;

himself and the certainty of his own knowing, but

on attaining to the knowledge of what is in itself


In short its theory of a knowledge of
real and true.

ILLUSTRATED BY PROGRESS OF PHILOSOPHY.


conceptions

determines

may

be deduced

theory

its
its

character.

From

this

'

breadth of view reaching

beyond the physical one-sidedness of the preSocratic, and the moral one-sidedness of the post-

Chap.
"_

alike

method
dogmatism, and

Aristotelian schools, its critical


to the earlier

and

later

in opposition
its

idealism,

transfiguring the whole aspect of the outer world,

without, however, entailing any withdrawal therefrom.

The development

of

this

theory was carried

^' ^<i-

out in a simple and natural order by three philoso-

^^ %IT"^
phic schools, the founders of which belong- to three Socratic

and are personally connected


teachers and pupils.^ First comes Socrates assert-

successive generations,
as

ing that the standard of


lies

his

human thought and

action

knowledge of conceptions, and teaching


followers to acquire this knowledge by dealing
in a

with notions critically.

j?hi/.

Hence Plato concluded that

objective conceptions are in the true sense the only


real

things, a derivative

reality

belonging to

all

other things, a view which


critical

he upheld by a more
analvsis, and developed to a system.
Lastly,

Aristotle arrived at the conclusion that in a thing

the conception itself constitutes its real essence and

moving power.

By an

exhaustive analysis of the

method, he showed how conceptions were to


be formed and applied to particulars, and by a most
scientific

comprehensive enquiry into the several parts of the


universe, he examined the laws and connection of
conceptions, and the thoughts which determine all
that really

is.

'

Sagrates had as yet no system.


^
Comp. Zeller, 1, 9, 136, 142.

He

(i) Socrates.

'

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

48

Chap,

had not even any material groundwork.

'

that only in acquiring conceptions


to
^

be found, that true virtue

is

Convinced

true knowledge
in

consists

acting

according to conceptions, that even the world has

been ordered in accordance with definite conceptions,


and therefore shows design, in any given case he
tries

by a

prevailing notions to

critical testing of

gain a conception of the object with which he has


to deal,

and to

this

he devotes

all his

conclusion of every other interest.

powers, to the

But he never

went beyond this formal treatment. His teaching


was confined to general requirements and presumpHis importance lies not in a new view of
tions.
things, but in a new conception of knowledge, and

way he forms this conception, in his view of


the problem and method of science, in the strength
of his philosophical bent, and in the simplicity of his
in the

philosophical
(2) Plato.

The

life.

Socratic search for conceptions has

grown in

Plato to a discovery of them, to a certainty of pos-*


sessing them,

and gazing upon them.

With him

objective thoughts or ideas are the only real things.

Mere

non-existent

what

matter as such

idealess existence or

is

all

made up

things else are

and partly of what

is

not

is

simply

partly of

they therefore are

only real in proportion to the part they have in the


Granting that this is in advance of the
idea.
8ocratic view,
logically

it

is

no

less

from that view.

certain that it follows

The Platonic

ideas, as

Aristotle rightly understood them,^ are the general


'

Met.

i.

6,

987, b,

1.

ILLUSTRATED

BY PROGRESS OF PIIILOSOPIIY.

conceptions, which Socrates had arrived at, separated

from the world of appearance.

They

are also the

central point of the speculations of Aristotle.

him the

conception or the form

essence, the reality,

things

only form

thinking of

and

is

as it

absolutely real

constitutes

were the soul of

only thought

is

between Aristotle and Plato, that whereas


Plato separates the conception from the appearance,
difference

independent as an Ihsa, Aristotle,


in things themselves, without, however,
implying that form stands in need of matter to beplaces

come

it

as

it

actual, since it

Aristotle will not

is

in itself actual.

Moreover,

remove the idea out of the world

of

appearances, because it cannot in a state of


separation serve as a connecting link between individual things, nor can it be the cause and substance

Thus the theory is seen to be one and the


same which Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle represent
of things.

at different stages of growth.

In Socrates

it is

un-

developed, but full of vitality, pushing itself forward


through the husk of earlier philosophy in Plato it
;

lias

grown

to a pure

and independent existence

and

Aristotle it has overspread the whole world of


^eing and consciousness, exhausting itself in the

in

effort,

and moving towards a perfect transformation

later systems.

lant

Socrates, so to speak,

is

the preg-

germ, Plato the rich bloom, Aristotle the ripe

(3) Ao-is*''^^^'

the most intense reality, and therefore also


the most intense pleasure in life.
Yet there is this

regarding

^^'

the

man

to

Chap.

With

without matter, simple spirit

itself, is

4J)

STATE OF CULTURE IN GREECE.

50

Chap.
II.

(4) Difficulty

caused hy
Socratic
Schools.

fruit

of

Greek philosophy at the perfection of

its

historical growth.

One phenomenon only

will not fall into this his-

but threatens to break the continuity


of Grreek thought, viz. the imperfect attempts to
expand the Socratic principle which are seen in the
Megarian, the Cynic, and the Cyrenaic schools. In

torical chain,

a real and essential progress of the


philosophic consciousness was not indeed to be found,
inasmuch as philosophy, which had arrived at any
these

schools

rate in principle even in the time of

Socrates at

objective knowledge, such as could only be found


in a system, was by them limited to subjective train-i'

ing of thought and character. Nor yet can they be!


For not only were:
said to be wholly unimportant.
they, at a later period starting points for Stoicism,

Epicureanism, and Scepticism, but they also pro-'

moted, independently of this, many scientific enqui-j


ries, by means of which they exercised an undeniable
influence on Plato and Aristotle.

occurs elsewhere, and

is

met

The same

casei

with, even in this epoch,

Academy, and in the Peripatetic schools,


which had no independent influence on the;

in the older

both of

growth of philosophy, but yet cannot be overlooked


Of all these phenomena one and the
in its history.

same thing must be said. Their chief importance lies


not in their having expanded a principle theoretically,
but in their having been practically helpful in advancing it, by preserving the older forms of culture
for cotemporaries to see, here

and there improvin,^

and widening them, and by thus keeping the

philu-

ILLUSTRATED BY PROGRESS OF PHILOSOPHY.


mind

sopher's

in sight of a many-sidedness, without

which later systems would never have included the


products of the earlier ones.

This permanence of philosophic schools is not


therefore met with until philosophy had attained a
certain general extension, in Grreece not until

the

time of Socrates and Plato.

ming up

all

Whereas Plato, by sumthe pre-Socratic schools, put an end to

their existence

time no theory was put forward which did not propagate itself in a school until
the time that Neoplatonism put the coping-stone on
;

after his

Greek philosophy, in and with which all previous


systems were extinguished.
In later times, however
many intellectual varieties rise up side by side, only a
few of

them

possess a distinct life of their own.

rest are a traditional revival of previous


views,

cannot,

in

The
and

considering

the peculiar philosophical


character of an age, be taken further into account.
They need therefore only to be mentioned by the
historian in a passing way.

This statement applies

to the imperfect followers of Socrates.


Their doctrines are not an advancement in principle,

but only
incomplete reproductions of Socratic views, and connected with Socrates in the same way that the elder
Academy is with Plato, or the Peripatetic school
with Aristotle.

'1

51

Chap.
^^'

PART

II.

SOCRATES.

CHAPTER

III.

THE LIFE OF SOCRATES.


|

Chap.
^^^'

There

no instance on record of a philosopher


whose importance as a thinker is so closely bound
is

up with

his personal character as a

man

Every system,

the case of Socrates.

being the work of a definite person,


studied in the light of

it

of their intellectual

they grew

is

it is

true, as

may

best be

the peculiarities, culture,

misfortunes and circumstances of

the case of others

was in

as it

its

author

yet in

easier to separate the fruits

life

from the stock on which

doctrines can generally be received and

handed down quite unchanged by men of very

dif-j

In the case of Socrates this

ferent characters.

not nearly so easy.

His teaching aimed

is

far less ati

which can be equally well em-|


braced by different men, than at a special tone of
definite doctrines,

life

and thought,

at a philosophic character

art of intellectual enquiry, in short, at a

to be directly imparted and

and

thej

something not|

handed down unaltered,

HIS LIFE.
but

to

be propagated freely,

others being stirred

up to an analogous development of their


peculiarities.
So much the more anxious should this
make us for
detailed information as to the training
of a character

which has had so powerful an influence


on history.
Here a very common difficulty meets

What

us.

Socrates was, and

how he

acted in his riper years, is


well known; but only the roughest
outline is preserved of the circumstances of his
life.
Over the
earlier part of it deep darkness
rests. For the history
of his intellectual and moral
training, if

we except a
few scanty and for the most part
untrustworthy
statements of earlier writers, we are
left

entirely to

conjecture.

The youth and

manhood of Socrates
the most brilliant period of
Grecian history.
during the last years of the Persian
early

wmV

J i^!^\^iT\^T''^^i''^^-

^""^^

Apollodorusiin Biog. a.

44),

in the

fe of Socrates is the
date of his death
According
to nemetrius
Phulereus
1

and

i{JJwd. XIV

61),

probably

the second half of the month


Ihaigehon
For at this time

must be placed the return of

Dehan e,c.ph, which, according to Pluto (Pha^do,


59,
day before the
?i;^'-''^'V^.^
execution
of Socrates.
Comp.
the

DeliL^ndTohof
r^:r^
'^^hol- '^G^ottmg.
184fi
846.

;r ; a month
About

(Xenophon,
definitely

the

Mem.

thirty days),

month Munychion,

dicial

earlier

iv. 8, 2,

says

in
tlie jui.e.

enquiry
took
pla'ce.
must accordingly liave

bocrates

fall

in

Born

he was

condemned in April or
399 B.C., and have suffered death inMay or June the
same year. Since at the tinip
of his death LTad passed
Ss
^^^^

May

17, D.), but not lono- rCrito


,2, E. cLlls him in round n^"'

bers seventy), his birth

canZt

have fallenYater than 01? 7^


or 469 B.C. If his birthdav

/
is

rightly fixed for tie Gt^ Thar


gelion (Apoll. in Dion
Pint. Qn.
Conv. viii
i
i
^^''^"' ^^- ^' '^' ^5)' ^^^ '^'^^
not past at the time of the
judicial enquiry, we should

iiu

have to go back for it ?o 470


or even %7l
b.c
rComr.
Pockh. Corp. Inscnpt i
3?f:
^
mr,na,m, L c. 7)
The question then arises whe'

Chap.
^^^'

SOCRATES.

54

Chap.
III.

nearly cotemporary with

those great

all

As a

adorned the age of Pericles.


he participated in

which thanks to

its

all

men who

citizen of

Athens

elements of cultm-e,

those

imrivalled fertility of thought,

congregated in that great metropolis. If poverty and


low birth somewhat impeded his using them,^ still
ther these statements respecting the time of his birth are

guage of the Thesetet. 183, F.,


and the Parmen. 127, C, ttolw

a mere fiction; and


whether the birthday of Socrates, the fiaievTiKos, was not
placed on the 6th of Thargelion
to make it agree with that of
Artemis, as Plato's was made
to agree with Apollo's. If so,
he may have been born in
Any469 B.C. (Olym. 77, 3).
how, Apollodorus, placing it in

v4os, (TcpoSpa veos.

facts or

468 B.C. (01. 77, 4), {Diog. 1. c.)


Nor can the stateis wrong.
ment noticed by Diogenes that
he was only sixty years of age
weigh against the clear language of Plato, and probably
rests upon a transcriber's misHermann's observation
take.

De Philos. Jon.
A. 39) that Socrates
could not have been born in the
third or fourth year of an
Olympiad, since he was twentyfive {Synes. Calv. Enc. c. 17)
at the time of his interview
with Protagoras, which interview happened {Plato, Parm.)
at the time of the Panathenaea,
and consequently in the third
year of an Olympiad, will not
Supposing the
hold water.
interview to be even a fact,
which is very doubtful, the
remark of Synesius (Calv. Enc.
respecting the age of
c. 17)
Socrates is a pure guess, and
altogether refuted by the lan(Plat. Phil. 666,

^^etat.

ii.

'

That his father Sophronis-

{Xen. Hellen. i. 7, 15
Lach. 180, D.
how
Epiphanius, Exp. Fid. 1087, A.,

cus

Plato,

comes to

call

him

Elbaglus,

is

was a sculptor,
may be gathered from Piog. ii.
The services of his mother
18.
Phgenarete as a midwife are
known from Plato's Thesetetus,
As regards circum149, A.
stances, it is stated by Demetdifficult to say)

rius Phaler. in PkitarcJi^sLiife of


Aristides, c. 1, that he not only
possessed land, but had seventy
minse a considerable sum at
but this statement
interest
is at variance with the testimony of the best witnesses.
The reasons for it are without
doubt quite as weak as those
for a similar statement respecting Aristides, and arose seemingly from some Peripatetic's
wish to find authorities for his
view of the worth of riches.
Plato (Apol. 23, B., 38, A.;

Rep.
((Ec.

i.

337, D.)
2 xi. 3

ii.

and Xenophon
;

Mem.

i. 2,

1)

represent him not only as very


poor, vdvv fiiKpa KKTT}fx4yos and
iv

Trivia

fivpia,

but they also

give reasons for thinking so.


Plato makes him say, perhaps
he could pay a fine of a mina,
and Xenophon depicts him as

HIS LIFE.
in the

55

Athens of Pericles, not even the lowest on the

city roll

was debarred from enjoying the rich pro-

most part devoted


nor yet from associating

fusion of art, which was for the


to the purposes of the state,

with

men

in the highest ranks of

personal intercourse did far

more

This free

life.

to advance intel-

lectual culture at that

time than teaching in schools

Socrates had reached

manhood

before the

Sophists

introduced a formal system of instruction.

Intelli-

gible as

it

thus becomes,

how an

energetic

man in

the

many incitements to
and how even he could be

position of Socrates could find

and means of culture,


carried

away by the wonderful elevation of

city, still

nothing very accurate

his native

known

is

respect-

ing the routes by which he advanced to his subse-

quent greatness.^

We may

suppose that he enjoyed

the usual education in gymnastics and music,^ al-

though the

stories

which are told of

estimating his whole property,


inclusive of his cottage, at five
min}\3.
The story of Libaniiis
(Apol. Socr. t. iii. p. 7), accord-

ing to which Socrates inherited


eighty minae from his father,
and lost them by lending, bearing his loss with extreme composure, looks like a story intended to show the indifference
of a philosopher to wealth,
Had Plato and Xenophon
known the story, we may be
sure they would not
have
omitted to tell it.
See the work of K. F. Hermami, De Socratis magistris et
disci plina juvenili, Marb. 1887.
- Plato says so plainly in the

his teachers in

Crito, 50, D.
Even apart from
this testimony there could be

no doubt.

Porphyry's state(in Theod. Cur. Gr. Aff.


i. 29,
a statement unp. 8)
doubtedly derived from Aris-

ment

toxenus that Socrates was too


uneducated to be able to read,
need scarcely be refuted by
authorities such as Xen. Mem.
i.

6,

14

iv. 7, 3, 5.

It is clearly

an exaggeration of the well-

known

a7rai5eu<rta {Plato,

221, E.,

which

1!);),

only

S3nnp.

A., Apol. 17, B.),

belongs

to

the

satirical outside of the philoso-

was readily taken


and exaggerated by

pher, but

hold of

jealousy in later times.

Chap.
i

SOCRATES.

66
Chap.
III.

music

deserve no credit.

We

hear further that he

enough of geometry to be able to gTapple with


difficult problems, and that he was not ignorant of
astronomy ^ but whether he acquired this knowledge
in his youth, or only in later years, and who was his
We see him, in mature
teacher, we cannot tell.^
learnt

more or less close with a number


of characters who must have exerted a most varied
and stirring influence on his mind/ It is beyond

years, in relations

According to Max. Tyr.


Connus was his
4,

xxxviii.

teacher in music, and Euenus


in

Alexander (in
poetry.
ii. 19) calls him a pupil

B'log.

of

Damon,

whereas

Sextus

13) makes Lampo


his teacher. All these notices

(Matth.

have

vi.

undoubtedly come from

passages in Plato, which are irrelevant. Socrates calls Connus


his teacher (Menex. 235, E.,
and Euthyd. 272, C), but according to the latter passage
he was a man at the time, so
that he must have gone to
Connus simply with a view to
revive a skill long since acquired.
It is more probable
(however often such notices
are given as historical, and
with further details
Cic. ad
Quint, i. 10
Fam. ix. 22
Diog. ii. 32
Val. Max. viii. 7
Flor. 29, 68) that the
Stoh.
passages in Plato refer to the
Connus of the comic poet
Ameipsias, from which the
whole fabrication comes.
See
Damon's
Herviann, p. 24.
name is mentioned in the
Laches, 180, D., 197, D.
Eep.
:

cian appears as the friend


rather than as the instructor of
Socrates, and as an important
political

iii. 400, B., 424,


C, in which
passages, however, this musi-

his

lastly, the Lampo of Sextus probably owes his existence


to a mistake. Sextus may have
written Damon instead of Connus {StotcBus, Flor. 29, 68, has
Connus in the same connection)
or else Lamprus (a name
which occurs in the Menexenus,
though not as that of a teacher
of Socrates), and transcribers
made it Lampo. The celebrated
prophet of this name cannot of
course have been intended.

2
^

from

And

character,

connection with Pericles. The


Phsedo, 60, C, and the Apology,
20, A., mention Euenus, yet not
as a teacher, and hardly even
as an acquaintance of Socrates.

Mem. iv. 7, 3, 5.
Maximus 1. c. says Theodore
Xen..

of Cyrene, but this is only an


inference from Plato's Theaetetus,
*

and not warranted by it.


For instance, the Sophists

PoluS;
Gorgias,
Protagoras,
Thrasymachus, but
Hippias,
Cf Plato,
especially Prodicus.
Prot., Gorg., Hip., Eep. i. Xe//.
.

Mem.
Also

ii. 1,
21
Euripides,

iv.

4,

5,

&ic.

who was on

HliS LIFE.

67

doubt that he owed much to such relations


but
these friends cannot in strict accuracy be described
;

as his teachers,

so-called

although we

neither

is

may

them

often find

any light derived hence

the history of his early training.

We

for

meet
with expressions which show that he must have had
a general acquaintance with the views of Parmenides
and Heraclitus, of the Atomists, of Anaxagoras, and
further

Whence he derived
impossible to say.
The stories

perhaps of Empedocles.'^

this

knowledge,

that

it is

he received instruction in his younger years from


Anaxagoras and Archelaus, can neither be supported

by satisfactory evidence, nor are they probable in


themselves.^ Still more uncertain
such intimate terms with him
that the comic poets charged
him with borrowing his tragedies

from Socrates.

(Cf. Bioff.

18; JElian, V. H. ii. 13.


Also Aspasia
cf Xoi. CEc. 3,
14
Mem. ii. 6, 36 J^schines
in Cic. de Invent, i. 31
in
Max. Tyr. xxxviii. 4
conf
Ilerr/iann De ^sch. relig. 16
ii.

Hermesianax in Athen. xiii.


599, a; Diotima (P^j^o, 8ymp.).
Respecting several of these

we

know not whether Plato was


true to facts in bringing them
into connection with Socrates.
'
Socrates calls himself in
Plato a pupil
of
Prodicus
{Zeller, 1. c. i. S73, D.), of Aspasia (Menex. 235, E.), and of
Diotima (Symp. 201, D.), all of

times.

Mag.

in

p, 11.

the two ladies consisted in free


personal intercourse, even allowing that Diotima is a real
person, and the Menexenus a
genuine dialogue
not only
this, but
the same applies
equally to Prodicus. Maximus
calls Ischomachus his teacher
;

in agriculture, but he probably


arrived at this conclusion hj

misunderstanding Xen. QEc. 6,


17.
The story that he was a
pupil of Diagoras of Melos (the
Scholiast on jWistojjJi. Nubes, v.
828), is obviously false.
- Xen. Mem. i. 1, 14
iv. 7, 6.
* The
authorities are
for
Anaxagoras, Aristid. Or. xlv.,
;

p. 21,

and the nameless authoriby Dioff. ii. 19

ties referred to

and 45, whom Suidas 'S.uiKpa.T.


according to custom follows

and present
Hermann, Soc.

for Archelaus, I>wg. ii. 16, 19,


23, X. 12, and those mentioned

past

See

his supposed inter-

re-

which statements have been


peated

is

We may

suppose

that the instruction given

by

by him,
Diodes.

Aristoxenus, and
Besides these Cicero,

lo,

(Jhap.
III.

'
;

SOCRATES.

58

Chap.
III.

course with Zeno and Parmenides.

known

Even

little

is

of the philosophical writings with which he

Sextus, Porphyry (in Theod.


Cur. Gr. Aif. xii. 67, p. 175),
Clement of Alexandria (Strom,
i. 302, A.), Simplicius, Eusebius
(Pr. Ev. X. 14, 13, xiv. 15, 11,
XV. 61, 11), Hippolytus, the spurious Galen, and a few others
Forsch. 210.
conf.
Krisclie,
The evidence in favour of
;

Anaxagoras

very insufficient,

is

and the language respecting


him used by Socrates {Plato,
Pheedo, 97, B. and Xenophmi,
Mem. iv. 7, 6) makes it improbable that he knew him personally, or was acquainted with
his views, except from books
and hearsay, which of course
does not exclude any casual or
accidental intercourse.
The
traditions respecting his relations to Archelaus are better
yet even here
authenticated
there is much that is suspicious.
Of the two earliest authorities,
lo and Aristoxenus, the former,
who was an older contemporary
of Socrates, does not make Archelaus his instructor. All that
is stated in Biog. ii. 23, on his
authority, is that Socrates, when
a young man, travelled with
Archelaus to Samos. This assertion, however, flatly contradicts
Plato (Crito, 52, B.), who says
that Socrates never left Athens,
except once to go to the Isthmian games, or when on military duty.
Miiller, however,
gets over the difficulty (Frag.
Hist. Gr. ii. 49, N. 9) "by supposing that Plato was only referring to Socrates when grown
up.
It is just possible that Plato
;

may

not have known of a journey which Socrates took in his


earlier years.
That he should
have knowingly omitted to
mention it, as Alherti Socr. 40
supposes, is hardly likely. It
is also possible some mistake
may have been made. lo may
not have meant a journey to
Samos, but his taking part in
the expedition to Samos of 441
B.C., which, strange to say, is
not mentioned in the Apology,
Or the error may lie
28, E.
with Diogenes, who applied to
Socrates what lo had said of
j

some one

else.

Or

it

may

not

be the lo of Chios, but some


individual
who thus
Certain it
writes of Socrates.
is, that lo's testimony does not
prove Socrates to have been a
pupil of Archelaus. Even if the
relation were proved to have
existed in Socrates' younger
days, it would still be a question whether his philosophy:
was influenced thereby.
Aristoxenus goes further. According to his account in Diog.
Socrates was the fa-'
ii.
16,
vourite of Archelaus, or as
Porphyry represents the mat-;
ter, he became acquainted with^
Archelaus in his seventeenthi
year, lived with him many
later

'

'

years, and was by him initiated


shall haveji
into philosophy.
occasion to notice hereafter ho:

We

dependence can be place


on the statements of Aristoxe
nus respecting Socrates. Wen
the other statement which
to be found in Diogenes closely

little

ii

connected with this one, that

HIS LIFE.
was acquainted.^

Phaedo

him

describes

.5t)

well-known passage in Plato's

advancing from the older

as

natural science and the philosophy of Anaxagoras to


his

own

But

peculiar views.

it

most improbable

is

that this passage gives a historical account of his in-

no other reason, at
one,^ that the course of development

tellectual development, if
least for this

for

there leads to the Platonic theory of conceptions; let

alone the fact that

it is

by no means certain that

Plato himself possessed any fuller information respecting the intellectual progress of his teacher.

No doubt
trade,'*

he began

worthlessness would be
shown for Socrates
was seventeen when Anaxagoras left Athens, and had long
passed his years of pupilage.
The assertions of Aristoxenus,
however, are in themselves improbable.
For supposing Socrates to have been on intimate
terms with Archelaus, when
young, twenty years before
Anaxagoras was banished, how
IS it conceivable that he should
ras, its

tlioroug-lily

md

have known Anaxagoras 1


if he was instructed by

lim in philosophy, how is it


hat neither Xenophon nor
Plato nor Aristotle ever menion Archelaus ?
All the later
I'luthorities for the relation of
he two philosophers appear to
rest on Aristoxenus.
As there
js nothing in the teaching of
"Vrchelaus, with which the SoI

father's

a trade which he probably never practised,

Socrates did not become a


pupil of Archelaus till after
the condemnation of Anaxago-

lot

by learning his

life

cratic teaching can be connec-

seems probable that he


do with the philosophy of Socrates, even though
Socrates may have known him
and his teaching.
Besides,
Socrates (in Xen. Sym.) calls
himself an avrovpyhs rris (piXoted, it

had

little to

<ro(f>ias,

self-taught

philoso-

pher.
'

He

seems to have known

those of Anaxagoras.
A supposed allusion to the writings
of Heraclitus (in Dioff. ii. 22),
is uncertain, nor is it established that he ever studied the
Pythagorean doctrines (Plut.
Curios. 2).
2 96, A.
^ As
Volqvardsen, (Rhein.
Mus. N.F. xix. 514; AlheHi
Socr. 13
Uebei'weg, Unters
d. Plat. Schr. 94
Steinhar'ty
;

Plat, L., 297.

Timon and Duris

in Diog.
Timiuus, according to
Porpliyry in CyHl c. Jul. 208,

ii.

19.

Chap.
III.

SOCRATES.

00

Chap.
III.

and certainly soon gave up.^

Considering

his special calling to labour for the

it to

moral and

be

intel-j

improvement of himself and others, this conviction forced itself so strongly upon him, as to

lectual

appear to him in the light of a divine revelation.*

He

was, moreover, confirmed therein by a Delphic

oracle, which, of course,

must not be regarded

as the

but rather as an additional support to, his


reforming zeal.^ How and when this conviction first;
cause

A.

of,

Plato (Eep.

vi.

496,

B.)

seems to have had the case of

writers, the matter stands thus


Chserephon had asked at Delphi
if there were a wiser man thani
Socrates, and the priestess had
answered in the
negative.!
The Iambics which purport to

Socrates in view.
Porphyry leaves it open
whether Socrates or his father
practised sculpture nor is anything proved by the story that
the Graces on the Acropolis
were his work {Biog. Paus. i.
No allusions are found in
22).
Aristophanes, Plato, and Xenophon to the sculptor's art.
Hence we may conclude that
if Socrates ever practised it, he
gave it up long before the play
of the Clouds was acted. Duris
'

and Demetrius
(in Biog.

ii.

of

Byzantium

19), in stating that

he was a slave, and that Crito


removed him from a workshop

and cared

for his education,

appear to confound him with


Phaedo.
2 Plato, Apol. 38, C.
eVol 8^
rovro
irpoffT^raKraL vnh
Tov deov irpaTTeiv Kal e'/c ixavTeiuv
:

....

KOL e| ivvirvLOiv Kou Tvavrl TpSirc^,


ipirep ris irore

avQpdiTcp

Koi &XX7} deia (xo7pa

KaX

briovv

irpoaera^e

iroieTu.

According

the wellknown story in the Apol. 20,


E., which has been repeated
countless times by succeeding
^

to

answer in DiogS
and Suid. aocj)6s belong'

contain the
ii.

37,

of course to a much laterperiod.


Whereupon, says So-'
crates, he had thought over'
the sense of the oracle, and, in'
the hope of finding it, he had
conversed with all who made
pretensions to knowledge. At
last he has found that neither
he himself nor any other manwas wise, but that others believed themselves to be wise,
whilst he was conscious of his
want of wisdom.
He considered
himself
therefore
pledged in the service of
Apollo to a similar sifting of
men, to save the honour of the
oracle, which declared him, although one so wanting in wisdom, to be the wisest of men.
Allowing that Socrates really
said this and there is no
doubt that he uttered it in
substance it by no means follows that his philosophical
activity dated from the time

>

HIS LIFE.

61

dawned on him, cannot be determined. Most probably it grew gradually in proportion as he gained
more knowledge of the moral and intellectual circumand soon after the beginning of
the Peloponnesian war he had found in the main his
stances of his time,

philosophical centre of gravity.'

From

that time forward he devoted himself to


the mission he had assumed, regardless of everything

His means of support were extremely scanty,^


and his domestic life, in company with Xanthippe,
else.

was far from happy.^

Yet neither her passionate

Pythian oracle.
Else
what should have led Chserephon to put the question, or
the oracle to give the answer
of the

it did 1
So that if in the apology he speaks as though the
Delphic oracle had first aroused
him to sift men, it must be a
figure
of
speech.
Without
going so far as Colotes (in
Plut. adv.
Col. 17, 1), and
Athenreus (v. 218) and many
modern writers (B?-ueker, Hist.

Phil.

i.

534,

Van Dalen and

Ileumann), and denying the


historical
character
of the
oracle altogether and certainly it cannot be very rigidly
proved we must at least attach no great importance to it.
It may have done a similar

service to Socrates as his doctor's degree did to Luther, assuring him of his inward call,
but it had just as little to do

with making

him a

philosophi-

cal reformer as the doctor's de-

gree had with making Luther a


religious reformer.
The story
of the response given to his
father when he was a boy

{Pint. Gen. Socr. c. 20) is altogether a fiction.


This is proved by the part
which Aristophanes assigns to
Socrates in the Clouds. If at
that time, 424 B.C., he could be
described as the chief of the
'

new

learning, he must have


for years according to
a definite method, and have

worked

gathered about him a circle of


friends.
In the Connus of
Ameipsias, which seems to have
been acted at the same time as
the Clouds, he likewise appears
as a well-known person, and lo
in his travelling memorials had
previously alluded to him. See
p. 56, 1

57, 3.

See

The name of Xanthippe

p. 54, 1.
is

not only proverbial now. Later


writers of antiquity {Teles, in
Stoh. Flor. 5, 64; Seneca De
Const. 18,5, Epist. 104, 177;
Porphyi'y (in Theod. Cur. Gr.
Aff. xii. 65)
Bioqenes (ii. 36)
Plutarch (Coh. Ira, 13, 461),
;

who however tells the same of


the wife of Pittacus, Tranq. An.
ii. 471
jElian (V. H. xi. 12)
;

Chap.
III.

SOCRATES.

t)2

Chap.

character would he allow

to ruffle his philosophic

III.

AtliencBus

(v.

219);

many

&c.), tell so

St/nesius,

little stories

and disgraceful traits of her


that one almost feels inclined
to take up the cudgels in her
behalf, as Heumann has actually done (Acta Phil. i. 103).

What Xenophon (Mem.

ii.

and Plato (Phajdo,


60, A.) say of her, shows that
she cannot have been altogether
badly disposed. At least she
was solicitous about her family,
though at the same time she
was extremely violent, overbearing, and hard to deal with.
Sym.

10)

2,

It is remarkable that Aristophanes in the Clouds says nothing of the married life of
Socrates, which might have afforded him material for many a
joke. Probably Socrates was not
then married. His eldest son is

called twenty-five years later


(Plato, Apol. 34, D. Phsedo, 60,
A.) fieipcLKiov ^St), and there are
two young children. Besides
Xanthippe, Socrates is said to
have had another wife, Myi'to,
;

a daughter or grand-daughter
of Aristides: after Xanthippe
according to Aristotle (in Diog.
conf Stoh. Floril 86, 25,
ii. 26
Posidon in Ps. Pint. De Nob.
18, 3 less accurate is Plutarch's
.

which Athen. xiii.


555 follows) hefoi-e her according to another view (also in
Diog.) and at the same time
with her according to ArisAristid. 27

toxenus,

Demetrius

Phaler.,

Hieronymus Rhod., Satyrus,


and Porphyry, in Cyril, c. Jul.,
so that he had two
vi. 186, D.
wives at once. The fallacy of
;

the last view has been already


exposed by Pangetius (accord-

ing to Plut.), and in modern


times most thoroughly by Luzac
Atticae,
Leyden
(Lectiones
Not only is such a
1809).
thing incompatible with the
but
Socrates,
character of
amongst his cotemporaries
foes and friends, Xenophon
Plato, Aristophanes, and other
comic poets, including Timon
there is no allusion to a rela^
tion,

which would most

im^

doubtedly have, had it existed


caused a great sensation and
have provoked attack and de
fence, and derision in the high
est degree. The laws of Athens
never allowed bigamy, and the
decree purporting to be vd
favour of it, by which Hie
ronymus attempts to give pro
bability to his story (the same

which reference is made bj


Gell N. A. XV. 20, 6, from the
supposed bigamy of Euripides'
either never was passed, o]
must bear a different meaning
The only question is, whethei
there can be any foundatioi
for the story, and how its ris<
Shall th(
can be explained.
Pseudo-Aristotle be believed

to

who

says that Myrto

was

hi;

second wife, and the tw(


younger sons her children
But this cannot be reconcilec
with' the Phaedo 60, A., let alon
the fact that Myrto, as
daughter of Aristides, must havj^
been older than Socrates (whosi
j

father in Laches, 180, D,is men


tioned as a school companion o
her brother), and far too old the)
to bear children. Or shall it, oi
the contrary, be conceded (witj
Luzac) that Myrto was Socrates
first wife, and that he marriec

HIS LIFE.

ej^i

composure,' nor could domestic cares hinder the oc-

Chap.
III.

Xanthippe

her death ?
This, too, is highly improbable.
For, in the first place, neither
Xenophon nor Plato know anything about two wives of Socrates, although the Symposium
would have invited some mention of them.
In the second
place, all the biographers (a
few unknown ones in Diogenes
excei)ted), and particularly the
after

Pseudo-Aristotle, from whom


the rest appear to have taken
the story, say that he married
Myrto after Xanthippe, and
that Sophroniscus and Menexenus were her children. Thirdly,
Socrates cannot possibly have
married the sister or the niece
of
Lysimachus, the son of
Aristides, before the battle of
Delium, since at the time of
the battle (Lach. 180, D.) he
did not know Lysimachus perall

sonally.

Nor can

his first

mar-

riage have been contracted


after that date, since Xanthippe's eldest son was grown
up at the time of his death.

And
150,

lastly, in Plato's Theitet.


E.,
shortly before his

death, Socrates mentions this


Aristides, as one of those who
had withdrawn from his intellectual influence without detriment to his relationship as a

kinsman.

Thus the connection between


Socrates and Myrto seems to
belong altogether to the region of fable. The most probable account of the origin
of the story is the following.

We
of

gather from the remains


the

iStob.

treatise
Flor. 86,

Trepi

24,

(vyeviias

25;

88,

For note

'

the genuineness of which


was doubted by Plutarch, and
certainly cannot be allowed,
that this dialogue was concerned with
the question,
wnether nobility belonged to
those whose parents were vir1

3),

tuous.

Now

none were more

celebrated for their spotless


virtue
and their voluntary
poverty than Aristides and So-

Accordingly the writer


brought the two into connec-

crates.

tion.
Socrates was made to
marry a daughter of Aristides,
and
since
Xanthippe was
known to be his wife, Myrto
was made to be his second
wife and the mother of his
younger children.
Others,
however,
remembered
that
Xanthippe survived her husband.
They thought it un-

likely that Socrates should be


the son-in-law of a man dead
before he was born, and they
tried to surmount these difficulties in various ways.
As
regards the first difficulty,
either it was maintained that

Myrto was his second wife and


that the younger cliildren were
hers, in which case it was
necessary to place her side by
side with Xanthippe, as HierouA^mus actually did, and Invented a decree' of the people
to make it probable
or to
avoid romance, this supposition
;

was given

up, and Myrto was


to be his first wife, who
then can liave borne him no
cliildren, since Lamprocles, his
eldest son, according to Xeno-

made

phon, was a child of Xanthippe.


The second difficulty could he

see next page.

SOCRATES.

(14

Chap.
III.

cupation which he recognised to be the business of


His own concerns were neglected lest he
his life.

To be

should omit anything in the service of God.^

independent, he tried, like the Grods, to rise superior


to wants ; ^ and by an uncommon degree of self-denial

and abstemiousness,^ he

so

succeeded that he

far

could boast of living more pleasantly and more free


from troubles than any one else.^ It was thus possible
for

him

to devote his whole powers to the service of

others without asking or taking reward


over either by making
Myrto a grand-daughter instead of a daughter of Aristides, the grandson of Aristides the Just. PUto, Lach. 179,
The former
A.; Theaet., &c.
was the usual way. The latter
is the view of Athengeus.
1
See Xenoplion 1. c, not to
mention later anecdotes respecting this subject.
2 Plato, Apol. 23, B.
31, B.
3 Conf. Xen. Mem. i. 6, 1-10,
where he argues against Antiphon, that his is a thoroughly

got

happy mode of life, ending


with the celebrated words
rh Sh ws iAaxiarcov iyyvraro} tov
deiov.

of Sosimplicity of his
life, his abstinence from sensual pleasures of every kind,
his scanty clothing, his walking bare-foot, his endurance of
*

The contentment

crates, the

hunger and

thirst, of

heat and

cold, of deprivations and hardConf.


ships, are well known.
Plato,
Xe7i. Mem. i. 2, 1 3, 5
Symp. 174, A., 219, B. Ph^dAristojyh. Clouds,
rus, 229, A.
103, 361, 409, 828, Birds 1282.
;

Xen.

Mem.

i.

6,

iv. 8, 6.

and

this

Mem. i. 2, 5 i. 5, 6
Plato, Apol. 19, D. 31
3
Euthypro, 3, D.
B.
33, A.
Symp. 219, B. In the face of
these distinct testimonies, the
statement of Aristoxenus {Diog.
ii. 20) that from time to time
he collected money from his
pupils, can only be regarded as

i.

Xe?i.

6,

a slander. It is possible that


he did not always refuse the
presents of opulent friends
{Diog. ii. 74, 121, 34 Sen. de
Benef i. 8 vii. 24 Quintil.
Questionable
Inst. xii. 7, 9).
anecdotes (JDiog. ii. 24, 31, 65
;

Stob. Flor. 3, 61

17, 17)

would

prove nothing, to the contrary,


but no dependence can be
placed on these authorities.
He is said to have refused the
splendid offers of the Macedonian Archelaus and the Thessalian Scopas {Diog. ii. 25
Arrian or
Sen. Benef. v. 6
Pint, in Stoh. Floril. 97, 28;
Dio Chrys. Or. xiii. 30), and
this tale is confirmed as far ay
the first-named individual is
concerned by Aristotle, Rhet.
ii. 23, in a passage which Bayle,
Diet. Archelaus Eem. D. disputes without reason.
;

SIS LIFE.

65

occupation so confined liim to his native city


that he
rarely passed its boundaries or even
^
its gates.

To take part

in the affairs of the state

not, however, feel a call

not only holding

impossible to act as a statesman


that day without violating his

it

he did
to be

in the

Athens of
principles, and loath-

ing submission to the demands of a


pampered mob ;^
but far more because he recognised
his own peculiar
task to lie in something very
different.
Any one
sharing his conviction that care for
one's own culture
must be preferred to all care for public
affairs, and
that a thorough knowledge of
self, together with a
deep and many-sided experience, is
a necessary qualification for public life,^ must
regard the influencing
'
of individuals as a fiir more
important business

than

the influencing of the

community, which without the


must consider it
a better

other would be profitless


service

to

country to educate able statesmen


than actually to discharge a
statesman's duties ^
Any one so thoroughly fitted by
nature, taste, tone
3f thought and character,
to elevate the morality
md develop the intellect in others by
means of
3ersonal intercourse, could hardly
feel at home in
his

'In the Crito, 52, P..; 58, A.,


e says, tliat except on military
uty he has only once left
Uhens, going as a deputy to the
sthmian games
From the
^haedrus,

230,

C, we gather
"

hat he rarely went outside the


\

m Apol
Pto,
^

pj^^
^ j^ 33 ,
the Gorgias (473, E.j ironical?^
expresses it\ because he was
too plain for a statesman
''^'^''^"Conf. Gorg. 521 D
^ P/../., Apol.
36,' Symp
210
A. Xen. Mem. i v. 2,
^iii 6
" I^lato, Apol.
29, C. 'dO d"33, C. Go;g. 513. E
4

31

C.

'

'

'

Chap.

; ;

SOCRATES.

66
Chap.
III.

any other line of

life.^

Accordingly, Socrates never

attempted to move from bis position as a private


By serving in several campaigns with tli
citizen.
bif
greatest bravery and endurance,^ be discharged
As a citizen he met miduties to bis country.

Socrates asserts this in


Plato quite explicitly. In Apol.
31, D., lie remarks that his
ZaifjiSviov sent him back from a
public life, and wisely too
for in a career spent in opposing the passionate impulses of
the masses he would long- since
have been ruined. The Sai/A(5viov which deters him is the
sense of what is suited to his
individuality. That this sense
^

him rightly, is
conducted
proved by the consideration
that a public career, had he
taken to it, would not only
have been unsuccessful in his
case, but would also have been
most injurious for himself
and Socrates usually estimates
the moral value of conduct by
If this consideration,
success.
as it no doubt did, confirmed
his dislike to a public career,
still the primary cause of this

dislike, the source of that insuperable feeling, which as a


haiix6viov preceded every estimate of consequences, was without doubt something immediate. Had a public position suited his character as well as the

he chose, he would as little


have been deterred by its dangers, as he was by the dangers of that which he adopted
life

(Apol. 29, B.). He states, however, that his occupation afforded him great satisfaction
with wliicU he could not dis-

pense, Apol.

'6rL
38, A.^
oi
ayadhv
Ti/yxavei jxiyierov
avOpuTTQ} rovro, iKatrTTjs 'hfi^pa

Trepl aperris

Koi
ifjLOv

rovs XSyovs Troielada

&Woi}v, -n-ept uv v^iel


aKovT diaXeyoixivov Ka

ruv

i/xavrhv kol &\Xovs iC^rd^ovros,


Se aj/eleVao'TOS )3tos ov ^lurhs av
OpWTTCf}.
2

See the stories in PhiU

Apol. 28, E.
219, E.
Lach. 181, .^
i.
Chai-m.
Of the three expeditions mer
tioned in the Apology, thn
to Potidsea, 432 B.C., that t
Delium, 424 B.C., and that t
Amphipolis, 422 B.C., the t\\
^
first are fully described.
Potidfea Socrates rescued Ale
blades, but gave vip in h
favour his claim to the pri:

Symp.

His fearless retre;


from the battle of Delium
A
mentioned with praise.

for valour.

tisthenes (in Athen. v. 216,


refers the afEair of the prize
the time after the battle
Probably Plato
Delium.
right, being generally well-i
formed on these matters. T

doubts which Athenasus rait


respecting Plato's account a
Naturally, howevi
trivial.
other accounts derived frc
his account cannot be quot
in support of it. The stc
that Socrates rescued Xer

phon at Delium

{Straho, ix.

seems to confou.
7;
Xenophon with Alcibiades.
Diog.)

HIS LIFE.

67

demands alike of an infuriated populace


and of tyrannical oligarchs, in every case
of danger,^
firmly and fearlessly; but in the
conduct
righteous

of affairs

he declined to take part.

Nor would he appear as a public


teacher after
manner of the Sophists. He not only
took no

the

pay, but he gave

no methodical course,^ not professing to teach, but only to learn


in common with
others; not to force his convictions
upon

them, but
examine theirs not to pass the truth
that came
to hand like a coin fresh
from the mint, but to
awaken a taste for truth and virtue, to
show the way
thereto, to overthrow spurious,
and to discover real
knowledge.3 Never weary of
converse, he eagerly
to

every opportunity of giving


an instructive
and moral turn to conversation.
Day by

Iseized

day he was
public promenades, in
schools and workshops, ever ready
to have a word
[about

in

the market and

^th

mi

friend or stranger, with citizen


or foreigner,
always prepared to give an
intellectual or

^urn to the conversation.^


X6;.

^htJ'Atl
5
^,

V? A

ep^^^^^^
epiist.
1 lat. vii.

1, 18,

and

'

^'

1ST'
^24, D.

2,

IrV
^^''
sec

'''^'''

12t-Tv./.?.V?'''/r.

eX:t".^
L

7^1 Of/.riv

.1.C

t
()6

'''''\ ^'^'^^

Tis

Epicurean

ixov

X^yovTos

lac^^^

moral
Whilst thus servin- God

and of Favorinus

in Dior,. ...
ii.
-?' *'^^' ^'^ ^-^^^ instruction in

?"'"3-i' eeds
tutation.
'

^^'^''^-^

^'^'''''''

no further

re-

"^ ^11 ie dialogues.

-^^1

^^^

discussed

h:?

after.

ScL^.V, b

LtT^ZX: t^^

Chap.
"

J^

SOCRATES.

g8

Chap
'-

;
-

Ws

he was persuaded that he


country in away that no one

wii>

hic'lier calling',

also serving his

else

he deplored the decline of


his native city,^ on the
discipline and education in
Sophists,' he could
moral teachers of his time, the

For deeply

could do.'

The

place no reliance.

won

for

him

a circle of

consisting of

as

attractiveness of his discourse


admirers, for the most part

young men of

family,^

drawn

to

him by

him

various

longer,

part,

he was

standing to
the most varied motives,

and coming to him, some


a shorter time.^ For his

relations,

others for

for

these friends, but to


anxious not only to educate
pertaining to their good.
advise them in everything
of this changing, anc
even in worldly matters.^ Out
society, a nulceus wa;
in part only loosely connected
admirers, a Socratii
gradually formed of decided
o
less by a common set
school, united, however, far
love for the person o
doctrines, than by a common
more intimate friends he tre

With
quently had common
founder.

its

have been a fixed institution.

scarcely

in- 4- 56

'"

5,

Such

ca,
a

of ui
to require other branches

him

appeared to
<?

meals,' which, however,

42, is no-

^^OToXoueoWTts

/^o.

ols

Aii\>ff->

tot
ardent admirers, not only
thenes, bnt also ApoUodor
Aristodemns, who appe
i

rt^fl n^dence

"'i "p;i^

36,

''''x;.

r
a, Z%

Mem

Conf.
30^'a
Gorg.
d":
i).,
41
^^
o
41,

^3
3,

Mem.

iii. 5,

iv. 4,

.5,

13.
.

which

is

not

at variance with Plato, Apol. 19,

B, nor yet with the passages

"""'^Kp

i.

23,

C,

oi

.'0.

and

^^^g^3igto PUU, Symp. I.


^*
i- A
''T Xen. Mem. 'iTl
= Conf.
iv 2 40
{^^^'
;

S Zm
~^^^1.

^^i^T

'''x..Mem.iii.l4.

HIS LIFE,
strueiion, or

69

whom

he believed unsuited for intercourse with himself, he urged to apply to other


teachers, either in addition to or in place of himself
J
Until his seventieth year he followed this course

of

iction with his

powers of mind unimpaired.^ The


an end to his life and his

olow which then put


ictivity will

be mentioned hereafter.

Plato, Thecctet.
len. Mem. in. 1
'-

'

.,

151,

Symp.

B.
4,

Aenophon and^ Plato most-

represent Socrates as an old


aan (such as he was when they

ly

knew him), without showing


any trace of weakness in his
mental powers up to the last
moment. That it was a wronoview is distinctly stated in

Mem.

iv. 8, 8.

Chap.
^"

SOCRATES.

70

CHAPTER

IV.

THE CHARACTER OF SOCRATES.

Chap.
IV.

Ancient writers speak of the character of Socrates in


terms of the greatest respect. There are, however,

A. The
greatness
of the character of

some exceptions, quite apart from the prejudice


occasioned by his condemnation, which no doubt
Followers of
survived some time after his death.

Socrates.

Epicurus indulged their love of slander even at his


expense,^ and one voice from the Peripatetic School
has scandalous stories to

tell

respecting his

life

as

a boy he was disobedient and refractory ; as a youth,


profligate ; as a man, coarse, importunate, given tc

sudden bursts of anger, and of


Cicero de N. D. i. 34, says
that Ms teacher, the Epicurean
Zeno, called him an Attic bvifEpicurus, however, acfoon.
cording- to Diog. X. 8, appears

to have spared him, although

depreciated every other


philosopher.
- The source from which these
unfavourable reports, collected
by Luzac, come is Aristoxenus,
Lect. Att. 246 (from whom we
have already heard similar
64,
61, 3
things, p. 58, note
From this writer come
5).
the following statements that
ws
mentioned in Pori)hyry
yeyovoi rpaxvs els opyrju,
<l>{iffi

he

Bui

fiery passions.^

Kul onoTC KpuTTjOeirf

r^

irddei Su

t^dSi^ev
Synesins (Enc. Galv. 81) wil
have this limited to his younge
years that of Cyril, c. Jul. vi
Theod. Cvir. Gr. Afl
185, C.
Sre Se (|)Aex06i
xii., 63, p. 174
(mh rov irdOovs tovtov Seiv%

-ndcTTjs

a.(Txr]fxo(rvv'i]s

elvai

ydp

7T]v

ovT

ovhevl

a<TXf]P-0(rvv7]V

ovS/xaTOS

airoffx^f^^*

ovT -Kpdyjxaros and another c


Cyril. 186, C. Theod. 1. c.) thi
;

Socrates was in
temperate, irphs

other
5e

t))v

waj
to

(r<po5p6Tep
XP^^*-^
fxkv elvai, a^iKiau Se /x't] irpoff^lvc
^ yap rais yap-erals ^ Ta7s KOivo
Xpvordai fidvais, and then aft
a(ppo5i(ri(i}V

HIS CHARACTER.
we have

the stories

and the chief

of this kind are so improbable,

relater is so untrustworthy,

that

we

cannot even with certainty^ infer that Socrates only


became what he was after a severe struggle^ with his
the lii.story of his bigamy he
concludes ^Ivai 54 (prjaiv ahrhv
:

iv TOAS

6/ni\iais

avexB^oya

alvcos

re

<^iA-

koI \oidopov Kal v^pia-

From the same source,


may be gathered from Pint.

tik6v.

as

Mai. Her. c. 0, p. 856, comes


the charge which Thcod. 1. c.

quotes from Porphyry,


naming Aristoxenus,

1.29, p. 8

vvithout

avThv

6e

e?j/at

ov5ey

irphs

fxev

airaiSevTou oe irepX irduTa,

o.<pvr\,

so that he was
read,
besides

hardly able to

what

follows

(Ibid. xii. 66, p. 174


conf. iv.
iXeyiTo 54 irepl avrov
2, p. 56)
us &pa ira7s Sov ovk e5 fiiaxreiej/ ovSe
euTuKTus' irpuTov (Xiv yap (paaiv
ahrhv TCf Trarpl SLureXeaai, aireiBovvra kou OTrdre /ceAeucetej/ avrhv
;

Kafi6vTa
Te'xfr/j/

opyava ra

TO.

irepl

airaj/rau OTTovSr^iroTe

tt?;/

6\i-

yopwavra

rov
irpoaTdyixaTos
irtpiTpexav
avrhv
OTrovd-n-nore
S6^eiu .... ^v
5e
/cat
ruv
iiriTifxuiJ.4vuv Kal raSc '^coKpdrei
'6ti (Is rovs ux^ovs daoiQuro
Kal
ras Siarpi^as iiroiuro rrphs ra7s
rpane^ais Kal

Herewith

irphs raTs

'Ep/ta?s.

to illustrate the

power of readefective natural


disposition, as illustrated in
Plato, Symp. 215, 221, B. If
the story was current in the
time of Aristoxenus, he may
have used it for his picture;
but it is also possible that his
description produced the story,
which in this case would have
an apologetic meaning.
The
son over a

name

of Zopyrus would' lead us


to think of the Syrian magician, who, according to Aristotle
in Diog. ii. 45, had

foretold the
Socrates.

violent death of

As may be already seen


from the stories respecting the
bigamy, the gross ignorance,
the violent temper, and the
'

sensual

indulgences

of

So-

crates.
2 As Hermann does,
De Socr.
Mag. 30.
3 Though
this is in itself
possible, we have no certain
authority for such an assertion.
The anecdote of Zopj-rus is,

connected the
the physiognomist

as already remarked, very uncertain, and where is the war-

(Cic. Tusc. vi. 37,


Fat. iv. 10 Alex. Aph.
De Fato, vi., Peru. Sat. IV. 24
Conf. Max. Tyr. xxxi. 3), who

rant that Aristoxenus followed


a really credible tradition?

story of
Zopyrus.

83

is

De

He

refers,

father

declared Socrates to be stupid


and profligate, and received
from him the answer, that by
nature he had been so, but had
been changed by reason. This
account can hardly be true. It

still

looks as if

stance

it

had been devised

it

true,

is

Spintharus, an

to

his

actual

acquaintance of Socrates. But


the question arises whether
this statement is more trustworthy than the rest.
The
chronology is against it, and

more
of

so

is

what

the

sub-

Spintharus

Chap.
IV.

'

SOCRATES.

72
Chap.
IV.

as the perfect

Our best authorities only know


man, to whom they look up with

whom

they regard as the exemplar of

natural disposition.

him

and

respect,

humanity and morality.


'

'

No

one,' says

Xenophon,

ever heard or saw anything wicked in Socrates

pious was he that he never did anything without

consulting the Gods

any one

in the least

so just that
so

so

first

he never injured

master of himself that he

never preferred pleasure to goodness

so sensible that

he never erred in his choice between what was better


and what was worse. In a word, he was of men the
best

and

He

happiest.'

further represents Socrates as a pattern of

hardiness, of self-denial, of self-mastery; as a

It may also be asked


whether Spintharus spoke the
truth, when he professed to

His
and inferences.
overdrawn imagination makes
Socrates as a boy dissatisfied
with his father's business, and

says.

sions

witnessed outbursts of
anger in Socrates, who must
then have been in the last

as a

liave

years

of

his

life.

we have no more
believe him than

Certainly
reason to
his

son.

Aristoxenus does not


his remarks to the
youth of Socrates, but they
are of a most general character,
Lastly,
confine

or refer distinctly to his later


Luzac, 1. c. 261, would
appear to have hit the truth

3^ears.

when he makes Aristoxenus


responsible for all these statements. For Aristoxenus appears not only to have carried
his warfare with the Socratic
Schools against the person of
Socrates, but also to have indulged in the most capricious
and unfounded misapprehen-

man

man

pass his life in the


In the same way he
finds that Socrates must have
been a man without culture,
because of expressions such as
that in the Apology, 17, B., or
that in the Symp. 221, E. 19!),
A. violent in temper, in support of which he refers to
Symp. 214, D. and dissolute
because of his supposed bigamy,
and the words in Xen. Mem. i.
ii. 2, 4, and p. 51, 2.
3, 14
Mem. i. 1, 11; iv. 8, 11.
R. Lange's objections to the
genuineness of the concluding
chapters of the Memorabilia
(iv. 8) (De Xenoph. Apol. Berl,
1873) do not appear sufficiently
strong to preclude their being
streets.

'

cited as an authority.

HIS CIIAliACTER.
of piety and love for his

coimtiy,

fidelity to his convictions, as

73
of

unbending

a sensible and trust-

worthy adviser both for the bodies and souls of his


friends
as an agreeable and affable companion,
with a happy combination of cheerfulness and
;

seriousness

above

all,

as

an untiring educator of

embracing every opportunity of bringing


all with whom he came into contact to self-knowledge
and virtue, and especially opposing the conceit and
character,

thoughtlessness of youth.

Plato says the same of him.


He too calls his
teacher the best, the most sensible, and the most
just man of his age,' and never tires of praising his
simplicity, his moderation, his control over the wants
and desires of the senses ; imbued with the deepest
religious feeling in all his doings,' devoting his
life

whole

to the service of the Gods,

and dying a martyr's


death because of his obedience to the divine voice
and like Xenophon, he describes this service as the
exercise of a universal moral influence on others, and
particularly on youth.
In his picture, too, the more
serious side in the character of Socrates is relieved

by a

real kindness,

an Athenian polish, a sparkling


cheerfulness and a pleasing humour.
Of his social
virtues and his political courage Plato speaks in
the
same terms as Xenophon, and adds thereto an admirable description of Socrates on military service.^

Every

which he mentions adds to the clearness


of that picture of moral greatness, so wonderful
for
'

trait

See the end of

tlie

Phiedo.

g^g p^g.^ gg^ ^^^^

2.

Chap.
^^'

:
;

SOCRATES.

74
Chap.

very originality, for the absence of

its

studied and artificial about


self-glorification

Hh

B.
character
refectin<i

Greek iJcculia^ntie,^.

Owing

and

that

all

is

for its exclusion of

it,

affectation.^

to its being a native growth, the Socratic

type of virtue bears, throughout, the peculiar impress

Greek mind. Socrates is not the insipid ideal


of virtue, which a superficial rationalism would make
of him, but he is a thorough Greek and Athenian,
taken, as it were, from the very marrow of his nation,
possessed of flesh and blood, and not merely the universal moral standard for all time. His much-lauded
moderation is free from the ascetic element, which it

of the

seems always to suggest in modern times. Socrates


enjoys good company, although he avoids noisy
carousals

and

he does not

if

the senses an object in

life,

make

the pleasures of

no more does he

.avoid

them, when they are offered to him, nay, not even

when

Thus the

in excess.

Xenophon's banquet

'

Most

is

not

the traits and


recorded by later

of

anecdotes

writers are in harmony with


Some
this view of Socrates.
of them are certainly tictions.

may be taken from wri-

Others

tings of

Socrates,

pupils of

which have been since lost, or


from other trustworthy sources.
They may be f omid in the following places. Cic. Tusc. iii.
Oif. i. 26 and 90
15, 31
;

Be

Seneca,
Ira,

i.

15, 3

Const.
;

iii.

5;

18,

11, 2

De

ii. 7, 1

Tranqu. An. 5, 2 17, 4 Epist.


Plin. H. Nat. vii. 18;
104, 27
Plut. Educ. Pu. 14, p. 10 De
;

small cups in

call for

made for

fear of indulging

Adulat. 32, p. 70 Coh. Ira, 4,


455 Tranqu. An. 10, p. 471
Garruiit. 20 Dioff. ii. 21, 24
vi. 8
Gell N. A. ii. 1
27, 30
;

p.

xix.

9,

Val.

9;

^lian, V. H.
36

iii.

xiii. 27,

Stoh.

28
32

i.

ix.

Max.
16
7,

29

viii.

ii.
;

11, 13

15

xii.

AtJien. iv. 157

17, 17 and
leg. Graeo. libr.

Flor.

c.

22

Op
Basil. De
179, a. Themist. Orat. vii
95, a. S'wqyl. in Epict. Enchir.
few others
c, 20, p. 218.

II.

have been or will be referred


to.
- Plato,
174, A.

Symp. 220, A.

conf

HIS CHARACTER.
too largely, but that exhilaration

Plato describes

rapid.'

much

equally well take

him

75

may

not be too

as boasting that he can

or little, that he can surpass

drinking, without ever being intoxicated him-

all in

and represents him at the close of the banquet


leaving all his companions under the table, and

self,^

as

pursuing his daily work, after a night spent over the

had happened.

bowl, as if nothing

appears with

him not

Moderation here

to consist in total abstinence

from pleasure, but in perfect mental freedom, neither


requiring pleasure, nor being ever overtaken by

its

seductive influence.
points

is

His abstemiousness in other


also recorded with admiration.^
Numerous

passages, however, in Xenophon's

prove that his morality was far

standard of principles.
affection

for

The

'Memorabilia''^

below our

strict

Grrecian peculiarity of

boys marks, indeed, his relations

youth, but his character

is

above

all

to

suspicion of

actual vice,^ and he treats with irony a supposed


Xen. Mem.

^v
2, 26
\
T}tuv^ oi TraTSes fxiKpais kxiKi^l ttvkva

e7ni|/e:a^a)(Ti>/,

virh

(6fj.evoL

dAA'

tov

avaTrei96fj.ej/oi

uUnrcpov

ovrws

ov

oXvov

fiia-

/xedveiv,

nphs rh iraiyvi-

a<pL^6ix(da.

Symp.

17(5,

C.

A.;

220,

J^

K.

^l'>>
"^

Xen. Mem. i. 2, 1 3, U.
have already seen that
;

We

Aristoxenus and his followers


cannot prove the contrary.
i. 3, 14;
ii. 1, 5
iii.
2, 4
11; iv. 5, 1).
Conf. Conv. iv.
^

'^8.
^

"

Tlie

crates

cotemporaries of So-

seem

to have found nothing to object to in Socratic

affection.

Not only

is

there

no allusion to it in the judicial


charge, but not even in Aristophanes, who would undoubtedly have magnified the smallest suspicion into the gravest
charge. The other comic poets,
according to Athen., v. 21 1>,

knew nothing of
Xenophon deem

it.

it

Nor does
necessary

refute this calumny, and


therefore the well-known story
of Plato's banquet has for it's
object far more the glorification tlian the justification of
his teacher.
On the other
hand, the relations of Socrates
to Alcibiades, in the verses
to

Chap.
TV
'

SOCRATES.

76
Chap,

^'

love-afiair

At the same time, what

of his own.^

Grreek in the presence of youthful beauty was proof

agaiEst a certain element of aesthetic pleasure, which


at least was the ground and origin, even though (as in
his case)

an innocent one, of deeper affection ? ^

The

odious excrescences of Grreek morality called forth


his severest censure

yet at the same time, accord-

ing to Xenophon,^ and ^schines,'* and Plato,^ Socrates described

relations to

by the name of Eros,

friends

ment grounded on
wise

own

his

may

or a passionate attach-

Not other-

sesthetic attractions.

be noticed in his

peculiarities

Grrecian

ethical or political views, nor

his theology free

is

from the trammels of the popular


not only in his simple obedience
life,

How deeply

belief.

these lines had influenced his character

country throughout

younger

his

may

be seen

to the laws of his

and his genuine respect for

the state religion,^ but far more also in the trials of


purporting- to be written by
Aspasia, which AtJienceiis communicates on the authority of

have a very susand Tertiillian


ApoL c. 46 mistakenly applies
the words SiacpOelpeiv rovs viovs
In Juvenal
to paederastia.

Herodicus,

look,

picious

(Sat. ii. 10) Socratici c'unedi


refer to the manners of his
own time.
*
Xen. Mem. iv. 1, 2 Symp.
4, 27: Plato, Symp. 213, C.
Charm, loo,
222, B.
216, D.
;

* In his Alcibiades he speaks


of the love of Socrates for
Alcibiades.
8ee A'^-istid. Or.
xlv, Trepi prjTopiKTJs, p. 30, 34.
* Prot.
beginning; Symp.
not
218, B. 222, A.
177, D.
to mention other expressions
for which Plato is answerable.
^ Plato, Apol. 28, E.
Xe)W2)hoii, Mem. i. 1, 2, assures us not only that Socrates
took part in the public sacri-

Xen. Mem. i. 2, 29 3, 8
Sym. 8, 19, 32, with which
2

Plato agrees.
'

Symp.

iv. 1, 2.

8,

and 24

Mem.

'

but that he
in the habit of

lices,

home.

D.

was frequently

In Plato

sacrilicing at

he invokes

Helios, Symp. 220, D.

and his

words, according to the


Phaedo, 118, A., were an earnest

last

commission to Crito to
cock to ^sculapius.

offer

Often

a
is

"

HIS CHARACTER.
his last days,

when

77

of violating the laws,

for fear

Chap.
IV.

he scorned the ordinary practices of defence, and


after

his

condemnation

refused

escape from

to

The epitaph which Simonides inscribed on


the tomb of Leonidas might very well be inscribed
prison.*

on that of Socrates

Deeply

as

He

died to obey the state.^

Socrates

rooted

is

in

the

national

C'.

about him a something decidedly milike a Greek, presenting a foreip-n


and even almost modern appearance. This it wa&
character of Grreece, there

which made him

appear to

thoroughly eccentric and


a

for

G-reek

is

so

cotemporaries

his

singular

person.

^raitTin
^^^^ ^^^-

This,

something, which
he described by one word as his singularity,^ consisted, according to Plato's account,^ in a want of
unintelligible,

agreement between

his

outward appearance and his

belief in oracles mentioned,


whicli he
always conscientionsly obeyed (Mem. i. 8, 4
Plato, Apoi. 21, B.) and the
use of which he recommended
to his friends {Xen. Mem. ii.
;

8;

6,

5).

iv.

He

10; Anabas. iii. 1,


was himself fully per-

good to

harm

himself, and much


his friends and de-

to

pendants. The Apology speaks


as if entreating the judges
were unworthy of the speaker

and his country.

7,

Xcii. says: irpo^lx^To ixaXXov

'^

ro7s

v6/j.ois

suaded that he possessed an

Trapavo/xwv

oracle in the truest sense, in


the inward voice of his lmix.6-

Xa

viov, and he also believed in


dreams and similar prognosti-

cations.

(Plato, Crito, 44, A.


Pliiedo, (50, 1). Ai)ol. 'M\, C.)

This motive

is

represented

by X<;noj)hon (Mem.
and Plato (Apol. M, D.

iv.

4,

4)

Phiudo,
the decisive one,
although the Crito makes it
appear that a flight
from
98,

C.)

as

Athens would

have done no

ifxixivuv airodaveTy

^rjv.

Plato, Symp. 221, C.


UoXovu &v Tis Kol &XXa exoi

'

fjL^v

Soj/cpctTTj
.

'djxoiov

fxr\r

rh

5e

ilvai,

Twu vvv

irai/rhs

Ka\ dav/j-da-ia

iiraivicrai.

avQpunrwv

/xTjSej/l

ixTirc

rwu

6vto)u,

Qavfxaros

iraXaicov

rovro

....

&,^iov

5e
ouToal yeyove tt]v aroirlau &vdp(oTTOs Koi avrhs ol x6yoi avrov ov5*
iyyvs ttv evpoi tis ^tjtoji/, ovt rwv
vvv ovTC Twv iraXaiccv.
Sym]i. 215, A.
221, E.
'

oTos

Pro-

SOCRATES.

78

Chap,

inward and real nature. In this respect he contrasts


most strikingly with the mutual interpenetration of
both, which constitutes the usual classic ideal.

we behold

the one hand

On

in Socrates indifference to

the outer world, originally foreign to the habits of


his countrymen ; on the other hand, a meditative-

unknown

ness

there

is

before.

to the former feature

about him a something prosy and dry, and,

may be

the expression

if

Owing

allowed, philistine-like,

sharply contrasting with the contained beauty and


Owing to the
the artistic grace of life in Oreece.
latter

there

about him something akin to the

is

revelation of a higher

life,

having

its

seat within,

in the recesses of the soul, and not fully explained in


its manifestations, and which even Socrates him-

regarded as superhuman. In their account of


these two peculiarities both Plato and Xenophon
self

Even from an outward point

are agreed.

of view,

the Silenus-like appearance of Socrates, which Plato's


Alcibiades,^ and Xenophon's Socrates himself^ describe with so

much humour, must

rather have con-

cealed than exposed the presence of genius to the


But more than this, a certain
eye of a Greek.

amount of intellectual stiffness, and an indifference


to what is sensibly beautiful, is unmistakeable in his
speech and behaviour. Take for instance the process
of catechising given in the

'

Memorabilia,'

by which
j

a general of cavalry
1

Symp. 215

is

brought to a knowledge of his

conf. Thfeet.

"^

]^4
^

tiis

E.
Synip.
(Diss.

crates a pleasing appearance,


this is of course quite imtenable.

t)^^t

4,

iv.

19

2,

19

Epicte-

11, 19) gives So-

iii. 8.

HIS CHARACTER.
duties, or the

formality with which

71)

things,^

familiar to his hearers, are proved, or

tlie

long

way

in

which the idea of the beautiful is resolved into that


Or hear him, on grounds of expediof the useful.2
ency, advising conduct, which to us seems simply

abominable,^ or in the Phgedrus

refusing to walk

but because he can learn nothing from trees and the


country, and taking exception in the Apology^ to the

works of poets and

artists,

because they are the re-

genius and inspiration, and not of

sults of natural

Or

him

Xenophon's Symposium,^
despite the universal custom of the ancients,* dancing-

reflection.*^

see

in

alone at home, in order to gain healthful exercise,

and justifying his conduct by the strangest of reflections


unable even at table ^ to forget considerations
;

Taking these and similar

of utility.

account, there appears in

him a

traits

certain

into

want of

imagination, a one-sided prominence of the critical

and intellectual

faculties,

in short

a prosiness

which clashes with the poetry of Grecian


'

Symp.

iii; 8, 4.

230, D.

i'

10, 9;

iii.

'^

iii.

11.

'^ 14.

C.

and the

M. Crasso, in foro, mihi crede,


saltaret; Plut. De vit. jud. 16,
533, also the expressions in
Xcnoplion, 'Opxrifro/jiat rr? Aia.
^EvTavda Sr] 4ye\aaav airauTes.
:

This point will be subsequently discussed.


*

life,

And

22, C.

wlien Charmides
Socrates dancingt^

2, 17.

irpcoTov e^eiT\a.yr)u

Compare Menexenus,

236,
ye 5^7 xapikUv oXiyov d jj.e

aWa

fxivToi aoi

ware
anoSvvTa

Cfo-Bai,

KfKevoLs

&v

Xapi(raifxr]v

Mur. 6
brius,

Nemo

nisi

Offic. iii.

opxvo'aadai,

and Cicero pro

10

fere saltat soforte insanit


De
;

Dares banc vim

found
/teV

ye

Kal eSeiaa,

/j.^

ixaivoio, k. t. a.
Of the same
character was his instruction
in music under Connus, if the
story were only true of ]iis
having received lessons with
the sclioolboys.
Plato, Eu-

tliyd. 272, C.
"

Xen. 8ymp.

3, 2.

(Jhap.

_ ^Zl_

SOCRATES.

80
Ghai'.

^1

Even Plato's

refined taste of an Athenian.

_ allows, that at

Alcibiades'

sight the discourses of Socrates

first

appear ridiculous and rude, dealing as they invariably do with beasts of burden, smiths, tailors, and

and apparently saying the same thing in the

tanners,

same words. Was not this the very objection raised


by Xenophon ? ^ How strange that plain unadorned
common sense must have appeared to his cotemporaries carefully avoiding all choice figures, and
using the simplest and most

common

expressions.

This peculiarity was not, however, the result of


any lack of taste, bat of the profound originality of
j

which customary figures were insuffiYet again, sometimes the soul of the philo-

his ideas, for


cient.

into

sopher, diving

its

own

far

so

recesses,

lost

labour as to be insensible to external

itself in this

impressions, and at other times gave utterance to


enigmatical sayings, which appeared strange to it iu
*
Serious and fond of meditation

a wakeful state.

was Socrates,

as

it

not unfrequently happened that


\

Conf. KalSjTnp. 221, E.


Trepl
licles in Gorgias 490, C.
(Tiria Keyeis koL trora Koi larpovs
Koi (pXvapias .... arexJ'cDs 76
oeJ aKVTeas re Koi yuapeas koL /xa1

yeipous
Travel

\6ywv
cos

koL larpovs

rovrwu

Trepl

ouSei-

T]ixiv

ovra

Tou \6yov.
-

Mem.

a\xi

i.

rS)v 5e roi
Sei]<TL,

<p'n.

2,

37

d)

'O 5e Kpirias-

(re

airexeffQaL,

'S.wKpaTes,

rwr

cKvriwv Kai twj/ reKTovuv


Tuv yahKeuv, Ka\ yap ol/xaL
'

Toi/s

-^Stj

Xov/xevovs
4,

6: Koi

KaTaTeTf>T(/)0ai
uTi-b ffov.

av-

5ia0pu-

Again in

(xeu 'linrias-

Koi

in.

iv.

yap

cru,

%^7],

&

2'iKpaTes,

avra \4yeLS a iyw

eKelva

trdKai.

rh

irore

The like complaint


and the like answer is met,

ffov i^Kovcra.

with in Plato's Gorgias, 490,


E.

Conf. 497,

anva

C.

fftiiKpa

koI

ipuT-fifMara.

^ Accordingly in the Aristotelian problems, xxx. 1, 953, a,

26, he is reckoned amongst the


melancholy, which is not at
variance with the gentle firmness (rh ffraffLfiov) which Aristotle (PJiet.

him.

ii.

15) assigns to

///* CIlAJtACTEll.
.

I.p in

81

thought he remained,

line, indifferent to

for a longer or shorter


the outer world,' and stood
there

one absent in mind. According


to Plato, he once
lomained in this state, standing
on the same spot
from one day to the next.^
So energetically did he
struggle with himself to
attain an insight into his
every motive.
In doing this, he discovered
a resiMS

duum

of feelings

and impulses, which he watched

'with conscientious attention


without being able to
explain them from what he
knew of his own inner
life.
Hence arose his belief in those
divine revelations, which he thought
to enjoy.
And not only
was he generally convinced
that he stood and acted
in the service of God,
but he also held that supernatural suggestions were
communicated to him not
only through the medium
of public oracles,' but
also
dreams,' and more particularly
by a peculiar kind

i)f

higher inspiration, which


goes by the

name

of the

"locratic baiixoviovJ"

.'6.

63 and Anerti

Sorr

lis

.ave

entirely ^Istatn !,te


.
neaning of the text in snppo^.ng that it attributes
to'^SoTates any ecstatic stqtp

he authority wliich he
follow-

l^elurinl^

-ion

' ^^^^^ ''

Mi.'"'"
=

Onnf n tc t
^^60 '
CoSf
^uxu '^
bu,
p.

his deai

"S^t^^^ ^^VT'

ini-'

-- .i^-

K?-

wtn

fn

occa-

"^"'^

'"^

"^

f f
in
2.

*.
the

*''f*

"" "'^

^.:r.^^-

chap

^'

SOCRATES.

82

Even among the

Chap.
IV.
(a)

The

intercourse with a special


suggestions as derived from
which Socrates
personally-existing genius,^ of

and

Zaiix6vioy

7wt a 2)cr
sonal

regarded these

many

ancients

boasted

in

modern times

time the dominant one.^

was for a long


It was no doubt somewhat
this view

(Socratische Stiidien II., UpATskrift,


Universitets
sala
1870.

accusation
of
bill
to have
seems
Socrates
against
understood the ZaijxSviov in this
him
sense, since it charges
1

The

eVepa Kaiva
of the
place
the
in
UiixSvia
Gods of the state; nor does
BiUing'M (Socrat. Stud. II. 1)

with introducing

this, that
Apol.
26, B.)
Plato
Meletus (in
Sothus explained his language
Gods
the
denies
crates not only
Athens but all and every

remark make against

cratis, c.

xiv. H
Socratis, the

Max. Tyr.

ApuUvus, De Deo

Neoplatonists, and the Fathers,


who, however, are not agreed
whether his genius was a good
Plutarch,
one or a bad one.
and after him Apuleius, menSoition the view that by the

must be understood a
power of vague apprehension,
by means of which he could
ouess the future from prognos-

,x6viov

tications or natural signs.

Compare Tiedenmnn,

of

20

Geisi

Philosophic, ii
MeAnerii, Ueber den Genius
(Verm. Schriften
Sokr.

der spekulat.
16

des
God; the heavenly beings,
Wissensch
1); Gesch. d.
iii
attrihe
introduction
whose
Gesch. d.
Bnlile,
899, 538,
II
butes to him not being regarded
Gesch. d
Krug,
388
371,
Phil.
time
as Gods, Just as at a later
to.
iMmulr,
158,
alten Phil. p.
S^eoj
Christians were called
1858,
p. 20
Leben,
(Socrates,
though worshipping God and
uncritical and unsatis
Afterwards this view in his
Christ.
treatise respecting th
factory
appears to have been dropped,
be a res
Zai}ji6viov, believes it to
thanks to the descriptions of
deity, or eve
the
of
revelation
Xenophon and Plato, and does
even Fo.
even a real genius, and
not recur for some time,
the cor
as
gathers
qiiardseri
;

attributed to
in spurious works
Cicero,
Even
writers.
these
not
does
122,
Divin. i. 54,

by genius,
by 'divinum quoddam,
and doubtless Antipater, whose
work he was quoting, took it
But in
in the same sense.

translate Zaifx6viov

but

Christian times the belief

ma

universal, bein with the current


For inbelief in daemons.
Sostance, Pint, De Genio
o-enius

cause

became

it fell

elusion of his careful, and


many respects meritorious, di!
divir^
quisition, that a real
ifi
Socrates,
warned
voice
older literature inOlearnis, 14J
which ij
185, JBrucker, I. 543,
tl
eludes many supporters of
i

genius
that the
re_
Socrates was only his own
particulars
Further
son.

opinion

Erug,

1.

c.

and Lehd, Demon

Socrates, 163.

<

Iim CHAIiACTEIl.

83

humiliatiDg- in the eyes of


rationalising- admirers,
that a man otherwise so sensible
as Socrates should
have allowed himself to be ensnared
by such a superstitious delusion.

Hence attempts were not wanting

to excuse him, either on the


ground of the universal
superstition of his age and nation,
or else of his

having a physical tendency to


fanaticism J
Some
even went so far as to assert
that the so-called
supernatural revelations were a
shrewd invention,^
or a result of his celebrated
irony.3
'

The first-named excuse

condition of the brain during


rapture affects the nerves o^f
the abdomen and
irritates

is

universal.

Marsilius Ficinus
(Tlieol. Platon. xiii.
2, p. 287)
!iad assumed in
Socrates, as
well as in other i)hilosophers,
a
)eculiar bodil}- disposition for
3cstasy, referrino- their suscej>
ibility for su})ernatural reveations to tlieir
melancholy

them. To exercise the intellect


immediately after a meal or to
indulge in deep thought produces peculiar sensations in
the hypochondriacal.' In
the
strain is Meiner,^ Verm
Schr. iii. 48, Gesch. d. Wissensch. ii. .5-38. Conf. Schwarze,

same

emperament.

The personality
the dfiimon is not however
-ailed in question by him
or by
lis supporters {Olem-ius,
147).
Modern writers took refuge in
he same hypothesis in order
o explain in Socrates the
posibility of a superstitious
belief
II
a ^ain6viov. For instance,
"iedcmaiin, ''J'he degree of
exrtion, which the analysisof
ab)f

fract conception requires,


has,
some bodies, the effect of

II

lechanically predisposing to
cstasy and enthusiasm.'
<
SoI'ates was so cultivated
that

eep thought produced in him


dulness of sense, and came
ear to the sweet dreams
of
\e iKarartKoV 'Those
inclined
ecstasy mistake suddenly
>
sing thoughts for insi)iraons.'

'The

exlraordiiiarv

Such a view.

HistoriscTie

Untersuchung war
:

Socrates

ein

H^7)ochondrist ?
quoted by A'ruf/, Gesch. d. alten
Phil. 2 A. p. 168.
-

Plessinr/,

Osiris

and

Sothat
Socrates had bribed the Delphic oracle in order to produce
a political revolution, and
vaunted his intercourse with a
higher spirit.
Chauvin in
crates, 185,

who supposes

Oleariua.
^ Fra(/uier,
Sur I'ironie
Socrate in the Memoires

TAcademie des

Inscriptions,

de
de
iv.

expresses the view that So-'


crates understood by the SojH-6viov his own natural
intelli.}(38,

gence

and power of combination, which rendered it


possible for him to make
riirht

G 2

ClfAP.
IV.

SOCRATES.

81

hard to reconcile with the tone in which,


Soon the testimony of both Plato and Xenophon,

however,

is

the hatfioviovj
crates speaks of the suggestions of
these suggesor with the value which he attaches to
To explain
tions on the most important occasions.^
sickly body
the phenomenon by the irritability of a
of a
not far short of deiiving it from the fancy
monomaniac, and reduces the great reformer of
these
philosophy to the level of a madman.^ All
with,
explanations, however, can now be dispensed

falls

Schleiermacher having shown,^ with the general ap^S^^e^L probation of the most competent judges,^ that by
an inward
(b)

Be-

oracle.

guesses respecting the future

somewhat ironically he had


represented this as a matter
Qfiov

pure instinct, of

of

or

and employed for


purpose la^v-bviov and simi-

eela

^.otpo^,

this
lar expressions.

He

remarks,
however, that Socrates had no
thouo-ht of a genius familiaris,"5atM'5vtovhere being used
as an adjective and not as a
Similarly BolVm
substantive.
in his Histoire ancienne, ix. 4,
2 and BaHMlemy, Voyage du
jeune Anacharsis, treats the
expressions used respecting the
;

laip.6viov in Plato's Apology as


plaisanterie, and considers it
an open question whether Socrates really believed in his

others sharing the

On
genius.
view, see Lclut.

p. 163.

1. c.

Xen. Mem. iv. 8, 4. Plato,


Apol 31, C. 40, A. 41, D
* Manv have spoken of the
superstition and famticism of
Socrates in a more modest way,
recently
but comparatively
Belut (Du Demon de Socrate,
'

1836) has boldly asserted, 'que


a cateSocrate etait un fou
"

he

places
in
amongst others not only Cardan and Swedenborg, but

which

gory,

Luther, Pascal, Rousseau and

His chief argument

others.

is

that Socrates not only believed in a real and personal


genius, but in his hallucmations believed that he audiThose
bly heard its voice.

who

rightly understand Plato.

and can distinguish what i^


genuine from what is false.
will not need a refutation oi
these untruths
3 Platoiis Werke, i. 2, 432.
< Brandis,
Gesch. d. Gri

Rom.

Phil.

ii.

a.

60.

Bitter

Gesch. d. Phil. ii. 40. Ser


mann, Gesch. u. Syst. d. Plat<
Socher, Uber Platon;
236.
Cousin in thi
Schriften p. 99.
notes to his translation o

i.

Apology p. 335. Kruclu


Bxb&in
Forschun-en, 227.
Conf. Hegel Gesch
16.
Ast too (Platon
Phil. ii. 77.

Plato's

HIS CHARACTER.

86

the haifiovLov in the sense of Socrates, no genius, no


separate and distinct person, can be understood, but
only indefinitely some heavenly voice or divine

No

revelation.

passage in Plato or Xenophon speaks


of Socrates holding intercourse with a genius.

We

only hear of a divine or heavenly sign,^ of a voice


heard by Socrates,^ of some supernatural guidance

many warnings were

by which

All that these expressions

vouchsafed to him.^

imply

that Socrates was

is,

conscious

within of divine revelations, but how


produced and whence coming they say absolutely
nothing,'^ nay their very indefiniteness
proves clearly
enough, that neither Socrates nor his pupils had

any

Leben and Sclniften,

Saifxouiuv.

who takes

yiyvSfx^vdy

p. 482),
for a subthe deity,

dai/xomoi/

stantive

meaningdocs not see therein a genius


but only a deTov.
The passage Mem. i. 4. 14

Urav ol Oeol

ire/xTTwa-Lj/,

S)oirep

(To),

irefXTreiv avrovs aufifiovkovs,


proven nothing, as o-y^jSouXows
is used as a metonym
for crv/x-

pTJs

3ou\ds.
:

rh ^aijiSvLuv a-nixiiov.
E.
eyeuero rh dco'^s (TTjuclov, 7h SaL/jLOuioi/.
Apol.
rh Tov d^ov arifx^lov
)0;
t^
iaflby o-TjjueW.
Ibid. 41, D. c.
y. 4J)(), C.
'iUtliy. 272,
:

(rr]iJ.e7of.

Pluto, Apol. ;n, D.

e>oi
4k TraiShs ap^dfxevov,
>uvri ris yiyvofxfvr].
Xc//. Apol.
2
6(ov (pcovT}.
I

icTTiu

Plato,

1.

a\ haiij.6uioi>
^'^.

ri

c.

on

fxoi

yiyviTai.

fludv^d. fxoi

duSy ri
Also 40

fxavriK^

rj

rov

/aoi

3,

fxdvLov (pfjs

rjuaundoOr]
8, 5.

Mem.

i.

rh

1,

i(pr] (rrnxaiyeiv.

Saifioriou.

and
with

rh
:

Hymp.
writ-

Apology and
do not go

the
all

iv. 8, 5.

Even the spurious

D.,

Eu-

ings, Xenophon 's


Plato's Alcibiades
128,

A.: rh

151,

5aL,u6uiov.

B.
on dr) <rv rh 5aiaavTui cKaarore yly.

veadai.Xen.
daL^ouiou

further;

Plato, Phjedr. 242, B. t6


)aiix6viov re koL rh eioodhs (rr]/j.i76t/
101
yiyufadai iyh^ro, Kai rua
bwv^v e5o|a avrooe aKovaai. Hep.
-

ovr'

thyphro

Thea3t.

its

Theages.

romance

respecting the prophecies of


the Saifx6vioy, expresses itself

throughout indefinitely, nor


need the (pcm/T] rod Sai/xouiov p.
1 28,
E. be taken for a person.
The spuriousness of the Theages.
notwithstanding Socher"s defence needs no further proof,
especially after being exhaustively shown by Hermann, p.
427.
*

Doubtless Socrates regarded


or the deity as its ultimate

God

source.
But lie expresses nc
opinion as to whether it came
herefrom.

1\'.

SOCRATES.

80
Chap.
IV.

These revelations,
moreover,, always refer to particular^actions,^ and

very clear notion on the subject.^

ovT i^iduTi eco0ej/ o'lKoOiv ijuavTiTh rov 0eoi} (T-nixelov, ovre


TjvLKa av4^aivov iuTav6o7 iirl rh
\6yc^
rep
iv
ovr
SLKaarrjpiov,

mvich the same thin


daiixouiou be taken
for a substantive or an adjecThe probable rights of
tive.
the case are, as Krische, Forsch.
229 remarks, that Xenophon
uses it as a substantive = rh
deiov or 6 dehs, whereas Plato
1

It is

wQt)

whether rh

ov?iaixov

fiiWovri

ri ipeiv

'

iv 'dWois A07019 TToAAaxoC

XeyovTa

eTreVxe

[xera^v.

Kalroi
St]

fx.e

(4)

if such
Plato, Theeet. 151, A.
as have withdrawn from
again return, eVtois
society,
Baifx6vLOV
ixv rh yiyvoixevSv fMOi
diroKwKvei ^vvdvai, iviois Se ia.
Add to these cases a few others
in which Socrates himself more
or less jokes about the Saiixdviov^
which deserve to be mentioned
because it there appears in the
:

my

uses it as an adjective, explaining it as Saifxoviov o-rnLielGU,


and says Saiix6ui6v fioi yiyv^rai.
The grammar will admit of
either. Conf Arist. Rhet. ii. 23,
1398 a, 15. When, therefore,
Ast cites Xenophon against
.

Plato's explanation of Sai/xSvia


as SaifxSuLa irpAryixara, he probably

same character as elsewhere.


Symp. 8, 5, where
(5) Xen.

commits a ixirdfiaais els aAAo


The very difference bey4vos.
tween Xenophon and Plato

Antisthenes throws in Socrates'


rh duLfiSviou
ovdia\4yp fioi roT\
5'^AAoy rov icpii/xevos. (6) Plato
Phsedr. 242, B., when Socrates

teeth

proves how
spoke of the Saiixovtou.
2 This applies to all the inintervention
its
stances of
mentioned by Plato and Xenophon. They are the following
loosely

Socrates

totc

ixhv

irpoepaaiCoiiievos

wished to depart

rh Saiti6vi6v

Mem. iv. 8, 5, where


when urged to pre-

T6 Koi eluOhs o-nixelov fioi ylyvea-dai


iyfvcTO del 5e jue eTTiffX^' ^
^e'AAco Trpdrreiv Kai riva (f)(tiV7]v

aWa
pare a defence, replies
v)} Thv Aia, -J/Srj jj-ov iirix^ipovvros,

/xe ovK
edo^a avrSdev aKovcrai,
ia airievaL 7rp\v h.v a^oaicijarwfxai.

(1) Xen.
Socrates,

^'^'

if}

irphs

(ppovriffai rris

a7roAo7ias

rovs St/cao-r^s
rh dai/xoviop.

S)s

D.

(2) Plato Apol. 31,

Why

did not Socrates busy himself


The
with political matters ?
tout'
BaifxovLov was the reason
iffrtv
ixoi ivavTiovrai ra iroXi:

'6

riKo, irpdrreiv.

(3) Ibid, (after

a singular
his condemnation)
occurrence took place, rj yhp
du)9v7d jxoi ixavTiK^ rj rov Saifxoviou
:

iv fx\v
irdvv

T(^ Trp6(rdev

TTVKVT]

fffxiKpoTs

aet

"fjv

XP^^V

''^^vti

Koi irdvv

ivavTiov/jLevr),

et

4it\

ti fxeA-

Koijxi fx^ bpQois TTpd^eiv uvv) 5e,

ri

rjjj.aprrjKora

(is

rh

Beiov.

as
(7) Ihid. Euthyd. 272, E.
leave
to
about
Socrates was
the Lyceum, ijevero rh elwOh.
ort
ff-nixilov rh oaifiSviov, he theref
sat down again, and soon af te:
;

rjuavricadr]

Euthydemus and Dionysodoru


In all thesi
really came in.
cases the 5a,fjL6viov appears t^
have been an inward voice de
terring the philosopher from
Even th
particular action.
more general statement tha
the daiixSviov always made it
:

warnings heard whenever

Sc

HIS CHARACTER.

87

according to Plato assume the form of prohibitions.

Sometimes the

doing something.

him from saying

stops

hai^jLovLov

or

only indirectly points out


what should be done, by approving what it does not
It

forbid.

In a similar way

>Socrates

to

advise

him from approving


or by silence.-^
The

his

Socrates re-

viov only liave reference to particular future actions (not only


of Socrates, but of others), from
which it dissuades. Tlie two
latter authorities are, however,
worthless.
TL

other interests, unless peculiar

fxevou

circumstances kept them, such


as sickness, which was a hindrance to political life.
rh

y^v7)rai

^jnerepoi'

ovk

dai/j.uviov cnixilov

6.Ww

ovd^pl

7]

Socrates

[)hilosophical

posing

Tcov

^jx-KpoaQcv

The heavenly sign

76701/6.

kee])s

Xiy^iv rh
^ yap ttov rivi

true

calling,

to

his

by op-

him whenever he

con-

tem[)lates taking up anything


else, as for instance, politics.
(Jouseciuently, not even this
j)assa.ge

compels

anotlier

meaning

us to give
to its utter-

ances tlian they bear according


to riato's express words, as

conveying a judgment respecting the


admissibility of a
definite action, eitlier contem-

commenced by SoEven at tlie commence-

plated or
crates.

ment of

'

the

spurious 'Alcithat is discussed, and in tlie Theages. 128,


1)., the prophecies of the 5at/iJ-

aiades,' this is all

Apol. 31, D. '6ri /jlol


Kol ^aiixoviov ylyverai
:

deldp

....

ifiol

5e toGt' iarlv
(pcovi)

e/c

iraiShs ao|a-

tls yiyvofJiivT],

del

awoTpeirei

/xe

^ 'drav
tovtov

^ h.v /iieXha) TrpuTTeiv, irpoTpenei


Se otjirore.
Phfedr. 242, C.

6.^loi/

not hindering

schemes, either by word

marks that most of those who


had the capacity for philosophy
were diverted therefrom by

5'

by

enables

subjects respecting which the

crates thought of a political


with this concoi)tion of it.
In a similar
sense the passage in the Republic vi. 496, D. should be

when

friends

their

CJireer, falls in

understood,

indirectly

it

From

the Platonic state-

ments respecting the 8aiix6j/iou


which have just been given,
Xenophon's statements differ,

making it not only restraining


but preventing, and not onl}having reference to the actions
of Socrates but to those of other
people. Mem. i. 1, 4 (Apol. 12)
rh yap Sai/xSuiov (pr] arjixaiueiv,
Kai TToAAoiS Tcit' ^vvduTwu irpoffi]ydpevf rik fihp Troteti/, rd Se /x^
TTOLiiv, cos Tov Saijxov'iov TTpOCTTJfJ.aivovros Ka\ rols /xku ireLOofieuois

'

avT<S (Tvvecpepe,

rols Se

fx4vois lUereVfAe.
(To\

5'

e<^77

/177

ireido-

Ibid. iv. 3, 12

(Euth3-demus),

&

^wKpares, io'iKacni/ 6T (piXiKtarepov


^ To7s &\Aoi5 xpTjfl^at (scot deol)
etye /ATjSe iTrepwruifxevoi inrS aov
irpoariixaivovai

Kal &

may

ctqi

a re ^.ph TTOieTy

both statements
be harmonised as in the

fx-f].

Still

Chap
IV.

SOCRATES.

88

Chap
IV,

heavenly voice makes

and character very

itself

heard are in point of value


Besides a concern of

different.

such deep personal interest to Socrates as his judicial

condemnation, besides a question having such a farreaching influence on

his

whole activity as that

whether he should take part in public

life

or not,

expresses itself on occasions quite unimportant.^

it.

It

friends,^ that whilst regarded as

and hi^
a something enigma-

unknown

before, affording, too.

is

in fact a voice so familiar to Socrates

tical,

mysterious, and

a special proof of divine providence,

it

can neverthe-

be discussed without awe and mystery in easy


and even in flippant language. The facts of the
phenomenon resolve themselves into this, that not

less

unfrequently Socrates was kept back by a

dim feeling-

based on no conscious consideration, in which he


discerned a heavenly sign and a divine hint, from
carrying out some thought or intention.

Were he

had been vouchsafed to him,


from his point of view the reply would be, because
that from which it deterred him would be harmful to
asked

why

this sign

himself or others.^
text.

Evident^ Plato

is

In order, therefore, to justify


more

His language is far


more definite than that of
Xenophon, and is throughout

accurate.

consistent, witness the various


cases mentioned in the previous
note. Xenophon, as is his wont,
confined himself to what caught
the eye, to the fact that the
dai/jLoviop
enabled Socrates to
judge of actions whose consequences were uncertain, all the

more so because

he

aimed

before all things at proving


Socrates' divination to be the
same as other divinations, and
so defending his teacher from the
charge of religious innovation,
As to the special peculiarity of
the Socratic 8aifx6uiov and its
inner processes, we can look to
Plato for better information.
^
See p.
iraw iirl cixiKpots.
86, 2.
-

Trai^u irvKv-f].

It

will

be

Ibid.

subsequently

'

;
'

ins CHARACTER
the

utterances

raison

cVetre,

which

it

beneficial

therefore

of

tlie

61)

and to give

Sal/uLouLop,

its

he attempted to prove that tlie actions


approved or occasioned were the most

and advantageous.
to

him

as

The Salfioviov appeared


an internal revelation from
^

heaven respecting the result of his actions, in a word


as an internal oracle.
As such it is expressly
included, both by

Xenophon ^ and

Plato,^ under the

general conception of divination, and placed on a par


with divination by sacrifice and the flight of birds.

Of

it

is

therefore true what Xenophon's Socrates

remarks respecting

all

divination, that

be resorted to for cases which


himself by reflection.''

man

i.

vinced of the care of God for


to the
smallest
matters, and on the other

Euthyphro, 3, B.
Xon. Mom. i.

man down

hand was accustomed to estimate the value of every action


by its consequences.
It followed herefrom that to his
mind the only ground on which
(rod could forbid an action
was because of its ill-consequences.
See Xe>i. Mem. iv. 8, 5,
where Socrates observes that
the Saiix6i/iov forbad him to prepare a defence, and then proceeds to discuss the reasons
why the deity found an innocent death better for him than
a longer life. In Rlato, Apol.
40, 3, he concludes, from the
silence of the Sai/xdi/iou during
his defence, that tlie condemna"'

tion to which it led


for him a benelit.

would be

only

cannot discover

shown that Socrates was, on


the one hand thorouglily con-

may

it

Xen. Mem.

i. 1, 8
iv. 3, 12
Conf. Apol. 12.
Apol. 40, A. Phajd. 242, C.
;

4, 14.
^

'
6
tA ^ey
1
auayKaTa (ruj/t/BcuAei/e Kal Tvparreiv
us iv6ij.i(i,v dpiar' a.v npaxdrjuai

TTcpl oh Toov aSriAcDj/

onoos av airo-

fir^croLTO
el

/j-avTevaofxevovi iTreiinrey
iroinrda.
For this reason,

therefore,
qiTired:

divination was reyap f)


fxeu

TKroviKhi>

XaA/ceuTtK^f ^ yeoopyiKhu

audpuapx^Khu
rcou roiovTwv epyccv
i^eraaTLKhu ^ KoyicniKhv ?) oIkovofxiKbv
(TTpaTTjyiKhy yiviadai
^
iravra ra roiavra fxaQr)ixara koI
TTcau

avOpcvirov yvco/xr)
eJpai

rois

'/)

-/)

TO,

alperea

5e /uLeytara

ivdfxi^e

rwv eV tov-

Tovs 6(ovs eavrols Karawv ov^kv hriXov eJvai


ro7s audpwnois.
Tlie greatest
things, however, as is" imme(p7i

Aelireadai

diately explained, are the consequences of actions, the question whether they are useful

Chap.
IV.

SOCRATES.

)()

Chap.
^^'
(c)

Limi-

^?ilc^'
^^^"'

Herewith the whole field of philosophical inquiry


is excluded from the province of the Baifiovcov, This
field Socrates, more than any one of his predecessors,
claimed for intelligent knowledge and a thorough
understanding. As a matter of fact, no instance
occurs of a scientific principle or a general moral law
being referred to the

Nor must the sage's

SaL/xoviov.

own higher mission be confounded

conviction of his

with his belief in the heavenly sign, nor the deity by


whom he considered himself commissioned ta sift

The fact
be identified with the haLfxovLov?
that Socrates thought to hear the heavenly voice
from the time when he was a boy, ought to be

men

sufficient evidence to

warn against such an

error

^
;

time he cannot possibly have had any


thought of a philosophic calling. That voice, more-

for at that

over, according

to

Plato,

always deterring, never

prompting,^ cannot have been the source of the.


positive command of the deity to which Socrates

detrimental to the doer.


Accordingly Socrates observes
that it is madness to think to
be able to dispense with divination, and to do everything

or

by means

of one's
gence (and as he

adds,
Se

own

afterwards

aOeixiffTa irote^o)

rovs

SLaKpiveiv,

Saiixovau

to7s

e^coKuv ot Oeol ixadovai

examples of which

are then given. Conf.

where

iJ.avreuofxvovs,

avQpoiirois

intelli-

fxavriKr},

and

tlie

yiyvoivTo).

This was often done in


former times for instance by,
Meiners, Verm. Hchrift. iii. 24,'
*

and

still

113,

p.

more

who

whom

from

so by Lelut, 1. c.
sees in the Behs

Socrates

derived

his vocation a proof of his


The same
belief in a genius.

mistake

committed by

is

quardsen,

1.

c. p.

12,

whose view see AlheHi,

also

the

56.

ra air o firmer 6 fxeva), and


appropriate means (i) Uv

'^

^k

iraiUs.

87, 1.
^

See

p. 87, 2.

Vol-,

9, 12, againstj

iv. 3,

Socratic /xavriKr], is said to


refer to consequences {ra (Tvjx<p4povTa,

'apiffTo.

See

Socr^

above

'

HIS CHARACTER.

91

Nor is it ever
deduced therefrom, either by Xenophon or by Plato.
Socrates indeed says that the deity had given him the
task of sifting men, that the deity had forced him to
referred his activity as a teacher.^

this line of life

but he never says that he had

received this commission from the Sat/jLopcov.^


this

he

To

only indebted for peculiar assistance in his

is

philosophic calling, which consists


in its dissuading liim

calling by

more

from proving

meddling with

particular!}^

faithless to his

politics.'*

Lastly, the haiixoviov has been often regarded as

the voice of conscience,^ but this view

wide and too narrow.

in the

at once too

Understanding by conscience

the moral consciousness in general, and


larly the

is

moral sense as

far as

more particu-

this finds expression

moral estimate of our every action,

its

moni-

tions are not confined to future things as are

monitions of

the Socratic

more frequently makes

Bat/jLoviov.

the

Nay, more,
the

first

place by the approval or disapproval following

upon

it

itself

felt

in

8ee p. 60, 2 82, 1.


Plato, Apol. 2'A, V>.
28, D.
:j:5, C.
Theiet. 150, C.
^ It
is
not true, as Volqmrdseii, 1. c. E., says, that
in Plato, Apol. 'M, D., Socrates
mentions the dai/j-Sviou as the
first and exchisivc ai'Tio// of his
mode of life. He tliere only
attributes to the Sai^iduiov his

i. 243 is a modithe above). Breitenhach, Zeitschriit fiir das Gjinnasialwesen,


491)
1868,
p.
Rotschei; Arist. 256. Ribbing,
too, 1. c. 27, defends tliis view,
ol)ser\ing-, liowever, that the
Sai/xoviov
(1) only manifests
itself as conscientia antecedens
and concomitans, not as con-

abstinence from politics, not


his attention to pliilosophy.
Seep. 86, 2.
Stajffe?; Biogr. Univers. T.
xlii. Socrate, ]). 531
Rrandis,
Gesch. d. Griccli. Mum. Phil.
ii. a, 60 (Gescli. d. Entwick, d.

scientia subsequens
and (2)
that its meaning- is not exhausted with the conception of
conscience, but that it figures
as practical moral tact in resi)ect of personal relations and
particular actions.'

'

'^

'

Griecli. Phil.
iicat ion of

'

Chap.
J_

SOCRATES.

iJ2

Chap.

Again,

actions.

the

^J
>

conscience

exclusively

moral value or wortlilessness

refers

an

of

action,

whereas the heavenly sign in Socrates always bears


reference to the consequences of actions.
Plato, no less than

of prophecy.

Xenophon,

Therein

sees a peculiar

kind

Allowing that Socrates was occasion-

mistaken as to the character of the feelings and

ally

impulses which appeared to

to

him

revelations, that

now and then he was of opinion that the deity had


forbidden him something for the sake of its prejudicial consequences when the really forbidding power
was his moral sense, yet the same cannot be said of
all the

utterances of the

deterring

Sac/juovLov,

him from taking

up

Doubtless in
the real

politics,

motive lay in the feeling that a political career was


incompatible with his conviction

of an important

higher calling, to which he had devoted his

life.

It

may, therefore, be said that in this case a scruple of


conscience had assumed the form of a heavenly voice.

But in forbidding

to prepare a speech for judicial

defence, this explanation will no longer apply.

only explanation which can be given of the

the

heavenly voice,

own

is

personal interests did not

him

and that

commend
it

itself to the

appeared unworthy

to defend himself otherwise than

by a plain

statement of the truth requiring no preparation.^,


^

two

Volquardsen

1.

c.

'

that such a taking in hand of his

sage's line of thought,

of

Here

confounds

tilings in explaining

the

prohibition, mentioned by Xen.


Mem. iv. 8, 4, to prepare a
defence in the sense of Plato,

Apol. 17, A., as meaning that it


was not a question of a simple
defence, but of a defence in
the usual legal style with all

the tricks and manoeuvres of

ins CHARACTER.

w.-;.

All this, however, has little to do with

judgments

Cha7>

morally admissible or not, and


to do with the questions as to what is

J^

respecting what

has

much

is

suited or unsuited to the individual cliaracter of the


philosopher.
Still less can the decision respecting

the receiving back pupils

who have once deserted


him, be referred to conscience. The question here
really was as to the capacity of the respective persons
by his instructions.

to profit

'

criticism

It involved, therefore,

of character.

The

jokes,

too,

which

Socrates and his friends permitted themselves as tothe Satfioi'tov^ were wholly out of place, if the
Baifiomov were conscience.

on

fact,

far as

they are founded

they afford a proof that the

be distinguished from

and

As

Bac/juovLov

must

moral sense or conscience

harmony herewith to hear Socrates


say,3 that the heavenly voice often made itself
heard
on quite unimportant occasions.
Eemembering further that Socrates was more than anyone else,
perhaps^
it is

quite in

bent on referring actions to clear conceptions, and


accordingly excluded from the field of prophecy, and
therefore from the province of the Bafjuoviov, everyixw 01-atoi-.

count there
tliis.

mg-,

In Xenophon's acis not a word of

Had
It

this been his meanmust someliow have

been indicated in tlie sequel


would have been said tliat
the Saj/ic^i/joj/ kept liim from deendino- himself, l)ecause a detence in keopino- with his principles would have l>een useless
it is by no means a matter
of
course that he would not have
been able to get up a speech
;

It

very

much worthy

But

as

of himself
Eos. i. 175
observes: what idea must we
form to ourselves of Socrates
if he recjuired tlie assistance
of
the haiixouiov to keep him back
from that which he clearlv
saw to be incompatible witli
his principles ?
See above p. 86, 2, No. 4.
~'
2 Ihid. No.
5, 7.
' Th'uJ.
No. 'd.
>

Cron in

SOCRATES.

<)4

Chap.

^ ^Zl

thing that might be known by personal reflection,'


we shall see how little right we have to understand
the Saifjbovtov as having principally or wholly to do

(d)

with the moral value of an action.


PMlnThe heavenly voice appears rather to be the

general form, which a vivid, but in its origin unexfionofflH'


piored sense of the propriety of a particular action

1^:!-^na-

daifiouiou.

assumed

The

for

the personal consciousness of Socrates.'^

actions to which this sense referred could, as

we

have seen, be most varied in content and importance.


Quite as varied must the inward processes and
motives

have

been out

of

which

it

grew.

It

might be some conscientious scruple pressing on the


sense of the sage without his being fully conscious
It might be some apprehension of the
thereof.

consequences of a step, such as sometimes rises as a


first impression with all decidedness in the experi-

enced observer of

men and of circumstances, before it

even possible for him to account to himself for the


reasons of his misgiving. It might be that an action

is

in itself neither immoral nor inappropriate, jarred


on Socrates' feelings, as not being in harmony with
his peculiar

mode

of being

and conduct.

It mighty

be that on unimportant occasions all those unaccount-,


able influences and impulses came into play, which
contribute so much to our mental attitude and de^
\
1

The

last

remark follows

not only from what has been


stated, p. 89, 4,

which he had discovcredi


Nor does it conflict herewith,

of

<^gg p^ 39^ 4.

but

it is

also

Socrates
inconceivable that
higher
to
a
referred
have
could
inspiration impulses the sources

that after the heavenly voice^


has made itself heard, heafter-[
wards considers what can hav
led the Gods to thus reveal
their will.

HIS CHARACTER.
cisions

the

all

more

'.)r>

so in proportion as the object

itself affords less definite

grounds

this respect the Bac/jbdvwv has

In

for decision.

been rightly called

the
understanding by tact
a general sense of propriety in word and action as
inner voice of individual

tact,'

'

'

exemplified in the most varied relations of life in


small things as well as in great. ^ This sense Socrates early noticed in

himself as unusually strong,^

and subsequently by his peculiarly keen and unwearied


observation of himself and other men he developed
it

to such a pitch of accuracy, that

or as he believed
cal origin

was,

consciousness.

never at fault.

was seldom

it

Its psychologi-

however, concealed from his own


It

assumed

for

him from the

beo-in-

ning the appearance of a foreign influence, a higher


revelation,

an

Herein

is

oracle.'*

seen the strength of the hold which

the beliefs of his

Hermann,

countrymen had over Socrates

Platonismus

i.

236
similarly Krische, Forschung. i. 281.
2 The objections hereto raised
by Volquardsen, pp. 5(5, 63, and
Alberti, Socr. 68, are partly
answered by the argument
which has preceded. Besides,
tliey have more reference to
words than to things. So far
as this is the case, there is no
use in disputing.
By tact we
imderstand not only social but
moral tact, not only acquired
but natural tact, and this word
seems very appropriate to express the sense which Socrates
described as the haifxdviov.
Sec p. 88, 3.
* Hegel, Gesch. d. Phil.
ii. 77
:

^
;

The pcnius

of Socrates is not
Socrates himself.
but an
.

oracle, wliich, however, is not


external, but subjective, his
o]-acle.
It l)ore the form of

knowledg-e, which was,

how-

ever, connected witli a certain

unconsciousness.
Kriitche 1. c.
Wliat is not
our power, what our nature
cannot bear, and wliat is not
naturally found in our impulses <')r our reflections, is
involuntary, or according to
the notion of the ancients,
heavenly to this category belong enthusiasm and prophecy,
the violent throb of desire, the
^

in

miulity force of feelings.

chai'.
^^'

SO CBATES.

f)(;

Chap,

herewith, too, are exposed to view the limits of his


Feelings whose origin he has not
self-knowledge.
discovered are seen to exercise over him an irresistible
On the other hand, the hainovLov when it does
power.
speak, takes the place of the usual signs and portents. Hegel ^ not without reason sees herein a proof

that the determining motives of action, which in the


case of the Greek oracles were things purely exter-

have come to be sought in man himself. To


misgivings incapable of being resolved into clear

nal,

conceptions, a high importance was here attached


in

them a very

most

revelation of deity was seen, proving

clearly that the

human mind,

foreign to Grreeks, had

in a

way hitherto

to occupy itself with

come

and carefully to observe what transpired within.


The power which these feelings early exercised over
Socrates, the devotion Avith which he even then

itself,

listened for the voice within, affords an insight into


the depths of his emotional natiure. In the boy we,

embryo of the man, for whom self-knowledge,


was the most pressing business of life, for whom untiring observation of his moral and mental conas
ditions, analysis of notions and actions, reasoning
see the

were
to their character and testing of their value

primary

necessities.

The same tone

of

mind

also shows itself in othei

peculiarities of Socrates, to his contemporaries appearthought,


so strange. At times he was seen lost in

ing

so as to be unconscious of
Hegel 1. c. and Eecht's
PMlosophie, 279, p. 369.

what transpired aroimc


^

Conf. Plato, Apol.

See above,

p. 60, 3.

38,

lUH CHARACTER.
him;

at times going

habits of his fellows

on

his

liis

97

way regardless of the

whole appearance displaying

a far-reaching indifference to
external things, a onesided preference of the useftd
to the

beautiful. What
these traits show if not the
importance which
he attached to the study of
self, to the

do

all

solitary

work

of thought, to a free
determination of self independent of foreign judgments
?

Remarkable

as it

may

^.om to find the dryness of the


man of intellect and
the enthusiasm of the
man of feeling imited in one
and the same person, both
features may be referred
to

common

source.

What

distinguishes Socrates
general conduct from his
fellow-citizens was
-his power of inward
concentration.
Tliis struck his
iotemporaries as being so foreign
an element, and
-hereby an irreparable
breach was made in the artistic
inity of Greek life.
>n his

What the general importance of


this peculiarity
nay be, and what traces
it has left
in history, are

uestions to answer which


'Ocratic philosophy.

we must enquire

into the

ch^
(""HAP.
"'

SOCRATES.

98

CHAPTER

V.

OF THE PHILOSOPHY,
THE SOURCES AND CHAEAC rERISTICS
OF SOCRATES.
Chap.
V.
A. Xenoj)J(on

and

Plato.

the philosopliy of
give an accurate account of
owing to the wellSocrates is a work of some difficulty,
Socrates
known divergence of the earliest accounts.
works
to writing himself; ' of the

To

committed nothing
of his pupils, in which he

is

introduced as

speakmg

and Plato are preserved.*


only those of Xenophon
alike, that we gather
These are, however, so little
view of the teaching
from the one quite a different
Amon^
other gives us.
of Socrates to what the
philosophy it was the fashion t,
early historians of
Athenian sage, withoi^
construct a picture of the
indiscriminately from th
principles and criticism,
Plato, no less than froi.
writings of Xenophon and

The unimportant poetical

attempts of his last days {Plato,


be
Phsedo, 60, C.) can hardly
counted as writinsjs, even if they
They appear,
were extant.
however, to have been very soon
The Psean at least,
lost.
which Themist. (Or. ii. 27, c.)
considers genuine, was rejected

by the ancient

critics,

ing to Diog.
spuriousness of

ii.

accord-

^^2.

The

the Socratic
and
letters is beyond question,
that Socrates committed no-

thing to writing is clear froi


the silence of Xenophon, Plat
and all antiquity, not to mei
tion the positive testimony
Dio.
Cic. de Orat. iii. 16, 60

16; Plut. De Alex. Virt.


A conclusive discussion i
4.
t
this point in refutation of
givj
is
Allatius
Leo
views of
by Olearius in Stanl. Hil

i.

Phil. 198.
2 For instance, those ot m,

'

chines, Antisthenes, Phaedo.

AUTIIORITim FOR HIS PHILOSOPHY.


later,

ami

for the

most part indifferent,


authorities.

Since the time of Brucker,


however, Xenophon came
'
to be regarded as the only
authority to be perfectly
for the philosophy of
Socrates; to all others,
Plato included, at most only
a supplementary value
was allowed. Quite recently,
however, Schleiermaicher has lodged a
protest against this
preference of
Xenophon J Xenophon, he argues,
not being a phi-

Wed

losopher

himself,

was scarcely capable


of understanding a philosopher
like Socrates.
The object
moreover, of the Memorabilia
was a limited one, to
lefend his teacher from
definite charges.
are
-herefore justified
vas

more

We

in

assuming a priori that


there

in

Socrates than Xenophon


describes,
ndeed there must have been
more, or he could not
.ave played the part
he did in the history of
philoophy nor have exerted
so marvellous a
power of
ttraction on the most
intellectual

and cultivated
character, too, which
Plato
ives him would otherwise
have too flatly contradicted
^>e picture of him
present to the mind of
his reader,
len of his time.

The

.esides

Xenophon's dialogues create


the impression
philosophic matter has,
with detriment to its
meaning, been put into
the unphilosophic
langua<.e
every day life; and
that there are gaps
left, to
TOly which we are obliged to go to
Plato Not tLat
e can go so far
as Meiners,'^ and say
that only those
lat

.Socrates,

Schlmcnmirl,,;;

If

*^'-''=''\,

'2

81

^-

""'

,j.j

Chap,
V.

SOCRATES.

100

Chap.

__^

parts of the dialog'ues of Plato can be considered historical, which are either to be found in Xenophon, or

immediately follow from what Xenophon says, or which


This hypothesis
are opposed to Plato's own views.

would only give us the Socrates of Xenophon slightly


modified, whilst the deeper spring of Socratic thought

would

safe course to

that adopted by Schleiermacher to ask,


may Socrates have been, in addition to what

pursue

What

The only

be wanting.

still

is

Xenophon reports, without gainsaying the character


assigns to
and maxims which Xenophon distinctly
him? and what must he have been to call for and
is given of him in the
to justify such a description as
Schleiermacher's estimate of

dialogues of Plato?

Xenophon has been


^

since adopted

by several other

even previously to Schleiermacher^


in the
Dissen ^ had declared that he could only see
outward
pages of Xenophon a description of the
appearance of Socrates. The like approval has been
writers

and

bestowed on Schleiermacher's canon


J

5m?i<^i.5,inIlhein.Mus. von

mehnhr und Brandh,

i.

b. 122.

Conf Gesch. d. Gr.-Rom. Philos.


'20
BiUer, Gesch. d. Phil,
ii a
44" RihUng, Ueber d. Verii*
h-iltniLs zwischen den Xenonhont. und den Platon. Berichten iiber Socrates. Upsala

1870,
TJniversitets Arskrift,
AlUHi,
specially p. 1, 125.
too (Socrates, 5), takes in the
main the side of Schleiermacher, whilst allowing that
Plato's account can only be
used for history with extreme
caution a caution which he

for finding out

has himself failed to observe


in using the Ph^edo (see above,
p. 59). In respect of the personality of Socrates rather than h\>
teaching, Van Heusde (Characterismi principum philosophornm veterum, p. 54) gives a
preference to Plato s pictuK
as being truer to life thar

Xenophon's Apology,
*

De

philosophia

morah

ir

Xenophontis de Socrate com


mentariis
m9.se/i'5

87).

tradita,

Klemeren

p.

28

(n

bchrif ten, p

AUTIIOIUTIES FOR Iim I'UILOSOFIIY.


lie

real Socrates

jyj

only to supplement it
has the
remark been made,' that the
language used by
;

Aristotle respecting the


teaching of Socrates may be
also employed to determine
its outside aspect.
On
the other hand, Xenophon's

authority has

warmly supported by several


critics.^
In deciding between these
two views, a
aowever, presents

itself.

been

difficulty

The authority of the one

or
other of our accounts can only
be ascertained by
I reference to
the true historical picture
of Socrates
ind tlie true historical
picture can
-he

rom these

only be known

conflicting

accounts.
This difficulty
rould be insra-mountable,
if the two narratives
had
he same claim to be
considered historical in
points
'Inch they state varyingly.
Indeed, Aristotle's
=anty notices respecting
the Socratio

ould have been insufficient


to
ren on the assumption
that he
itormation

at

command

philosophy
settle the question,

had other sources of

beside

the

enophon and Plato- -an assumption

writinc^s

of

for which^'there

not the least evidence.


But if one thing is clearer
lan another, it is
this,-that Plato only claims
to be
ue to facts
those descriptions in which
he agrees
th Xenophon, as for
instance, in the Apology and
e Symposium.
On other jwints no one could well
<ert that he wished
all to be

taken as historical

By Braudis.
iu,jci.

la di

1.

99

c.

Gesch. d. Phil.

ii.

8ocrate (Napoli, 1871)

n^. r

^i, i^Tss

rr

'^'orfn,?r''i.''-

^^oorng,

l.

c.

ChuV-

'

;;

SOCRATES.

102

Chap.

__J'

he puts into the mouth of Socrates. Of Xeno-phon, on the contrary, it may be granted that,
wliicli

whether from his deficiency in philosophic sense, or


from his exclusively practical tastes, not unfrequently
the scientific meaning and the inner connection of
the principles of Socrates escape his notice. Nor

must we ever forget that the Memorabilia

are prima-

intended to be a defence of his teacher against


the charges brought against him, which charges were
the cause of his condemnation, and passed current

rily

years after his death.

For

this

purpose a description

was requisite, not so much of his philosophy as of


his morals and religion, setting forth his piety, his^
integrity, his obedience to the laws, his services to

and fellow-citizens rather than his inteland Xenophon candidly conlectual convictions

his friends

the main object of his

fesses that this is

treatise.'^

Even the question, whether, with the means at


command, a life-like reproduction of the dialogues

of

Socrates can be expected from Xenophon, cannot hi

answered affirmatively without some limitation.

Hii

was not written until six years after the


death of Socrates, and we have not the least indica
tion that it was based on notes made either by him
self or others in the time immediately following th(

treatise

What was committed

dialogues.^
'

.3,

1
2

Mem.
:

it

i.

1, 1

and 20;

2, 1

8, 11.

25 5, 1
cannot be inferred from

iv. 4,

173, B.
C.
Thejet. 143, A., that Socrates'
friends (as Volquardsen, Daemon
a. Sokr. 6, says) took down his

PUto, Symp. 172,

to writing year

discourses at home and fill&


up their sketches by furthe
enquiries. Nay, the very dif
courses which are vouched fc
by this supposed care, cannc
Sue
possibly be historical.

statements

cannot

therefoi

AUTHORITIES FOR HIS PHILOSOPHY.


afterwards from his

own

103

memory has
not the claim to accuracy of a verbal report, but
rather owes to himself its more definite form and

No

doubt

or his friends'

was his intention to give a true


account of Socrates and his teaching. He says that
he writes from his own recollection. He expressly
setting.

it

observes in a few cases that he was present during


the dialogue, but had heard similar things from
others,

mentioning his authority.^

Socratic discourse is
his

memory,

if

unknown

to

If,

him

many

then,

or has escaped

one or other line of thought has not

been

thoroughly understood, or
importance misunderstood by him,

philosophical

its

it may neverthebe assumed that a pupil of Socrates, accustomed


to consort with him for years, and able to communicate all that Xenophon actually communicates,

less

neither repeats on the whole

what is false, nor leaves


any essential side of the Socratic teaching untouched.

From

Plato, indeed, so far as his description

his-

is

permits a reference to the Socrates of history,


many a trait supplementary of Xenophon's narra-

torical or

tive

may

be expected, and

the real

meaning of

reports

as

which his fellow-pupil


understood only from the standpoint of

more than similar ones


n Parm. 126, B. Neither does
Mem. i. 4, I refer to writings
pupils of Socrates, but to
he views of opponents. Mem.
V. 8, 2 appears to refer not
iven to writings, but to oral

)f

''Ommunications.
^

i.

iSSKei

3,

fxoi

is Se 8^ kuI
rovs

....

|ui/(J>/Tas

roiTotv

Siafxvr]fiouv(r(v.

5}}

ypd^pu 6ir6cra hv

iv.

8,

2; others

have reported similar conversations respecting- the Gods, at


wliich they were present iyi,
:

5e

Ue

-nphs

rotdSe
iv 8 4

Evdiid-n/jLov

8i\4yTo irapeyfudix-nu
5^ kuI & 'Epixoy^pov^ rod 'Inttovikov iJKovaa nepl avTov.

Ae'lco

Mem.

explanation of

sayings,

oiean

i>^AcTj/

many an

Cha

SOCRATES.

104

Chap.

Henceobjectioncanhardly be taken
Neto the above-quoted canon of Schleiermacher.^
vertheless, it is highly improbable that in essential

practical utility.

points there should be an irreconcilable difference

between Xenophon's description and that which we

may

take for historically established as Plato's.^ The

real state of the case, however, can only be ascer-

tained

by examining

authorities

of various

statements

the

in detail to test their worth

and their

agreement, and this enquiry naturally coincides with


the exposition of the Socratic teaching, from which it
could only be distinguished in point of form.
not, therefore, be separated from

it

here.

It will
Socrates.

be described from the three accounts of Xenophon, Plato, and Aristotle. If the attempt to form

will

a harmonious picture from these sources succeeds,

Xenophon
it will

will be vindicated.

Should

it

not succeed,

then be necessary to ask, which of the tradi-

tional accounts is the true one.^

To begin with the

B. Phllo-

^^Utform

Supposed
^pMlo^^'
sophy.

question as to the philosophi-

and fundamental principle of Socrates.


Here the sketches of our main authorities seem to
According
giv6 ground for the most opposite views.

^^^ platform

P. 100.

As RihUng,

1.

c.

asserts,

Hard is it to reconcile herewith


that Kibbing declines to question the essentially historical
accuracy of Xenophon's de'

'

scription.

The course here followed


is also in the main that taken
by Striimpell, Gesch. d. Prakt.
^

He conPhilos. d. Gr. i. 116.


siders it impossible to distin-

guish in point of speculation


what belongs to Socrates and
A>
what belongs to Plato.
regards morals, he hopes to
gain a true general view ol
Socrates by taking the maxims

which are attributed to hirii


unanimously
by Xenophon.
Plato, and Aristotle, following

them out to their

consequences,

and testing the traditions by


these.

(JHARACTEUmTKjlS OF HIS VIIILOSOIUIY.

iU5

to Plato, Socrates appears as


an expert thinker, at
home in all branches of knowledge;
whereas, in

Xenophon he

is

represented far

less as

a philosopher

man innocent and excellent, fnll of piety


and common sense. Hence Xenophon's
account is
than as a

specially appealed to in support


of the conception of
Socrates as a popular moral man,
holding aloof from
all speculative questions,
and in fact as far less of

philosopher than a teacher of morality


and instructor
of youthJ
It certainly cannot be
denied that
Socrates was full of the most lively
enthusiasm for
morality, and made it the business
of his life to
exercise a moral influence upon
others.^
Had he
only discliarged this function
after the unscientific
manner of a popular teacher, by
imparting and
inculcating the received notions
of duty and virtue,
the influence would be inexplicable
which he exerted,
not only over weaklings and
hairbrains, but over the
most talented and cultivated of his
cotemporaries. It
would be a mystery what induced Plato
to

connect

the deepest pliilosophical enquiries with


his person, or

what led all later philosopliers, down to


Aristotle,
nay even down to the Stoics and
Neoplatonists, to

'How common

this view
times, needs not to
be proved by authorities which
abound from Cicero down to

wasMn past

Wipers and Keinhold


It

IS

not

yet

That

altooether ex-

plodedmaybeg^therednotonly
from writers hke Tr^;.y/.,,.rf,,
Charact^erismi p. o3, but even
disciple
of the
Hegelian philosophy, asserts in
bis Gesch. d. Philos. i. 1
74, 1 78,

Marhmh, a

181, that Socrates 're-arded the


speculative philosophy which
aimed at general knowledge
'
as useless, vain, and loo^Sli
and that he took the heM not
only a-ainst the Sophists as
prefenders to knowffi: but
against all philosophy ;' hi
short, that
he was no philo"
'

sopher

'

Conf. Ai.ol. 215, D


30
38, A., and Ibove, p 4t).
"^

'

'

chaf.

'

^-

SOCRATES.

10(;

Chap,

regard

him

trace their
set

own

peculiar

on foot by him.

Even
feature
it

new epoch, and to


systems to the movement

as the founder of a

is

in himself

and

his doings

more than one


Whereasr

at variance with this conception.

would follow herefrom that knowledge

value in as far as

it is

is

only of

instrumental for action, so far

was Socrates from sharing this belief that he considered actions only then to have a value when they
proceed from correct knowledge; that he referred
moral action or virtue to knowledge, making its perfection depend on perfection of knowledge. Whereas,
according to the ordinary assumption, he would in
his

intercourse with others have before ali things

aimed at moral training, so far was it otherwise that


it appears from his own words that love of knowledge
was the original motive

we observe him

for his activity.^

Accordingly

in his dialogues pursuing enquiries,

which not only have no moral purpose,^ but which,


'
Plato, Apol. 21, where Socrates deduces his whole activity from the fact that he pursued a real knowledge.
Examples are to be found
in the conversations (Mem. iii.
10), in which Socrates conducts
the painter Parrhasius, the
sculptor Clito, and Pistias, the
forger of armour, to the conceptions of their respective
arts.
It is true Xenophon introduces these conversations
with the remark that Socrates
knew how to make himself
But the
useful to artisans.
desire to make himself useful

can only have

been

very

subordinate one; he was no


doubt really actuated by the
motive mentioned in the Apology, a praiseworthy curiosity
to learn from intercourse with
all classes, whether they were
clearlj- conscious of what their
Xenophon himarts were for.
self attests this,

Mem.

iv.

6^,

aKoirwi/ ovv ro'is avvoixri, ri %Ka-

crov

etrj

rcDr/

ovrtav

ovSeirttyiror

This pursuit of the


conceptions of things, aiming
not at the application of knowledge, but at knowledge itself,
is qviite enough to prove that
Socrates was not only a preacher
ekrtyev.

of

virtue,

but a philosopher.

CHARACTERISTICS OF HIS PHILOSOPHY.


in their practical application,

moral purposes.^

These

107

could only serve im-

traits are

not met with ex-

clusively in one or other of our authorities, but they

are equally diffused through the accounts given

the three main sources.

by

Socrates can therefore not

possibly have been the unscientific moral teacher for

which he was formerly taken. Knowledge must have


had for him a very different value and importance from
what it would have had on such a supposition. It may
not even be assumed that the knowledge which he
sought was ultimately only pursued for the sake of

and only valued as a means to morality.^ He


who pursues knowledge in this sense, only as a means
to an end whicli lies beyond him, not from an indeaction,

pendent impulse and love of knowing, will never


study so carefully and so independently the problem

and method of philosophic research


will

as Socrates did

never be a reformer of philosophy as he was.

Even Xenophon found


difficidty in

some

bringing it into har-

monj^ with his practical view


of things, as his words show

from which
JSocrates
critical.

it

made

may be

seen that

his friends

But criticism

more

is

the

organ of knowledge.

Mem. iii. 1 1 contains a


paragraph adapted more than
any otlicr to refute the idea
that Socrates was only a popular teacher.
Socrates hears one
'

of his companions commending


the beauty of Theodota, and at
once goes with his company to
see her.
He tinds her acting
as a painter's model, and he
tliercupon enters into a convcr-

sation with her, in which he


endeavours to lead her to a
conception of her trade, and
shows her how she will best be

able to

win

lovers.

Now,

al-

though such a step would not


give that offence to a Greek
which it would to us, still
tliere is not the least trace of a
moral purpose in his conduct,
Prandis' (Gesch. d. Entw. i.
286) remarks are little to the
point.
A purely critical interest leads Socrates to refer to
its general
conception ever^'
action across which he comes,
regardless of its moral value,
"PihhhKj, Socrat. Stud. i. 4G.

Chap.
^'

^0^

SOCRATES.

Nay more,

Chap.

would have been incapable of exertingdeep reforming influence over Ethics which,
according to the testimony of history, he did exert,
lie

tJie

had he thus confined himself to practical interests.


His importance for Ethics is derived not so much
from the fact that he insisted on a re-establishment
of moral

life

many

others

scientific

this Aristophanes

did, but from

basis for

'

and without doubt

his recognising that a

moral convictions must

be an

indispensable condition for any real reform of morals.

Herewith

it

presupposed that practical problems

is

are determined and vindicated by knowledge

in other

words, that knowledge not merely subserves action,

but leads and governs it a view never as yet held


by any one who did not attribute to knowledge an
independent value of
as

we

shall note,

its

own.

If,

therefore, Socrates,

confined himself in principle to

enquiries having for

man

a practical value,

it

can

only be inferred that he was not himself fully conscious of the range of his thought.

went beyond these


in such a

manner

In practice he

limits, treating ethical questions

as

no one could do unless

fired

with an independent love of knowledge.

The

area

is

thus determined within which the fun-

damental conception of the Socratic philosophy must


be looked for. True knowledge is the treasure to
discover which Socrates goes forth in the service of

the Delphic G-od;

to gain the

knowledge of the

essence of things, he, with his friends, unweariedly


labom's

to true

moral demands.

knowledge he ultimately

The

force with

refers all

which he asserted

CHARACTERISTICS OF
demand

this

constitutes

IILS RIIILOSOPIIY.

him

t]ie

creator in Greece

of an independent system of
morality.
is not enough that men
should do

what

must

know why they do

also

it.

lOO

For him
is

it

right; they ^

He demands

Chap.
V.

^'m.

^S^'
'^^

that
they should not follow a dark
impulse, an undefined
enthusiasm or the aptitude of
habit, but should act
ff.::""^"
trom clear consciousness ; and
because it was deficient
this characteristiche refuses
to allow true wisdom
to
the art of his time, however
high it otherwise stood ^
In a word, the idea of knowledge
forms the central "^
point of the Socratic philosophy.^
All philosophy aiming at knowledge, this point
must be further circumscribed to give it precision,
which was done in this wise
that, whereas the pursuit
of true knowledge had
been'

'
In Plato, Apol. 22,
B.,
Socrates observes In his sift-

with

in.? of

men

had turned

lie

to

the poets, but had soon


found
that they were usually not
able
to account for their
own works
"Eyvccv
iroioiev

oZu

&

TTotoIej/,

Uri

^\\^

oh

aocpia

(p{,a-u

rivl

Kal iveovaidCoPTcs, Sxrirfp


ol Oeofidvreis Kal xpWIJ-V^oikoX yap
avrol \4yov(ri yuev TroAAa
Kal Ka\a,
To-oo-i 5e ovHv &v
\4yovaiv.

Beno one knows the limits


of his knowledge, but
thinks
to understand all th ino-s.
He
had also observed the
same
sides,

in

the x^ipoT^xvai, the


presentatives of sculpture

re-

and

art.

SchleiervMcher, Werke, iii.


300:
The awakenino- of the

*
'iy

<

idea of knowledge,
and its
J^t utterances, must have been
the substance of the
philosojihy
Socrates.'
RiUer ao-rees

11-

Gesch. d. Philosophies
only differs
unessential points, Rhein.

iUus.
1.

this,

.->0.

<;,

Brandis

von Nxehvlivund BrandU


Gr.-Bom. Phil, ii '^

i:50;

To him the origin of


'J'l
the
doctnne of Socrates appears
to

be a desire to vindicate
against
the Sophists the absolute

worth
moral determinations;
and
then he adds to secure
this
purpose the first aim of
Socrates was to gain
a deeper
ot

insight into his own


consciousness,
order to be able to distinguish false and true
knowledge with certainty.
Similarlv
Bnunss, Gesch. d. Phils.
Kant

155.
The important feature
in Nocrates was
this, that to
iiim morality
appeared to be
a certain kind of
knowledge
1.

proceeding from the


thoulht
ot the good inborn
in the soul

SOCRATES.

110

Chap.
^-

with earlier philosophers an immediate and instinc-

became conscious and


methodical. By him the idea of knowledge as knowledge was first brought out, and having been brought
tive activity, with Socrates it

out, took precedence of every other idea.^


This statement, again, requires further explanation.

knowledge was shared also by previous


philosophers, why, it may be asked, did it not before
develope into a conscious and critical pursuit ? The
reason which may be assigned is this The knowledge
If the love of

which

philosophers

earlier

pursued, was, in

itself,

from the knowledge which Socrates required.


They were not compelled by their idea of knowledge
as Socrates was to direct their attention to the intellectual processes and conditions, by which it was
different

Such a necessity was, however,


imposed on Socrates by the principle which the most
trustworthy accounts unanimously report as the soul of
must proall his teaching that all true knowledge

truly to be acquired.

ceed from correct conceptions, and that nothing can


be known, unless it can be referred to its general

In this principle,

conception, and judged thereby.^

Schlelermacher.

c.

1.

299

Xen'oph.

Mem.

yap rohs

:Sa}KpdTvs

iv.

rols

6,

fihv il^^Tui,

eKaffTov eU-roov ovTcop,


Ce Koi

as

explained by the conreferred all doubtful

is

text, lie

Bmndis.
2

i.e.,

&K^OLS Uv

ri

v6tii-

l^r}y^7(reai

Uvaadai Tovs d ix^ elUras ovdhv


^7} eav^iaarhv elvai aurovs re

'

(TcpdWeaeai Ka\ &\\ovs 0(pd\\iv


S}V V^Ka (XKOTtS^V aVV TOIS (TVUOVCTl
rl e/cao-TOj/ e^Tj ruv ovtuv, ovSeeVl tV
13
xciTTOT' :^\T,7e.
^,iT69nv iTrdvriy^ TrduTarhi^\6yo^,
.

points to universal conceptions,


in order to settle them by
means of these; iv. 5, 12:
Kal rb SiaXeyeadai ovo-^
ec^T? 5e
/uLaadrivaL ea toG (TvvidvTas Koiv^
dLa\4yQVTas ^ Kara
^ovKeveaOai,

y4vr\ra
paaOai
kavrov

Comp.

SeTv oiv ttci-

-npixyiiara.

fldKKTTa

'6rL

froiixou
i.

instances

1,

Vphs

TOVTO

Trapatr/ceyaCeJP.

U, and

tlie

many

tne Memorabilia.

'

CHARACTERISTICS OF HIS PHILOSOPHY.


simple as

111

may

appear, an entire change was dein the intellectual procedure.' The ordinary
it

manded
way is to take things

as being

what they appear to


or
if
contradictory experiences for;
bid doing so, to cling to those appearances which make
the senses to be

the strongest impression on the observer, declaring


these to be the essence, and thence proceeding
to
further conclusions.

Hitherto this was exactly what

philosophers had done.

Even those who attacked the

senses as imtrustworthy

had invariably started from


one-sided observations, without being conscious
of
the necessity of grounding every judgment on
an
Ariatotle (Met. xiii. 4, 1078, b,
2tt/cpaTous 5e irepi ras
17, 27)
7]6iKa^ apeTas irpay^aT^vofxivov Kal
:

irepl

TovTcou

^riTOvvTos

dpi^eaOai Ka66\ou
irpwTOv .... e/ce?foy

fvXoryoJS

e^i^ret

iio yap

4<rTiv

rh ri iariv
a ris hv airoSoirj
.

"SuKpaTei SiKaicos, rovs t' eiraKriKovs \uyovs


Koi
rh opl^eaOai
KaB6Kov.
Both are, liowever, at

bottom the same.


iircMTiKol

The Koyoi
are only the means

for finding

universal concep-

and therefore Aristotle

tions,

elsewhere (Met.

i.

G, 1)87, b, 1

1080, b, 3; De Part.
Anim., i. 1, 642, a, 28) justly
observes that tlie seeking- for
universal conceptions or for the
essence of things is the real
service rendered to ])hilosophy
by Socrates.
Accordingly, in
xiii.

9,

the dialogues which Xenophon


^as i)reserved, we always see

lim making straight for

the

general conception, tlie tI ea-nv.


Even in Plato's Ajiology, 22, B.,
18 describes his sifting of men
IS litpur^v ri Xfyuiff, that is
to

he asks for the conceptioii


deeds of the practical
man, or of the poetry of the
say,

of

t]e

poet.

Conf.

Meno, 70, A.
262, B.
It
265, D.
can, liowever, hardly be proved

Phffidr.

from Plato that Socrates

reallx

distinguished
iTna-r'fi/x-n
from
S6^a,
as
Brandis (Gr.-Rom.
Phil. ii. a, ;J6
Gesch. d. Entw.
i. 235) would have it
for we
cannot decide whetlier passages
like Meno, 98, B. represent the
view of Socrates or that of
Plato.
Antisthenes, too, wh.o.
according to IJiof/eftcs, vi, ]7,
wrote a treatise nepl So^rjs kuI
;

may owe

this disEleatics.
It
can hardly be found in Xen.
Mem. iv. 2, 33. In point of
iiriiTT'fiij.rjs,

tinction

to

the

substance, no d()ul)t tlje distinction was im])lied in the


whole conduct of Socrates, and
in passages sucli as Xen. Mem.
iv. 6, 1 ; P/ato, Apol. 21, B.
'
Conf. wJiat has been said

above,
Pliil.

i.

p. 39,

860.

and

in Gesch. d.

C'HAi'

V.

SOCRATES.

112

exhaustive enquiry into

Chap.

^\

its

By means of

subject.

dogmatism had been overthrown. Ifc


was felt that all impressions derived from the senses
were relative and personal, that they do not represent
sophistry this

things as they are, but as they appear and, that,


consequently, whatever we may assert, the opposite
;

may be

asserted with equal justice.

moment this is true,


moment that is true.

person at this
at another

Similar

sentiments

relative to the value of

are

For, if for one

for another

expressed

common

person

by Socrates

opinions.

He

is

aware that they cannot furnish us with knowledge,


but only involve us in contradictions. But he does
not hence draw the inference of the Sophists, that ne
knowledge is possible, but only that ifc is not possible
in that way. The majority of mankind have no true

'

knowledge, because they confine themselves to suppothey have never


sitions, the accuracy of which
only taking into consideration one or
examined

'

another property of things, but not their essence, \


Amend this fault ; consider every object in all its
bearings, and endeavour from this many-sided observation to determine the true essence ; you have
'

i\

then conceptions instead of vague notions a regular


examination, instead of an unmethodical and unconscious procedure a true, instead of an imaginary

In thus requiring knowledge of conceptions, Socrates not only broke away from the current
Wiew, but, generally speaking, from all previous

knowledge.

philosophy.

A thorough

observation from every side,

a critical examination, a methodical enquiry conscious

CHARACTERISTICS OF HIS PHILOSOPHY.


of

own

113

basis, was demanded all that had


hitherto
been regarded as knowledge was rejected,
because it
its

short of these conditions

fell

Chap.

'

^-

and at the same time


the conviction was expressed that, by
observing these
;

knowledge could be secured.

rules, real

For Socrates

this principle

had not only an inbut a more immediate moral value. It


is
one of the most striking things
about him

D. Moral

tellectual,
.

in fact

Hhat

he

unable to distinguish between morality


and knowledge, and can neither imagine

^^^^P"'''^'

Tcor!,!^''

is

knowledge

>

without virtue, nor virtue without


knowledge.
In
this respect also he is the child of
his age, his great^

ness consisting herein, that with


great penetration

and

spirit

he gave

effect to its

requirements and

its

legitimate endeavours. Advancing


civilisation having
created the demand for a higher
education

amongst

the Greeks, and the course of


intellectual development having diverted attention from the
study of
nature and fixed it on that of mind,
a closer connection became necessary between
conduct.

Only in

philosophy and
could philosophy find its

man

highest object; only in philosophy


could the support

be found which was needed for

had endeavoured
great

skill

life.

The Sophists

meet this requirement with


and vigour; hence their extraordinary
to

success.

Nevertheless, their moral philosophy


was
too deficient in tenable
ground ; by doubting
it

had loosened
hence

'

it

its

intellectual roots only too efFectually

degenerated with

terrific speed,

entering th J

Particular proof of this will be given


subsequently.
I

'

SOCRATES.

1X4

Chap,

wicked and

service of every

selfish

impulse.

Instead

of philoof moral life being raised by the influence

had taken the


sophy, both conduct and philosophy
same downward course.
This

sad state

of

things

Socrates

thoroughly

Whilst, however, his contemporaries,


Sophistic teacheither blind with admiration for the
or else through
ing, were insensible to its dangers,
indifference to the
dread of these, and with a singular
history, dewants of the times and the march of
the innovators in the tone of Aristophanes,

understood.

nounced

he with keener penetration could distinguish


what was right and what was wrong in the
the age.

want

The

between
spirit of;

insufficiency of the older culture, the

obscurity of the
of basis in ordinary virtue, the
notions so full of contradictions, the ne-

prevailing

all were felt and


cessity for intellectual education,
the Sophists.
taught by him as much as by anyone of

and higher ends,


But* to this teaching he set other
but rather to
not seeking to destroy belief in truth,
how truth might be acquired by a new intel-

show

lectual process.
selfishness of the

from

selfishness

His aim was not to minister to the


age, but rather to rescue the age
and sloth, by teaching it what was

undermine morality
truly good and useful ; not to
foundation o
and piety, but to build them on a new
^>

"

knowledge.

Thus Socrates was

at once a moral anc

great thought wa
an intellectual reformer. His one
mean
how to transform and restore moral conduct by
elements were so closel;
of knowledge and these two
he could fin(
associated together in his mind, that
;

CIIARACTEIilSriCS OF IILS PIIILOSOPIIY,

115

no other object for knowledge


save human conduct
'
and no guarantee for conduct
save
in

How great the services were which

knowledo-e

he rendered to both
morality and science by this
effort, how wholesome
was the influence which he
exercised on the intellectual condition of his people
and of mankind generally
history attests. If in the
sequel, the difference
between
morality and intellect was
recognised quite as fully
as their unity, yet the
tie by which he
connected
them has never been broken
;
and if in the last
cen unes of the old world,
philosophy took the place
of the waning religion,
giving a stay to morality,
purifying and quickening
the moral consciousness
To revert to

mooted above, as

tlie

question

to

whether

other liand, R/ihlmfs


(Socrat.
Studien, i. 46) view does
not
seem to carry conviction,
that, according to
both Plato
and Xenophon, Socrates took
the first place a
pi-actical
view of life, and that nhe
theory of knowledge
was only
developed by him for the sake

he primarily reo-arded
knowledge as a means to
moral
action, or moral action
as a
result of knowledge, so
much
may be said: that his peculiarity

for

consisted

him

herein

that

this

dilemma did
not exist, that for him
knowledge as such was at
once a
moral need and a moral
force,
an<l that therefore virtue,
as
shall find, was neitlier

'

know-

we

a simple
coiisecjuonce of knowledg-e,
nor
an end to be attained bv
means
ot knowledge, but
was directly
and in itself knowledo-e
If
therefore, Labriola
(Uottrina

di ocrate, 40)
describes the
only inner motive of
Socratesaction as
the m(n-al need of
certainty, and the
conviction
tnat this IS only
attainable bv
a clear and indubitably
certaiii
knowledge,' his statement
may
be accepted as true.
On
'

of a practical purpose.'
We
have already seen that,
according to Socrates, true

ledge coincides with right


intention.
But, for the reasons
set

forth on p. 105, we cannot


allow that knowledge witli
him
has no inde])endent value,
and
IS only pursued
as a means to
a practical pui-pose which
must
be the view of Ribbing,
in as
far as he contradicts
the one
given above. Nor do the
passages quoted l)y Ribbing
(Plato
Apol 22,p.; 28, D.;
;

A.
view.

thJ-

29, E.
A.) suggest this
';

^i,

38,

Chap.
V.

SOCRATES.

11(3

Chap.

this great

^'

and beneficial

result, in as far as it

can be

assigned to any one individual, was due to the teach-

ing of Socrates.

The interest of philosophy being thus turned


^^ay from the outer world and directed towards man

E. The
llmrfctcr
of the

and

his moral nature,

man

and

only regarding things

and binding of the truth of which he has


convinced himself by intellectual research, there
appears necessarily in Socrates a deeper importance
as true

SoamtX

attached
this

to the

modern

personality

of

writers have thought to

peculiar character of his philosophy.^

however,

is

thinker.

the

In

discern the

Very

different,

the personal importance of the thinker

with Socrates from the caprice of the Sophists, different too from the extreme individualism of the
Socrates was aware, that
post-Aristotelian schools.
each individual must seek the grounds of his own
conviction for himself, that truth is not something
given from without, but must be found by the exerHe required all opinions
cise of individual thought.

examined anew, no matter how old or how


common they were, proofs only and not authorities
Still, he was far from making man,
claiming belief.

to be

He
as Protagoras did, the measure of all things.
declare
did not even as the Stoics and Epicureans
the
personal conviction and practical need to be
ultimate standard of truth, nor yet as the Sceptics,

him knowresolve all truth into probability ; but to


persuaded
ledge was an end in itself; so too he was
J

Hegel, Gescb. d. Phil.

ii.

40

Kotscher, Aristoph., pp. 246, 388.

CHARACTJEIilSTICS OF HIS PHILOSOPHY.

117

true knowledge could be obtained by a


thoughtful consideration of things.
Moreover he saw in man
the proper object of philosophy, but instead
of making
tliat

of personal caprice a law, as the Sophists


did, he
subordinated caprice to the general law residing
in the
nature of things and of moral relations.^
Instead
too of making, with later philosophers, the
self-contentment of the wise man his highest end, he

conhimself to the point of view of old


Greek
morality, which could not conceive of the
individual
apart from the community,^ and which
accordingly
fined

regarded activity for the state as the first


duty of a
itizen,3 and ihe law of the state as the
natural rule

of conduct.^

Hence the Stoic apathy and

to country were entirely alien

be truly said

<jan

indifference

from Socrates.

If

it

him commences an unbounded reference to the person, to the freedom


of
the inner life,' ^ it must also be added that
this statement by no means exhausts the theory of
Socrates.
Thus the disputes as to whether the Socratic
'

that in

doctrine

on a purely personal or a really independent


basis will have to be settled, by
allowing indeed that,
rests

compared with former systems,


Proofs

maybe found
"^'^'

f-^^'-'^^'
^^'
'

:.

Kc^^'^'
*' *^^-

Xen.

"^'

^'

compare the conversation


with Aristippus, Xeii. Mem. ii.
,

K{

1,

and

Plato's Crito, 53, A.

^^^^ been ah-eady seen


Socrates placed his own
activity under this point of
view See pp. 65, 68 Xen. Mem.
1. t*, J5
Plato, Apol. 30, A.
ti,
iJiHi
,

Mem.

iv.

4,

12,

and

3, 15,

his teaching exhibits

with which the previous re^^""^^ respecting the peculiar


conduct of the sage may be
compared,
^

Hegel,

1.

c.

Compare the views of Rotscher, 1. c, and Braadu for the


opposite view.
Ueber die

<

vorgebliche Subjektivitat der


Sokrat. Lehre,' iii Khein. Mu"'
ii.

l,

85.

Chap.

SOCRATES.

118

a deeper importance attaching to the personality of

Chap.
'

the thinker, without, however, by any means belonging

which are purely

to those

It

relative.

aims at gaining

a knowledge which shall do more than satisfy a per-

and desirable for


but the ground on which it

sonal want, and which shall be true

more than the thinker


is

sought

is

the personal thought

This theory
Socrates.

is

He has

of the individual.

indeed not further expanded by


established the principle, that only

the knowledge which has to do with conceptions


true knowledge.

To the

being of conceptions

is

further inference that only the


true being,^ and that there-

fore only conceptions are true,


'

exposition

of

is

conceptions

and to a systematic

true in

themselves

sa

Knowledge is here something


sought, a problem to be solved by the thinker philosophy is philosophic impulse, and philosophic method,
a seeking for truth, not yet a possessing it and this

far

he never advanced.

deficiency countenances the view that the platform


'

Hegel

saj^s

nothing very

but

the

which

Socrates from the Sophists he


in Socrates the creation
says
of thought is at once clad with
an independent existence of its
own,' and what is purely personal is externalised and made
universal by him as the good.'
Socrates is said to have substithinking man is the
tuted
measure of all things,' in place
man
of the Sophistic doctrine
is the measure of all things.'
In a word, his leading thought
not the individual as he
is
knows himself experimentally,

agree also

when

'

'

'

'

all

universal

element

found running through


individuals. With this view

in distinguishing (Gesch. d. Phil. ii. 40, 166)

different,

is

Ilotsclier,

1.

c. p.

246,

392, and Hermann, Gesch. und


Syst. des Plat. i. 239.
The objections of AUertiy
Sokr. 94, to the above vanish
'^

only is properly
if the word
emphasised. He only assorts
what is already well know%
that Socrates did not develope
his theory of conceptions to the
theory of ideas, nor contrast
the universal thought in the
conception, as being the only
thing truly real with individual
'

things.

'

CIIARACTEliWnCS OF HIS PIIILOSOPHY.


of Socrates was that of a narrow reference to
person.

Still it

the

should never be forgotten, that the

aim of Socrates was always to discover and set forth


that which is in itself true and good. Mankind is to be
intellectually

and morally educated, but the one and

only means thereto

is

The primary aim

to attain a knowledge of truth.

of Socrates being to train

men

to think, rather

than to construct a system, the main


point with him was a philosophic method to determine the way which would lead to truth. The substance of his teaching thus
partly

appears to have been

confined to questions having an immediate

bearing on

human conduct

partly

it

does not go

beyond the general and theoretical demand, that


action should be determined by a
ceptions.

There

is

knowledge of con-

no systematic development of

individual points of morality

a reason for them.

all

and no attempt to give

119

Chap.
^'

SOCRATES.

120

CHAPTER YI
THE PHILOSOPHICAL METHOD OF SOCRATES.
Chap.
\

The

peculiarity of the

method pursued by Socrates

consists, generally speaking, in

deducing conceptions
from the common opinions of men.
Beyond the
formation of conceptions, however, and the intellectual exercise of individuals his

nor

is

method did not go

there any systematic treatment of the concep-

tions gained.

The theory

of a knowledge of concep-

tions appearing here as a claim, the

of

its

necessity

must be presupposed

consciousness

as existing,

and

an insight into the essence of things be sought.

At

the same time, thought does not advance further

than this seeking.


to

It has not the

power to develop^

a system of absolute knowledge, nor has

it

method sufficiently matured to form a system. For


the same reason, the process of induction is not
reduced

within

clearly

defined

Socrates has clearly expressed


late,

tion.

is

rules.

All

that

the general postu-

that every thing must be reduced to

its

concep-

Further details as to the mode and manner of

and its strict logical forms, were not


yet worked out by him into a science, but were
applied by him practically by dint of individual skill.
this reduction

The only thing about him

at all resembling a logical

KNOWLEDGE OF
rule,

the

maxim

^ELF.

]2I

that the process of critical enquiry

must always confine

itself

to

what

is

universally

Chap.
^^'

admitted/ sounds far too indefinite to invalidate our


assertion.

This process involves three particular steps. The


first is the Socratic knowledge of
self.
Holding as he
did that only the knowledge of conceptions constitutes

(f-'<''^A

true knowledge, Socrates was fain to look at all sup-

TS-*''

posed knowledge, asking whether it agreed with his


idea of knowledge, or not. Nothing appeared to him
more perverse, nothing more obstructive to true

knowledge from the very outset, than the belief thatyou know what you do not know.^ Nothing is so
necessary as self-examination, to show what

we

know and what we only think we know.^

Nothing,

too,

is

more indispensable
^'

^'

J'\V ^""^l"
cLu^"^'"'.'''
"'I''
^"^":'
^'"Z""
lltV'
M.d\^Taof.o\oyovf.eua>ue7rope{>eTo,
V^o^fii^ooyjavrnuTvuaacpa^eLauehai

V\'',, Tv/r
^?'''., .r /

""'"''

liaol

VLT

^'"T"'

'"'"

'>",

,.

\/^''^''

'>^

''""' ""'-

'\'- ?'

-^^'

'5e

,twr
co^ieiP re KatoUadai yiyi^ciaKeiy,
g2^ZI

cLnp^
'Called

'^''"'-

^""'"'i '^"-y'^^r'
'"^' ^^'"'^ ^^'^

"^/^?
mad
who

are mistaken

about what IS commonly known,

mistaken
about things
t?n-n r of
fwhich
i""'^,
most men
are ignorant. Also Plato,
Apol.
"""' c^'T'' '""' '''"' "^^'

^^>
,

^'^;,''"*

l"
in

tins

'""^ '^^^^

sense

practical

relations

speaking in PUto, Apol. 21,


^^^^t

'^^y'

according-

to

B.,

the

oracle he had interrogated all


with wliom he was ^brought
^^^^^ contact, to discover whether they had any kind of know^^^^^ ^''^ tl^at in all cases he
had found along with some kind
^*"
knowledge an ignorance,
which he would not take in exchange for any kind of knowledge-an opinion that they
^"^'^ ^^l^at they did not kno^v^
On the other hand, he considered
'

''Jl^^^^^^^oTVf^o-

"^
Iw/7"1
^^^'^T
'"'^^^%'^"; ^ ^^

for

really

Socrates,

be his vocation, cptAoao^povp4^erdCoura i^avrh. Kal


robs &\Aovs (28, EoTand he
says elsewhere (38, AO that
*^'ere could be no higher p-ood
it to

ra

(fl^ Kal

'

lie

did

6 Sk

a.,i4raaros

ISicvrhs avOpcoTrcf.

fiios

ou

A. The

kZ^e
re-

^<^<^(i<^ofnot
"-"'''"'''

SOCRATES.

[22

Chap.
VI.

than to become acquainted with the state of our inner


capacities,
self, with the extent of our knowledge and
with

oui'

defects

One

and requirements.^

result of

the discovery that the

this self-examination being

actual knowledge of the philosopher does not correspond with his idea of knowledge, there follows
further that consciousness of knowing nothing, which
Socrates declared to be his only knowledge. For any

other knowledge he denied possessing,^ and therefore


refused to be the teacher of his friends,^ only wishing.

Mem.

Xe)iojjhon,

>

2, 24,

iv.

Delpliic
enquiring- into the
yvuQi ffiavTov, says that self-

attended wdtli
the greatest advantages, want
of it" with the greatest disadol
p.y yap clZores
vantages

knowledge

is

ovdirepos ovdev Ka\hj/ Kayo.dov etSeVai. aW' ovtqs (xev oUtuI


Tt elSevai ovk eiSws, iyu) Se oJcirep
23, B. :
ouv OVK oiBa, ovSe oXofxai.
riixwv

ovTos

vfjiiov, S) 6.v6p(t}Troi,

oaTis,

iffTLV,

<ro(pd)raros'
ScoKpdTTjS',.

Sicrirfp

OTL ov^evhs a|ios iCTi rp

g-yj/oj/cei',

eavrovs rd re iiTLTTjSeia eauTots


diayiyvctXTKovaLV a re
i(ra(ri Koi
ZvvavTai

Koi

4iri(TTavTai

b.

ixrj-

kuI

&

fxhv

(self-

irpaTTovres

examination always refers in


the first place to knowledge,
because with knowledge right
action is given) TropiCovrai re
wv deovTUi Koi eu -npdrrovcTiv.
8ee also Plato, Phsdrus, 229,
he had not time to give
E.
to the explanation of mji:hs of
which others were so fond, not
being even able to knov\' himself according to the Delphic
oracle; Sj-mp. 216, A.; when
avaycomplains
Alcibiades
KO^et yap fie bjjioKoyelv, on iroKAou ivSerjs &V avrbs en ifxavrov ixev d^aeAw, rd 5' 'Adrjvaiuv

before

And a

crotpiav.

Trpos

d\r)0eta
little

rh 8e Kiv^vvevei,

3>.

&vdpes 'AO-qvaioi, T<^ ovri 6 dehs


aocpos

elvai,

iv

Kal

Tourcp TOVTO Xey^iv,


TTij/rj

eVri

D.

0)5

t^

on

oKiyov

cro(pia

xpV^^H-V
avOpco-

rj

tiiA)S

a|ia

S}Tnp. 216,'
07^06! Tvavra koX ovSev olSev,
rh (TX^f^^ avTov, Thesetet.
ouSej/os.

KoX

150, C.

ayovos

elfjn

ffo<pias,

Kol

OTrep ^Stj ttoKKol /aoi ajveidiaav, a>S

TrpaTTco.
iyco
Flato, Apol. 21, B.
5rj ovre fxeya ovre a/xiKpov
avvoLca i/xavTw aocpos cov.'Il,
D. TOVTOV fxkv Tov di/QpcoTTou iyci}
-

yap

ao(pwTep6s dfiL- KivBvvevei fxhu yap

robs ixkv aXKovs ipwrw, avrbs 5^


ov8eu aiTOKpivoixai irepl ovdevhs Sio
rb ^7)Sei/ exeiv ao(p6v, dArj0es 6^ethiCovai- Th Se a%nov tovtov Tt^Se"
fiaieveaOai

fxe

Oehs

avayKd(ei,

Comp.
yevvdv 5e d'neKuKvffev.
Rep' i. 337, E. Men. 98, B.
That this trait in Plato has
been taken from the Socrates
of history, may be gathered
from the Platonic dialogues, in
;

which his teacher is by no


means represented as so ignorant.
^

See above,

p. 67.

KNOWLEDGE OF

SELF.

common

123

with them, to learn and enquire.


This
(.onfession of his ignorance was certainly far from
lacing a sceptical denial of knowledge,^ with which
the whole philosophic career of Socrates would be
ill

On

irreconcilable.

a\-owal as to his

the contrary,

own

contains a simple

it

personal state, and collaterally

the state of those whose knowledge he had had


the opportunity of testing.^
Nor again must it be
regarded as mere irony or exaggerated modesty.^
as to

Socrates really

knew nothmg,

or to express it other-

he had no developed theory, and no positive


dogmatic principles. The demand for a knowledge
wise,

of conceptions having once


i\

all

fulness,

dawned upon him in

ail

he missed the marks of true knowledge in

that hitherto passed for

wisdom and knowledge.


first to make this demand,
lie had as yet attained no
definite content for knowledge.
The idea of knowledge was to him an
i)eing,

however, also the

unfathomable problem, in the face of which he could


not but be conscious of his ignorance.^
And in so far
a

certain affinity between his view

Koiv^ fiooXeveaeai, kolvtJ oKenreadoi, Koivfi Cvreh, (rv^-nre-if,


'

^c. J^efL, Mem. iv. 5, 12;


6,
1; I'lato, Theait. 151, E. ; Prot.

,'

r?''^'''-'"^-

B.

Meno,

^^^89 E.

^'

^^'^*-

As the Aew Academicians


u^.uld have it, Cic. Acad. i. 12,
-

.'

i]' ^'^'Z'^-

.
already
quoted Ianguage of the Apology, 23, A.,
does not contradict this; the
I'osxxhUity of knowledge not
Ixing there denied, but only

llie

and the sophistic

the limited character of human


knowledge being asserted in
compai-ison with the divine.
^

As

Cerate

remarks (Plato,

i.

referring to A7^ist.
Soph. El. 34, 183, b, 7: ^Trel
Kal 5m toCto :^wKpdrr]s rjouTa
dAA' oi,K a-rreKpiuero- i:^io\6yiyhp
^^0,

^'^'^

323),

^'^^'"'''

Coi^f- Flato,

Rep.

337.
^

Compare

Phil.

32G.

ii.

Ileael,

Gescli. d.

54; Hermann, Plato,

chap.
^^'

'
1

SOCRATES.

in
Chap.
VI.

may

scepticism

In as

be observed.

the possibility of

denied

far as it

knowledge, Socrates opposed this

all

scepticism, whilst agreeing with

in as far as

it

re-

it

Natural philosophers,

ferred to previous philosophy.

he believed, transcended in their enquiries the limits


of

human knowledge.

clear proof of this fact is

that they are at variance with one another respecting


Some hold being to
the most important questions.

be one, others

make

of

it

a boundless variety

some

teach that everything, others that nothing, is subject


to motion some that all things, others that nothing;
;

comes into being or

Just as the Sophists;

perishes.^

destroyed the conflicting statements of the natural!'

means of each

philosophers by

from the contest of systems, that no one of

infers

them

Socratesf

other, so

is

ference

Their great

in possession of the truth.


herein, the

consists

Sophists

making

dif-

Not-,

knowing into a principle, and considering the highest)


wisdom to consist in doubting everything Socrates
;

adhering to his demand

for knowledge, clinging to the

belief in its possibility, consequently regarding igno-

rance as the greatest


B. The

search for
knowledge.
Sifting of

evil.

Such being the importance of the Socratic Notknowing, it involves in itself a demand for enlightenment the knowledge of ignorance leads to a searcl
;

Ms fellowmen. Eros

and

irony.

Xen. Mem.

that

Socrates

1,

i.

did

13,

not

says

busy
of

with questions
natural science, but on the
contrary he held those who
ieavfia^e 5'
did to be foolish

liimself

ei

fiT]

(pavephv

avrois

eariv,

ravra ov dvvarov iariv

'6ti

avQpoo-

TTOts'

upe7v

iirel

(TTOV (ppouovvras

Twv

\4yciv

aKX-^Kois
ofioiccs

ov

ahXa

/cat

robs

tm

e^ri

rahrb.
rots

/xeyi-

Trepi

rov

5o|a^eti

jxatvoniuoi:

SiaKeiadai. irphs dA\^\ous'

then follows what


the text.

is

quoted

ii

SEARCH FOR TRUE KJSOWLEDGE.


The

knowledge.

for true

125

consciousness of our

own

Not-knowing continuing, and the philosopher having


:in idea of knowledge without finding
it realised in
the searcli for knowledge naturally assumes
form of an application to others, with a view
of

liimself,
lie

ascertaining whether the knowledge wanting


at home
is to be found with them.i
Hence the necessity of
enquiry in common by means of the dialogue.^

For

SocrateF', this

mode

of intercourse has not merely an

educational value, procuring easier access and


a
fruitful

an

effect for his

ideas, but it

is

to his

more
mind

indispensable condition of the

development of
and one from which the Socrates of history
departs.3 Speaking more accurately, its
nature

lought,
IK 'ver

men such as it is described in


Apology,^ or in a bringing to the birth,
as it is
called in the Theaetetus
in other words, the philoconsists in a sifting of
(lie

'^

x'pher by his questions obliges others to


unfold their
inner self before him ^ he asks
after their real
:

The connection

'

lan-n

is

very ap-

in tlie Apol. 21,

B.,

if

inner thou-ht of the


I'liilosophy of Socrates is put
m the place of the oracular
nl.ytlie

'"*-'^I'*^"-'^e.

Compare

p.

U^,

irpoa-nKoicrais

^p&l,<nv ahrohs duac


.V.m6A.?to
and the enquiry
into human nature has this
meaning- in Mem. iii. 6 iv 2
but clearly this is not its orie-i-'
^
nal object.
:

2.

^^^ p. 149 122, 2


Plato, Lach. 187, E
he
wlio enters into conversation
with Socrates /.^ Traieaeai imh
;

(.omi)are, besides the Men-.rabilia


Apol. 24, C.
i'>tao-. 33o, B.,
336, B. Theajt.

Pto

Mm.larly

Xe>,. ^Mem. iv.


^a^Tco, f,,vyap c^u.y^ oTda
aA^<rTa ./xeAei' avrc, uSeuuL '6rov
.

eU rwu avySurccu
Xenophon only took it

eiricrr^f^a^u
^f

^^V.
"

|)rovc

'6ri

avrdpKfis iv

ra7s

^^h hu i^^^iav ^Is rh ScLac Zol


airod A6you, bynua rpiirov vdv re
nor is there any escape
(fj,
from the most thorough Ba(raviC^adai.

Chap.
^^-

SOCRATES.

126

hap.
^'^'

opinions, after the reasons of their beliefs

and in

this

and actions,

way attempts by an interrogatory analysis^

of their notions to bring out the thought latent


therein, of which they are themselves unconscious.*

In as

far as this process presupposes that the

know-

ledge which the quesHoner lacks

may

others, it resembles an impulse to

supplement one's

own

defects by their help.

others

is,

for a philosopher

be found in

Tliis intercourse

with

whom knowing

coin-

with

cides with purposing, not only an intellectual but also


To enquire in common
a moral and personal need.
is

at once to live in

at once impulse to

Love of knowledge is
friendship, and in the blending

common.

together of these two sides consists the peculiarity of

the Socratic Eros.^


In as far as others do not possess the knowledge

sought

for,

and the questions of Socrates only serve

to

expose their ignorance, the process bears also the


Irony, however, must not be
character of irony.
understood to be merely a conversational trick
1
It is assumed as a matter
of course, that every one can
2:ive an account of what he
knows and is, Phto, 1. c. 190, C.

Charm. 158, E.
2 See above, p. 75.
Besides
Brandis ii. a, 64, reminds us
with justice that treatises on
fpws are mentioned not only by
Plato and Xenophon, but also
by Euclid, Crito, Simmias, and
Antisthenes, which shows the
importance of it for the So-

The chief passage is in Xenophon, Symp. c.


of a
.S, where the advantages

cratic schools.

still

spiritual and the disadvantaires


of a sensual love are unfolded,
apparently (as a careful surve\

of the Platonic Symposion wil.


show) by Xenophon, speaking
for himself, but undoubtedlj
followin<j: in the train

of So;

Even ^Eschines ant


Cebes had treated of epcos ]i

crates.

the Socratic sense. See Plut


Puer. Ed. c. 15, p. 11, and th.
fragment of iEschines in Aris
7^?VZ.

Or. xlv. p. 34.

Gesch. d. Phil,
53, 57; Conf. Arist. Eth.
13; 1127, b, 22.
^

jferjel,

ii

OF EROS AND

f/W
less

IJiOxXr.

12;

that derisive condescension


or affected simphcity which as it were
lures others on to the
ice in
order to laugh at their
falls; or that absoh.te
reference to the person and
destruction of all general
truth which for a
time bore this name
it

c
Chai'.

Tn7l

romantic school.

Its proper nature

consists rather

herem

that without any


positive knowledge, and
prompted only by a desire
for knowledge,
addresses himself to
others, in the hope

lo^rate.

learning

from them what they


know, but that in' the
atteTpf
to discover it, upon
a critical analysis

of their notions,even' their supposed


knowledge vanishes. This

S Zf

fe^e::i^t,^Zr^S
Socrates.
See Rep.

*a)

roiro^s

337 a

^poi^Keyou

tipwv,6aoco 5h Kal nr6,vTa


^P<ora.

And

Arfyo./cai

aoain

V2

aaXXou

s-fv

387

^]!'

^'^""l"''^

^^

.'

""'^^'l

^vepd,.ovs

har.X,:,

wliich

as

context shows refeinart?^


to the fact that
Socrates m-e
tended to be in
-.1^
:
being sfAn t,ie G
: k's^n i'of
the term, and
partly to t,e

wJ

words
oKJe.
I

word

a^.oe?

4.r .alo/s^^

The same, omitting


the
..>co,,.r,

Pas^age of the

is

said in the

The.tetus

l^l!

In

after

the

f^o^J^y^uacri

^""J^^'^^'^

e'|eAeV|a,.

^^-^-

('Oni

-'

1.
.

"-

u^jtSs

goes on to

^''

AA..

1"

ttWo^

.'^^"^'

"^^"^"^ '^C,^' it

e'A^^-TwWcfso^ ^J'''
^aTaf;'" 4?'^''

tlie

o^^^''

crates replies'^'^Ls

'"

"''%'

\-

2,

Likewise
^'^0: 5..

36

kXXd

^-xp-r.s, .r^eas
1> ''^'^t'
"''' !^'' ^ '^^^^'^^^ ^V^^S".
^
"^^"^^
(Mtilian,
"^

ix.

t^?'

'''''' '''^

cauThV'T'^

^'^^'^'"^

.n
^^^^^r
wTsdo^ n? ,f

Part

tl

of

>

4^

^^^-^^ l^^e of
"^^^""^^' ^^-

-''^^''^r-

^J^'^^^^

of

^^^e

the

^^""ected

-;-^;ch

.
'

'''
'

SOCRATES.

lit*

.r.
Chap

^^_

irony

is,

the dialectical
therefore, speaking generally,

the Socratic method, assumor the critical factor in


to the presuppeculiar form it here does owing
ing the
posed ignorance of

C.

no

,^.,pssio-

"'-i'-

'"""

instrument

of

knowledge, he must at least have


method
possessed the notion and the

real

t,::Z Lie^ed that he

'^Z!X

for his

Socrates might he of
Doubtless, however conscious

ri,o

fo,-,mtion

him who uses it

true knowledge.

Without

this

conviction

he

to confess his own ignowould neither have been able

that of others, both being only


ranee, nor to expose

comparing the knowledge he


rendered possible by
knowledge residing within
found with the idea of
where to b.,
The fact that this idea was no
himself
a challenge to him to set;
found realised was in itself
resulted as the third point
about realising it; and hence
the attempt to create real,
in his philosophic course
he could only allow
knowledge. For real knowledge
from the conception of
that to pass which emanated
step here is the formation of
a thing, hence the first
For even if Socrates does
conceptions or induction.'
definitions, he at least
not always make for formal
quality applicable to the
always seeks some universal
of the object, in order
conception and to the essence
|

referring the
question under notice by
to settle the
universal quaUty.^ The classparticular case to this

fi?"

f'nnf

i,

ic

Plat

2i8fD
T^p
Only
M

also Leop. Schmid


Marbnrg 1873
Lection,
in Ind.
Compare the remarks o
already mentroned

tlic

word

^Z^S^r^-^ A^^

A,^fl

S^r;t;lS45,:fGrcl,

.....W^V. eep.nO,.

*l'^-

iv

its

the use ot
d. Phil. 83, and for

T
FORMATION OF COycEPTIOXS.
quality

The

is

therefore to hin. of
the greatest import-

starting- point for


this

by the commonest notions.


taken from daily Hfe,
.i,,
admitted truths. On

inducMan

is supplied
beoins with .
,

He

^..^ l^^^

every disputed
pointTe go"^
back to such mstances,
and hopes in this
way to
attam a universal
agreement
All
^,^.'^''^'i'All
previous science
oeng donTrffi.i
beinodoubtful, nothing
remains but to begin
anew
'

,-,

: h the simplest experiences.


On the o
.nduotion has not as yet
so far advanced

S^ hand

Jenving conceptions
from an exhaustive
and

^mX

as to

tested series of
observations.

This

is

being

the'

a later! quir!

nent due partly to


Aristotle, and partly
nodern philosophy.
The wider basis of a
hensive knowledge of
facts being as yet

'en

an

JZl

L^re

wantingna

despised,

and

Socrates

abit of

being

the'

expanding his thoughts


in personal convem
|on wi h distinct
reference to the' case
befo^eh
I'd to the capacity
and needs of his

fellow-speakerT
confined to the
assumptions which
>fances and his own
limited experience
supply Te"
"lust take isolated
notions and admissions
'h;
Pomt of departure, and
can onlv ^o a flras
oh
an oUow. Hence
l;e IS

tLTcum
4

r^C^lT^^^

in most cases h^
-ular instances than
on an exhaustive
;

I
i

Compare

'

what

looted, pp. 80, 2:


;e

has
12],

been
1

IZ

whole of the Memorabi^a

':'to,

too,

gives instances of
1"^ procedure.
See
CFc

Xm

-'^

%..

.
.

... ..

u ,. ,,,

anaS;;-

^^'^

f.^^T^''
^71/
Vs

Vo

fL\

"^'''" ^'''^^^'^ ^''^'5e.;c.^.

'^'^'"'

';i;

^-ra^^a., dva.e/-

"' "'^ "^"^^^ ^''^^--^-Pi'mciple that from

^^^^^:::i^^^,a

SOCRATi:S.
1?.0

Chap.
VI.

in his principles
This chance element

experience.*

by collectrng
endeavours to eliminate

^h wever,

supplement
to correct and
opposite instances, so as
ron,
one another. The ques
varying experiences by
of mhim being the conception
for instance, before
who has,
He is unjnst, says Euthydemus,
iustice
Yet, rejmns Socrates,
like.
deceives, robs, and such
and to rob an enemy.
lie, to deceive,
it is right to
must be more accurately
Accordingly the conception
who does such thmg.,
ttus: He is unjnst
perEven such action is, however,
to his friends.
A general rs not uryu t
fitted under circumstances.
army by a lie, nor a father
when he encourages his
by deception, nor a fnend
who gives his son medicine
which he
the weapon with
robs his friend of
:

delS

who

suicide.
would have committed
fore,

We ^^^^^'^^^

Unjust s he
limitation.
introduce a further
them
friends in ord.r to do
deceives or robs his
ruler has to be disthe conception of a

who
harm^

Or

ruler as one who


General opinion regards a
But this power,
give orders.
has tbe power to
steersman on
conceded only to the
Socrates shows, is

covered.

physician in case of sickship, only to the


conversan
other case only to those
ness, and in every
Only he, therefore, is
the special subject.

board
with

who

ruler

ruling

'

knowledge necessary fo.


belongs k
must be determined what
The smith says, it must be^

possesses

Or

it

the

a good suit of armour.

in the comwith
politician
the
paiison
&c.
the physician, pilot,
.

As

to e^mple

'

2. Jl;
1^-^"i- '

IM-

'

METHOD OF INDUCTION.

therefore has the


proper size

apposing a .a wishes
fit exactly?
Not so n.
hi.s

what

R f ""'
raZ,,''""^*
Isfthe
^^^le f
armour
it fits

r,

We'm i\r

moveLnts

fitting

to

when

''"^"^'^

'^

'"

"^^^.^^

is

comfortable for use ^


way we see Socrates
analysing thoTougWy
thl
men notions of his friends
'^ ^^"^ comW.

"f

^ -lu

leiauon to some
other

^r^A

\.r.

."?'

"'
by additional
observations
""*'*^'^^^"ois, assumptions
resting on a n^ .-a a
tbem 'and
teV^P^-^-' ^* --Pleting
'^"^^^-By this prfoes'
correcting,

gLH

essence of every
captions are

ra:L\rwT r^f
^''^'

obieotTT t

^l^itoT.:^^

In order'to
invitigate

tt

''''

""

Mem.

iii.

10,9.
'
' iv.
6, B.
' t'or instance,
in order tn
;;eprove Lamproctes
fori fs con?

^'^^

-""

'

'T'''^'

"" ^"'''''S conceptions


'

* t'^e

*^'"^^-

he always

,.

that his conduct


JT" "^l^ows
'^'"' *'"^
conception
fn
IJ''"""f

K 2

P"]' '''*

"^'''ic'

before

SOCRATES.

_-

CHAP
vt

kuowB and universally adprogresses from what is


Hence hrs method o
here.
>
so, too, he does

2ed

as.
varied turns,; according
He
another point of departure.
starts from one or
granted,
to he taken for
a general principle
particular ca.e ; = he refutes
^ndlncludes under it the
corjrabringing home to them
foreign assertions by
undoubted
or with other
dTctions with themselves
builds up the premrsse
assumptions or facts- he
conclusions by means o

;: UUhe'most

Sws

his
torn which he deduces

by an apparent

straight off
nduction, or concludes
proof he has
A theory of this method of
analogy.^
the various krnds o
:: g!ven, nor distinguished
this that
point about it is only

The

Zool

Everything

To

find

essential

is

conceptrons.
measured and decided by
end rs reached .s
turns by which this

a matter of personal

LIL,

Anstotle,

critical dexterity.

from
chief merit of Socrates
in rSaking the
-ncepti-and
in the formation of

h side'consist
on the whole be allowed
in induction,<> must
"^'Isking further

as to the objects

practised lis method,

SaofXenophon

in the

Memora-

materrals-xna motley array of

Pf

have

on which Socrates

we encounter

the
in order to prove
begxns
he
Gods,
teing of the
<>
with the general
*f^
an end must
all that serves
cause
intelligent

pts

to be

an

enquires
better citizen, he first
of a
features
peculiar
into the
l*;good citizen (iv. 6,

^^^^iJi^M^S^ d.
-^

"'in
p.

}fj-^^^,^^^^^ Mem.

Mem.
>.

j21.

tte cases quoted o

2, i^^
^_

i.

2,

34

APPLICATION OF HIS METHOD.

133

vc^tigutions into the


essence of virtue, the
duties of
man, the existence of
Gods, disputes with
Sophists

""

""'

^"'^'

^^'

^-- ^ f-Js and'

acquaintances, conversations
with generals as to the
-ponsibilities of their
office,

tradesmen as to their
o thexr mode of life.

wlh ar^lers

arts,

id

even with loose

Nothing

is

women as
too small to arouse

the curiosity of
the philosophy and
to call for a

^^-'--- As Plata
^Z^\^TT''^'
"^ ^" """^^ -*^-t

tL cl

T'

-ception

^0
1^S^'lf"^a
""'^"^
r;

''' "'^^^ "^^ educational


'^''
apparent, referred
everything to
ts conception..
He looked upon the life'and
pu
misof man as the real
object of his enquiries,
and
her things only
as far as they
affected the conJit ons and
problems of human life.
Hence his
philosophy, which in
point of scientific
form

was a

application a science of
'

human

8ee p

10*

actions (^ft.^).

Chap.
VI.

SOCRATES.

j3^

CHAPTER

VII.

OF SOCRATES: ETHICS.
THE SUBSTANCE OF THE TEACHING
not discourse concemSocrates, says Xenophon,' did
Uke most other philosophers
ing the nature of the All,
the essence ot
him; he did not enquire into

.HAP
Chap.
TO.'

TF^a.
mental

before

re.

tj^e

phenomena; on
world and the laws of natural
such
it folly to search into

f^'^lT"-^ the contrary,


ject-mat-

MMos.

g^ygg^g
.

he declared

quiz things divme


for it is unreasonable to
things human ; besides,

before f^ly understanding


philosophers prove
conflicting opinions of natural

the

research transcends the capathat the object of their


After all, these enqiuries
city of human knowledge.
Quite in keeping with this
are of no practical use.
Xenophon tests even geometry
view, the Socrates of
utility,
'
by the standard of immediate

and astronomy
as

respectively reqmsite tor


being the knowledge

surveying and navigation.

To

carry

them

fui-ther

a useless waste of time,,^


than this he considers to be
man can never come upon the
or even impious ; for
the
of the Gods, nor do
track of the mighty works
attempt such knowledge.
desire that he should

Gods
.

Mem.

i.

1,11.

Conf. p. 124,

1.

Ibid. iv. 7.

HIS TEACHING CONFINED TO ETHICS.


Hence

in

such attempts, extravagances such


as

all

those of Anaxagoras are sure to come to


view.^
The accuracy of this description of Socrates
has,
however, not passed unchallenged by

modern

Granting,

it is

these and

said, that Socrates really

similar sentiments, can

writers.^

expressed

they be right-

fully so understood as

though he would altogether


deprecate speculative enquiry into
nature ? Would
not such an assertion too manifestly
contradict his
o^vn fundamental view,
the idea of the oneness of all
knowledge

Would

it

not lead,

if

propounded

as

Xenophon has done, to consequences


manifestly unreasonable ?
Even Plato ^ bears testimony to
the

fact that Socrates did not


attack natural science in

but only the ordinary treatment


of it nor can
Xenophon himself conceal the fact that
he did devote

Itself,

his attention to nature,^


"'''

<,uplT-i" J^j;-" 'Tel:


'
YaVarr'

Ji t^^-^ia-rov

83
130

cppou-fjcra,

7^.w:/m

uescn.
&.fGeth
*

^^r

m";

rr P-'

inl

0^5^;,

t^s

tc5

'^:'

^^'''-

P-

^-'

\v

d'^'phiV'
Phil. n.
ii' 48,
ct.

f
^^^

'

^'^'

^nly lead to absurdities,

hoping by considering the

^"^'"''^

^^^^' ^'^ Wolken

Aristophanes,

Pha^do 96

Leg. xii 966

A*"'

97

p.

Pi

t?

'

^'^^XMa*, for these ao<po\\,evd


'^^^

^^

necessarily be the oarHer

r-^^p^^^i^^'p^--also
used of poets,

clironiclers,

''hap.
...
-

^^^^

SOCRATES.

13(5

relations of

Chap.

__XE:

means

to ends in nature to gain an in-

Allowing,
reasonable arrangement.
no
therefore, that Socrates, as was the fact, had
not
special talent for natural science, and hence did
into

sight

its

any great extent, at least the germ of a new


form of this science may be discovered in him. In
study

it to

his notion

of the

means

of

relation

ends in

to

the thought of a universal


whole of
diffusion of intelligence throughout the
of man
nature,' ' the theory of an absolute harlnony

nature must have lain

'

and nature, and of man's occupying such a position


V If he
in nature as to be a microcosm of the world.'
to
stopped at the germ, confining his study of nature
mere practical requirements, this must have been, ac-cording to his own opinion, only as a preliminary step.

He must

have only intended that

man

ought not to

reach into the distance until a critical foundation


inner
has been securely laid in the depths of his own
life

or else it

must have reference to popular and

not to philosophical study.^


Unfortunately this view of modern writers rests
on assumptions which cannot be supported. In the
first

place, not only

mention

to

Xenophon, but Aristotle also,3not

later writers,^ asserts that Socrates

it is expressly stated
their
that Socrates perused
works, in order to find in them
what was morally useful for
.^c,

Met.

and

cp^xreccs

SArjs

De

as though
Krische, 208,
Socrates made any distinction
l)etween training for a philosopher and training for a good

bpiaaaQai

man.

(987,

Se^ Trepl

irpayfiarevofievov,

himself and his friends.


ScJdeiermacher and Bitter.
'

i.

^(^Kpirovs

Part.

irept

ohe^u

Anim.

1.

eVl 2co/cpciToi;s be

tV

fi^v^

never

l)r
b,
ra 7,0tK*
5e
xiii.

ttjs

i;

(642, a, 28)

Tovrofiev [t^

ov<nav\ VHvSjl,

^d.

Cw^:v rh irepl <pj><rws eXv^e.


Conf Eth. Eud. i. 5 1^16, b, A
^
Cic. Tus v 4, 10; Acad.
De Fm,
iv. 29, 123
i. 4, 15
Sh

ms

TEACHING CONFINED TO ETHICS.

pursued the study of nature.

Aristotle

the very autliority called in


to arbitrate
phon and Plato differ. What
right
to

stand

aghast at his

declares against Plato

is,

IS

however,

when Xeno-

have we, then,


testimony as soon as he

Even

Plato, however, indi-

rectly admits

in the Timajus that


natural science
was foreign to Socrates. If
he elsewhere puts in
his

mouth sayings

referring to nature, there is

still

no evidence that these


utterances are historically
true.
Not even in the passage in the
Phsdo can
such evidence be found,
unless what follows that
Socrates had fallen back on
the theory of Ideas
can be taken to be historical.'
In one respect Xenophon fully agrees with Plato, in
saying that Socrates

demanded a consideration of the


ends in nature.
relation of

If it

is

relation of

means

to

further required that the

means

to ends should not be


understood
the lower sense of a later age,
in which it was

indeed
understood by Xenophon, but
that higher speculative
Ideas should be sought
therein, where, we ask, is the
historical justification of
this view ?
Lastly, if an
appeal is made to the logical
consequences of the
feocratic theory,

do they not prove that Socrates


must

have been quite in earnest in


disparaging a speculative study of nature, and
in his popular notion of the
relation of means to ends ?
Had he indeed placed
at the

head of his system, in this


xdea of the mutual dependence
of
Ep^71^7-' sw'
(Ml. N. A. xiv.

Lt?' ^""T
6,

S,

and, ac-

"'"'^'"S

explicit form, the


all

knowledge,

it

Demetrius of By-

Phsedo, 100,

Chap

SOCRATES.
Chap.
VII.

would be impossible to account for Ms low estimate


If, on the contrary, he was concerned,
of physics.
not about knowledge in general, but about the education and training of men by means of knowledge,
is it not very natural that his enquiries should be
exclusively directed to the conditions and activities
of man,i nature being only taken into account in as
far as it

was useful to

man ?

Doubtless this view of

the relation of means to ends was, for natural and


scientific enquiries, like a seed sown broadcast, which

sprang up and bore fruit in the systems of Plato and


but to Socrates himself this new departAristotle
ment of natural science presented itself only as a
;

subsidiary branch of ethical

enquiry, without his

in his
In this respect Socrates is necessary consequence,
witli
principles
intellectual
in
position
Kant's
Kant,
like
said
it
be
may
justice
same
the
history being also not unlike
notwithstanding
that,
Kant,
of
destroying
after
Kant,
As
his.
reason, he
the older Metaphysics, only his critic of pm'e
disputing the
whilst
must,
Socrates,
so
Ethics,
retained
aside natural Metaphysics of Wolff, have
after setting
that his prinscience, turned his attention necessarily seen
him consisexclusively to morals. In the ciples would lead
of Fichtc
Idealism
the
to
tently
the
other,
one case, as in the
philosophy of
one-sidedness with which the and the natural
whom, and
founder begins has been sup- Schelling both of
against
plemented by the disciples, and the first-named even
appealed
protests,
own
Kant's
the treatment at first adopted
consequences. For all
for Ethics has been extended to these
it
is
a dangerous business,
that,
to the whole of philosophy.
of logical
consideration
from
a
of
said
be
may
it
Just as
historical
the
and
consequences
Socrates, that, despite his so
principle, to correct
definitely attested declining of results of a
statements as to
clearest
the
all cosmical and theological
of its originator,
doctrine
the
he
principle,
speculation on
question really being,
nevertheless, whilst actually the
to what extent
refraining from such enquiries, whether and
realised these concould not conceal from himself the founder
that they were involved, as a sequences.

JUS TEACHING CONFINED TO ETHICS.


being conscious of

its

range.

applies only to Ethics.

tion of

l;J9

His conscious interest

Even the study

Chap.

^^^_

of the rela-

means

to ends in nature was, according to


his
view, subservient to a moral purpose
that of urging

his friends to piety.

It cannot be altogether neg-

lected in considering his teaching


;
nor yet can w(^
allow it, in the sense in which it
was used by Socrates,
an independent value, nor for this reason
prefer it to
Ethics.

The same remark

applies to theology, which here


coincides with natural science.
The motives
which deterred him from the one must
have deterred
him from the other also.^ If, notwithstanding,
still

he

expressed

definite

views

as

to

the Gods and the

worship of the G-ods, these views


were the outcome
of a practical love of piety.
Theology then can only
be treated by him as an appendix
to Ethics.

Even then, there are comparatively


very few
definite opinions in theology

home

to

could

it

Socrates

be

with

otherwise,

certainty.

considering

matic treatment of Ethics


basis either
rest

upon

iv'si'andT?*

Aentlem\
\ynrZf
^OCvMe^

aT65i/c/i;6.

^'
1

ovSe yap

Ta ro.au.a [or,^as

The
''

Indeed,
that

how
syste-

impossible without a
"^
metaphysics or psychology for it to

in

which can be brought

chief service which Socrates here

' ""'"'^

'^

'

,^.

^''ot^"^g*

'}^

'

-^.p]

it is

*is

rvs Tu>u

said^]5

He asked

wliethcr

^^^ fully mastered human


^^ ^^''^^^ advanced to
^^^'T^'^
'}^^^

such enquiries, ^ ri

u'ey iudocc-

aKoirodvres

rk

vyodura,

y.ro,a.on^. riel>ae^k,

iroocr-h

rhae^s

;:

SOCRATES.

140

rendered was a formal

Chap.
^'"-

onethat

of generally refer-

no sooner, however,
moral acts and
is it a question of deducing particular
himself
relations from knowledge, than he contents
or
partly with falling back upon prevailing custom,
ring moral action to knowledge

an accidental reference to pur-

else there intervenes

of which are certainly partially

poses, the defects

corrected in the sequel.


15.

The leading thought

n.

-^^y be expressed in the

leadvuii
"^

^Emcs:

^-g

.^j^

the

sentence

All

virtue

is

most closely connected


His efforts aim from
^I^Qlg ^,|g^^ of things.
it
at re-establishing morality and rooting
This assertion

knowledge.^

AlUiHnc
ledge.

of the ethics of Socrates

first

more deeply by means

is

The

of knowledge.

experi-

the conences of his time have convinced him that


it does
ventional probity of moral conduct, resting as
and authority, cannot hold its ground*

on custom

His sifting of

most

'iscovered, even in the

men

cele-

place
brated of his contemporaries,^ a pretended in

Arist. Eth. N. vi. 13

o-ets

1144,
(ppovv-

28: ScoKpciTTjs
^ro ^hai trdTas ras aperds
:ZwKpdT'ns fJi.y olv x6yovs

b, 17,

'

Ths 'aperhs <iiero dual, iirifTT-hficis


yhp dvai 'j.daas, Ibid. iii. 11;
Eth. End. i. 5 1216,
1116, b, 4
ehai -ndaas
iTTLar^fias c^er
b, 6
;

ehar

ayaQh.

Kal

ovdh

irpo\4(rdai,

eVto-TO^weVous

a\Xa Koi

oHf

hWo

radra d56ras

&*/

jobs

avrl rovrwP

ovre

5vvacr0o:

rovs

irparTeiv,

Vav e^X^'P^f '" a/xapra-

he always con16
versed of justice, piety, Kaljepi
rS^v dXK^v, h rovs fxev^ etSdras

''eiv.

i. 1,

rh.s

ap^rds,

^aO'

ffv[x^aivuu
ZiKaioa^^v-nu KaX
'diia

T6 T>tiv
Conf Ihid. iii. 1
dvai ZiKawv.
1229, a, 14; vii. 13; M. Mor.
1- 1182, a, 16; i. 35 ; 1198,
i
erSei/J

10

Xen.

Mem.

iii.

9,

koI
I^TJ 5^ Koi r^v diKuioaivw
(Tocpiav
dp^r^v
traaav
&XK'nv
rvv
ehat rd r yap Skaia Ka\ irdvTa
offa apcT^ KparreroLi Kohd re Kal
'

vy^^ro Ka\ohs Kai ayaQovs


to\js 8^

^v

elvoi,

h.-^voovvTas a/5pa7ro5S6

^inaio^s K^KK^crQai.

The

latter

Plato, Lach. 194, D..


iv. 2, 22.
iroXKdKis h.Ky\Koa a ov Mn/ovjosJri

Tavra ayadhs eKaaros w^p airep


^Sh ^fxad^s ravrade KUKds.
Euthyd. 278, E.
^9, !<..
^ piafo, Apol. 21, 0.

(ro<(>6s,

MOltAL VALVE OF

KNOWLEDGE

141

oi a genuine virtue. To
attain true morality
must seek he standard of action
in clear

knowledge.'

man

and certain

The

principle which has thus


dawned
upon him IS, however, only
understood in a narrow
and exclusive spirit.

Knowledge is for him not only


an indispensable condition
and a means to true
morality, but it is the
whole of
morality.

''""

Trr""^'

peTt
ect, but there
p

I totr.

'

is

""''

absolutely no

"'

Anstotle, to improve

only-

'''" '^^

Where

virtue im-

virtue at

all.

^"^

--Pl^tely
upon the Socratic doctrine
of

the point that without


right knowledge right
action ^
IS impossible, and
conversely, that wble
fnowTedg
exists, right action
follows as a matter
of course
the former because no
action or possession
is of any
use, unless it be
directed by intelligence
to a proper
object ^ the latter,
because everyone only
;
doesTi

See p. 113.
It is only in

'

'

Plato fEuth
B.; Meno, 87, C)^
d at
Socrates expressly takes
tMs

280,

ground.

Hence ^he

MoraHa

:Magna(i. 35; 1198, a,


10)
appear to have derived
the
corresponding- view but
it no?
only sounds very Ike
Socle^^^

^ut

it is

'3hon
;

also implied in Xeno.'


Socrates there (Mem iv

,26) explaining mole iSme-'


liately in connection
with sPlf
^owledge, that itaone
cin
ell us what we
need and

wW

ect...

ana

U^^^^^^

Slff^^.^'''''^'''''^^^''^^^ action.
^^''^^^ tliat

fZnl'A
-S^

]^^R

'

i^^^^f^^
afterwards it is
f;!^^
*^^' ^^'^^"^ ^^^ ^" '^-^-

--tntli^r,,
l1''^ and Pala-Dasdalus

m!dol^
t^,n

o p

'

'

'
1

^^^" ^^"^ed for


^T""'^
^^.f^^om. For this is

''and'^ ^^
'^'^
TcSl'.
eve ra'^t"^^^^

men

V^^^

^^^^^

^^'^^^

*^^^^ in

^^^"^^

its

kind of

^^ knowledge, in

IT]}^^^^''^'''^

""^^'
'"

llj^a!

^^e

term,

C -X
,

Chap.
VII.

;.

SOCJRATHS.

J^2

Chap.

YU.

of use to himself:
he believes he must do, what is
for this would" be
no one intentionally does wrong;
oneself intentionally unthe same thing as making
always the strongest
happy i^ knowledge is, therefore,
by passion.^
power in man, and cannot be overcome
does.
identical therewith, also
respect14,
iii.
9,
said,
^Vhat is
to
ing viTpa^ia in contrast
KpanffTov
is
it
evrvxia, that
knowimri)^evfj.a, also refers to
in
consists
euTrpa^ia
For
ledge.
cZ
uadSvra ti koL txeXer-hcravra
Euthydemns
TToielu, or as Plato's
eTrio-rfi^T?
281, A, explains it:
nse^of
teaches to make a right
KaTopBovffa
as
and
goods,
all
T7JJ/

irpa^Lv it

and

i.

expresses this view

1,

Phil. ii. a, 39) that


this refers in the first place to
the arguments of the Platonic
Socrates (see Meno, 77, B.

(Gr.-rom.

Prot. 345, D.

the same

more

how
he inherit the knowledge
?

see
4
elUras
above, p. 140,1; iw.6,6:
oUadai
Se a 56? TT0L7v oUi rivas

Mem.

Xeii.

SeTj/ (J.^

-n-oteTv

ras^h

olovr ai

Ibid.

^<^.

Ouk oXofiai,
rivas &\^a iroiouvOvk 670:7',
SeTv

radra

Ol5a- 8e

icb-T].

9,

iii.

and 11

Pla,to, Prot.

Tb
t

elj/a:

(T-novZaiovs

'yap

ris,

bvriuaovv,

ZUaios

(pV^^lv,

<pav\ovs'

ipur-hcreiev

fioihoiro

&v
BiKos, ovdels hv

TrSrepov

hai ^

More
T^v adiKiav.
definite are the remarks
14;
Eth. Nic. iii. 7; 1113, h,
1223, b,
conf. Eth. End. ii. 7
in-

'dxoiro

353, C),

asserted
iii. 9, 4

but that

by Xenoiv. 6,

6-

and by PUto, ApoL

(pOcipu

Dial,

de

'6

iravaofxai

driXov

'6ti

76 &Kcav

iav fxiQay

Conf

rroica.

justo, Schl. IHoff.

LaeH,

31.

ii.
3

Ka\

Plato, Prot. 352, C.


(To\

T0wvr6u

dp

oty-

auTTjs

rrepl

ri

[ttjs eVto-Tirj/xrjs] 5oKe?,

^ KaXdu re

iinffThlJ-t], Koi oJov &px^iy


T]
rod avepuTTOV hal i&virep yiyvuxncij
^vris rayaOa Koi to kok& fih^

eivai

Kparv6r}vai
'd\\'

ehai

riju

h.

<pp6vr\<nu

ti.v

t]

tfcav^J^

a\\'

KiXeir,,

iiriffr-hfJi-n

(txrre

jwrjSevos,

virh

&rra irpdmiv

^otiQeiv

rcf

then
affirmed with the consent of
(The further reasonSocrates.
ing is probably only Platonic.)

The

h.vdpuit(f',

358, C.
n
^
22 Arist. M. Mor. 1. 9
76J/6V0at
i<p>' W^v
OVK
Kodrvs e<p-n

rovro toe'7w 5e .
25, E.
TOffovrov KaKbv kK^v ttoiw, us <P]is
ravra iycv (toi oh ireidofxai,
(TV
MeA7)T6 . . . t 5e &Ka}V StaS)

11

3,

is

Mem.

2)liun,

question
Gr. ix. 122, puts the
Socrates
into the mouth of
rich inthe
of
.when speaking
Did
heritance of Alcibiades:

fioKap.

^KOOV

OuS'

TTOV-nphs

Brandis remarks with justice

^schines, too,
definitely,
Demetrius de Elocu. 297, Rhet.

to use it

ovZels

on the statement ws

kKblV

fvirpayi^a

produces

XenopJto/i,

evTvx^a.

6, 4,

3,

latter is

eiriffraArist. Eth. Nic. vii. 3


rives oTov re
ixivov ju-ev olv ov (pacri
:

ehai. IdKpareveffdai'].
iTTiffr-hfiris

ivoiiff-ns,

deivov ydp,

us

^T0

Eth.
SwKparrjs, &^^o ri Kparelv.
Eud. vii. 13 opQws rh :^uKpari:

k6v, Sti

ovUv

iffxvp'^'repov <ppovi\-

MORAL VALUE OF KNOWLEDGE.


As regards

that

virtue which

appears to

be

furthest

removed from knowledge, the


virtue of
bravery, he more especially
insisted upon it,
that in

he who knows the true nature


of an apparent danger and the means
of avoiding
all cases,

braver

it, is

than he

who has not such knowledge.^

concludes that

knowledge

virtue

entirely

is

and accordingly he defines

ticular virtues in such a way,


as to
sist

Hence he
dependent upon
the par-

all

make them

conm knowledge of some kind, their difference being*

determined by the difference of


their objects.

who knows what is right towards


God
who knows what is right towards

pious
just
Teus-

men.^

aW

'6ti

iwKTTrjfx-nv

e(f>7],

ovK opeSu, aper}} ydp icrri


Kal ovK
iiriaTrjfiT}.
If, therefore, anyone seems to act contrary to
his better judgment,
Socrates
does not allow that is really

the case.
contrary.

He

rather infers the

His conduct being


opposed to right reason, he
concludes that he is wanting
in this quality

Mem.

'-po<Tepu}Tci,fj.euos Se, et

f.(vovs^ fieu

ras

56

iii. d,

robs

& Se? irpdrTeiv,

ravavTia,

iiriffra-

iroiovu-

ao(povs re

koX

hKpaT7s eluai vofj.i(oi


owSeV 76
f^aWov, ^-q ^ a.76<povs re Kal
aicpaTfTs. In Xenophon,
indeed,
tins IS so put, as if
Socrates
iiad admitted the
possibility of
a case of knowing right
and

doing wrong.
The real meanof the answer, however,
can only be the one
given
inj?

above.

He

is

he

is

He

is

points ovToi roi^ y^


e^ufi^vovs
raSe avri\4^eiu hi o'h^ai,
ds ovxl
:

Kai

7)

auSpda

Prot. 341), E.,


by_ various

SiSafcroV.

where

it is

Plato

proved

examples divers

kniglits, peltasti^ that


ol eV*Tiiv fx^
^'^^I'oyes
liTiaraixht^v
Oa^pa\(iTpoi daiv.
Az-ist Eth

Nic.

iii.

11;

1116, b, H:'5oK.?
^ Trepi '^Karrra
avSpeia ris duai
Hd^v Kal 6 2-

de

/coi

7]

ifiTreipia

Kpar-qs

c^-f^dr}

auSpeiap.

dvai r^v
Conf. Eth. Eud. iii 1
iri(rT'fifM'r]v

1221), a, 14.
- (bae^^s =
6 rh. wepl robs deobs
vd^i^iaelUs- 5lKaios = 6 el8ci>s

rit

Tovs avepdjTTovs v6^iixa.

Trpl

Mem

the definition of which


is here
given, is the same as the
SaiSTm
the conception of

sought in Plato's
If,

therefore,

which is
Euthyphro.

Grofe,

Plato,

i.

remarks a propos of the


latter,
that Xenophon's Socrates was neither asking
after
^28,

^'^'^' "^- ^' 2;


9 ',.^''t

Symp.

IS

sword

-, IL: Socrates remarks, in


reference to a dancing girl wh()

deliberating

about

the general conception


of the
nor indeed could pre-sup-

iioly,

Chap.

vn.

'

SOCRATES.

144

Chap.
VII.

how

brave who knows

he
is

to treat dangers properly

prudent and wise who knows how to use what


evil.^
good and noble, and how to avoid what is
is

or knowIn a word, all virtues are referred to wisdom


The ordinary
ledge, which are one and the same.^
virtue is incornotion that there are many kinds of

Virtue

rect.

pose it, liis observation is


contradicted by appearances.
follow
It does not, however,
wished
Socrates
that
herefrom
the Gods to be honoured v6ixw
Why could he not
irdKeois.
have said, piety or holiness
consists in the knowledo^e of
that which is ri^ht towards the
Gods, and to this belongs, in
respect of the honouring of
God, that each one pray to them
after the custom of his country.

not the same


thing as worship. That may
remain the same when the
forms of worship are different.

A pious mind

Xe)>.

is

Mem.

iv.

iirKTrafMCfoi

&pa

fi,

toTs

11

oj fx^v

deivo7s

re

xpffQai
Kol iiriKivdvi/oLS KaKu>s
hiafxapTavovres
5e
ol
elaiv,
dfSpeToi

TovTov
D. 71
:

fx^

SetXoi.
(ro<pia

beivccv

Pkito, Prot. 360,


&pa ruv 5e7v(av koI

a/'Speia

same thing

is

iffriv.

The

conveyed by the

definition' in Laches, 194, E.


(which is not much imperilled
by the objections raised thereto
from a Socratic point of view).

Courage

is

rj

rwv

Scluuv

koI

only Bapparendered
\4os must not be
*bold' (as ScJiaarschmidl,^am.m\.

ea^paXiwv

imar-hfJi.V

Nor does the

in truth but one.^

is

It
d. plat. Schr. 409, does).
means rather, according to
198, B., as it so often does, & fi-n

5eos

Conf.

Trape'xet.

Bouit:,

441.
2 Mem. iii. 9, 4
(rocpiau 5e koI
(ru(ppoTvvnv ov SiwpiCev, aWa tuv

Plat. Stud.

iii.

TO. fXu

Ka\d re kol ayada

yiyvo}-

(TKOvra XPT/O'Sat auro7s Koi rhv ra.


aiVxpa 6t5oTa evKa^eiffQai ffo<p6v

re KOL (Tiicppova eKpive.


:Mem. iv. 6, 7 iTrKTr-hM
'^

&f>"-

No
man can know everything, t &pa
(Tocpia

iariu

'Eixoiye SoKei.

eKaarosrovro Koi ao(p6s

iiriararai
eariv.

Plato developes this thought


earlier writings, Prot.
his
in
360, E.
349, B.
329, B.
*

kept much
which,
more closely to the platform

however,

of Socrates

it is

also evidently

His
contained in Xenophon.
gathered
be
may
as
meaning,

from Mem. iii. 9, 4, is certainly


not some one may possess the
knowledge in which one virtue
:

consists,'

whilst

lacking

the

knowledge in which another


consists but he assumes, just
;

as Plato's Socrates does in tlic


Protagoras, that where one
virtue is, all must be there, all
depending on the knowledge of

the good. From this doctrine


of Socrates the Cynic and Megarian notions of the oneness
of virtue arose.

MORAL VALVE OF KNOWLEDGE.

145

difference between
one person

and another, one time


''"; ""-^ ^^^ ^"'^ -*'>-' affect tTe
question
For mall cases it is
one and the same
thing, which makes
the conduct virtuous,'
and inTu
persons the same natural
capacity for vir ue
be
assumed to exist.^ The
main nnint fi,

11 r

1"

i^

to

eWte

this

disposrn

may

^^^^

bring with them more,


others fewer gift for
anv
particular activity
yet all alike require
;
exercS an J

Serobll"t:;~:Xdge tr^- ^^^-Wledge, nothing can inTmlTpr


oHLT
more
the

urgently necessaiy than


self-kno'wledge toipe
unfounded semblance of
knowledge and Vl

toman hiswants and


edge, just as
'

Plato,

needs.

wrong action

Meno,

71,

i^r^

llowmg- the passao-e


in Plato
216, a, 20,

>mo
^th

way
the

which he must in
have harmonised
Socratic

teaching

X ^ a^T^ ^cc^poo-^.^

y,,iX

7P ^,...0. a4.'.;
'fet,ovuT,srhs6.p,Tds.
^^

'Pf^,

^aUAAo.s

Eigh^Srn ac

5^A..,

'ol

TafeV

o.Se^ xe/pc^ rijs


rov ^u8phs
'^-r^xd.u, f>^^r^, sh Kal
r*s

,vX

follows

^I

/d

from absence of

x ...

^'m^^
iv 2 2

virtno
re u?t

V;.

fnIS*'t^

1' 3;
question whether
^'

"^^^

Ji.^

^i

^^'""'-^^

'''

^^'

^ ^

*^^^^i^gh discussion

thank^ to ^tb "^ ^^^^ussion,


tbo^ni. ..^^ appeaiance of
''"'^.

Pindar L;i'

!'
and
^^3^^^^^^^^

"' ^^^^ ^^^^^-

^.^^^'^'^n
:ifts.

natural
See above.

'

Chap.

vn.

SOCRATES.
fail,

himself will, without

knowledge he who knows


r:h:tfshealthful>stashewhoisignorant^^^^^^^^
Only the
is harmful.'
without fail, do what
;

Chap.
VII.

self will

knowledge can do anything


as the
In short, knowledge
useful and esteemed.^
knowledg^ rs the
action.; want of
moral
all
of
root
wrttmgly to
and were it possible
vice;
every
of
cause
wrong uuwrtbetter than doing
wrong, that were
of ngh

^lol

f^^^^^Z

'

r
Wrtor

the first condition


in the latter case
wanting whilst inthe
moral sentiment, is
only faiththere, the doer being
case it would be
What, however, the knowthe moment.^

IS'the
tme
Srilf"
I

For examwhich
conversations,

Mem.

ples of

iv. 2, 24.

to bring
Socrates endeavoured
of
to a knowledp
m.
Hem.
^
see
themselves,

Srlnds

accuser

^''^'Mem i. 2, 52 the
with inducing
charged Socrates
t
:

to

followers to despise
tor ne
friends and relations

Ms

AtjXoJ/
.'^auar^v oT5ev, ^ b &Ko:u
5e L4>?'^
AiKaiSrepoP
'6ti dlKcl^v.
^mcrra^x^vov to Z^KaiO.
ehai-] rhv

Sclared,thoseonlyd^^^^^^^
who can make
to be honoured
useful by means of
themselves
theS knowledge.

*-.o^cu.
e..aT^M-ov
rov
in.
382,
u.
Eep.
Plato,
Cont.
53.o,
vii.
C.
iv. 459,
S89 B.
It is
E 7 Hipp. Min. 371, E. to supcase
an imaginary

Xenoi^ion

only
can knowpose that any one
do
intentionally
ino-lv and
according
for
wrong;
is

what

of
to the principles
to
impossible
is
it

bocrates,

conceive

possesses
should, bj
such
as
knowledge
d(
virtue of his knowledge,
what is right, o

man who

that the

showed how
ignorant
and
TittlT useless
their
were esteemed by
anvthins but
relatives :biit
spontane
and
^Tfoiends
that anV one should
not
did
Socrates
wrong
is
that
what
h^savs
them ouslv choose

Inows

that

he

We

teach
thereby intend to
dependants, but
despise
to
that understand-

onlyto^show
aimed
ing must be^
"^'

Mem

iv.

2,

19

at,cir:

ro

to^v 5e 5,

an untruth i
intention
told knowingly and
apparer
an
be
only
can
it
allv,
whic
untruth,
and seeming
t

If

therefore,

allows as a means
n
higher ends (Rep. ii. 382
where?
C),
459,
iv.
B89, B.
on
want of knowledge is the
lie beir
proper
a
lie,
proper
Plato

question is after
^ b Lu>v The
-rk S.^a.a
settled
lards thus
;

ms
ledge

THEORY ABOUT THE GOOD.

I47

in which virtue
consists, whether
experime-.
alor speculative, purely
theoretical orpractiXia
quest:on upon which
Socrates has not entered.
In
Xenophon at least he
places learning and
exercise
is

gu.shed them,^ and to


prove that virtue
consists in
knowkdge, that it requires
knowledge, and
a
qu>red by instruction,
he chooses by preference
evel
the pages of Plato,
examples

^"1

CiJAP.

vu.

of practical ac uTre-

ments and of mechanical


dexterity.'
As yet, however, all that

has been laid down


is in c w
he nature of a formal
definition. All virtue
", ^^oTa.,
is kn"
ledge, but of what
is it the knowledge ?
To this
if'"^-

He ts
what

""'^*^''' '^""^'^^'g^
of thegood.
!virtuous, ^'''''''
just, brave, and so
forth, who knows
rs good and
right.^
Even this

addition

de and indefinite as those


always unintentional
382; V. 535, E. lee
Phil. Stud. p. 152.
'

At the

Meno.
'

Mem.

beffinnino-

iii. 9,

1,

TJpr,

ii

of
""^

^^''^^Y^^
t?

and

generally required,

"o /difference

proof of which it
may bo
^otod that no
natio^

o.p

IZ'

'

'

^^^'^

i, \^

i"""

biit

made

^^'"^"

are

even
be-

^'re

in spinnir.o,
^"^^^^'e*^

^s

^i-

^y ^^'^^m-Il,
a
1/'^^*' '' ^- ^^^'^r
1

^v-rist. J

t 2

Mem.

"^^'^ ^^^'^

^-^f^^^^on,

un

is

In

TraiSeia

'^^"^' ^"d athletics,


^^^^e it th.nr

T women
Tf
?Z''f 2^T^

with
en

mastery.

'

'n

^ounter those wh6


are familiar
ri^l'them.
So, too, in eve
y.
-^
nniir else it i! ti,L ^
'f

^ifts are really do-

^^^f%^
^' *^'/^'?'^*s

ih^
^^^

power

weapons to which it
is
accustomed ventures
to

Knowledge which

^^J'J
^^'''

Socrates an

as various as is
bodily

before.

isT

46.

(1)

r,.

f'^^T'

^^X-

SOCRATES.
148

OH.P.
"ll
-

virtue, is

makes

the ffood'

e?ed

as

knowledge of the good

whaUs

but

of a thing

conception
The good is the
.hat is good, is acting
an end.' Doing

uj>

action
of the corresponding
to the conception
The
application.
in its practical
short, knowledge
explained by
is therefore not
ten'ce of moral action
of the
that it is a knowledge
the general definition,
so forth.
good! the right, and
advance
^;i^-l''^llZt
Socrates did not
definition, however,

philoso^y

Just as his speculative


the general
stopped short with
^^^^-^^^t.X;;ly:
to

h
,

pMlo^ophy.

---P^--

knowledge belonged

^J^ ^

indefinite
short with the
ticM Tjhilosophy stopped
conformable to concepUons.

tllatcLduct

Clch

a theory

it is

impossible to deduce defin-

^-^-^""^hiT:\orf;;t:misi:

to louirv iv^
QUprnative remains but
the necessary princieither by adopting
^

ieTway,
;t%rom^he

prevailing

m.a^-^^^^^^

rhtxir-rk^iedjr---^^^^^^
and to

to experience
thought, by a reference
of actions.
well-known consequences
courses were followed
matter of fact both
explained the
On the one hand he
*?<?4 ; by S crates.
The
of the lawful.
the right by that

aH

Sif
cither hy
custom or

'Utmty.

inception of

...

Mem.

iv.

?,

^^

*/.

8^

A;^'J^

olaQa,

ecpv,

oiro.o,

'^^^'^'*'^. .

,,,

In

Mem.

IV 4

oi;

crates says:

<;>rjf<.i

7P

2
^7"'

SfKaioj; etrnt,

^(^jt.t/xoi/

Hrppias asks for


as to

^ mation

So-

crat^es

^^^.

and when

f urther

what

IS

mfor-

meant by

.^,^^^ ,^^ ,^^^^^. ^^.

APPEAL TO CUSTOM AND UTILITY.


best service of God, he says,

with custom

and he

will not

from an unjust sentence,

lest

On

laws.^

that which agrees

is

the other hand, as a necessaiy


consequence of this view of things,
he could not be content with existing moral
sanctions,

but was

fain to

seek an intellectual basis


for morality.
This he
could only take from a
consideration of consequences
and
so doing he frequently
proceeds most superhcally, deriving his ethical
principles by a line of

argument, which taken by itself


differs in results
more than in principles, from
the moral philosophy
oftheSophists.3 When asked
whether there could
be a good, which is not
good for a definite purpose,
he distinctly stated that he
neitlier knew, nor desired
to knov of such a one ^
everything is good and beau:

Sip z.:x t:^z '^:i:^ --> ".r:X.:r^lTi.fj;


'

^Oas

Mem

'van

'At,

V
a

2,.

ciple is attrihutea

^'Seep. 77,

/,Tv.

ifi

^^

T
/,

^^^

withTS'

it is

J"J',

statement^

l^P^f^T^iTTTrosj

Ka\a re

Kal

^.t ^t^ttS ^^^


f^^

Philosophia Mor. Socr.


Orote
:Hist. of
Greece viii fiott
agrees

where
'l^^^^^Z%
amongst other things

ToL

^""'^

7T^

^
?
^''^^^'

Ch^p

withdraw himself even _


he should violate the

are the

^
'I

^^^^ ^

'^^^

same), but

"^"
'^''

^---

^'

'''''''

'^i

<

SOCRATES.

,gQ

it subthe special needs which


and the same thing may be
serves, and therefore one
He declared
for another.

tiful in relation to

CHAP,

V"-

one and bad


that the good is nothing
a manner most pronounced,
the beautiful nothing else
else but the advantageous,
therefore is good and
but the useful ; everything
which it_ is
to the objects for

<.ood for

beautiful in relation
confirming his doctrine
advantageous and useful;'
of evil-one of the leadmg |
of the involuntary nature
remark that everyone
principles of his ethics-bythe
for himself.
which he thinks advantageous
, does that
to his view no absoThere is, therefore, according
and disadrelative good ; advantage
\ lute, but only a
Hence
of good and evil.'
vantage are the measures
Xenophon he almost always bases .
in the dialogues of
e 1
utihty.
precepts on the motive of
, his moral
because the abstinent man
should aim at abstinence,
than the incontinent: we
has a more pleasant life
because the hardy
inure ouselves to hardships,

.hould

can more
more healthy, and because he
honour and glory
avoid dangers, and gain

man

easily

is

we

found in Plato's

con..Sp,^,.'X..a.i.ae^.
eluding:

thing similar

"T

importance can be attached to


as
the treatment of happiness

Xen. Mem.
'''"

ir.

8.

6,

LlxiH/r;
"'''^^"J^T'

xp^cri^ov apa

.pb.1

Symp.

Plato, irot.

5,

6;

6,

3;

"fl.

and afterwards explains


good to be that which affords
pleasure or averts pam.

Joes,

xen. Mem.

iii. 9,

some-

is

^*Si"the 'ott^" hand,

xue

'^

Mem.

iv.^5

little

philoso-

i.

5,

n.

i,

9.
ii.

i. b.
confff^'
.

1,

18

'

INCONSISTENCY OF SOCRATIC J^^ORALITF,

should be modest, because


boasting does harm and
brings disgrace.
We should be on good terms with
our relatives, because it is
absurd to use for

Chip

_J^

>

harm

what has been given us for our


good;^ we should
try to secure good friends,
since a good friend is the
most useful possession 3 we
should not withdraw
from public affairs, since the
well-being of the community is the well-being of
'
:

the individual ;
we
should obey the laws, since
obedience is productive of
the greatest good to ourselves
and to the state; and
we should abstain from wrong,

wrong is always
should live virtuously,
since

punished in the end.^

We

because virtue carries off the


greatest rewards both
from God and man. To
argue that all such-like
expressions do not contain
the personal conviction
of the philosopher, but
are intended to bring those
to virtue by meeting
them on their own ground

who cannot be got

by higher motives,

at

laboured, considering

the definiteness

bocrates expresses himself.^

phon

evidently

is

with which

Unless, therefore,

Xeno-

misleading on essential points,


we must
allow that Socrates was in
earnest in explaining the
good as the useful, and
consequently in the corresponding derivation of moral
is

duties.

True

it

is

utterances are
'

-'

^^
:

Mem.

i.

that in the

met

mouth of Socrates other


with, leading us beyond this
suner"

7.

Ibid. ii. 3, 19.


Ib.d. ,,.4,
5; u. 6, 4
Ibid.

iii. 7.

ii. 1,

and

'

iii.

o^
^^l^""^^ an ex-

tract fmn,''
dicus, the substance

taTt

14.

Mb,d..v.4,land20;

at o^

^ofwhih

appropriates.

^%p ^^ ^^

quently discussed.

Conf.

i.

,, ,,^^.

(3) j..
'"''^'-

tency of
Soeratic

Momlify.

SOCRATES.

J59

CHAP.

_ZL__

essential
ground of moral duties, by placing the
it serves and
advantage of virtue, the purpose which

ficial

good and beautiful in its inMost unof man.^


fluence on the intellectual life
be the view of
doubtedly and decidedly would this

because of which

Socrates could

it is

we

attribute to

him the maxim

so

that righteousness
familiar to the Socrates of Plato,^
disease of the soul, and
is health, unrighteousness
invariably injures
consequently that all wrong-doing
and
does it, whereas the right is necessarily

him who

always useful.

Language

of this kind occurring in

not justify our bethe Republic and Oorgias does


the
In these dialogues much is put into
lieving it.
never can
mouth of Socrates, which he never said and

have

said.

Nor can

it

be pleaded that Plato would

conceptions, unless
never have held such pine moral
them from his teacher. Otherwise the|

he had had

theory of ideas and

much

besides which

is

found in

We
to Socrates.
Plato would have to be attributed
contained in
cannot even vouch for it that everything
author not having
the Crito comes from Socrates, its
it describes.
been present at the conversation which
committed to
the death of Socrates, and

Having apparently, however, been


writing no long time after
not going beyond his point of view,

it is

noteworthy

same principles
that this dialogue contains the
>

On what

follows compare

RiUing, p. 83, 91, 105, whose


researches are here thankfiilly
Icknowledcred, whilst all his
c

Sion? are not accepted.

See Z.Z/^r-.Phil.d.Griech.
p. 561 of second edition.
2

^
:

as in the
^
Crito 47 D
treatment of the body, the
physicians advice must be
:

questions of
followed, so
^d vi.e
wrong
and
right
J^^e

him

a.

e.

^t, ^ a/coAo.07,(ro^ej,

^ia<pQ^povti.v .kuvo koX Ki,^D<r6-

'

INCOmiSTENCr OF SOCRATIC MOItALITY.

153

circumstance which at least shows


that they have a
support
the teaching of Socrates.
To the same effect
lilcewise the Apology
expresses itself,

Chap

_^"-

Socrates therein

summing up

the purpose of his

life as that of convincing his fellow-citizens


that the education of the.

soul

IS more important
than money or property
honour or glory ; declaring
at the same time in
plainest terms, that
whether death is an ill or not
he knows not, but that
injustice is, he knows
>

'

well.^

Similar language is found in


Xenophon.
pages too Socrates declares

In his

the soul to be the most


the divine part of his
beine

valuable thing in man,


because it is the seat of
able IS of value.^
ftrst

He

reason and only the Eeasonrequires, therefore, that


the

care should be for the


soul.^

He

convinced

is

^^L % %^i^: ^-^:~' ^^


moreover,
If,

life in

body has no value

oou

a diseased

'

^er' iKeiuou

than that 49, A


wrono3oing always in/ures 'aiTd
d^f

?rac?s

him'who JomLit

AeV;/

oF^Trep ''ccda

aj/dpa;;/
I

" ovK

aiaxvi^ei

i
'

^^^>

"

thT^fac^'^rh:?"'

'6ri

^J'

xpVf^aTwu

Imnn

^"^

Mem

'"'^.'''""''

^m

m^

i.

53 and

" T''^ ^^

J'^'^P^lou

tov Odov uere'vet


*
i
9

f^

:hireTwLTce"

'

iq

.-^-

*^^^^^^t Sn rh

it

imfie\o6/jLeuos,

ould rather blame

-ry case

^f'J9(r^,

kk

Ibid 29

Mem

-^

ye x^vxh,

+.xfls imi.4Kav

"te'^Sr'ihf^

'>^?'"^'?^

SOCRATES.
Chap.

^^-

more you aim at the^


the more
education of the soul, and more enjoyable,
perfecyou are conscious thereof.^ The intellectual
on his knowtion of man depending in the first place
wisdom is the highest good, without compare

that conduct

is

better, the

ledge,

more valuable than ought besides.^ Learning


but
recommended not only on account of its utility,
which it directly
far more because of the enjoyment
These expressions fully agree with what
is

confers.^

has been quoted from Plato


consistent in a philosopher

they also appear quite


who bases the whole of

and so
moral conduct so decidedly upon knowledge,
and to dealing
expressly leads man to knowledge of
with

self, as

Socrates does.^

in which
A\^at then must be made of accounts
entirely on grounds
Socrates recommends moral duties
purpose, such as we freof outward adaptation to a
Are we to assume that
in Xenophon?

quently find
only intended for those who
all such explanations are
sage's real meanwere too unripe to understand the
hypothesis of the ordiing, to show that even on the
purpose, virtuous
nary unsatisfactory definition of

mcomisTJs^cr of sochatic morality.

154

conduct

is the best ?
that Xenophon took
these
preliminary and introductory
discussions for the
whole of the Socratic philosophy
of life, and hence
drew a picture of the
latter, representing,

it

true, his

own but not the platform of


the

Ch.p

^U.'

is

real SoThis view has no doubt its


truth, but it is
bardly the whole truth.
We can readily believe that
Xenophon found the more
tangible foundation for
noral precepts which
judges them by their conseluences both clearer and
more intelligible than the
leeper one which regards
their working on the
inner
ondition of man.
We naturally, therefore, expect
IS
description to give the
preference to this
crates ?

'-itelligible

'
.
st

le

T.."""'!
of
the other;

explanation even at the

and to throw the other


more into
backgi-ound than the actual
state of

the case
must, therefore, allow
double value
such Socratic utterances
as he reports implying
deeper moral life.
We cannot, however, consider
m so bad a guide as to report
utterances which
)crates never expressed,
nor can we give to
these
terances a meaning by
means of which they can
brought into full accord
with Plato's description

We

arrants.

'

>

the Socratic ethics.

Take
lere

for instance the


dialogues

Socrates

is

with Aristippus,^
asked to point out a thing
good,

**"V.
it^S'
ff vf
htud. ^^116
Volqmrd-

lat.

I.

Mem.

iii. 8.

'

SOCRATES.

jgg
CHAP,
^11'

and both times


and afterwards a thing beautiful,
nothing
consist
answers that goodness and beairty

certain purposes.'
else save a subserviency to

^^

hat

withhold his own


inducement had Socrates here t
of the unripe unopinion? Was Aristippus one

condition to understand
philosophic heads, not in a
Plate
Was he not rather in addition to
his views?
independent and mteland Euclid one of the most
thinkers in the Socratu
lectually best educated
Why should Socrates say to him everything
circle ?
bears
for that to which it
is good and beautiful
:

rela
and hence the same thing may
h
another an evil ?
tion to one be a good, to
there is which is alway
does he not add one thing
which improves th
and unconditionally good, that
Xenophon omit
Or did he add it, and
souP
otto
^
was this so
although the main point ? and
We could only be justified in such a
cases?'

o-ood relation,

assumption, were

it

shown that Socrates could

n.

makes him spea

Xenophon
possibly have spoken as
cannot possibly have had tl
or that his utterances
Xenophoi
they have according to
meaning, which

not sufficient to appe


account; * to prove which it is
which Socrates is otherw.
to the contradiction with
contradiction to ci
charged. ( It is certainly a
tii
life, and at the same
virtue the highest end of
advantages itbrmgs
it because of the
to

recommend
.

""

E:^.^"Sh'n"70.''

'

What

Brandis

has

wen, and that he

el

'INCONSISTENCY OF SOCRATIC MORALITY.

md
t.^

Plato recognising this


contradiction has avoided
Still the question really
is, whether

and to what

extent

Socrates has

avoided

ustify our assuming,


that
)een involved in it.^

liction

he cannot possibly have

For

Kant

and nothing can

it,

is

there not

rejecting most

a contradecidedly for the

aoral estimate of our


actions every standard based

Hows

happiness in its ordiary sense a


place amonglings relatively good.
The
rmer statement 'is in

Mem.

but this distinction


'en by a decided
advocate
Eudfemonism, such as Arisppus, could be admitted,
asi.

9,

14

mmg

that true and lastingis to be attained not


the uncertain favour
of

ppmess

ance, but
-'Y

at

by one's own actiand understanding, and


man must not make himdependent on extreme

cumstances, but ensure a


ting enjoyment of life
by
ing superior to himself
and
surroundings. If Brandis

atw.

237) declares

i.

possible,

this

he need simply be

arred to the fact that in


the

^naic and Epicurean schools


h views are actually
met
h.
See below, ch. xiv. B,

and

Zeller's
Stoics, Epi3ans, &c., p. 44. For
the lat-

statement Brandis appeals


^em. iv.2,34. Here Euthylus has to
be convinced
his ignorance in
respect

good

and evil. After it


been proved that all thino-s
iidcred

by Eutliydemus

goods,

under

to

wisdom included,
certain

circum-

stances,

be

on

disadvantageous,

Euthydemus

says
Kiv^vv^iu
avafx<pL\oyd}Tarov ayaOhv dvai
t5
:

(vSai^oueTv, to which
Socrates
replies
e^ y, f,-fj ^s airh
e'|
a^<piK6y(cv ayadwv (TupTiedr],
or
as it is immediately
:

explained,
7 fx-q Trpoa-eija-ofieu avrcf kcHWos
fj
KTXvv ^ irXodTOv
56^au ^ Kai
ri
aWo Tuv toiovtwv, since
among all these things there
is none which is not
the source
of much evil. Far from
e<

-f)

mg,

deny,

this proceeds

on the distinct understanding


that hap-

piness

the highest good


ethi^cs invariablv
presuppose neither is it called
simply an afi(f>i\oyou ayadhv
except in the case that it is
comis

which Greek
;

pounded

of afi<t>i\oya ^yaSa, i.e


of such things as mider
certain

circumstances lead to evil, and


are not simply ^.yadh, but
some-

times KaKi. Still less is


this
statement at variance
with
passages which estimate
the
value of every thing
and of
every action by its
consequences, a standard beinothe
very thing which
SocratSs is
here laying down.
As riato has already remarked, Rep. ii. 362, E.
PhcTdo
J^ii'tuo,
68 D.
^

'

167
Chap.
Yll.

SOCRATES.

J58
CHAP,

_I^

deciding the question as


experience, and afterwards
unisuited to the principle of
to what maxims are
the consequences
legislation, having regard to
versal'

universally adopted
which would follow were they
contradiction in the same writer, at
Is there not a
outrance against Eudtemoone time waging war a
the belief in the existnc<
nism, at another founding

of

God on

the

to

worth?

Is

asserting the
\

"^

'.

at the

demand

a bliss

for

corresponding

reason, ii
not the critic of pure
anc
independent existence of a thing

denying that
same time unconditionally

it ca,

contradiction so blatant

be known, entangled in a
opinion that if it real!
that Fichte was of the
existence of a thing, h
assumed the independent

a strange coir

work of
would rather regard it as the
Can the historia
cadence, than of human brains?
sa
the philosopher of Konigsberg

make

therefore

what he did not say

Can he

violently set asid

instead of explaimng them


these contradictions
that the same thm
would it be so inconceivable

And

doctrine ? The phil<


should be true of the Socratic
conduct upon knowledg
sopher wishes to build moral
conception of knowledge
In point of form his

includes besides philosophic


so indefinite, that it
skill derived from e
convictions, every kind of

In point of matter

perience.'

similar indetimteness.
tical

what is

Cont

r,

from

subject matter of pra

is

147

suffers

the u.
the good, and the good is
But
the same thing the expedient.^

knowledge

f d, or

The

it

149, 4

and

2.

good o
Tlie identity of the
presappo:
the useful is also

i^co3,sisrs^-cr

of sochatic morality.

]o9

what

this consists,
Socrates according
to all accounts
has no expressed
with sufficient

pLsion

all

ambig-uity in his pfhiVc


from whiJh we can

avot

IttrT;

of History,
ot
historv

to

^ ^^^*

^"""T'
^'''''

^ ^^"^ S-ates
^
wTh sonae
with
certainty, he does
not even ^o
''"P'*""' ''"^

""^
eSr all h
"''"'^^
nate
natetndl
and iinal^ purpose is
^0

''^^

*'^'

*''

^-"-

Still

their ulti-

impossible for his


unsvste

naticand casual ethical


theories, nnsuppor
ed bTlnv'
omprehensive psychological
research.
other
nds having to do
with man's well-being

Vnce

ntt

^^^"^""^

portThatXhT '"'""'

-depenUy

P"-P^' '-"^d moral


appears as a means
towards
'""'"'as attaining
,iu^w.l
leseends.'
,.
If (,hprpfi^v<>
'
+ J. "^'^^-^e'^op'^on reports a number
<?
Socratic
dialogues in which
thing are so^pr
-tivity
^tivitv Itself
i t,f

tHe feocratic basis


of '^LJiicb,
ethics
hui
w^ have
i.
out we
^^^
no
to question the
accnmp^
^f
^
of his description,
^^^"^^^J
PDorterl as
n n>t is i.
pported
by many traces in
Plato, nor yet to
lust

yhi?lit

re only the

^y

beginnings of dialogues
the renl

on the contrary

is

vouched

;epion of tl.e useful


s
ewliat extended
tliere.
Compare the sound
remarks
^rnmpell, Gesch. d
Prak-t
.

:
'

r. 138, resuitin^lln
bocrates made no

^^-

such

for

nK.'

by the circum-

*o
i^S th/'""^"^^^ T'^'''
belonging to
'-^^

^'x

virtue.

otler .ood
r.i

f'''''^

'^^

/^^'

^-^^^

'a"

for the

''^^^^
^^X^'t'"^ T''^'^^''
"'"^^^

expedient

^'

^^^

<

Chap.

vn.

SOCRATES.

160
Chap.
VII.

side
the Socratic schools side by
and the criticism of
with the morals of the Cynics
found too for the Cyrenaie
the Megarians, a place was
that the founders of these
doctrine of pleasure ; and
were firmly persuaded that
schools to all appearance
Socratic teachreproduced the true spirit of the

Stance,' that

among

they

this

no foothold,
that teaching afforded them
In
phenomenon would be hard to understand.

its

essence

ing.

Had

selfish

the

Socratic

morality

is

anything but

prevent its
fact does not, however,
theoretical
form of Eudaemonism in its

That

assuming the

not complain of it as wanting


as wanting in philosophicin moral content, but
explanation.

We do

precision.
D. FarticuXar

moral

re-

of moral actions was


give a systematic account
His views
of Socrates.
not a part of the intention

To

lations.

To which Hermann, Plat. i.


attention.
257, rightly draws
writer
this
however,
When,
^

of utility
finds in the principle

(Ibid. p. 254 Ges. Abh. 232)


call it
or as he prefers to
predominence of relative

found in
(iii. 8, 4-7;
Memorabilia
the
in
10,12; iv. 6,9; 2, 13), nor
Plato
of
(p.
Major
the Hippias

trine neither to be

latter by the way a


It if
very doubtful authority.

288)the

indeed stated in these passages^,


the
beautithat the good and the
point
value not merely a weak
beautifa
and
good
only
are
Socrates, ful
in the philosophy of
by virtue
an in- for certain purposes
time
same
the
at
but
ever]
that
not
but
use,
one of their
stance of Socratic modesty,
of these attribute;
application
wherein
feels inclined to ask,
only a relativ(
consist/ to a subject has
does this modesty
no circum
Under
validity.
And when he connects here- stances would the passag'
with the more general doctrine, authorise a distinction betwe^ei
the
constituting in his view
bo
Socratic and the
bo- the
the
between
main difEerence
one of tii
philosophy
phistic
Sophiscratic dialectic and the
of the Sophist
foundation ot characteristics
tic, and also the
their allowm
in
consisting
on_ the
the Socratic teaching
value to a
conceptions, only a relative
truth of universal
principles
moral
and
scientific
appears to advocate a doc;

he

CENTAL INDEPENDENCE.
161

were fi-om time to time


expanded as occasion
required
Chance has to a certain
extent, decided which
oflt
dialogues should come
down to us
Still ,f
v
that Socrates kept
thos^bjermo::;^;

cially

view, to which he
preference according
to

is

seciired

^^^ ^"-i "^^^

by the control of his


wants and delt;.

3Sr;1r'"'''^'
'"'""^^'^"''^ '^f

ship

Lrel 3d^

Xenophon.

:\::rrrr
s

constantly revertlnl
bv

e^d'ated commonwealth.
regulated

"''^'^^

-ninfrien

the public weal


by a
To these maybe
added

exceeded the range


of the ordinary
morality of the
ffreeks by requiring
love for

enemies

Not only was Socrates


himself
lenial

ntr

,.
<
a mnH.i
"''^and abstemiousness
""*'"ess, but
Dut he endeavoured
,,
to

^anabstemio^nessinthetir^^^

ill:!

In tt,^^^^^^^^^^^^^

-^'--^

P'* "^' ^^d


occupied
P eu was nearlv
neaily the same as
that which aft,ards gamed such
importance for the
s;hoo,f ;
e

.1

" *'^

'^''**""' P!'

.Sp,

y,/^^X,
^f
'PT. Ap,,^, ,7,,
fmto,t9,
diet the

k'nd of knowledge.
S!'''"t
" /'bove quoted passage

'"

This does not eon

assertion that aU
te consist, in
knowled^i'

Socrates had at a.,


reflected

.,.,

conviction

of

the

ZlT''"?'' ''''''"'''' ^^J-VS^rafCwlX'*'^^'-^"*-

S'^f'"'''^
"^"^^

SOCRATES.
162
Chap.

vn.

man can only become master


the Cjnics and Stoics;
by the
independent of wants, and
of Mmself by being
conwhile depending on the
exercise of his powers;
resembles a
of the body, he
ditions and pleasures
slave

'

philosopher

who

considers knowledge to

highest good, will


--^^^^''^'^^'ZlZ
by the desu^^
uninterrupted
mind's devoting itself,
pursuit of truth
senses,^ to the
and appetites of the
thing; and the less value
^preference to every other
more
things as such and the
he attaches to external
happiness to be bound^ .^
exclusively he conceives
mo e
condition of man,' the
with the intellectual
into
carry these principles
feel the call to

Lthe

^iU he

of

himself independent
by really making
which
Other motives, however,
xternal worli

Practice

erv d

moralists of a later epoch,


a standard for
He was not only an

Socrates.
were unknown to

but
pleasures of the senses,

to the
Iscetic in relation
than
delayed less strictness

-ig^^t^-^-^f;;;

from -Jypied, neither shrinking


himseh
To continue master of
needful.

f '/^^^

feeling it

clearness of

by the lucid

enjoyment,
iu he midst of
moderation
the aim which his
his thought-that^was
proposed to

itself."^

11 i. 2, 29
in particular, iv.

ii. 1,

111-

5,

l^^^^^^g'
bymp- o,

^J^^^^^^

iSes'^ird ^hiwithatTaSa
ormodevation mates man
makes
whilst moderation
"lave,
free,

Mm

^,p,^ia

he continues

ffo*'""

S rohuav.ioucanahrohs
any one
.M;

^^^

^^^

what,
?uled by the desire of

Plf-fJ
|ee pp.
^ P-

3. 15,.

i
,

' '

FUIENDSHIP.
163

Strongest appears this


character of the So.v.f
^ocratic
abstinence in the
tne language
lano-ncr.^ v.
he uses in referpnp^ f^
-sensual impulses.
However exemplarv hi
^"^^^^'^ ^^'^ wn conduct in this respect

<

m.v h.

^rr-

MnXl

prove a
eet
thought of his moral
teachlg
purity as freedom
of mind

not so

is

^ii^I

". "^

I ^'^ '*"''*

alit?ree:ive?1tsT''r"^'''^"" ^^"-'^ "^

^^^^aaj lemarked,
can only de.
-nd thiQ
-na
tnis v.i
relation on the o-rmmr] ^^ -^
"^
g^^o^ind of Its
advantas-es
iill thprp
..o
1.
t^ere can be no
^
mistaking the foot fi.
l'
-,

fern.

1.

-5...c^re.

3,

U:

..i.,

oi;'tco

^>

5^ ^ai

,^;^

th.
the

-;

SeoMe.ou ToC ^c^^a,,,


>^ ^^
^o.|.ro;;;/..;,^,5e^..o,5^,/

r^ay^ara Trapeyoi
The lt
l-^-k applied partly
to tte
luchcial working/of
pis!
which makes a slave
'>
of
and deters him
;>
from
^t
IS good,
and partly /S
.

J^

harm
i

it

does to property,

incm danger and

trouble

^^ ^"Joyment,
.vjiich oof n
f"^"^'^ ^^^ procured in n
ZTo"'' ^^"^P^^^" "tanner from

^""^
5%T"'n
^^'^

Pvn?.

^'^^^- "'

"^"^

will
^^^" b'
be .een hereafter.
2

^^l^ich t)ie
"''"^","^ ^^^^^
Principles

SOCRATES.
164

community

:h.p.
Chap.

more extended
inconceivable without a
become, too a
These personal relations
of life.
arls
proportion as the thrnker
he more necessary in
and feels a
his own thinking
to be satisfied with
others and
in common w.th
need for investigation
the caje
Just as
of ideas.
for mutual interchange
pursuit
league, from a common
of the Pythagorean
of clanreUgion, a lively feeling
of mLlIty and
and brotherhood was
fondness for friendship
like causes produced
tdoped, as in other cases, too,
the blendmg
the Socratic school
like results, so, in
the ground of.
intellectual interests was
of moral and
with the
connection of the pupils
a more intimate
than could hav
teacher, and amongst themselves,
intellectual
association of a purely

ira

edited from an

be aske
The .uestion can hardly

character.

whjc

whether the
with him, which afterwards ;
condetermined Socrates to a
need of friendship
-,uuy
need of a common
tinuous dialogue, or the
having a natural turn
drew him towards all

came

first

t^-a

the

this-and this it is
b
philosophic lover dra^n

consists
His peculiarity rather

lich makes him

his research dispense


nor in his intercourse

in
Plato-that he could neither
others,
with association with

with research.
are found impressive
Accordingly in Socrates

eusst;:
^

a.

fo\he value and nature

a\o
dis-

of friendship^^

tm

that
comes back to the point,
In these he always
virtuous met.
exist amongst
friendship can only
necessary
altogether natural and

S"

for

them

Mem.

ii. 4:-6.

FRIENDSJIIP.
166

true fnends he
..y., will do everything for
o.e anotiier.
Virtue and active
benevolence are the only
means for securing friends.
From this platform the
'

prevaihng custom

Ch...
V"-

'~

then criticised. Socrates


not
only allows friendship
to assume the Greek
form oU
atfection for boys and
men, but he adopts that
form
of .t lm,lf, hardly
only out of mere
deference to
others.
In applying, however,
his own moral princples to this relation,
he opposes the prevaSing
errors and demands
a reformation, in order
that the
sensual conception cf
Eros may be transformed
into
he moral conception
of Friendship.^
True love he
Glares can only then be
said to exist when the
g'ood
rf the loved
olyect is sought
disinterestedly ; not
hen, with reckless
selfishness, aims are
pursued and
is

ineans

employed by which both


persons become con-

'

"" "7 '*'""


^"^y ^y ^" ""-Ifi^l^ Jove
!
an fidelity
and constancy be secured.
The plea that
e complaisance of
the one buys the
kindly offices
f another for
its complete training
is wholly a mis^l^en one
for immorality and
immodesty can never

irS

means

moral ends.*
seems that with these
principles Socrates
enunciating to his
cotemporaries
to

It really
>

a new truth or
'

'Similar

explanations are
rked into the
Platonic Lysis,
t probably
in too free a man
'
for ns to be able
t^^afn

tlienr

any

in/ormS

Pecting Socrales
^e,i.

Symp.

^ocratic.

8, 12,

Mem.

the lead
'^

90

ii

31

27
'>7
Svmp ^,
'^piP-

17"'^'"

^
".
ov yap
oi6v re
'

-^^''--oC.ra

i^yaBhu rh.

'''' ^^

<^Xvi^rlau
.T::i:/::^'^"''
nal aKpaai'au

?''"'

''^"^'"'"^ ""'

^^^

P- ^^'

"-

'irapex6-

"'^^-^/^^^o"

rhv

r
%^
r,,

the State.

SOCRATES.

266

memories one long sinc^


On the other hand, in his low estimate

at least recalling to their

Chap.

^n.

forgotten.^

of marriage he agreed with his fellow-countrymen.


This was no doubt partly the cause of the Greek

affection for boys

partly, too,

was a consequence,

it

Whilst assuming in women a


even
moral disposition similar to that of men,^ whilst
maintaining with intellectual women an instructive

favoured thereby.^

interchange of opinions, he still speaks of married,


the husband of
life in terms more in keeping with

He

Xanthippe, than with the friend of Aspasia.


allows that a clever

woman

is as

useful for the house-

hold as a man, and he reproaches

men for

not caring^

about the education of their wives,^ but he considers


and
the procreation of children the end of marriage/
life.^
his own conduct shows little love for domestic

His

social

and his personal

instincts are satisfied

men

friendly intercoru'se with

by

in their society he

means of fulfilling his peculiar mission as an


educator of mankind apart herefrom, with the pecuand not the
liarity of a Grreek, he considers the state,

sees a

"

family, to be the chief object of moral action.

Conf. Plato, Symp. 178, C.

217 E
Conf. Plato, Symp. 192, A.
3
gge p. 145, 2.
*
Xen CEc' 3, 10 but the
question may be raised, in how
far the substance of these re-

ISO C

'

'

marks applies to Socrates himSymp. 2, 9.


self.
5

Mem.

ii. 2, 4.

If in addition to the trait


described by Plato, Phado, 60,
e

Xanthipp
(which has no pretensions t(
great tenderness) be consider

A., the character of

the joking character ot tn<


conversation in Xen. Symp. ^:
into tbil
10, being thrown
scale against the passages ii;
Plato, Apol. 34, D., the balanc
of probability is, that Socrate
public
lived almost entirely
and almost never at home,

THE STATE.

j^.^

Of the importance

of the state, and the obligaChap


tions towards the same, a very
high notion indeed is _ ^"''
entertained by Socrates
he who would live amongst
:

men, he

must

says,

He

as ruled. 1

live in a state, be it as a ruler


or

requires, therefore, the

tional obedience to the laws, to


such

most uncondian extent that

the conception of justice is


reduced to that of obedience to law,2 but he desires every

competent

man

to take part in the administration


of the state, the

well-being of

all

individuals depending on the well-

being of the community.3

These principles were


by him throughout life.

really carried into practice

With devoted
were

self-sacrifice his duties as

citizen

even death being endured in order


that
he might not violate the laws.^
Even his philosophic
labours were regarded as the
fulfilment of a duty to
fulfilled,

the state ;^ and in Xenophon's


Memorabilia

we see
him using every opportunity of
impressing able
people for political services, of
deterring the incompetent, of awakening officials
to a sense of their
duties, and of giving them
help in the administration of their offices.^
He himself expresses the
political character of these
efforts most tellingly, by
including 7 all virtues under the
conception ""of 'the
ruling art.^

Mem.

'

Sep

^e^v

'

11

'76

''

111.

^a..A.,

. 1^

'

'^'

'
,

001

], 12.

iiQ

See PD 65 7

mem.
^

ii.

r9

j_,

Wx.^ in Mem. ii.


IV. 2, n. Plato, Euthyd.

^l

^,
'

'^0^''^"^^

-1

stands

for

Accordingly the story told


^'''''"^

^^^^-

^-

^7, 108,

and
,

j^
^ j^.
son. in Stab. Flodl 40
9) tha^
in answer to the quest^ion,

to

'

'

;;

SOCRATES.

68

Whilst thus doing homage to the old Greek view


of the state, in other respects he deviates from it
If knowledge is the condition of all true
widely.

Chap.

J]h-^
^

virtue, it

is

also the condition of all political virtue

the more so in proportion as the conception of


Hence everyone
political virtue is the higher one.
all

who
,

aspires to the position of a statesman is required

by a thorough
and a course of intellectual labour and

to prepare himself for this calling


self-sifting

conversely, Socrates only recognises capacity or right


to political position where this condition is fulfilled.
Neither the possession of power, nor the good fortune
of acquiring

it

by

lot or

knowledge makes the

popular election, but only

ruler.^

what countrv he belonged, he


replied that he was a citizen of
the

command

cannot

world,

credit,

and the question

itself

sounds strange as addressed to


Socrates in Athens. In Plato's
Crito and Apol. 37, C, he uses
language very different from
Ihe later cosmopolitan philosoProbably one of these
phers.
attributed to him the above
giQjy^
1

Mem.

iii.

6,

particularly

towards the end; iv. 2, 6


See p.
Plato, Symp. 216, A.
55 Q
10 ^aaiXels 5e
Tovs ra ffKriTTTpa
^yovras <pv ^hai, ov5h rovs virh
ru^v TvxovTU'u aip^eivras. ov8h
Tovs KK-r]po> Kaxovras, ouSe rovs
fiiaaafiiuovs, ou5e robs i^aTrari}a-auras, a\\a tovs i-Kicxranhovs
&pxeiv in all other cases obedience is given to men of pro2

Mem.

iii. 9,

Kal &pxot''ras

oi)

'

fessional

knowledge ;which

As regards the

rule of

then iUustrated by the example of physicians, pilots,


and others. Similarly in Mem.

is

iii.
iv. 2, 2
4
iii. 5, 21
1,^^
Ihid. 4, 6 K^w I7W76, ws otov
&p ns Trpoarareirj ihv yiyv^aiq}
re Siv Se? koX Tavra ^iropiieo-eai
:

ayadhs h.u e^rj TrporrraSimilar views are advocated by Plato with the same

Uv-qTai,
rvs.

illustrations,

Polit.

297,

D.,

and they appear to have been


in the school
Accordingly the

generally held
of Socrates.

accuser Xen. Mem. 1. 2, 9,


charges Socrates with having
contributed to bring existing
contempt^:
into
institutions
XiyoiV ws fiu}pa>u is robs fxh' Trjs
ttSk^o^s 6.pxovTas airh Kvdfiov KaBSc /x^Se^o
KvlBepwhrr]
iffTaffQai,

QiMiv Kexcvaeai Kvafxevr^^ ^r,Se


reKTOvi jutjS' avKv^V H-V^' ^'^ '^^roiadra, and Xeuophon does
not deny the accuracy of this
statement, but only attempts

THE
the majority, his
lor a

{STATE.

judgment

is, that it is impossible


Chap
statesman desirous for right and justice
to hold _J^^-

his

own

else

can an upright

against it; hence, where

man

it prevails,

what

do but withdraw to private

life?

political principle

was here advocated, which


brought Socrates not only into
collision with the
Athenian democracy, but with the
whole political
administration of Greece.
In place of the equality
of all, or the preference
accorded to birth and
wealth, he demanded an aristocracy
of intelligence
in place of citizen-rulers, a
race of intellectually educated officials in place of a
government of tribes
and people, a government by
professional
;

adepts,

which Plato, consistently developing


the principles
of Socrates, attempted to
realise in his philosophic
community.'
Socrates is here
observed

in

the track which the Sophists


being themselves the first to

first

offer

following

struck out,

and to declare

necessary a preparatory intellectual


training for a
statesman's career.
Still what he aimed at was
in
pomt of substance very different from
what they

aimed

For him the aim of

at.

politics was not


power of the individual, but the well-being
of the'
community the object of training was
not to acquire
tlie

personal dexterity, but to attain


truth ; the means of
3ulture was not the art of
persuasion, but the science
)f what really is.
Socrates aimed at a knowledge
by

neans of which the state might


be reformed, the

SOCRATES.

170

Sophists

Chap.

vn.

at

one by means of which

it

might

be-

governed.

The

aristocratic tone of this view of the state-

appears to be contradicted by the ease with which


rose

Socrates

above the

social

of his

prejudices

by the
what it may,

nation, meeting the ruling contempt for trade

maxim

that no useful activity, be

it

but only idleness and activity need call forth shame.


For just as
Still both come from a common source.
Socrates will have the position of the individual in
the state settled according to his achievements, so
conversely he will have every action appreciated

which leads to any good result.^ Here, as elsewhere,


the conception of good is his highest standard.

One consequence of the political character of


Greek morality was that the problem proposed to the
virtuous man was customarily summed up as doing

(4) Love
for enemies.

'

good to friends and harm to foes. This very definition is put into the mouth of Socrates ^ by XenophoUj
who likewise considers it most natural to feel pain
the success of enemies.^
of the earliest

On

and most

the other hand, in onj

historical of Plato's dij

In keeping as the son of a poor labourer.


2, 56.
he urges a friend Xenophon and Plato as men of
rank and property.
(ii. 7) to employ the maids of
2 Mem. ii. 6, 35
koI '6ti iyvoihis house in wool work, and
1

Mem.

with

i.

this,

another (ii. 8) to seek for occupation as a steward, refuting


in both cases the objection,
that such an occupation was

unbecoming

Xenophon
view
and

for

held

men.
free
diiferent

(see (Ec. 4. 2,

and

6, 5),

well known that


Plato did also. Socrates speaks
it

is

Kas avSphs aperrjv eivai viKav rovs


fxhv ipiXovs u TToiovfra rovs Se
i^(^dpovs KaKcJJs.
'

Mem.

iii.

9,

<^Q6vov

8e-

^eV tiio,
i^iipi(XKv avrhv ovra, ovr fiipTOiTTjr iirl (p'lKuv aTUX'C'S ovre tV

aKOTTwv

eV

o,ri.

e'lr},

Kvirriv

^x^pSov iVTvxiais yiyuo[J.epriv.

LOVE FOR ENEMIES.


logues,^ Socrates declares it
to be

wrong to injure

Chap

the same thing as wrong-cloinoand wrong-doing may never be


permitted, not even
towards one from whom wrong-doing
has been suffered.
The contradiction of these two
accounts is
hard to get over ^ for assuming
it to be

_J^

another

injury

is

granted

that the Socrates of Xenophon


is only speakinofrom
a popular point of view, still
the fact would Temain
that Xenophon cannot have
been conversant with
explanations such as those given
by Plato. No

doubt

Plato's account even in the


Crito cannot be regarded
as strictly conformable to
truth

still it may well be


;
questioned whether he can be
credited with such a
flagrant deviation from his
master's teaching 3

as this

would

That there is such a possibility


cannot be
we must then be content to leave

be.

denied
;

it in
uncertainty as to which were
the real principles of
Socrates on this subject.'^

334 b"*''

^^' ^'

^^^"^

''The remarV nf

^^1'-

^'

M.-

456) will not pass muster that

fhlf

f ^"f

enemies,
enemicTs

<

'iHii

''''"'^.,

"

''"^^-

*"
not ^to*""^^
to
injure

but
bu^Z

"'

as rth" ab
c^i^se^nng

lin

"

T^.r/'"'^
Hxldelmmd

umi. er. AiKst. d:i^r;^""-'Krei'i'^iir'


ae LLconomia
.

ica Doctrina, part


.

l84S)-that Socrates

i.

Marb.

was

P^nciple opposed to slavery.


^^e held many things
which

-^^

in

unworthy of a free-man Tt bv
">=> follow ttat he d^^
^^^'"''"^ "' slavery fand the
view that slaverv U eonfrsr-.^

""

vrould undoubtedly have


been
the whole
connection does not snit ^.^
'" mentioned.

'"
r^-^'
between

vZ

">'- -diZctfon

Oilna
a,-,/i
i
foreign
rathe*
think of the Cynfcs.

^0,,^^

to

SOCRATES.

172

CHAPTER

^^^^'

A. Suhor-

means

t/

ends in

GOD AND MAN.

ON NATURE.

CONTINUATION.
Chap.

VIII.

Enquiries into nature, we have seen, did not form


Nevertheless, the

part of the scheme of Socrates.

him to a peculiar view of


One who so thoughtfully
design.
problem of human life from all sides

Iy^q of his speculations led

nature and

its

turned over the

he did, could not leave unnoticed its countless reand judging them by the
lations to the outer world
as

standard which was his highest type the standard


could not but come to the conof utility for man

viction that the whole arrangement of nature was


subservient to the well-being of the human race, in

To

short that it was adapted to a purpose and good.^


his

mind, however,

that

all

good and expedient

is

appears of necessity to be the work of reason for


just as man cannot do what is useful without intelli;

gence, no more
exist
'

is

it

without intelligence.^

^For Socrates, as has been

already shown, understands by


the good what is useful for
gee

is

useful to

His view of nature,

crates

is

desirous of convincing-

a friend of the existence of the


Gods, and hence proposes the
question Whether more intelligence is not required to produce living beings than to produce paintings like those ot
:

T^2in.
2

what

possible for

Mem.

i.

4, 2,

in

which

the argument from analogy

most clearly brought

out.

is

So-

VIUWS OF NATURE
1

therefore,

was essentially that of a


relation of means
to ends, and that not
a deeper relation going
into the

inner bearings of the


several parts, and the
purpose
of Its existence and
growth inherent in every
natural
being. On the contrary,
all things are
referred as a

the. highest end, and


that they serve this
purpose is
also set forth simply
as a matter of fact,
and as due
to a reason which, like
an artificer, has endued
them
with this accidental
reference to purpose.
As in the
Socrafc ethics, the wisdom
regulating human actions
becomes a superficial reflection
as to the use of
particular acts, so, too,
Socrates can only conceive
of the
wisdom which formed the
world in a manner equally
p-fic.al.
He shows what care has been
taken to
'

air,

in that not only the


sun shines

by day, but

also
in that the heavenly
bodies serve for divisions
of seasons, that the
earth

the

moon and

ctZ

the stars by night

''"''

^"' "''-'

"~^^^^'

--l

"^'

^'^

change of
o? seasons prevents
excessive heat or cold

*'' '''''''''''' "'"''^


- derived
from cattle, from oxen,
from pigs, horses, and
other

tmZal

Sr^nrt^rralLv^ltS tl:
^e,.r..p^iV^,,^/:,:f--!
.0

i.

fates

immediately
by S
with the ^^estioj^'.

aT;u<f,Ta,s^;^,(^^^3^.V^

^^

.'-* ' cofes, r, ...

9,71-'-

.also

P/uto,

TsTfJl "'"'."".' "'^'^ ''^<


''''^,P''^S-o as SItl historical
'f
ac?>^
'"'^^

'

mnnt

Ji

Chap.
ch.z

^^
~~

SOCRATES.

^^4

To prove

animals.

Chap.
^UI-

made man,^ he

the

wisdom

refers to the

of the Craftsman

who

human

organism of the

of sense, to the
body, to the structm-e of the organs
dexterity of his
erect posture of man, to the priceless

He

hands.

the natural

in
sees a proof of a divine Provicjence
impulse for propagation and self-preser-

the fear of death.


vation, in the love for children, in
wearies of exalting the intellectual advan-

He

never

tages of man, his ingenuity, his

memory,

his intelli-

He
disposition.
gence, his language, his religious
God and in
considers it incredible that a belief in
men,

Providence should be naturally inborn in


immemorial,
and have maintained itself from time
the ripest years
clinging not to individuals only in
communities,
age, but to whole nations and
all

of their

unless

it

were true.

He

revelations vouchsafed to

appeals

men

to

also

special

for their good, either

Unscientific, doubtless,
by prophecy or portent.
became in the
these arguments may appear, still they

sequel of importance for philosophy.


As Socrates by his moral enquiries, notwithstandscientific
their defects, is the founder of a

ing

all

of the relation
doctrine of morals, so by his theory
popular
its
of means to ends, notwithstanding
the founder of that ideal view of
/ character, he is
ever after reigned supreme in the
\
'

nature which
and which with^
natural philosophy of the Greeks,
itself of so much value
all its abuses has proved
1

In

Mem

4, 12,

a remark

thepopnis found indicative of


lar character of these general
tI 5^ koX ras
considerations
:

tC^v

cK^podiaiu^v 7}dovb,s
C^fo^s Zoiva.^

&X^ojs
rov irovs xpovov,

toTs

h^v

T^^'^^tTyS',
Se <rvv.x<^^^

-ni^iu

Trapexe..'.
m^XP^ 7^P^ ^"^-^^

'

CONCEPTION OF GOD.
for the empxr,cal study
of nature.

17.5

True, he was not


himself aware that he
was .^engaged on natural
^cience, having only
considered the relation of
means
to ends in the world,
in the moral interest
of piety,
fetill from our
previous remarks it follows
how closely
his view of nature
was connected with the
theory of
fhe knowledge of
conceptions, how even its
.

Chap
^"r'

defects

were due to the universal


imperfection of his intellectual method.

'"?"

"'"' '''" "'

most

y speaks of Gods

in a popular

doubt thinking, in the

t o- B. Ooa
that Socrates "'^^''^

^'^""''^

selvet of"''
selves
of creative reason, the
reply

is,

way

as many,-

no

'Zt'

"'

first place,

of the Gods of the ?^ ^<'-^'';


multiplicity the idea of he
oneness of God,' an idea
""*
not unknown to the
Greek
re igion, rises with
him into prominence, as is
not
infrequently met with at
that time.< In one
passage
he draws a curious
distinction between the
creator
ad ruler of the universe and
the rest of the God.
Have we not here that
union of polytheism
and

popular faith.^

Mem.

i.

'

Mem.

iv. 3

Compare

'

'-on

to

1,

19

Mem.

Zeller's

invisible

":;

iv. 3,

1 1

.""' ""^"^^

Introdnc
GriecheiT

H7-

-/^e.ra^ea,t,t

'

16

Philos. d.

ov <pp6ur^cr,v.

Sl^/

Outof this

13

;'o?t

'

Tlie

^^

^^"^

Pn^

It txt

f TT^"^" '"'^^" ^^^--

li'^^'r'
L"

"'^"^^ '^'

"^' M^i/

"^^'^^

^^ i hu.
-^^'x-. 6-rroy

V'P'''''^

-g;-t(Forsch. 220) to prove


that this language
^^/^^'^^^.^^^on i"s

Pi

''^'

'TT

inconctus've

'

is

spurious,

own
^"

sliowing
^^^^^ru^s

""'''

"^^^^^^^

SOCRATES.

176

a Greek by his
monotheism, so readily suggested to
VIIL^ mythology, which consisted in reducmg the many

CHAP

Oods

(2)

many instruments

of the

One Supreme

to the notion of One


In as far as Socrates was led
of the
by the reasonable arrangement

God

conceived
as the
Reason of
the world.

to be the

Supreme Being

formed to himself of this


world, the idea which he
Heraclitus and Anaxagoras)
Being (herein resembling
which he conceives
was as the reason of the world,
relation to the world that the
of as holding the same
Herewith are most closely
soul does to the body.^
and pure ideas of Ood as a being
connected his high

present everywhere.;
invisible, all-wise, all-powerful,
visible, produces visible
As the soul, without being

As
the world.
the body, so does G-od in
dominion over the small
the soul exercises unlimited
belongs to it, its indiviportion of the world which
dominion over the whole
dual body, so Ood exercises
in all parts of its body,
world As the soul is present
And li
Universe.
present throughout the

effects in

so

God

is

confined, can perceive

is

the limitations by which li


the soul, notwithstanding
what is distant, and have
kinds, surely the
thoughts of the most varied

(hp6viiJ.6v

S^

cw 5e ffahrhv
&\\0dL
TL SoKeTs ^x^iu,

Mem.

i.

4,

ohdafxod
Ktt'

dual

ohd'eu

cppdvitiov

oXei

-^"S^ '^^ v-rrepfieyee-n

(the elements,
KoX TTXrieos &ireipa

parts of the
or generally, the
Ttva outcos
acppoaiuvv
world) 5i'
KaratiaOe
17
ix^iv
ehrdKTCVs
oUi
rb (Xbv
ivuu
vovs
6 (Ths
:

'6ri

KoL

C^rai

^ovMrai
oUffOai oZv XP^

Sttcos

ffSiixa

ixtrax^ipi' '^'J" ^^

Tcp 7ra(/Ti (ppSu-ncriv

know

ra irdura

o-K(t>

Uv ahr-^ T]^v ^, ovrca rlOeffdai

kc

UvaffQai h
fx^ rh 'ahv ixiv ofxixa
TToXKa ffrddia iiiKvelaOai, rhvj^
eJvi,
Tov dOv o<p9a\tJ.hv aUvarov
(T\
jWTjSe,
afxa izavra bpav
^

Twv
UvaaOai
Trept

tV

iv AlyinrTCf) Koi 2iKA.


(ppovriC^iv, t)?*' 6 re,

deov (ppou-nffiu 1X7] iKav^u eivai


irdvTwv iirifji.iM'io'Oai.

a/-,

'

WORSHIP OF GOD.
ledge and care of

I77

God must be

able to embrace all


Besides had not a belief in the
providential care of G-od been already 2
taken for granted,
in the argument for His existence
from the relation
of means to ends ?
Was not the best explanation of
this care to be found in
the analogous care which
the human soul has for the
body ? A special proof
of this providence Socrates
thought to discern in
oracles ^ by them the most
important things, which
could not otherwise be known,
are revealed to man
It must then be equally
foolish to despise oracles,
or
to consult them in cases
capable of being solved by

and moreJ

Chap.

__Z^

Dur
is

own

From this conviction followed


a matter of course, the
worship of God, prayer'
reflection/

iacrifices,

and

obedience.-^

As to the form and manner of


worship, Socrates,
^ we already know, wished every one to
follow the
ustom of his people. At the same
time he propounds
.urer

maxims corresponding with

rod

He would

^ast

of

hat IS

'Compare the words in Mem.


18
If you apply to the
ds for prophecy, yvd,<rv rh
ov STi^TOfTodrou Ka\ ToiodrSu

rS>u

4,

cicrff
'dfxa irdura bpau koX
vra uKovfiv Kal irauTaxov Trape?-

em tiv

e,S.>u

X^s

Mem.

iv.

2.\so

i.

Conf

1, 6.

yvdxrri,

tus fiopcpas

Compare
Seep. 149,

19

Mem

iv

r,

P-

76 7
'",<

4
4,

77
Q
'
o

q
^'

2, 14.

ii.

ad-

and 1
12 ^d
i^
and iT
/
i.
16
i

Ibid. iv. 3,
^,
Ibid.

is

And, with

65, 5.

,Ka\ S,fMa. nduTc^u iir,f.,\,:adai


i the words, Ibid. iv. 3, 12:
dvafxeprjs,

it so fully ?

14.

Tiu,

S4yh\-nev\eya,

idea of

who but God knows what

for

intageous for man, or knows

own

his

men pray

for particular,
external goods, but only
to ask for

all for

good

not have

' ,

ii
^^'

C^) The

Zt"^"^

SOCRATES.

178

Chap.
^^J^-

of
regard to sacrifices, he declared that the greatness
the spirit
the sacrifice is unimportant compared with

pious the man,


of the sacrificer, and that the more
so that it
the more acceptable will the offering be,

correspond with his means.^

Abstaining on principle

seeking
from theological speculations,^ and not

to

fellow men
explore the nature of Grod,but to lead his
combining the
to piety, he never felt the need of
into one
various elements of his religious belief
consistunited conception, or of forming a perfectly

which
ent picture, and so avoiding the contradictions
that belief may easily be shown to contain.^
0. Dignity
qfrruin.
mo7i;ality.

A
T^gfore

man.^

certain divine element Socrates, like others


Mm, thouffht to discern within the soul of

Perhaps with this thought

is

connected

his

immediate revelations of God to the human


vouchsafed to himself.
soul, such as he imagined were
Welcome as this theory must have been to a philosomoral and
pher paying so close an attention to the

belief in

nature of man,

spiritual

it

appear that

does not

argument.
Socrates ever attempted to support it by
proof of
Just as little do we find in him a scientific

was inclined
the immortality of the soul, although he
opinion of the dignity
to this belief partly by his high
'

Mem.

i.

3,

ggg p 139^

iv. 3, 17.

2.

have all'tbe less reason


for supposing with Denis (His3

We

toire des Thiories et des Idees


morales dans I'Antiquite, Paris
Soet Strasb. 1856, i. 79), that
crates, like Antisthenes, spared
polytheism from regard to the
needs of the masses, whilst

believing in only one God.


This assumption would belie
not only the definite and re-

peated assertions of Xenophon,


but also Socrates' unflmchmg
love of truth.

Mem.

iv.

,,,^
kKXa
m^j

Kai audpwirov ye ^pvx^, ezTrep ri Ml


&\\o rHu avOpo^mvccv, tov dmv
ixir4x^i.

iMMORrALirr of the soul.


of

man,

partly, too,

on grounds of expediency.'
Nay
^'' ^P'g7,^at a moment when
tie
.r?." of a
witholdmg
conviction can least
be supposed he
expressed himself on this
question with
dtb
and caut.on.3 The
language, too, used by
the
Cyrus .n Xenophon ^
agrees so well herewith,
thai w!
are dnven to assume
that Socrates

mS

dig

considered

t^e
existence of the soul
after death to be
indeed pro!

belonged no doubt to
those problems
which surpass
sZas
the powers of man.
'

Compare Hermann

P^f

in

Mar-

'^1.?'^'"' description of
*
Socrates
rel ^'^T"^^^
exclusive autho,
rifv of Xenophon,
rity
Plato, and
Aristotle,
later wdters
'"" -""^t P'^rt token
trom these sources,
and when-

''L^''''^''''^^^^^og, 1835-6,

40, C.
tion.

after his

tt,

nfV"*

condemna-

mat

" Death is either


an external
sleep or a transition
to a new

lite,

but

m neither case

is it

evil.

Z''lr

an

ever

S J\

sible that

(It

particularly
8
IQ
with Plato's. Phaido,
.u, 105
,, ,.,
C)
In conclusion, the
possibili'tv of
the sours dying

^'^f^ro

^^^

Conf. 37 B
IS feared as the
greatest
evil,
whilst It mav be
the
greatest good
iych 5h

t^em
them

oOtw Kai

oXofiai

.
:

104^..
104, 7 (travelling
K

^^j^^

^'?^""'^^^ between
?>.
the statements
in Cic

mL^i V.V^^'^^^^-^v?v ;V^' ^f- Cyrop.


^'/^^'^P^t-^8'2;

oijK

ovk e/StVat.

the

(^Ult. 111.
-^
'i
A +u lo
;>,n;,
that hocrates tauo-ht
thp
^dentity of justice
and happi!
PP
ness cursm^ th,

death

place

ty^ZZtl,?'''''^'' ^*^^

'

A.

utter-

^schines and others,


whijh
by our authorities!
category

either case death is


stated to
be the end of all evils.
21),

however, just pos-

some genuine

^"""ed

w'ith1heSdy

Apol.

"*'

ances of Socrates
may have
been preserved in the
writings

proofs.

(Compare

It goes beyond
them, there
no guarantee for
its acu-

.s

Cyrop. viii. 7, 10.


Several
reasons are first adduced
in fa
vour of immorlality,
but they
need to be <,n-eatly
strengthened
to be anything like
rigid
*

i.

is

of no g^od

Chap.
VIJI.

SOCRATES.
is the only good,
ignorance the only evil, and
that riches and noble birth do

intelligence

to fools); 71, 16 (truth and


virtue are identical) in Pint.
Ed. Pu. c. 7, p. 4, on education
(the passage in c. 9 is an inaccurate reference to Plato, Gorg.
Cons, ad Apoll. c. 9,
470, D.)
106, that if all sufferings
;

more harm than good in Diog.


or to abii. 32, that to marry
stain from marriage is equally
bad: in Gell. xix. 2, 7 {Athei).
;

p.

iv.

be equally divided,
every one would gladly pre-

had

to

Pint.

own:

God

tion of
Floril.

Legg.

Num.

E.), that selfthe best form of

c. 5,

p. 550,

Dam.

Jo.

ii.

13,

126,

Mein, that philosophy


ought to confine itself to o, ri

p. 221,

TOi iv ixeydpoicn, kukou t ayaGou


(others attribute
re Te'ruKTai
;

the words to Diogenes or Aristippus) Cic. de Orat. i. 47, 204


Socrates said that his only wish
was to stimulate to virtue
where this succeeded, the rest
:

followed of itself (a statement


thoroughly agreeing with the
views of the Stoic Aristo, and
probablv coming from him.
Conf Zeller, Stoics, Epicureans,
.

&c., p. 60; in Diog. ii. 30, blaming


thesophistrv of Euclid in Diog.
;

31 (undoubtedly from some


Cynic or Stoic treatise) that

ii.

is

in

40, 8,

apud
blaming the

Teles,

Athenians for banishing their


best, and honouring their worst

Floril.

626,

government
%ob. Floril.

deprecating
in Demct. Byz. quoted
ano-er
h/niog. ii. 21,(Gell N. A. xiv.
Exc. e
6, 5), 3Iuson. in the

Vind.

i.

restraint

Ibid. ii. 356,


(conf. Plato,

26

48,

the looking glass

4,

live to
;

Ser.

And. Poet.

men

Conj. Prsec.
ii.
33
c. 25,
p. 140 {Diog.
Exc. e Floril. Joan. Damasc. ii.
Stoh. Floril. ed. Mein.
B. 98
on the moral use of
202),
iv.,
his

serve

158

p. 21), that most


in
eat. whilst he eats to live
Stob. Ekl. i. 54, giving a defini-

men, and the apophthegmata


in Valer. Max. vii. 2, Ext. 1.
large number of sayings
purporting to come from Socrates are quoted by Plutarch

in his treatises and by Stobaeus


some, too,
in his Florilegium
howthem,
of
Most
Seneca.
by
ever, are colourless, or else
;

they aim at

being epigram-

matic, which is a poor substitute for being genuine. Altogether their number makes
them very suspicious. Probably

they were taken from a collection of proverbs which some


under
later writer published
the

name

of Socratic proverbs.

ACCUHACY of XENOPJIONS description,

CHAPTEK
EETROSPECT.

18

IX.

XENOPHON AND PLATO.


AND THE SOPHISTS.

SOCRATES

Looking back from the point now reached


to the
Chap.
question raised before, as to which of his
biographers _^'
we must look to for a historically accurate
account ATrruthof Socrates and his teaching, we
must indeed admit, ^xZt' '^

that no one of

them

so satisfectory an authority as
any original writings or verbal reports
of the utteris

P^>^o!>'-'^

de-

'''''^'^''"^

ances of the great teacher would


have been.^ So
much, however, is patent at once, that
the personal
character of Socrates, as pourtrayed
by

both Xenophon

and Plato,

in all essential points, one and


the same.
Their descriptions supplement one
another
is

in

some

few points, contradicting each


other in none.
Nay
more, the supplementary portions
may be easily inserted in the general picture,
present before the eyes
of both.
Moreover the philosophy of Socrates is not

pl^^'

main represented by Plato and Aristotle


'''
in a f''
a different light from what it is
by Xenophon, pro- >^S"S
the

vided those parts only in the


writings of Plato be
t^,]frh.
"
taken into account which undoubtedly
belong to So- '^"^^''^-

"

Conf. p. 98.

SOCRATES.
and in the Socrates of Xenophon a distinction
be drawn between the thought underlying his utterances and the commonplace language in which it was
crates,

Xenophon, Socrates expresses the


opinion that true knowledge is the highest thing, and
that this knowledge consists in a knowledge of con-

Even

clothed.

in

ceptions only. In Xenophon, too,

may

be observed

all

the characteristics of that method by means of which


In his pages
Socrates strove to produce knowledge.

position

reduced to knowledge, and this


supported by the same arguments, and

virtue

likewise,

is

is

therefrom are deduced the same conclusions, as in


Aristotle and Plato. In short, all the leading features
of the philosophy of Socrates are preserved by Xenophon ; granting as we always must that he did not

understand the deeper meaning of many a saying, and


therefore failed to give it the prominence it deserved.

then for the same reason he used a <^ommonplace expression instead of a philosophical oaej

Now and

for instance, substituting for,


ing,'

with

less

Nor need we

accuracy,

'

'

All virtue

All virtue

feel surprise

is

is

a know-

knowledge.'

that the defects of the

Socratic philosophy, its popular and prosaic way of


treating things, the want of system in its method,

the utilitarian basis of

its

moral teaching should

appear more prominently in Xenophon than in Plato


and Aristotle, considering the brevity with which
Aristotle speaks of Socrates, and the liberty with

which Plato expands the Socratic teaching both in


On the other hand,
point of substance and form.
Xenophon's description is confirmed partly by indi-

XENOPHON VINDICATED.
vidual admissions

of Plato,^

partly by

183
its

truth and conformity to that picture which

make

inward

Chap.

we must

_^1

to ourselves of the first appearance of Socrates'

newly discovered principle. All then that can be conceded to the detractors of Xenophon is, that not fully
understanding the philosophical importance of his
teacher, 'he kept it in the

background in his description, and that in so far Plato and Aristotle are
most
welcome as supplementary authorities. But it cannot be allowed for one
in

Xenophon has
account of Socrates, or
impossible to gather from his description

any respect given a

that

moment

it is

that

false

the true character and importance of the doctrine of


his master.
It

phon
is

may
is

indeed be said that this estimate of Xenoat variance with the position which Socrates

known

observes

to
;

have held in history.


'

Had

As Schleiermacher

Socrates done nothing but discourse

on subjects beyond which the Memorabilia of Xenophon never go, albeit in finer and more brilliant
language,

hard to understand how it was, that


in so many years he did not empty the marketplace
and the workshop, the public walks and the schools,
by the fear of his presence how he so long satisfied
it is

an Alcibiades and a Critias, a Plato, and a Euclid


how he played the part assigned to him in the dialogues of Plato

in short, how he became the founder


and type of the philosophy of Athens.' Fortunately
in Plato himself we have a valuable testimony
to the
'

See above, pp. 80

150,

1.

Werke,

iii. 2,

250, 287.

(2) Sclilei.

""ohTctimi'

answered.

SOCRATES.

184

Chap.
IX.

To what

accuracy of Xenophon's description.

element

divine

to disclose the

when anxious

his Alcibiades appeal

concealed

does

Silenus-like

under the

appearance of the Socratic discourses ? To what


does his admirable description of the impression

What is it
produced on him by Socrates go back ?
which to his mind has been the cause of the revolu^

tion and change in the inner life of Greece

What

but the moral observations which in Xenophon form


Symp.

E.

'6Tav

'yap

aKOVu [SwKpctTOUs] iroKv /xoi


XOV ^ TOOV KOpv^aVTKjOVTWV

/xaX-

>

KopSia

215,

7]

T6

KoX SoLKpva eKX^^TCtl-

TTTjSa

virh Toov

x6ya}U

rwv rovrov.

6pa>

iSd}v

&v

[jevos

ns

Kal ivrhs

irpoorov

ouSe Tedopv^rird fxov r) ^uxv ouS'


TjyavaKTei ens av^pairoBcadcHs 5ia-

yadu) eo-eadai.

TTafiTrdAKovs

(similarly Euthydemus
in Xen. Mem. iv. 2, 39) aXA.'
virh Tovrovt rov Mapffvov iroWaKLS

KLfji.evov,

^iwrhu

ju.7y
.

SotTTe

outco dire6r)p,

Stj

TToKKov

(JTi

yap

auajKOL^ei

fxoi

5o|at

exouri ws

^Ivai

ivde7)S

ifxavTOv fxev afiiKu

/ue

exa)
btxoKoy^lv

tav

avTos

ra

5'

'

en

AQrivaiwv

Mem. iv.
(conf.
6) TreirovOa 5e ivphs rovrov
[x6vov avOpdoTTUv, h oiiK &!/ ris
otoiro iv ifjLol ive^vai, rh al(TX^-

Trpdrrco

iii.

....

vecrdai birivovv

ovv

avrhv Kal

(pevyco,

tSo)

alax^J^ofxai

ra

hpairerevoj

Kal

'6rav

wij.oXoyrjfj.4va'

Kal TToXXdKis ixev 7}d4oi)s tt.v


avrhv jutj ovra iv avOpcoirois

Idoi/J-i

et S'

av ruvro yevoiro, ev ol5^ on iroXv


fxel^ov Uv ax0olixT}v, ware ovk ex^,
'6

xp'h^oyLai rovrca rca avQpwircf.

tiaX ol Xoyoi avrov


lb. 221, D.
ofioiSraroi elai roh ^iXriPo7s ro7s
Sioiyofj-ivovs Se
5ioLyojj.vois
:

exovras

TTX<H(Trov reivovras, ixaXi

Ka\ eVi

&KKOVS

avrwv yiyvo-

vovv

evdov fiovvovs evp'f](ri rwv X6ywv


Kal irXeio-i
deiordrovs
eireira
aydXfiUT aperris iv avrols exorTas!

ra
avTU iTa.(TXovTO.s\ this was not
the case with other speakers,
Koi

Se

fiev

Xov 5e

eTrl

ffKOTreiv

rw [jeXXovn KaX^

irav

offov

Trpoa'fjKet

AlberWs

Ktti

78)
objections to the above use of
these passages resolve themselves into this, that those 'elements of conversation which
rivet the soul,' which are not
altogether wanting in Xenophon, are more frequent and
noticeable in Plato, that therefore the spirit of the Socratic

philosophy
clearly in

comes
Plato.

we

(p.

more
Far from
out

grant

denying

this,

readily.
are not

The above remarks

it

directed against the

statement that Plato gives a


deeper insight than Xenophon
into the spirit of the Socratic
teaching, but against Schleiermacher's statement that the
Socrates were
discourses of
different in substance and subject matter from
those reported by Xenophon.

essentially

VALUE OF HLS METHOD.


the substance of the Socratic dialogues.
these only are dwelt upon by Socrates,

Apology

Plato's

vices

to his

1^5

These, and

Chap.

_^-

speaking in

of his higher calling and his ser-

country;

it

is

his

business to exhort

others to virtue;

and if he considers the attraction


of his conversation to consist also
in its critical attempts,2 the reference is to a process
of which many
examples are to be found in Xenophon,
that of convincing people of ignorance in the
affairs of their
calling.

The

produced by the discourses of Socrates


us, were they only of the kind
reported by Xenophon.
The investigations of Socrates
as he gives them, may often
appear trivial and
tedious
and looking at the result with reference
to
the particular case, they may really
be so.
That
effect

need not surprise

the forger of armour

who has

to wear it

attended with

must

suit the

armour

to

:^

^wl'^"
teaching

^^mT
^'"^

him

that the care of the body

many advantages

'B.lmijort-

is

that friends

be secured by kind acts and


attention

must
these and

such-like

maxims, which are often lengthily discussed


by Socrates, neither contain for us,
nor can they have
contained for his cotemporaries, anything
new.
The
important element in these inquiries,
however, does
not consist in their substance, but in
their method,

Apol. 16,

rmo*
ols

.o.

MO*

-rrphs Se rovejraK.Ao.0o.>r6.

naXiara axoKv

^'jr.^

ol

rihu

ir\ovaicoTaTU3v avTo/^iaToi

ffw

aKovouTes

x^'^povi^tTttCofx^ucou ruu

avepwirwv, Kal auTol TroKXdKis e>e


liifiowTai iha ^irtxetpovaiu 6,\Aovs

ample of such sifting is to be


found in the conve?sation of
Alcibiades with Pericles, Mem
i.

^'

40.

Mem.

iii.

10 9
12 '4.'

<

Ibid.

i\j{^^ ii.'io'^'e

iii.

0.

'J^

^"*^'^-

SOCRATES.

18G

what was formerly unexplored hypothesis and unconscious guesswork, was now arrived
at by a process of thinking. In making a too minute

Chap.

in the fact that

^^'

pedantic application of this method, Socrates


would not give the same offence to his cotemporaries

or

they to learn for the first


time the art of conscious thinking and emancipaNay, did
tion from the authority of blind custom.^
not the enquiries of the Sophists for the most part
as to us,

who have not

much

contain very

as

less,

which notwithstanding their

imparted an almost electrical shock to


their age, simply and solely because even in its partial application, a power, new to the Greek mind,

empty

cavils,

and a new method of

reflection

had dawned upon

therefore Socrates only dealt with those


unimportant topics, upon which so many of his diait?

Had

logues exclusively turn, his immediate influence, at


least

on his cotemporaries, would

still

be

intelligi-

ble.

These unimportant topics, however, hold a subEven in


ordinate position in Xenophon's dialogues.
these dialogues the main thing seems to be real ininto

vestigations

the necessity of knowledge, into

the nature of morality, into the conceptions of the


various
analysis

virtues,
;

into

moral

and intellectual

practical directions for

conceptions

self-

the formation of

critical discussions obliging the speakers

what their notions implied, and at what


Can we wonder that such investheir actions aimed.

to consider

Comp. Hegel, Gesch.

d. Phil.

ii.

59.

HIS RELATION TO THE SOPHISTS.

17

tigations should have produced a deep


impression on
the cotemporaries of Socrates, and an^enti^

Chap.

change ^_i!L__

in the Grreek

nimously

mode

tell

us

of thought, as the^istorians unaor,

that a keener vision should

have anticipated behind those apparently


commonplace and unimportant expressions of
Socrates, which
his biographers

unanimously record, a newly discovered world ?


For Plato and Aristotle it was reserved to conquer this new world, but
Socrates was ^
the

first

Plainly

to discover
as

and to point the way thereto.


see the shortcomings of his

it,

we may

achievements, and the limits which his


individual
nature imposed on him, still enough

remains to

stamp him

as the originator of the philosophy


of con-

ceptions, as the reformer of

method, and as the

first

founder of a scientific doctrine of


morals.

The

relation, too, of the Socratic philosophy


to
Sophistry will only become clear
by considering

the

c.

Hu

^^^^'''"

and unsatisfactory element in its method


^.j/L.
is well as its greatness
and importance. This relation as is well known has,
during the last thirty years,
5een examined in various
directions.
There

3iie-sided

being

general agreement previously in


accepting Plato's
'iew, and looking on
Socrates as the opponent of
he Sophists, Hegel first obtained
currency for the
ontrary opinion, that Socrates
shared with the
sophists the same ground in
attaching
I

importance

the person and to


'hat different sense,

introspection.^

Grote^ has

^^^ 122, 2.
^ ""''^-^
PfHist, of P^'
Greece, viii. 479, 606.

S?f

'

'

still

In a some-

more recently
=

See ^
p. 116.

SOCRATES.

188

Chap.
^^'

contradicted the traditional notion of the antithesis


If
the Socratic philosophy and Sophistry.
Sophist means what the word from its history alone

_ between

mean, a public teacher educating youth

can

practical

life,

Socrates

is

for

himself the true type of a

hand it denotes the character of certain individuals and their teaching, it


is an abuse to appropriate the term Sophistry to
Sophist.

If on the other

this purpose, or to

group together under one

the different individuals

all

Sophists.

The

school, but a

who came forward

Sophists were

profession,

class

men

not a

of the

sect

as

or

most varied

most part highly deserving and meritorious people, at whose views we have not the
If then, Hegel and
least reason to take offence.

views, for the

his followers attacked the

common

notion of the

re-

lation of Socrates to the Sophists, because Socrates

one respect, agreed with the Sophists, G-rot^


attacks it for the very opposite reason, because the

in

most distinguished of the

so-called Sophists are

ai

one with Socrates.

Our previous enquiries

will

have shown, that botl

views have their justification, but that neither


altogether right.

It is indeed a false

view of his

tory to contrast Socrates with the Sophists, in th(


same sense that true and false philosophy are con
trasted, or

good and evil:

and in

this respect

deserves notice that in Xenophon, the contrast be


tween Socrates and the Sophists is not so great as i
Plato, ^ nor yet in Plato nearly so great as it
1

Compare Xen. Mem. iv. 4,


69, 1 and Zeller's

besides p.

Phil. d. Griech. Part


1, 2.

is

I.,

draw
p. 87.

HIS RELATION TO THE SOPHISTS.

modem

by several

previous enquiries

writers.^
^

]8!

the results of our


will not allow of our bringing
Still

Socrates, as Grote does in his


valuable work, into so
close a connection with men
who are grouped to-

gether under the

m their whole tone

name

of Sophists, and

and method bear

so

who

really

much resem-

blance to him.

The scepticism of a Protagoras and


Gorgias cannot for a moment be
placed on the same
with the Socratic philosophy
of conceptions,
nor the Sophistic art of controversy
with the Socratic
siftmg of men ; the maxim that
man is the measure
level

of all things, cannot be

demand

for

Proofs

compared with the Socratic


action based on personal
conviction,^

in

Protao-oras

and

iorgias, Thaeetet. 151, D.


; 162,
D'>. 164, D. ; 165, E. ; Rep. i.

'>4,

A.

vi.

Zeller,

'

As

498, C.

Part

882, 938.

1.

done by Grote, Plato

is

305.
Respecting Socrates'
ixplanation in Plato's Crito
49,
^., that he was convinced
that
aider no
circumstances is

vrong-doing allowed, it is
iiere observed
here we have
he Protagorcan dogma Homo
;

y/ensura

which Socrates
be found combating in
he Thieetetus
proclaimed
y Socrates himself. How unike the two are will
however
e seen at once by a moment's
iitiectionon Protagoras' saying
'onf. Part I. 809 ..
p. 259,'
.

v'ill

'55;

479.

Grote even asu'ts that not the Sophists


but
ocrates was the chief quibbler
Greece he was the first to
^stroy the beliefs of ordinary
linds by his negative
criti1

iii.

cism, whereas Protagoras,


Prodicus and Hippias used
previous authorities as they
found
them leaving untouched the
moral notions current. II. 410
and 428 he observes respecting Plato's statement
(Soph.
232, B.) that the Sophists talk
themselves and teach others to
talk of things which they
do

not know, which Socrates did


all his life long.
In so saying,
he forgets that Socrates

in
the opinions
of men neither pretends
to
better knowledge himself
nor
is content with the
negative
purpose of perplexing o'thers.
His aim was rather to substitute permanent conceptions
for

examining into

unscientific notions.
He forgets, also, that in the case

of the
Sophists, owing to their
want
of earnest intellectual
feeling
owing to the shallowness of
their method, owing to
their
denial of any absolute
truth,

Chap.
IX.

SOCRATES.

190

nor can the rhetorical display of the older Sophists,


the dangerous and unscientific character of their later

Chap,

ethics

be

lost sight

As regards the Hegelian

of.

grouping of Socrates among the Sophists, this has


called forth a greater opposition than it deserves.

The authors of

view do not deny that the Socratic

this

reference of truth to the person differed essentially

from that of the Sophists.^ Neither they nor their


opponents can deny that the Sophists were the first
and
to divert philosophy away from nature to morals
the

human mind,

that they

first

required a basis

foi

practical conduct in knowledge, a sifting of existing


customs and laws, that they first referred to personal

conviction the settling of truth and falsehood, righl


and wi'ong. Hence the dispute with them resolves
itself into

the question.

Shall

we say that

Socrates

and the Sophists resembled one another, both taking


personal truth as their ground, but differing in theii

views of personal truth? or that they differed, th<


nature of their treatment being a different one
whilst they agreed in

making

it

relative ?

Or

t(

put the question in another shape : There bein^


both points of agreement and difference betweei
them, which of the two elements is the more impor
tant and decisive?
explained, only one
difference

Here

for the reasons alread;

reply can be given,^ that th

between the Socratic and Sophistic philo

together with an incapacity for


positive intellectual achievements, those practical consequences were sure to result
which soon enough came to

view. See Part I. 920.


*
See p. 118, 1.
^
^ See p. 110, and Part
938.

.,

iq'
1. \6i

'

HIS RELATION TO TUB SOPHISTS.


Sophies

far

exceeds

their

points

of

101

resemblance.

The Sophists are wanting in that very


thing which is
the root of the philosophical
greatness of Socrates
the quest of an absolutely true
and universally valid
knowledge, and a method for
attaining it.
They
could question

all

that had

previously parsed for

but they could not strike out


a new and surer
road to truth.
Agreeing as they do with Socrates
in
concermng themselves not so much
with the
truth,

study of

nature, as with training for


practical
this culture has a different
character,

with them
and a different
life,

importance from what it bears


with Socrates. The
ultimate end of their instruction
is a formal dexterity
the use of which to be
consistent must be
left to'

individual caprice, since


absolute truth is despaired
of; whereas with Socrates,
on the contrary, the acquisition of truth is the ultimate
end, wherein alone
the rule for the conduct of
the individual is to be
found.
Hence in its further course,
the Sophistic
teaching could not fail to
break away from the philosophy which preceded it,

and indeed from every

intellectual enquiry.

Had

it

succeeded in gaining

^disputed sway, it would have dealt


the death stroke
to Greek philosophy.
Socrates alone bore in himself

the

germ of a new

life for thought.


He alone
oy his philosophical
principles was qualified
to be
.he reformer of philosophy.'

he history of philosophy
,nst

gathered

far

more from

hi.

tryim^S

from

of'socrat^: on

'^"Pj"''
t'S;

^^ t'heUfof"

Chap.
u.,

_if

SOCRATES.

192

Chap.
IX.

germ. But how is


t^i^ admission consistent with
making the second period of
philosophy commence with the
Sophists instead of with SoOn the other hand,
crates ?
the latest treatise on the question before us (Sieheck, Untersuchung zur Philos. d. Griech.
p. 1, Ueber Socr.Verhaltniss zur
iSophistik) is decidedly of the
and
opinion here expressed

fruit -bearing

likewise most of the later editors of the history of Greek philosophy. Strilmpell, too (Gesch.
d. Pralit. Phil. d. Griech. p. 26),
writes to the same effect, al-

though his
phists differs

view of the Sofrom ours in that

he denies a closer connection

between their scepticism and


their ethics.

He makes the dis-

tinctive peculiarity of Socrates


to consist in the desire to
reform ethics by a thorough
and methodical intellectual
treatment, whereas the Sophists aspiring indeed to be

teachers of virtue, accomniodated themselves in their instruction without independent


inquiry to the tendencies and
notions of the time.

nm

TRAGIC END.

GHAPTEE

193

X.

THE DEATH OF SOCRATES.

Wb

now

are

for the first

correct

time in a position to
form

opm:on of the circumstances


which led t^
Ae tragic end of Socrates.
The actual history of

hat event

well known.

.eached

when

^/.w'

never judicial"

in the year

nfaithfulness to

tl>e

399

b.c.,3

t! A-~-

an accu^ion

religion

of his country, with


itroducmg new Gods, and
with exercising a harmful
inuence on youth
T]ip
n\^\c.f
-^^^e chief accuser 5?
was Mele.06
-^T,
is,
with whom were associated
Anytus, one of the
'*

->-,'-.,

part of 6^n>f^>, Plato i.


283, to
consider the parody of
the in-

See p! 53, 1
'The indictment, accordin..
Favorinus in Bun, ii.

?\^^^^,"^ ^^'hich .Socrates puts

,E.
^

whole lifetime had been


labours at Athens, during
which Socrates T"^""'
been often attacked
but

pent

ad

:s

c.
x""

PUto, Apol. 17

'

D
'

'

4(5:

01. 24, B.,

was

rciSe

eWitaro

M^^ ^.c;a. .opT- ^.oT'oi


.>^.^..-

aa,r /,.

accuser^ a^'Tn'oH "^

^^^^^

^^^^

u" ud7d" ^T.^"

^""""

/'

b!S

9Q

'

'

t,^

Ti

'

^^
^*'

'''"^^^ Accusatori-

n..j"yts:"i:s*'?

'""^

;^S
""^''^

;;

SOCRATES.

194

Chap.
X.

leaders
cracy,^

and re-introducers of the Athenian demoand Lyco,2 an orator otherwise unknown. The

have considered
friends of Socrates appear at first to

condemnation impossible

his

was formerly the


Hermann. It ap-

as
custom, see

Me'XiTos,

pears by a comparison of
various passages, that the accuser of Socrates is neither the

Forchhammer
as
to be, nor the op-

politician,

makes him
ponent

with

Andocides,

of

others have identified


yet the poet mennor
him,
tioned by Aristophanes (Frogs,

whom

1302), but some younger man,


perhaps the son of the poet.
1
Further particulars about
him are given by Forchliammer,

They
and Hermann, 9.
79
are gathered from Plato, Meno,
Schol. in Plat. Apol. 18,
90, A.
adv.
adv. Dard. 8
lAfsias
B.
hoc. adv. Callim,
Agorat. >78
;

23
p.

Pint. Herod, malign. 26, 6.


862; Coriol.c.l4; Aristotle in
;

Haiyoh-ates v. 5eKaC<a'' Schol.in


^schin. adv. Tim. 87 Diod.
He is mentioned by
xiii. 64.
;

Xenopli. Hell. ii. 3, 42, 44, as


well as by hocrates, 1. c, as a
leader of the Democratic party,
together with Thrasybiilus.
2 For the various conjectures

about him

Hermann,
above-named

consult

p. 12. Besides the

persons a certain Polyeuctus,


according to Favorinus in Diog.
in assisting
ii. 38, took part
"Plwtos
ProDably
accuser.
the
ought to be written in this
passage instead of UoXievKTos,
in the following passage
noAueuKTos instead of "'Avuros,
TloXvevKTos being here probably

and

he was himself

still

transcriber's

mistake

for

See Hermann, p.
But the words as they
14.
stand must be incorrect. The
Polycrates
celebrated orator
is said to have composed the
speech of Anytus, JDiog. 1. c.
Hermippus
to
according
Or. xxiii. 296, 6;
Themist.

TVo\vKparT]s.

Hypoth. in
Quintil. ii. 17, 4
^jsch. Socrat.
Busir.
Epist. 14, p. 84 Or. Suidas,
two
of
knows
UoXvKpdTTis
;

Isoc.

and it is proved
speeches
beyond doubt by Isocr. Bus. 4
u^an, V. H. xi. 10, that he
drew up an indictment against
But it is also clear
Socrates.
from Favorinus, that this indictment was not used at the
Indeed it would appear
trial.
from Favorinus that it was not
written till some time after
;

the death of Socrates. Conf.


Ueherweg, Gesch. d. Phil. i. 94.
3 This is proved by the Euthyphro, allowing, as Scldeiermacher, PI. Werke, i. a, 52, and

Werke, ii. 191


and 199 do., that this dialogue
was hastily penned after the be-

SteinliaH, Plato's

ginning of the trial, its object


being to prove that Socrates,
though accused of impiety, had
a deeper piety and a keener
appreciation of the nature ol
piety, than one who had incurred ridicule by his extravagances, but had nevertheless
brought himself into the odour
of sanctity a view which, not;

THE ACCUSATION.
under no misapprehension as
to the danger which
threatened him.' To get up a
defence, however, went

contrary to his nature.^

Partly considering

and undignified to attempt


anything
simple truth

it

wro^g

except

bv

partly finding it impossible


to move
out of his accustomed groove,
and to wear a form of
artificial oratory strange
to his nature, he tliought
trustfully to leave tl,e
issue in the hands of
God
convinced that all would turn
out for the best ; and
m_ this conviction
confidently familiarising
;

himself
with the thought that death
would probably bring
him more good than harm, and
that an unjust condemnation would only save him
the pressure of tlie
weakness of age, leaving his
fair name
unsullied.'

and

dialo<?ue to

when' the

Ms
'

k n?

GroteWHato

""""'

se?ioiLes.^>f
''

wL felt

Comp. Xen

Plato,

Apol

iv R

19^?
a

^InXen.ilem

c^n

say"] at when'hewtw
tothinklboiftM Te^ce \^^
^aiix6v,ou opposed him
wl t

cording to

Sr

ii

To'-

ctt

30; xi. 1, 11 ./^i^,'!'"; ^4'


2; .W. Floi'il 7 56 he dp
clined a speech which Tv^t"
offered hinJ 'it i^
^serted
Plato, Apol. 17
B

bv

tW S

^^^^^^^>'

' truth

"'''

P^^'

^-

'

iv.

^'^
3*' C.,

'

8,

4-10.

however,

^"^^^'edit for a great deal


^^Iculation than can be

0?^^'"^
1

^^'^^^

^' ^' N^n^";.''


^^' ^-

fern.
^^^
Cousm and Grote,
^"'"^^

iv

crates

'='-''

.^^''-

A '-*,
9"i V:
A.

39

'^-"^

-Vf
a^^

"""

Mem

^! "*"^

crates the above seems


to fol-

belono- in ^ \\-^

full

position

28, A.; 86

"/'^

''''^.

?""''''' ^'"

t^'^^'^"^'
^^^^^

i""'^
^^^^

V^^

"^'^^^

'^^^^^^".^-

*^^^

^est of

Cousin ((Euvres

'^i-'^tes

was aware

must perish

in the con-

I
f/^Vyj^h his age, but

f. ^\

lie for^^ets

explanation given in
^^^'^^f.^^Pi".^y, 29. B., is only

Chap.
X.

SOCRATES.

196

Such was the tone of mind which dictated

Chap.
X.

defence.^

(2) Socrates' de-

fence of
himself.

sen

(Damon,

The language
d. Sokr.

15),

is

in

attempting to prove from Mem.

Apol. 19, A., that So4


crates had predicted his condemnation, forgets that in these
passages the question is only as
iv. 4,

Even
probable guesses.
asserting,
in
far
too
goes
Grote
in his excellent description of
the trial (Hist, of Greece, viii.
654), that Socrates was hardly
anxious to be acquitted, and
that his speech was addressed
far more to posterity than to
his judges. History only warto

rants the belief, that with magnanimous devotion to his cause


Socrates was indifferent to the
result of his words, and endeavoured from the first to
reconcile himself to a probably
It does
unfavourable result.
he
that
follow
however,
not,
was anxious to be condemned
nor have we reason to suppose
wished
so, since he could have
for nothing which he considered
to be wrong, and his modesty
kept him uncertain as to what
was the best for himself. See
Plato, Apol. 19, A.; 29, A.;
We cannot,
30, D.; 35, D.
;

therefore, believe with Grote,


had well
p. 668, that Socrates
considered his line of defence,
and chosen it with a full conthat
sciousness of the result
;

in his conduct before the court


lie

was actuated only by a wish

to display his personal greatness and the greatness of his

mission in the most emphatic


and that by departing
this life when at the summit
to
of his greatness he desired

manner

his

not that of a criminal,

give a lesson to youth the most


impressive which it was in the

power

of

man

to give.

To pre-

suppose such calculation on the


part of Socrates is not only
contradictory to the statement
that he uttered his defence
without preparation, but it
appears to be opposed to the
picture which we are accustomed to see of his character.
As far as we can judge, his conduct does not appear to be a
work of calculation, but a
thing of immediate conviction,
a consequence of that uprightness of character which would
not allow him to go one step
His
beyond his principles.
principles, however, did not
allow him to consider results,

since he could not know what


result would be beneficial to
It was his concern to
him.
speak only the truth, and to
despise anything like corrupt-

ing the judges by eloquence.


This, may appear a narrowminded view, but no other
course of conduct would so
well have corresponded with
the bearing and character of
and herein consists
Socrates
his greatness, that he chose
what was in harmony with
himself in the face of extreme
danger, with classic composure
and unruffled brow.
We possess two accounts of
the speech of Socrates before
his judges, a shorter one in
Xenophon and a longer one in
Xenophon's
Plato's Apology.
;

'

Apology is certainly spurious,


and with it any value attach-

HIS DEFENCE.
wishing to save his
biter,
ing to

who would
tlie

mogenes, to

life,

but that of an impartial ar-

dispel erroneous notions

testimony of Her-

whom the compiler,

by a simple

tation of
prejudices, which
lasted undeniably (according
to the testimony of Xemplwn,

imitating the Mem. IV. \ 4,


professes to be indebted for
his information, is lost. Touch-

Mem.

i.

Symp.

ing Plato's, the current view


seems well established, that
this Apology is not a mere
creation of his own, but that

6,

much to his condemnation.


He misses, with Steinhart in
Plato, many things which So-

in all substantial points


it
faithfully records what Socrates
said and the attempt of Georgii,
in the
introduction to his
;

'translation

1, 11;
(Eg. 12, 8:
6) till after his own

death, and perhaps contributed

might have said in his


defence, and did actually say
according to the Apology of
crates

Xenophon.

But to

this state-

the Apology ment no importance


can be
(conf. SteinJiart, Platon.Werke,
attached, and it is probable
ii. 235) to prove the
contrary that in an unprepared
speech
will not stand.
Georgii com- Socrates omitted
much
which
plains that in the Socrates of might
have told in his favour.
Plato that fieyaKrjyopia is want- He
can hardly be convinced
ing,which Xenophon commends that
Socrates cross-questioned
in him a j udgment with which
Miletus so searchingly as Plato
few will agree, not even the describes
but this passage
writer of the Apology attriagrees with the usual character
buted to Xenophon. He also of the
discourse of Socrates,
considers
the sophism with and the sophism
by which Sowhich the charge of atheism crates
proved that he did not
was met, improbable in the corrupt
youth is quite his own.
mouth of Socrates, though it See
p. 141.
That Socrates
may just as likely have come should have
met the cliarge of
of

from him as from one of his atheism


by quibbles, instead
He doubts whether appealing to the fact of of
his
Socrates could have maintained reverence
for the Gods of the
a composure so perfect
alstate, he can only understand,
though all that we know of by supposing
that we have here
Socrates shows unruliled calm an
expression of Plato's relias a main trait in his character.
gious views
altliough Plato
He sees in the prominent fea- would have
had no reason for
disciples.

tures of that character a diplomatic calculation, which otiiers


will look for in vain.
He considers it incredible that Socrates should have begun with

a studied (j notation from the


Clouds of Aristophanes, aiming
at nothing else than tJio
refu-

suppressing the fact, supposing


Socrates had really made such
an appeal
he even describes
the devotion of his master to
the Gods of his country, and is
himself anxious to continue
that service.
Touchino- the
sophisms, even Aristotle^ m\QX.
:

Chap.
X.

SOCRATES.

198

Chap.
^'

setting forth of the truth, or of a patriot warning

He

and overhaste.

against wrong-doing

seeks to

convince the accuser of his ignorance, to refute the


At the same time dignity
accusation by criticism.
so far forgotten as to address

and principle are never

the judges in terms of entreaty.

not feared, whatever


service of Grod,

and

may

it

is

His
Gondemna'

(3)

tion.

He

is

stands in the

determined to keep

faithless to his higher calling, or

his post in

make
prevent him

No commands

the face of every danger.

him

be.

Their sentence

shall

from obeying G-od rather than the Athenians.


The result of his speech was what might have
have' been expected.

The majority

of the judges

would most unmistakeably have been disposed to


pronounce him innocent,^ had not the proud bearing
of the accused brought

members of a popular

him

into collision with the

tribunal, accustomed to a very

deportment from the most eminent statesMany who would otherwise have been on his

different

men.^
ii.

23

1419,

iii.

a, 8,

18

1398,

a,

15

has no fault to find,

Plato's
literallj-

intention to record
the words of Socrates,
may be satisfied witt

The same may be said in reply


most of the reasoning of

and we
comparinghis Apology with the

On the contrary, the


Georgii.
difEerence in style between the
Apology and Plato's usual writings, seems to prove that this

speeches in Thucydides, as
bearing ir
Steinhart does,
mind what Thucydides, i. 22,
says of himself,that he hac
kept as close as possible to tht
sense and substance of what
and applying i1
was said
equally to Plato. Conf Uehcrweg, Unters. d. Plat. Schr. 237
*
Xen. Mem. iv. 4. 4.
- Let the attitude of Pericles
be remembered on the occasior
of the accusation of Aspasia
and that depicted by Plato ir

to

Apology was not drawn up with


his usual artistic freedom, and
the notion of Georgii referring
as the
it to the same time
Phsedo appears altogether inconsidering the
conceivable
great difference between the
two in regard to their philosophical contents and their artisIt certainly was not
tic form.

HIS SENTENCE

AND DEATH.

199

side were set against him,

the sentence of

Griiilty

and by a small majority


was pronounced.^ According

the Apology, 34, C. Indeed it


a well-known fact that judging- was
a special hobby of
the Athenian people
(conf.
Aristophanes in the "Wasps,
Clouds, 207), and that
it
watched with peculiar jealousy
this attribute
of its
sovereignty.
How VolquarcUen,
Diimon. d. Sokr. 15, can conclude from the above words
that Hcgels judgment respecting Socrates' rebellion against
the people's power is shared
here, is inconceivable.
According to Plato, Apol.
is

'

he would have been acquitted if 3, or as another


reading has it, if 80 of his
judges had been of a diflPerent
mind. But how can this be
reconciled with the statement
36, A.,

of

Diog.

ii.

41

KarediKoia-dr}

oySo-qKoyTa fxia TrXeloai


ruu avoKvovauiu ? Either

SittKocriais

^r]<pois

the text here must be corrupt,


or a true statement of Diogenes
must have been strangely perverted.
Which is really the
case it is difficult to say.
It is
generally believed that
the
whole number of judges who
condemned him was 281. But
since the Heliaja always consisted of so many hundreds,
most probably witli the addition of
one deciding voice
(400, 600, 600, or 401, 501, 601),
on this hj^othesis no proportion of votes can be made out

which

compatible
with
whichever
reading is adopted. We should
have then to suppose with
Plato's

is

assertion,

Bock, in Siivern on Aristoph.

Clouds, 87, tliat a number of


the Judges had abstained from
voting, a course which may be
possible.
Out of 600 Heliasts,
281 may have voted against
and 275 or 276 for him. It is,
however, possible, as Bockh
suggests, that in Diogenes, 251
may have originally stood instead of 281.
In this case
there might have been 251
against and 245 or 246 for the
accused,
making
together
nearly 500
and some few,
supposing the board to have
;

been complete at first, may


have absented themselves during the proceedings, or have
refrained from voting.
Or, if
the reading rpiaKovra, which
has many of the best MSS. in
its favour, is established in
Plato, we may suppose that the
original text in Diogenes was
as follows
/toTeSucao-^Tj 5m/co:

oySoriKovTa xprjcpois,
ruv airoAvovauv.
(Tiais

We

|'

irkeio(n

should
then have 280 against 220,
together 500, and if 30 more
had declared for the accused,
he would have been acquitted,
the votes being equal.
2 This course of events is
not
only in itself probable, taking
into account the character of
the speech of Socrates and the
nature of the circumstances,
but Xenophon (Mem. iv. 4, 4)
distinctly asserts that he would
certainly have been acquitted
if he had in any way condescended to the usual attitude
of deference to his judges. See
also Fl(ito, Apol. 38, D.

chap.
^

200

SOCRATES,

Chap,
X.

to the

Athenian mode of procedure, the next thing


was to treat of the measure of the penalty. Socrates,
however, spoke out with undaunted courage were
he to move for what he had deserved, he could only
:

move

for a public

entertainment in the Prytaneum.


repeated the assurance that he could not on any
account renounce his previous course of life. At

He

length, yielding to the entreaties of his friends, he


was willing to consent to a fine of thirty minse, be-

cause he could pay this without owning himself to


It may be readily understood that to
the majority of the judges such language in the accused could only appear in the light of incorrigible

be guilty.

obstinacy and contempt for the judicial office


f hence
the penalty claimed by the accusers was awarded

sentence of death
(4) Hix
death.

.^

The sentence was received by Socrates with


composure corresponding with

He

persisted in not in any

his previous conduct.

way repenting of

his con-

duct, frequently expressing before the judges


conviction, that for
tune.^

him death would be no

his

misfor-

The execution of the sentence being delayed

'
The above is stated on the
authority of Plato's Apolog}-,
in opposition to which the less
accurate assertion of Xenophon, that he rejected any
pecuniary composition, and
that of Diog. ii. 41, cannot be
allowed to be of any weight.
2 How
distinctly
Socrates
foresaw this effect of his conduct is unknown. It may have
appeared probable to him but
he may also have anticipated
;

the more readily a contraiy


he thought such conduct imperative.
Nietzsche's
idea (Sokrates Bas. 1871, p. 17)
that Socrates, with full consciousness, carried through his
condemnation to death, appears
untenable for the same reasons
as the above.
^ According to Biog. ii. 42, it
was carried by eighty more
votes than his condemnation.
* Plato, Apol.
38, C.
all

effect, if

'

lim SENTENCE

AND DEATH.

pending the return of the sacred-ship from Delos,^


he
continued in prison thirty days, holding his
accus-

tomed intercourse with

his friends,

and retaining

during the whole period his unclouded


brightness
of disposition.^ Flight from prison,
for which his

had made every preparation, was scorned as


wrong and undignified.^ His last day was spent in
quiet intellectual conversation, and when
the evening
came the hemlock draught was drunk with a strength
of mind so unshaken, and a
resignation so entire,
friends

that a feeling of wonder and admiration


overcame
the feeling of grief, even in his
nearest relatives.^
Among the Athenians, too, no long time after his
death, discontent with the troublesome
preacher of
morals is said to have given way before
remorse,

m^ consequence of which his accusers


were visited
with severe penalties ; ^ these statements,
however,
Mem.iv.8,2;P^i2^o,Phffido,

2^*1
J
^r.
T.
Phffido, 59, D.
^^

Mem. 1. c.
^^lV:JT,l-^GCordmgio

^.

J^to

Crito urged him to flight.


ine .picurean Idomeneus, who
saysitwas ^schines(Z>/^.^. ii.
Du; 111. 6b) IS not a trustworthy authority.

bompare the Phasdo, the


iccoimt in which appears to be
n^a

^,

t^t"^^"'- ^^^ ^^' ^?


A.; Xe,i. Mem. iv. 8, 2.

J^nether

the

statements

^n. Apol2S 'Dioff.


^han, V. H. i. 16, are
'^?

t\\^loril. 5,
^Too.

if

P'"'''^-

ii.

in

35;

liistori-

'-^^^'^^^

'"^

67, are certainly

xaggerations.
JJiodor. XIV.
lie

37, says that


people repented of having

put Socrates to death, and


attacked his accusers, puttinethem to death without a judi^
cial sentence.
Sni das msiVes
M4\r]Tos (Meletus) die by stoning.
Pint, de Invid. c. 6, p
538, says that the slanderous
accusers of Socrates became so
hated at Athens that the citi-

zens would not light their fires


or answer their questions, or
ba^l^e in the same water with
them, and that at last they
were driven in despair to hane
themselves. Dior/, ii. 43, conf
vi. 9, says that the Athenians

^^o" ''^f^ei'' overcome with compunction, condemned Meletus


to death, banished the other
accusers, and erected a brazen
statue to Socrates, and that

201
Chap.
^'

SOCRATES.

202

Chap.
X.

are not to be trusted, and appear on the whole improbable.^

B. The
cause of
this sen-

tence of

condemna-

of

The circumstances which brought about the deatt


Socrates are among the clearest facts of history

Nevertheless the greatest difference of opinion prevails

^'^*
(X) I^

justice of his

not the
work of
the Sojfhists.

which led thereto and tht


condemnation. In former times it was

as to the causes

tion.

Anytus was forbidden to


foot in their city.
Or. XX. 239, says

set

Themist.

The Athenians soon repented of this


Meletus was punished,
deed
Anytus tied, and was stoned at
Heraclea, where his grave may
still
be seen.
TcHullian,
Apologet. 14, states that the
Athenians punished the accusers of Socrates, and erected
to him a golden statue in a
temple. Aug. De Civ. Dei, viii.
3, reports that one of the accusers was slain by the people
and the other banished for
:

life.

This view, already expressed by Forchammer (1. c. 66)


and Grote, viii. 683, appears
to be the correct one notwithstanding Hermann's (I.e. 8, 11)
arguments to the contrary.
For though it is possible that
political or personal opponents
'

of Anytus and his fellow-accusers may have turned against


them their action against Socrates, and so procured their

condemnation, yet (1) the authorities are by no means so


ancient or so unimpeachable
that we can depend upon them.
(2) They contradict one another in

all their details,

not to

mention Diogenes' anachronism


respecting Lysippus.

And

(3)

the main point

is, that neithe:


Plato, nor Xenophon, nor th(
writer of Xenophon 's Apology
ever mention this occurrence
which they could not hav(
failed to regard with grea1
satisfaction.
On the contrary
five years after the death oj

Socrates Xenophon thought 11


necessary to defend him againsi
the attacks of his accusers
while Ji^schines appealed to th(
sentence on Socrates withoul
dreading the very obvious
answer, that his accusers had

met with

their deserts. Thai


Isocrates is referring to this
occurrence rather than to anj
other (Trepi avri^Sff. 19) is not
established, nor need the passage contain a reference to anj
event in particular. And lastly,
nothing can be made of the apocryphal story coming from some
editor of Isocrates, to the eifect

that the Athenians, ashamed


of having put Socrates tc
death, forbad any public mention of him, and that when
Euripides (who died sevec
years before Socrates) alluded
to him in the Palamedes, all tht
audience burst into tears. H
is only lost labour to suggesi
that these scenes took place a1
some later time, when the pla}
was performed.

CAUSES OF THE SENTENCE.

203

thought quite natural to refer it to an accidental out-

Were Socrates the colourless

burst of passion.

ideal of

virtue he was represented to be

by those lacking a
deeper insight into his position in history, it would indeed be inconceivable that any vested interests could
have been sufficiently injured by him to warrant a
serious attack.

If then, he was nevertheless accused

and condemned, what

else can have been the cause


but the lowest of motives personal hatred ? Now

who can have had so much reason for hatred as the Sophists, whose movements Socrates was so effective
in
thwarting, and who were otherwise supposed to be caipable of

any crime

Accordingly

at their instigation that

it

must have been

Anytus and Meletus induced

Aristophanes to write his play of the Clouds, and afterwards themselves brought Socrates to trial.

This was the general view of the learned in former


times.
Nevertheless its erroneousness was already
'

pointed out by Freret.^


child

much

He

proved that Meletus was


when the Clouds was acted, and that at a

later period

Anytus was on good terms with Sothat neither Anytus can have had anything to
lowith the Sophists Plato always representing
him

Jrates

their inveterate

IS

J^rith

'

i49,

Aristophanes

enemy and
;

r\i,
In
the admirable treatise:
)bservations sur les Causes et
-,

urquelquesCirconstancesdela
.ondamnation de Socrate, in
lie
Mem de 1 Academic des
nscript.

1.

47, 6, 209.

nor Meletus

and he showed, that no writer

Reference to Brucker, i.
in preference to
any

despiser

Meno, J)2, A.
Aristophanes often amuses
himself at tlie expense of the
poet Meletus, but, as has been
remarked, this Meletus was
probably an older man than
the accuser of Socrates. See
Hermann, De Socr. Accus 5

SOCRATES.

204
Chap,

of credit knows anything of the part taken by


Sophists, in the accusation of Socrates.^

the Sophists,

who had

little or

no

th<

Besides

political influenc<

in Athens,^ could never have procured the condeni'

nation of Socrates.
preferred

against

recoiled on their

would they hav(


charges which immediately

Least of

him
own

all,

These arguments o
unnoticed/ have latterh

heads.^

Freret's, after long passing

met with general reception.^ Opinions are other


wise still much divided, and it is an open questioi

whether the condemnation of Socrates was a work o


private revenge, or whether it resulted from mor(
general motives

were

if

the latter, whether these motivei

or moral, or religious
and lastly
whether the sentence was, according to the popula:
view, a crying wrong, or whether it may admit of
political,

partial justification.^

In one quarter even the lengtl

JEJlicm (V. H. ii. 13), the


\
chief authority for the previous hypothesis, knows nothing about a suborning of
Anytus by the Sophists.
2 The political career of Damon, who according to the use
of the Greek language can be
called a Sophist, establishes
nothing to the contrary.

^Protagorashadbeenindicted
for atheism before Socrates, and

on the same plea Socrates was


attacked by Aristophanes, who
never spared any partizans of
sophistry.
* The treatise of Freret was
written as early as 1736, but
not published till 1809, when
it appeared together with several other of his writings.
See

Mem. de

I'Acad.

i.

47. 6, 1.

was therefore unknown

to

th(

German writers of the las


century, who for the most par
follow the old view
for in
stance, Meiners, Gesch. d. Wis
senschaft, ii. 476
Tiedemann
Geist d. spek. Phil. ii. 21
Others, such as Buhle, Gesch
;

Phil.
i.
372
Tenneman
Gesch. d. Phil. ii. 40, confin<
themselves to stating genC'
rally, that Socrates made man]
d.

enemies by his zeal for mO'


without mentioning t"i(

rality,

Sophists.
^ There are a few exceptions
such as Heinsms, p. 26.
^ ForcUlmmmer: Die Athene]

und Socrates, die Gesetzlicher


und der Kevolutionar.

PERSONAL HATRED NOT THE ONLY CAUSE.


been reached of asserting with Cato,i
that of all
;entences ever passed, this was the
most strictly legal.
Among these views the one lying nearest to hand,

205

las

that of

some older

ution of Socrates

who

writers,

to

attribute the exe-

personal animosity

always

up the unfounded idea that the


Sophists were
any way connected therewith.^
A great

:iving
Q

deal
favour of this aspect of the
case.
Socrates expressly declares that

said

'lato,3

may

is

however

lato hints

said,

Even Anytus,
owed him a personal grudge!

at his

being aggrieved with the judgments passed by Socrates


on Athenian statesmen
ad, according to Xenophon's
Apology,-' took it amiss
^

This* is^^fiunf 'in

^sch

d 'phn

940

7,

^:T'

those who considered


philosophy incompatible
^h ancient
discipline and
rahty, and those who could
endure his moral earnesttte

inclines to the same'

vSw]

how unpopular Sotes must have made


himself
his siftino- of men
Ho
proves

iarks

that^^Athenrwas the

r^^

^^^^^ '""^^'^

^*

^^^^1^ have
it on so

,^^^^P|bleto carry

lations to CritL and


Alcibia
des, and partly in the
hatred o^
""^ ""^^^^^
of
-^
^

Anytus.
3
^

^pol. 28, A.

Meno,

U m

22

Commro t-M^Vt-

Gesch

Phi7 V

2'?

reievit

fJ^^Ur .ir^o^^
09'

.^^'
Hi!t Af n
"' ""''''"' ""^- ^^^'

rr

__5l__
(2) It did

'efedfroui
P^^'-'^oml'

~''y'

^Z^

In ^Zrlh'!'
''^''"'^''

he is not the
ictim of Anytus or Meletus, but
of the ill-will which
e incurred by his criticism
of men.
.

Chap

to

^^''
,

/^'^'
^''''^^

SOCRATES.

206

him

that Socrates urged

Chap.
^'

to give his competent soe

a higher training than that of a dealer in leather,

Anytus

tent with his trade. ^

moved Aristophanes

man

young

the

thereby encouraging in

discon-

said to have

is

firsi

to his comedy, and afterwards

ii

with Meletus to have brought against hin


That such motives cam(
the formal accusation. ^

common

into play in the attack on Socrates, and contributec


in no small degree to the success of this attack

antecedently probable.^
"

ignorance

is

To convince men

ii

of thei]

the most thankless task you can choose

Anyone who can persevere in

it for

a life-time so re

gardless of consequences as Socrates did,

must mak(

many enemies dangerous enemies too, if he takes fo:


his mark men of distinguished position or talents.
;

(&)

Still personal

But

^haveUen
other

txon.

cause of his condemnation.

statements

worktT
lead to

^^^^

animosity cannot have been

are Plato'

Indeed the mor<


upon us.
pupils became convinced of th(

binding

Socrates and his

Ms justice of

Nor

thi

Ms

cause, the less were they able to dis

cover any grounds in fact for the accusation.

Th(

one wish of Socrates being to will and to do what wa


best, what reason could anyone possibly have had fo

Ale.

762

writers

Later

details.
c.
;

give

According
4 Amator.

and

to

more
Pint,

17, 27, p.
Satyi'us in Atlienceus,
;

Anytns was a lover


of Alcibiades, but was rejected
xii. 534, e,

by him, whilst Alcibiades


showed every attention to Socrates, and hence the enmity
Such
of Anytus to Socrates.

an improbable story ought no


to have deceived lAizac (D
Socr.
since

Give,

133)

Xenophon

especiall;

and

Pl?.t

would never have omitted

i]

silence such a reason for th


accusation,
^
1.

jEliaiiy V.

H.

ii.

13.

Dio(f

c.
^

Compare

Grote,

1.

c.

638.

PERSONAL HATRED NOT THE ONLY CAUSE.


apposing him, except wounded pride

The narrative

ofXenophon's Apology would at most only


explain
the hatred of Anytus
it would not account for
the
;

wddely spread prejudice against

pestion whether

Socrates.

It is a

is true at all ;
and whether,
granting its truth, this personal injury
was the only
3ause which arrayed Anytus as
accuser against him.^
Lastly, allowing, as was undoubtedly
the case, that
Socrates made enemies of many
influential people, is

it

t not strange that their personal


animosity should

mly have attained its object after the


re-establishnentof order in Athens?
In the most unsettled
tnd corrupt times no serious
persecution had been
et on foot against him.
Neither at the time of the
Qutilation of the Hermae, had
his relations witli
dcibiades

nor after the battle of Arginus*,^


;
had
he incensed state of popular
feeling been turned
gainst him.
Plato, too, says ^ that what told
against
cerates at the trial, was the
general conviction that
teaching was of a dangerous character
;
and he
:ates that as matters then
stood, it was impossible for
ay one to speak the truth in
political matters withiit being persecuted
as a vain babbler and
corrupter
is

^e

.t

This is just possible. That


character of Anytus was

ummpeachable we gather

om

the story (Anstot.m//.,,.-

'^'^'r/^'^^^'^^.^Tfr'^^^^Plut. Coriol.
14), that
hen he was tirst charged
jh treason he corrupted the
,

^r
'rVin^l;:
(in caliira. 2,\)
'.n'n'"^'
praises

for

being together wi(h

Thrasybuhis

faithful

to

the

and not abusinos


j,olitical power to make
amends
for his losses durinothToli
^'"
treaties,

fe^archical

^''

governmenf.

The astonishment exnres


sed by Tenneman at th^s i"
'^

fro^lX |x.in of ew
his solutionT^l^'dTffi.-

rmtural

Only

culty

is hardly satisfactory
Apol. 18, B. ; 19 B. 23, D.
;

207

SOCRATES.

208

Chap.
^-

testimony of writers so

of youtli.^

On

opposite as

Xenophon and Aristophanes proves that

this point the

the prejudice against Socrates was not merely a passing prejudice, at least not in Athens, but that it

lasted a whole life-time, not confined only to the

masses, but shared also by

and influence in the

state.

the feeling against

Athens,

men

of high importance

Very deeply, indeed, must

Socrates have been rooted in

Xenophon found it necessary six years


death to defend him against the charges on

if

after his

which the indictment was framed.

\Yith regard to Aristophanes, it was an obvious


blot in his plays to allow here and there such a pro-

minence to political motives as to forget the claims


of art, and for a comedian, who in his mad way holds
up to ridicule all authorities divine and human, tc

clothe himself with the tragic seriousness of a poliYet it is no less an error to lose
tical prophet.2

sight of the grave vein which underlies the comi(


license of his plays, and to mistake his occasiona

pathos for thoughtless play. Were it only this, th(


hollowness of the sentiment would soon show itsel
in artistic defects.
patriotic sentiment

496

Instead of this, a sincerity o

may be

Polit. 299, B. Kep. vi. 488,


C -Apol. 32, E. ; Gorg.

473'

521

D.

'R5t'scher's spirited description suffers from this onesided-

and even Hegel, in his


passage on the fate of Socrates,
Gesch. d. Phil. ii. 82, is not
quite free from it, although

ness,

observed in Aristophanes

both of them justly recognisi


560
{Hegel, Phanomeno 1.
JEsthetik, 537, 562 Botscher
p. 365), that there is an ele
ment subversive of Greek life
quite as much in the comedie
in th
of Aristophanes, as
;

things of
complains.
state of

which

h^

PERSONAL HATRED NOT THE SOLE


CAUSE
not only in the unsullied
beauty of
utterances;' but the same

many

individual

patriotic interest sounds

through

all

his plays, in

some of the earlier ones


even disturbing the purity
of the poetic tone,^ but

provmg

all

the

more

conclusively,

how near

ot his

the love

country lay to his heart.


This interest only could have

brought him to give


comedies that political turn,
by means of
which, as he justly takes
credit to
to his

himself,'

comedy

?ained a far higher ground


than had been allowed to it
by his predecessors. At the
same time it must be
rranted that Aristophanes is
as
)thers

much

deficient as

the morality and the faith


of an earlier
ige," and that it
was preposterous to demand
the
'Men time back, men and
circumstances having so

horoughly changed. Only it


does not follow hererom that he was not sincere
in this demand.
His
'as rather one of
those cases so frequently
met with
3 history, in which
a man attacks a principle
in
thers to which he has
himself fallen a victim, withat

owning

it

^.novations in

to himself.

Aristophanes combats

morals, politics,

religion,

and

art.

lemg, however, in his inmost


soul the offspring
of
age, he can only combat
3

>d

them with the weapons


With the thorouoh

the spirit of this age.


slike of the narrow
practical
,'

f^ee p. 29.

Compare

ScJimtzer,

mjelcker,

Suvern

trans-

and

man

unable to give^a

CloudTS?
seems io go too

'

^^^'P''

"''
far.

^^^^J

*^'"''

209

SOCRATES.

2JQ
CHAP,
S-

immediate needs, he
thought to anything beyond
analyse moral and poliproscribes every attempt to
their reasonableness or the
tical motives, or to test
he thinks nothmg of
reverse; whilst as a poet

provided the
with truth and good manners,
He thus becomes entangled
desired end is reached.
demanding back, and yet bj
in the inconsistency of
the old morality
one and the same act destroying,
inconsistency cannot b(
That he committed this
it wai
And what a proof of shortsightedness
denied
of culture whicl
attempt to charm back a form

trifling

to

had been

ii-retrievably lost

'.

That he was consciou

cannot be believed. Hardl;


of this inconsistency
which is what som
would a thoughtless scoffer
upon the dangei
would make of him have ventured
Hardly would Plat
Cleon.
ous path of attacking
th
him into the society of Socrates

have brought

a speech full (
Symposium, putting into his mouth
seen in him only a despic
spirited humour, had he
upon Socrat(
If, however, the attack

Lble character.
is

seriously meant,

and Aristophanes

really thougl

rel
a Sophist dangerous alike to
morality-with which character he cloth

to discern in

him

gion and
charges preferred at tl
him in the Cloudsthen the
pretence, and something mo:
trial were not a mere
led to the condemnation
than personal motives
Socrates.
,3. ,r.

ke

the victim,

were ? I
ask further what those motives
charaot
known of the trial and the personal

Do we
that

is

us a choice between t,
:{;y:"y.' of the accusers only leaves
attack on Socrates w
alternatives: either the

NOT CONDEMNED FOR POLITICAL


directed against his
political creed
more generally against his

VIEWS.

in particular, or

whole mode of thought

and teaching in respect


to morals, religion
and
politics.^
Both alternatives are
somewhat alike, still
they are not so alike
that we can avoid
distinguishing
*^^^^ ""^^ ^"^ '^^^ i"
fevour of the view
.K
tF""^^
that
the attack on Socrates
was in the first place
set
on foot : the interest
of the democratic
party.
Amongst the accusers, Anytus
is known as one
of the
leading democrats of
that time.3 The
judges, too
are described as men,
who had

been banished and

had returned with


Thrasybulus.^
over, that one of
the charges

We

know, more-

preferred

Igainst

Socrates was, that he

had educated Critias, the


most
unscrupulous and the most
hated of the oligarchical
party ;^ ^schines
tells
the Athenians

'pltty
lou have put to death the
Sophist
Socrates, because'

among the

friends and pupils of


Socrates, who must
have been hated by the
democrats becau.^ of

Zl

^St^t!e^l^^
De

"^^-^^-V-U.

lamnato (Lips. 1738)!'^^


erii (notes to
Clouds, p. 86) of

niJtt

lisseitation

ma;

Gescli. d.

eruml

l>l,il^ ii

Socrates, p. Iw).

otscker,

mal

p.

2o6,

268,

30

^'''^^^'i*'

S'

""

''

2'

P 2

^' '^^^ ^^^^^'^t

sivs

.!.{'

.^ an

ora^'tof'
^^^'' ''^^ ^

ij

l^; i-toc

..idvTimir"

with

mr,

Kpo%, io^ ,
p, F' ?\^-

.Apof

i.

reference to the Clouds


Aristophanes
mnninff,
;

More

i<lehmtc,s //.,, Plat.

Con.,

ff 'T^f "V^?'='* "nd Chris,

Socrate n,stP

''
'^^^

',^?^^^
^"stor-


SOCRATES.
Chap
^-

Such were Charmides,^


^
and Xenophon, who was banished from Athens
sympathies.

aristocratical

about the time of the

of Socrates, perhaps

trial

even in connection therewith, because of his intimacy


with Sparta and the Spartans' friend, Cyrus the
younger. Lastly, one of the formal indictments is
referred to as charging Socrates with speaking disparagingly of the democratic form of election by lot,^
and with teaching his audience to treat the poor with
insolence,'*

by

so frequently quoting the

Each prince

He

fired

of

name

with praise,

arms approved,
or with persuasion moved.

or chief in

words

But if a clamorous vile plebeian rose,


Him with reproof he check'd, or tam'd with blows.*
Charmides, the uncle of
Plato, one of the thirty, was,
according to Xen. Hell. ii. 4,
19, one of the ten commanders
at the Peirteus, and fell on
the same day with Critias in
conflict with the exiled Athe1

nians.
2 Foreliliammer,

p.

84:

he

also mentions Theramenes, the


supporter of the thirty tyrants,
who may have been a pupil of
Socrates without, as Forch-

hammer

will have

it,

adopting

the political opinions of

his

But Biodor., xiv. 5,


from whom the story comes, is
a very uncertain authority.
For Diodorus combines with

teacher.

it the very improbable story that


Socrates tried to rescvie Thera-

menes from the clutches of the


thirty, and could only be dissuaded from this audacious attempt

by

many

entreaties.

Neither

Xenophon nor Plato

mention

Theramenes

among

the pupils of Socrates. Neither


of them mentions an intervention of Socrates on his behalf,
as Plato, Apol. 32, G. does in
another case. In the accusasation brought against the victors at Arginusae, it was Socrates who espoused their cause,
and Theramenes who by his intrigues brought about their

Pseudoplut.

condemnation.
Vit.

Decrhet.

iv.

3,

tells

similar and more credible story


Probably it was
of Socrates.
of him and then
first told
transferred to Socrates.
3

Mem.

Ibid.

i.
i.

2, 9.

2, 58.

5 Iliad, ii.
Forcliham188.
mer, p. 52, detects a great deal
He
more in these verses.
thinks that Socrates was here
expressing his conviction of

CONDEMNEL ON GENERAL GROUNDS.


Taking

all

these facts into account,


there can be no
doubt that, in the trial
of Socrates, the interests
of
the democratic party did
come into play.
Still these motives were
not all.

The indictment
by no means places the
anti-republican sentiments of
feocrates
the foreground. What is
brought against

him

his rejection of the

IS

213

his corruption of youth.i

Gods of his country, and


Those Gods were, however

(4) Be nag
the victim

of Trior e
general
causes.

{a)

were
the necessity of an oligarchical
constitution, and was usinPthe words of Hesiod ^pyov 5'

The

chm'ges
riot

directed
stance, he enumerates
not only against
the
Cntias but Alcibiades
among political
the anti-democratical
pupils of element
ohUu 6vlSos (which the
in
acSocrates ; and he speaks
of the his
cusers also took advantage
teachof),
political activity of
Socrates ing only.
as a plea for not delaying,
but after the battle of
Arginus*
for striking when the time
for
by remarking that the
oliaction came. The real imporgarchs elected on the
council
tance of the quotation
from board their brethren
in politiHomer, he contends, must not
cal sentiments.
It is true the
be sought in the verses
quoted levity of Alcibiades
made him
by Xenophon, but in
those dangerous to the
democratic
omitted by him (II. ii. 192-197,
party, but
his own time he
203-205) the charge was not
never passed for an oligarch,
brought against Socrates
for but for a democrat.
See Xen.
spreading anti -democratic
senMem. i. 2, 12; Tkuc. viii.
timents, which Xenophon
63,
alone 48 and 68. With
regard to the
mentions, but for promoting
condemnation of the victors of
the establishment of
an oli- Argmusai, Athens
had then not
garchical form of government.
only partially, as Forchhammer
This is, however, the very
op- says, but altogether
shaken oif
posite of historical
criticism.
the oligarchical constitution
of
If t orchhammer
relies upon the
Pisander. This may be
gathered
statements of Xenophon, how

he at the same time assert


hat they are false in most
imwrtant points?
And if on
he other hand he wishes
to
trengthon these statements,
10 w can he use
them to upJan

hold

the

ondemns
^'vvever,

view,

by wliich he

them?

^'iidencies elsewliere,

faces of

He

has,

detected oligarcliical

ihem

exist.

where no
For in-

from Fverefs remark, 1. c.


p.
from the account of the

243,

trial

{Xen. Hell.

i.

7), as

well

from the distinct statement

as
of

Plato (Apol.
^
ravTa (Xiu i)v ^ri
rrjs

Tr6\iu>s);

32, C.
koL
^fxoKpaTovfi4urts
not to mention
:

the fact that these


generals
were decided democrats,
and
hence could not have
been
elected by oligarchs.

Rlato,

Apol

2i,

13.

p. 193, 1

SOCRATES.

214
Chap.
X.

not only the Grods of the republican party, but the


If in some few instances, as in the
G-ods of Athens.
trial for the mutilation of the Hermse, insult to the

was brought into connection with attacks on a


republican constitution, the connection was neither a
Grods

necessary one, nor was

it

Further, as

Socrates.

named

in the indictment of

regards

the corruption

of

youth,^ this charge was certainly supported by the

young men contempt


for republican forms of government and aristocratic
insolence, and also that he' was the teacher of Critias.
But the training of Alcibiades was also laid to his
charge, who had injured the city by republican

plea that Socrates instilled into

rather

by

than

opinions.

aristocratic

further

count was, that he taught sons to despise their


action need
fathers,^ and said that no wrong or base

be shunned

Herefrom

(&) Biii

be of advantage.^
would appear that not so

only

if

it

it

much the

the narrower sense of the term, as


the moral and religious character of his teaching was

extended
political character in
toitsnwral

and

re-

ligious

hearings.

The latter

the subject of attack.

aspects exclusively

draw down the wrath of Aristophanes. After all the


ancient and modern discussions as to the scope of the
Clouds,^

it

may

crates of this

be taken

comedy

drawn with a
1

Mem.

Xen. Mem,

i.

for established that

is

2,

49

Apol.

Mem.

i.

2, 56.

Rotscher (Aristophanes, p.
272) gives a review of previous
<

of a

mode of thought

Since then, Droysen]


opinions.
and Schnitzer, Forchhammer,

and Kochly, Akad. Vortr.^


have further gone into the'

p. 25,

20 and 29.
3

not only a representative

poet's license

2, 9.

the So-

1,

question.

CONDEMNED ON GENERAL GROUNDS.

216

which Aristophanes knew to be foreign to the real


man
nor yet was only a general attack thereby
intended on the fondness for metaphysical subtleties,
;

'

;md the absurdity of sophistry and useless learning


but the play was distinctly aimed at the
philosophic
;

tendency of Socrates.

Just as

little

can

it

be sup-

posed, after

what has been said, that this attack


proceeded only from malice or from personal
animosity

Plato's description in the

out of the question.


are

also

Eeisig's

untenable.

Reisig

which Aristophanes

assigns

Symposium puts this


and Wolfs ^ opinions

distributes
to

the traits

Socrates,

between

himself and the whole body of his pupils, Euripides'*


in particular; still the spectators
could not do
otherwise than refer them all to Socrates;

hence

Aristophanes

must have intended

this

reference.

Wolf supposes that the

portrait drawn in the Clouds


of Socrates in his younger years, when
he was
given to natural philosophy.
But the very same
charges were repeated against him eighteen
years
IS

in

later

Apology

the Frogs

and we gather from Plato's

that the current view of Socrates and his


teaching up to the time of his death agreed
substantially with that of Aristophanes
not to mention the
6

As

assumed by G. Herad Nubes, p.


srf, 11, and
by others.
Com)are, on the other hand, Rot'

is

iiann.

elier,

Praaf

p.

294,

273,

307,

311;

mwv/,

p. 3
ITaat. ad

ISubes
Rhein.
(1828) i. K. S. 191.
' In
his translation of the
'louds,
see
Rotschcr,
297.

ilus. ii.

Similarly Van Hensde, CharacConf. Win-

terismi, p. 19, 24.


gers' Sokr. p. 20
*

Who

was

fy^m

'

10 vears^ older
than Socrates, and certainly
not his pupil, although possibly
an acquaintance,
Frogs, 1491.
'->

See'p.' 18.

Chap
X.
^

SOCRATES.

216
Chap.

fact

Socrates

that

natural

attacked

probably never was a lover of

philosophy, and that


as

Sophist

in the Clouds he

is

rather than as a natural

'

philosopher,
(c) Tills is

flwJmH^
a.^sifjfiedto

Aristophanes must, then, really have thought to


discern in the Socrates whom the history of philosohis attack.

p^y sketches features deserving

tlTcioudl this, however,

not

is,

caricature

attributing to
all that,

it

Saying

of course, not saying that he did

the

many

consciously

really foreign features.

we may suppose

his picture agreed

figure,

historical

with

that the
thcj

main

For

features in

idea he had formed to

himself of Socrates, and also with common opinion.!


Siivern, therefore, in supposing that the Socrates of
"^

not meant for an individual, but for a


symbol, and that the poet's attack was not aimed at

the Clouds

is

and rhetorical school in


Far from it, Socrates was

Socrates, but at the sophistic


general,^ cannot be right.

champion of sophistry, because in


Aristophanes' mind he really was that the poet be-

made

to be the

lieved that, taken in his public capacity, he was

he represents him to
Not a single line of his picture has an exclube.
Independently of some
sively political colour.

really the dangerous innovator

things which are obviously not seriously meant,^ the


charges against him are threefold, his being occupied
Clouds, 98.
In the treatise already ref erred to, pp. 19, 26, 30, 55.
3 Not to mention
the false
opinion, which however is supported by Zr<?7'fc&e?'/7 (Alcibiades,
p. 67), that the play was aimed
'

at Alcibiades, who is concealed


under the name of Phidippides.
See, on the contrary, Droysen,
Schnitzer, p. 34.
p. 180
* Such as the calculation ofi
'

flea-jumps.

CONDEMNED ON GENERAL GROUNDS.

217

with useless physical and intellectual subtleties,' his


rejecting the Gods of the city,^ and what is the
corner-point of the whole play, his sophistic facility

Chap.

of speech, which can gain for the wrong side the


victory over the right, and make the weaker argu-

ment the

stronger.3

In other words, the unpractical,


irreligious, and sophistical elements in the
Socratic
teaching are attacked there is not a word about his
;

anti-republican tendency, which Aristophanes, we may


suppose, had he observed, would before all things

have

exposed.

Even

at a later time,'* Aristophanes brings

no other complaints against Socrates than


these.
Only these points, too, according to Plato, constituted
the standing charges against Socrates,
causing him
special danger.*
And there is every reason for believing his assurance.
If then the
theless,
this

impeachment of Socrates has, neverbeen set down to a political motive, how can

admission be made to agree with the previous

{d) Sacra]'^jf/^
'^^^

^'^^k

because of
his anti-

^^^'
2

qfi?~i?n
A
<^iouas,

Al
oon
r.
Droysen,
y.
AowdB, p. 177, unfairly blames
his play for making a stronger
irgument into a right one.
cue hdyos Kpelrrwu is the really
tronger case in point of jusice, according to tlie original
oeaning of the word (Xenoph.
Eg 11. 25 Artst. Rhet. ii. 24),
rtich is however t n-own into
he S],ade by the X6yos Vro,.

nd what
6yoy

meant by rhv t^tto,


Kpelrra, ^oi,7u is, making
IS

le case

which in point of

ce

weaker,

is

to

be

jus-

the

stronger as to the actual re- 'r^^^iblicaii


suit, giving to an unjust act ^^^'''^^' *"^^
as being aii
the colour of justice.
enemy of
Frogs, 1491.
* Apol. 23, D.
hiyovciv i,s ^^^^ 'lood

Sco/cp^TTjy -vis

Siacpdeip^t

^an

t^iapd^rarol Kal
Ka\ eVeiSd,/

robs piovs

ns

ahrohs 4p<,ra,

S,5da,ccoy,

'6

^x'^vai

iroiiiu Ka\

,r,u

'6

oddkv

diruu, dAA' ayvooZcnu, ha 5^ ah


BoKu>a.. anope7u, -rh Kara nduZl
ri)^ <pi\oao<{>o{>uTa,u irpove^pa
rav-

ra KeyooaJ, '6r. .^ '^..'idpJZx


tA
y9,s, Ka\ e.ohs ah uo^U\,^

Ka\ rhu ^rro,

Ibid. 18, B.

Xoyov Hp.irr^

ttol.Tu

^^^ time.

SOCRATES.

218
Chap.

true answer to this question has


The conbeen already hinted at by other writers.^

statement

The

viction of the guilt of Socrates rested on the assumed

dangerous character of his teaching for morality and


religion the reason that this offence was judicially

prosecuted lay without doubt in the special political


The rationalism of the
circumstances of the time.
Sophists was neither the sole nor the chief cause of

the

fall

of Athens in the Peloponnesian war

still it

contributed unmistakeably to that result, and the opponents of the new culture were naturally disposed to

make

Had

guilt out to be greater than it really was.

its

not the schools of the Sophists sent forth not a

few of the modern statesmen, who either as the leaders


of oligarchy or democracy had torn the state to pieces ?
Was not in those schools a corrupt form of morality
publicly taught, which substituted the wishes and
caprice of the individual in place of existing custom

and

religion,

taught

men

summit

of

put gain in the place of right, and


to

desire absolute sovereignty as the

human happiness?

Were not

those

unscrupulous eloquence,
which employed a variety of technical tricks for any
purpose, no matter what, considering it the highest

schools

the

cradle of an

triumph to make the wrong side the winning side ?


Gan we then wonder that Aristophanes thought the
new-fangled education responsible for
tunes of the commonwealth
ymtter,

p.

31.

Ifarhach,

and
185, 9
Schwegler, Gesch. d. Phil. 30.

Gesch. d. Phil.

i.

all

the misfor-

that Anytus in Plato


Clouds, 910; Knights, 1373,

Further

details

Clonds, 24.

in

Suvern.

CONDEMNED ON GENERAL GROUNDS.


cannot find

terms strong

219

enough to express his

Chap.
'

horror of the pernicious influence of the Sophists

good old time believed that in


Sophistry lay the chief malady of the state; and
that all friends of the

that this feeling was intensified during the last years


of the Peloponnesian war,
reign of force
those

Was

it

and under the oligarchial

then other than natural that

who had rescued Athens from the

oligarchy,

re-establishing with the old constitution her political

independence, should wish by suppressing the education of the Sophists to

stop the evil at its source.

jNow Socrates passed not only for a teacher of the

modern Sophistic school, but the

evil effects of his

leaching were thought to be seen in several of his

among whom Critias and Alcibiades were


prominent.^
What more intelligible under such
:'ircumstances, than that just those who were bent
|)iipils,

upon restoring a popular form of government, and


ancient glory of Athens, should see in

the

'orrupter of youth,
le

and a dangerous citizen

him a
Thus

certainly fell a victim to the republican reaction

ikvhich set
E'^or

that his political views were not in them-

all

elvcs

in after the overthrow of the thirty tyrants.

the

ittack.

principal

motives which provoked the

His guilt was rather supposed to consist in

he subversion of ancestral customs

and piety, of

vhich the anti-republican tendency of his teaching


I

Meno,

How

1)1,

C.

largely this

circumtance contributed towards the


''ondemnation of Socrates is

I
'

'

proved by Xen. Mem.

i,

2, 12,

as well as by the above-mentioned authority, ^schines.

SOCRATES.

220
Chap.
X.

was partly an indirect consequence, partly an


manifestation.

How

Justice
of the
C.

sentence.

(1) Unfounded
cliarges.

(a) In relation to
Ids teaching, life,

and
ence.

influ-

isolated

then does

it really

and of the sentence to which


And what must be thought of the moderE

tice of this accusation


it

led

stand touching the jus-

Most of the charges which

attempts to justify it?

were preferred against Socrates, rest undeniably od


misunderstandings, perversions, or false inferencesj
is

said to have rejected the G-ods of the

We

have already seen this statement contran

Socrates
state.

dieted by

all historical

have substituted his

testimonies.^

He

is

said to

Bai/jLovtov in their place.

however, likewise know that he neither put


known

that Hegel
on the side of
Greek law, and Dresig, a hundred years earlier, maintained
in a very superficial treatise,
that Socrates, as an opponent
of a republican government,
had been justly condemned.
*

It is well

has defended

it

Forchhammer goes a great deal


further in his treatise, and so
See p. 178, 3.
does Denis.
Kochly, on the other hand,
confines himself, in Acad.Vortr.
i. 382, to the assertion that in
the indictment of Socrates
guilt was equally divided and

minimum on
to a
The answer of
either side.
Heinsius to Forchhammer (So-

reduced

crates nach dem Grade seiner


Schuld. Lips, 1839) is unimportant, and the learned Apologia
Socratis contra Meliti redivivi

Calumniam, by P. van Limburg


Brouwer (Gron. 1838), is deinto the
in insight
general questions involved, and
ficient

We.)
it

ir

inferior to the treatise o1


Preller (Haller, A. L. Z. 1838;
No. 87), although many of its
Luzae
details are valuable.
de Socrate cive 1796, despite
his usual learning, does little
for the question. Grote's re^
is

marks, on the other hand


touching the extenuating cir
which, withoul
cumstances,
altogether justifying, excuse
the condemnation of Socrates
are deserving of all attention
Grote, Hist, of Greece, viii
678, 653.
2

Forchhammer

repeats

th(

charge without proof, as if it;


truth were obvious of itself
and he speaks of orthodoxy anc
heresy like a modern theolo
But a Greek though
gian.
far less of belief than of out;
ward service, and hence X<?W(?[
phon, Mem. i. 1, 2, refutes th(
charge by an appeal to the fac
that he had sacrificed to tin
Gods.

JUSTICE OF THE SENTENCE.


;he place of the

m the

221

Gods, nor sought thereby to encroach

ground of

Chap.
^'

It was a private oracle

oracles.^

n addition to those publicly recognised and in a


jountry where divine revelations were not
the exclu;

property of the priesthood, a private oracle


could

live

He

refused to no one.^

)e

moted to the

is

said to have

been deheavenly wisdom of Anaxa-

atheistic,

although he expressly declared it to be absurd.^


said according to Aristophanes to
have given
nstruction in the Sophistic art of oratorya
charge

foras,^

le

is

untrue, that to

appearances even Meletus did

all

venture to prefer

lot

He

it.

een the teacher of Critias

is

blamed

for having
and Alcibiades, to which

harge even Xenophon justly replied ^ that


these
aen did not learn their vices from
Socrates, nor
egenerate, until after being separated
from him.
dlowing, too, that a teacher must
instil into his
upils a lasting turn for the good,^ is
it
necessarily

is

fault if

Compare

he does not succeed in some few


cases
p. 76,

7; 89; 149,

\4jr.
X
Xenoplion ^1,
therefore
appeals
1

goodfaih
cratjes'

Id Plato

belief

(Mem.
as

i.

2)
proof of
1,

the Gods,

compares his revela-

P^'^l'^^^^^^^

of
B).

nn
ivthyphro ;j?^
(Euthyphro, 3,
IS indeed known, from
other

urces, how much private dination was practised, besides


>pealing to public oracles.
Not only Aristophanes
but
eletus brings
this
charge
ainst
I,

p.

him
10,

Leben und Schriften,

p. 480).
considers it

Forchhammer

-^^

the 5a.^o.o.

in Plato, Apol. 26,


like Ast (Platon's

incredible that Meletus should

have

given

such

careless

reply to Socrates, he forc^etl


that it is always' the wajof
tlie world to confound
relative
^^ith positive atheism,
doubts

about particular religiourno!


tions with the denial of all re
ligion.
This is quite universal
in the nations of ant in
uitv

and therefore the early Christ'


^
ians were called i.e,o^
*

See p. 135,

Mem.

Forchhammer,

i.

2,

12
p. 43

SOCRATES.

222

CHAP.

X-

estimated
of any instruction can only be
these bear as bright a
^^y its collective effects, and
of Socrates
testimony to the value of the instruction
A man whose beneficial influence
wished.

The value

can be
not only reached to
as

many

by whom
which served

individuals,^ but

morals was laid


as a matter of course,
his people for centuries, was,
the verses o:
'no corrupter of youth. If further
promote usefu
Hesiod, by which Socrates sought to
^ Xenophon has conare alleged against him
a

new foundation

for

activity

clusively proved that an

ill

use has been

made

of these

he has been accused of teaching


h(
men to despise parents and relations, because
worth
maintained that only knowledge constituted
inference from principles
surely this is a most unfair
mouth. Am
which had a simple meaning in his

verses.

If lastly,

teacher

who makes

his

pupil

understand that

become a usefu
must learn something in order to
Onh
in order.
and estimable man, is surely quite
a grudge for making
the rabble can bear the teacher
'

Very different woub


sons wiser than their fathers.
Socrates spoken disparagingly o
it have been had
set lightly by the dut;
the ignorance of parents, or

of children; but

from

so

Plato s Apol. 33, D., menalso


tions a whole string
1

X^rMem.

i.

2, 48.

t\em

.2,56; PZ^l^., Char,


Conf.
p. 212, 4.
163 B
sM^rn i 2 49

A
Mem.'ii. 2, 3.
further charge is connected
w?th the above, viz., that he
4

Tnduced many young

men

to

doing he was far removed.


follow his training rather tlja:
Th
that of their parents.
s Apology al
and attempts to just.
order to decid
But
fy.
whether it is an establishe
fact, and whether Socrates
here to blame, it is mdee
quite possible we need a mor
trustworthy authority, and w

fact
lows,

Xenophon

UNFOUNDED CHARGES.

223

might be replied that one who judged the value of


a man simply and solely by his knowledge, and who at
the same time found all wanting in true knowledge,
was making his pupils self-conceited, and teachIt

ing them to consider themselves above


by their own imaginary knowledge.

all

Chap.

authority

But whilst

with partial eye overrating the importance of knowledge, Socrates avoided this practically harmful inference by above all endeavouring to

conscious of their

make his friends

own want

of knowledge, and laying


no claim to knowledge himself, but only professing
to pursue it.
No fear that any one imbued with
this

of humility and modesty, would misuse


the Socratic teaching.
For its misconstruction and
spirit

for the

consequences of a superficial and defective


conception of it Socrates is as little responsible as
any other teacher.

in

Of more moment is another point touched upon


the judicial proceedings the relation of Socrates

himself to

the

Athenian democracy.

As

is

(J)
affJJ[-'n

well huposi-

known, Socrates considered the existing constitution


llZdTthe
a complete failure.^
He would not have the power ^^^^^^
in the state awarded by lot or by election,
but by the
qualification of the individuals

;
and he occasionally
sxpressed opinions respecting the masses who thronged

the

Pnyx and

filled

the theatre at assemblies of the

people containing no doubt a great deal of truth,


night

to

know

the circumIn the single


Jasc there mentioned, that of
^he son of Anytus, the trutli
)t which appears doubtful.
Sourates probably did not set the
stances

better.

son

against his father, but


urged the father to give him
a better education, or else expressed himself to a third party
to that effect,

See p. 167.

SOCRATES.

224

Chap.^
^-

but coming very near to treason against the soveIt was natural that his
reignty of the people.^
use of such expressions, and
on the
that they should not be without influence
Still a free censure of existing institutions
judges.
accusers should

make

may
by no means treason. Some Grrecian states
very
have confined the liberty of speech within
narrow limits, but at Athens the freedom of thought
and of speecli was unlimited it formed an integral

is

Athenian
portion of the republican constitution ; the
regarded it as an inalienable right and was proud to
be herein distinguished from every other

state.^

In

quarrels there is
the time of the most violent party

no instance of interference with either


or political teaching.

political viewsj

The outspoken

friends of al

Spartan aristocracy could openly stick to theirf


actual attacks^
colours, so long as they refrained from

on the existing state of things

and was

Socratesji

^
not to be allowed the same privilege ?
In the shape of actual deeds nothing, however^
He had never trans-t
could be laid to his charge.
I

In Mem. iii. 7, Socrates attempts to relieve Charmides of


his dread of appearing in publie by reminding him, that the
1

people

whom

he

is

afraid of,

consist of peasants, shoemakers,


nedlars, &c., and therefore do
not deserve such consideration.

The charge preferred by the


Mem. i. 2, 58, that
accuser
Socrates thought it was reasonable for the rich to abuse the
poor, is clearly a misrepresen\lli^^
2

Compare

Plato, Gorg. 461,

E.

603

Demosth. in Androt.
Funebr. 1396.
G.pte s reference to the

il

Platonic state,

1.

c. p.

679,^ in^

which no freedom of mdividual opinion was allowed i^


not altogether to the pomtJ
fundamental ideas ofi
The
Plato's state are different td

Athensii
those then prevailing
reckon^
B.,
viii.
557,
Kep.
Plato,
freedom of speech among thf
evils of a democracy, a type o^
which was the Athenian form
of government.

UNFOUNDED CHABOBS.

g,,^

gressed the laws of the


state.

had

been conscientiously

t.:

"^" ""^*

z. "^H

acUon

On"

His duties as a citizen


fulfilled.
His avowed

.>,

'^^^ ^^

^^- -2

*^^

" P"''*""" '

^'''^

oligarchical

''^^ ^'^'''^ '^^^ '"'^^ ''--dad his


oncel
once
to rescue the victors
at Arginusee
o-ond
lemocrats-fron. the
extrajudicial mer!i s
ofTn i^
^ite,
ffe

unated populace, the


other
ained out

His school,

tin>e

to

prevent an

too, in as far as
it

a school, had no
decided political
e greater nunnber
of his pupils were
lied

e upper

cWs,3

and hence Jrobably

can he

bi"

If

taken from

beWedT
Lt iS,L
:tosrofr:r::j7or-^^
e

aristocratic

'^e^

party,

one of his

^t

no decided

^htical inactivity
has

TX^Tf

been brought against

odern times.
On this head,
ay be passed on him
from

d^fferenT^grn

different poin/s

ZZ]

rr

Mm in

"'^ P^^'^

o/v"e"

'"- forcontinrg

^' "* ""^^^^^g his powers


hi, Ufc
d his
hfe on a career, in
which he would have
a.ned no success,
and for which he
was unfitted

unthtje"o7'
able
offence

*^'^^"'

"

^^

-^^-'y -^

of all to avoid it
under the conviction
that you
do more good to
the state in other

^st

>

''^

to avoid a
statesman's career;

'Z

ways.

^^n.
See

i.

1,

pp.

17.

66;

67;

148;

17^
*

'

^P""^-

^"^'

^'

Chjerephon, ibid.
21,

^^^

P-

r...

"

"

'

"

SOCRATES.

22(3

was to Socrates an
help the state in his own way
His
deepest interest.^
object of the highest and
corresponded with
theories may not have

CH^p

_^1__

political

character as a citizen
existing institutions, but his
according to the
must be admitted to be pure ; and
of no crime against the
laws of Athens, he was guilty

Nor were the

(2) ReUtion home

t^

His whole position was


at variance with th(
as Hegel has so well indicated,^
Th(
morality.
occupied by the old Greek
national form of life
moral life of Greece, like every
It relied partly oi
rested originally on authority.

^^-^^g

to

theancient

""^''''
.-

onlj
political views of Socrates the

^;tiich

gave offence.

the laws of the stat(


the unquestioned authority of
influence of custor^
and partly on the all-powerful
convictions to tb
training, which raised general

and
traceable by no one
rank of written laws of God,
a definite origin.

To oppose

this traditional moralitl

conceit, an offenc
was regarded as a crime and
To doubt i^
against God and the commonweal.
any one, nor wi
rfghtfulness never occurred to

indeed permitted

an

enquiry into

^^

and
its

for this

reason, the need^^

foundations,

of proving

i'

But this law had lo]!


fallen into disuse, if indee^
force, a
had ever been
who can blame Socrates for
rio-Ms.

RK

.TlnM'li

period it
that
offence,
given
mio-ht have
Soorates appeared to hold aloof
questions of
froTthe
Ms time and an appeal might
have been made to the old law
Arist.
of Solon, pL. Sol. c. 20
threaten12,
1,
in Gell. N. A. ii.
ing neutrals in case of an mcivil
ternal quarrel with loss of

pSal

--^-^ --*-\^"ji
conscientiously side withnc

of the conflicting parties


haps it was a pol
^%^' ^^^^V
'

/pU

?P

na^

!
81
i
Gesch. d. PhU. n.

im

llELATION TO THE ANCIENT MORALITY.

necessity, or even of supporting it


spection, was never felt.

227

by personal intro-

Chap.
X.

Socrates, however,

demanded such an enquiry.


allow nothing to be believed, and
have nothing done, until men were first
fully convinced of its
truth or expediency.
For him it is not

ia^~p^

He would

enough

rule, universally recognised

lished,

but the individual must think out


each subject

and discover

its

JXf

to

have a

for himself,

''''*^^

T^,{Ze

and legally estab-

^^ '^^^*^'''^^'

reasons: true virtue and

right action are only possible

when they spring from

personal conviction.

Hence his whole life was spent


examining the. current notions touching
morals, in
nesting their truth, and seeking
for their reasons,
rhis examination brought him
in nearly all points to
:he same results as those
which were
in

established

)y

custom and opinion.

espects clearer

and

7hich he shared in
'f

If his notions were in many


sharper, this advantage was one

common

with the best and wisest

his contemporaries.

Nevertheless, tried by the


tandard of the old Greek morality, his
position seems
ery critical. In the first place the
ordinary morality,

nd the received rules of conduct resting


on authority
nd tradition, were by him deprived

of their chief

In comparison with knowledge, and


the connous virtue of Socrates, they were
so much depreiated, that not only was the
self-love of individuals
urt, but the actual validity
of the laws of
alue.

the state

as called in question.

If

man

has only to follow his

mi convictions, he will agree with


the popular will
ily when, and in as far as,
it agi-ees with his convic-*
ons.
If the two come into collision,
there can be
Q 2

'''

'

SOCRATES.

228

This
which side he will espouse.
Socrates in his deprinciple is candidly avowed by
j
that he would
in his celebrated declaration

no doubt

Chap.
X.

as to

fence,

And thus his


rather than the Athenians.^
and irreconcileviews stand, even in theory, in sharp
It was imposable contradiction to the older view.
aod

obey

therefore

sible

to guarantee, indeed it was highly

agreement
improbable that there would be, a perfect
matter of
between the two in their results, and as a
undeniably
Socrates by his political views was
fact,

opposed to the existing form of constitution.^


the
There can moreover be no mistaking

Less
importance attached to
(Z>)

fact,

Socratic philosophy
that the whole character of the
preponderance given to politi-|
is at variance with the
without which the Greek states could

politics.

cal interests,

range, have achieved,


never, considering their limited
The duty of the individual towards the!
greatness.
was indeed recognised by Socrates to itsf

community

extent.

full

Even

his

friends he

mged

to devote'

when any of them!


their attention to public affairs
keeping back'
showed ability for the task,^ and in
those who were young ^ and unformed,"
meritoriously from the point of view ol

from public
he acted

'

life

Still the maxim that man must be


ancient Greece.
sure of his own mora?
clear about himself, and be
that of others and
well-being before meddling with
of Socratee
the community;^ the conviction

with

only alien to his owr


that a political career was not
^

2
3

Plat. Apol. 29, C.


See p. 167 and 223.

See

p. 167, 3.

Mem.

iii.

216, A.
Plato, 1. c.

Symp.

iv.

Plato

Hm

RELATION TO THE ANCIENT MORALITY.

'2n

character, but impossible, in the


then state of things,
to a man of integrity ;
the whole inward turn

Chap.

given
thought and pursuits, the demand for
self-knowledge, for moral knowledge, for
self-training- all

bo

^_

this

3ould not

but weaken in himself and his pupils


the
nclination for political life.
It could not fail to
nake the moral perfection of the individual
the

main

)oint,

while

reducing activity for the state that


lighest and most immediate
duty of a citizen accordng to the ancient view to a

subordinate and de-

ivative rank.

And,

lastly, if

the charge of rejecting his country's


rods was, as he believed, unjustly
preferred against
Derates, still his theory, it must
be admitted,

was an

xtremely perilous one, as was


seen in the case of
.ntisthenes,
when once the Socratic demand for

nowledge was developed to its


consequences, and
ihgious notions were similarly
dealt with in order
discover what people understood
thereby.
This is
)

ue also

of his 8aifi6vcou,

ideed a place
its

As a kind of oracle it had


on the ground of the Greek faith, but

internal character it

made the decision depend


the subject instead of depending
on external pornts.
And yet how dangerous was this

7
I

proceeding

a country in which oracles were


not only a religious
It a political
institution
How easily might others
led to imitate the example
of Socrates, taking
unsel,
iad of

however, with their own understanding


int
with an undefined inward feeling,
and thus

inking little of belief in the


'

Gods

Rluto, Apol. 31, C.

or of their utter-

{c)

His

^'"''^''"'

7^i.

SOCJRATES.

230

indeed be convinced that Socrates


main, and it is
was in all these points right in the
and founder of
quite true that he was the precursor
could this new
our moral view of the world ; but how
who shared the
idea of right be admitted by any one
the ancient Greek world ? How could

ances

CHAP.

X
*

We may

traditions of

upon these traditions allow such an idea


an act of suicide ?
to be spread, without commiting
and
Even remembering, then, that Socrates laboured

a state built

Sparta oi;
taught in his simple manner, not in the
generation
Lycurgus, but in Athens and amongst the
shall still find it,
that had fought at Marathon, we
to restraii^^^
quite natural for the state to endeavour
For Athens was absolutely ignorant o_

his action.

which Socratej
that freedom of personal conviction,
In such a com
required, nor could she endure it.^
can cans
munity the punishment of the innovator
no surprise.

For was not a dangerous doctrine, ac

the state
cording to old notions, a crime against
tlj
And if the criminal resolutely refused to obey
actually di^
sentence of the judges, as Socrates

T
follow ?
could the penalty of death fail to
Greek view
one therefore starting from the old
of Socrat
right and the state, the condemnation

how

<

cannot appear to be unjust.


To say that the line adopted by Socrates was not opposed
'

to the constitution of Solon,


but was instead a return to
old Greek custom, as Georgii

(Uebersetzung
o-ie,

p.

129)

d. Plat. Apoloasserts, is not

For not only did he


of appointdisapproval
express
ing by lot to public offices.

Correct.

which was,

it is

true,

an inj

tution later than Solon s tin


but he disliked the popu
and
elections of Solon
^nvestigat
free
of
principle
;

is

widely

^^f'^^^f
s times.
spirit of Solon
the remai;ks
^ Compare
Koch on Aristophanes, i. 7.

HIS RELATION TO

A
that

very different question

whether Athens at

it

is

TIME.

time had a right to this opinion, a point which

the defenders of
LIS

THE MORALITY OF HIS

Athens assume

far too readily.^

To

the question appears to deserve an unqualified

legation.

Had
and

a Socrates appeared in the time of

231

Chap.
X.
(3) Relation home
hy his

theory to
the times
in whicJb
he lived.

and had he been condemned


:hen, the sentence might be regarded as a simple
{a)Theold
let of defence on the part of the old morality against
morality
Miltiades

Aristides,

In the period after the was already in a


Peloponnesian war such a view can no longer be state of
admitted.
For where was the solid morality which decay.

he

spirit of

innovation.

Vnytus and Meletus were supposed to defend

kinds of relations, views, and modes of

lot all

Had
life

ong since been penetrated by an individualising


endency far more dangerous than that of Socrates ?
iad not men been long accustomed in place of the
Hegel, 1. c. -g. 100, is here
nost nearly right, although he
'

egards the Athenians excluively as the representatives


tf
the old Greek morality,
rorchhammer, on the contrary,

anything but impartial, in


Qaking the Athenians conservative, and Socrates a revolus

ionary,

and attributing to the


extreme consequences

atter the

those principles, notwithtandinghisprotest. Nietzsche,


00 (Sokr. u. d. Griech.Tragodie,
29), overlooks the difference
'f times in tliinkingthat, when
iocrates had once been imf

).

leached,

liis

condemnation was
were allowed,

[uite just. If this

a word could be said against


he sentence of death.
For,
according to Athenian custom,
lot

when a verdict of guilty had


been brought in, the judges
could only choose between the
jienalty
plaintiff

demanded by the
and that asked for by

the defendant
in the present
case between death and an illusorj fine.
But the question
really is whether Socrates de;

served punishment at all, and


to this question a negative
answer must be given both
from our point of view as well
as from that of his cotemporaries
from ours, because we
take liberty of judgment to be
something sacred and inviolable from theirs, because the
Athenians had long since departed from the ancient state
;

of things.

^
i

SOCRATES.

232

Chap.

great statesmen of old to see demagogues and aristo-

'

on every other point,

crats in feud with each other

but agreeing in the thoughtless play of rivalry and

ambition

Had

not

men

of that

time passed through a school of rationalism which

had entirely pulled to pieces the

and the

for a gene-

the cultivated

all

morals of their ancestors

Had

beliefs

not

men

ration lived themselves into the belief that laws are

the creations of caprice, and that natural right and


positive right are very different things

What had

become of the olden chastity when Aristophanes


could

tell his

hearers in the midst of his attacks

on Socrates, half in joke, half in


were one and

all

What had become

adulterers?^

when the

ancient piety at a time

derision, that they


of;

sceptical verses of'

Euripides were in every one's mouth, when everyyear the happy sallies of Aristophanes and other

comedians in

successful derision of the inhabitants!

Olympus were clapped, when the most unprejudiced


complained that fear of Grod, trust, and faith, had|'
vanished,^ and when the stories of future retribution!
of

were universally derided

This state of things Socrates did not

(h) So-

Tir^ ^'^'ti ^^^^^

i^ existing.

What

sists

existim.

time, trying to reform

making the

blamed

it

he

for really con-

by means of

hisj

itself, inste?

and silly attempt to bring i1


a type of culture which was gone for ever^

back to

useless

was an obviously

It

is

in this, that he entered into the spirit of

wluit he

of

he

make

Conf

Clouds, 1083.

p. 29.

opponents

false attack of his


3

Thuc.

Plato, Rep.

iii.

82
i.

ii.

53.

330, D.

t(

>

HIS liELA TION TO THE MORALITY OF HIS TIME.


hold

him

responsible for the corruption of faith

and

morals, which he was trying to stem in the only


possible way.
It was a clumsy self-deception on
their part to

imagine themselves men of the good old


time. His condemnation is not only a great injustice
according to our conceptions of right, but it
also according to the standard of his own time

is
;

so

it is

a crying political anachronism, one of those unfortunate measures, by which a policy of restauration is
ever sure to expose its incompetence and
shortsightedness.

Socrates

certainly

left

the

original

ground of Greek thought, and transported it beyond


the bounds, within which this particular
form of
aational life was alone possible.
50

)f

But he did not do

before it was time, nor before the untenableness


the old position had been amply demonstrated,

rhe revolution which was going forward in


the whole
spirit of the Greeks, was not
the fault of one individual, but it was the fault of destiny,
or rather it
vas the general fault of the time.
The Athenians

n punishing him condemned themselves, and


comnitted the injustice of making him pay
the penalty^
>f what was historically the
fault of all.
The conlemnation therefore was not of the least use :
intead of being banished, the spirit of innovation
was,
'n the contrary, thereby all the
more aroused. We
lave

aoral

then here not a simple collision between two


powers equally justified and equally limited,

and innocence are not equally divided between


he parties.
On the one hand was a principle his3rically necessary and higher in
respect of importhiilt

2Z:\

Chap.
^-

SOCRATES.

234
Chap.
X.

ance, of which Socrates had an unquestioned claim


On the other hand, one
to be the representative.
far

to

more

by

limited, represented

his opponents,

which they have no longer a just

do not faithfully adhere to

it.

but

right, since they

This constitutes the

turn in the fate of Socrates. A


is truly conservative is attacked by

peculiar

tragic

reformer

who

nominal and imaginary restorers of old times. The


Athenians in punishing him give themselves up as
lost; for in reality it is not for destroying morals
that he is punished, but for attempting to restore

them.
(6-)

hreacU
hetween
Socratas

and

his

countrym,en was
tihsolutelif

nccessarij.

To form a correct judgment of the whole occurrence, we must not forget that Socrates was condemned by only a very small majority, that to all
appearances it lay in his own power to secure his
and that undoubtedly he would have escaped with a far less punishment than death, had he
not challenged his judges by the appearance of pride.

acquittal,

These circumstances must make us doubly doubtful


of regarding his ruin as an unavoidable consequence
AsJ
of his rebellion against the spirit of his nation.
they place the guilt of the Athenians in a milder;

light,

by laying

it

in part on the head of the accused,,*

they at the same time prove that accidental


events, in no way connected with the leading charao

so too

had great weight in the fini


No doubt Socrates was at variance wiiiP
decision.
the position and the demands of the ancient moralit}

ter of his teaching,

in essential points

but

it

was not necessary in

then state of opinion at Athens, that


to a breach between

him and

it

th<

should com*

his nation.

Althoug|

RESULTS OF HIS DEATH.

235

the political reaction after the expulsion of the thirty


tyrants was sufficiently powerful to bring about

Chap.
^'

an

attack on him, the conviction of his guilt was not so

might have been possible for


punishment of death.
honour and his cause it was a happy

universal but that

him

it

to escape the

For

his

thing that he did not escape.

What

(4)

Socrates in hu^fth.
that

pious faith expressed after his condemnation


die would be better for

has

him than to live


been fully realised in his work. The picture of the
dying Socrates must have afforded to his pupils, in
to

the highest degree,


to us

it

now

after centuries affords

simple testimony to the greatness of the

human mind,
victory

what

of a

to the
spirit

clear conviction.

It

power of philosophy, and to the


pious and pure, reposing" on

must have stood before them

in

glory, as the guiding star of their inner life,

all its

as it is depicted

by Plato's master hand.

It

must

have increased their admiration for their teacher,


their zeal to imitate him, their devotion to his teaching.

By

his death the

impressed on his

life

stamp of higher truth was

and words.

and happy cheerfulness

The sublime repose


with which he met death,

was the strongest corroboration of

all his

the zenith of a long life devoted to


virtue.

convictions,

knowledge and

Death did not add to the substance of

teaching, but it greatly strengthened

The

its

his

influence.

had been spent in sowing the seeds of knowledge with a zeal unequalled by any other philosopher
life

either before or after; his death greatly forwarded

the harvest, so that they brouglit forth fruit abundantly in the Socratic Schools.

1 ,

PAET

III.

THE IMPERFECT FOLLO WERS OF SOCRATES,

CHAPTEE XL
THE SCHOOL OF SOCKATES

XENOPHON
Chap.
XI.
A. School
(>f Socrates.

MIND

SO great

HIS POPULAR

PHILOSOPHY.

^SCHINES.

and active in every way

Socrates could not fail to

make

as that of

a lasting impression

it came into
most
perfect
contact.
systems are often
all
their
adherents in the same
not understood by
might
not
much
a
greater divergence and"
sense,
apprehension
be expected, in a case where
variety of
no system lay ready to hand, but only the fragments
and germs of what might be one a person, a principle, a method, a mass of individual utterances and of!
The greater part of the foldesultory discussions ?
lowers of Socrates confined their attention to what
was most obvious and lay nearest to an ordinary in-

on every kind of character with which


If then the

telligence

the

originality, the purity of character,

the intelligent view of


beautiful moral

smaller

life,

maxims

the deep piety and the

of their teacher.

number gave more

Only

at

careful attention to the'

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

2'67

deeper thoughts, which often appeared


under so unpretentious an outside, and even
of these nearly all
took a very narrow view of the
subjects which occupied Socrates.

Combining older theories with the


teaching of their master, which it
is true needed to
be thus supplemented, they did
so in such a manner
as almost to lose the distinctive
merits of his philosophy.
One only with a deeper insight into
the spirit
of Socrates has succeeded in
creating a system which
presents in a most brilliant and
extended
Socrates had attempted in another
more limited scale.

In the

form what
manner and on a

of these classes must be placed


without doubt by far the greater
number of those who are
known to us as the pupils of Socrates.
The writinsfs
first

Besides the Socratists who


be presently mentioned,
are Crito {Xen. Mem. ii.
9
Plato, Crito, Pheedo, 59, B., 60,'
A--,
63, D., 115, A.
Euthydeoaus
Ding. ii. 121, who makes
iim the author of seventeen
looks, which, however,
belong
'

will

him

as little as his supposchildren Hermogenes, and


>thers), and Clitobulus his
son
;o

ed

Xen. Mem. i. J],


-6 Symp. 4, 10
;

8. ii. 6

(Ec.

Plato, Apol.
PhsKdo, 59, B.
;

D., 38, B.
Esch. in Athenceus v. 220, a.)
'hasrephon (Mem. 2, 48 ii. 3
i.%

Apol. 20, E.
Charm!
Gorgias, Aristophanes,
clouds, Birds, 1296)
and his
rother
Chserecrates
(Mem.
""lata,

IJS,

c.)
1,

B.

also Apollodorus (Mem.


11, 17;
Plato, Apol. 34,
38, B.
Phasdo, 59, B., 117,
;

.
;

Symp.) Aristodemus (Mem.


;

Plato, Symp. 173, B.,


174,
223,
B.);
Euthydemus
(Mem. iv. 2
5 ; 6 ; PL,
3
Sym. 222 B.) ; Theages (PI
Apol. 33 E.
Kep. vi. 496, B )
1.

Hermogenes {Xen. Mem.


4
h}\?'
PL Phffido,

Sym.

ii.

lo'

46 Apol. 2,
59, B).
In Mem. i.
2, 48, perhaps "Epixoy^v-ns
should
be read for Hermocrates
bui
;

4,

any rate this Hermocrates


must be distinguished from the
Hermocrates
mentioned PI
Tim 19, C, 20, A, Krit. 108,'
at

the latter being a stranger


stays at Athens on

who only

his way.
Compare Steinhart,
PI. W. vi. 39 and 235
Phaido;

nides (Mem.
59,

C.)

33, E.)

?;

48 PI. Ph^do,
Theodotus {PL Apol.
i.

2,

Epigenes (Ph^do, 59,

Mem.

iii. 12);
Menexenus
(Phasdo, 59, B. Lysis, 206,
D.'^
Ctesippus
(Phaedo, Euthyde;

SOCRATES.

238
Chap.
XI.

too which are attributed to

Socrates

amongst

many of these

followers of

which, however, there

is

much

spurious were, on an average doubtless little


more than summaries of popular moral maxims.'

that

is

underof the best illustrations of this mode of


standing and applying the doctrines of Socrates may

One

be found in Xenophon.^
mus,

and

Lysis);

Jud. de Thuc. c. 31, p. 941,


reckons among the followers of
Socrates and Alcibiades in
their younger years (Mem. i.
2, 12, Plato); not to mention
others who were acquainted
with Socrates, but did not join
his way of thinking, such as
Phsedrus the friend of Sophistry
{Plato, Fhied., Symp.); Callias
(Xeti. Symp., Plato, Phot.) the

Theaetetus
Prod, in
the younger

(Theajtet. Soph. Pol.

Euclid. 19, m. 20)


Socrates {Plat. Theaet. 147, E
Soph. 218, 8 Polit. 257, C
Arist. Metaph. vii. 11, 1036, 6
25 conf Rerinann, Plat. i. 661)
;

Terpsion (PI. Theast. PhfBdo


59, C.) Charmides (Xen. Mem
Symp. 4, 29
6, 14;
iii. 7;
;

19 Plato, Charm
Sym. 222, B. Prot. 315, A.)
Glaucon the brother of Plato
(Mem. iii. 6; the same individual to whom Bioff. ii. 124,

Hellen.

ii. 4,

younger Pericles (Mem.

iv.

attributes

nine

genuine

Aristarchus (Mem. ii. 7.)


therus (Mem. ii. 8) and
;

and

thirty-two spurious dialogues,


and who is identical with the
Glauco of Plato's Republic, and
the Parmenides, as we assume
following Bockh; conf. Abhandlung d. Berliner Acad.
1873, Hist. Philos. Kl. p. 86)

Cleombrotus (Phd. 59, C.


perhaps the same who is said
;

by Callim. in Cic. Tusc. i.


84, and Sext. Math. i.

34,

48;
Bavid, Proleg. in Cat. 9 Schol.
in Arist. 13, b, 35 Ammon in
Porphyr. Isag. 2, b, to have
committed suicide over the
;

Phsedo, probably not from niisunderstanding the exhortation


to a philosophic death, but
from shame for his conduct
there blamed) Diodorus (Mem.
;

ii.

10)

Critias,

whom

Dionys.

5)

Eu-

many

others.
1
Crito

and Glaucon.
Xenophon, the son of the
Athenian Gryllus, died accord2

ing
ii.

to a statement in
56,

360-359

B.C.

Pioff

Froir

Hellen. vi. 4, 35, however, ii


appears that he survived th(
murder of Alexander of Phera
If the treatise respecting
357.
the public revenues of Athen;
belongs to the year 355, h<
must also have outlived tha
On the authority of Pi
year.

Macrob. 21, his birtl


placed in 450,^ o
formerly
was
on account of his participation
in the battle of Delium, p. 66
The first of thes
2, in 445 B.C.
extremel
however,
is,
passages
untrustworthy, as giving ir
Ltician.

formation depending on th
date of his death which is ver

XENOPIION.

2?A)

impossible in

It is

reading the works of this


author not to be struck with the purity and loftiness
uncertain.
The latter
much at variance with

is

so

what
8ymp. 220, D. says, that
it is a most uncertain foundation on which to build.
Neither passage agrees with
what Xenophon himself says
(Anab. iii. 1, 4 and 25, ouSej/
Plato,

Trpo(paai^O(xai

rrjv riAiKiau) 2,

87,

where he mentions himself and


Timasion as the two youngest
amongst the generals.
These
passages place it beyond dispute,
that at the time of the expedition he is describing, 401-400
B.C., he was about 45 years of
age and not much older than
his friend Proxenus, who fell
in it about 30.
(So Grote,

Plato iii. 56.3;


Cobet, Novie
Lect. 635 Bevffk in Ersch. u.
Gruber's Encyl. i. 81, 392
;
_^*/.75msGriech. Gesch.iii. 772,
;

The circumstances of

31,)
life

He

he

died

that he was banished by the


Eleans (probably in 370 B.C.,
when they joined the Thebans
after the battle of Leuctra
Diodor. xv. 62), and spent the
rest of his life at Corinth
{Diog. 53).
His banishment
appears to have ended, when
Athens joined Sparta against
Thebes, as the treatise on the
revenues indicates,
whether
before or after the battle of
Mantinasa, in which his two
sons fought among the Athenian cavalry, and the elder one
Gryllus fell {Bwg. 54; Plut.
Consol. ad Apoll. 33, p. 118),
Xenophon 's writings are distinguished for purity and grace
of language, and the unadorned
clearness of the description

his

Tliey appear to have been pre-

served entire.
The Apology,
however, the Agesilaus, and
the treatise on the Athenian
constitution are certainly spu-

iii. 1, 4, Memorabilia and


(Economicus of his relations
to Socrates, as to the origin of
which Piog. ii. 48, tells a
doubtful story, and
in the

Anabasis of his activity and


experience in the retreat of
the 10,000.
After his return
he entered the Spartan army
in
Asia Minor, and fought
under Agesilaus at Coronea
against his own countrymen.

Banished for this from Athens,


he settled in the Elean Scillus,
colonised by Spartans (Xen.

Anab.

De

More

v. 3,

v.

6,

6 Pior/. ii. 51 Pan4; Pint. Agesil. 18;


;

Exil. 10, p. 603).


According to an ill-accredited story

XI.

B. Xenohere. plioii
credible authorities state

Pausanias

imperfectly.
speaks himself in the Ana-

we only know

basis

.w;t.

in

Chap.

and several others of the


smaller treatises are either
spurious or have large interrious

polations. Stc'mha7't,'^ Flat. I.


300, wrongly doubts the

i)5,

Symposium.

For his

life

and

writings

consult Krilger, De
Xenoph. Vita, Halle, 1832, also
in 2nd vol. of Historisch. philol.
Studien, Panke, De. Xenoph.

Vita et Scriptis, Berlin, 1851.


Grote, Plato iii. 562; Pergk, I.e.
Pdh7' in I'auly's Kealencyclop.
vi. 6, 2791.
For other literature on the subject Ibid, and
Ueberweg, Gesch. d. Phil. i. 95.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

240

Chap.
_^^'_

of the sentiment, with his chivalrous character, and

mind

the healthy tone of his

his philosophical

still

capacities cannot be estimated at a very high rate.

His description of Socrates

full of

is

character

the greatness of his

admiration for
philosophical

his

merit and his intellectual labours he has only imNot only does he share the|
perfectly understood.
narrowness of the position of Socrates

as for instance

when he quotes the derogatory opinions

of his mastery

respecting natural science in proof of his piety and


but he misunderstands the true phiintelligence,^

losophic worth of the discussions he reports.

The

formation of conceptions, constituting as it does the


germ of the whole teaching of Socrates, is only acci-

him

dentally mentioned by

in order to show what^

care his master devoted to the critical culture of his


All that he gathers from Socrates' peculiarj

friends.2

habit of asking every one


thirst for

whom

he came across, in his

knowledge, as to his mode of

life, is

that

he tried to make himself useful to people of everyj


The importance of those!
class, craftsmen included.^

maxims

which the whole

too, relative to virtue, in

peculiarity of the Socratic ethics consists, can only


be gathered with so much difficulty from his account,

that

it

Xenophon

how

obvious

is

was understood by

it

Many echoes and reminiscences

himself.^

of teaching are indeed to be

mode

of the Socratic

little

found in his independent sketches


>

Mem.

Ibid.

Mem.

i. 1,

iii.

11

10, 1

iii. 9,

and

conf. 106,
p. 140.

i.

but he
^

iv. 7.

2.

is

Ibid. iv.

too ex-

6.

XENOPHON.

241

cliisively

occupied with their practical application


to
engage in any really scientific researches.
He
de-

scribes the catechetical

mode

of teaching,' in which

he seems to have been somewhat


skilled; but his
dialogues do not aim, like those of
the genuine Socratic type, at the formation
of conceptions, and are
often far too easy in their
proofs and deductions.
He recommends self-knowledge,^ but primarily
only
in its popular sense, meaning,
that no one ought to
attempt what is beyond his powers.

He

piety, self-restraint,3
to hold

maxim

the

consist in

and

so forth,

on
but he appears not
insists

of Socrates,^ that all these


virtues

knowledge.

Following the method used


by Socrates he proves that nothing
is a good of which
you do not make a right use ^ that
every one readily
submits to the wise,^ that right and
law are synonymous terms,7 and that the rich are
not more happy
;

than the poor, that the true


measure of riches and
poverty is not simple possession,
but a possession proportionate to the needs of the
possessor.^
He repeats
what Socrates had said about
truth and error,io yet
not without hinting that
these principles are 'liable
to be abused.
With the same decision as his master,
lie

!
-

declares against the sensual


p^^- ^^' ^}'

Cyrop. vii. 2, 20.


Ihid. viii. i;23.

Compare the conversation


Cyrus and Tigranes,
vrop. 111. I, 10^ and Mem. i.
2,
in which the ordinarv
view is

'
e

p.

>etween
J>,

riven rather

he ffier.'^''

than the Socratic,


^^"^"'^' ''^""^'^

and unnatural abuses


See above, p. 141, 2
' %.^\^

c^,.^^,,

'

li^l'T
'

jjfi

148,1.

29

"'

'"

(Ec 9

^^

6 4
9**

^^-^^P-^-"^' ^^'^

^^^ ^^^''

^^
^^^

'

li,id viii

Mem

^^-

^'

la

^.-^^
'

'

P"
,

^' ^'

Mem. iv. 2,13.

Chap

_J^

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

242

of thought, he
and, following out his train
have a recognised, social
requires that woman should
more care spent on her education,

of love

...
Chap.

^^

'

and have

position,

made into a real comand that her union should be


based on a recipropanionship for life, and should be
city of capacities

He

and performances.^

exhorts to

liis teacher condemning


work, without, however, like
manual labour.^ By
the Greek prejudice against
us to know what is
of his expressions he gives

many

he

but
and happy life ;
his ideal of a beautiful
philosophic reason for his
neither attempts to give a
ideal,

nor does he place

it

outside the platform ot

Touching the knowledge


care for mankind,
and omnipotence of the Gods, their
piety,^ he expresses
the blessing consequent upon
time he fullj
with warmth but at the same

Greek

traditional

ethics.

himself

shares the belief of his nation


tions

and

in regard to predic-

himself understanding their intermakes Cyrus express the hope of

sacrifices,

He

pretation.

higher

after

life

that view

death, confirming

however, venturing
several considerations, without,
He reminds us tha
to assert it with full assurance.
the soul

is

invisible

that vengeance surely comes

oi

and that honour is du


the murderers of the innocent,
He cannot believe that the soul whic
to the dead.
^

Symp.

165.
7; see p. 166 4.

8, 7, p.

(EC. 313, c.

amongst

Compare

passages,

Cyrop.

i.

6,

othc

23

''"''' ^p^.^.l 5,U;V^U


\^:',%V'^
''

'?Vem'

Iv'-

i 7. (Vo

8,

"V-J;^ '. t-iV;


2;(Ec.7,

18.

11;

Cyrop.

V^/'
and

6, 28,

'cyrop.

Cyrop^

i.

6,

i.

with Mem.

11.
also pp. I-.''r''ll
65, 5

6,
1.

23
1, 6.

agrees

f^

'

XENOPHON.
gives

243

body should be itself mortal, or that


Chap.
reason should not survive in greater purity
after its _
separation from the body, seeing a sign thereof
in
prophesying in sleep.
In all these explanations we
life

to the

_^_

may

discern the faithful and thoughtful follower


of
Socrates, but there is not a trace of original

thought.

Indeed

it

doubtful whether

is

the few passages in

which Xenophon seems to have somewhat


amplified
the teaching of his master, ought not really
to be attributed to Socrates.

His larger work on politics, the Cyropgedeia, is,


as
a book of political philosophy, unimportant.
Xenophon here proposes to pourtray the Socratic
ideal

of a ruler
cares

who understands

for his

flock

people as

his business,^

a shepherd

but what he really gives,

is

and who

cares

for his

a description of

a valiant and prudent general,^ of an


upright man,
and of a chivalrous conqueror. Not an attempt
is

made

mark out more

to

clearly the province of go-

vernment, to give a higher meaning to the state,


or
by fixed institutions. The demand
for a careful education ^ may reveal
the follower of
to fulfil its object

Socrates, but there is so little reference in that


education to knowledge,^^ that it might more
easily pass for

a Spartan

2
^

-'

Cyrop.
.,

r,
Ihid.
Ibid.

than for a Socratic education.

viii.

7, 17.

See

may be the nameless


friend referred to in this pas-

p.

phon

i.

saye.
^^
Cj-rop.

1.

1, 3.

viii.

2,

See
14

p. 167.

Mem.

Every

i.

2,

viii.

8,

13

vii. 5, 72.

f^L.

Ibid. G, 12, speaks of these


auties ni language similar to
^Uem. 111. 1.
Perhaps Xeno-

A weak

ciple of
4, 3.

eclio of tlie prin-

Socrates

is

found

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

244

CHAP,

^_

The state
prince.
thing centres in the person of the
The highest aim to which
is an Asiatic kingdom.
tend,^ is the strength and wealth
all its

institutions

of the sovereign

and

his courtiers.

Even

this view is

many important
very imperfectly carried out, and
omitted.^
departments of government are altogether
dia-

In this
The same remarks apply to the Hiero.
enough, how little the
logue Xenophon shows plainly
sovereign is
supposed good-fortune of an absolute
touching the means
really to be envied. His remarks
and his
such a sovereign can make himself

whereby
of his proposals
people happy-allowing that many
beyond a benevolent
are expedient- do not advance
successful is his smaller treatise on

More

despotism.

family

It bears witness to

life.

an intelligent mind

out particularly
and a benevolent heart, which comes
the position assigned toj
in its utterances respecting
it makes
woman ^ and the treatment of slaves.^ But

no pretensions to be a philosophical

treatise,

though

thoughts
may contain many individual Socratic
j
can
From Xenophon, then, the history of philosophy

it

gain but

little.^

Compare viii.!. The treaty


between Cyrus and the Per.Tans ^ii. 5, 24, has for its
obTect uri^y by the advan>

?ages if governmJnt.
^ Compare the spirited remarks of Mohl, Gesch. d.

Sr^swiienschaf t,
3 r
^ IS o 7
4

Vo s

14*

9'-

i.

c.

204.

21

7,

37

9 11

.r.d 41
5

Qp J

-n

242 2

Xe

fa^o^irable view of

^^^^P^^^^^y/Yrf
4^6^^^^
d. Prakt. Phil. d. Gr. 466-509!

^
sees in him the develop
of Socratic thought fr on.
the point of applied ethics

He

ment

and a ^^PPl^^^^^V^f*,
^^,
pure speculations. Yet he to.
th
excepting
that
says
OEconomica there can oe n
trace of a systematic develop
^ent in Xenophon (p. 481
bis ethical teaching is extremel
simple, almost entirely devoi

^f
m

.ESCHINES.

24/5

^schines* would appear to have treated the


teaching of Socrates in the same way. The writings

among

of this disciple,2 are reckoned


of Attic prose/ and are by

Xenophon.^

It

is

philosophic language (p.


he never really proves
484)
anything, nor employs
any
form for deduction, not even
the favourite method with Socrates, that of definition (p.
;

In what then does his


importance for philosophy and

467).

history consist 1
The application of the thoughts of others,

without

verifying their contents or observing their method, may in many respects be


very meritorious, but it cannot
be regarded as a service rendered to philosophy.
iEschines, son of Lysanias
{Plato, Apol. 33 E), against
'

IJiug.

ii.

60,

can have no

weight, is praised for his adherence to Hocrates {Biog. ii.


31
ISeiiec. Benef, i. 8).
Plato
mentions him (Phaido, 59, R.),
among those who were present
at the deatli of Socrates.
Idomeneus, however {Diog. ii. 60,
35 iii. 36), transferred to him
the part played by Crito in
Plato, probably only out of
;

spite to Plato.
We afterwards
encounter him in the company
of tlie

younger Dionj^sius {Dioq.

63
Pint. Adul. et Am.
26, p. 67 PMlost. v. Apollon.
135, p. 43
Lnciaiiy Paras, c.
32, conf. Diodor. xv. 76), to
li.

61

c.

whom he had been recommended by Plato, according to


Plutarch, by Arstippus according

to

Diogenes.

some preferred

to those of

Aristippus

appears as his friend in JDiog.


82: Plut. Coh. Ira, 14.
Poor
to begin with {Diog. ii. 34, 62)
he was still poor in after-life
on his return to Athens. He
did not venture it is said to
found a school, but delivered a
few speeches and treatises for
money {Diog. ii. 62; what
ii.

Atlwri. xi. 507, c. and Bxog. ii.


20 say is not credible). Whether
the dirty stories are true which
Lysias in Atheii. xiii. 611, tells
of him is a moot point.
His

writings according to Athc/i.


give the impression of an honourable man. The time of his
death is not known.
2

64,

According to Diog. ii. 61,


Phrgtdchus in PJwt. Biblio-

thek, c. 151, p. 101, seven of


these were considered to be

genuine.

The scanty remains

of them have been collected by


IIcvDiann, De ^schin. Socr.
Reliquiis, Gott. 1850. ^Qelhid.
p. 8.
^

Longin.

irepl

ewpe's.

Ehet.

Gr. ix. 559 (ed. Walz).


* Phrgnich. in
Phot. Cod. 61,
Schl. 158, g. E; Hermogenes,
Form. Orat. ii. 3 Rhet. Gr. iii.
394.
M. Psellos in Con. Catal.
of Bodl. M8S. p. 743 quoted by
;

Grote,

Plato,

iii.

XL
C. jfjs^''^'^'^'"'^

moreover asserted that they repro-

of

whom

the best models

Chap.

469, against

which authority Timon in Diog.


ii.
55 Q2 carries no weight.
He is said to have imitated
;

Gorgias in speech, Diog.

ii.

63.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

o40

Chap.
XI.

with wonderful fidelity,^


and the few fragments which remain confirm this
Nevertheless they appear to have been singuview.

dace the

spirit of Socrates

Their strength

larly poor in real philosophic thought.

consists far

in the grace

more

and elegance of their

language than in an independent treatment of the


Socratic teaching.
D. Simntias

and

Cedes.

jMore philosophic characters were the two TheBoth were pupils of


bans, Simmias^ and Cebes.^

Philolaus

men.

ful

as

thought-

known

of their

both are described by Plato

Still

nothing certain

is

The

philosophical opinions and performances.

writ-l

them ^ were already rejected by'


as he knew them, and the single

ings attributed to
^

Pansetius

as far

one extant, known as the


tainly spurious.^

Demetr. De Interpret. 297.


Hence the story {Diog. ii. 60,
62; Athen.yiiii. 611), that his
speeches had been composed
by Socrates, and given to
him by Xanthippe. D'wg. ii.
47 ranks him among the most
distinguished followers of So2

17

Xen. Mem. i. 2, 48 iii. 11,


PM.o, Phasdo, 59, C, 63 A.
;

Mem.

Ph^do,

Mirror

Still less

Aristid. Or. [\.]). So. Conf.

'

59,

C,

60,

C.

phgedo, 61, D.
It is said (Phajdo, 242, B.),
that Simmias delivered and
composed more philosophical
4

speeches than any one else. In


the Phaedo, 85, C, he is made
to utter the maxim, that every
question should be pursued as
Of Cebes, it
far as possible.

'

of Cebes,

is

cer-

can any dependence

be^

is said (Phsdo, 63, A., 77, A.),


that he could always raise'
objections, arnd w^as the most
and the
inveterate doubter
part which he and Simmias
play in the Phfedo correspond'
;

with this description.


Bioq.
ii.
124, mention!
twenty-three lectures of Sim
mias and three of Cebes, in
eluding the Mirror. Other test!
monies for the latter in Schmeig
Muscr, Epictete Enchiridion e
Cebetes tabula, p. 261.
^
Diog. ii. 64 iravToiv /xevri
ruv 'ZotiKpariKc!}]/ SiaXoycov Uavdi
:

rios aArjfleTs elvai 5oKe? Tobs TIAd


Twvos, "Etvo^oivros, 'AvTiffOevov
Al(Tx'i-vov

4>aihoivos

^KTrd^ei
KoX

8e

Eu/cAeiSou,

Trepi

rS

rovs ?

&\\ovs avaip^l vdvTas.


^

In modern times its ge


nuineness has been maintained
8

SIMMIAS AND CEBES.

247

placed on the genuineness of the writings which were

name

circulated at a later time under the

shoemaker Simon.

Probably he

is

of the

altogether an

imaginary person.^
In addition to Plato, four founders of Socratic

known to us Euclid, Phsedo, Antisthenes,


and Aristippus. Of these the two former are much
schools are

alike

the two

follow

courses

peculiar

There arose thus from them three

themselves.

Socratic

tinct

others

schools

Cynic, and the Cyrenaic.

dis-

Megarian-Elean, the

the

to

All these are derived from

One-sided liowever in their aims, and

Socrates.

dependent themselves on earlier theories, they only


imperfectly

by

catch

the

Bdhr {Pauhfs Real-Ency-

Cebes) and
Schweighauser, c. 13, 33; but
their assumption is refuted by
two passages in it, one of
kvhich mentions a Peripatetic,
ind tlie other quotes from
Plato's Laws.
In other respects too, notwithstanding its
clop.

vol.

Art.

general colourlessness, traces


ippear of later times, e.g. in
ts Stoic morality and attacks

false culture.
'

8ee

Dio(f.

ii.

122;

Snid.

Epist. Socrat. 12, 13


^^lut. c. Prin. Philos. c. 1, p.
76 Bockh. in Plat. Minoem.
:2.
Simonis Socrat. Dialogi
V. Hermann, Plat. i. 419, 585.
ScuKpciTTjs-

What Diogenes

lira is

unsatisfactorj',

says

of

and the

the teaching

of

spirit

of

likely to be true.
Of the
dialogues attributed to him a
great part are found in writings belonging to other people
{Hermann, 1. c). It is suspicious, that he is not mentioned by any ancient authority, and that both Plato and
Xenophon should be silent
about an old and very remarkable pupil of Socrates.
In
addition to the above, Svidug
(SwK^aT. p. 813) mentions also
Bryso of Heraclea as a pupil of
Socrates.
Others, however, as
Suidas remarks, called him a
pupil of
Euclid's, and the

comedian Ephippus in At/ten.


xi. 501), c. calls him an Academician.
Theopompus' state-

ment

(1.

c.

508, D.) that Plato


hi^ writings,

tory tliat Pericles asked to be

copied some of

aken in by him, but tliat he


efuscd, besides being chrono>gically suspicious, is hardly

would harmonise with either


view but it is in any case
;

false.

Chap
XI.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

248

Chap.

Socrates,

and diverge from him and from one another

'

in the

most opposite

directions.

man

Socrates placed

knowing the good.


What that good was he could not mark out more

the highest business of

in

accurately, being partly satisfied with

description of

of

it,

a practical

being partly restricted to a theory

relative pleasure.

These various sides of the

now diverge, and are rounded


One party confines itself to the

Socratic philosophy
into

systems.

general burden

of the

abstract idea of the good.

pleasure which

is its

the

teaching of Socrates

result

Others starting from

make

that the gauge of the

good, and the good itself something relative.

within the former class some

make

Again

the theoretical,

others the practical treatment of the good, to be the

Thus the Socratic teaching gave rise


the three schools just named, which in so far as

main
to

point.

they bring into prominence individual elements


the spirit of Socrates to the detriment of the

in

rest,

revert to older lines of thought, long since passed

in the historical development of philosophy.

The

Megarians and Cynics go back to the Eleatic doctrine of the One and All, and to the Sophistry oJ
Grorgias

the Cyrenaics to

the negative teaching

of Protagoras, and to the early scepticism of Heraclitus.

THE MEGARIANS.

CHAPTEE

249

XII.

THE MEGARIAN AND THE ELEAN-ERETRIAN SCHOOLS.

The founder

of the Megarian school

is

Euclid.^

Chap.
XII.

De

Megaricorum
Doctrina, Bonn, 1827, whose
careful work
has not been
added to by Mallut's Histoire

he was educated at Gela. That


I. The Mehe also possessed property in
yarians.
Attica,
Grote, Plat. iii. 471,
A. History
concludes, but without suffi-

de TEcole de Megare, Par. 1845.


More independent, but sometimes too diffuse, is Ilenne^
Ecole de Megare, Par. 1843.
mttcr, Ueber die Philosophic
der Meg. Schule in
Rhein.
Mus. ii. (1828), p. 295 Harten-

cient reason,
Judic. de Isao,

Deyclis,

'

Ueber die Bedeutung


der Meg. Schule fur die Gesch.

stciii,

Metaphys. Probleme,

d.

Ver-

handl. der ISachs. Gesellschaft


der Wissensch. 1848, p. 190;
Prantl, Gesch. d. Logik, i. 33,
whicli enters most deeply into
the logical teaching of the

Megarians.
Euclid's

{PlatOy

home was Megara

Phjedo, 59,
that it was his birth-place
is asserted by Cic. Acad. iv. 42,
129; Strahu, ix. 1, 8, p. 393;
C.)

The.-Btet.

crat.

from
c.

14

on ra iiriKiqpvTT.

Bionys.
;

Karjm-

Poll. viii.

Dionysus only refers to a


judicial speech of Isssus irphs
EvicKeiSrjv aprojJos of a piece
of land, but that this Euclid

48.

was the follower

of Socrates is

pure conjecture. The time of


his birth cannot be accurately
determined, nor does the anecdote in Gell. vi. 10 help for
this.
He was, however, probably older than Plato. This
seems to be proved by the fact
that on the death of Socrates
he served for some time as a
centre to his disciples.

time of his death

The

I>io(f. ii. 106.


The statement
that he came from Gela {nvh
in Diotj.) doubtless rests on a

also uncertain.
If Stilpo and Pasicles
were his personal pupils, he
must have lived at least till
360 B.C.; but this is ver}'- uncertain.
On the whole little is

misunderstanding. Deyclis, p.
4, imagines it arose from confounding him with Euclid the

known of him. A celebrated


saying of his to his brother,
which bears witness to a gentle

whom, how-

cjuoted by Plut. de
Frat. Am. 18,
Stoh. Flor. 84, 15;
p. 489;
Dioy. ii. 108, mentions six discourses of his.

jester, yiXolas, to

ever,

does

Atken. vi. 242,


not give this

b, 250, e,

epithet.
conjectures, but
without sufficient reason, that

He line,

p. 32,

character,

Ira, 14, p.

is

462;

is

of the

School.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

250
Chap.
XII.

faithful friend

and admirer of

Socrates,^

same time familiar with the Eleatic

made

but at the

doctrine,^ Euclid

use of the latter to develope the Socratic phi-

losophy as he understood

it.

He

thus established

separate branch of the Socratic School,^ which con-

tinued to

exist

century.'^

Ichthyas'^

vmtil

the early part of the


is

'
The story told by GelL, N.
A. vi. 10, of his nightly visits
to Athens is well known. It
cannot, however, go for much,
though not in itself improbable. On the contrary, it maj^
be gathered from Plato's Thetetet. 142, C. that Euclid constantly visited Socrates from
Megara, and from the Phasdo,
59, C. that he was present at
his death.
A further proof of
his close connection with the
followers of Socrates will be
found in the fact (^Diog. ii. 106;
iii. 6) that Plato and other followers of Socrates stayed with
him for a considerable time
after the death of their master.
He is usually spoken of as a
disciple of Socrates, and has a
place amongst his most dis-

tinguished disciples.
2 As may be gathered from
his system with greater certainty than from Cic. and Dioij.
When Euclid became acquainted with the Eleatic Philosophy
is inicertain.

It is

most pro-

bable that he was under its


influence before he came under
that of Socrates, although the
story in Diog. ii. 30, is too uncertain to prove much.
^ The
cxoAt? Eu/cAeiSoi (for
which the Cynic Diogenes in

JDiog.

N. 31,substitutes Eu/cAeiSou

named

as

his

thirc^

pupil and

Megarian oi
called
XoA^),
Eristic or Dialectic, Diog. ii.'
Consult Beychs as to
106.
these names. He proves that
the terms Eristic and Dialectic
were not confined to the Me-I
garian School. Compare Sex
tus Empiricus, who generalljj
understands by Dialecticians
Stoics, for instance, Pyrrh. ii
146, 166, 229, 235.
^ How
early Euclid was a1
the head of a special circle oi

and whether he appeared


formally as a Sophist, or likt
Socrates onlygraduallygathereo
about him men desirous tc
learn, we are not told. Perhapi
the emigration of many foli
lowers of Socrates to Megar;
gave occasion for the estabi,
lishment of this school, i. e.
for the formation of a society
pupils,

which

at

first

moved

aboui,

house and personi


busying itself with discussions;
There is no ground for sup|,
posing that Plato and hiji
Euclid's

friends removed to Megara


attracted by the fame of th|
School of Euclid, as Hen
maintains, pp. 27 and 30.
5 Siiid.
Diog. i\
EvKXei^-ns
112, only makes the generi
remark, that he belonged tl
the School of Euclid.

HISTORY OF THE MEGARIANS.


successor, respecting

251

whom, however, nothing

further

Of greater note was Eubulicles,^ the


3elebrated dialectician,^ who wrote against Aristotle,'*
ind who is mentioned as the teacher of Demosthenes.^
Cotemporary with him were Thrasyma3hus^ of Corinth, and Dioclides,^ perhaps also
known.

is

Clinomachus.^

be younger.
)f

Pasicles,^ however,

Cyrene, surnamed Cronus, * the

teacher of the

His name

15, p.

is still found in
12
vi. 80 (Diogenes
iedicated to him a dialogue
'

Diog.

ii.

;alled Iclithyas).

Atlien. viii.

535, a.

Of Miletus according to
108.
Whether he was
he head of a school, or whether
le was an immediate disciple
)f
Euclid, we do not know.
^

Diof/. ii.

3iogcnes

only

says,

CuKAeiSou StaSox^y

Compare

'

Math.

Sesc-t.

Dior/, ii.

5'w.s.

'iii.

^^''''-

Biog.

rris

'^"*
ii.

5'

Eu/3.

108

109

Aristocles in

Pr. Ev. XV. 2, 5 ; Athen.


354, b. Themist. Or. xxiii.

From these passages it


seen that the attack of Eumlides was very violent, and
lot free from personal abuse.
s

Ve also hear from Athen. x.


37 of a comedy of Eubulides.
Uit he can hardly be the indiidual whose
work on the

Diogenes

'ynic

^og.

is

quoted by

vi. 20, 30.

* The fact seems pretty


well
stablished (although it is conpicuously omitted by Plutarch

his

eing
>iog.

>ec.

life

Demosthenes),
only attested by
'Pseiidoj}Ivt.

viii.

21

v.

Ajnilei.

c.

478

Sttid.

and Phot. Cod. 265,


but being also alluded to by
the Comedian in Diog., who
can hardly have called a bare
acquaintance a disciple.
* According to IJiog. ii.
121,
a friend of Ichthyas, and a
teacher of Htilpo's.
^ Sitid.
STtATTcuf, a pupil of
Euclid, and the teacher of
Pasicles.

Thurian (according to
112), and a teacher of
Stilpo's son Bryso, Suid. Uvppcoi^,
Diog. says he was the first to
write on predicates, sentences,
and such like.
^ According to Suid. StiAttw^,
a brother of the Cj-nic Crates,
who had also Dioclides, a j^upil
of Euclid's, for teacher, and
^

ii.

Stilpo for pupil.


Diog. vi. 89,
in calling Crates his brother
and Euclid his teacher, pro-

bably confounded Euclid with


Dioclides, unless this be tlie
work of a transcriber and
AioKXeiSov should be read for
EvK\eidoy.

of

not
ii.
108;
Orat.

De Mag.

ATJiaoadeuTis,

Diog.

vii. 13.

{85, c.

would appear to

pupil of Eubulides was Apollonius

'"

2,

Diof/.

21,

838.

p.

ii.

Go8;

Ill

Strabo, xiv.

xvii.

3,

22, p.

Chap
XII.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

252

Chap.
XII.

sharp-witted

Diodoms

pupils was Euphantus,

and

Cronus,^

and another of

known only

his

to us as a poet

historian.^

All other

members

of this school were, however,


Stilpo,^ a pupil of Thrasy-

thrown into the shade by


'
Diodorus, a native of lasos
in Caria, belongs to the most
distinguished dialecticians of
the Megarian School. Cic. De
Fato, 6, 12, calls him 'valens

made

a gross mistake,

must be read
Mallet, p. 96.

irpcSrou

See
for rpirov.
Callicrates, also

mentioned by Athenseus, iknown from IJwdor. xx. 21, aa favourite of Ptolemy Soter.
Sext. Math. i.
dialecticus
* Stilpo of Megara {Diog. ii
Seoct.
SiaAeKTt/caTaTOS
309,
and Diog. ii. Ill, give two 113) must have lived until tht
epigrams of Callimachus ad- end of the fourth century. At
dressed to him. His fallacies least he survived the capture oi
and his researches into motion, Megara by Ptolemy Lagi, anc
and into h\3)othetical sen- his defeat by Demetrius Poliorcetes, two events which hap'
tences, will be mentioned herePique at a dialectical pened 307 and 306 B.C. respecafter.
defeat inflicted by Stilpo at tively, Diodor. xx. 37 and 45
the table of Ptolemy Soter, is On the former occasion th(
interview with Diodorus Cronu;
said to have killed him {Diog.
may have happened for Stilp(
Pliii. Hist. Xat. vii. 53, 180).
He bequeathed his dialectic to never visited Egypt {Diog. 115)
Since he died at an advancec
his five daughter^; Clem. Al.
'

Strom,

iv.

adv. Jovin.

523,

A.

t.

iv.

i.

Hieroii.

186.

His

Kronos, is differexplained by Strabo and


Diog., and in modern times by
Panzerhieter in Jahn's Jahrb.
Philol. Supplement b. V.
f.
223, f., who, however, does not
explain it altogether satisfacConsult, also, Steinhart
torily.
in Ersch. und Gritber"s Ency-

nickname,
entlj'

clop.

Sec.

i.

B., 25, p. 286.

All we know of him is from


Diog. ii. 110, who calls him the
tutor of King Antigonus, and
says that to Antigonus he addressed a book, Trepl jSacriAetoy.
Atheii. vi. 251 quotes an extract
from the fourth book of his
history, in which if he has not
'^

age,

we may

approximateh

place his birth in 380, and hi:


death in 300 B.C. Probably w<
ought to place the date of botl
later, for the notices about hi
pupils in Diog. ii. 113-12C
Senec. Epist. 10, 1, lead us t'
believe that his activity wa
cotemporary with that of Thee
and accordingly i
phrastus
cannot have begun long befor
the death of Aristotle. Siiio
EvK\dd. calls him successor t
Some of the pupil
Ichthyas.
of Euclid are mentioned as hi
teachers, and {Diog. ii. 11B;
in particular ThrasjTnachuj
{Suid. EvK\ei5. and SrlAiro.
Even Euclid himself is name
;

by some, but none

of

thes

STILPO THE MEGARIAK.

2otl

His spirited lectures made him an object of


lavender to his cotemporaries, and the crowds who
jlocked from all sides to listen to them gained for
the
inachus.

|Megarian School a lusti-e such as

it had not hitherto


At the same time the development of their

linjoyed.i

took with him a new turn, the principles of


fhe Cynic School, into which Diogenes had initiated
iim,2 being incorporated with his
own to such an exlioctrine

ent, that

doubts

may

be felt whether Stilpo rather bejOngs to the Cynics or to the Megarians.^


Thereby he
pecame the immediate precursor of the Stoa,
j

into
vhich these two branches of the Socratic
philosophy
i^ere carried over by his pupil
Zeno.^ Other

Mega-

ians,

however, continued faithful to the exclusively

ritical

character of this School.

tatements are probable.

His

haracter,

as to which more
all be said hereafter, is comtended as upright,
gentle,
ersevering, open,
generous,

nd unselfish, Dioff. ii. 117


Hut Vit. Pud. c. 18, p. 536

P; ^}\^^"^
.rUr^vi
irly life ^l'dissipated, he enrely mastered this tendency
y^ strength
of will (Cic. De
mo, o, 10).
He also took
ut in public business, Dior/.
xNme of his dialogues are
11.
^'

entioned by
^u'r/.
I

11.

Dioff. ii. 120.


113, exaggerates

saymg,TO(rodTop

5'

el>pe(riAoyla

il(ro({>L(rriaTrporjyeTohs

^w/'T'' ^^'^'^-'
\\\a5a a^opoxra,/

e/s

id

'^^''*

a{,Thu /^e-

^^' mentions (110


the pupils, who joined
from other philosophers,
the universal admiration

''^i^i'^-N?^
llo)
l>U

dWovs,

'^"'^"''

Alexinus of Elis, a

bestowed on him at Athens and

by several princes.
the more strikino-

It

tliat

120 call his speeches


2

;I.yypt

^-

later.

^^^^^

Stilpo

120

all

Dior,

j^
The proof of this will be
j)^^^^^

given
'

is

is

^^o

^^

stated

by

a pupil of
Dior/

ii

on the authority
of Heraclides.
The same pei
son is no doubt referred to in
Dior;,
ii.
116,
as Zeno the
Phoenician.
The founder of
the Stoa is frequentlv called a
;

vii. 2, 24,

Phoenician, i?/^;^. vii. 15, 2o, 30


In no case can it be Zeno of
Sidon, the pupil of ApoUo-

^os as J/allet, p. 62, supposes, who was himself a punil


of Epicurus, and who, according to Dior/, x. 25 vii 35
continued faithful to' Epicureanism.

Chap

__^"

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

i>54

Chap.
XII.

cotemporary of

Stilpo,^

but somewhat younger,

notorious for his captiousness and logical subtletiei


Othe:
are recorded ^ of Philo, the pupil of Diodorus.^
;

Megarians of this and the following age are onb


known to us by name/ With the verbal criticism o
1

Diofj.

ii.

109, spealis of

him

as a pupil of Eubulides
5e 'dXKcou uUTwu rris EvfiovXiSovdia'HAetos).
Sox'^s 'AAe|t;/o- iyevero
can
lived
he
which
The age in
(fxeTa^v

approximately determined
by his disputes with Stilpo
(Pint. Vit. Pud. c. 18, p._ 536)

be

with Menedemus (Bioff.ii. 135),


and with Zeno, whose strongest
opponent he was, Biog. ii. 109
Plut.
Sext. Math. ix. 108
;

Comm.

Not. 10,

3, p.

1063.

He

must have been younger than


Stilpo, and have flourished

the first ten years of the third


century. His love of contention and his malicious ways
chained for him the nickname
'EAe7|rj/os, Biog. Plut. Vit. Pud.
Eu. xv.
18 Aristotle in Ens. Pr.
We also learn from Her2, 4.
mippus in Diog. that he retired
to Olympia in his last years, in
order to establish a new school
This place of abode not
there.

Clemens, Stromal, iv. 523, am


Jeo'ome adv. Jov. i., quote fror
his Menexenus the informa
tion already given respectin,
Diodorus
the daughters of

whom

he must then hav


spoken of in terms of prais(
It is a clear mistake on th
part of Jerome to make hii
the teacher of Carneades. Sti
stranger is Mallet's mistak(
disputai
the
confounding
Philo with Philo of Lariss:
the founder of the fourth Ac?
demy. The latter lived son:
N(
150 to 200 years later.
can Philo be reckoned amor^
the Stoics, although this hf
been done by Fabricius in Sex
Pyrrh. ii. 110, and by Pram
Gesch. d, Logik, i. 404.
3 Biog.
vii. 191, 194, me:
tions Philo's writings Trepl c
ixaaioiu, and vrepl rp6irwv, again
which Chrysippus wrote, wit
out doubt meaning this Phil
To the same individual mnbe referred what Cic. Acad.

suiting his pupils, he remained


there alone, but soon died of
an injury. For his writings consult Biog. ii. 110 vii.163 Athen.
Aristotle in JSus. 1. c.
XV. 696
2 Biog.
16, a passage
vii.
which does not appear so ambiguous as RiUer, Kh. Mus. ii.
30; Gesch. d. Phil. ii. 145,
;

47, 143, and Sext. Math, vi


113, Pyrrh. ii. 110, say respec
ing his views of hypothetic

would have

when

it,

particularly

the subsequent accounts

are taken into consideration.


Zeno of
Diog. relates that

Cittium was fond of his society;

'

'

'

sentences diff erring from thd


of Diodorus, and Alex. Apl
in Anal. pr. 59, b, says respej
ing their differences in respfl
By Biog. y
of the possible.
16,

and

named

Clemens he

is

si'

6 SiaXeKriKSs.

* A dialectician Panthoid^
doubtless the same person

MEGARIAN BOCTHINE.
the Megarians

doubt, Pyrrho,

and

i>5r,

connected Pyrrho's philosophy of


whom Bryso is said to have taught,'
is

chap.
^^^

Timon, who

studied under Stilpo himself,^


being the connecting links, in the same way
that the
scepticism of Gorgias

is

connected with

tlie critical

subtleties of the Eleatics.

The Megarian philosophy

is only partially known


b. tIwA;
us from the fragmentary notices of the
;
(^ctnnr.
ancients
ind frequently it is impossible to
decide

to

whether

statements refer to the founder and


the older
Gaembers, or only to the later followers
of the School.
:heir

Math

ScH.

vii.

Diodorus

in

2:^ ^m
Diss.
bpictot.
Ih
.8,

18,

mentions,

whose disagreement with

ind

respect

the

of

""^

'

11

\
\'o'
f^
19, 5, speaks

ZTZ

^'

/.f

is the teacher of the '%


as
Pen-

Lyco, and must thereore have flourished 280 to 270


i.e.
A dialectician Aristides
s also mentioned hy Diog. ii.
)atetic

13,
;

among the cotemporaries


and an Aristotle

btilpo,
^

^^'^

oZ^xf^i
Lvt. Arat.
here

^^'""T-^^^''V
Lmias
3.
who

mentioned

with

is

him

^^^''

f ! younger
bomewhat
^"^

'K?nn
leoaiian.

..

aust have been Art emidorus,


.ho wrote against Chrysippus,
log.ix.bi)
Jhog. ix. (>1
Uvpp(vv ^Kovac
:

fvac^uos rov :ZTl\na>uos,


:^u5pos
e,
Am5oxa?s.

i^s 'AA^'-

Suid.
[vpl^<^u:^ ht.-nKovcre ^pvcru^vos, rod
Aeivo^axo^^A^a^r/ToG. Instead of
.ryso, Apvao^u
was formerly
^

,3aa
i^

in

Uwg.

however

ryso.

Sext. Math. vii.


also
calls him

Suid.

atements

are

Uip^'^t-.

not

These
without

their difficulties.
Allowing it
to be possible that Clinoma-

chus and not Stilpo instructed


J'^^^^' ^^ *^-^ be enjoved the
instruction of both, the chro'^
""^ troublesome.
T^""^^
For how can Pvrrho, before
Alexander's expedition to Asii
as Diog^ exprisdf "yl? tve
studied under the son' of a

man, whose own professional


career probably comes after
tlmt expedition ? It ^eems as
though the relation of Pyrrho
to Bryso as pupil and teacher
were an

imaginary combinaconnect the


school of Pyrrho with the Me^^^"' ^le^^i^^ed to

garian.
Possible it also is that
Bryso, the teacher of Pyrrho
has been wrongly identified
with the son of this Stilno
,Stnd. 2a,/cpaT. calls Bryso
the
teacher of Pyrrho, a pupil of
Socrates, or according to other.
a pupil of Euclid.
lioper
Philol. xxx. 462, ijroposes
to
read in the pas.sage of Dio!'
instead of Bp^n-c^osroO St/At;.'
pos, Bpia. ^^ ^rix^
*

IJioy. ix. 10^.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

25G

Chap.
XII.

;;

It is all the

from Plato

satisfactory to be able to learn

more

particulars respecting a theory in which


j

Schleiermacher^
which, in

first

recognised Megarian views, and

with most writers,^ we

common

Plato deSoph. 242, B.


fined Sophistry as the art of
deception. The difficulty immediately arises, that deceponly then possible,
tion is
when not -being, to which all
deception refers, admits a certain kind of being. It may
then be asked, how is the
being of the not-being posTo answer this question
sible ?
Plato reviews various opinions
respecting being. In the first
place he examines the two
most opposite statements, that
being is the many, and that it is
1

the one, and after having shown


that neither a manifoldness of
original substances without a
substratum of unity, nor the
unity of the Eleatics excluding
the many, can be admitted, he
continues, p.

2-15, E.:TouS;uej/ T0-

vvu 5iaKpi^o\oyovix4vov5 ovtos re


Trept KoX jxh iravras fJ.ev oh oteArjXvOafiev, o/jLcos 5e iKauws e'xeTW
Tovs 5e &\\03S Xiyovras av dear4ov.

These are again di\aded

those who only


allow reality to what is material, and others who are called
Of
248, A. ol rciu el^wv cpiKoi.
the latter it is stated 246, B.

into

classes,

roiyapovv ol irpos avTOvs (the


materialists) a^4)i(ri8r)Tot} vres^/xaKa euAajSws dvwdev e| aopArov
TToOep auvvovrai voTjra arra Kai
a.(T6yLara d^t] ^La(6p.^voi.
Bivrjv

ovaiav ivaL

(TcofxaTa

Koi

rr]u

ra

tV

5e

Ae-yo^eVrji'

avTWU aXriOeiav Kara

oKt]-

iKeivwv

fffxiKpa

wtt'

lia-

OpavovTes eV toTs XSyois yi^e<nv

ahr' ova'ias
yopevovaiv.

feel justi-j
Tiua

(pepoix^vrji/

irpoffa-

Platon's Werke, ii. 2.


Leben u.
Platon's
Ast,
Beycli, 37
Schreiben, 201
Hcindoof on Soph. 246, B.
2

Bra/idis, ii.
Plat. 339;

SUllhanm,

114 Hermann,
246;
Ges. Abh.

a.,

Plat.

Parm.

60;

Smemild,
Soph. f. Polit. 61
Genet. Entw. i. 298 StcinhartAllg. Encyk. i. 29, 53 Platon's
Werke, iii. 204, 423, 554
Henne, Ecole de Megare, 84158 Po-anfl, Gesch. d. Log. 1
Against Schleiermachei
37.
are Ritter, Rhein. Mus. voi
;

Xiebuhr und Brandis

ii.

305'

Petersen, Zeitschrift f. Alter':


thiimer, 1836, 892, Heiine, p
49, and Mallet, p. xxx., refer|
the description in Theaetet
185, C. of the formation o
conceptions, to the Megarians
on the ground that it does no
agree with Plato's ownmethoc
But it would seem that he i
wrong in so doing, since w
have no reason to think c

others besides Plato and Sc


Just as little may th
crates.
passage in Parm. 131, B. be re
f erred to the Megarians, as bf

been done by Sclileiermachc"


PL Werke, i. 2, 409, and Deych

The question whethe


42.
things participate in Ideas,
one which the Megarians di
not examine, and it is widel
remote from the view discusse
in the Sophistes.

p.

MEGARIAN TEACHING.
Bed in applying to themJ
testimony of Plato, and

By making

'm
use of the

by considering the inward

The followingf are the reaIt IS clear and


generally

ons.

-Ilowed that Plato's description


s too minute to
be without
eference to some philosophic
chool then existing.

Even

leum, De

Plat.

Sophistes

larb. 1869, p. 44, is

reduced to

dmit

this.

There

is

also defi-

ite reference to
a
chool in the passage

where an

pmion

Socratic

IS

attributed to certain
hilosophers, to the effect
that
ueexislence only belongs

Qmatenal things.
ly

to
philoso-

of

conceptions was unlown before the time of


Soates,
and the description
Tees witli no one of the
preSchools.
The philoof conceptions
are

'cratic

phers
iarly

distinguished from the


featics, and
are manifestly
ite

different

from them.
can the Pythagoreans
thought of, as Mallet has

Ill
'

less

ne

p.

liii.;

for

they had
a philosophy of conDtions, nor did they
indulge
ither

that subtle
3onents,

refutation

which Plato

of

attri-

es
r
'

to these philosophers.
can the language of
Plato,
^., be quoted to prove

contrary,

where speaking

t'le

dispute between the


lalists and the
materialists
ays that
^v ^licrc^
^^pl

|Ta
I

wl

fiTTAfTos

dfi(poTpoou

fxdxv

ly/'eVrr^/ce,/.

This does
mean that this dispute has
ays existed, but
that it was
old as the
Schools themes, or that,
every time the
It
was touched upon,
a

violent altercation
ensued bethe parties.
We are

tween
not

obliged

by this stateto refer this view


to an
earlier period than
that of
Socrates. And among
the Socratic Schools there
is none to

ment

which it can be
attributed
with so much probability
as to
the Megarian.
Some think

that

the passage refers to


Plato
{as Soaker, Plat.
Schriften, 265

and Sc/Ma9'sc/m4dt, Die


SammungderPlat.Sch.,210,do);and
tills

reference

commends

itself

most to those who with


them

declare that the


Sophistes is
not the work of
Plato.
The
reference would of course
to

be
an earlier form of
Plato's

teaching or to such
Platonists
as had failed to
advance with
their school. This is
the view of
l^'hern-eff Unters. Plat.
Schrif.
P,lffer, Ueber d.
a. Plat. Soph. Berlin,

^77

Orote,

Plato,

Athetese
1869, 21

468
iii. 482
Campbell, the Sophistes
and
Pohticus of Plato, Soph.
Ixxiv.
i125.
But is it likely that
1 lato can have treated a
theory
ot his own with so
much ironv
as he lavishes, p.
246, A.
i.

B.,

on

these etSft),/ (piKoi ? Is it


Plato's
teaching, or have we
reason
for thinking that it
ever was
Plato s teaching, that
the Sivafxis rov noieTu does
not belono-

to Being but to the


Becoming"?
In his system, as far
as it is
known to us, it does belong to
the idea of the good,
to the
creative povs of Timreus,
to the

airla of Pliilebus,
which must
at any rate be reckoned
as ovaia

Chap.
XII.

THE SOCEATIC SCHOOL.

258

we hope a picconnection of the several doctrines,


the Megarian doctrine..
ture will be produced of
and not

as y4ue(ns,

and in Phaido

ideas in
95, E., it belongs to

mises, the contradiction is noi


greater than that involved ii

Moreover, if the congeneral.


tested theory only belonged to
small portion of Plato's

denying every change, and yd


speaking of an action, an iuep

scholars, how could the little


fraction be opposed to the materialists as the chief supporters of the idealistic point
Does not the whole
of view ?
description create the impresone
sion that the contrast was
before
saw
writer
which the
him, and not one made from
different conceptions of his own

metaphysic?

It

Indeed, ho\
can he have ad
vanced from the Socratic phi
losophy of conceptions to hi
doctrine of unity? And does nc
the language of the Sophistei

76?i/

might seem

that by friends of ei'Sr? in this


passage Eviclid cannot have
been meant, because (1) ac-

cording to Aristotle's definite


assertion (Metaph. i. 6, 987, b,
Eth. N.
xiii. 4, 1078, b, 9
7
Plato first
1. 4, 1096, a, 13)
brought up the doctrine of
ideas, and (2) the Megarians
held one and not many primary
substances. The first reason is
Doubtless
not very cogent.
;

Plato first brought into notice


the doctrine of ideas to which
Aristotle refers, allowing that

Euclid agreed with him in declaring the ddos to be the only


Neireal element in things.
argument
second
the
ther is
Euclid may well
conclusive.
have
materialism
of
in cases
insisted, that in every object
the incorporeal form was the
only real thing, and yet have

gathered all these forms together under the one substance


good. If the latter assertion involved him in contradiction with his original pre-

the

of

being.

otherwise

246, B, telling, how that th


friends of ideas destroy mattf
by resolving it into its sma
lest particles, best correspou

with Euclid and his school


Does it not best harmoni;
with the statement of Ari
respecting the Meg
that the latter shou
have refused to being t
capacity to act or to suffe
whereas this would not at

tocles
rians,

harmonise with Plato.

Tl:

these philosophers are includ


245, E., among those hWas
yovres is not true, ^AXw? \eyopmeaning here literally th<;
/

who speak

differently,

does not turn


with the philosophers in<,
tioned 243, D) upon the /
tithesisof being andnot-beiil
With the philosophers to wh
Plato comes 245, E., the qv
tion is not whether there is
or more than one formi
being, everj^hing else be

whom

all

<

not-being, but whether th


thai
is only the corporeal or
Conf. p. 243,|
corporeal.

with 246, A.

Compare

ffe^

Bo/iitz, Plat. Stud, ii.'


105
In the explanation of diuKpf
;

Koyovixfvovs,

no one appear;

have exactly hit the mark.

MEGARIAN TEACHING.
which

shall,

in

"im

the main, faithfully represent


the

Chap.

facts.

Xli.

The

starting-point of

must be looked
ledge

tlie

for in Socrates'

of conceptions.

demand for a knowWith this demand Euclid

.3ombmed the Eleatic doctrine of a


contrast between
sensational and rational knowledge.
Distinguishing
;hese two kinds of knowledge
far more by their
objects than by their form, he
arrived at the convicwn that the senses show us wliat is capable
of change
ind becoming, and that only
thought can supply us
vith the knowledge of
what is unchangeable and
eally existing.'

He

stood, therefore, in general,

on

he same footing as Plato, and


it is possible that this
lew was arrived at by both
philosophers in common
a their intellectual
intercourse,

and that owing to

Euclid was influenced by


Heraclitus' view of
he world of sense.
Socrates had indeed made
the
mmediate business of thought to
be the acquisition
f a knowledge of
conceptions.
Conceptions, accordigly, represent that
'
part of a thing which
never
aanges.
Not material things, but only
'lato

incorporeal

Jecies,

'Ti

Hfi^

taught Euclid, admit of true


being

tjfius

yeuca-ei

("^7^

Megarian phiiosophy

5i'

aladv-

'^

Tn

iu^

The

'"i'*'""

"''

&V,^
.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOL.

260

Chap.
XII.

to allow

same view Stilpo expressed, when he refused

individual things,
the general conception to apply to
implies someon the ground that a general conception
individual thing,
thing quite different from every
definite timeJ
not like these only existing from a

and

again agree witt


In this respect the Megarians
aj
Whilst Plato, however, regarded species
Plato.2
following in the steps
living spiritual forces, Euclid,
kind of motion to being
of Parmenides, denied every
passion to th(
He, therefore, reduced action and
Of being, he asserted, jo\
sphere of the becoming.
passion, nor ye
can neither predicate action, nor

motion.^
'

Biog.

ii.

119, says of

him

ihai
eAeye, rhu Xeyoura 'dvOpuTrov

which we

suggest
fivUucL (in
yap
ovre
elvai),
of
instead
etTreTv
yap
ToVSe X4yeiv ovre rdvde. rl
ovre dpa
fxaWov
Koi TrdKiW rh Ka-xa-vov ouk
TocSe.
TOJ/56

6(TTt

fxev

TOj/Se;

deiKUvfJicvov.
rh
yhp ^v irpb juvptwj/

Kaxavov
eVwj/

ovk

sal

and

from an

different

particular
that what

man.
is

He

shown

to

denit_

him

i|

there W!
cabbage,
cabbage 10,000 years ago i;
other words, because the gene
cabbag
conception of
ral
unchangi
something
means

because

able, not

something which

hi

We

mi
Dio- come into
dpa eo-Ti rovTO xdxavov.
Ilegel, Gesc
with
believe
then
the
genes introduces this with
Phil. ii. 123, and Stallbaw
remark Setfbs 5e ^7av tbv ivrols d.
Parm. 65, that either Di
Plat.
and
ipKXTiKols dvripei Kol ra eUr],
or his authority mu
genes
possible,
be
it would in itself
some mistake her
made
have
had
that Stilpo and others
2 Probably
expressions Ii
geneto
hostility
derived their
mult
a in Platon
quoque
Hi
especially
ral conceptions, and
by C
Megarians
the
of
said
the
from
.to the Platonic ideas,
su
to
refer
129,
iv.
42,
Acad.
Cynic School. But the above
similarity.
of
points
directed
examples are not
3 PlatOy
Soph. 248, C.
against the reality of groups
yevi(TL fxiU fire(
OTi
yovfXLU,
conexpressed by a general
Swd^ei
reality rov Trao-xeiv Kal Troieti/
ception, but against the
ouSeTe/'
Stilpo irphs Se ovcriau rovrwv
being.

'

'

of

particular things.

a
denies that the individual is
man, because the expression
man means something univer-

T^v Uvajxiv apixoTTiiv (paff'iP.


;-.
is accordingly afterwards
ne^
their
as
stated
peatedly

MEGARIAN TEACHING,
jhe

261

Connected with this denial of the becoming is


assertion, probably coming from Euclid, certainly

srom his school, that capacity does not exist

he time of

its

exercise

alone possible.

and that thus what

What

beyond

is

actual

simply possible but not


ctual, would at the same time be and not be.
Here
70uld be the very contradiction which Parmenides
5

is

bought to discover in the becoming, and the change


rom the possible to the actual would be one of those
hanges which Euclid could not harmonise with the
onception of being.^
rh TTOJ/TeAcDs

*ov~\

Hence, only what

aKlvi\Tov ecTThs

rh Trapdirav ecrivai, and in opposition to this


evv Plato requires
'^aX
rh

vai.

aKiuTfTOv

vovfievou
iTfov

5rj

Kal Kivricriv axryx'^-

ws ovra

KoX TvoXKa

....

1x^)7 ^

raiu

Xeydt/ruv t6
iv eo-TTjKbs airoSex^ordai.
Ariscl. in Uus. Pr. Ev. xiv.
17, 1.
le proofs by which the Me7]

e'lSr]

denied motion will be


It does
however, seem likely that

irians

scribed hereafter.
t,

e objections raised to the


eory of ideas in the first part
Plato's Parmenides are of
3garian origin, as IStallbauvi,
Parra. 57 and 65, supposes.
.

'

AH.st.

Metaph.

Ttj/es o'i(paaiv,

ix.

8:

e/o-2

oTov ol MeyapiKol,

iv^pyrj ^6vov hvuaadai, OTau


M^ fi^fpyf] ov 5vuaa6ai. oXou
nh olKodofiovfra ov hvi/aadai
oBo/xui/, aWa rhu olKoSofiovyra

iv

'

IV
>

oIkoSo/x^

HXAuv.

tement

dfioicas

5e

Kal

eTTi

In refuting this
Aristotle observes

would make all motion


becoming
impossible
ich was just what the
Melans wanted.
Further par-

It it

is

imma-

ticulars on this point will be


quoted from Diodorus in the

sequel.
The passage
Hophistes,
248,
C,

He fine,
that

p. 133,

of

something
^

in the

which

connects with

Aristotle, refers
different.

Hai'tetistei/i, p.

to

205, is of

opinion that the above statement is made in direct contradiction to Aristotle. It would
in this case belong to Eubulides.
But the Aristotelian
technical terms Svvaadai, ii/epy^'ty,
do not prove much.
Aristotle often expressed the
statements of others in his
own terminology. On the
other hand, no very great importance for the system of
Aristotle must be attached to
the Megarian doctrine already
quoted, even if it comes from
Euclid. It is only a peculiar
way of understanding the
Eleatic doctrine against becoming and motion. Still less
can we here support the Megarians against Aristotle as
Grate, Plato, iii. 491, does
because a builder without ma:

Chap.
XII.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOL.

262

Chap.

terial

XII.

actual,
(2)

and regarded

allowed by

is

him

to

b'

as the subject matter of science

Socrates had described the good as the highes

The

Good.

and unchangeable

In this he was followed b

object of knowledge.^

mos
the highest object of knowledg

Eegarding, however, that which

Euclid.^

essentially real as

in accordance with his

is

principles, Euclid though

himself justified in transferring to the good

all tb

had assigned to rej


good is there, unchangeabL

attributes which Parmenides

being.

One only

real

ever the same, of which our highest conceptions ai


Whether we speak of God,
only different names.

of Intelligence, or of Eeason,
terials,

tools

and intentions,

cannot build, and when these

and other conditions are there,


must build. For this is not at
all the point on which the
dispute between Aristotle and
ArisMegarians turns.
on the contrary says in
the connection of the above
enquiry (Metaph. iv. 5, c. 7

the

totle

1049, a. 5), that if the necessary conditions for the exercise


of a capacity are given (among
which besides the Zuvdix^is Ao-

the intention must be


included), its exercise always

yiKoX

This, according to
follows.
Grote, is likewise the meaning
sentence,
Megarian
of the
which he disputes. Its real
meaning that a capacity until

shows itself by action is not


only kept in abeyance by the
absence of the necessary means,
and conditions, but is not even
existing maybe gathered from
the objections urged by Aristotle, c. 3, and from the quota-

it

we always mean

oi

Grote to defei
Megarians attributes
them reflections, which we ha
no right to attribute to them
See p. 133 and 147.
2 That
his assertions abo
the good should have nothi:
to do with the Socratic kno
ledge {Hermann, Ges. Abhan
tions, p. 230, 2.

the

242) could only be i


cepted on the supposition tt
that knowledge was not kno
ledge about the good, and tl
Euclid was not a pupil of i
Nor can it be read
crates.
conceded that a pure Elea
philosopher, if he had oi
moved in an ethical sphere
ideas, would have treated t!
part of philosophy in the sa:
way as Euclid. As long as^
remained a pure Eleatic phi
sopher, he could not hi
taken this ethical direct:
and have placed the concept
of the good at the head of
system.
lung,

MEGARIAN VIEW OF THE GOOD.

263

For the same reason

and the same thing, the Good.^

the moral aim, as Socrates had already shown,

always one

the knowledge

speak of

many

virtues,

of the Good,

and

if

names for one and the same virtue.^


What, however, is the relation of other things
one Good?

Even Euclid,
denied any existence to what
this

which

it follows

nothing real

XII.
is

we

these are but varying

all

to

as accounts tell us,


is

not good

from

immediately, that besides the Good


This statement

exists.

on better

is

authority attributed to the later Megarian School/

Therewith

many

conceptions, the reality of which

had been originally assumed, were destroyed as such,

and reduced, in

as far as

any

reality

was admitted

about them, to mere names of the Good.^


*

Acad.

Cic.

iv. 42,

29

Me-

bonum solum esse


quod esset unum et

garici qui id

dicebant,
simile et
says

idem semper

ravrSu).

'onoiov

Diof/.

Euclid

of

ovtos tu

ayakht/ a.TrCpaluero

(pp6D'riaiu,

vovv
^

Ko.\

ra

TToWas

rh
6v6-

Aristo

161, says of the


aperds t' oUtc

elariyei/,

fxiav TToWo'is

us

Z'f]iccu, oijre

v6fxaaL KaAovfiei/rju,

us 01 MeyapiKoi.
That this one
virtue was the knowledge of
the good, appears not only
from the internal connection
of the system and its external
relation to Socrates, but also
from Cicero 1. c. who asserts

Menedemo autem
Erequorum omne
bonum in mente posit um et
a

triaci ap})ellati

acie,

Here,

qua verum cerne-

Illi
(the Megarians)
retur.
similia, sed, opinor, explicata
Conf.
uberius et ornatius.
Plato, Rep. vi. 505, B., in

is mentioned in addition to Euclid.


^ Uiof/.
ii.
106 ra 5e avriKfiixeua tw ayad<^ av/jpei yuTj eluai

which Antisthenes

<pd(TKWV.

Xoiird.

I)iu(j. vii.

Stoic

ttoAA-oTs

106,

ore /jlcv yap


ore 5e Oehu, Kal &\\or

KaXov/xevo}/

fiaai

{oiov,

ii.

mentis

Arist. in Ens. Pr. Ev. xiv.


oQ(v r]^iovv ovroi ye [^ol

17, 1

2T(\7rwva Kal tovs MeyapiKovs'\ rh hu eu dual Kal rh ^ut; ou


eiepou (Ivai, nrjBe yevvao'dal ri

Trepl

fxrjSk

(pOeipfddai.

/uTjSe

Chap.

Kiudffdai

Arist. Metaph. xiv.


4
101)1, b, 13, refers to Plato,
and can hardly be applied to
Toirapairav.
;

the Megarians.
* PrantVs view, p. 35, that
the conceptions of the Megarians must invariably have
a nominalistic meaning, does

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOL.

264
Chap.
XII.

probably, traces of gradual development in the Megarian doctrine are to be found.


Euclid apparently
first

spoke of a plurality of essential conceptions in

contrast to objects of sense, and this form of teach-

ing belongs primarily to a time in which his system


was being developed out of this contrast.^ At a later
period the Megarians appear to have used the mani-'

foldness of conceptions for the purpose of attacking

popular notions,^ otherwise keeping it in the background, and confining themselves to the essential
oneness of being and the Grood.
Inconsistent, no"
doubt, they were

became involved

we can understand how

yet

in this contradiction

they!!

by gradually

pushing the Socratic theory of conceptions to

the^

abstract doctrine of the Eleatic One.^

The sharper the

C. Eristic.

contrast which they presented

not agree with the statements


of Plato.
If the Megarians
declared conceptions and only
conceptions to be aXrjdiv^ oucria,
surely they were Realists, not
Nominalists. Not even Stilpo
can, accordingly, be called a
Nominalist.
He had, moreover, absorbed too much of
the Cynic doctrines for us to
be able to form from him any
conclusion respecting the original Megarian views.
Plato, at least in the passage before quoted, does not
^

mention a good which is One.


On the contrary, he speaks of
his philosophers of conceptions
differing from the Eleatics in

assuming many conceptions.


2

gge p_ 260,

'

He/i/ie, p. 121, tries to

1.

get

over the difficulty in another


The Megarians, he believes, attributed being to each
particular idea, in as far as it
was a unity, and various conceptions were used by them to
express various kinds of the
good.
But this very pointthe being of various kinds of
good was what the Megarians
denied. Starting with tl^e oneness of being they cannot have
arrived at the notion of a manifoldness of conceptions, since
this oneness excludes in its abj
stract form any development'"
or subordinate distinction. But
it is quite possible that the
Socratic
may|'|
conceptions
gradually have been lost in
the Eleatic unity.

way.

'

'

MEGARIAN
to the current

mode

ERISTIC.

of thought, the greater

the necessity of fortifying their

own

example of the Eleatics.

became

Chap.
^^^'

position against

Here again they had only

assault.

i>Orj

the

follow

to

To prove the soundness

of

their position directly, as

Parmenides had done, was


More important results might be

no easy matter.

expected, if their opponents' ground was assailed by


jthe criticism of Zeno and Gorgias.
From Zeno the
(founder of the School

had appropriated the Eleatic

doctrine precisely in this

its

critical function,

Zeno

and the Sophists being the principal persons who


drew attention hereto in central Greece. This path
of criticism the Megarians now struck out with such
preference, that the whole school herefrom derived
its

name.^

We

the practice

are assured

in

explanations

by Socrates
pakes nothing
ased

rrelevant.

was
%

other words, to refute by a

ad absurdum.

rejected

it

even of Euclid, to attack conclusions

and not premises


[reductio

by Diogenes,^ that

It

is

also said that Euclid

by analogies

form much

(l) TJuit

"f

^^^^^^f^-

because a similar thing when cited


clearer,

The most

and a dissimilar thing

is

telling description of Euclid's

nethod will probably be found in Plato, who, speakSee p. 250,^3.


roAs re aTroSei^eo-ij/
107
'vlffraTo oif Kara X-nfifiara aWa
car' iiricpopdu.
Since in Stoical
erminology which we are of
'-ourse not justified in ascribing
o Euclid on the strength of
his passage AtjjUjuo means the
uajor premiss, or more often
>oth premises, and 4-ni(popa the
.onclusion {Deychs, 34 Prantl,
^

li.

470), it

most probable that

is

meaning given above is the


real meaning of these words,
^ iMd. kuI rhu 5ia irapalSoXiis
the

Adyov

ainjpei,

avrhi^ ^
/cot

Se7v

ei

'e|

Aeywj/ ^tol i^ SfMoiwu

avo/xoioov a-wia-Taaeai

fxev e^

fiaAAov

ai^aaTpecpeaOai

-KapiKK^iv

tV

6i.Loicov,
t)

oh

5'

irepl

o/xoid
e'l

TrapaQ^av.

avra
ioTiv

avofiolccu,

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOL.

2G6

Chap.
VTT

ing in the Sophistes of the philosophers of conceptions, says that in their discourses

they destroy matter

piecemeal, in order to prove that

it

but

has no real being

subject to flux and change.^

is

This

is

exactly

the line which Zeno adopted, in order to prove the


uncertainty of the perceptions of the senses

which we notice
Megarians
is

in

no limit to

Sorites

of the later

component parts, and there being


the division, and no ultimate atom
its

contemplation

which

the

and

the apparently substantial bodily mass

divided into

on

also

;2

can

rest,

it

is

argued

must be itself unreal, and a mere passEuclid is accordingly rightly reing phenomenon.
garded as the founder of the Megarian criticism.
Still, with him criticism does not seem to have atthat matter

tained the character of formal captiousness, although


objection

may

would appear

be taken to his controversial tone


that, like

:^

it

Zeno before him, he wa?

primarily anxious to maintain his positive princi-

and that he only used tlie subtleties of argument


Nothing, at least, is knowD
as a means to this end.
of him which would lead to an opposite conclusion,

ples,

nor

is

any one of the quibbling

fallacies laid to his

charge, for which the Megarian school was afterwards


notorious.
See p. 256,

1 ; 259, 2.
SeeZeller, G. d. Griecli. Part
I., 496.
3 According to Dior/, ii. 30,
'

Socrates had already observed,


that because of his captiousness,

sibly

he might associate poswith Sophists, but not

with human beings.

But

this

statement

proves

but

little,

since it uses the term Sophist


in a way peculiar to post- Socratic times. It is more worth}
of belief {JDiog. ii. 107) that
Timon called him a quarrelsome person, who introduced

amongst the Megarians a


for disputes.

rage

MEGARIAN CAPTIOUSNESS.
Among

the immediate successors of Euclid, how-

element of

the

ever,

positive teaching.

too scanty to

abstract to

267

captiousness

Such teaching

command

had was
long, and too

as they

attention for

On

admit of further development.

other hand a polemic

over

prevailed

the

against prevailing opinions

presented to the sharp-witted, to the contentious, and


to those

ambitious of intellectual distinction, an un-

which the Megarians eagerly

over

explored

field,

ranged.'

Not seldom

their metaphysical assumptions

served only as occasions for hard-fighting with words.

Among

the fallacies which are attributed to

though they probably belong to an

lides,^

The ordinary form of these


captious proofs is that of askHence the
ing questions.
regular expression xSyov ipwrav (to raise a point) in IJiofj.
IIG Se.H. Math. x. 87
ii. 108
and the McyapiKa epcoT'^/iora in
the fragment of Chrysippus
in Pint. Sto. Rep. 10, 9, p. 103(5.
Conf. Arist. Phys. viii. 8 2(53,
Anal. Pr. ii. IJ), 6(5, a,
a, 4, 7
But
i. 32, 47, a, 21.
36
2(5
like the Sophists, they refused
every answer but Yes or No.
Diog. ii. 135.
- Diog.
ii.
108, enumerates
that called v/zeuSd/Aei'os, that
7
called ^laKauQaviav, the Elect ra,
the iyKKa\vixfxiuo9, the trwptTTjs,
the /ceparti/Tjs, the <pa\aKp6s. The
:

of them is given as follows in Ai^st. Soph. El. 25, 180,


Alex, ad loc. Cic.
a, 34, b, 2
Acad. ii. 29, 95 If a man says
he is at the moment telling a
lie, is he telling a lie, or is he
speaking truth ? The ^iuKavdd-

first

Eubuearlier

the iyKeKa\vixfieuos, and the

vwy,

Elect ra are only different forms


Do you
of the same fallacy.

know who is concealed ? Do


you know who is behind the
veil ?
Did Elect ra know her
brother before he announced
himself to her ? and the solution of them all consists in
the fact, that he who was concealed, or behind the veil, or

announced himwas known


but not immediately recog-

had

not.

self

respectively,

to,

j^et

nised by, the lookers on.

Arut.

S. El.

c.

See

24, 179, a, 33;

Lucian,
Alex, in loc. and 49
Vit. Auct. 22, and Prantl. The
Have
Kparip7)s is as follows
you lost your horns ? If you
say Yes, you allow that you had
;

If you saj' No, you


allow that you have them still.
vi. 38
Seneoay
I)iog. vii. 187
Gell. xvi. 2, 9;
Ep.' 45, 8;
Prantl, p. 53. The Sorites conHow
sists in the question:

horns.

Chap,
XII.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOL.

26S

Chap.

^pEnhu-''
I ides.

time,^ only one, the Sorites, has

argument
belongs

it

to

intelligible rela-

of this form of

could be proved that no enduring being


objects of sense, but

object passes into

its

that

every such

and represents what is


real and unchangeable.

opposite,

changing, and not what

The

any

By means

tion to their metaphysics.

is

appear to be simple sophisms, having no


other object than to involve opponents in difficulties/
rest

critical

works of

art,

which made indeed the need

of an accurate investigation into the laws of


thought, but in the pursuit of which the desire of
felt

conducing to a right intellectual method by pointing


out difficulties and refuting untenable opinions
altogether into the background.
(3)

The powers of Alexinus

TiMtof

falls

argument seem

in

to

Alexitms.

many

grains

make

a heap

or

more generally
With what
number does Many begin ? Of
:

course

impossible to assign

it is

a number. See Cic. Acad. ii. 2S,


92 16, 49 Diog. vii. 82 Pers.
;

Sat. vi. 78 ; Prantl, p. 54. The


(paXaKphs is another form of the

same How many hairs must


you lose to become a bald-head ?
:

See Hor. Ep.

ii. 1,

45

Prantl,

Dei/cks, 51.
are, for instance, indications of
the Sorites in
1. c.
'

There

Zeno and Euclid.


it is

difficult

In general
to say who are

the

discoverers of
quibbles,
which are taken seriously at
the time they are produced,
but are after all only bad jokes.
Seneca, Ep. 45, 10, says that

many books had been written


on the \pevB6ixvos, among which
those

of

Theophrastus

and

Chrysippus

are

known

to us
196
v. 49.
Chrysippus, according to Bioff.
vii. 198, 192, also wrote on the
5ia\au6dvcav, the iyKeKaXv/x/jLivos,
and the awpirrjs. Philetus of
Cos is said to have worked
himself to death in writing
about the \l/ev56iJ.uos, Athen.

from

ix.

Dioff.

401,

e.

vii.

The /cepoTiVrjs and


were also attri-

iyK^KaXv/xixei/os

buted
Ill),

Diodorus {Diog.

ii.

and the former {Diog.

vii.

to

187) as also the Sorites {Diog.


82) to Chrysippus, certainly
without reason to Chrysippus.
^ Compare what will be later
said about Diodorus' proofs in
vii.

denying motion.
^ The
motive which Prantl,
p. 52, sees in the iyKcKaKvfxfxevos
is not so patent, and the as-

sumptions of Brandts,
do not seem accurate.

p. 122,

DIODORUS THE MEGARIAN.


have been of a similar kind.

known

to

us

further

is

known

He, at

m.)

only

least, is

Nothing
of him beyond an argument in
which he vainly attempted to entangle Menedemus
in what is called the ' horned fallacy,^ and a refutation of Xenophon's proofs of the reasonable arrangea

as

captious disputant.^

Chai'.
^^^'

'

ment

of the world, ^ which was subsequently repeated

by the Academicians."

In close connection with the

Megarian doctrines may be placed the discussions of


Diodorus on motion and destruction, on the possible,
and on hypothetical sentences.
Tradition has preserved four arguments, by which

Diodorus attempted to

support

the fundamental

{i)

That of

^*'''^^''*''''-

teaching of his school on the impossibility of motion. MotioL


The first,^ which in the main is the same as that of
Zeno,

must

Supposing anything

is as follows.

either

move

in

the space in which

to

the space in which

it

is

it is,

In the former

not.

not room to move, because

move,

it entirely fills it

latter it

can neither act nor be acted upon

motion

is

'

'^

The second

inconceivable.^

Zeno

concluded, because the


world is the best possible, and
reason is higher than the absence of reason, that the world
must have reason.
See Cic.
De N. D. ii. 8, 21; iii. 9, 22.
To this Alexinus replied
rh
TToiT^TiKhu Tov jxi] TTotTjTiKoD Koi rh
:

tov fi^ ypafj-ixaTiKov


KpuTr6y fVrt /cat rh Kara ras
&\\as Tc'xi'as Qiwpovixivuv Kp(:ht6v ia-Ti TOV ju?^ TOLovTov.
ou5e
*

it

has

in the

hence

a less

is

6 K6<r/xos.

had

ypap.fxa.TiKhu

or in

%v Se kSct/ulov Kp^lrrov iarr ttoitjTiKhv apa koI ypaiuL/xaTiKoy iariv

See p. 254, 1.
In Diog. ii. 135.
Sext. Math. ix. 107

it

N. D.

Cic.

21

242

iii, 8,

10, 26

11, 27.
*

Sext. P\'rrh,

Math.

x.

85

i.

ii.

iii.

71

311.

^ Sext. Pyrrh. iii, 243, mentions a similar argument against


becoming in general, in immedlatc conncctiou with the proof

given above
is

come

Neither can what

into being, for

it

exists

already nor can what is not,


for nothing can happen to it
;

THE SOCHATIC SCHOOL.

270
Chap.
XII
'

accurate form of the same proof. ^


.

is

in space

what

is

What

moved

moves

All that

is in space reposes

reposes.

Therefore

third proofs

is

based on

the assumption of infinitesimal atoms and particles.


It

is

generally attributed to Diodorus.^

Probably he

Zeno did

his argument,

only used

it

hypothetically, as

to refute ordinary notions.'*

the particle a

is

does

space, B

it

completely

it

move when

for

no sooner

it is
is

Accordingly

has ceased.

As long

as

in the corresponding space a, it does

not move, because


little

It is this

it

it

fills

Just as

it.

in the next following

there than

move

does not

In this conclusion one cannot

fail

motion

its

at

all.

to discover the

note of Zeno's inferences, and of that critical process

which had been already described by Plato.^ The


fourth proof,^ besides assuming the existence of atoms,
distinguishes between partial and complete motion.^
Every moving body must first have the majority of
consequentlj- nothing at all is,
It is possible that this argument also belongs to Diodorus,
But Steinlidvt is wrong in attributing to him (Allg. Encykl
Sect. i. vol. XXV. p. 288) the
distinction between space in
the wider and in the narrower
sense, which is found in Scxt.
Math. x. 95,
Pyrrh. iii. 75
since it would appear from
these passages that the distinction was made with a view
to meet Diodorus' objections,
;

Sext. Math. x. 112.


Id. X. 143 and 119.

Alexander, too, De Sensu, 125, b,


mentions Diodorus, X6yos irepl
'^

T&'i/ kfj.<:p<i)v.

^ Id. ix. 362


Pyrrh, iii. 32
Dionys. in Bus. Pr. Ev. xiv. 23,
Pseudo4 ; Stob. Ekl i. 103
clement, Eecogn. viii. 15, all of
which point to one common
source.
Simjjl. Phys. 216, b
;

Schol.

in

Arist.

Diodorus called

405,

these

a,

21.

atoms

afx^prj,
*

Even the

first

proof, accor-

ding to Sext. Math. x. 85, was


put in such a shape as to prove

that every atom fully occupied 11


but this is unim- l'
its space
portant here.
^ See p. 265.
;

'

Sext. Math. x. 113.

Kivncris

nar

iirifcpdrfiap

Kifijais kt' elKiKpiv^MV.

and

DlOnOHUS THE MEGAUIAN.


moved, before

particles

its

that

should

it

can

it

move

271

as a

move with the majority

whole

Chap.

however,

is,

For supposing a body to consist of


three atoms, two of which move whilst the third is
at rest, such a body must move, because the majority

not conceivable.

move.

of its particles

atom

fourth

moved kut
consists are

at rest

is

applies,

added:

the body being

for

airiKpdrsiav^ the three

atoms of which

it

rest

Why

not

when a

equall}^

moved, consequently the fourth at

added to the three moving atoms.

is

when

The same

fifth

and a sixth atom

added

is

So

body consisting of 10,000 particles must be


moved, if only two of these first move. If this is, howthat a

ever, absurd, a

movement of

the majority of particles

and therefore a movement


That there is an inconclusiveof the whole body.
ness in this argument Sextus has already noticed.^

is

therefore inconceivable,

Diodorus, however, appears

to

have considered

unanswerable, and hence, he concludes

all

his

it

re-

searches by saying that it never can be said of a

thing. It

was,

in

senses

is

moving, but only. It has

other words,

prepared to allow wliat the

seemed to prove,^ that a body

place and

now

in

He

moved.'-^

now

is

one

in

but he declared the

another,

from the one to the other to be impossible.


indeed a contradiction, and as such it was

transition

This

is

A
Scft. Math. X. 112, 118.
further argument, the first
argument of Zeno's, is not attributed to Diodorus by Scxt.
Math. X. 47. He onl}'^ says as
to its result, that
Diodorus
'

aiirccd therein with the Eleatics.


-

Se.rt.

07-102.
^ This

Math.

x.

reason

mentioned 1y

48; 85
is

>V'.rf.

J)l

specially
x, 80.

Math,

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOL.

i^7^

Chap.

by the ancients, and by him very


inadequately met.^
At the same time it is a deviation from the original teaching of his school.
Euclid
denied motion absolutely, and would just as little
laid to his charge

have allowed a completed motion as a transition

Idi

the present.

On

(J))

With

Destrncfiori.

the third of these arsfuments


agrees
sub^

stantially the argument of Diodorus that nothing


.

perishes.

not perish
stands

It is as follows.
;

so

Wall, he says, does

long as the stones keep together,

but when the stones are separated

That

longer exists.^

it

may however hxwe

it

it

no

perished,,

he appears to have likewise allowed.


{c)

On

Closely related to the enquiry into motion, are,

the

on what

his discussions

possible.

is

the conceivability of change


in

one case

the

other

is

In both cases

the point raised, but

raised in reference to somethino', in

it is

abstractedly.

In both

cases,

Diodorus

stands on exactly the same footing with regard to


his School.

The

older Megarians allowed as possible

only what actually

is,

understanding by actual what

was before them in the present.^ To this Diodorus'


added what might be in the future, by saying Pos-'
:

sible is

what either

is

actual or what will be actual.*

'
^ee Sext. ^1, ^1
Diodorus
here proves the assertion that
anything predicated of the past
may be true, whilst it is not
true predicated of the present
by such irrelevant statements
as that it can be said of Helen
that she Jmd three husbands
(one after another), but never
that she lias three (cotempora,

This example is^


show how erroneous,
Grote"s view (Plato iii. 501) is,'

neously).

sufficient to

that Diodorus only intended to


assert that present motion is
only the transition point between the past and the present,
^ ggxt. Math. x. 347.
^ See p. 261.
*

Cic.

De

Fato,

6,

12;

7,

13;

'

PHILO THE MEGARIAN.

273

proof of this statement he used an argument,


v^hich goes by the name of icvpiBV(dv,
and is still
.n

Chap.

^^

idmired after centuries,' as a masterpiece of


subtle
riticism.
It is in the main as follows
From any:

hing possible nothing impossible can result 2


but
b is impossible that the past
can be different from
;

had this been possible at a past


loment, something impossible would have resulted
rem something possible.
It was therefore never
^hat

it

is;

for

And speaking

ossible.

generally

it

impossible

is

anything should happen differently from what


happened.^

iat
as

Far less exacting was Philo, a pupil of Diodorus, (5) Thatr


hen he declared everything to be possible,
even ^a^^on,
lould outward circumstances prevent it
from being Poi^nU,:.
Ep. ad Fam. ix. 4 Phut.
Rep. 46, p. 1055; Alex.
3h. in Anal. Pr. 59, b
Schol.
Arist. 163, b, 29; Simpl.,
17

the

id. 65, b,

19

Philip, ibid. 163,


Boeha, de Interpret. Op.

Basil,

364

19.

)g. i.

Prantl, Gesch. d.

The above sentence

expressed here thus Possible


^TTfp ^ eVxij/ aATjOes ^ iffrai..
Comp. Epict. Diss. ii. 18,
we ought to be proud of
)ral actions, ovk eVi tw rhv
HfvouTa ipwrrjaai, and just
:

'

fore

Kojxrphu (ro^Kr/LidTiov eAu-

i,'JTo\v KOfM\p6Tepou
.

He

rod Kvpievou-

also mentions,

ii.

:reatises of Cleanthes,
'pus,

Antipater,

Chry-

and Archi-

on the Kvpidcov.
pus could only meet

iBus

19,

Chryit (ac-

ding to Alex, in Anal. Pr.


h, in Schol. in Arist.
163, a,

by asserting that possibly

impossible

from the

.0.

might

possible.

result

Other pas-

sages are quoted by PrantL r>.


^
40, 36.

^ So aKo\ovd7u is
rendered,
thus keeping up the ambiguity
of^ the original, where d/coAouBf'iv means not only
sequence
in time, but causal sequence.

Epict. Diss. ii. 19, 1


6
\6yos airh toiovtoou Tivuy

Kvpivoou

acpopixHv vpcvTrirrOai (paivcrai


V7)s

yap

koi-

/ndxvs roh rpial


Toinoi<s TTphs ^AATjAa, tw 'ttSj/
-ap\7]Xv6bs a\r]6h avayKoiov cluai
oijarjs

'

Kai T(2

'

\ovde7u,'
oijT

Sviarw aSvyaroi'
Koi Tc?

'

a\7]dh

ea-TLu

a-vviSwu

tV

araaiu

rov

fih

Suj/arb*/

out'

olko-

dvai h
eo-rai,'

ixdxvt' ravTt]u 6 Ai6Supos rfj ruv rrpcoTwv SvoTu iriQavorriTi


o-vvfxpVfreTO irphs irapdt>

oijT

^urjSej/

^(TTiv

Conf. Cic.

De

dATjflej

Fato,

dvai
oUt'
6.

Swarhu
eo-Tai.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

274
Chap.

realised,^

^^^-

therefor.

provided a thing has only the capacity


This was undeniably a departure from

the Megarian teaching.


(&) Onhij^sfrdences

In regard, too, to the truth of hypothetical senfences, Philo laid down criteria different from those

Diodorus declared those conditional

of his teacher.2

sentences to be true, in which the apodosis neither

can be

false,

nor ever could be false

true in which there


apodosis.

only the pro-

Philo says more vaguely, those are

be true.

tasis

if

is

not a true protasis and a

The question here

false

appears, however, to

have been one of formal correctness in expressing


logical rules.^
(c)

On

With

the

Diodorus' view of the possible the assertion

that no words are meaningZmZI^^^'^ appears to be connected,


less or ambiguous, each one always meaning some-

thing, and everyone requiring to be understood ac- j


cording to this meaning ^ he will only allow that j
:

to be possible

meaning of a word

present to the speaker's mind.

which

is actually

Eespecting Diodorus

however, and the whole Megarian School, our


in
Categ.Alex.-^\m^\.
Schol. in Arist. 65, a, 39, b, 6
1

Pantlioides, according to Exnct. Diss. ii. 19, 5,


attempted by another turn to

BoeTiSy

1. c.

avoid Diodorus' argument, by


disputing the sentence that
every thing past must be of
necessity.
2 See
Sext.

Math.
Acad.

viii.

113

Philo,

do not

infor-

affect his rea

however mucl
they may follow from the word
of his definition. Hence Pranti

meaning

at

all,

can hardly have quit>


grasped the meaning of Philo.

p. 454,

*
Ammon., D
Gell. xi. 12
Interpret. 32, a Schol. in Ar: s1
Simpl. Categ. f. C I
1103, b, 15
In order to show that everj J
h.
word has a meaning, DiodorujJ
;

Pyrrh.
;

i.

ii.

309

110;
Cic.

iv. 47, 143.

The inferences by which


M. viii. 115, refutes

Sextus,

according to Ammon., gave


name aXKafir\v to one of

th'

hi

slaves.

STILPO THE MEGARIAN.

276

mation

is far too scanty to enable us


to bring the
fragments of their teaching into a perfectly
satisfactory context/ granting that enough is
known

Chap.

^^-

to

evidence one and the

same tendency in all these


thinkers.
It may then be assumed as probable,
that
the Megarians did not confine themselves
to those
logical subtleties

which are known to us

our notices
however, too deficient for us to be able to
attribute others to them with anything like
certainty.2
;

are,

peculiar position in the Megarian philosophy

is

(6)

That

that occupied by Stilpo.

Ever ready to defend the


^Mclr'
teaching of the School at the head of which
he stood, 'adopud
-clinging to universal conceptions,

maintaining the imbecoming, the unity of being,^ and the


difference between sensuous and rational
perceptions,^
possibility of

J^^^^^^'^'^^
^V'^'''^-

^comuZ^

he at the same time combines with his


Meo-arian ^^^.^/
views theories and aims which originally
belonged to '^"^edithe Cynics.
In the first place he rejected, as did An-

Jf/J^,

im,j)08sible,

muer^s (Rh Mus

Cxesch. der. Phil.

ii.

ii.

310,

140) con-

seem m many respects


to go beyond historical probabihty and beyond the spirit of
the Meganan teaching.
To
aiustrate this here would take
jeclures

.t^\i
PrantU

Kr

.,
.
P- 43, believes that
majority of the sophisms
3numeratcd by Aristotle really
Delongto the Megarians. Most
)f them, however,
would ap3ear to come from the So3hists; in proof of which a
cference may be
made to

the

Euthydemus, which
'.an hardly have the Megarians
nvievv.
Towards Euclid Plato

Plato s

would not have used such language, as may be gathered


from the Sophistes 246 C
and the introduction to' the
The^tetus and Eubulides had
not appeared when Plato composed the Euthydemus
That
*^^ Megarians made use of
;

many of

the Sophistic fallacies


of course not denied
Onfv
nothing for certain is 'known
of such use.
is

ggg pp ggQ, 3-263 4


Compare the' passage in
Aristoclcs quoted p 250 l in
^

which

o.'

^repl

M7ap.oi;s

Sr/ATrco.a Kal Toi.s

are spoken of
addition to the Eleatics

T 2

in

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

270

Chap.
XII.

combination of subject and predicate,


since the conception of the one is different from the
conception of the other, and two things with different
tisthenes, every

conceptions can never be declared to be the same.^


The doctrine of the unity of being,^ in as far as it can

be shown to have originated

may

with Stilpo,

deduced as a corollary from this \dew


can be predicated of anything else,
being can alone be predicated of

for if

it

be

nothing

follows that

itself.

Truly cynical are also Stilpo's moral principles.


The captious logic to which other Megarians devoted
themselves with speculative onesidedness, to the entire
neglect of the ethical element,^ was also a charac-

In Pint. adv. Col. 22, 1, p.


1119, theUpicvrean Stilpo raises
the objection rbv dehv avaipu(rQai utt' auToG, K^yovros erepop

erepov

fxr)

KaTTjyopelcrOai.

ttuis

\4yovTS &vaW' avOpwdpct3TTOV ayaQhv


ayaOhv
irov ^.uOpcoTTOV Koi X^P^5
and again, c. 23
ayadov
ou ix7]i' aWa rh iir\ 2Ti\7rcoj/os
el Trept 'Ittttov rh
roiovTOV icrriv.

yap

5(aj(rd/x60a,

[x^

rpXiv Karriyopovfieu, ov (piqai


ravrhv eJpai to? irepl ov Karr^yopelrai rh KaT7}yopovfXVOV, aAA.'
'itepov fj.eu avOpcaTTcp tov ti "^v
erepov 5e rw
elvai rhv Koyov,
ayaQw koX -rrdXiu rh "ttttov eivai
rov rp^xovra dvai diacpepeiv hKaripov yap airaiTOvuevoi rbv \oyov
'

'

ov

rhv

avrhv airodiboixev v-nlp


a^aprdveivrovs 'drep^v

aiKpotv. odev

krioov Karriyopovvras. The very


will be found in the
case of Antisthenes. All the less
reason has Plutarch to regard

same thing

Stilpo's assertion as a mere


The same proof is given
joke.
by Sim-pl Phys. 26, a. Sia Sh
Tepi ravra (the distinction
between the different categories and the ambiguity of
words) 6.yvoiav Kal ol MeyapiKoi
K\7}64vres (pi\6cro(poi Ka^ovres us
ivapyrj TrporacTLv, ori uv ol \6yoi
:

tV

ravra eVepa icrri Kal 3t


erepa /cexcopjCTai ctA-A-i^Acuv,
idoKovv BeiKvvvaL avrov avrov Kei.e. since
eKacrrov
XC'pi-o'lJi-dvov
the conception of SwKpoTTjs
fxovariKos is a different one to
that of 'S.wKpdrTjs \vk6s, the
one according to Megarian
hypothesis must be a different
person to the other.
2 See p. 263.
3 Excepting
Euclid's doctrine of the oneness of virtue,
eVepoi

ra

nothing bearing on Ethics is


as belonging to the
Megarians.

known

;:

STILPO THE MEGAlilAN.


teristic of Stilpo

and perhaps

'

it is

277

only an accident

that no captious assertion or discovery of his

Ch.a

on __^il_
His character, however, is not only always (*) ^^'
mentioned by biographers with the greatest respect,=^ gHod^
but many traits are recorded of him, which identify '^^^^^^ ^"
nis morality with that of the Cynics.
The highest
good he placed in that apathy, which forbids the
is

record.

feeHng of pain even to

The wise man

exist.

is

re-

quired to be in himself independent, and not even to


stand in need of friends to secure happiness.^ When

Demetrius Poliorcetes enquired after his losses by the


plunder of Megara, he gave for answer that he had
seen no one carrying off his knowledge."*
When re-

minded of the immoral

life of his daughter, he rehe could not bring honour on her, she
could not bring disgrace on him.^
Banishment he

joined, that if

See Chrysipp. in Plut. Sto.


Rep. 10, 11, p. 1036, and pp. 211,
t ; 210, 6.
2 See p. 251, note 3.
* Sen. Ep.
* An
merito
9, 1
-eprehendat in quadam epistola
'

Epicurus eos, qui dicunt sapi-

contentum
propter hoc amico non indi-

intern se ipso esse


3t

Hoc obStilboni ab Epicuro et

?ere desideras scire.


jicitur

is,
quibus summum bonum
/isum est animus impatiens.'
\nd a little further on
Hoc
nter nos et illos
interest
loster sapiens vincit quidem
ncommodum omne sed sentit
llonmi ne
sentit quidem.'
Ilonnected herewith is the ob:

'

iervation of Stilpo in Teles, in


'itoh. Floril.
103, 83, in order
o wain from excessive grief

at

the

death of relative^;.
Aphr. De An. 103,
remarks also probably applies

What AUx.
a,

to Stilpo, that

look

on

the Megarian.s
as irpuTou

do-xATjaio

oIk^Iov.

Plutarch, Demet. c. 9
Tranquil. An, c. 17, p. 475
Puer. Ed. c. 8, p. 6 Seti. de
Const. 5, 6
Epis. 9, 18 Diog.
ii. 115
Floril. Joan. Damasc.

13, 153 {Stoh. Floril. ed.


Mein. iv. 227).
That Stilpo
thereby lost his
wife and
daughter is probably a rhetorical exaggeration of Seneca,
ii.

The well-known

mecum
Seneca

'

omnia mea

porto,' attributed by
to Stilpo, is by Cicero

referred to Bias of Prisne.


* Plut. An. Tran. c.
Diog.
6
;

ii.

114.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

278

Chap.
"VTT

would not allow to be an evil.^ To be independent


of everything without, and to be absolutely free from
wants this highest standard of Cynicism for the wise

man was

And

also his ideal.

lastly,

the free attitude

towards religion adopted by the Cynics was also shared

(c)

The

by him, and finds expression in many of his utterances.^


Whether, and if so, in what way, he attempted
to set up a logical connection between the Cynic and

we

In

such a

mgaHan

Megariau

theories

task was not difficult.

oaMy har-

subject can admit a predicate, Euclid's hostile attitude

theories,

wonised by towards proof


rests

are not told.

With

by analogy

is

itself,

the assertion that no,

closely related

too

tliis

on the general proposition that things dissimilar

cannot be compared.

It

is

also quite in

harmony

with the negative criticism of the Megarians

and

if

Euclid denied to the good any form of manifoldness,


others might add, as Antisthenes really did, that the

one and not the manifold could alone

exist.

More-

over from the oneness of the good the apathy of the


wise

man might

else besides the

be deduced, by considering that

good

is

unreal and indifferent.^

The'

denial of the popular faith was also involved in

doctrine of the one, even as

Xenophanes.
>

was

first

8.

2 According to Diog. ii.


116,
he proved that the Athene of
Phidias was not a God, and
then before the Areopagus

evasively replied that she was

not a Bibs but a Sea, and when


Crates asked him as to prayers
and sacrifices, replied that

thei

taught b}

In the Cynic element as adopted

In the fragment in Sioh.

Flor. 40,

it

all,

b}

these subjects could not


discussed in the street. TL
story in Pliit. Prof, in Virt
12, p. 83, of the dream in whicl
he conversed with Poseidon ii
apparently invented to justify
his omission to sacrifice.
^ Conf. Diog. ii. 106, and
j|
1

263, 3

ELEAN-ERETRIAN SCHOOL.
Stilpo, there

approach

were not wanting,

to the Megarians,

it

but

true, points of

is

it

270

Chap.
XII.

was a deviation

from the original form of the Megarian teaching to


allow explicitly such an element to exist.
Closely connected with the

Megarian school

is

the Elean-Eretrian, respecting which, however, very


little

information

was Phsedo of
^

and

reached

has

Elis,^

the well-known

See Preller's Phasdo's Life


Mus.
Writings, Rhein.

Pheedo,
fur Phiiol. iv. 391.
the scion of a noble Elean
family, had been taken captive not long before the death
of Socrates, probably 400 or
Preller concludes
B.C.
401
from Phaedo, 89, B,, that he
was not eighteen years of age
at the time of the death of
Socrates it may, however, be
;

asked whether Phaedo followed


Athenian customs in his dress.
He was employed as a slave
in most humiliating services at
Athens, until one of Socrates'
friends (besides Crito, Cebes
and Alcibiades are both mentioned, the latter certainly not
being at Athens at the time,
and probably not being alive)
redeemed him at the intercession of Socrates.
See Diog. ii.
Suid. under ^aiZwv
31, 105
and Hesych. Vir Ulustr. 4>a(5coj/
Macroh. Sat.
Gell. N. A. ii. 18
i.
11; Lact. Inst. iii. 25, 15;
Orig. c. Gels. iii. 67 Cic. N. D.
i.
Athen. xi. 507, c.
33, 93
Preller not improbably finds
the source of the story in
Ilermippu^, Trepl tuv Stairpe;

^6,v((iiv

(Plato,

iv TraiSeia ^ovKoov.
iii.

us.

Gi'Ote

503) objects to this

Its

founder

favourite

of

no conquest of Elis
took place at that time, whereas Diog. says of Phaedo
(tvstory, that

vedXo} rfi Trarpidi.

He

therefore

infers that M-f^Kios should be


read for 'HAeTos in Diog. ii. 105.
Yet Phfedo is called an Elean
by both (rell. 1. c. and Straho,
ix. 1, 8, p. 393, and his school
called Elean.
If Elis itself
did not fall into an enemy's
hand, its suburbs were occupied by the Spartan army in
the Elean- Spartan war, probably in the spring of 408 B.C.
{Xen. Hell. iii. 2, 21, and Preller, on the passage, Curtms, Gr.
Gesch. iii. 149. 757.) Phajdo
appears to have been taken
captive at that time.
Most
probably Phaedo left Athens on
the death of Socrates. But
whether he at once returned
home, or repaired with others
to Euclid at Megara, is im-

known. Diog. ii. 105, mentions


two genuine and four spurious
dialogues of his. His Zopyrus
is even quoted by Pollux, iii.
18, and the Antiatheista in
Bekhers Anecdot. i. 1 07. Panaetius seems to have had doubts
as to all the treatises passing
under his name, Diog. ii. 64.
He is called by Gellius * philo-

11.

Elean-

school^^''

a. Its
^'^'^^^(^'y-

1
.;

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

280

Chap.

On

Socrates.^

the

death of his

Phsedo

teacher,

XII.

collected a circle of disciples in his native town,

name

thence received the

named

who

of the Elean philosophers.^

and Archipylus
and Moschus as his pupils.'* Beyond the names we,
however, know nothing of any one of them. By
Menedemus and Asclepiades,^ the school was removed
Plistanus

is

Eretria,

to

sophus

and

illustris,'

was then called the Eretrian.^

it

and

his writ-

ings are spoken of as

dum

as his successor,-^

'

Even

elegantes.'

admoDiog.

enumerates him among


the most distinguished Socra47,

ii.

ti cists.
^
Compare for his relations
to Socrates the Phsedo, 58, D.

89,
2

H.

Straho, ix. 1, 8, p.
Diog. ii. 105, 126.
' Diog. ii. 105.
* 126.
Perhaps these men
were not immediate pupils of
his.
Since nothing is said of

393

'HAeto/coi,

Menedemus'

studying under
the latter, we may
suppose, was no longer alive.
^ The account given by Diog.
ii. 125 of these philosophers in
his life of Menedemus (probably
taken from Antigonus of Carystus and Heraclides Lembus) is
as follows Menedemus of ErePlistanus,

tria, originally

had been sent as a

tradesman,
soldier to

Megara. There he became acquainted with the school of


Plato (so Diog. says with Plato
but this is chronologically im;

possible) and joined it together


with his friend Asclepiades, both
cf them (according to Athen.
iv. 168, a) earning a living by
working at night. Soon, how-

they joined Stilpo at


Megara, and thence went to
Moschus and Archipylus at
Elis, by whom they were in-i
troduced to the Elean doctrines.
Returning to theirj:

ever,

native city and becoming con-'


nected by marriage, they continued together in faithful
friendship until the death of
Asclepiades, even after Mene-ti
demus had risen to highest
rank in the state, and had'
attained wealth and influence
with the Macedonian princes.
The sympathetic, noble and
firm character of Menedemus,
his pungent wit (on which)
Plut. Prof, in Virt. 10, p. 81;
Vit. Pud. 18, p. 536), his moderation ^Diog. ii. 129; Athen.
X, 419, e), his liberality and
his merits towards his country,
are a subject of
frequent
panegyric.
Soon after the
battle of Lysimachia, which
took place 278 B.C., he died,
possibly by suicide the result
of a grief which is differently
stated at the age of sevent}'four.
According to Antigonus
in Diog. ii. 136, he left no
writings,
* Straho, ix.
1,8 Diog. ii.
105, 126 Cic. Acad. iv. 42, 129.

ELEAN-EIiETIilAN SCHOOL.
Flourishing as was

!>i

condition here for a time,

its

it

Among

its

adherents

Chap.
-^-^^-

appears soon to have died out.*

Phuedo and Menedemus are

b. Re-

the only two respecting whose opinions any informa-

^'^^^J^" ''f

tion

teaclnu<j.

be had, and that information

to

is

is

little

By Timon ^ Phsedo

enough.

is classed with Euclid


which points to an argumentative tenPerhaps, however, he devoted himself to

as a babbler,

dency.4

Ethics

more than Euclid

did.

Menedemus,

at least,

appears to have been distinguished from his cotemporary quibblers by having directed his attention to
life

and

He

moral questions.

to

is,

however, spoken

and skilful disputant.''^ If he hardly


went the length of Antisthenes in declaring every combination of subject and predicate impossible,^ it still
of as a sharp

sounds captious enough to hear that he only allowed

judgments to be

afiBrmative

Phit. Tranqu.

'

An.

13,

p.

^72.

valid,

of morals,
41, quotes

Athen. iv. 162, e, mentions


Ctesibius as a pupil
of Menedemus, but what
he
>ays of him has nothing: to do
with philosophy.
A treatise
3f the Stoic iSphasrus against
:he Eretrian School in 260
B.C. is the last trace of the
3xistence
of the
Eretrian
2

a certain

school.
=

but rejected nega-

Diog.

Bxog.

ii.

vii. 178.

107.

The Platonic Phaedo does


give the slightest ground

I)\og.

which Sen. Ep.


from Pha^do.

ii.

tcj/otjtos b

184

M.

noiX

iv

i]v

94,

5e Zvana-

rw awdfa-eai

SvaavTaydcvKXTOS.
irphs irdvTa Koi

eVrpe^ero re
eupeaiKdyei' ipia-

TiKdoraTds re, Kadd <pr]aiu 'Ai'rtaQ4vif]s iv


hiaboxah, iiv.
The

verses of

Epicrates in Athen.
cannot well refer to this
Menedemus, since they are also

ii.

59,

directed

against

was then
'
Even

still living.

Plato,

who

Steiuhai-tyVlsil.

this is asserted.
According to Phvs. 20, a (Schol.
in Arist. 330/a, 3), the Ere-

397, does, tliat. Pha^do


vas inclined to a sceptical
vithholding of judgment.

trians asserted /xrjSev Kara /xehevhs KaTnyopitaeai.


They appear in this passage to be con-

lot

01 i\nnV\x\^,

^.

2is

iv.

Compare the

:lever

short

but

fragment on the subject

founded with the Cynics and


the later Meirarians.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

282
Chap.
XII

tive

and hypothetical

Chrysippus^ blames

ones.^

him

as well as Stilpo, for their obsolete fallacies.^

may

also

be true that he disputed the view that pro-

perties exist apart


spirit of

It

from particular

On

Cynic nominalism/

objects,

in the

the other hand,

it is

asserted that in positive opinions he was a Platonist,

and only employed argument for amusement.^ From


what has been already stated, this seems incredible,
nor can it be deduced from his disputes with Alexinus.^ Indeed, it is in itself most improbable.^ Still

much seems

so

Stilpo,

to be ascertained, that, together with

he attributed

doctrines a value

to ethical

For we not only hear that he ad-j


mired Stilpo, who was his teacher, more than any
other philosopher/ and that he was himself often

above criticism.

us

oufTtcoSes Iv Se ro'is

Diog. ii. 135.


Pint. Sto. Kep. 10, 11, p.
1036.
3 Hermann^
Ges. Abh. 253,
refers to Menedemus the verses
of John Salisbury (Enthet. ed.
Peters, p. 41), in which a certain

Endymion

is

mentioned,

who

called fides, opinio vera, and


error, opinio fallax, and who
denied that you could know
what was false, for no knowledge could be deceptive. The
not, however,
allusion does
appear probable. The continuation, that the sun corresponds
to truth, and the moon to falsehood, that error and change
bear rule under the moon, but
truth and immutability in the
domain of the sun, certainly

does not come from Menedemus.


* Simpl.
Categ. Schol. in
Arist. 68, a, 24 oX airh ttjs
:

'Eperpias avfjpovv

ras rroioTrjTas

ovdafxus

i:Xovo'o-s

ri

Koivhi

KadiKaara

/cot

(TvvOeTOis vTrapxovffas.
^ Heraclides in JDioff. ii. 135.
Ritter's conjecture, Gesch. d.'
Phil. ii. 155, that this Mene-

demus is confounded with Menedemus the Pyrrhsean, whom

we know from

Plut. adv. Col.


1126, 8, and Athen., it
Foi'
hardly to be trusted.
Heraclides Lembus had treated
the Eretrians in detail, as w
learn from Biog., so that it is
difficult to imagine such a conThe context also tells
fusion.
32, p.

against that view.


" Diog. 135, 136, says that h(
was constantly attacking Alexii
nus with violent derision, bu]
yet did him some service.
^
Diog. 134 twj/ Se 5t5a(rK('
:

Koiv rcav Trepl


KpoiTTju
8

UAdrava
KarecppSvei.

Diog. 134.

Koi

s,Po'

ELEAN-ERETRIAN TEACHING.
derided

for

know

being a Cynic,^ but we

2^Sl

that he

Chap.

busied himself with enquiring as to the chief good

He

in a practical way.

one good

affirmed that there was only

intelligence,^

which,

to

his

mind, was

identical with a rational direction of the will.^

commonly spoken

are

What

of as distinct virtues, are, he

maintained, only different names of this one virtue

by

^'^

his activity as a statesman,'^

he proved that

he did not

aim at dead knowledge.

In his free views

of religion

he likewise reminds us of Stilpo and the

and,

Zeno, however,

Cynics.^

having about this time

tmited the most valuable and lasting parts of the

Megarian and Cynic teaching in the more comprehensive system of the Stoics, stragglers, such as the
Eretrians, soon found themselves unable to exercise

iny important influence.


to
kvuv

Diog. 140

'

can(ppoue7TO,

fx^v

oZv irpura

kol \T]pos virh

ruu 'EpcTpeioou aKovccv.


^

Cic.

Acad.

ii.

42

Diog.

irphs 5e rov lTr6vTa TroAAa


ayaQa iirvBero -niaa rhv apiQ-

123
r^

rwu Ka-

ihv KaX il voixi^oi TfAeiu)

'6v and in 134 are some ques-ions to prove that the useful
s not the good.
' Diog.
136: /cat Trore rivos
iKovaas, ws fx4yiaTov ayadhv U7]
h iravTwv i-nnvyxd-viiv wv tis
'niQvfx^l,

elirc

'

iroKv

Se

iJ.i7(ov

iTTidvixelu Siv Se?.


^

Pint. Virt. Mor. 2

r]fxo<i

wv

juei/

ia<popa.s,

cl's

.i/rh

Kaddwep

' That
he exercised a considerable
influence
on his
friends by his teaching and
his personalty is shown by
Plutarch, Adnl. et Am. c. 11,
Diog. ii. 127-129.
p. 55
Biog. 125 Bicavos re eVt^neAa)$ KararpexovTos twv jxavr^wv,
veKpohs avrhv iiri(r(pdTTiu \y'
against which a trait of personal fear, such as is described
by Diog. 132, proves nothing.
Josephtis, Antiquit. Jud. xii. 2,
12.
Tertullian'n Apologet. 18,
;

<*

language on Menedemus and

t6 TrKyjOos kuI ras

belief
in Providence, is
probably as worthless as the
whole fable of Aristeas.

Kol

iJ.ias ofja-qs

ivqs TToAAoTs,

XeyeffOoi,

avijp^i

4^ 'Eperpias

ap^TOtiu Koi

Meve-

SiKaiocrvvrjv

fiporhu koI 6.udpcoirov.

6v6fxaai

<T(a<ppoavvi]v koL

'

xp^rd yap

ai'dp^Lav Kal

liis

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

!^84

CHAPTER

XIIT.

THE CYNICS.
Chap.
XIII

L^

The

Cynic,^ like the Me2:arian


School,7 arose from <
O
fusion of the teaching of Socrates with the doctrines
c/

A. History
of the

Cynics.

been already remarked, were united by Stilpo, anc

and Sophists.
^

Eleatics

^|^g

Both

schools,' as ha^

The founder

passed over into the Stoa in Zeno.^

o:

Cynicism, Antisthenes, a native of Athens,^ appear;


'

It is

accordingly not com-

patible with an insight into


the historical connection of
these schools to insert the
Cyrenaics between the Cynics
and the Megarians, as Tennemann, Hegel, Marbach, Braniss,
Brandis, and Striimpell have
Otherwise it is of no
done.

moment whether we advance


from the Megarians to Antisthenes and thence to Aristipfor these
pus, or vice versa
three schools were not being
developed from one another,
;

but grew up side by side from

The order
the same origin.
followed above appears, however, to be the more natural
one the Megarians condning
themselves more closely to the
;

fundamental
crates

ing

its

position of

So-

Antisthenes considerpractical consequences

and Aristippus its effects oi


happiness, according to his owr
imperfect conception of it.
- Antisthenes was the son oi
an Athenian and a Thraciai
slave {Diog. vi. 1 ii. 31
Sen
De Const. 18, 5 Pkit. De Exil
17, p. 607, calling his mother
and Clemens, Strom, i. 302, C. ii
calling himself a Phyrgian, ar(
;

him with

confounding

Dio

genes, or else must have beei


thinking of the anecdote ii
Diog. vi. 1
Sen. and Phit.
1.
for further particular
c.
consult WinJtelmann, Antisth
Fr. p. 7
Miiller, De Antisth
vita et scriptis Marb. 1860, p. 3)
He lived, according to Xen
;

Mem. ii. 5 Sym. 3, 8 4, 34


in extreme poverty.
The tim
of his birth and death is no
further known to us. Diodo')
XV. 76, mentions him as one o
;

;;

HISTORY OF THE

CYNICS.

28/

have become acquainted with Socrates only late


life,' but ever afterwards to have clung to him ^

to
in

with

enthusiastic devotion,^ imitating

his

critical

though not always without an element of


captiousness and quibbling.
Early in life he had
reasoning,

9njoyed the instruction of Grorgias,^ and included other


Sophists likewise among his friends.^ Indeed he had
iiimself appeared Sophist-like as a pleader

and teacher,
the acquaintance of Socrates.^
It
therefore only a going back to his old mode
of

before he
w^as

made

when on the death of Socrates he opened a


School.^
At the same time he did not neglect to
life,

men

living about 866 B.C.


Plut. Lycurg. 30, Sch.,
quotes a remark of his on the
jattle of Leuctra.
According
o Eudocia ( Villoison's Anecd.

:he

md

56),

he attained the age of

years,

rO

which would place

birtli in 436 B.C., but the


nrcumstance is vmcertain.
We have every reason to
lis

'

efer Plato's yepSvrcov tois 6\pLfid'co-i,

Soph. 251, B., to him, as

be subsequently seen. The


miy thing against it is the
iccount in Biof/. vi. 1, that Anisthenes was praised by Sovill

rates

for

his valour in the


Tanagra. This objecion applies even if the battle
eferred to was not the victory
'f the Athenians
in the year
56 B.C. (in which it is imposible that Antisthenes can have
aken part), but the battle
uentioned by Thncyd. iii. 91
n 426 B.C., or that which was
ought late in the autumn of
)attle of

23 B.C. between Delium and


'anagra {TJmc. iv. 91), which

usually called the battle of

is

Delium.

The

story, however,

of no account, for Biog. ii.


31 quotes the same words of
Socrates in a different way.

is

Xen. Mem.

44

iii.

11,

17

Sym.

4-6.
Plato, Phsdo,
59, B.
Diog. vi. 2; Ibid. 9.
^ This at least is
the description given of him by Xen.
4,

8,

Symp.
5

6,

2,

10; 3,4; 6; 4,2; 6;

8.

* Diog. vi.
1, referring to the
rhetorical school of Grorgias

nor does Antisthenes deny his


teaching.
At a later period
Antisthenes wrote against Gorgias, Atheii. v. 220, d.

According to Xen. Symp. 4,


he introduced Prodicus and
Hippias to Callias, and recommended to Socrates an unknown
Sophist from Heraclea.
^

62,

^ Hermippus
in Diog. vi. 2
HieroH. c. Jovin. ii. 14.
' In the yvfii/da-iou
of Cyno-

sarges, Diog. vi. 13


Gottling,
Ges. Abh. i. 253, which was
intended for those who, like
;

Chap
XIII.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

286

numerous treatises,"
of which are most highly

his views to writing in

Chap.

commit

XIII.

the language and style


praised.^

Among

the pupils

of Antisthenes, Diogenes

himself were of mixed Athenian


blood, Pint. Themist. c. 1. According to Diog. vi. 4, he had
but few pupils because of his
harsh and severe treatment of
them. It is not reported that
he required payment, but he
appears to have received voluntary presents. Diog. vi. 9.
Diog. vi. 15 (comp. Miiller,
1. c, p. 25) gives a list of these
writings, which, according to
Diog. ii. 64, was in the main
,

approved of by Panaetius. They


are by him di\aded into 10
Excepting a few
volumes.
fragments, the only ones which
are the two
are preserved
small and comparatively worthless declamations, Ajax and
Ulysses, the genuineness of

which is fully ascertained.


(Antisthenis
Winckelmann
Fragmenta, Zur. 1842) has
collected

all

fragments.

the

Because of his many writings^

Timon

called

him

iravTO(pm\

(pXeSova, Diog. vi. 18.


2 See Theopomp. in Diog. vi.
14 and 15, and vii. 19 Dionys.
Jud. de Thuc. c. 31, p. 941
PhryEpictet. Diss. ii. 17, 35
nich. in Phot. Cod. 158, p. 101,
b ; Fronto, De Orat. i. p. 218
Longin. De Invent. Rhet. Gr.
Cic. ad Att. xii. 38
ix. 559
and Lucian adv. Indoct. c. 27
Theopompus passes the same
opinion on his spoken ad;

Called by Aridotle, Metaph.

viii. 3

1043, b, 24, 'Aj/Tr0eVetot,

of

but in later times universally,


and probably even in the time
of Antisthenes, called KuvikoI,
partly from their place of meeting, partly because of their
mode of life. Conf. Diog. vi.
13; Lact. Inst. iii. 15. g. E.
35,
Schol. in Arist. 23 a, 42
Antisthenes was already
a, 5.
called airXoKvav (Diog. 1. c),
and Brutus speaks disparagingly of a Cynic (Plut. Brut.
Diogenes boasted of the
34).
name (Diog. 33 40 45 55-60
;

Stob. Eel.

ii.

dog on

348, u, a),

Corinthians placed

and

the,

marble

(Diog. 78.)

his grave.

SteinhaH, Diogenes, AUg.


Encyc. sect. i. bd. xxx. 301
GUtling, Diogenes der Cyniker.
Ges. Abh. i. 251 Bayle, Diet.
Art. Diogene is always worth
Diogenes was the^
reading.
son of the money- changei
In his
Kikosios at Sinope.
youth he had been engaged
*

father in issuing
counterfeit coin, and in conse-.
quence was obliged to leave his
Diog. vi. 20, quoting
country.
authorities, gives further parnot alwayf
ticulars, but is

with his

faithfully explained by GottConf. Ihid. 49, 56


ling, 251.
D(
Plut. Inimic. Util. c. 2
Exil. c. 7, p. 602; Musoniuf
in Stoh. Floril. 40, 9 Dwcim
Bis Accus., 24 Dio Chrys. Or
;

viii.

We

have no

reason

ti

as Steinhar
does, p. 302, although the ac
coimts may disagree in a fev

doubt this

dresses.

fact,

HISTORY OF THE
Sinope
tric

is

alone

known

imperturbable

details.
In Athens he became
acquainted with Antisthenes,
who, for some reason or other,
dro^e him away with a stick,
but was at length overcome by

his perseverance.

^lian, Y. H.

x.

{Dior/.

16

21

Ilieron.
When this
;

adv. Jovin. ii. 206.)


took place is unknown, and
Bayle's conjecture
that the
condemnation of Socrates was
the cause
of
Antisthenes'
hatred of mankind, is not to
be depended upon for chronological reasons. Diogenes now
devoted himself to philosophy
in the Cynic sense of the term,
and soon surpassed his master
in self-denial and abstemiousness.
He himself mentions
Antisthenes as his teacher, in
the verses in Plat. Qu. Conv. ii.
He appears to have
1, 7, 1.
lived a very long time at Athens,
at least if the account of his
meeting with Philip before the
battle of Chseronea may be
trusted {Diog. 43;
Plut. de
Adulat. c. 30, p. 70
De Exil.
c. 16, p. 606
Epict. Diss. iii.
22, 24
it is not, however,
stated that Diogenes fought at
;

Clueronea, as Gottlimj, p. 265,


nor is this probable of a
Cynic), according to which he
was then still living at Athens.
But it is also possible and
this agrees with his principle
of having no home
that he
may have visited other places
as a wandering preacher of
morals, particularly Corinth.
{Diog. 44
Pint. Prof, in
63
Virt. 6, p. 78
Dio Chrys. Or.
vi.
Val. Max. iv. 3
Diog. ii.
says,

287

and eccen-

to fame, that witty

whose

individual,

CYNICS.

Q()

vi.

According

50.)

Diogenes,
in

originality.

Syracuse.

journey he

to

met Aristippus
On some such

he

fell into

the hands

who

sold him to
Xeniades, a Corinthian.
For
this event see Diog. vi. 29 74
Plut. Tran. An. 4, p. 466
An.
Vitios, s. 3, p. 499
Stoh. Floril.
3,63; 40, 9; Epict. Diss. iii.
24, 66
Pldlo, Qu. Omni. Prob.
Lib. 883, C.
Julian^ Or. vii.
212, d.
Xeniades appointed
him the instructor of his sons,
and he is said to have admirably discharged this duty.
Highly esteemed by his pupils
and by their parents, he remained with them till his
death. At this time occurred
of

pirates,

the meeting with the younger


Dionysius, mentioned by Plut.
Timol. 15, and the conversation with Alexander, so greatly
exaggerated
by
tradition.
{Biog. 32; 38; 60; 68; Sen.
Benef. v. 4, 3; Juvenal, xiv.
311 TJieo. Progym. c. 5 Julian,
Or. vii. 212.)
The most simple
version of it is that found in
;

Plut.

Alex.

c.

14;

De

Alex.

Virt. c. 10, p. 331


Inerud. c. 5, p. 702.

ad Princ.
Diogenes
died at Corinth, on the same
day, it is said, as Alexander
;

{Plut. Qu. Conv. viii. 1, 4, p.


Demetr. in IHog. 79), i.e.
B.C., at an advanced age
{Diog. 76, says almost ninety,
Cens. Di. Nat. 15, 2,
says
eighty-one). The story of his
death is differently told. {Diog.
76 31 Plut. Consol. ad Apoll.

717
323

c. 12, p.

14;

107

Cem.

1.

^lian,,Y.B..
c.

2'atian

viii.

adv.

Chap
XIII.

::

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

288

Chap.
XIII.

coarse humour, strength of character, admirable even

and vigorous mind, have made

in its excesses, fresh

him

the most typical figure of ancient Grreece.^

Of the

By

celebrated.^

influence,

his

2 Hieron. adv. Jovin. ii.


207, m; lALcian, Dial. Mort. 21,
Stoh.
Cic. Tusc. i. 34, 104
2
Floril. 123, 11.) Most probably
he succumbed to old age. The
Grr. c.

Corinthians honoured him with


a solemn burial and a tomb,
and Sinope erected a monument to his memory {Biog. 78
Anth. Gr. iii.
Pausan. ii. 2, 4
;

558).

JDiog. 80,

mentions

many

writings which bear his name.


A portion of them were, however, rejected by Sotion. Others
denied that he left any writTheophrastus' treatise
ings.
ru>v Aioyevovs avuayooyr] (in Dior/.

by Grote,

Plato,

508,
to the Cynic Diogenes, certainly refers to Diogenes of
V.

43),

iii.

Apollonia.

That he exercised an

'

irre-

charm over many persons by his manners and words


is attested by Diog. 75, and
confirmed by examples like that
of Xeniades, Onesicritus, and
sistible

his sons.
2 Amongst them are linown,
besides Crates and Stilpo
companion
the
Onesicritus,
and biographer of Alexander,
with his sons Androsthenes and
Philiscus {Dioq. vi. 75 73 80
84
Pint. Alex. 65 for particulars respecting Onesicritus
in 3Iuller, Script. Rer. Alex.
M. p. 47) Monimus of Syracuse, the slave of a Corinthian
money-changer, who was driven
;

is

the most

wife

Hippar-

pupils of Diogenes,^ Crates

his

away by his master for throwing money out of the window


in Cynic fanaticism, one of thej

most distinguished Cynics, and


the author of several treatises,

amongst them
XaX7]dvia

of

iraiyi/ia a-irovSy

ixefxiy/xeva

Menander
82)
(Diog. vi. 84),
;

(^Diog.

vi.

and Hegesias
and perhaps

Bryson the Achgean (Ibid. 85).


Phocion is also said to have
been a pupil of his {Diog. 76
Phoc. c. 9) but Plutarch was[
not aware of it and as Phocionj
adhered to the Academy, therej
is probably no truth in thej
;

story beyond the fact of a passing acquaintance.


^ The Theban Crates, generally called a pupil of DiogeneS;
but by Hippobotus, a pupil of
Bryson the Achaean {Diog. vij
78), flourished about 328-324
B.C. {Diog. vi. 87). Since, however, stories are current not
only of his tilting with Stilpo
{Diog. ii. 117), but also of his
quarrelling with Menedemus
in his later years {Diog. ii. 131;
vi. 91), his life must have lasted
to the third century. Anothei,
Crates, a pupil of Stilpo, whQ
is mentioned Diog. ii. 114, must]

not be confounded with thd


Cynic Crates. He is probabli
the same as the Peripatetic oil
that name in Diog. iv. 23. In
zeal for the Cynic philosophy,
Crates gave away his considerr
able property. For the different

HISTORY OF THE
chia

'

and her brother Metrocles

CYNICS.

289

were gained for the


The names of several immediate and
remote pupils of Metrocles ^ are known,
through whom
:he School may be traced down
to the end of
^

Chap.

Cynic School.

the third
nobler features were cultivated
3y the Stoics from the beginning of the third
century,
mly toned down and supplemented
bv the addition'
)f other elements also.
Henceforth

Yet

century.

all its

Cynicism was

a special branch of the Socratic


philosophy.
nibsequent attempts which were
made to preserve
ts distinct
character only resulted in
caricatures.
iseless as

nd yerj conflicting accounts


Diog.

je

87; Plut. Vit.


er. Al. 8, 7, p. 831
Apul. De
[ag. 22
Floril. ii. 14
>Simj?l.
I
Epict. Enchir. p. 64
Pkivi.

Apoll. i. 13. 2
Ilieron.
iv. Jovin. ii. 203.
He died at
V.

'Str.

advanced age (IMor/. 92, <J8).


98 mentions some letters

iog.

his,

the style of which re-

mbled Plato's, and some traidies, and Demetr. De Elocut.


'0, 259, also
mentions moral
d

ng

satirical poems.
Accorto Julian, Or. vi. 200, b,

utarch also wrote an account


his life.
From Dioq. 91
oul. Floril. 14, we learii
that
;

was ugly and deformed.


The daughter of an opulent
truly from Maronea in
Thrace,
10 from love to Crates
reunccd her prospects and
bits of comfort, and followed
'

n in his beggar's
;

Apiil. Floril.

ii.

life,

Diog.

Formerly a pupil of Theorastus and Xenocrates,


but
n over to Cynicism by
31,

vol.

after having been cured


by him
of his childish idea of
suicide.

At a

later period, however, he


to escape the
burdens of age, Diog. 94. Respecting his apathy, see
Plut.
An. Vitios. Ad. Infelic. c.
3, p.
499 for a conversation of his
with Stilpo see Plut. Tranqu

hung himself

An.

(5,

p. 468.

Diog. 95.

His pupils were


Iheombrotus and Cleomenes
the former was the teacher
of
^^

Demetrius, the latter of Timarchus, and both of them of


Echecles.

Contemporary with

Echecles was Colotes, Diog.

in Stoh. Floril.
214, Mein.),

iii.

vi.

102.
Contemporary with Metrocles was Diodorus of
Aspendus, mentioned in Zeller's
Phil,
d. Griech. vol. i. 289.
At an
earlier period, under

Antigonus

the Great, lived the


Cynic
Thrasylus {Pint. Reir. Apophtheg. Antig. 15, p. i82
Vit
Pud. 7, p. 531); under one
of
t^ie Ptolemies, Sotades,
whose
Cynical
abstinence Nonmii<
Exeg. Histor. Greg. Naz.
26
(Greg, in Julian. Invect
ed
Eton. 1610, p. 136) mentions.
;

14.

'

ites (Telos.

XIII.

'

'

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

290

Chap.
XIII.

are
of the basest of its later representatives
known to us in the persons of Menedemus and Me-

Two

nippus .2

Soon

after it

became extinct

cian Ikaromen. 15, who make;


Menippus an eye-witness of
number of things, all of whicl

pupil of Echecles, and


previously, as it would seem,
of the Epicurean Colotes {Diog.
only
vi. 95, 102), of whom we
hear that he occasionally appeared in the mask of a fury,
to add greater force to_ his
A pupil of his is
philippics.
Ktesibius, whom Athen. i. 15,
a
as
162, e, names
iv.
c.
cotemporary of Antigonus (Go-

happened about 280

to

Menippus was,
Diog.

vi.

99,

B.C.

Ii

face of so many cleaj


proofs, the language of Diog
vi, 99, who, speaking of Me;
leager living about 100 B.C
says, rov Kar' avrhu yefiofi4voi

the

cannot go for much. There i\


probably here a mistake in th
text; perhaps Kar' is writte^

natas).
2

as a School

for fier', or as Nitsche, p. 32, pre


poses, we ought to read rod K^

according

Gell.
conf.
originally a
He is said to

kvvikov.

Pk

avTOV yevofieuov
N. A. 'ii. 18, 6,
this Menippus is tl
bably
slave.
Phoenician
as Menippus (
person
have amassed a considerable same
by Diog. vi. 9
called
Sinope,
money-lending
by
fortune
distinguishe
most
the
(Hermippus in Diog. 1. c), the one of
of Metr*
school
the
of
men
much
so
took
loss of which he
Diog. vi. 101
for
to heart that he hung himself. cles
the various
His career must fall in the first counting up
does not mention hi
half of the third century. Dio- nippuses
this Menippus, b'
genes indicates that, placing as well as
as Athen. xiv. 629,
him
calls
and
Metrocles
between
him
Meviinros
Menedemus, it being his habit 664, e, likewise does
%vci)ir(hs
name
The
kvvik6s.
of
philosophers
the
mention
to
explained his master w
this school in chronological thus
Baton of Pont
certain
he
a
that
story
the
also
order
Diog. vi. 99), wi
in
(Achaicus
was the author of a treatise
probably lived
he
whom
of
festivities
the
respecting
also
Epicurus' birthday {Diog. vi. Sinope. (Compare
Quellenkun
z.
Beitr.
sche's
Arcesilaus
an
of
101), and
Laert. Diogen
{Athen. xiv. 664, c; the Acade- u. Kritik des
According
28.)
p.
Basel,
1870,
at
a
died
name
mician of this
Diog. 13 treatises of Menip^
also
great age in 240 B.C.)
circulation, of which
the circumstance that a portion were in
the titles of seven, a
gives
attributed
was
writings
his
of
the titles of two mc
to a Zopyrus (Diog. vi. 100), Athen.
not his o,
probably the friend of the Sil- That they were
o:'
probably
is
production
ix.
114)
lograph Timon {Ihid.
All th'
slander.
enemy's
vi.
Eel.
(Virg.
who
Probus
also
Menippus much writings appear to have b
calls
31)
His proficiency
satires.
also Luearlier than Varro
i

Me

CYNIC TEACHING.

md

only reappeared at a very


)ffshoot of Stoicism.'

much

2fa
later

time as an

The Cynic philosophy claims to be the


genuine
eaching of Socrates.^ The many-sidedness,
however,
Socrates,

whereby the intellectual and the moral


dements were completely fused, and the
foundations
hus laid of a more comprehensive and
deeper-going
cience, was above the powers of
Antisthenes. Naturaf

lly

narrow and

trength
iiings

of will,

but fortified with singular


Antisthenes admired^ above all

dull,^

the independence of his master's


character,

^e strictness of his principles,


his self-control,

and

universal cheerfuhiess in every


position in life,
bw these moral traits could be in a great
measure'
16 result of free enquiry on the part
of Socrates, and
is

DW they could thus be preserved from


narrowness,
tirist may be gathered from
school.
It would fnllv Pvnl^ir,
e fact that

utated

he was not only


ancient times by

eleager (i>.-^^. vi. 1)9), but


>o by. Varro in his
Satiric
enippe3 {Cic. Acad. i. 2, 8

rciot). r^atnTn.
5f;/s'fturni''^'l'^^'T
conf.
1
11,'ohus, 1. c.)
and that even
Cian gives him a prominent

Varr. Sat. Eel p. 7.


Besides the above, Meger of Gadara should be
ntioned, could
^^^ be sure
tt
he was a member of the
ese^

^'"^

tthat Athen.
HhiTT^l

W'^T'

these

stateCn ts

at

^ t^

attaching himself as a wn'tPr


' ^'
to Menippus.
2 See d '1^^
9 ^""^
^r^A n,-
^'
^'
'

II

^'"^f'

'

'/his liis teaching proves


independently of the o^^inion^
of opponents, such as
Thea^tet. Ios/e., in which
tl^

^S

6.vep^^ovs

and

^c^a'

,Z &uovcroi

refer without doubt to


AntTs
thenes and not to the Att"
mists; Soph. 251, B

roh
'''

4",pZ..\7i.:ri

iv. 15y, 6, in
Iressing a Cynic calls him
p6yopos bfiwu, and that he is

taph.

haps mentioned by Diogenes


a Cynic, does not prove
continuance of the Cynic

and

raadra

As

r^Oav^aKScrt.

v.

2J),

1043 b 23
*

y%6tZ
LT
JJ^

dibiudd.trL

'cic.

De

Orat.

Bioff. vi. 2,

rently on the

-irhf

M^!

b 33 viii%

'

iii

I7 62

remark a^na

same au'LttT'

Chap.
XUI.

^^^^^

'^'^^;.,.
"^^^'^ "f

w2^f

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

L'02

did he see that the prinhe did not understand nor


far beof conceptions reached
ciple of a knowledge
All knowplatform.
yond the limits of the Socratic
subservient to ethical purposeledge not immediately
;

Chap.
.^P
XIII.

aas unnecessary, or eveu


he accordingly rejected
and love of pleaas the offspring of vanity

injurious,

Virtue, he maintained,

sure

is

an

affair of action

and with wisdom.


and can dispense with words

Al
(

strength of will of a Socrates.


that it needs is the
only regarded logical an(
Thus he and his School not
worthless, but passed the sam.^
physical enquiries as
-

opinion on

all arts

moral improvement

Tws TOF

"""
^r".'

'^

and sciences which have not th


immediat
of mankind ^ for their

'Apt-

lu.sei>m

sf rp..'x'jCu^Vo,
7.^1 "ordinc to Dio-

Ts"
Sr,
others

said-what

Diogenes

to Socrates
Attribute
attribute lo
p. 150 and
(see
or Aristippus

t^at
that

ougni.
we ought

to

.. .V /'^^P"'^;;;,"

T.Tvra..

learn

J7i ,a

,^
'"''"'3''

-^, 5j

^V'""'Zoi..' atZZZ

""'"TroCra
xa^TaraTornvTa.

Srr.

-!

Whenadial
"^

T^*r?

u^as
was not a bad
jbeing ate
instrument *
27iW^
-'
for meals

plied, that It

^7*

irpiTTeiy Se H7j5afta,s.

The pa

sage on astronomers may po,


sibly have been supported I
the%try of Thales fallu,
into a well whilst contempla
heavens. An answ
g^^^^ .^ ^^^ ^^^^^^ .^
The^tetus 174 A, 176, D, ontl

Thracian maiden who upbrai


ed him for so doing. T
mother of Antisthenes was j
Thracian slave, and the wor
whieh Plato puts into t
^oth of the Thracian g
closely resemble those quot,
It would &.
Diogenes.
by i.
s,^^
^^^ ^^^^^^^^
Antisthenes, that he as
^

CYNIC TEACHING,
>bject;

said

for,

2f);i

Diogenes,' as soon as any other

bject intervenes, self is

Even reading and

neglected.

writing Antisthenes declared could

The

be dispensed with.^
statement must in any case be taken

last

considerable

/ith

nor can the Cynic


whole be regarded as so hostile to culture
s this language would seem to imply.
In fact, some
ecided language as to the value of culture is on
limitation,*^

ichool as a

coming from

3cord

not

ith

troubling

Antisthenes,"* Diogenes,^ Crates/

himself

Dout the general conception


I things.
iJiog. 73 says of Di(j3nes: ixovaiKrjs re KalyeoofierpLKris
i\ aarpoKoyias koL twv toioutwu
xeAuv ws axpVffrccu kuI ovk avaytlau.

Conf

ulian,

Or. vi. 190, a

24
39
Seneca,
88, particularly 7, 32

p.

Dioff.

Floril. 33, 14

tob.

id.

80, 6

man

in a

fJ.V (Tuifxa

nt

Se

jxi]

^v5ov

TIP

ol

16

saying

oif

yap

ovto'l

yvfjivaaiois

irXovniois

aight line.

Floril. Jo.

'

of

Diogenes

Excerp. e Joan. Damasc.

ii.

61. (Stob. Floril. ed. Mein.)


Dior/. 103
ypd/x/naTa yovv
:

fxavQaviiv
fvrjs
fX.^

k'^atTKcv

'AfT<-

Tovs crdcppoi/as yevo/x4uovs,


dia(TTp4(pOLVTO ro7s

aWOT-

IS.
'

It

anXKiiv,

answer to the question trolos


crrecpavos
KaWiaT6s i(Triu, lie
replied
*

^
e/Tre

6 a-nh -rraiSdas.

Diof/.
68
rrjv
iraiSeiau
to7s /lev viois aoocppocrvvqu,
:

TOis 5e Trpeo-jSurepots irapafxvdiav,


To7s 5e TreVrjcrt -nAovrou, to7s 5e
Kda/jLOv

jraiSeia

S/xoia

(pdvtf

Koi

'

earl

yap

TToAureAetai/.
^

IHof/.
e/xaOop Ka\

Movauu

ehai.

Damasc.

Exc.

29:

r]

13,

y^pvaw

<tt(:-

^^ei Kal

rifx^v

Ibid. 74, 75.

86

raiJT

i(pp6uTiaa

(rejuLv

4hdr]v.

6x
Kal

to.

Kal vAfiia rvcpos f/xapype.

would be hardly credible

tt^v

Ibid. 33, in

y\ii>xiiv TratSevetj/.

a\?C ovroi.
in
mpl De Coelo, 33, b,"Schol. in
ist. 476, b, 35, that even an
s takes the shortest cut to
s food and to the vi^atcr, was
obably meant as a hit at
ometry and its axiom of the
irKavdofi^voi,

writing.

it may either rest upon some


individual expression, such as,
that it would be better not to
read at all than to read sucli
nonsense, or it is based upon
more general statements such
as that quoted by Dioff. 5, that
wisdom must not be written in
books, but in the soul.
"
Exc. e Floril. Jo. Damasc.
li.
Se? rovs fxeWovras
13, 68
ayaOovs &i/5pas yV7}a(r6ai rh

astronomer pointing to a
ap of the heavens says
rol flcriv 01 irXavdjjxevoi rwu
Tfpuv upon which Diogenes
plies, pointing to those pre1

so fond of

not altogether a fancy,

If it is

rody of this verse

is

5e

oVo-'
fM^TO.

iroWa

pathe epitaph

XJIL

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

394
Chap.
Xlll.

and Monimus.^ Diogenes too is said to have zealously


impressed on his pupils the sayings of poets and oi
Besides,

prose writers.^

it

cannot be conceived that

men, who wrote so much that was good, should have


One thing we maj
declared war against all culture.
for established, that the value of culture

however take

producin^c
was exclusively estimated by its efficacy in
Hence this School depre
the Cynic type of virtue.
logi.
ciated all speculative knowledge, only studying
and physics, in as far as these sciences seemed neces

From

sary for ethical purposes.^

this

judgment

w.

founder.
are not justified in exempting even the
on Sardanapalus in Clem. Stro1

ii.

Damasc.

ii.

13,

^4>V Kpelrrov
88: M6vi}xos
ehai rv(pKhv ^ airaidevTOU' rhv
5'
fxkv yap ets rhu ^dOpov, Thu
19 rh ^dpadpov ifxiriiTTeiv.
2 Dior/. 31, according- to Eubulus KareTxov 5e ot TraTSes ttoX.

\a

TTOiriTwv

tS)v

Kol

avyypacp^cev kol

avTOv Aioyevovs,

iracrau

<po^ov avvTOjxov irphs rh evfxprj^o-

vevffrov
*

eTrr/crKet.

KrUclie, Forschungen, 237.

See Bitter,

ii.

rod 5mA.
rod apt
Aiyetu, Uepl 5iaKKTov, Uepl ovi
ovojxdroiv XP^""^"
(xdroov, Uepl
nepi epcoTr?(Tews koX aTTOKpicrea

Ae^eojs, 'AXijdeia, Uepl

yeaOai,

411, D.
Floril. Jo.

mat.

120.

Although the division of philosophy into Logic, Ethics, and


Physics can have been hardly
introduced in the time of Antisthenes, and hence the words
in Biog. 103 cannot be his, it
1

does not thence follow that the


statement there made is false.
Amongst the writings of Antisthenes some are known to us,

which would be

called logical

writings, to use a later division


others are on physical subjects.
To the first class belong Hept

Ilepl

^ddwv ^

Koi

8o|i7s

Trepl

iin(ni]ixi]S, A({|

ipiariKhs,

Uepl rov fiavddve

irpo^K-fiuara.

To the second, Ue

^coctiv

(pvffecos,

Uepl (pvaews (pe

haps the same which CiG&


mentions N. D. i. 13, 32), 'Epi
Trjjua irepl

(pvaeoos.

commei

tary on the writings of Her


clitus, which Bioff. ix. 15 me;
tions, does not belong to hii
See Zeller, Phil. d. Griech.
527, and Krische, p. 238.
I

little,

however,

is

known

these writings, that no co


elusions can be arrived
which contradict the aboi
assumptions. His logical WTl
ings, to judge by their titlf
appear to have contained thd
polemical dissertations on cc

ceptions, judgments, and _e


pressions, which were requir.
as a foundation for criti
Of the writir
researches.

CYNIC LOGIC.

205

riie

utterances of Antisthenes on logic, so far as they

ire

known

to us, consist in a polenaic against the

jhilosophy of conceptions, the object of which

is

Chap.
^^^^-

to

the impossibility of speculative knowledge.

orove

L<ikewise his

remarks upon nature have

for their ob-

what is natural for man. For this no


research seemed necessary to him or his fol-

act to show,

leep

owers

a healthy intelligence

^
;

know

vhat he ought to

can

tell

everyone

anything further

is

only

iseless subtlety.

In support of these views Antisthenes put forward


theory, based it is true on a leading position of

>ocrates,2

orm and
lisciple

but one, nevertheless, which in

its

expanded

in its sceptical results plainly shows the

of Grorgias.

Socrates having required the

and conception of every object to be investibefore anything further could be predicated

ssence
gated

Antisthenes likewise required the conception of


hings what they are or were to be determined.^
i

it,

n Physics, it is not known


whether they treat of other
han those natural subjects,
^hich Antisthenes required imlediately for his Ethics, in
rder to bring out the ditfer-

nee between nature and cusDm and the conditions of a


ife
of nature.
Even the
reatise Trepi

(^ixav

(pvaeoos

may

ave had this object.


Proably Plato, Phileb. 44, C,

3ckoncd
tie

Antisthenes

among

^ctAa SciVous A^yo/jLcvovs to.

only because in all


uestions about morals and
revailing customs, he invaribly referred to the require(pl

(pvaiv,

lents of nature.

'

Even

Cicero ad Attic, xii.

Antisthenes 'homo
acutus magis quam eruditus."
^
Compare the relation of
this theory to the doctrine of
88,

calls

and what Z>%. 39, ;6"jm^/.


m, 278, b, u, says of
Diogenes, with what the 8choideas,

236, b,

Hast on Arist. Categor. p. 22, b,


40 sa3^s of Antisthenes. Seu^.
Pyrrh. iii. 66, only asserts of a
Cynic in general that he refutes the arguments against

motion by walking up and


down. Similarly Diogenes in
LHog. 38.
"

Bioff. vi. 3

naro \6yov
to tI

?];/^

eliruf

irpwrds re

i>pi.

hdyos iarlu

eo-n drjXuw.

Alexander

(2)

Logic.

'

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

296

Confining himself, however, exclusively to this point

Chap.
xni.

>

of view, he arrived at the conclusion of the Sophists,^


that every object can only be called by

its

own pecu-

name, and consequently that no subject can admit


a predicate differing from the conception of the subThus it cannot be said that a man is good, but
ject.
liar

man

only that a

is

human,

or that the Grood

is

good.^

Every explanation, moreover, of a conception consisting in making one conception clearer by means oi
another, he rejected all definitions, on the ground
in Top. 24, m, Scliol. in Arist.
256, b, 12, on the Aristotelian
Ti ^v ehai says that the simple

a great progress as proving


that Antisthenes recognised all
analytical judgments a priori

which Antisthenes want-

as such to be true, but has^


since been obliged to modifj
his opinion (Plat. i. 217, Ges

Ti ^v,

ed, is not sufficient.

See Zeller, Phil.

d. Griech.

Abh. 239), on being reminded

904.
2

b,

Arist. Metaph. v. 29
33 ^AvTKxQiVQs Ssto

ev-fjBcos

X6yo) eu

oiKeio}

crvt/e^aiv,

oxe5b^' 5e

iv6s

i(p'

Soph. 251,
re

B.

viois

Plato,

odev ye,
tccv

koX

(hu

Alex-

/urjSe i|/eu5ecr0a:,

ander on the passage.


rails

e|

'

auTiAeyeit^,

^Juai

fjLi]

1024,

olfxai,

yepoirwu

rols o\|/t/to0eVi Qolvriv irapeaxVKa-

fiev ev&vs yap avTiXafiiaOanrauTL


re
TvpSx^ipov Q3S aSvvarov ra

TToWa

V Koi rb

iroWa

ej/

elvai,

ovk ioovres
ayadhf Kfyeiv avOpwirov, dWa rh
jxkv dyadhv dyadbu, rhv 8e audpojKoi

irov

5i]

-x^aipovcTiV

Cf Philebus 14,
Soph. El. c. 17, 175,
Phys. i. 2, 185, b, 25
b, 15
Simpl. in loc. p. 20 Isokr. Hel.
and particularly what is
i. 1,
said p. 276, 1, respecting Stilpo.

irov ^udpoDirop.

C.

Ari.<it.
;

Hermann,

Sokr.

Syst. p. 30,
to discern in
these sentences of Antisthenes,

once

thought

by BiUer (Gesch.

d.

Phil,

ii

Antisthenes coulc
only be speaking of identica
judgments. Still he adheres
to it so far as to state that by
the teaching of Antisthenes
philosophy for the first tim(
133)

that

gave to identical judgments ar


In wha'
independent value.
this value consists, it is han
to say, for nothing is gainec
by recognising identical judg
ments, nor has it ever occurred
to any philosopher to dei
them, as Hermann, Ges. Abi.
asserted though without quot
ing a single instance in supper
Still less can it be
of it.
forward step in philosophy tdeny all but identical judg
ments. On the contrary, sue)
a denial is the result of ai
imperfect view of things, an(
destructive of all know
is
ledge.
;

CYNIC LOGIC.

'2ii7

that they are language which does not touch the


thing itself.
Allowing with regard to composite
things, that their

component parts could be enumeand that they could in this way be themselves

rated,

explained, with regard to simple ones, he insisted


all
the more strongly that this was impossible.
Compared these might be with others, but not de-

Names

fined.

there might be of them, but not con-

ceptions of qualities, a correct notion but no

The

ledge.'

characteristic of a thing, however, the

Jrist. Metaph. viii. 3


1043, b, 23
wo-re rj airopia, %v
01 ^AvTKrO^pdoi Kol oi ovTcos airai'

SevTOi rjirdpOLU, e^ei riva Kaiphi/,


OTi ovK

(an TO

know-

ri eoriv dpicraaOai,

TdAAa, \6yov ovk exot.


aurc) yap
Kad avih CKacTTOP opofxdaai fMOPop
eirj,
TTpoa-enreTp
Se ovSeu aWo
SvpaThp, ovO' us ^(TTLp ovO' ws ovk
taTip .... eVei oi/5e t^ avTh
ovSe Tb iK(7po oiiSh rh eKaaTop
ovde Th fidpov irpoaoLiTT^op, ou5'

rhvyap opop \6yov eJvai /xaKpSp


see Metaph. xiv. 3
I091, a, 7
and Schvveg-ler on this passage a\Aa iTo7ov fxep ri ^crriv

aAAa TroAAa Toiav'ra raDra /xep


yap irepiTpexovTa iraffi Trpocr(p4p-

^I'Sexerai

uxrirep ap-

crdai,

oTi

6eTaL.

yvpov Ti

koI

fjLip

Ziha^ai,

4(niv, ov^

S'

oTov

KarriTcpos.

uxtt' uvaia^ ctTTt fxeu


eVSexerai ehai opov kol K6yov,
ciov T7]s o-vvdeTov, idu re alcrdrfr^
(du re voriTT) ^
S>v S' avrrj
e'l
TTpWTWV OVK ^(TTIV.
Tliat thls,
f}S

too, belongs to tlie description


of the teaching of Antisthenes,

appears from Plato, Theajtet.


201, E.,

and

is

wrongly denied

by lirandis, ii. b, 503 the expressions are indeed Aristotelian.


Alexander, on the passage, explains it more fully,
;

but without adding anything

That this view was not


put forward by the disciples of Antisthenes, appears
from Plato's The^etet. 201, E.
fresh.
lirst

yap aS e^6Kovv olkov^iv tivwu


TO /xip TrpuTa coairepil (TTotXf^a,
UP ijfius re (rvyKdjjL(0a Kal

(yu)

OTI
f^

'

Tpa uptu iK^ipcap oh irpoaTiS(7p 5e, eXirep i)P SvpaThp

avTo \4ycrdai Kal


avTov \6yop, 6,p(v
airdpTODP Aeyetrflat.

TOP

Clpal

oik7ov

elxez/

twp

6.kAup
pvp 8e dSvpa-

OTIOVP

TCOP irpuToop
ov -^ap ejpai avTw
aAA* v) opoixd^caQai ix6pop opo/xa
yap fxSpop exetf to, Se e/c tovtcop
priOrtiai

Koyw

^Stj (TvyKel/jLipa, uxrwtp

aura Tren-ovtw Kal to. opS/jLaia avTup


(Tu/xir\aK4pTa Koyop
y^yopipai.
opofiaTUP yap av^xTrKoKr]p dpai
Koyov oixrlap.
And 201, C: Ic^t?
Ae/crai,

5e Tr]p /xfPixeTo. \6yop Sd^ap d\r)6ri


iTnaTT)uj]p dpai, t^p dk 6.Ko-)Op

(KThs eiria-TTjfMrjs
eVri Aoyos, ovk

Kal

wp

is.'kp

iir l(xtt]t a.

/lu)

dpai,

ovTwal Kal opofid^wp,


eVjo-TTjTa.

& 5' ex^,


This whole descrip-

tion agrees witli what ha.s been


quoted from Aristotle so entirely, trait for trait, thai

we

Chap.
XIII.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

jm

defined, the conception of

name which can never be

Chai'.
XIII.

the subject which

is

borrowed frona nothing

else,

and

therefore can never be a predicate, consists only in


its

By

proper nanie.

explained by nothing

known when

All that

it

can be

is real is strictly

nature of things, but they express men's thoughts


about them. Plato having derived from the Socratic

demand
,

else.

is

Greneral conceptions do not express the

individual.
V

this it

for a

knowledge of conceptions a system of

the most decided Eealism, Antisthenes derives therefrom a Nominalism quite as decided. Greneral conceptions are only fictions of thought.
cannot possibly refer it to any
one else but Antisthenes, It
the more remarkable
is all
that Plato repeatedly (201, C.
202, C.) affirms the truth of his
In modern times,
description.
;

Sclileierniacher, PI.

was the

W.

ii.

and

to recognise
the reference to Antisthenes.
184,

first

His opinion is shared by Brandis, Gr.-Rom. Phil. ii. a, 202, f


Susemihl, Genet. Entw. d. Plat.
and
ScJi/iveglei'
Phil. i. 200
Boiiitz on Arist., 1. c, but con;

tradicted by Hermann (Plat.


499, 659) and Stallhaum (De
Arg. Theastet. ii. f). Steinliart
(Plat. W. iii. ] 6, 204, 20) finds
that the explanation of knowledge, as here given, corresponds with the mind of Antisthenes, but refuses notwith-

standing to deduce it from him.


Hchleiermacher (as Brandis, ii.
Susemihl, pp. 200, 341,
a, 203
remark) has not the slightest
right to think the reference is
to the Megarians in Theget.
;

201, D.

What

is

there stated

Horses and

agrees most fully with the


statements of Aristotle touching Antisthenes, whereas no
such principle is known of the
School of Megara. We may,
Schleierendorse
therefore,
macher's conjecture (PI. W. ii.
b, 19) that the Cratylus was
in ;reat part directed against
conjecture
Antisthenes
a
which appears to harmonise
with the view that Antisthenes
was the expounder of HeracliIt is opposed by Brandis,
tus.
Nor yet would
ii. a, 285, f.
we venture to attribute to Antisthenes a theory of monads
connecting it with the theory
of ideas (Susemihl, i. 202, in
connection with Hermann, Ges.

What we know of
him does not go beyond the
Abh. 240).

principle, that the simple elements of things cannot be

what he understood
by simple elements may be
gathered from the example
quoted from Arist. Metaph. viil A
1
3, of the silver and the tin.
defined

CYNIC LOGIC.
men

are

201)

not, however, the

seen,

From

horse or a man.'

campaign against
for other reasons

conception of a

this position he

opened a

whom

his fellow pupil, with

he was

not on good terms,^ but his

met with corresponding

spirit.^

fire was
Holding these views

Simpl. in Categ. Schol. in


rwu 8e
45, says
iraXaioov ol yikv avripovv ras ttol6tt]-

The character and position


of the two men was
widely different.
Plato must

rh iroibv (Tvy)(^upovvTes
(the terminology of course
belongs to the Stoics) wrnrep

have felt himself as much repelled by the plebeian roughness


of a proletarian philosopher
as Antisthenes would
have
been annoyed by the refined
delicacy of Plato.
^ Compare (besides what is
said, p. 292, 2) Plato, Soph. 251,
C, and the anecdotes in Bioff.
iii. 35, vi. 7
also the corresponding ones about Plato and
Diogenes, which are partially
fictions, in vi. 25
40 54 58
JELiaHy V. H. xiv. 33
Theo.

'

Arist, Q&^ b,

Ttts TeAecos,

elvai

'AvTiadevr]S,

os

Siaixcpia^nrSju,
'

'

'iirirou /uihu ^pco,

Trore

&

TlkaToci'L

UXdrcDV,'

e(p7),

tTTTror/jTa 5e ovx,

which Plato gave the


answer
True, for
you have the eye with which
you see a horse, but you are
dericient in the eye with which
6pw,' to

excellent

you

the

see

Ibid.

idea

of

horse.

b, 18 ; Ibid. 68, b, 26
'AvTiaOevrju Koi rovs ircpl avrhv
Xiyovras, ^uOpcoirou opca auOpuirdfi7,

ovx

Se

TTjTo

Quite

opco.

yame, Ibid. 20, 2, a.


53, tells the same

the

Bioff. vi.

story of

Diogenes and Plato, with this


difference, that he uses rpaire-

and

CoTTjs

KvaQSrins

Isag.

22, b,

Ta

lAcye

instead of
in Porph.

Amman,

av6p(air6Tr]s.

says

yeur)

koI

'AvTiad&rjs

ra

etS?;

ip

and then
he mentions av6puir6Tr)5 and
tTTJTf^TTjs as examples.
The same
language, almost
word for
el\a7s iiTivoiais ehai,

word,

is found in Tzetz. Chil.


605, f.
Plato is no doubt
referring to this assertion of
vii.

Antisthenes, when in the Parm.


132, B,, he quotes an objection
to the theory of ideas, ^r? tw;/

in

life

Progym. p. 205 Stoh. Floril. 13,


37.
As to the picked fowl
story in Diog. 40,
compare
;

Plato, Polit. 266, B.

Gottlin^,

For the Cynical attack


which Antisthenes made on
p. 264.

Plato in his ^dQcav, see Diog. iii.


Athen. v. 220, d,
xi. 507, a.
A trace of Antsthenes' polemic against the
doctrine of ideas is found in
the Euthydemus of Plato, 301,
A. Plato there meets the assertion of the Sophist that the
beautiful is only beautiful by
the presence of beauty, by saying
iau ovv irapay4ur]Tai <Toi
35, vi. 16;

fiovs, fiovs
Trdpeifxi

el,

Koi oTi vvv (yd)

Aiouv(r65u,pos el;

oroi

We may

ovSafiov avTCfi Trpocrjicr] iyyiyv^adai

suppose that Antistlienes really


made use of the illustration of
the ox, to which Plato then

&KKo9i

replied by

nSwu

'^Kaarov

i)

ij

tovtcov u6r]fxa koI

(V \pux,a7s.

making use

of tlie

Chap.

xm.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

;5()0

Chap.
XIII.

only natural that Antistlienes should have at-

it is

tached the greatest importance to enquiries respecting

names.

Stopping at names and refusing to allow

any further utterances respecting things, he in truth


made all scientific enquiry impossible. This fact he
drawing from his premises the

partially admitted,

conclusion that

Taken

self.^

impossible to contradict your-

it is

same

illustration in the person


of
Dionysodorus.
Steinhart
(Plato's Leben, 14, 266) considers the 'ZdQoov spurious. He
will not credit Antisthenes
with such a scurrilous production.
Antisth. in Epict. Diss. i.
'

17, 12
OLpxh
ovofiaTuv TriaKe\pis.

TraiSeucrews

tup

7]

a pity
that we do not know more accurately the sense and the connection of this saying. As it
is,

It is

we cannot judge whether

it

required an individual enquiry


into 1 he most important names,
or only a general enquiry into
nature and the meaning of
names, which the principles
contained in the above should
develope.
the
Respecting
theory that Antisthenes held
to the etymologies of Heraclitus, see p. 297, 1.
-

296, 1; Top.
oiiK

e^Tj

'

see
104, b, 20:

v.

11
avTi\yiv,

effTLV

i.

AuT i<T 6 4 i>r]s,

29

Kaddirep

which Alex.

(Schol. in Arist. 732, a, 30;


similarly as the passage in the
topics, Ibid. 259, b, 13) thus

explains
Ka(rrov

Se 6 'Auncrdevris

(pero

ruv uvtwv \4yeadaL r^

olKelcp

Xoyca

A6yoy

iJi/ai

yiouai
.

yeiv eireiparo

keyeiv rovs

on

eamu

fxr}

auTi-

yap dpTi\youras

(jl^v

rivos Sidipopa X4yeiv ocpeiXeiv,


Svuaadai 5e Trepl avrov Sia(p6povs Tovs Koyovs (pep^crOai, rep kva
rhv otKe?oj/. iKdffTov eivai Hva yap
kvhs elvai Ka\ rhv Xiyovra Trept
avTov K4yeiu (xSvov oJcTe t jjikv
TTpdyjxaros rov avrov
Trepi ToO
Aeyniev, rd
avrd oli/ \4yoiev

irepi
(x))

'

(eis
yap 6 irepl euhs
Xoyos) Xiyovr^s 8e ravrd ovk av

dXK'f]\OLS

et 5e 5taduriXeyoieu dAAi^Aois
(pioovra
\4yoLev, ovKeri
X4^eip
avrovs Trept rov avrov.
Prantl,

Gesch. d. Log.

i.

mentions

33,

writers, who, however,


only repeat Aristotle's sayings.
In exactly the same way Plato's
Dionysodorus (Euthyd. 285,
E.) establishes his assertion,
that it is impossible to contra(l(x\v eKdarca rwv
ovrccv
dict
Ovkovj/ ws effrif
XoyoL Tldvv ye.
eKaarov ^ ws ovk ecrriv 'fls earip.

later

Metaph.

Arist.

from these pre-

strictly the inference

KoX %va eKuarov


c|

uy

Koi avvd-

yap

Et

ix4)xvr\(xai, ecpr], S)

Krrjffnnre,

Kal 'dpTi iire^ei^aixev firi^eva Xiyov-

ra

d'S

OVK

rh yap

effri.

fih ^v
TlSrepov ovv

ovhels icpdvT) X4yci}v.


.

dvriX4yoijxev

irpdyfj.aros

XSyov

h-v

rov

avrov

df.L(p6repoi

X4-

yovres, ri o^ro} fxkv Uu Srjirov


ravrd x4yoijxev '%vvex<^p^^. 'AAA'
;

'6rav

iJ.riB4repos,

Trpdyfiaros

x6yov

^(pV,

X4yri,

'J"^"

TO''

r6r dvri-

CYNIC MORALS,
mises

301

not only that drawn by Aristotle' that no

is

false propositions,

Chap.

bnt also that no propositions of

any kind are possible.

The doctrine of Antisthenes

was logically destructive of

knowledge and every

all

kind of judgment.

Not that the Cynics were themselves disposed to c. Thenri^


renounce knowledge in consequence.
Four books %oodand
came from the pen of Antisthenes, respecting the ^^''^
difference between

knowledge and opinion.^

Indeed,

the whole School prided itself in no small degree on

having advanced beyond the deceptive sphere of


opinions,^ and being in full possession of truth.
KiyoLixiv

Kav

6.V

ou5'

Trpa.yij.aros

Tovro

&j/

f;

ovTut ye rh irapd-

ixefjiv-q/xevos

ovSerepos

ffuvwiJ.o\6yei.

tirav

Ae-yoi fj.hu

iyiii

etrj

7}(iS)v

'AW'
rh

rod
Koi
&pa,

irpayfja,

irapdwav b
X^ywv rw K^yovri ttoos tiV
avTiXeyoi
Plato probably had
Antisthenes in his eye, although
this line of argument had not
originated with him.
Conf.
(TV

5e ouSe Xeyeis rh

Se

ixr]

See

296, 1, Prod, in
'AvTiaOtv-ns eAeyev fi^
avTiXeyeit/
vas yap, (prjai,

'

p.

Crat. 37
Seiv

X6yos dKr]6evi
Aeyei

6 Se rl

6 yap \4ycov rl
Xeywv rh hu Ae-

6 Be rh iv \4ycou aXrjdevei.
Conf. Plato, Crat. 429, D.

yei

'^

riepi

So^rjs

Kal

eVtrrTTj/iTjs,

Zeller,

Doubtless this treatise contained the explanation


given p. 253, 1.
^^ IHoff. 83 says of Monimus

53

ovros fxev ifx^pLOeararos eyeVero,

I. c. i. 905, and Biof/. ix.


rbu ^AvTicrOei/ovs \6yov rhv
Vfipwfxevou oLTTodeiKuveiu ws ovk
iariv avTi\4yiu, outos (Protagoras) TtpwTos SteiAeKxat KUTii
:

(prjcri

nxdrwu

eV

Ev9udr]fj.C}}

(286,

Here, too, belongs the


saying of Antisthenes in Stob.
Flor. 82, 8, that contradiction
ought never to be used, but
only persuasion. A madman
will not be brought to his
senses by another's
raving.
Contradiction is madness for
he who contradicts, does what
is in the nature of things impossible. Of this subject the ^ddwi/
c).

jrepi

Toy auir\4y(iv treated.

17.

Bioff.

(oare b6^r]s /xeu Kara^povelv., -rrphs


dXijOfiau irapopfxav.
Metian-

5'

Ihid. says of tlie same


nic t^ yap viroK-q^Qev rvcpov

dcr,
C}'

elyai irav
viii.
eiircii/

Ttt

Ic^tj,

and

MSvifios

Sext.

Math,

kvoov

rv<pov

irdura. o-nep

ol'Tjo'ts

rwu OVK ovrwv ws ovrwv.

eVrl

Conf.
31. Aurel. irp. kavr. ii. 15: Srt
TTav vTr6\r}\pis
Srj\a /xev yap rh
wphs rod KuviKov Moviixov \ey6ixeva.
On this ground the later
Sceptics wished to reckon Monimus one of themselves, but
wrongly so. Wliat he says has
only reference to the worthless

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

ao2

Chap.
XIII.

With them, however, knowledge is directed entirely


to a practical end, that of making men virtuous, and
happy in being virtuous,^ As the highest object iu
the Cynics, herein agreeing with

life

philosophers, regarded happiness.^


in general distinguished

united

to

Nothing

lutely identical.

an

but vice

evil

other

man

is for

what

is
is

good but

common

See p. 292.
Diog. ii. ahrapK-r)

Trpbs

SO

evBaifxoviau,

kpe-

that

happiness

is

the

end,

and

virtue the

means.

Stob.

Eel.

103, 20, 21.


^

auTOiS

104

vi.

Dioff.

r4Kos

Kai

cnKiffLv

Ihid. 105

KaKias

Koi

dfxoiois

apeT^v \pvxas aya6hp fi6vov


aSe yhp avdpuiv
fxovva KoX ^lorhu pilxraro Kal

According to Diogenes it wouldi


appear as though the Stoic
doctrine that virtue is the only
good were therein attributed
to the Cjmics.

apeaKei

rh

elvai

S'

8e fiera^b dper^s
adidcpopa
Aeyovaiu

rh.

rep

Xicp.

Dio-

des, in Diog. vi. 12 says of Antisthenes Tor^aQh Kaha rh kuko.


aiffxpa.
Epipk. Exp. Fid. 1089,
C e</)77(re [Diogenes] t^ kyaQhv
olarhv TOt/cetoi/ iravTl aocpa elpai,
:

rh

maxim follows from


who states as the

This

Kar''

o/uoioos rols aTU}iKo7s.

"'KpicTTwvi

5'

&AXa irdvra ovSej/

Whether

rj

(p\vap[as

the

epiof Athen. in Diog. vi. 14,


refers to the Cynics or the
Stoics is not quite clear.
virdpx^i-v.

gram

iravapuna

ivd4iXvoi\

'

Tixu

12,

teaching of
'HpaKKel,

The only real

it.'*

Myixara tqus hpa7s

Dioff.

T^

virtue, nothing

iroAids.
rrjv

rr}!/

abso-

as

For each thing that

it

and freedom.
^

two

neither the one nor the

indifferent.^

opinion and
considers a good. In
Lucian v. Auct. 8, Diogenes
calls himself a prophet of truth

what

not

or, at least,

the

only can be a good which belongs to


ness of

other moral

Happiness being

from virtue,

they regard

virtue,

all

TTovTjph

Antisthenes

fSfxiC^

Compare

Trdvra

Plato, Sjiaip.

oh yap rh eavrcou,
affna^ovrai, et fj.7j

olfiat

ri

^eviKd.\
20.5,

E.

eKcurroil

ef tls rh juevj
ayadhv oIk^'lov /caAot koI eauroG, rh
5
Kanhv aWSrpiov.
In the

Charm.

163,

C. Critias

says,,

only the useful and good

isj

Although Antisthenes!
is not here mentioned by name,
yet the passage in Diogenes
olKelov.

makes

it

probable

that

the

antithesis of ayaOhv and olnelop


belongs to him, even if he wasj
not the first to introduce it.

CYNIC MORALS.

man

thing which belongs to

matter of chance.

else is a

moral powers

30;3

Only in

he independent.

is

virtue constitute the only

attacks of fortune recoil

;^

Everything

mind.*

is

mental and

his

Intelligence and

armour from which


that

man

only

is

all

the

free

who

the servant of no external ties and no desires for

is

things without.^

Thus man requires nothing


but

All else he

virtue.'*

make him happy

to

may

learn to despise, in

order to content himself with virtue alone.^

Compare p. 293, 6; Xen.


Symp. 4, 34, puts words to the
same effect in the mouth of

ro7s

Antisthenes

yovcrav

vo(.ii^o>,

Sj

AvSpes,

ovk iu rc^

robs audpwTTovs

o^Ka)

rhv ttKovtov kol tt^v Tr^viau exf',


iAA' eV rais t^vxo^s this is then
further expanded and Epictet.
Diss. iii. 24, 68, makes Diogenes
say of Antisthenes i^ihali /ue
TO ^jxk KoL rit ovk ifid KTTJcris
OVK iixT]
(rvyyeve7s, oIkcToi, (pi\oi,
'

Ekl.

rSiroiy

(Tvvrjdeis,

<P'flfxr])

ravra

iravra

oZu

'rl

TT]v

e5ei|e

'6ti

p.oi

aWdrpia.

(pavracTioiu.

p^prjcTts

Siarpi^rj,

'6ti

(rhv

rav-

bLKuiKvTov ^X^>

We

have,
however, certainly not got the
very words of Diogenes or
Antisthenes.
^ Diog. 12 (teaching of AnkvavayKaffTov, k.t,\.

tisthenes)
kper'f]

(pp6uir](T IV

UriTf

ava^alpTov SttAo;/
re^x^^ k(T<paX4(T'r arov

yhp

/UtJtc

'

TfpodidocrOat.

The same

is

ip<i)Tr}6f\s

ri

avru ircpiycyovev

<l>i\o(ro(pias, i<pT]'

tvxv^ nap:

apeaKei

aii-

'

This

says

is

what

himself

of

Diss.

iii.

24,

67

Diogenes
in

e| o5

Epict.
/*'

'Ar-

Ti(Td4vT)s r]\vd4p(t)(rv, ovk^ti 4Sov-

Xevaa,
JJioff.

and he also asserts in


71 that he led the life of

Hercules,

/UTjSej/

iAevdepla^

Crates in
Clem.
Strom, ii. 413, A. {Theod. Cur.
Gr. Aff. xii. 49, p. 172) praises
the C3mics
irpoKpivwv.

tjSout}

avSpa-rroBcodfi

d.Sov\o)Toi

Kal ^KafxiTToi

addvarov

^aaiKiiav

iAevOepiav

t' ayaTTwffiv,

and he exhorts his Hipparchia


TcDfSe Kpdrei

^vxvs

^dei

ayaX-

Kofx4vr],
oijff

d Kal firiSev ^A\o,

TO yovv TTphs iraffav


(TKfvaaOai
and 105

e/c

^vopwcrav avT(f Koi Aerovrov 5' ou 5uvap.ai

$a\6eiv Kvva \va<rii]Tr)pa.


(The
same verse is applied by David,
Schol. in Arist. 23, to Antisthenes.)
Conf. Stoh. Floril.
108, 71.

Kara^^uv

a little differently expressed


by Epiph. Exp. Fid. 1089, C.
63 says of Diogenes
Dwfjf.

rvxV /HTjSei/ eTrtrp4irti/. Stah.


ii. 348
Aioy4vr]s e<^7j Spav

rV Tu^i?*'

For

virh

oCiO' uir'
*

XP^^^^^

SovKovfievj]

4pwT(DV 6rf^nr6diov.

See note 2.
See Dioff. 105:

iip4aKei

5'

(JUAP.

xiu.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

cm
Chap,
XIII.

what

is

wealth without virtue

and venal menials, a temptation

prey for flatterers

for avarice, this root

of all evil, a fountain of untold crimes and deeds of

shame, a possession for ants and dung-beetles, a thing


bringing neither glory nor enjoyment.^

can wealth be,

else

if it

Indeed what

be true that wealth and virtue

can never dwell together,^ the Cynic's beggar-life


being the only straight way to wisdom

honour and shame

no child of reason

The

? ^

What

are

talk of fools, about which

will trouble himself ?

For in truth

what we think. Honour


an evil. To be despised by them is
keeps us back from vain attempts.

facts are the very opposite of

amongst men

is

a good, since

it

Glory only

falls to his lot,

avrols Koi Xircas ^lovv, irKovrov


KOL d6^T]s Koi evyeveias Karacppo-

Diog. 24.

vovai.
i.

Ejpict.

Diss,

Antisth

in Stoh. Floril. i.
30; 10, 42; Xeii. Sym. 4, 35
Diog. in Diog. 47; 50; 60;

Galen Exhort, c. 7, i. 10, K.


Metrocles in Diog. 95 Crates
in Stoh. 97, 27; 15, 10; the
same in Julian, Or. vi. 199, D.
2 Stoh. Floril. 93, 35
Aioyi;

j/rjs

eAeye,

eV irdAei kKoiktIo.

^u'l^re

olKia ap^rvv oIkuu SvvaCrates therefore disposed


of his property, and is said to
have settled that it should
only be restored to his children
when they ceased to be philosophers {Diog. 88, on the authotxr\r^ eu

adai.

Demetrius Magnes).
Unfortunately, however, Crates
can at that time have neither
had a wife nor children.
rity

of

Diog. 104

Floril. 95, 11

Diog. in Stoh.
^ee Ducian

19.

seeks it

What

not.'*

V. Auct. 11
Crates in Bpiph.
Exp. Fid. 1089, C. i\veepias\
;

elpai T^jv aKT-r]jxoavv7]v


*

24, 6.

who

Epict. Diss.

761/775) Ae76i,

elmann,

p.

i. 24, 6
(Ato-I
oTt eiSo|ia ( Winck:

47, suggests d5o|iaJ

which certainly might be ex4


pected from what preceded)'
i\i6pos

icnl

iJ.aivoiJ.evwi/

avOpcviruv.

Diog. 11 says of Antisth.: riiv


t' ado^iav ayaOhv
Koi Xaov t^'
TTOvcp, and 72
evyeveias 8e Koi
So^as Kal ra roiavra ndvra Sie7rai(e (Diogenes), TrpoKoapi.'fffxaTa
KaKias ilvai \4ycav.
In 41 he
:

speaks of SS^r^s i^avB-fiiJ.ara.


92: eAeye 5e (Crates) jJi-^xp'80V

(piKoffocpuv,

Setj/

SS^coaiv

Aarai.

oi

arparriyol

Compare

^V
)U^XP'
elvai ov^-

also 93.

pater in Aphthon.

c.

In
'''O'^-

2,

DoxoRhet.

Gr. i. 192, says that Diogenes,


in answer to the question, How
is
honour to be gained 1 replied ' By not troubling yourself at all about honour.'

CYNIC MORALS.
is

death

18

an

i05

Clearly not an evil.

For only what is bad


and death we do not experience to
be an
since we have no further
experience when
?

Chap.

evil

evil,

we

dead.*

All these things are then only

nothing more.

Wisdom

consists

i^ifi
"

are

empty fancies,^

in holding one's

thoughts free from them.^


the

The most worthless and


most harmful thing is-what men
most covet-^

'

pleasure.

Pleasure the Cynics not only


deny to be
good,* but they declare it to be
the greatest evil
md a saying is preserved of Antisthenes,
that he'
vould rather be mad than pleased.*
Where the desire
)f pleasure becomes
unbridled passion, as in love,
i

Epict.

1. c.
Aeye/, on 6 OdvaovK 0-T6 KaKoy, oifdh yhp alSee p. 302, 3,
XP^v.
'

os

Diogenes

''

in
Dior/.
68.
Tusc. i. 43, 104.
ividently the Cynic here is
ot thinking of immortality,
or does it follow from the
relark of Antisthenes on II. xxiii.
(8chol. Venet. in Winckel>
a/m, p. 28) to the effect that
le souls have the
same forms
their bodies.
' Or
as the Cjrnics techni!onf.

call

0OS.
id p.

it,

mere smoke,

See Mioff, 26, 83,


301, 3.

AvTiffB4vr]s fxkv

t^v

oltv-

Cratesprobably the

-nic proves in

Teles, in Stoh.

72 by the considera'U, that the human


life from
?inning to end brings far
oril.

re

Ih. ix.

1)8,

unhappiness than plea-

'e; if

101.

^A76 t6 awe-

Conf. Sext. Math.*

XI.

741:
[^ ^Uv)) Uli.i^To.iX
KCLKbv xm Avriaeivovs.
The sam^

in Gell. ix. 5, 3

Clemens. StroT

mat. n. 412, D. Eits. Pr.


Ev
XV. 13, 7 {Theod.
Cur. Gr. Aff
;

xii. 47, p. 172).

Conf. 7>i^^. vi.


258,4. Plato is
no doubt referring
to this
Cynical dictum, Phileb.
44, C.
AtW fMfii(Tr]K6Tuu T^u Trjs
rjSop'vs
8,

14,

and

p.

therefore the ttMouo-

Kal

VV0fJLlK6TWV

obSh

vyus, Sxrre Kal a{>Th tovto


a^r^s
rh iirayaiyhv yo-fjrcvfxu

ohx

(Ivai,

a,

As

Bioff. vi.

Svua^ilJ,

Clemens. Strom, ii. 417, B.


lieod. Cur. Gr. Aff. xi.
8, p!
:'

86,

2)

were the measure


happiness, a happy man
could not be found.

Oic.

lly

Covffai rjSoual

of

and

27:

oi

Arist. Eth. x.

T}dov^v

1 172
fih y^p rayadhv^Zov^l

],

}^noy<riv, ol 5'

e'l iuavrias KofxiSij


lb. vii. 12, 1152, b, 8*Toh fi\v oZv SoK(7 ovSeula
ijSov^
luai icyadhu oUre kuO'
abrh oih^

(pavKov.

Kara avnfie07}K6s
rahrhv ayadhv Kal
pare p. 296.

ov

yhp

T]Zovriv

that,

Com-

'

THE SOCBATIC SCHOOLS.

of his delowers himself to be the slave


can be too violent to eradicate
sires, there no means
'
fear, labour and
1
Conversely, what most men
it
they only bring man to that
toil, are good, because
be independent.^ Hercules'
state, in which he can
patron-saint and pattern for the
is therefore the

where

CHAP

I-

man

way through sc
no one else having fought his
for the good of mankmd
arduous and toilsome a life
vigour. In support of thii
with so much courage and
argued that plea.
Antisthenes appears to have

Cynic,*

view,

sure

pain.^
nothing but the pause after

is

C iyii
:iut?:<reill,
^

,,'

aSvol

4-nfi

A4>po5^r,v
^V 'aStv

k&v

Xe-yo.Ta
Xejo^T

susceptible of culture.

y-; -J^;^ 2r^lpL


TO. re .p
0...a.Ks 5.ec|>0e.p6.^

Or. vi. 198, D.)

?pTa

5e

et

Ki^i^s,

Travel

i^.)],

fxh divri xP^o'^''

On the same subject compare


TsoBiog. vi. 38 51 67 StoK
;

6,

64 i
66 To\;

:Jo^^5.^^<Jra.s.

4v
toJ;s

18,

ol'c^ra.

kSITu!
.o...

-It^

2,

27
e>,

5^ <pa{>^ovs

Ta X'-SouA.^-q^o q
^'iion. vi.

Who

had

says of

Seep,
Anti-

Diogenes
.oC K^po'
Fvo e Floril. Jo.

ed. Mein. iv. 200)

that boys,

also

tempi

near Cynosarges.
^ Antisthenes speaks of

tv,

Therefo
]x,,0ep/as Trpo/cptVcov.
cal
j^^^^ p^. Ev. xv. 13, 7,
Antisthenes

XpSvosihu Se TouTOLS
Ppdxos.

Floril

oVt

.oXXhs

Mian,

thi

they are to come to an


to be educated b
good,
abstemiousness, as early as the
if

Aa^o^M^

e.

KaTaTo|e.(ra.Ac.

On

'UpaKXeuriKds

'

rh (t>p6uwa and in lAicia


V. Auct. 8, Diogenes replies
the query as to whom he w
imitating rhv 'HpaKXea, at t
same time showing his sti

dvrjp

a club, and his philosophe


cloak f or a lion^ k^^'
the addition which probal
comes from a Cynic wrinr

f or

arpar^i^ofxa^^e licr^ep

eKel.os

^H

pcor^s ^.: -''^^^P^-^^


bee JJens. i^yn.
rtov iraBuv.
'

Plato, Phileb. 44,

15.

(be

CYNIC MORALS.

307

supposition it will appear absurd


to pursue pleasure

which can only be attained by having


previously experienced a corresponding

From
to
his

amount of pain.
rigid development of their
principles

this

which Antisthenes had been brought,


partly by
own natural temperament,^ partly
from regard
to

61, A.

Rep.

ix. 583, B.)

speaks

without

including
pleasure
thereunder.
If
the further
objection is raised, that
the
opponents of pleasure here
referred to, hate (according
to

of people, as ^aAa l^ivovs Aeyo\i.ivovs^ Ttt

irav

they

7rep2

TjSoi/as

(^vcriv,

ov

maintain

(pacriu

ot roirapd-

ehai,

Xviraiu

for

ravras

fluai irda-as airocpvyas &s


vvv ot
repl 4>i\r}l3oy -rjSouas iirovojxd^ov-

ihiL 46, A) Toy Twv


aax-nnducou
vSoms, whereas the Cynics
al-

This passage refers withto


Antisthenes.
Wendt (Phil. Cyren. 3 7, 1)
applies it to philosophers who
declare freedom from pain to
be the highest good.
Grote,
Plato, ii. 609, thinks of the
Pythagoreans, from whom he
<riv.

out

lowed no

doubt

.^"t'^thenes

from pain the highest


As to tfe PythagorlaS

'reedoffi

rood.

ve
lut
s

know

of

with so mn^h ./
he h/reTes
at one thno of li'fp.

their asceticism

no ethical theory of theirs


known to us fhoroughi;

ejectrng
'ther

piea,e.

hand we know

his

Lrn^

TucTTZ
v a^

ZH

'^'^

'

.ZXlL7%>T'Z't
doesnot

On

the
that Anti-

thenes did reject pleasure,


'he probability is, therefore,
hat Plato in writing this pasage had Antisthenes in his
ye.
That the expression
^
iivo\rh.Trcp\(l)V(Tivis no obstacle
3 this view, has been already
idicated, p. 294, 4
the exression not referring to phycal research, but to the
praccal enquiry as to what
is con>rmable to nature, to which
ntisthenes wanted to go back

difference between

things seemly and


unseemly,
this rests on a
misapprehension; for the 7}Soval rwv
k(rxnti6vwv are,
as the
context
shows, condemned by the
opponents of pleasure, not because
ot their unseemliness,
but be-

it

followThaVafter the

lapse of years, and in


respect
ot a question on which
their

views more nearly approximated, he could not express


himself more gently and
appreciatingly.
Yet even here
he will not allow to him
the

properly scientitic capacity,


the

Plato,

roh oZv

1. c,

ijfxas

continues
Tr6Tpa

<TVfifij,v\evis.J) TTws,

S,

tovTrddeaBai
^d^KpaT^s;
:

OvK, a\?C wanep /xduTeai


irpoaXPWOa.1 rm, fiantvrxivois ov

X 2

chap
^^^^

'~

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

308

it as

CHAP.

^^

education,^ the Cynics, however, so.


pleasure
to recognise a certain kind of

means of

far departed, as

Pleasure which

to be legitimate.

remorse') or
-

is

not followed by

more accurately, pleasure resulting from

been called a good,


labour and effort,-^ is said to have
Diogenes recomeven by Antisthenes. In Stobseus,^
same time
justice as the most useful and at the

mends

most pleasant thing, because it alone affords


and sickness,
peace of mind, protects from trouUe
as the

He

and even secures bodily enjoyments.

also asserts,^'

joy which can


that happiness consists in that true

mind.

cheerfulness of
only be obtained by an unruffled
forth thd:
Moreover, the Cynics when wishing to set
fail to follow
advantages of their pMlosophy, did not
that life with
in the steps of Socrates, by asserting
than
them was far more pleasant and independent
gave the
other men, that their abstemiousness

with

mental delight^;
right flavour to enjoyment, and that
Te>7,, aWd TLVL Zvcrx^p^ia
,ls ohK ayevvods, Xiav, k.t.K.
See V 305 6
'

'

jirist

X.

Etli.

aBhr^s

ol6f.evoL
aivo^ oD'ro, Ka\ %x^^^^ ol
fieXriov eha^ -Kphs rhu filou vt^S,u
anocpaiveiv t^v V^ovh^ rocp <pafpeneiv yap
\f.>v
Koi t uh iffriv

x^ieiv Ta7s

iidouah, d^h

Kal
5eT.

U.is

rh^^aov. JJlog. vi. 35


rohs
t.,l.,tcreai, ix.y, {C.ioyiv-ns)
yopoZiZaffKaXovs Kal yhp Ik^'ivovs
imtp r6vov eVStSoVai eVeKaToDrous
Xoiirovs a^aaOai rov Trpo(X'i]KOUTOS

aires

iirl

r6vov.

o'e

(pdaKccv,

Home

hold pleasure to be altooetber


a mistake: ol t^'^v tcrc.s 7r.7re.0--

"Zs .oTx^L^ipbs alrC

jUhcn

'^

cpi-

xii

513,

t^ fovw ayadou .Im


7rpoa-e0ri/ce rw afx^racfn

we

require to kno\'
the context in ^^icb Anti>
thenes uttered this
in Sfoh. Floi 2.
' Antisth
65 ^fovhs ras ^era rovs '^6,ov
SicvKreov, aX\ ovxl ras irph t
X-nrov,

but

-kovwv.
^

Floril 9, 49

24, 14

wher

probably the Cyiiic Diogend

question whether ^he wo^l


are taken from a genuine
writing ot his.
Ibid. lOii, ^U ; /i.

CYNIC MORALS.
.-afforded

309

higher pleasure than sensual ones.


Still all that this language proves is,
that their theory
was imperfectly developed, and that their
mode of
expression was inaccurate, their meaning
being thjff
pleasure as such ought in no case to
be an end,^
flir

and

that

when

it is

anything more than a natural conse-

Tims in Xen. 8ymp. 4, 34,


where tlie description appears
on the whole to l)e true, Anti'

sthenes demonstrates that in


his poverty he was the happiest
of men.
Food, drink, and

he
enjoyed
better
clothes he did not need and
from all these things he had
more enjoyment than he liked
so little did he need that he
was never embarrassed to think
how he sliould find sujjj^ort he
had plenty of leisure to associate with Socrates, and if he
wanted a pleasant da}', there
was no need to purchase the
requisite materials in the market, but he Jiad them ready
in
the soul.
Diogenes in IJiofj.
n, speaks in a similar strain
;not to mention Dio Cliry^. Qr.
n. 12 33) he who has learned
-sleep

o despise pleasure, finds theren his highest pleasure ; and in


^lut. De Exil. 12,
p. 605, he
ongratulates himself on not
aving, like Aristotle, to wait
or Philip for breakfast;

or

ike Callisthenes for Alexander


I^n)ffA5) to the virtuous
:

man

ccording to Diogenes (Pint.


ranq. An. 20, p. 477) every
dav
a festival. In like manner
^lut. Tranquil. An.
4, says tliat
rates passed his life in jesting
!

id joking, like
stival;

and

one perpetual
Mctrocles (in

Plutarch, An. Vitios. ad Infelic.


3,

p.

499), like

Diogenes (in

Lncian, V. Auct. 9), blesses himself for being happier than


the Persian king.
<^ee Dion.
'

44, 78.
''

As

Bitter,

ii.

12], has re-

marked, the difference between


the

teaching of

Antisthenes

and that of Aristippus might


be thus expressed: Aristippus
considered the result of the
emotion of the soul to be the
good Antisthenes considered
the emotion itself to be the
end, and the value of the
action to consist in the doing
of it.
Eitter, however, asks
with justice whether Antisthenes ever went back so far
as this, since it is never distinctly imputed to him. And
in the same way it will Ijo
found that Aristippus never
regarded pleasure as a state of
rest, but as a state of motion
for the soul.
The contrary is
not established by what Her;

mann,

Ges.

Abh. 237,

f.

al-

leges.
Hermann proves, it is
true,
that Antisthenes con-

sidered the good to be virtuous activity, and that Aristippus took it to be pleasure, but
he does not prove that Antisthenes and Aristippus spoke
in explicit terms of the rest
and the motion of the soul.

Ohap.
xin.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

310
Chap.

quence of action and of satisfying essential wants,

XIII.
is

it

a thing to be avoided.

From these considerations followed the

conclusion,

that everything else excepting virtue and vice

is

in-

and that we in turn ought to be


indifferent thereto.
Only those who soar above
poverty and wealth, shame and honour, ease and
fatigue, life and death, and who are prepared to
submit to any work and state in life, who fear no

different for us^

one, troubling themselves about nothing

only such

no exposed places to fortune, and can

as these offer

therefore be free and happy.^


(1

As

Virtve.

yet, here are only the negative

What

happiness.
thereto

conditions of

the positive side corresponding^

is

Virtue alone bringing happiness, and tb

goods of the soul being alone worth possessing, in

what does virtue

consist

Virtue, replies Antis-

and Euclid, consists]


and Eeason is the only

thenes, herein following Socrates

wisdom

in

prudence

or

Diog. in Stoh. Floril. 86,


19 (89, 4), says the noblest
men are ol Karacppovovures ttAovI

rov

5o|7js

ivavTioov

Tjdovrjs

twv 5e

C'^Jjs,

ovtss,

virepdvo}

irevlas

Diog.
iiryvet
29 says of the same
rovs /meWovras yafiuv /cat fi)]
yafxelv, Koi Tovs /xeWovras Karaado^ias

Bavdrov.

irouov

TrAetv KoX

fXT]

[x4x\ovTas

KarairX^lu, Kol rohs

tovs

TToXtreveadai, Koi
(I>e7u

Kol

fxTj

(xtj

irai^orpo-

TraLdoTpo(pe7u, Kal rovs

irapacTKeva^oiuLevov^

Swdarais

koX

TToXiTiveaOai

kol

ffvfi^iovv

toTs

fx)]

Trpoffiovras.

86,

says

that

what he had gained by

philo-

Crates,

Ibid.

sophy was

Qipjxoov

TO

fx4XLu.

re X^'"'!
Antis.

*^^

in
oaTLs 51
Sfob. Floril. 8,
cTepovs 545oiK hovXos wv \4Kiq9ei
iavTov.
Diogenes in Dio(/. 75
(xr)Bevhs

SovXov Th (pofi7cr6ai.
See pp.
302, 2
303, 2 and 3
305, 4.
This follows from Biogl
13
Teixos aacpaXecTTaTou (ppSVT](Tiv
Teix,V KUTaaKeuaaTeok
;

iu

To7s

afjio^s,

if

o-vTuiu

^oyi-

avaXcoTOis

we connect with

it \A&

maxims about the oneness and


the

teachableness

and his doctrine


man.

of

of

virtue.'

the wise

CYNIC VIRTUE.

311

thing which gives a value to life.^ Hence, as his


Chap.
teacher had done before him, he concludes that virtue __^^'__
is one and indivisible,^ that the same moral problem
is

presented to every class of men,^ and that virtue

is

the result of teaching.^

virtue

is

He further

maintains that

an inalienable possession ; for what

known can never

He

be forgotten.^

once

is

thus bridges

over a gulf in the teaching of Socrates by a system


in which Sophistical views ^ contributed no less than
practical interests to

make

virtue in itself indepen-

dent of everything external.^


Compare the saying attributed to Antisthenes in Pint.
Sto. Rep. 14, 7, p. 1040, and to
Diogenes in Biog. 24 eis Thv
fiiou irapea-KevdCca-dat. Se7u \6you
^
Bp6xov.
Also Dior/. 3.
- ISchol.
Lips, on II. 0. 128
(Winckelmann, p. 28): 'Avti'

crdevrjs

(prforlu,

ws

et ri Trpdrrei 6

Kara iraaav [dpeTTjj/ eVepye?.


Diog. 12 according to Dio-

aocphs
^

des

avZphs Kal yvvaiKhs

tj

auri}

aper-f].

Biof/. 10 SiSaKT^u anedelKwe


{'AvTiadcvrjs) ttju ap^rqu.
105
'

apecTK^i 5'

Kad^
Trepl

Wherein, however.
andyTuv icxTiv dXKoL 5e
rds epidas diarpi0ov(n k.t.A.

The expression

ol

/ueu,

ol

does not prove that the first


of these statements belongs to
a different school from that
to which the second belongs.
5e

"*

Diofj.

dperi]^

12

dvacpaipeToy '6ir\ov

Mem.

Xen.

i.
2, 19
Uv iroXXol rcou
<pa<TK6vToov (pi\oao^e7u, on
ovk
hv irore 6 SiKaios ddiKOs yei/oLTo,
ou5e auxppwu vl3piaT7]s, ou5e dWo
rj

laws ovv

iXiroi^u

ovShv, oov jxdQriais icTLV, 6 /naduv


az/eTTiCTTTjyUCoj/ a*/

avTo7s Kal rriv aper^v

"

Trore ydpoiro.

The maxim that prudence

Si5aK7T]v clvai,

Ka6a (pT]alv 'AvTiiu T65 'HpaK\e7, Kal duaT6fihr)Tou


virapxeiv.
Without

is

TQivi]s

loubt the reference in Isocr.


i. 1 is also to Antisthenes.
[socrates quotes the passages
just given, with the sentence
)f Antisthenes which was dis-

The maxim that you cannot


forget what you know is only
the converse; of the Sophistic
that j^ou cannot learn
what you do not know.
^ It is only independent
of
external circumstances, when
it cannot be lost
for since the
wise and virtuous man will
never, as long as he continues
wise and virtuous, forego his

Hel.

Jussod p. 300, 2, added: KaraY^yvpaKaaiv ol /xcv ov (pdaKouTcs


>i6i>
t' thai \l/vSri \4yciu ouS'
iVTiXiyeiu.
OS

01

5e

die^ioures

auSpla Kal aocpia Kal diKaioavur]

avr6v iarr Kal


vTwu

exo^ej/,

(pvaei /j.^ ovSeu

fj.ia

5'

eVio-ri^/iTj

insuperable.

See p. 142,

3.

'

maxim

wisdom and

virtue,

and

since,

according to the teaching of


Socrates, no one intentionally

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

812

true prudence consisted

Chap.

1_ more

If

precisely.

were described as knowledge

it

concerning the good,^

the Cynics could not say

was simply a tautology.

on the contrary,

If,

what

consist in unlearning

said to

does

Plato justly observed,^

this, as

negative

this

expression

So much only

further.

lead

is clear,

it

were

bad/ neither

is

single

step

that the prudence of

Antisthenes and his School invariably coincides with

a right state of will, of firmness, of self-control and


of uprightness,'^
V

thus

bringing

back

us

know-

Socratic doctrine of the oneness of virtue and

Hence by learning

ledge.

intellectual

They would not have recognised

they understood

virtue,

moral exercise rather than

the

to

research.*)

the Platonic and

Aristotelian distinction between a conventional and


^

a philosophical, an ethical and an intellectual virtue


does wrong, it follows that
knowledge can only be taken
away by a cause foreign to the
will of the individual.
Plato, Kep. vi. 505, B.
'

ec/)??,

rh KaKa

same

is

Floril. ed.

IJLu

rS^e ye

fXT]v

oilada,

'7:oX\o7s Tj^our]

on

5ok6? elvai rh

ayaOhv, rots 5e KOfx^oripoLs


(Tis

rovTo

OTL ye,

Ka\

to7s

&

<pp6vr)-

<^tA6, ol

ovK %xov<n Se?|ai


aAA' avayKa^ovTai.
ayadov
rov
reKevTwvTes r^v
(pavai.
If the Cynics are not
T]rLS

TjyoviJLepoi

(ppov-riais,

here exclusively meant, the


passage at any rate refers to
them.
2

1. c.

Diog.

nias
rov

%(ToiTO,

8,

according to Pha-

TL

e(p7]'

Kokhs Kayadhs
Ttt KaKo. h ex^is

TToiitiv

el

OTL (t)evKTd ia-ri /j-deois irapa


elSdroov.

ruv

and

Ibid.

/JLttdrjudrccv

Twv

ipwrndels ti
avayKai6Tarov,

7:

iv. 193).

292, 1

303, 2

3.
,

Here it may suffice to call.


to mind what has been said p.
292, 1, and what Diogenes in
^

Diog. 70 says

^itttiv

eJuat riju &(rKr}(nv,


tt]u

kt)v,

5e

r^v

5'

eXeyev

fihv J'ux*"

(ToofxaTiK-fiv

ravrrfV

(the text here appears


faulty) K:a0' '7]v iv yvfxvaffla <Tvi/e-[
.

x^*^ [o'wexet"] ? yipS/xeuai


(pavraaiai ei/Xvaiav irphs ra

[ai]|

r^si

epya irapexovrai'
6?j/at 5'
dreAT] tV erepai' x'"'?'^ t^s ere'/joy
iraperldeTO 5e reK/xripia rov
paSlws airb rrjs yv/xvafflas iv rf
aperrj Karayiveadai (to be atl
home in); for in every art practice makes perfect; 71: ouSeV 76
/x^v eXeye rh irapdvav iv r^ fiio)
aperris

{^Avri(Tdiv7]s) ipwryiQeh inrh

Mein.

Compare pp.

aWa

The'

airoixaBuv.

found in Exc. e Floril.'


Joan. Damasc. ii. 13, 34 (Stob,

CYNIC WISDOM AND FOLLY.


and

in answer to

Meno's

813

question, whether virtue


was produced by exercise or instruction, they would
have replied, that practice was the best instruction.

Chap.

._^^
.

He who

has attained to virtue by the help of the


ynic teaching, is a wise man.
Everyone else is

To

lacking in wisdom.

tell

(2) Wis-

'^l}i^^^

the advantages of the

one, and the misery of the other, no words are too

The wise man never suffers


all things are his.
He is at home everywhere, and can accommodate himself to any circumstrong for the Cynics.

want, for

stances.

and love-inspiring, fortune cannot


An image of the divinity, he lives with
His whole life is a festival, and the Gods,

Faultless

touch him.2
the Grods.

whose friend he
reverse

is

bestow on him everything.^ The


the case with the great bulk of mankind.
is,

Most of them are mentally crippled, slaves of fancy,


severed only by a finger's breadth from madness.
To find a real man, you must look for him with a
lantern in broad daylight.
Xoph

dtr/cTjo-ews KaTopdovaQai, 5uI'ar^v Se ravrrju irav iKuiKriaai.


'

J*lato,

IJitif/.

Menu,

init.

11
avrdpKv t' ehai
(To^ov^ irdvra yap
avrov

rhv
ilmi

TO,

ruv

&\\a}u.

Ibid.

12

(according

to
Diodes): r^
ovdeu ov5' &Tropov.
h-^Upacrros 6 ayae6s.
Ibid. 10.")
^upaarou re Thf ao(phv kol ava<TO(pw

|eVo;/

^dpT7]rou Ka\(pi\ovr^ 6ij.oiw,Tvxv


re nr]5h iirirpiir^Lv.
Sec p. 803,
2.

The passage

^. vii.

in Arist. Eth.

U,

1053, b, 19, probably


ilso refers to the Cynics
ol 5e
rbi/ Tpo\i(6fivou Ka\
rhv Svarv:

jCaij

fieydXois

)aifiova

Trepnriirrovra

(pd(TKoj/Ts

dvai,

idv

v-

Misery and stupidity are


hyaBhs, ^ eKdvres
\4yov(nv.
Yet

&KOUTes ovSev

rj

Diogenes (in
Diof/. 89) allows that^no one is
perfectly free from faults.
^ Diogenes, in Dior/. 51
rovs
ayadovs &pSpa5 Bcmv Mvas dvai.
Bnd. 37, 72: ruy Otuu ia-ri
:

iravra-

B^oh

(piKoi

Se

ot

ao(po\

tols

ruv (p'lKwv.
Trctj/r'
&pa eVrl rwv (Xocpuv.
Diog. in Pint. Tran. An. 20:

Koiva

8e

to,

dyuOhs ov iraaav rj/xepav


eopT7> 7]yCirai
Exc. e Floril.
Joan. Damasc. ii. 13, 76 'hvriad^v-ns ipur-qe^h vir6 rivos r[ 5i5a|ei rhv vlhu, dircu el jxeu Bio^s
/xdWei (Tu/xfiiovy, <pi\6ao'pov, d 5e
dv)}p

'

duBpwnois, ^VTOpa.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

814
Chap.
XTTT.

Accorclingiy

the universal fate of mortals.^

kind are divided into two


stand opposite

to

Only a very few are

all

man-

Innumerable fools

classes.

menhappy through prudence and


small

number

of

wise

All the rest live in misfortune and folly,

virtue.

only the fewest of

all

being aware of their deplorable

state.
D. The
practical
effects of
their
teaching.

Following out these principles, the Cynics conceived it to be their special mission to set an example
themselves of strict morality, of abstemiousness, of
the independence of the wise man, and also to exercise
a beneficial and strengthening influence on others.
To this mission they devoted themselves with extranot,

ordinary self-denial,

however, without falling

into such extravagances and absurdities, such offensive;,


coarseness, utter shamelessness, overbearing self-cons

hard to say
whether their strength of mind rather calls for adceit,

and empty boasting, that

it is

miration, or their eccentricities for ridicule;

33

Diog.

a.va;ji\povs

^Xeye

rovs Kcocpovs Koi


rvcpXovs, aKKa rovs fxr} i^^vras
tovs vrAeiIhid. 35
irripav.
ffTOVs eKeye irapa ZolktoKov fjuaive{Ai.oy4v7]s)

oh

and

had found nowhere, bnt boys


he had found in Lacedeemon.

Compare what has been

Tbid. 41 the story of Diogenes


Tbid. 86
with his lantern.
verses of Crates on the stupiCompare
dity of mankind.

said of Socrates p. 121, 2, Tbid.


47 rovs p7]Topas Koi iravras tovs
iv^o^oKoyovuTas rpicrai'dpdnrovs arpiaadXlovs,
tov
di^rl
TTCKaAei
Tbid. 71 Instead of becoming
happy by practice of virtue,

Dioalso Stob. Floril. 4, 52.


genes in Exc. e Floril. Joan.
Damasc. ii. 13, 75, says that
the vilest thing upon earth is a
man without culture. Eitheii
Diogenes or Philiscus asserts iij

(xdai.

men

irapa rr^v &uoLav

vovffi.

elirovTa
likv

ovv,

SpoLTToda.

Tbid.
Uvdia
eiiTV,

33:

KaKoSaifxoir^ihs

rhv

&v^pas, eyu)
6,ydpas, ffv 8' avvlkS)

Tbid. 27

Stob.
vi.

80)

Flor. 22, 41 (Conf.


:

rdcpos

0eAet [tovs ttoTvXovs]

pare p. 292,

mog\

cbarirep iroifXTju

Ixyei.

ol

Com-^

2.

men he

CYNIC SELF-RENUNCIATION.
whether they rather
commiseration.

command

esteem, or dislike, or

Previous enquiries, however,

Chap.

^^^

make

possible for us to refer these various peculiarities

it

to

common

one

source.

The leading thought of Cynicism

is

the

self-suffi-

Blunt and onesided in their conseption of this principle, the Cynics were not content
mth a mere inward independence of the enjoyments
md wants of life. Their aim, they thought, could
ciency of virtue. ^

(i) Self-

uoZ^'^^'''

3nly be reached

by entirely renouncing all enjoyment,


by limiting their wants to what is absolutely indispensable, by deadening their feelings to outward
impressions,

and by cultivating indifference to

all

own power. The Socratic independence of wants 2 became with them a renunciation
that is not in their

:>f

their
'

Poor to begin with,^ or renouncing


property voluntarily,-'^ they lived as beggars.^

the world.^

8ee p. 302.

.vhich
)4,

we saw

Socrates used, p.

To the same

3.

effect is

he story that Diogenes, at the


beginning of his Cynic career,
:efused to look for a runaway
ilave,
because he could do
vithout his slave as well as
he slave could do without
lim. Diog. 55
Stub. Floril. 62,
[1.
Ihid. 97, 31, p. 215 Mein.
' See
pp. 303; 310, 1.
^
Such as Antisthenes, Dio;

and Monimus.
Such as Crates and Hip-

i^enes,
*

larchia.
^

According

Diog.

eady

to

Diodes

in

Antisthenes alassumed the beggar's

vi.

13,

guise, the staff and scrip nor


the truth of his account impugned by Sosicrates, in saying
that Diodorus of Aspendus
was the first to do so ; for this
statement is not very accurate,
;

According to Biog. vi. 105,


^onf. Lvcian, Cyn.
12, Dio^enes repeated the language
2

is

both Antisthenes and Diogenes


being older than Dioclorus.
Nevertheless, in Diog. 22, Diois described with great
probability as the originator
of the full mendicant garb,
and he is also said to have been
the first to gain his living by
begging.
Uiog. 38; 46; 49;
Teles, in Stub. Flor. v. 67;
Hieron. adv. Jovin. ii. 207.
His followers Crates (see the
verses in Diog. 85 and 90) and
Monimus (Diog. 82) adopted
the same course.

genes

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

316
Chap.

xin.

Possessing no houses of their own, tliey passed the

day in the
nights

or in other public places;

streets,

the

they spent in porticoes, or wherever else

chance might guide them.^

need,^

Furniture they did not

bed seemed superfluous.^

G-reek dress was

by them made

were content with the tribon

still

The simple
and they

simpler,

of Socrates, the ordi-

nary dress of the lower orders,^ without any underDiogenes must have been

the first to act thus. For Antisthenes in Xot. Symp. 4, 38,


still speaks of having a house,
although its furniture was confined to the bare walls.
Diogenes, however, and the later
Cynics lived as described. See
Diog. 22; 38 76 105: Teles.
;

and

in Stoh. Floril. 97, 31,


p. 215 Mein. Hieron. lAician,
V. Auct. 9. Diogenes for a
time took up his abode in a
tub which stood in the entrance-court of Metroon, at
Athens, as had been done by
homeless folk before.
Biog.
23 43 105 Sen. Ep. 90, 14.
But it cannot have been, as
Juvenal^ xiv. 208, and Lucian,
Consc. His. 3, represent it, that
he sj)ent his whole life there
1. c.

without any other home, even


carrying his tub about with
him, as a snail does its shell.
Compare SteinliaH, 1. c. p. 302
Gbttling, Ges. Abh. 258, and

Brucker's report of the discussions between


Kasaius, Hist.

Equally
tic

Hermann and
Phil.

i.

872.

romanstory that Crates and Hipfictitious is the

67, 20, p. 4, Mein. says is that


they spent day and night in
the open porticoes. In southern countries they even now
often spend the night in a

portico.
- The
story that Diogenes
threw away his cup, when he
had seen a boy drinking with
the hollow of his hand, is well
known.
Biog. 37 Phut. Prof,
;

in Virt. 8, p. 79 Seneca, Ep.


Hier. 1. c. He is also
90, 14
reported to have trampled on
Plato's costly carpets with the
words, Trarcy rhv TIXoltcduos tv<pou, to which
Plato replied,
irepcfye rv(p(a, Aioyii/es.
Biog.
;

26.

Antisthenes in Xen. Symp.


boasts that he slept admirably on the simplest bed.
And the fragment in Bemetr.
de Elocut. 249 (Winckelmann,
As far a^
p. 52), belongs here.
Diogenes {Ejpict. Dido. i. 24, 7,
^

4, 38,

distinctly asserts this of Dio-

genes) and Crates are concerned, they slept, as a matter of


course, on the bare ground.
^
Compare
the
passages
quioted p. 54, 4.
^ That
is
at

parchia lived in a tub. Simpl.


in Ej)ict. Enchir. p. 270. All

Sparta the

that ]VIasonius in Stoh. Floril.

sal

Athens

Gottling,

at

was imiver256 Hermann^

rplficav

CYNIC SELF-RENUNCIATION.

317

clothing.i

In scantiness of diet they even surpassed


the very limited requirements of their
fellow countrymen.2
Rre,

by

It

said that Diogenes tried to do


without
eating his meat raw,3and he is credited
is

with

jaying that everything, without exception,


human
lesh included, might be used for
purposes of food.^
Even in extreme age he refused to depart

from his

iccustomed manner of living,^ and lest


his friends
ihould expend any unnecessary care on
his corpse, he
brbad their burying it at all. A life

harmony

in

bitiquit.

iii.

from

21, 14),

vhioh it will be seen, that the


vord did not originally' mean
omethino- worn out, but a
ough dress which rubbed the
kin an Ifxanou rpifiov not an
;

xdTiou

rerpififM^vov,

and that

iiariou rpifiuv yevS/xeuoi/

in Stob.

means a covering
/hich had grown rough.
This was often done by the
^loril. 5, 67,

'

oor (Hermann, 1. c.)


Antithen es, however, or Diogenes,
cco]-ding to others, made this
ress the dress of his order,
llowing the rpil3uv to be
oubled for better protection
gainst the cold.
13
Bioff. G
2
76 ; 105.
Teles 'in Sfoh.

'lorih

1)7,

;}],

p. 215.

Cyniic ladies
tme dress, Dioff.
lie

iigle

'ten

article
in the

mdition.

Moin.

adopted the
93.

This

was
most miserable
of

dress

See the anecdotes

30ut Crates, Dior/. 90, and tlie


jrses on him. Ibid. 87.
BeLusc of tlie self-satisfaction
ith whiclv Antisthenes ex)sed to view the holes in his
oak, Socrates is said to have
)served that his vanity peered
irough tliem.
Dioff, 8.

Their ordinary food con-

'

sisted of bread, tigs, onions,


garlic, linseed, but particularly
of the dcpfMoi, or beans of some

kind.
Their drink was cold
water. Dior/. 105 25 48 85
90; Teles in Stob. FloriL 97^
31 Ibid. p. 215, M. Af/n.'/i. iv.'

c; lAudan, V. Auct. 9
nio Chry^. Or. vi. 12 and 21
^
and Gottling, p. 255. But, iu
order to prove their freedom,
156,

they occasionally allowed


a
pleasure to thems(>lves and
others.
Diog. 55 Aristid. Or.
XXV. o60 (Wi//r7,'el7)i(f/i/f,p.
28).
^ Dior/. :U
76 PHciido-Plut
;

de Esu Cam.

6,

995; Lio

Chrt/x. Or. vi. 25.


" In niof/.
73, this

principle

i.

supported by the argument,


that ever^-thing is in everything else, even flesh in bread,
is

&c.
Diog. refers for this to a
tragedy of Thycstes, the ^vriter
of which was not Diogenes,
but Philiscus. A similar statement was subsequently made
by the Stoics.
Sec Zeller's
Stoics, kc.
^
^

Sec
See

dift'er

Diofj. .34.

the

accoimts

which

in details in Dio>j.
79;

Chap.
xni.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

318

Chap.
XIII.

with nature,^ the suppression of everything artificial,


is the
the most simple satisfaction of all natural wants,
watchword of his School.^ They never weary of belaud-

which they
ing the good fortune and the independence
owe to this freedom from wants.^ To attain thereto,
a principle.*
bodily and mental hardships are made
A Diogenes whose teacher did not appear to treat him

with sufacient severity/

is

said to have undertaken

Even the scorn


of
and contempt necessarily incurred by this manner
with the greatest comlife were borne by the Cynics

self-mortification in this behalf.^

do. Tusc. i. 43, 104;


^lian, V. H. viii. 14; Stoh.

52;

Floril. 123, 11.

The same

is

in
Chrysippus
Math.
iii.
258;
Pyrrh.
Sext.

by

repeated
xi. 194.

Which Diogenes

also

re-

quired, witness for instance


^^ov
his saying in Dioff. 71
:

ovu avrl roiv aXP'h'^rcau irovwv


Tohs Kara (pvffiv hXofxivovs Cv^
euSai/xovws, iraph rrjv 'dvoiav kuko-

subject
the expressions of Diogenes in
Diog. 44; 35; StoJ). Floril. 5,
41 67, the hymn of Crates on
fhrehiia, and his prayer to the

Compare on

and 3.
Compare

303, 2
*

this

p.

250,

and

1,

Diogenes' training
appears to have been described
by Eubulus in the same glowing terms as that of Cyrus was
by Xenophon. Exc. e Floril.
67.
Joan. Damasc. ii. 13, 68
Diog. 30.

Diogenes in Stol. Floril. 7, 18,


expresses the view that mental
vigour

daiixovovcTi.
2

Teles in Stoh. Floril. p7, 31,


Mein. and the quotations p.

is

exercise,

body.
5 Bio
{Stol.

the only object of all


even that of the
Chrys.

Floril.

13,

Or.

viii.

19);

conf,

Muses in Julian, Or. vi. 199,


addition to what Pint, de
93,
125, Diog. 85
and 8tol)a;us tell of him. Compare also Liician, V. Auct. 9,
and the anecdote of the mouse,

Sanit. 7, p.

the sight of which confirmed


Diogenes in his renunciation of

the world in Phut. Prof, in Virtut. 6

Diog. 22, 40.

Compare the language used


by Crates and Metrocles in
3

Diog. 18.
According to Diog. 23
34
he was in the habit of rolling
;

in the summer in the burning


sand, and in winter of walking
barefoot in the snow, and em^
bracing icy columns. On th(
other hand, Philemon's wordi
about Crates in Diog. 87, thaf

he went about wrapped up

summer and

ii'

in rags in winteif
are probably only a comedian'
jest on his beggarly covering.)

CYNIC RENUNCIATION OF SOCIETY.


posure ;

319

nay, they accustomed themselves thereto,^ on


the ground that the reproaches of enemies teach man
^

Chap.
xin.

know himself,^ and the best revenge you can take


to amend your faults.'*
Should life from any

to
is

reason become insupportable, they reserved to themselves the right, as the Stoics did at a later time,^ of

securing their freedom by means of suicide.

Among

external things of which

it is

necessary to

he independent, the Cynics included several matters


which other men are in the habit of regarding as
morally good and as duties.

man must

respect, the wise

by no relations to others.

Antisthenes

requires

repuu
Xoiro.

in

Biog.

7,

KaKoos aKovovras KapjxaXXov ri et Xldois ris ^dX-

He

also says in Epict.


Diss. iv. 6, 20 (conf Diog. 3)
fiaffiXiKhv, S> Kvpe, TrpdrTeiv fikv

KaKm

v,

S'

aKoveiv.

It is said

of Diogenes,
Diog. 33, and
also of Crates, Diog. 89, that
when his body had been illtreated, he only wrote by the
side of his blains the names of

those

by whom they had been

inflicted.

Diog. 90 says of Crates, tAs


iirhrjSes eXoiBSpci, avyyvfxvd^oiv eavrhv irphs ras /8Aa*

irSpvas

Antisthenes remarks, Diog.

12

irpoadxeiv to7s ix^P^^^' Trpu)Toi yap roou afxapTrm.drwv alcrOd:

vQvrai.

Inim.

He

also says in Pint.

Util. 6,

same saying

p. 89,

and the

attributed to
p. 74
Virt. ii. p. 82: rots
is

Diogenes in De Adul. 36
Prof,

in

free in every
be fettered and hampered

He must

To be

fieXXovai
yvrjfficov
*

ri

satisfy his social

aco^cadai

r)
(plXwv
Siairvpwu ixOpcov.

Se?

Diog. in Plut. Inimic. Util.


88 and Poet. 4, p. 21.
When Antisthenes in his

4, p.
^

last illness

under his

became impatient

sufferings,

Diogenes

offered him a dagger (Diog.


18) to put an end to his life,

which Antisthenes had not the


courage to use. That Diogenes
made away with himself is
indeed asserted in several of
the accounts to which reference has been made, but cannot be proved. In ^lian, V.
H. X. 11, he refuses the contemptuous challenge to put an

end to his sufferings by suicide for the wise man ought


to live. Nevertheless, Metro;

cles

put

(Diog.

an end

to-

himself

not

to mention
Menedemus (Ihid. 100). So
also Crates in Diog. 86
Clemens. Strom, ii. 412, D.
95),

(2) Re'"^'^^^^^^^

Ufe.

THE SOCEATIC SCHOOLS.

320

Chap.
xni.
(a)

Of

family
life.

wants by himself alone,^ or lie will be dependent on


others, and nothing which is out of his power ought
To these matters belongs
to influence his happiness.
family

Xot that Antisthenes would do away

life.

with marriage, because he thought it useful to keep'


up the race of men;^ but Diogenes early discovered
that this object might be attained by a community
of wives.^ Deeply imbued as these philosophers were

with Grecian peculiarities,

it

never occmTed to them

to require, in the spirit of a later asceticism, the en-tire

uprooting of

all

might, however, be

sexual desires.

satisfied in a far

6, Antisthenes in
reply to the question, What
good philosophy had donejiim,
answers rh ZvvaaQai kaxn^ bfxiOnt of this came the
Xetv.
caricature of later Cynicism,
described by Lucian, V. Auct.
Yet Diogenes and Crates
10.
were anything but haters of
their fellow-men.
ya/jL-fjcreLV re \_tov
Biog. 1 1
1

In

Dioff.

Natural impulses

more simple way.*

Chrysip]3us, according to Biog.


vii.33, 131, projected the same
state of things for their ideal
state.

"]

Something of the same


kind has been already observed
^

With
in Socrates, p. 163, 1.
the Cynics this treatment of
the relation between the sexes
becomes an extravagance and

a deformity. In Xefi. S>Tnp.


4, 38, Antisthenes boasts of his
reKVonoiias
(r6(pou']
X-P^^
comforts, since he only assoyvuai^i.
ffvuiSvra
evtpveffTOLTaLS
ciates with those fair dames to
d(pvcrTdTaLS
conjectiu'e
The
whom others would have noaccording
29,
(Winkelmaim, p.
mis- thing to say. That he did so
to Hermann) appears
in JDiog,
taken Antisthenes might well on principle is stated
declared adultery,
require eixpyea-rarai -rrphs t^kvo- 3. That he
permissible, as Clemens. Floril.
TTouau, women most suited for
no means cer-,
child-bearing, whilst consider- V. 18 says, is by
said to havel
even
is
He
tain.
a
for
ing anyone good enough
satisfied his lusts in a coarsei^
plaything.
3 Dior/. 72
eKeye 5e koX Koiva^ way, complaining that hungei^
could not be treated in thel
ydfiov fx-qyvva7Kas,
TCts
5iz/
elvai
same way. Brucher, i. 880,{
izeiffavra
S4va voixlCcov, aXKa rhv
Steinhm-t, p. 305, and GoUling^
Se
KOivovs
(Tvveivai
rf) ireiadeiar)
The p. 275, doubt the truth of thes3
5ta TouTO Koi rovs vt4as.
and similar stories. Without;
supported
is
this
correctness of
accuracy, i%
bv the fact that Zeno and vouching for their
:

"^^^^

CYNIC RENUNCIATION OF
SOCIETY.
Their mendicant

life,

an opportunity'

fo home

-m

moreover, not affording


them
pleasures, it

is

readily

understood that they were


in general averse to
mar!
nage,2
^ to feminine
family

society, or at least
treated

life as

a thing indifferent.^

may be enough to say that they

Diogenes

is

said

also accused
of having
publicly practised
unchastity,
I^tog. 69
Theod. Cur. Gr Aff
xii. 48, p. 172.
In Corinth the
10; GaUn. Loc. Affect, vi 5younger Lais, according
nii. 419, K. Atken. iv.
to
158 f
Athen xiii. 588, b, or
Dio Chrys. 34 Horn, in
Ph?yne,
Matli' p'
according to Tertull.
Apol 46
|98 a.,s'. ^,,^;, Civ. Dei,xiv:
IS said to have
had a whim to
.0 but also, according to
Plat
bestow on him her
5tob. Rep. 21, 1, p.
favours
1044, Chry- gratuitously,
whereas the philoiippus had on this score
vindi- sopher did
not despise others.
jated the Cynics, and
accorCleviens (Hom. V.
ling to Sext. Phyrrh.
18) repreiii. 206,
sents him as purchasing
Jeno ajDpears to have
them
done the by scandalous
conditions
ame. Dio. probably borrowed
In
his tragedies
(according to
lis
revolting
extracts from Juuan
Ov. vii. 210, c)
>hrysippus.
stood
The things are things
t^hat one might
owever, not so out of keepin<^
believe
ath the ways of Antisthenes% vjr^p<poKnu a^^rjrovpyUs ovSh raTs
fTaipais ctwoheAe^cpeai.
hat we could call
On the
them im- other hand his
morality is comossible; and the very
thino- mended,
Bemefr. de Eloc 261
inch to us appears so
unin*''^'\'^ <^ase of
Crates is an
3lhgible, this public
want of exception, and
even Crates had
lodesty,
makes them very not
wooed Hipioarchia.
kely to be true of
He
Diogenes\ only married
her, when she
true, they were an
attempt would not
renounce her affec1 his part to expose
the folly tion for him,
but was prepared
mankind.
It is from this
\
to share his mode
of life
)mt of view rather than
He
on certainly married
his cliildren
ly moral grounds
that the
^'^y' according
y^nics conduct
their attacks to
l"^ Bioy.
n-^'"''^}'''''
*
88 93.
adulterers and stupid spend-

not only quoted by Dion


46, 49
IJio Chrys. Or. vi.
16,
K.
p. 2C;3,
Lucian, Y. Auct'
are

IS

'

To them it seemed
olish m llie extreme
to incur
iicli toil, danger,
and expense
r an enjoyment,
wbich might
liad much more
easily.
See
rifts.

0U-^\ 61; 60; 66 89 P/,,^.


IPu 7, Schl. p. 5; S^oh.
""! 6; 39; 52.
Diogenes
;

^Popl^thegms

in
ni^^'t
^^'l
3, and Zueian, V.
Auct.

J^^off.

.i
yafiou Se afie\-f,aei^ kuI
:^
TraiSuv
Ka^ narpiSos.
Far less objec-

tionable

IS

thenes in

the

maxim of

Antis-

i>;W/. J2: rh^


5^^^,^^
T6pi TTAetoros iroie7<Tdai
roD avrvt.
'
yovi.
'

'See

pp. 310,

1,

and 277.

Chap
XIII.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS,

^22
to

(^HAP.

^^^(b)

between
have seen nothing revolting^ in marriage

the nearest relations.


to be
Another matter which they considered
for the wise man,
equally indifferent with family life
contrast between
was civil life. Indeed the sharp
affect the wise man.
slavery and freedom does not
who is really free can never be a slave

Oj-

'''""^ ^'^'

The man

one who is afraid and for the same


The wise man is
reason a slave can never be free.
although he may b('
the natural ruler of others,

for a slave is

'

called a slave, in the

same way that the physician

i{

thai

Accordingly it is said
the ruler of the sick.
had the questioi
Diogenes, when about to be sold,
declining the offer o
asked Who wants a master ?
buy him back.^ Not that such condue
:

his friends to

the contrary, th.


was a vindication of slavery. On
among Greeks t
Cynics seem to have been the first
.

declare
>

T)in

it

quite
an institution opposed to nature,^

Clmn

Or. x. 29,

whose

fpreeTnTwUh the universal


See
doctr nf oT the Stoics.

STstoics, &c.,
2

T>n

moa
286

to'X:

29
4

16,

p. 4.

Compare

74.

According
Antisthenes wrote

332,

4.

T/e.e.;^as Ko^^ 5ovAe(as, and


;:'rh:ps th?s is the origin of the
in Stoh. Flor. 8, 14.
account
'
For his we have certainly
Still (as
direct authority.

111

no

has been alreadv observed, p.


re171 rfit is probably in
that
Cvnics
the
ference to

irS
Tavs

PoYit.

i.

TeJollL.o..'.a
llpic

1253, b, 20,

toSm^. 5oereWT7V^Te'

^iL

rh Sea.SCe^p

ro:s 5^
'

v6i.^

7P

"'^^

i*^^"

^'^''^^^
^/''f '

5.W

S.c^.ep o^^

p...

ii

T^"
^.au

The contrast betwee


t-Pv6,. and ^^ae. is -t fon^^^
strongly drawn at that tin
except

among

Cynics.

Nor

the Sophists an
is it only m<

with in their religious

vie^'

heir who
On
politics, and even their prac.
cal philosophy, are governe

the contrary

.^^e effort to brin^^^^^^


society from an artificial sia

^^

recognised by law and custO;|


Vl
to a pure state of nature
sophist
should hardly look
circles for the opponents

slavery
tions,

whom

Aristotle m.

where the rule

of

CYNIC RENUNCIATION OF CIVIL LIFE.

o2'i

conformity with their principle, that every


diflference
between men other than that of virtue and

chap.

vice is

unimportant and has nothing to do with the


law of
nature and reason.
Yet they did not go so far as to
attempt even in a small circle (as the
Essenes did

at a later time) the abolition of slavery,


regarding the
outward state as something indifferent, the

wise'^man

even in slavery being a free man. Nor


was
wise with civil life.
The wise man of

it

other-

the Cynics
himself above the restraints which
civil life
imposes, without therefore feeling any
impulse to
mix himself up in such matters for
where could be a
3onstitution which would satisfy his
requirements?'
feels

popular government

(V

:henes.

ihese

An

is

severely censured by Antis-

absolute

monarch only appeared to


freedom-loving philosophers a bad and
miser-

over the weaker was


egarded as the most conform^ble to nature.
But the view
sail the more
keeping with
tron,Q,er

which do not distinguish the


good from the bad iBior, 5 6)
must be intended for a hit av
democracy.
The sayin- in

m
_

^'^'"'^

''^

'^^^

^'''(f' 8, tliat

?? ^^T^^
'f^ allow
ould
that one portion of
nanKmdeiwthe right, quite
'

nians

nd

fool resting

upon reason,

naturally all

men

being

izens of one state between


low-citizens the relation of
laster and slave cannot exist.
1

the fable-the applicawhich to a democracy


obvious-of the hares sug-

5, tells

.on ot

esting umv^ersal
le

hons

attaches to

equality to

The blame which


those

states,

asses horses

would be quite as Jooc'


as choosing incompetent
gC:
rals-must also be d ricted
against a popular form of
it

ndependenlly of their moral


ate, to govern the rest, the
laimot the wise man to govern
he

should the ?the.

call their

government.
Athen.

v.

Accordino^

220, d

to

AntSenes

had made a shLrp attack

nal

the popular leaders at At


en
Likewise in Diog. 24 41 Dk>-'

and he amuses himself at


DemoSen^^^^
IHd. M, on which Tee
vovs,

the expense of
Diss.

iii. 2,

^"w

See also wlft*


was said of Socrates
Socrates, nl
fir
p. I6(,.

T 2

11.

^"^'

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

324

Aristocratical institutions

able man.^
XIII.

fell far

below

none being adapted for the rule of wise


what law or custom can fetter him, whose

their ideal,

men

for

regulated by the laws of virtue ?2 What


country can be large enough for those who regard
is

life

Allowing

of the world ?^

themselves as citizens

and laws/
the Cynics^ refused in their homelessness to take any
part in civil life. They wished to be citizens of the

there-fore a conditional necessity for a state

world, not of any one state their ideal state, as far


as they do sketch it, is a destruction of all civil life.*^
;

Compare Xen. Symp.

Or.

Dio Chrys.

vi.

97, 26
Also Plut. Adul. et

Floril. 49, 47

4,

36

a negative answer to
Alexander's question, whether
he did not wish to see Thebes

given

Stol.
Diog. 50.

47;
;

Am.

c.

rebuilt

27,

^X^^^ ^^ irarpida a5ottj tux??

ireviav avdhcara

p. 68.

|tai/ /cat

2 Antisthenes,
in Diog. 11,
rbj/ aocpov oh Kara rovs
says

hoX Aioyevovs eJyai tioAittjs aveiri-

PovKevToi'

KCLfjifVOvs

See

(pdofcf.

JEpict. Diss.

TToXiTevaeaOai

vojiiovs

iii.

also

24, 66. Lucia/if

DioecpaaK^ 5' avTigenes, ihid. 38


riOevaL rvxv t^^^^ Odpaos, vo^w 5e
This
Se Xdyov.
(pvaiv, irdOei

Also the Stoic


V. Auct. 8.
doctrine in Zeller's Stoics, &c.,
chap, on Stoics, and what has
been said above, p. 278, 1.

antithesis of vSfios and <pvais


seems to be what Plato has in
view, PML 44, C. See p. 294, 4.
5 hiog. 63 says of Diogenes

*
The confused remarks of
Diogenes in Diog. 72 support

aWa

Ku-^a rhu rrjs aperris.


:

epa)Trj0eis Troflev

See

e<pv.
(j.6vr}u

Te

eiTj,

KO(Tjj.OTroX'm]S,

IMd. 72
p. 167, 8.
6p6^v iroXireiav eiuai
:

T^v iu Koafxw. Antisthenes, ibid.


12: TJp (TocpCf) ^evov ovdei/ ou5'
Crates, ihid. 98
&TTopov.
:

OVX

e^y

Trdrpas ^oi irvpyos, ov fxia

(rreyr),

irdarjs 8e x^pffov

Ka\

irSKicriJ.a

Koi

Soixos
TO/iOS

T/jU?*/

iudiairaadai irapa.

The same individual in Plut.


de Adul. 28, p. 69, shows that
banishment is no evil, and according to JDiog. 93 (conf. Ael.
Y. H. iii. 6) he is said to have

this statement.
^ Antisthenes was not without
a citizen's rights (see Hermann,
Antiquit. 1, 118), although a

by birth and cirDiogenes was


cumstances.
banished from Sinope, and
lived at Athens as a foreigner.
Crates had chosen this life;
after his native town had
proletarian

been destroyed.

Monimus

was'

a slave whom his master had[


driven away.

Stoh. Floril. 45, 28

'Aj/t*-

cOeVrjs epojTrjflels trws dv tis nrpoff'

eXQoi TToKiTeia, eiire KaddTrep Trvpl,


fi-fjre Xiav iyyvs 'iva ixh Kafis^fxilTi
irSppco 'Iva

fj.r]

piydicnjs.

CYNIC DENUNCIATION OF CIVIL LIFE.


mankind

All

nation

are to live together like a flock.

may have

severing

its

own

iV2b

No

and boundaries

special laws

from others.

it

Confining themselves to
the barest necessaries of life, needing no
gold, that
source of so much mischief, abstaining from

marriage

and family

life,

they wished to return to the simplithe leading thought of

city of a state of nature


their

enlarged political sympathies being not so


the oneness and the union of all mankind,

much

the freedom
social life

of the individual

'

and silYer^Athen.

We know

iv. 159, e.

further that Zone's

ToAirem ran to this effect 'iva


i^ Kara irSKcis /UTjSe Kara dri/xovs
:

tlKWflCU, iSioiS KCi(TTOl Stc>}pL(riJ.evoi

aAAa

UKaiois,
'Tycvfxeea
'e

Rios

Traj/ray

S-qfjiSras

ri tcai

avO pwrrovs

Kal rroXiras efr

K6crfxos,

rvvv6fiou vSjxco

ucnrep aye'Arjs

KOLv<f

Tpe(t)oiJ.4vr]S,

Alex. Vit. i. 6, p. 829;


.nd since this treatise of Zeno
vas always considered to ex-

^Hut.

cess the opinions of the Cj-nic


Ichool,

we have every reason

look in
'hat

it for a Cynic's views,


such views were on the

'hole
tiencs,

but
from the bonds of

and the limits of nationality.

The above description rests


only in part on direct testimony, but the combination
which is the basis of it does
not lack great probability. We
know on authority that Diogenes in his iroAireta {Diog.
80) demanded a community of
wives and children, and that
in the same treatise he proposed a coinage of bones or
atones {aa-ToayaKoi) instead of
ifold

advocated by Antisprobably in the treatise

Trcpl

vSjxov

Here again
TTcpl

TToAtTefay,

which appears to be identical


with the -ToAiTiifhs did\oyos mentioned by At/ten. v. 220, d, is
in itself probable, and is contirmed
by Plato's Politicus.
Rejecting, as his dialogue does,
the analogy between states-

manship and the superintena flock, we might


naturally think that Plato was
provoked to it by some such
theory; and since we know
from Plutarch's account of
dence of

Zeno, that the Cynics reduced


the idea of the state to that of

a herd
natural

of men, it is most
to
think of
them.
IMoreover, the description of

the natural state, Kep. ii. 372,


appears also to refer to Antisthenes.
Plato at first describes

though from himself, but


afterwards clearly intimates
that it belongs to another,
when he calls it a state tit
for ]ugs.
Nor do we know of
anyone else to whom it could
be better referred than to the
founder of the Stoic School.
it

lie

as

Cha p
Xllf.

THE SO CRATIO SCHOOLS.

:V2Q

be seen the negative spirit of their morality,


destitute of all creative power.

may

Chap.
XIII.

The same

Str

'^

character

may be

recognised in a feature

^^^ ^^^^ revolting in Cynicism their deliberate suppression of the natural feeling of shame.

f^^'

^is

not consider altogether unreasonable,^ but they urged that you need only be
ashamed of what is bad, and that what is in itself

This feeling they did

good may not only be unblushingiy discussed, but


done without reserve before the eyes of all.^ They
therefore permitted themselves what they considered
natural, without regard to places, not shrinking even
from doing in the public streets ^ what other men
It is expressly told of Diogenes, B\og. 37 54, that he expostulated with a woman who
lay in an indecent position in
a temple, and that he called
blushes the colour of virtue.
2 See the following note, and
Nee vero
Cic. Off. i. 35, 128
audiendi sunt Cynici aut si qui
fuerunt Stoici pfene Cynici,
'

qui reprehendunt et irrident,


quod ea, qu turpia non sint
(for instance, the begetting of
children) nominibus ac verbis
tlagitiosa

consider

dicamus (that we
imseemly to name

it

them), ilia autem qute turpia


sunt (stealing, &c.) nominibus
appellemus suis.
3 This is especially said of
Diogenes, Diog. 22 Travrl Tp6-n(f
:

ixpwo

eis Trdura, api<nci}U ti koI

Kadev^ccv

Koi

dia\ey6ijLuos,

and

according to JDiog. 69, he supported this by the argument.


If it is at all allowable to
breakfast, it must be allowable

to

Fol-

breakfast in public.

lowing out this principle, he


not only took his meals in public in

the streets (Diog. 48

but he also

did

many

58),

other

eccentric and startling things,


in the sight of all passers by
It is even,
(Biog. 35; 36).
asserted of him,^ JDiog. 69
TroteTi/ iv r^ f^^cTf,
Koi TO Ar^firiTpos Koi to ' A^poSirtjs.
Theod. Cur. Gr. Aff. xii. 48, p.

elwOei 5e ttuj/to

172,

says

the same of

him,

We
mentioning an instance.
have already, p. 320, 4, observed
caO'
that these statements
hardly be altogether fictitious.
But it is incredible that Crates,
and Hipparchia, as is said tC;
have been the case, consum-f
mated their nuptials in thQ

midst of numerous spectators^


There are, however, not a fe^
authorities for it
Sext. Pyrrh. i. 153

Diog. 97

iii.

Clemens Strom at. iv. 523, A.


Apul. Floril. 14; Lact. Inst
;

200.

CYNIC RENUNCIATION OF RELIGION


prefer

way

do in

iV>7

Lest he should in

any

Chap.

forego his independence, the Cynic puts out of

sight

to

all

regard

secret.

for

others,

and what he

not

is

ashamed of by himseK, he thinks he need not be


ashamed of before others. The opinion of men is to
him indifferent. He is neither hurt by their familiarity

with his personal

life,

nor need he fear

sucli

familiarity.

To the same

may be referred the Cynic


attitude towards religion.
Xo course of study under
Antisthenes was needed to make men doubt the truth
jf

source

the popular faith.

Such doubts were raised on

all

and since the appearance of the Sophists, had


permeated the educated classes. Not even the Socratic circle had passed unscathed.^
From his intersides,

course with Grorgias and the other Sophists, Antis-

thenes in particular must have been familiar with


freer views respecting the Grods

and their worship,


and specially with the principles of the Eleatics,
whose teaching in other respects he also worked into
his

For him, however, these views had a pecumeaning.


Hence, too, may be explained the

own.

liar

iii. 15, who mentions it as the


common practice of the Cynics;
S. Aug. Civ. Dei, xiv. 20, who

does not altogether credit it,


but does not improve it by his
interpretation.
Yet all these
authorities.
The
story may rest upon
sorae such story as that this
niarried couple once passed a
night in the aroa TroiKiK-q, or
else upon the theoretical assertion of some Cynic pbiloso-

are

later

whole

phers, tliat a public consummation of nuptials was permissible.


On the other hand, we
have no reason to doubt what
Diog. 97 states, that Hipparchia went about in
public
dressed as a man.
As we gather from the dialogues of Socrates with Aristodemus and Euthydemus, Xen.
Mem. i. 4 iv. 3 not to men'

tion Critias.

{d) Re-

^.'f^^^J^f

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.


Chap.
XIII.

and

sharp

popular

hostile

attitude

of the

Cynics to the

which they so distinctly deviated


from the example of Socrates. The wise man, indefaith, in

pendent of everything external, cannot possibly be


dependent on a traditional faith. He cannot feel
pledged to follow popular opinions, or to connect his
well-being with

customs and devotional practices,


which have nothing to do with his moral state.
Thus in religious matters the Cynics are decidedly on
the side of free thought.

The

existence of a G-od

they do not deny, nor can their wise

one

without

but they object to a number of gods resembling


popular gods, owing, as they say,^ their existence

men

man do

to tradition

in reality there

is

but one God, who

resembles nothing visible, and cannot be represented

by any symbol.^

The same reasoning holds good

In this way we must explain the free thought of Aristodemus, Mem. i. 4, 2, 9-11
14 who is also described by
Plato, Symp. 173, B., as a kindred spirit to Antisthenes.
Cie. N. D. i. 13, 32: 'Antisthenes in eo libro, qui physicus
inscribitur,
populares
\_v6ix(i}']
Deos multos, natura'

lem [(^vaet] unum esse dicens,'


which is repeated by Minnc.
Fel. Oct. 19, 8, and Lact. Inst.
i. 5,

Clemens, Protrept.

epit. 4.

46, C, and also Stromat. v.


"
Apt icr 9 evrjs
601, A., says:
Oehu ou5ej/t ioiKeuai (prjaiv 5i07rep
.

'

axnhv ohZels
Svyarai.
i.

p. 14
ToD 0oD

75,

Trepi

iKiJ.a9e7u

Ik6vos

e|

cIkovos

Tlieod. Cur. Gr. Affect.


:

'AvTto'fle'i/Tjs

TcDi/

....

oXoov j8o5

o.ir)i

oh yt/wpi^eTai, ocpdaXfxois

oux dparai, ovSeul

eoiKe

dionep

avThv ovSels

iKjxaBelv e|

of

elKoyos

Ad

Xat. ii. 2:.


In reply to the question. Quid'
dvuarai.

Te-rtull.

in coelis ag-atur ? Diogenes replied


Xunquam ascendi to;
the question, Whether there;
;

were any Gods ? he answered

Nescio nisi ut sint exj)edire.


No very great dependence can,
it is true, be placed in Tertullian's sayings.

Id. Apol. 14

Ad. Nat. i. 10 Diogenes nescis


quid in Hereulem ludit, without, however, giving furthei,
particulars.
Compare whai
r

was said
' The

of Socrates, p. 175.
CiTiics are therefore

Atheists in the ancient sens(


of the term, i.e. they deniec
the Gods of the state, althougl
from their point of view thej
were certainly right in reject
ing the charge of atheisBi

CYNIC RENUNCIATION OF RELIGION.


the worship of the gods.
pleasing

God by

stition.

Wisdom and

virtue

wise

is

but one way of


everything else is superis

make

uprightness

and friends of the gods.


secure their favour

There

329

What

is

us followers

generally done fo

worthless and unmeaning.

The

man

honours Grcd by virtue, and not by sacriwhich Grod does not require.^ He knows that a
temple is not more holy than any other place.^ He
does not pray for things which are considered goods
fice,i

by the unwise

not for riches, but for righteousness.^

Herewith the ordinary notion respecting prayer


is also surrendered
for everyone owes virtue to his
own exertions. Hence Diogenes may be understood
ridiculing prayers and vows.^
The same sweeping
;

judgment
prophets.^

biting

pronounced on

is

The mystic

oracles, prophecy,

rites

also

and

were assailed with

scorn/ both by Diogenes and Antisthenes

these philosophers, as far as religious views are


conNothing folio ws from the anec-

and

Dwg. 37 42.
\Julmn, Or. vi. 199, B., excusmg Diogenes because of his

man the most intelligent

dotes

povcrt}^

entercd
sacrifice.

says that

he never
temple or offered

Crates, {h\d. 200, A.,

promises to honour Hermes and


the Muses oh ^a.ix6.vais rpvip^pats,
oAA ap.rahdaiais.

philosophers,

he

thinks
beinff

but looking at interpreters of


dreams, or prophets, or credulous l)elievers in them, he considers him the most foolish of
creatures.
Similar statements
in Z>?V>.7. 43
48; Theod. Cur
Gr. Alf. vi. 20, p.' 88
and IXo
Or. x. 2
17.
Antisthenes ap^
pears also in Xen. Sym. 8, 5, to
have doubts upon the subject
;

bee p. 315, 2.
/iTjSeV
^QQ^Dwf). 73
rt
ftTOTTov ilvai e'l Upoi rt Ka^tlv
* See the prayer of Crates in
-

Juhan 1. c. and Diog. 42.


* Compare the anecdotes

^TiIn'^U
^'^'o.
Biog.
24

in

of the ^aiix6viou of Socrates, but


no conclusion can be formed
from a joassage so jocular.
'
Diog. 4 39 4'^- Pint Aud

.
he says that,
1

looking at pilots, physicians.

^^'^^-

^'

P-

trept. 49, C.

21

;'

Clemens', Pro^

Chap.

^"-

'

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

330

Chap.
^^"-

holding a perfectly independent attitude


towards the popular faith. Not but that they gladly
took hold of points which mythology supplied for their
cerned,

own arguments, taking all the more occasion to do so,in


proportion to the earnestness of their desire to influence
the masses Antisthenes being aided in so doing by the
:

which he had previously enjoyed.^


The various traditions must all be explained in har-

sophistical training

mony

with this view.

Hence we

find Antisthenes

in no small degree engaged in allegorical interpretations of the myths and the poets, and in an expla-

nation of Homer, which he committed to writing in


^
numerous volumes.^ Looking for a hidden meaning
disin legendary stories, he was everywhere able to
cover moral teaching,and to build on moral reflections.*

Indeed, by laying down the further axiom, that the


he
poet does not always express his own sentiments,^
1

Symp.

For the allegorical inter-

pretations of that period consuit Krische, Forsch. 234 Xen.


Sym. 3, 6 Plato, The^tet. 153,
G' Rep ii 378, D. lo, 530,
a! Phsedrus, 229, C. and
ZeUer\<i Phil. d. Griech. i. 930,
3; also pp. 755, 831; Stoics,

D.

3,

Plato, Rep.

lo, 530, C.

ii.

378,

he enquired in what sense iroXvrpoOn,


Tria was meant for praise.
Od. v. 211; vii. 257, he remarked, that no rehance could
be placed upon lovers' promises. In II. xv. 123, he found
^^
^
his doctrine of the oneness of
twelve
Bioo 17, mentions
See the passages
virtue.
on
his
of
volumes
thirteen
or
WinTielmann,
p. 23-28.
of
Homer and various portions
' Bio Chrys. Or. lin. 5, says
one
and
poems,
Homeric
the
Here, too, that whereas the same had been
on Amphiaraus.
on Hercu- previously said of Zeno, 6 Sc
treatises
belong the
x6yos olros 'Kvnfevovs .(TtI
Julian, Or. vii. 209, A.
les.
irpSTcpov, on ra fiev SO^v "ra <>
testifies
also
A.,
217,
215, C
etp'orai to) Troivrfj- a\\
to the 'fact of his frequently aX-nO^la.
i^eipyaffaro avrhv, o 5
ovk
&
Xrische,
See
n.^
myths.
usin<^
"^
rwv inl fi^povs eOT)eKua-rov
Kaff
243
Xaxnv,
The virSvoia 01 ^idpoia. Xen.
;

'

Thus on Od.

i.

1,

CYNIC INFLUENCE ON THE WORLD.


had

no

difficulty

Traces of

tliis

finding

in

anything anywhere.

allegorical interpretation

found in Diogenes.

.331

may

^^^^'

also be

Yet the Cynics do not seem

Chap.

to

have carried this process nearly so ftir as the Stoics \^


which is also quite natural, Cynic teaching being
very imperfectly expanded,^ and
activity being with

From

the above

them very

tlie taste for

learned

small.

be seen in what sense the

it will

E. Their

Cynics spoke of the self-sufficingness of virtue.


The
wise man must be absolutely and in every respect
independent; independent of wants, of desires, of
prejudices and of after-thoughts.

l^'flfie''^

tvorld.

The devotion and

strength of will with which they compassed this end,


has certainly something grand about it.
Disregarding, however, the limits of individual existence,

and putting out of sight the conditions of a natural


and a moral life, the Cynic grandeur borders on pride,
and their strength of principle on
out of all proportion

is

self-will.

value

attached to the form of

life,

to such an extent that they again

become dependent
The sublime becomes
and every humour at last claims to be

on external circumstances.
ridiculous,

honoured as being higher wisdom.

who-

Plato, or

who called Diogenes a Socrates gone mad,


was not far wrong in what he said.'^

ever it was

According: to Stoh. Floril.


he explained the legend
Medea boiling up the old

29, 02,
pf

into young to mean that, by


bodily exercise, she made effeminate men young again.
2 Dio
says this expressly,
ind little has come down to us
Df Cynic interpretations.

Even their Ethics are


scanty enough, and their systern gave no opportunity for
those lengthy, physical discussions, on which the Stoics
=>

were so great.
^JUany V.
H.

xiv. 33

Diog,

vi. 54.

'^

THE SO CRATIO

332

SOTIOOLS.

Chap.

Notwithstanding these pretensions, the indepen-

r___!

dence of these philosophers was not so great that they


could dispense with every relation to others.

It

was

only natural that they should wish to see all virtuous


persons united as friends*/ and, besides, they considered

the wise man's business to raise

it

mankind

own

to his

others, they sought for

people,

desiring,

work

them

bring a lax and

to

effeminate nation back to the days of moral

slaves of pleasure,

The Cynic

pride.2

of

he considers
Biog. 11

koX

yap

Se fxdvov

ipaaBTja-ea-Oai

(lb4uai

rhi/

are

fools,'

a physician to heal their dis-

is

his mission

it

men

strict--

from self-conceit and

suffering

a guide to lead them to what

ease,^

The mass

and simplicity.

ness

with'

as educators of their

possible,

if

of

Anxious not to monopo-

level.

the blessings of virtue, but to share

lise

tlie rest

crocphv,

Hence

is good."*

to care for the outcast

praising the Spartans, replied


uvSe yap laTpha vyieias &v TToimi-

ripccv -xpv ^p4^.


12: a^iepafrros
ayados
ai
ffnovda^oi (piKoL.
6

Khs eu to7s vyiaivovffi t)]v diarpi-

Antislhenes

genes

'

wrote
and an

'EpwTjKos

{Diog.

14;

both

an

'Epw/xevos

and he had

18),

mentioned love in his Hercules


{Prool. in Ale. 98, 6
Winckelmanti, p. 16), An 'EpwriKbs of
Diogenes is also mentioned,
Diog. 80.
See p. 314.
^ Biog. 4
'h.wriaQfvns ipaoTn;

jS'/jv

Troielrai.

calls

V. Auct.

8,

Accordingly, Diohimself in Lucian^


iXevOepwTT^s roov av-,

twv iva6uv,BXidi
he expresses astonishment in
Bpuircav Kollarphs

Dio. Or. viii. 7, that men le s


frequently apply to him, the
healer of souls, than they do to

an

oculist or dentist.

when asked why he remained

When Diogenes was purchased by Xeniades, he is said


to have told Xeniades that he.
would have to obey his slave,
just as in another case hej
would have to obey a pilot or'
physician. JDiog. 30 36 conf.i
Flut. An. Vitios. c. 3, p.(
74
Philo^'
499 Stob. Flor. 3, 63

in Athens, whilst he was always

Qu.

Qeis

Sm

ti

eVtTTA.i^TTet,

iriKpcbs

Kal

Tots Kdjxvovaiv

ol

rots fxadr^ra'Ls
larpoi,

Ihid, 6:

larpoi

(pi}(n,

fxera

elaip,

dAA.'

oi)

rwy

<py](Ti,

Ka\ oi

vocrovuTcov

irvperTovcriv.

In

Stab. Floril. 13, 25, Diogenes,

Omn.

Pr. Lib. 833, E.

CYNIC INFLUENCE ON THE WORLD.

and despised, only the sick needing a physician,^


and
no more fears contamination from such
intercourse

Chap.

i^L

than the sun fears impurity from shining


in the

dirtiest haunts.

The improvement of mankind, however, is no


easy task.^
He who will be saved must hear the
truth nothing being more destructive
than flattery.-*
;

Yet truth

always unpleasant

is

an incensed

enemy

friendly service,

or a real friend dare tell

This

it.^

the Cynics propose

them

a good kind of

Agreeable to bear with


)f

no good to any

one.^o

man

being always dishe who annoys no one is

was moreover a principle


)f theirs to pitch their demands
both in word and
example above what they really wanted,
because
It

men

)nly imperfectly

conform to them.^^ Thus they pressed


.hemselves on friends and strangers alike
with their
^xhortations,i2

^j^^^j^

Diogenes,

According to Ejyict. iii. 24,


Diogenes read a lesson to
he pirates who captured him.
t cannot however, liave
done
luch good, for they sold him
>

'6,

'

otwithstanding; and the story

and above, p. 332, 3.


and p. 332, 3.
'^-'
^"^/'?; 1;. ^\'
in
V?//
P 'a ^"^j-^^h^^Jf
hU. VH
\it. Pud.
c. 18,
E.,
^J/>y. 63,

nwg.

4,

p.

g,

Diogenes
Damasc.

^an.

Exc. e Floril.
31, 22
rh

ii.

Kvees^^LKpdu iaTL Hal i.vdh roTs


'OT/To.j
It IS like light to
lose

to render to
If in so doing they give offence,
matters

tnankind.7
aot to

none save either

;5

who have weak

eyes.

in

particular,

in-

See p. 319, 3
Diogenes in Stoh. Flor 13

26:

ol fi'.v

Opohs

&\Xol

k{,v,s

SdKuovaiu,

iycb

rohs eV8k rohs

<pi\ovs, 'Lva aciao,.

Seep 818

TeTo^.-Antisth.

in Philo

Omn.

'

On

Pr. Lib. 869, C


'" IriPlut.
Virt. Mort. c 12
g, E., p. 452, Diogenes say.s of
Plato rl 5' eVeu-oj l^e. alf^yhv,
:

ovUua

K,\{,iry^K,u

" See

p.

308,

1.

'^
Compare what Dioq vi 10
saysofAntisthenes,andvi'4
46; 65 of Diogenes
also
;

XIII.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

a34

Chap.

manner,^ although more gentle


traits are not altogether wanting.^ At the same time

stilled in the coarsest

the coarseness of their manner was somewhat relieved by their humour in which Diogenes and Crates

more

They loved

particularly excelled.

serious teaching in the

to clothe

form of a joke, or of poetry,'

to hurl sharp-pointed words* at the folly of mankind ;^ Diogenes even, like the oriental prophets,

and

giving greater force to his utterances by symbolical

and thus attracting

actions,

No

them

for

attention.^

doubt the position occupied by the Cynics

the Greek world

a peculiar one.

is

Eidiculed because

of their eccentricities,^ and admired for their


Lucian V. Auct.

Because

10.

gym,
5

self-

Progym. c. 3;
Mcol. Pro5

Hermog.

Theo. Progym.

of his importunity, Crates received the name of Qvpeiro.voiPhut. Qu.


86
Kr-ns.D'wg.

in

c.

c. 3.

Abundant

examples

of

Conv.

ii.

632

4, p.

1, 7,

these ways of the Cynics are*


to be found in the a7ro(p6hixa'a
of Diogenes, in his sixth book,
Hee
and in Stoba^us' Floril.

Apul-

'

Floril. iv. 22.


1

24

Diog.

32

46

Damasc.

Floril. Jo.

Ex. e

7, 43.

i.

The

attractiveconversation of

ness of the
Antisthenes and
also

Diogenes

commended,

Biog.

is

14.

Conf. Xen. Symp. 4, 61.


3 See Diog. 27
85 De83
261
259
170
Blocut.
de
metr.
Plut. Tranqu. An. 4, p. 466;
Jidian, Or. vii. 209, a Antisth.
;

;_

^fia

Sia

rwv

Similarly,

fxvOcou

IMd.

a'n-^77fXAe.

215, c

217, a.

Frag. Plut. Prof, in Virt. c. 11,


Virt. Doc. c. 2, p. 439
p. 82
Coh. Ira, c. 12, p. 460 Curios.
Cup. Div. c. 7,
c. 12, p. 521
An.
Exil. c. 7, p. 602
p. 526
Seni. s. Ger. Rep. i. 5, p. 783
De Alex,
conf. Prrec. c. 26, 141
Epict. Diss
Virt. c. 3, p. 336
;

being received with friendly


words of warm com fort instead of the violent language

he expected.

Antisth.

Winckelmann,

also

2 Plut. De Adul. 28, p. 69,


relates that when Demetrius
Phalerius, after his banishment, fell in with Crates, he
was not a little surprised at

'.

iii.

2,

11

xviii. 13, 7

Gell.

not

TeHuUian, Apol. 39;


mention others.

tc

6 See Diog. 26
31
39 64
41 (the lantern) Stoh. Flor. 4
This eccentricity become
84.
a caricature in Menedemm^
;

Diog. 102.
' Diog. 83, 87, 93.

CYNIC INFLUENCE ON THE WOULD.


denial, despised as beggars,

oor:

and feared as moralists,

Chap.

of contempt for the follies, of pity for the moral


miseries of their fellow men, they met both the

_J^^

full

wisdom and the effeminacy of

their time with the

rude vigour of a resolute will, hardened even to insensibility. Possessing the pungent, ever ready native
wit of the plebeian, benevolent, with few wants, full
of whims and jokes, and national even to their very

they resemble in
the Middle Ages;i nor can
dirtiness,

withstanding

all their

many ways

in

many
it

points the friars of ^

be doubted that, not-

extravagances, their action was

For all that, philosophy


could expect but little from this mendicant philosophy.
Not until it had been supplemented by other
elements,

beneficial.

regulated

and received into connection

with a wider

view of the world in the Stoa, was


Cynicism able to bear fruit on a large scale. The
Oynic School, as such, appears to have had only a very
aarrow extension, a fact which will not appear strange,
ionsidering

the

terrible

seA^erity

of

its

demands.

Besides it was incapable of philosophic expansion,*

md

even

was chiefly of a negative


and the follies of
nen.
It required independence and self-denial, but
t separated man from man. It placed the individual
entirely by himself, thus offering play to moral pride,
character.

its

practical action

It attacked the vices

Cynics really have a


connection with the
aonks of Christendom.
The
\^^. ^ct'^'een the two is tlie
'ynicism of the time of the
'aesars, and the late Pythago'

Tlie

listorical

rean asceticism, which exercised,


panly directly and
partly through the Essenes, so
important an
influence 'on
eastern monasticism.

\
'

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

336

Chap.
^^"-

vanity,

and the most capricious whims, which were

not

miindulged.

left

The

abstract sovereignty of the

personal will resulted ultimately in individual caprice,


jand thus Cynicism trenched on the ground of the
/

philosophy of pleasure, to which as a system


diametrically opposed.

it

was

THE CYREXAICS.

CHAPTER

337

XIV.

THE CYEENAICS.l
Respecting the Cyrenaic branch
of the Socratic
school, the information
we possess is quite a imperfect, or even more
so, than that which
we
have touching the Cynics.
Aristippus ^ of Cyrene ^
the founder, had been
brought to Athens^ by a call
from Socrates, whose
extraordinary personal
3nce

had unusual attractions

See Wendt,

be Philosophia

.yrenaica, Gott. 1841.


yihe accounts of ancient
md the views of modern
mters on the life of Aristip|us
are found in detail in
y. V. Stein's De Philosophia
^yrenaica, Part, prior, de
vita
^nstippi (Gott. 1855),
which
light to have proceeded
somewhat

more

sceptically.

There

30 are

references to the earlier


terature.
' All authorities
without exJption state this.
His father
called Aritadas by ^wt^.
'Ad/

riTTTros.

^schin. in Biog. ii. Q5, says


'at he came to
Athens /cara
^oy
2.<*>Kp6.Tovs,
and Plut
*

^nos.

2,

516, gives full


^rticulars how at the
Olympic
mes he heard of Socrates
and
p.

influ-

for him,^

although his

his teaching from


Ischomachus,
at once so taken by

and was

it

that he did not rest till


he had
made his acquaintance.
See
Biog. ii. 78 80.
^ Aristippus is
not only universally described as a
follower
or Socrates {Biog. ii.
47 74
80; Strabo, xvii. 3, 22, p.' 837
^'^^^^^Ev.xiv. 18,31; Stein.\
;

but he also regarded


himself as such, and
paid a
tribute of most genuine
respect
to his teacher.
According to
Biog li 76, he prayed that
he
p.

-^b),

might die

like Socrates.

Ibid

he says that if anvthing


good can be truly repeated
of
himself, he owes it to
Socrates,
71,

and Ar int. Khet.


b,

29,

says,

riAara-i/a
(i^di'Ta,

ii.

23

'Aplamriros

1398
nphs

eVaryeAri/raSrep^,/
d,s

^fTO-

aWa

;*,>

ri

Chap.
XIV.
A. History
of the
Cijrenaics.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

338

Chap.
XIV.

weak

character was too

to endure in the last

trial.'

at that time
Cyrene, his luxurious home, which
and power,^ he had
at the height of its wealth

From
was

removed from the simplicity and


Perhaps he had been
abstemiousness of Socrates.^
Sophistical influences which
already touched by those
At any
in his subsequent career.^

brought habits

far

may

be observed

rate

attained
we may assume that he had

^ra7p6s

W<^v,

^<pyi,

ob^P 7010V.

(which

AeV "^^^ 2KpciTr)i/

TOf,

17,
Steinlmrt, Plat. Leben, 308,
sense,
contrary to the natural
sanguine
refers to Plato's too
expectations of the younger
also see from
Dionysius).

We

that he

Xen. Mem. 1. 2, iii. 8,


was on an intimate footing
and Plato
with Socrates
blaming him, Phaedo, 59, C.,
the circle
for being absent from
the day
of friends who met on

Socrates' death, evidently


to
reckons him as belonging

of

25,

Conf.

circle.

this

who

also, pp.

Stein.,

p.

50 and 74,

groups together the authorities


relations
respecting Aristippus'
Socrates.
to the pupils of
'

Phto,

1.

who however

c,

and
only savs that Aristippus
Cleombrotus

had

been

fertile
MQivi^', that on this
the
on
caroused
they
island
as
day of their master's death,
asserts,
288,
Elocut.
de
Bemetr.
The accuis barely possible.
is
statement
Plato's
racy of

indisputable, notwithstanding
ii.
^5; but
Bioq. iii. 56
whether Aristippus left Athens
his
from excessive regard for
or whether his
;

own

saie+Y,

weakness led

him

to

escape

to a certam

painful

the

interval

pending the death of Socrates


cannot be ascertained.
Cyrenen
2 See Thrifje, Res
slum, 191.
3 This may be gathered tron
Xeii.

Mem.

ii. 1,

1,

in additioi

hi
to the proof afforded by
Aristippu
That
later conduct.
belonged to a wealthy famil;
would seem to be establishec
his whole mode of living

by
and by the journey which h

undertook to Athens.
We might have imagine
that a city so rich and culti
vated as Cyrene (on this poir

see Thrige,

1.

c, p. 340, 354

would not have been neglecte


by the Sophists, even if thei
were no express evidence
prove it. It is, however, know
1

from Plato,

Theastet. 161, B
the celebrate

162, A., that

mathematician, Theodf^rus
Cyrene, was a friend of Pt'
tagoras, and the principles
Proto2:oras are also afterwar
met with in Aristippus. Frof
the zeal with which Aristippj
'^

followed Socrates it may


t^
further conjectured that
study of philosophy was to hi

no new thing.

wish to

HISTORY OF THE CYRENAICS,


maturity of thought when
he
with Socrates.^
It is,

first

therefore,

.339

became acquainted

no cause

for wonder
young man ^ met his teacher
with
considerable amount of
independence,3

that this talented


a

^hole so blindly following

He

is

afterwards

is

peculiarities.
is

lid

not on the

him

as to sacrifice his

own

even said to have come


forward
a teacher before the
death of Socrates;^ that
he
so

ilso

a better established
fact, and

that, contrary to the


principles of his gTeatest
nend, but quite in harmony
with the

practice usual

tmong the Sophists, he


required payment
nstruction.-^

The chronology of his life


very uncertain. Neither the
ime of his birth nor of

have

pay for his instruction.


How
dependence can be placed
upon this story will be
seen
from the fact that Aristippus

which is placed in 361


But Diodorus probably
3rived from
Dionysius his
lecdote about the interview

says in his reply, that


Socrates

did the same, only taking

therefore be relied upon


we are ignorant how old
-istippus was at the
time,
ese accounts are anythino-

)uld appear,
veral years

of Phanias, that
Aristippus
offered to give Socrates
some
ot the money he had
o-ained in
this way
Perhaps,

satisfactory.
IHng. ii. 83,

however,
Phanias said was, that
Aristippus had taken pay,
and
offered it to his teacher,
without however bringing
the two
tacts into closer
temporal con-

According
however, it

an

he was older by
than ^schines
;

It

at

would also appear, from'


has been said p. 337

tJiat

nection.

that at the time he


followed
urates he was independent
his civil relations, and
fur-

that he was connected


h him for several years.
This is what he appears
to

le-<s

Another passage, Diog. ii. 60'


seems to imply, on the authority

accuracy can-

)t

It

is

little

C.

id as

that
;

icily,

Its

all

See Stein., p. 29.


' See Xen.
Mem. ii, 1 iii g

According to Diog] ii. 'so


Socrates blamed him
fortakin-

his

Plato.

been from

ioiown.

eath is known to us.


Accoring to Diodorua, x.v.
76, he
as living in 866 B.C.,
and
'Int. Dio. 19, tells
us that he
let Plato on his
third visit to

ith

for his

In yet another point he


followed the

Phanias

in

Ihid. 72
74
also stated in

Diog.

ii

where

80,

6.5

it

is

what wav he defended this conduct. Alexis


in

Athen.
Pu.

z2

xii. .544, e

7, p.

Phtt.

Edu

Stoh. Exc. e Floril'

Chap,
XIV.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

340

Chap.
XIV.

example of the Sophists, by passing a great portion


any fixed abode.'
of his life in various places without
Joan. Damasc. ii. 13, 145 (that
Aristippus is meant here appears from 146 conf. Diog. ii.
Also Xeyi. Mem. i. 2, 60,
68).
appears to have an eye on him.
The amount of these fees is
estimated at 1000 drachmae by
Plutarch, at 500 by Diog. 72.

He says of himself in Xen.


Mem. ii. 1, 13 ouS' ets7ro\/Te/a'
l^vos
KaraifXeico, oXKa
eju-aurbj/
In Plut Virt.
irauToxov d[xi.
Doc. p. 2, p. 439, sorne one asks
;

time the elder Dionysius, at


another the younger Dionysius,
at another simply Dionysius, is
spoken of. Conf. Stein., p. 57.
It is asserted

by the Scholiast

13, that Aristippus was at Syracuse under


This
the elder Dionysius.
statement is borne out by
Hegesander in Athen. xii. 544,
c for the Antiphon there mentioned was (according to Pint.
De Adulat. 27, p. 68) executed
command of the elder
by
to
ei
apa
him iravraxov (fv
The anecdote of
Dionysius.
bad
a
with
replies
which he
in Galen. Exshipwreck
his
later
joke. He is mentioned by
hort, c. 5, must be referred to
bad
doubt
no
often
writers,
It can only
same time.
authorities, as having been in the
first visit to
his
to
belong
Megara,
in
different places:
by Vitruv. vi. Praswhere he met with iEschines Sicily, but
transferred to the
was
fat.
Socr.
Ep.
conf.
(Diog. ii. 62
On this
he island of Khodes.
29) in Asia Minor, where
On the
61.
Stein.
see
point
Persians,
the
was imprisoned by
Dio.
19,
Plut.
hand,
in Corinth, other
(Diog. ii. 79)
with
contact
into
him
brings
Lais
with
where he revelled
third journey
(Hermesianax in Ath. xiii. 599, Plato on Plato's
361
B.C., in the time
Sicily,
to
^gina,
in
Diog. ii. 71)
b
Dionysius. The
where he not only lived for a of the younger
xi. 507, b:
Athen.
in
notices
Soof
time after the death
ii. 66-69, 73, 75, 77-82.
Diog.
to
according
where,
but
crates,
are indefinite, although the
conf. xii.
Athen. xiii. 588, e
there told harmonise
stories
up
took
year
every
544, d, he
the court of the
with
better
with
his residence in company
than witl
Dionysius
younger
where
Scillus,
at
Lais: and
Nothing
father.
his
of
that
him his Me-

on lAician, Men.

Xenophon read

to

morabilia, Ep. Socr. 18. Much


in particular is told of his stay
his
at the court of Syracuse, of
hostile encounter with Plato,
and of many other adventures,

which he there experienced.


But in these notices there is
great confusion, since at one

can however be laid down wit

certainty respecting the visit;


of Aristippus to Sicily. Thai
he visited Sicily may be he
lieved on tradition. That h(
there met Plato is not impos
sible, though it is also possibU

that the account of this meet

HISTORY OF THE CYRENAICS.

Ui

Subsequently he appears to have returned


to his
native city, and to have taken
up his permanent
residence there.^

Here

we

it is

that

The

heiress to his principles

family and his School.^

hear of his

first

was a daughter, Arete, a lady of sufficient


education
to instruct her son,^ the younger
Aristippus,^ in his
ing was invented in order to
out the contrast between
both philosophers.
In fact,
Plato's journeys to Sicily
were
a favourite topic for later
anecbring-

dote mongers.
.he

above

But anyone of
taken by
must be accepted

stories,

tself alone,

caution
nor is it even
jertain that he visited
both
he Dionysiuses.
When the
ounger one came to the throne
368 B.C.) he was at least 60
-ears of age, and yet most
of
he stories which are told
apA^ith

'car to

have reference to him.

)n the other

hand, Aristippus
here appears in a character
etter suited to his years
of
ravel than to his later
years,
'lie

valueless as a historical testi-

mony, nor does

it even render
the existence of a corresponding tradition probable; and
the hypothesis based on Diog.
ii. 62, that Aristippus
flourished
at Athens in 356 has been with
justice refuted by Stein., p. 82.

accidents of
Aristippus
nd Plato probably went the
)und as anecdotes, without
ly attention having been paid

between

their historical connection


id when this was done
)

by

ibscquent biographers, it beime impossible to find out


bat was fact.

Whether this stay was


ortened by frequent travels,
blether Aristippus
died in
rrene or elsewhere, and
how
Qg he lived, are points unlown.
For the journey to
eily in 361 b.c. is,
as we

Leben, 305, 33,

Stei)iliart, Plat.

proposes to read

'Api(rTor4\r} for
'Aplariinroi/ in Bioff. ii. 62, but

the chronology
correction,
be better.

supposed

leeting

'

have seen, uncertain.


The
twenty-ninth letter, which Socrates is
supposed to have
addressed to his daughter from
Lipara after his return, and
in expectation of death, is

is

against this

^irevannroy

Generally called Cyrenaics,

more rarely Hedonists,


Athen.
^

would

vii.

312, f

Who was

as in

xiii. 588, a.

thence called

jxti-

TpoSlSuKTOS.
* Strabo, xvii.
3, 22, p. 837
Clemens, Strom, iv. 523, A.
Ens. Pr. Ev. xiv. 18, 32 Theod.
Cur. Gr. Aff. xi. 1
Dwg, ii.
72, 84, 86; Suid. 'ApiaTimros

The mist.

Or.

xxi.

therefore, uElian, H.

244.

Anim.

If,
iii!

Arete the sister of


Aristippus, it must be through
an oversight.
Besides this
daughter he is said to have had
another son, whom he did not
40,

calls

Chap.
XIV.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

:>42

<'HAP.

XIV.

grandfather's

Besides

philosophy.

of the elder Aristippus.^


is

said

called the Atheist

daughter,

mentioned as pupils
His grandson, the younger

^thiops and Antipater are


Aristippus,

this

also

have instructed Theodoras,

to

the fruits of Antipater's teaching^

;2

What
Diog. 103.
particularly notorious was his atheism. Indicted
on this account at Athens, he

own, Diog. 81 Stoh. Floril. 76,


Most likely this was only
14.
the child of an kraipa, although
Stobaeus calls his mother a

governor,

wife.
'
know
Diog. ii. 86.
further from Cic. Tusc. v. 38,
112, that Antipater bore the
loss of sight with resignation.

was rescued by Demetrius, but

made him

We

obliged to leave the city (Diog.


The assertion
Philo.).
101
;

of Amphicrates (in Diog. and


Atheri. xiii. 611, a), that he was
put to death by a hemlock-f
draught, is contradictory to all

Cicero tells a somewhat tame


joke.
2 Diog. 86.
This Theodorus
appears to have belonged to
the Optimates, who were driven
from Cyrene in the party
quarrels immediately after the
death of Alexander, and took
refuge with the Egyptian soveThrige, Res. Cyren.
reigns.
We hear of him as an
206.
exile in the last years of the
fourth century (Plut. Be Exil.
Philo,
Diog. 103
16, p. 606
Qu. Omn. Pr. Lib. 884, C), in
Greece, and particularly at
iv.
Athens (Diog. ii. 100, 116
52 vi. 97), where a friend of
Ptolemy's, Demetrius Phalereus, helped him, between 316
and 306 B.C., and subsequently
at the court of Ptolemy, on
whose behalf he xmdertook an
;

embassy to Lysimachus (Diog.


102;
Philo, 1. c,
Valer. vi. 2, 3
Plut. An. Vittos. 3, p. 499
At last he
Stob. Floril. 2, 33).
returned to his own country,
and was there held in great

102;

Cic.

Tusc.

i.

43,

honour by Magus, the Egyptian

we know of him. According


to Antisth. in Diog. 98, he was
a pupil not only of Aristippus
the younger, but also of Anniceris and of the dialectician
however diffi-

Dionysius.

It is

cult to see

how he can

been younger than


Suid. 0eo5.

and Bryso
chers,

have

Anniceris.'

makes Zeno, Pyrrhoi


(see p. 255, 1) his tea^

the

first

one

probablj

reason, the two


mistake.
quite by

with

otheif

Unde:
'kutipar. he makes him a pupi
of Socrates, at the same Htm
confounding him with a mathe'
matician from Cyrene of tb

same name

(see p. 338, 4), whJ


to us through Plate
In Diog. ii. 102, iv. 52, he
called a Sophist, i. e., one wh
took pay for his instruction.
^ According
Diog. 8(
to
through Epitimides of Cyren
and his pupil Paraebates, thlatter of whom is said to havi
studied under Aristippus. Sniii

is

known

ii

'Avi^'iKepis.

HISTORY OF THE CYRENAICS,


were Hegesias

and Anniceris.^

343

These three

men

established separate ])ranches of the Cyrenaic School,


which bore their respective names.^ Amongst the
pupils of Theodorus were Bio the Borysthenite,'' and

perhaps Euemerus, the well-known Greek


'
A cotemporary of Ptolemy
Lagi, who is said to have prohibited him from lecturing,
because he described the ills
jf life so graphically that many
were led to commit suicide.
Cic. Tusc. i. 34, 83
Valer. Max.
/iii. 9, 3;
Plut. Am. Prol. 5,
5. 497.
Suicide was also the
iubject of his book 'AiroKap;

'fpwv,

lame
"iuid.

Cic.

1.

c.

U^KnedvaTos,

Hence

his

Biog.

86,

'Apiar.

Probably also under Ptoleny L, although Suidas, 'Awik.,


)laces him in the time of Alex'^

mder.
i.

Conf. Antisth. in Bioa.


"^

88.

' For the Qeo^dpeioi


and their
caching see Bioff. 97
Calliaachus in Athen. vi. 252, c for
he '\iyii](naKoi, Biog. 93 for the
KvviKip^ioi, ibid.
96;
Strabo,
vii. 3, 22, p. 837;
Clemens,
;

trom. ii. 417, B. ; Suid. "Avv'ik.


trabo calls Anniceris 6 doKcbu
TavopBuxrai rrju Kvprji/a'iKrju a'lpeIV KaX Tvapayay^tv avr' avrris t))v

To the Annicereans
elonged Posidonius the pupil,
ad probably also Nicoteles, the
rotlier of Anniceris. Siiid. 1. c.
*
This individual lived at
thens and other places (Bior/.
46, 49, 53
ii. 135). AccordivviKepdav.

'.

ig to
ler,

Biog. iv. 10, wliere, howthe Borysthenite appears

be meant, he was acquainted


Xenocrates.
In Biog. iv.
), 54, ii. 35
Athen. iv. 162, d,

>

ith

rationalist,'^

he appears as a cotemporary of

Menedemus

(see p. 281), and


PersEeus (Zeller's
Stoics, &c.). He appears, therefore, to have lived to the middle
of the third century.
Accord-

the

Stoic

ing to Biog.

iv. 51,

he left the

Academy, which he first frequented, and joined the Cynics


(which reads in our text of
Diogenes as if he had deserted
the Academician Crates, in
order to become a Cynic, but
this is not possible in point of
time
perhaps the original
text meant that by the agency
of Crates he was brought over
from the Academy to Cynicism).
He then turned to Theodore,
and at last to Theophrastus,
Biog. iv. 151. His free thought
and the instability of his moral
;

principles (Biog. iv. 49, 53)


recall the School of Theodore,
in which Numenius in Ens. Pr.

E V. xi V. 6, 5, actually places him.


In other respects he is rather a
literary wit than a philosopher.
See Biog. iv. 46-57, various
sayings of his in Plutarch.
* Euemerus of Messene,
according to the most numerous
and approved authorities according to others, of Agrigent um, Cos, or Tegea (see
;

Sieroka,
De Euhemero. Konigsbg. 1869, p. 27), is often
mentioned in connection with

Theodorus, Diagoras, and otlier


Atheists {Sieroka, 19, 31). The

Chap.
XIV.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

844

Chap.
XIV.
B. Teaching of the

while amongst his

contemporaries was Aristotle of

Cyrene.^

The Cyrenaic teaching, the leading

which

traits of

i^ndoubtedly belonsf to Aristippus,^ like the Cynic,


notion that Theodore was his
teacher rests solely on hypo-

For we have no busi-

thesis.

ness to write Eu-l^ixepov in Biog.


ii. 97 instead of 'E-Ki^vpov (with
Nietzsche, Khein. Mus. N. F.
Epicurus derived
XXV. 231).
his views respecting the Gods

mostly from Theodorus' treaA connection


tise irepl deau.
with the Cyrenaic School is
not in itself probable, since
this was the only School which
at that time busied itself with
combating the popular belief.
Doubtless, too, that tame resolution of the myths into history,
for which Euemerus is known,
is also quite after their taste; indeed, the Cynics who, together
with the Cyrenaics, were at
that time the representatives
of free thoiight, did not resort
to natural explanations, but to
In point of time
allegory.
Euemerus may easily have
been a pupil of Theodorus. He
lived under the Macedonian
Cassander (311 to 298 B.C.),
the latter having sent him on
that journey on which he
visited the fabulous island of
pretended to
Panchsea, and
have discovered in a temple
there the history of the Gods,
the account of which is given
Diodor.
in his hpa avaypa<p-f].
Phd.
in Bus. Pr. Ev. ii. 2, 55
'

De

Is.

23,

p.

360.
this

Copious

work are
extracts from
found in Diodorus,v. 41-46, and
fragments of the translation

undertaken by Ennius, or of a
revision of this translation in
Lactant. Inst. i. 11, 13 (see
Vahlen, Ennian. Poes. Eeliq.,
p. xciii. f)

17, 22,

c.

1.

169.

Shorter notices of the contents of his treatise in Cic.


N. D. i. 42, 119, followed by
also
Minue. Fel. Octav. 21, 2
in Straho, ii. 3, 5
4, 2
p. 102,
104; vii. 3, 6, p. 299; Plut.
Athen. xiv. 658, e Sext.
1. c.
Math. ix. 171, 34 Aug. C. D.
Ep. 18 Serm. 273, 3
vii. 26
Higgin. Poet. Astron. ii. 12, 13,
See also SieroTta and
42, D.
Encykl. v.
Steinhart, Allg.
Ersch. d. Gr. i. vol. 39, 50;
3IuUer, Frag. Hist, Graec. ii.
;

100.

According to Diog. ii. 113,


president of a philosophical
School in the time of Stilpo,
Dioapparently at Athens.
genes there calls him Kuprivaik6s.
jElian, however, V. H.
X. 3, in recording a saying of

his, calls

him

Kvp-qvaios.

He

is

probably the Cyrenaic, who,


according to Diog. v. 35, wrote
a treatise Trepl koi-qti.kwv. A saying in Stoh. Floril. 63, 32, belongs to him according to some
MSS., but to Aristippus according to Cod. B.
2 The thing is not altogether
undisputed. Eus. Pr. Ev. xi^.
18, 31, f, says of the elder
Aristippus, without doubt on
the authority of Aristocles
aAA.' ou5e* txkv ovrws eV t^ (pauepw
irepl TeAous SteAe^aro, Svyd/J-ei. 5e

TEACHING OF THE CYRENAICS.


up the practical side of the philosophy of Socrates.
Of Aristippus too, and his pupils, it was
takes

T^s evSaifiovlas rr]u v-nScraaiu


eKeyfv iv r}5ova7s Keladai.
del
yap \6yovs irepl rjdoi^rjs Troiovfie-

lists of the
of
Aristippus, which
agree in the main, and one of

vovs (Is VTToypiav 7^76 tovs irpoaiSu-

which was acknowledged by


Sotion and Panaetius.
Theo-

Tos avrcf rov \4yeiv reXos iivai


Th 7]^((ios Cfjf^ and of the younger
one, ts Kal (Tacpws wpiaaro t4\os
ehai rh ijdeoos (rju, r]Sovy}v iuToiTrwv t)]v Kara Kivrjoiv.
This
testimony appears to be further
corroborated by the fact that
Aristotle, in refuting the doctrine of pleasure, Eth. x. 2,
does not mention Aristippus,
but Eudoxus, as its representative.
To this must be added
what Sosicrates and others,
according to Diog. 84, maintained, that Aristippus left no
'

writings which would at least


point to a lower development
of his teaching.
Diog. ii. 64
does not quite prove so much
;

iravTcav

/xeuToi

ruu

'S.wKpariKuiu

Sia\6ya)u Trauairios aXridels dvai


SoK(7 TOVS UKaTuuos, s.euocpcovTOs,
^AvTiaOei/ovs, AjVx'Vou
for, ac:

cording

to

84

our

in

text,

Pansetius is quoted as an authority for a number of dialogues of Aristippus. It may


therefore be asked with Bran-

whether in 64,
Aristippus' name has not been
omitted by some oversight on
the other hand, Aiarpi^al were
dis,

ii.

a,

92,

hardly dialogues cf. SuseviiJil,


Rhein. Mus. N. F. xxvi. 338.
For these reasons Bitter, ii. 93,
supposes that the views of
Aristippus were not reduced to
a connected form till a later
:

time.
crates

The assertion of Sosihowever appears to be

without foundation

for Dio-

genes gives two

works

pompus knew

of writings of
according to AtJien. xi.
508, c, he accused Plato of
plagiarism from the diatribes
of Aristippus.
Allowing then
that subsequent additions were
made to the writings of Aristippus, it cannot be supposed
that the whole collection is
spurious.
Perhaps in ancient
times, and in Greece proper,
these writings were less diffused
than those of the other followers of Socrates. This fact
may easily be explained, supposing the greater part of them
not to have been written till
Aristippus had returned to his
native country. It may also be
the reason why Aristotle never
mentions Aristippus; perhaps
he omitted him because he included him among the Sophists,
his, for

Metaph. iii. 2, 996, a, 32. The


remarks of Eusebius can only
be true in one sense, viz., that
the elder Aristippus does not
use of the expression
Te'Aos, and does not put his sentences in the form which subsequently prevailed in the

make

Schools. That he recommended


pleasure, that he declared it to
be a good in the most decided
manner, that thus the leading
features of the Cyrenaic teaching are due to him, cannot be
doubted, taking into account

the numerous witnesses which


it, nor would the unity

affirm

345
Chap.
XIV.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

346

asserted, as well as of the Cynics, that they neglected

Chap.
XIV.

questions touching nature and logic, giving to the

(1) Their
general

gtudy of ethics

Nor is

exclusive value.

this assertion

*^

disproved by the fact that they were themselves unable to keep clear of theory, the sole object of their

teaching being to establish ethics, and indeed their


own exclusive pursuit of ethics.^ The end to be secured

by philosophy

is

the happiness of mankind.

point Aristippus and Antisthenes agree.

On

this

Antisthenes,

his School be otherwise


Doubtless
comprehensible.
Plato wrote the Philebus with
an eye to this philosopher, and
Speusippus had written on

Tii/es

Aristippus, Diog.
Diog. ii. 92

fieXriov ^ X^'fo*' Xiyeadai irdvra,


Ttts Se fiaQ-qpLariKOLS ovQiva iroiila6ai x6yov Trept ayadcou /cot KaKcav.

of

acpiaravTo

Te'xJ'ais,

8s

(pvaiKwi/ 5ia

fxivr]v aKaraKri^^ilav, tccv St

KoX SeicnSaiixovias iKxhs eluai Koi

rhu
rhv

TTcpl

irepl

Qai/oLTOv (pdjSov

11

^K^^vynv

a7a0a)V Koi KaKoov x6yov

eKfieixad-qKOTa.

hoKOvcTL 8e

Sext. Math. vii.

Kara rivas Koi

ot

airh T7}9 Kvp-i]vr\s fxovov haird^eaOai

rh

riOinhu fxepos TrapairefXTreiv 5e rb

Kol rh KoyiKhv ws fx-qhev


rh euBaiiJioyws fiiovp crvvepPlut. in Dus. Pr. Ev. i.
yovvra.
'ApldTLinros 6 Kvpr]va7os
8, 9
(pvcriiihu

irphs

5e

KaKwu
&Wr]v

irepiypd<pei,

^ovov

Tf'Aos ayat^cou rriu ridovrju,

Se T7)V

aXyri^6va,

(pvaioKoyiav

t')]]/

uxp^AifMOV eJvai XkytJiv rb frjTeij/

/cat

[ret?

"Otti Toi eV jxeydpoKTi Ka.K6u t'


hyaddv re rervKrai, which is also
told of Socrates and Diogenes.
Arist. Met. ii. 2, 996, a, 32:
&cre Sia ravra r&y ffoipicruv

fxadrj/JLaTiKas

ydp Tats 6.Wais

rals fiavavaois,
KoX

T^KTOVIKY)

r^" e/x^aivoAoyiKwu
Me5ia Try*' euxpTVcrrmv TjTrrotTO.
'koI KAetrd^axos
\4aypos Se
(paalu avrovs axpi?o'Ta r)ye7<rQoLi 76 re (pvaiKhv fxfpos koI rh
8ia\eKTiK6u. dvi/acrdai yapev Key^iv

ruv

Kcu

avrds

eTTicTTi^/ias] iv jjiif

iv. 5.
:

oiou ^ApicrTiinro^ TrpoeTrrjAa-

Ki(ou

oiov
8l6ri

aKVTlKTJ,

The same in Alex, on the passage Schol. in Arist. 609, b, 1


1078,
Ps. Alex, on Met. xiii. 3
Syrian
Ihid. 817, a, 11
a, 33
in Metaph. Arist. T. V. 814, b,
Compare the
6; 889, b, 19.
language of Aristippus in Diog.
Plut. Ed. Pr. 10, 7.
ii. 71, 79
2 According to the sense in
which it is understood, it is
equally true to say that they
set logic aside and that they
made use of it. See p. 347, 2.
Of what was afterwards called
logic, they appropriated just as
much as was necessary for their
theory of knowledge, but they
assigned no independent value
to it, nor did they extend their
study of it beyond what was
wanted for their purposes.
Conf. Sen. Ep. 89, 12 Cyrenaici naturalia cum rationalibus
sustulerunt et contenti f uerunt
moralibus, sed hi quoque, quae
removent, aliter inducunt.
;

GENERAL POSITION OF THE CYRENAICS.


however, knows of no happiness which does not immediately coincide with virtue, and thus makes virtue
the only object in

life.

U7
Chap.
XIV.

Aristippus, on the other hand,

considers only enjoyment an end in itself,

and only
pleasure an unconditional good,^ regarding everything
good and desirable only in as far as it is a
means to enjoyment.^ Both Schools therefore at the
else as

commencement diverge

very

in opposite directions,

their divergence, however, not preventing their subse-

quent approach to a greater extent than might seem


at first sight to be possible.

The ground thus occupied was worked out by


Aristippus and his pupils as follows.^

Perceptions,

(2) Feelthe
only object
in-/s

of know-

Aristippus in Xeii. Mem. ii.


i^avrhv tolwv totto) ets
1, 9
Tovs ^ovAofjLfvos ]7 paara re Kal
'

^Siarra fiioreveiu.

Cio. Acad. iv.


voluptatem sumbonum esse voluerunt

131

42,

mum

alii

quorum princeps
Ibid.

Fin.
87

Biof/.

ii.

6,

rjSopiiv

Aristippus.

18;

39;

13,

...

Kal

pus in mind will be presently

shown in- respect of the Philebus, and it is therewith proved


for the Republic, which refers
to the Philebus.
' Biog.
ii. 91

ayadhv

/xey

tV

^p6vr\(nv
Kiyovaiv. ov Si
:

eJi^ai

aWa

eavTTju 8e aipT7}v,

avTTJs irfpLyivo/xeya.

Slo,

92

rh e|

Kal rhy

t4Aos ehai, 88
i] tjSovt] Sl' avrr\v
alpeT-)] Kal ayaddu.
Athen. xii.

vAovTOv

644,a:['Api(rTt7r7ros] d7ro5e|a|Uej/05

116 Cyrenaici atque Annicerei philosophi nominati omne bonum in voluptate


posuerunt virtutemque censuerunt ob eam rem esse laudan-

tV

T]^vTTaQiiau ravrriv

Ka\

f<p-n

iv avrrj

PefiKrjaOai.

t^u

Emeb.

r4\os eiuai
evSai/jLOviav

1.

296,

c. p.

The same view is mentioned


and attacked by Plato, Gorg.
I.

491, E.

Rep.

vi. 505, B.

(See

above

p. 312,. 1), and Pliilebus,


B., where it is thus des-

II,

cribed
(hai
Kal

4>iA7?/3os fxfv To'ivvv

(pr](Ti

tV

ayaOhu

to x^'^P^^v iraai

(^wois

Kal Tepxpiu Kal

7]Sovr,i/

oaa

Tov yfvous eVri tovtou (Tvyicpwva,


Ibid. (iO, i).
TayaBhu iridfTu
'n^'iv 7]5oi/^v ehai iraaav Kal iravrtXri.
Tluit Plato had Aristip:

oil

5t'

be TToi-qriKhv rjdouris elyai

aurhi/ alperhv

Off. iii. 33,

oi^ra.

C'ic.

dam, quod efficiens esset volTo this sentence of

uptatis.

Aristippus,
28, and Ast
the Phffido,
reason.
It

Wendt, Phil. Cyr.


tlie passage of
68, E., but without
refer

refers

to

common

unphilosophical virtue.
^ The Cyrenaics divided
their
ethics into live parts.

Math.
TTfadai

11
T0VT0V5

vii.

Sejct.

Kahoi Trfpnpf.
ivioi vevofi'iKaaiv

ledge.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

348

Chap,
'

a change within ourselves, do not


supply us with the least information as to things in
beinsf

feelins^s of

We may

themselves.

be indeed conscious of having

a sensation of sweetness, whiteness, and so forth

but whether the object which causes the sensation


sweet, or white,

is

unknown to

is

One and the same

us.

thing often produces an entirely different effect upon


different persons.

How

then can we be sure, that in

any given case, whether owing to the nature of our


organism or to the circumstances under which we
receive the impression, things do not appear to us
entirely different

from what they are in themselves

Knowledge, therefore,

is

limited to our

own

feelings

we are never mistaken but of things


themselves we know absolutely nothing.^
Just
as to these

e| S}v rh 7]Qlkov ^laipovffiu eXs re

rhp

alpeTWf Koi (pivKT^v


Toirov KoX els rhv irepl tuii/ iraOcci/
Koi eri els rhv rrepl toov Trpd^ewu
Koi ^Stj rbv irepl loiv alrioo!/, Kal
reXevralov eh rhv Trepl rcou iriareuiw ev tovtois yap 6 irepX alriwv
Trepl twj/

T6'iros,<paa\v, 4k

tov

4>v(tlkov fiepovs

irvyxay^y, o 5e irepl iriffreuu eK


TOV AoyiKov. Sen. Ep. 89, 12
(according to what has been
said, p. 346, 2) in quinque enim
partes moralia dividunt, ut una
sit de fugiendis et expetendis,
altera de adfectibus, tertia de
actionibus, quarta de causis,
:

quinta de argumentis caus


rerum ex naturali parte sunt,
argumenta ex rationali, actiones ex morali. We cannot,
however, tie our faith to this
account, not knowing how the
subject was divided among
these several parts, nor how old
:

?
;

in
as

and universal the division is.


That it was not made by Aristippus may be gathered from
the statements as to his writings.
In the division irepl iriffTecau probably the theory of

knowledge was treated, and in


the preceding one the theory of
motion.
Cic. Acad. ii. 46, 143 aliud
judicium Protagore est, qui
putet id cuique rerum esse, quod
cuique videatur aliud Cyrenaicorum, qui prseter permotiones intimas nihil putant esse
judicii.
Ibid. 7, 20 de tactu,
et eo quidem, quem philosophi
interiorem vocant, aut doloris
aut voluptatis, in quo Cyren^

putant veri esse judiPhit. adv. Col. 24, 2, p.

aici solo

cium.
1120

\_ol

KvprjuaiKoll

t^

ira0rj

koI ras (pauraaias ev avrois Tidev-

res

ovk ^ovto rriv

a-rro

tovtwv

FEELINGS THE SUBJECT OF KNOWLEDGE.

349

do we know of the feelings of other


people.
There may be common names, but there are no
comlittle

vtffTiv

TcDy

elvai SiapKrj irphs

ras

uTrep

TvpayixaTuv

KaraPf/SatcCaeis,
&AA.' LiJTTfp iu KoXiopiiia rcbv eKrhs
aTToa-rdi/Tfs elsra irddrj

rh

avTOvs.

TO

5'

iarl

fxT}

ruv eKrhs

TTfpl

Kar^KK^Kxav

(pait/erai

riOe/xeuoiy

TrpoaaTro(paiy6/xi/oi
.

yAvKaiyeaOai

yap Xeyovcri Kal niKpalueadai Kal


(p(t}Ti(eaeai

Kal

aKOTovcrdai

rcvu

vadwy Tovruv eKoiffTOv Tr)i/ ^i (pyeiau


oiKeiay iv avT^ Kal anfpicnraaToi/
eXOfTOi ft Se yAvKv rh fieAi Kal
'

eaWos

iriKphs 6

vnh iroKXcou

k-.t.A.

ayTifiapTVf)e7<jdai

nal

Bripiov Kal
irpay/xdrui/ Kal dv9piLiv(av, twu jx^v

yXvKavdrivai, just as

a diseased
eye or a mad brain always sees
things different from what they
are.
outu Kal tj/jlcls ^vXo^wTarSu
irXeov

icrri

/UTjSev

rSov

olKeicou

Xa/ii^dueiv

individual impressions
must be said ndyra
rb. <paiv/)fiiva aXridrj
Kal
KaraXr)Trrd. If, on the contrary,
every
name means the thing by which
the impression is produced, all
<paip6(j.va are false and cannot
(paivSnei^a
(Trde-n),

it

be known.

Strictly speaking,
rh irddos T)fuv icni <paiv6Hevov rh 5' Ktos Kal tov irdOovs
fx.6vov

aTTOKaofxeucDV virh ttjs


X^^^-Cvs, Kal

TTOirjTiKhv -rdxa ^ueV

$\TrouTwy.
irddeaii/

tj

oOev
5(/|a

ndpTTjTou-

i/xfjLeuouaa

SiaTrjpe?

eK^aiuovaa

-rh

tols

ava-

Se

Kal
voXvirpay/uLOuovaa tcJ Kpiv^iv Kal
iLno<paivendai wepl tcDj/ eKrhs, avTr\v
Te -noXXduis Tapdacrei Kal fxdx^rai
TTphs erepous awh rwv avTwv
ivavTia -rradr} Kal diacpopovs (pavTacrias

XafiRdvouTas.

Math.

Sext.

vii.

who gives the most

19],

detailed
account, but probably to a great
extent jn his own language
(paalv uZv

01

KvprjuaiKol Kpirr}pia

flmi TO, Trddr] Kal fiSua KaraXa/x^avfaBai Kal dxpevara rvyxaj/eii/,

T^v

Se Tr(iroi7]K6TUV

KaToXrjinhv

(Ivai

a-Tov

'6ti

<pa(rl,

Kal

ra

7ra0r? /XTjSer

yap XevKaivoneea,
yXvKaCdfieOa, Swarhv

[x\v

^ yXvKv

a7ro0a(j/ea-0at.
^"^^

i(TTiv,

elKhs

ovx oUu t'


yap (an Kal

XfVHOv riua XevKavrtKus


haTidijpai Kal vnh ht) yXvKios
fJ.^

(paivofx^vop

?e

eVxij/

Kal

t]ix7v.

%v

ov

ravTTj

TTepl fxiv TO. irddr] rd yc


oiK^ia
irdures ia/xeu dirXavi7s, Trcpl Se rh
(Krhs vnoK^ijxevov irdvT^s irXavu)-

fieBa- KaKfTiva fx4u iari KaraX-qTrra,

rovTO Se aKaTdXT]TTruv, rrjs ^vxrjs


daQevovs Kaden-rcoa-qs irpos
^idyvwaiv aurov irapa tovs tottovs,
iravu

irapd

rd

Kivr)(T^is,

dXXas
Pyrrh.
re

SiaaTV/uLaTa,
irapd
tus
-napd rds jUerajSoAas, irapd

irafiirXridels

215;

i.

irddr)

KaTaX-qirrd,

avrd, ovK

93

ray

air'ias.

Dior/,

dXrjdfieiu.

d(p'

92

ii.

See
rd

eXtyov oZp
Ibid.

Sou yii/erai.

alaerjaeis

irdtn-ore

fxr}

Ibid. 95 of the School

of Hegesias, w^liich does not


in
this res})ect differ from others
:

ddid\pv-

yitTjSe

Xeyeiu aSiaxl/evarcos
'6ti
Se
rh ffxiroi7]TiHhv Tov irddovs X(vk6v
4(TTi

If,

we understand by

therefore,

Svaxipatydi/rwu [add Th fieu^ ruv


5e irpocriefxeycop tt)v OaXXiav, Kal
KaTa\pvxoiJ.i'wi' virh dtvov, Kal irphs
ftXlOV ajX^XvOOTTOVTCOV Kal vvktuio

iraQuv

SivaaOat.

avijpovv Se Kal rds

aKpi^ovaas

tV

ovk
Aris-

alcre-fjaeis

iiri-yvwaiv.

totle in Enft. Priep. Ev. xiv.


19,
e|^s S" tv eUu oi Xiyovres fiova
1
:

rd

irdOi]

e?7roj/

(VIOL

KaraXTjirrd.
TU)v

e/c

ttjs

tovto

S'

Kvp-^vrjs

(whicli in the face of tlie definite statements of Cicero, Plutarch ajid Sextus, does not prove

Chap,
XIV.

THE

350

Chap.
XIV.

moD

feelings,

S OCR A TIC SCHOOLS.

and when two persons say that they

them can be cerhave felt the same


tain that he has experienced the same feeling as the
other, since he is only conscious of his own state and
thing, neither of

not of that of another.^

Thus, like Protagoras,^ the Cyrenaics regard all


notions as relative and individual their view differ;

ing from his in this respect only that they refer


notions

directly to internal feelings,

more
^

out of sight

Heraclitus' doctrine of perpetual flow

that this doctrine did not belong to the whole School, nor
can this be intended. Conf c.
Ka.djxevoi yap eXeyou
18, 31)
.

/cat reixvSfxevoL

yvcopiC^iv,

'6ti -na-

ttSt^pou 5e rh Kouov ^1,ri


rh r4fxvov ai5r]pos ovk e^etv
Sextns, Math. vi. 53,

(TXoi^v Ti
irvp

t)

dit^7v.

says

irddr],

akXa

irdOos

ru)v

But
The Cyrenaics, we gather
this is

denied the existence of things,


but only our knowledge of their
This whole theory
existence.
probably belongs to the elder
Aristippus, as will be probable
from a passage in Plato soon to
be mentioned. Against Temieman's notion (Gesch. d. Phil. ii.
106) that it first came from
Theodorus, see Weiidt, Phil.
4.5.

Sext. Math. vii. 195

^vB^v

Koivhv
avdpciiivwv, ouSfxara Se KOLi'd TiOeadai

ouSe

Kpiri\pi6v

(f>a<n

eluai

\VKhu jxev ydp ri


yAvKu KaXovcri kolvws irdures,
KOivhv 5e Ti KfVKOV t) yXvKu ovk

rois Kpifiaffi.

Kal

kol

rdxo.

Tov

M yiveadai
inaccu-

tSiou

rh 5e et
XevKov iyyi-

t^

ovt^

TreAas,

avTh^ dvvarai Xiynv, /xr) dvah^x^'


fx^t'os rh rod ireXas trdOos, ovre 6
ireAas, firj di'adexoixuos rh iKeivov

5e

from the above, cannot have

Trddos dirh

avT(3

VTai

'dWo

virapKTwv.

Cyr.

TOVTO rh

fxoua

ol'crav

ydp rod

e/carTToy

crvyKlKpLfxai

vnapx^i-v to,
ovQ4v. oOev Ka>

irdOous TTotTjTi/cV,

rate.

X"V<TLU'

Trddovs dvriXaixfiaVf-rai.

(paalu

T'^i/ (j)wvrjv, ix^

and leave

e^ci^deu

ydp
ojs

iyu}

ovroo

jx\v

'S^vnaiuefrQai

Tvpoairi-movrcs,

virh

hrepos

Sh ovTOD Kar^(TKeva(rjx4v7}v exei rrjv


aiaQriffiv, &(rr

ir4p(as

Siarcdrivai,

in support of which the example


of a jaundiced or diseased eyesight is adduced. It follows

then

Koiud

ix\i>

yjfxas

ovofiara

riOeuai rocs irpdyiian, trdQi] Se 76


exeii/ 'i^ia.
-

Zeller's Phil.

d. Griech,

i.

869.
3

last point has been too


lost sight of by Schleier-

The

much

macher (Plato's Werke,

ii.

1,

who

considers the description of the Protagorean


teaching in the Theastetus to be
chiefly meant for Aristippus,
whose view does not absolutely
coincide with that of ProtagoSee W^e)idt, Phil. Cyr. 37.
ras,
On the other hand, the differ1

3),

ence between them

is

exagger-

j.

'

FEELINGS THE SUBJECT OF KNOWLEDGE.


as

something not wanted

for

their

purposes and

transcending the limits of human knowledge.'


If
knowledge, however, be confined to knowledge of
feelings, it follows on the one hand that it
would be
absui-d to seek for a

knowledge of things, such knowledge being once for all impossible; and thus
the
sceptical attitude assumed by the Cyrenaics in
respect
to knowledge, was the ground of their
conviction of
the worthlessness of all physical enquiries.^
On the
other hand, for this very reason feeling only can
give
ated by

the

Academician in

Cic. (see p. 348, 1),

who

ascribes
to Prota<joras a view entirely
different from that of the Cyrenaics, and by Eus. Pr. Ev. xiv.
19, 5, who after discussing the

Cyrenaics introduces Protagoras

with these words

eVeTat tovtois
ovv (Twef^eToicraL koI tovs tt;!/ ij/avriav ^adi^ouras, Koi Travra
XP^'0'
TriaTViv Ta?s tov crdfxaTos aiaOr]:

Hermann appeals,for they do not


make Protagoras more subjective than Aristippus, but Aristippusmore subjective than Protagoras. In the next place it is
not correct. Of course Protagoras did not deny that certain
names were used by all, he even

treated himself of the apddrris


ovofidruu (Zelle?''s Phil. d. Griech.
i. 933, 1), but what
is the use
a-fCTLu 6pi(TafA.4uov?, for
Protagoras of agreeing in names when the
only asserted the truth of all things differ
?
The Cyrenaics
perceptions in the sense that are only
more accurate than
they were all true for him who Protagoras
in asserting tl at
perceived them, that things perceptions
which are called by
were to each one what they ap- the same name
are not the same
peared to him to be. In this in ditferent
persons. But there
sense the Cyrenaics, as Sextus is no
disagreement in the teachhas rightly sliown, declared all ing of the
two.
to be true, but both they and
Had they acted consistently
Protagoras said nothing about they must have
regarded as such
objective
truth.
Hermann's every attempt at a natural exobjection here to Ges. Ab.
planation of our perceptions.
235, on the ground that ProtaWe must, therefore, not be misgoras was far more subjective led by
Pint. N. P. Suav. Vivi
than Aristipj)us, since AristipSec. Epic. 4, 5, p. 1069, so as to
pus presupposed an agreement attribute
to them the view of
iraongst men in describing their
Democritus about pictures and
mpressions, is still more at emanating
forms.
/ariance with the statements of
As Diflff. ii. 92 remarks.
picero and Eusebius, to which (See
p. 346, 1.)
'

351

Chap.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

352

Chap.
XIV.

the rule by which the aim of actions is determined


and their value tested. For things being only known

own

to us in our

feelings, the production of certain

that can be attained by action hence


the best thing for us will be what is most gratifying
Here from the Cyrenaic theory of
our feelings.^

feelings

is all

to

knowledge follow those ethical principles, which in


establish.
other ways also it was their main object to
(3) Pleasiire

and

pai)i.

All feeling, as Aristippus assumes, following Proexperitagoras, consisting in an emotion in him who

the motion be gentle, there arises a feeling


again
if rough and violent,^ of pain ; if
of pleasure

ences

it, if

Ka\ rrju Aeiav rris crapKhs Kivriffiv


rehos ihai Aeyei. Math. vii. 199 :

Sext. Math. vii. 199 audXoya


5e dvai SoKet to7s -jrepl KpLTT]piov
Xeyofi^vois Kara tovtovs tovs &vSpas Koi TO. TTepl TeAwj' XeySixeva
>

TCtiv

'

TO.

yap

8fc

irddcou

ra

fxev 'z^riv ri84a,

dXyeLvd, ra Se [xira^v.

That

these statements come, on the


yap ra irddr)
Si-^/cei
whole, from the elder AristipIbid. 200.
reATj.
appears to be established by
pus,
2 Emeb. Pr. Ev. xiv. 18, 32,
passages in the Philebus.
several
Aristippus
younger
the
of
says
Socrates
(p. 31, B.) has
After
on the authority of Aristocles
that pain consists
shown
there
eivai
/caTacrTaTets
e<pr)
yap
Tcets
in a violation, and pleasure in
irepl r^v r/pterepaj/ (XvyKpaaiv fxiav
rc^
a restoration, of the natural
ioiKulau
aXyovfxev,
fihv Ka9'
between the parts of
Kara da\a(rffav x^'MWi'' Irepoj/Se connection
he appends (p.
being,
living
a
Kv^ari
Aeiqy
rw
Kad' %v T]Z6iJLeQa,
What
question
the
D.)
42,
elvai yap Keiau Kii(poiJLOiovfJLeur]V
if neither of these
happen
would
irapa^aXovpicp
vqffiv T-r]U r/5oj/V
changes were to take place?
Se toIttjv
tt]v
XofjLevnv avefj-u)
The representative of the theory:
KaO'
fie(n\v (Ivai Karda-Tan-iu,
of pleasure having answered in a
ovT d\yov[Xv ovT rid6iJt.ea,ya\wV
by
Diog. ii. 86, way afterwards repeated
TrapairK-fiaiov ovcrav.
Plato, Rep. ix. 583, C, that in
of
thing
same
the
almost
says
case there would be neither,
the older Cyrenaic school 5yo this
nor pain, he continues
pleasure
t]^ovt}u,
Ka\
ir6vou
v(pi<rTavTO,
7rd0rj
Koi

ini,

ra

'

'

:j

tV M^''

Aeiai/ Kivr\(TLV

tV

KdWiar'

7]^ovf}U,

rhu 5e Tr6vou rpax^'^av KLUT^cnv.


Ibid. 89, 90: fxeaas re Kara(TTda-cis

[t]

asvofxaCov

ar]do/i.av

Sext. Pyrrh. i.
Kvp-nvaiKT) a7W7rj] rrjv

airoviav.

koi

215

^SorV

eln-es

aWa

yap, olfAM;

rode Aeyeis, ws aei ri rovruv


auayKa7ou 7)fx7u ffufx^alveiv, ws ot
auvs
aocpoi (paaiV aei yap dnavia

re Kal

Kdrai

the answer

is

Accordingly
modified to mean

ptTi.

PLEASUHE AND PAIN.

353

we are in a

state of repose, or the


motion is so
as to be imperceptible,
there is no

feeling either of

pleasure or pain.

of pleasure

weak

Of

these three states, only


that
absolutely desirable.

is

bears witness

all

Hereto nature
following pleasure as the
highest

end, and avoiding nothing


so carefully as pain,i
unless
indeed their judgment be

perverted by unfounded

fancies.^

To put freedom from pain

^hat great changes


produce
Pleasure and pain, but
small
ones neither. To the same

tion IS felt or
produces pleasure. Perhaps it is in
reference
to this that Arist.

view

comes back (on


vith the words apa
le

^v/c

6.KnHodp.iu,

<rTiv,

ovaia Be

Sourjs;

0V7 0U

p. 53, C.),

13,

-ncpl ^Sov9il

KaXm

oel

o{,k ((Tti

Ho/x^ol

rhu

Wveiu

ws

yap

A6yoi;

y4u^ais
ri^es

iirix^ipovai

i]^uv,

when

wrote the Philebus and


nee with the exception
of
nstippus no one is known to
horn they could be
referred
^rotagoras did not draw the
;

hical conclusions of his


prinmoreover this asrtion is universally

did not Aristippus say


VVeare atall times in a

ot gentle or violent
motion, but
pleasure or pain only
arises,

when we become

most pro-

this

id tlie

same

all
n.
-js

to

the remark, that


changes make no impres-

Likewise, Diog. ii. 85,


of Aristippus
t4\os S'

makes

r)]v

\dav

Kivnaiv

e/y

Ho^iv avaSiZoniv-qv,
accordino-

Which not every slight


ino

his

representative say,

though certainly not


without
some conversational help
'

I)iog.^^; 87; Plato,


Phil.

bee above

-iJ, i5.

'xpaivc

conscious of

motion ? Yet this is exactly


what he did say accordinto
Diogenes,
and what Plato

that both this passage

plies

state

attributed
the School of Aristippus,
ince too the epithet
i<ofx^\>hs

passage connected with


on the two kinds of
motion
a rest, are his. The

yiv^aiv

Nor can

Why

'

iible

V^ov-fju.

jecture that Aristippus


actiuired
from Plato the more
accurate
limitation of his
teaching.

ples), since

best, it is

tV

ala-d-hTTiv

lan-

;lato

him

r^fi rh

guage of Plato, p. 42, D.,


and
the statements which
attribute
to Aristippus the
assumption of
an intermediate state
between
pleasure and pain.
Hence we
cannot countenance the
con-

hat the assertion, all


pleasure
onsists in motion, had
been
ttered by some one else,

Its

Etb. N. vii.
says Sih koI o'v

a, 12,

we allow that there is a discrepancy (as SusemiJil,


Genet
Entw.d. Plat. Phil. ii.
35, note'
720 asserts) between the

av

oU Su xapiy ^x^iv.
latter words clearly prove

'hese

1153,

(payai eiuai

rh itapdirau

Si]

in the place of

"'

(parrt

Diog.
Ka\

aipeiadai

A A

ii.

tV
Kara

347 1
UvaadaL S^
vSou-fjy
riuas uh

8i>

p.

ha(rTpo(p-f]y

Chap.
XIV.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOL.

354
.HAP.
Chap.
>-iy-

for where there is no


pleasure would not be correct,
pam the
enjoyment is as little possible as

emotion,

as in sleep.'
condition being one of insensibility,

Thus

with what is agree-the good comes to be identical


is disagreepleasure ; the evil, with what

able-with

what affords neither pleasure nor


evil.^
pain can be neither good nor

able, or unpleasant

(4)

From

The

this

view

a matter of coiuse,
pleasure must, as such, be

it follows, as

that individual feelings of

'"i'"'^

Simple repose of mind, that


Epicurus at a later time
freedom from pain, in which

'

the ends of all actions.

cannot, for the reason just


placed the highest good,
appeared to the Cyrenaics
given,be this good.= It also
happiness of the whok
unsatisfactory to make the
view, and to
the point to be kept in

life

explicitstatementsprobablybeprincipally to
curus,

^ ff'.^M.

vii

oirep

^aeos

ij5o.^,s

dA7.5^.os.

^^-ri

'^'' 2
352,

8ee

p. 300, 1.

i?%-

Ateja^

cee
ii-

^f.^^^J/

39^

ai

sensus dulciter ac ]ucunde m(


qv
vetur ... nee Aristippus,

199- ra^ev

Kal

^.'/^

it the

^^^ voluptatem tm

HaKbv,

'

.cbooi

the

accomm^

make

p.

87

summum bonum p

^;;^^^fj^,^^^,^tes istam v
cuitatem doloris.

THE HIGHEST GOOD.


aim of mankind

sum

355

to procure for themselves


the highest

total of

enjoyments that can be in this life.


Such a principle requires the
past and the future as
well as the present to
be included in the pursuit,
neither of which are in our
power, and which certainly
afford no enjoyment.
A future feeling of pleasure is

an emotion which has not


yet begun a past one is
one which has already ceased.^
The one only rule of
life is to cultivate
the art of enjoying the
present
moment.
Only the present is ours. Forbear
then
to trouble for that which
is already past and
for that
what may never be yours.
;

Dioji.

87

5o/c6? S' ai-rols koX

Tf Aos ^hlaiixovias

5ia(l)peip.

tV

t^h yap dvai

KaTo.

V0ov7]u, (vSaifjLouiau 5e

fx4po<:

rh in ruv

fJ-epiKwu T)^ovSov (Tvarri/na.

ah

rruj/a-

pieunvvTai Ka\ al Trapcf^xVKvTai


Kal
Oi ^eA-Aouo-ai.
ehai re
fx.fpi-

tV

K^v
S'

rjhovT^v 5i' avT7}v alp^Trji/


evBaifj-oviau ov di avT-qv,

5ia ras

Kara

^i4pos ri^ovds.

'

r^v

aXha
89

oXXhix^i; ovdk Kara fxi'Tj/u-qv twv


ayadwu ^ irpooSoKiav r)hovT]v (paaif
airoTfXeloeai,
^Kovpcv,

birfp

ijpeaKeu 'Ettj-

iKKikadai yap tw ^p6uco


Kivinixa.
Ibid. 1)]':

rh TVS ipvxvs
!ap/C?5 Ktiv

Kara

filav [tjSoj/t/i']

Tis irpoa-irlirTovo-ap rjd4ws

inaudyr)
Idthen.xii. 544, a: ['ApiariT^irosj
i-ToSc^a^euos
r-ny

'Vv

rhv

Tf'Aos efi/at

fvdaifioviau

TjSvirddeiav lav-

Kal eV avri)

e</)7j

fi^^Krifrdai

Kal

iov6xpovov avr'qv dvai TrapaTr\nriusroTs aacoTois ovtc rr]u


y.urjixr)v
CO./ ycyouviwu
aTroAavaewu irphs

vrhu^ V-yGvfxiuos oi/Ve

ov

iaofxevojv,

yaehv

dAA'

tV

iul

ovK ^t'

r4\us

e'ATrtSa

rh 6

ovTTO) Kal

xiv. 6

&5n\ov
-wdw acpSBpa

eppufxeucos

(fKi \eyeiv 6 'Apiirapiyyvuv, fj.-f]r roTi


irapeXeodaiu iitLKaixvciv. /xr)re

ariinros,^

rwu

a.T^iovrwviTpoKdfjLVLv

5f?7^a rh roiovro,
yotas anoBei^is

W/pa T^u
TraAij/

T^y

;Ufpet

KaQ'

'

eudvLLias

yap

Kal '/Aew Sid-

irpoaerarre Se e>'

yvciifjLT]^

7]^l4pas

|;^6<j/

eV

Kal o5

e'/ce(V(y

tw

Kaaro5 ^ trpdrrL
Tt 77 eV/zoe?
fjidvov yap e^ao-zcej/
Vfi^repoi/ elvai rh iraphv, /xrjre
Se
rh (pedvou fxT]r^ rh TrpoaSoKcofx^uov
rh [x'^u yap anokwXduai. rh 5e
ddr]kou ehai eJfTrep iarai.
There
h

can
be no doubt that Aristippus
had already propounded these
views, his whole life presupposing them, and his other
views immediately Icadinoto
them, p. 852, 2. The precise'formularising of them may very
possibly belong to the
period
of Epicurus.

fxovw rh

Kplvocv ru> irdpovri, rh 6e


irokiKavK^vai Kal a-Kohava^iv
ov^v vofu^uy TTphs
aurhi^, rh /xh is

hu,

^lian. V.H.

Diof/.

66

['Apio-TiTTTToy]

aneXave juh yap

rjSofy^s

rcov Trap6v-

rwu, o^K (dvpa Se ttSvcv r^v


diroKavaiv ruv oii irapovrocv oO^v

A A 2

Kal

Chap.
XIV.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOL.

35(3

(Jhap.

^^1_

pleasure arises

in itself

is

whence the feeling of


unimportant. Every plea-

of the things

The character

there in this respect


and another.
any difference between one enjoyment
from opposite
They may spring from various, even
themselves, they are all
sources, but considered by

sure as such

alike,

one

is

is

a good, nor

as

good as the other, a pleasurable emo-

is

object of desire.^
tim, and as such always a natural
that there
The Cyrenaics therefore can never allow
by law and custom
are pleasures not only declared
In their
very nature.
to be bad, but bad by their
by a disreputable
view pleasure may be occasioned
nevertheless good and deaction, but in itself it is
sirable.^

several

(5)

Modi.

pedform
^''"
""'"
thin exof

treme
rien'.

received
At the same time this principle
its seventy was con-^
limitations by means of which
application restricted.
siderably toned down, and its

In the

place, the Cyrenaics could not

first

Aro7eV7,s iSattXtKb^

Kiva iX.'^ev

wheie the champion

of plea.

tarchus replies: ^Ss

^^ ^'

ZlZ''l^sy^pvBo.hy^V^ouv

yi.vra,M<Pva^u

\t'\k

riXys^ble

yap kyaOa

Ae'7e:.

^Ua

how

is

Z the^JTthe

worst pleasures

to

which Pro-

little will

Just as

13

Ae^s

^lotaicnus
^^^^^^Z:^'

of
mire answers the objection
SocraSs that goocl pleasures
from
,n'St be distinguished

Thid

deny that

allow that there is


imaginary pleasure and pain.
(36,

^5o.^

C.)

St'

-^|--

a{>7^u aiperv Ka\

To the same

^^^

ay aOjv.

effect is the pas-

sage quoted from the Philebus

on

p.

io^,

1.

CYRENAIC THEORY OF PLEASURE.

357

notwithstanding the essential likeness there were yet


differences of degree in feelings of pleasure: for

Chap.

__^^J'

allowing that every pleasure as such is good, it does


not follow that the same amount of good belongs to
as a matter of fact one affords more enjoyment
;
than another, and therefore deserves to be preferred
all

to

it.'

Just as

little

many enjoyments
greater pain

it

escape their notice, that

are only purchased at the cost of

They

therefore required

the
consequences of an action to be taken into account
thus endeavouring again to secure by an indirect

method the contrast between good and


they would not at first allow to attach

evil

which

to actions

An action should be avoided when therefrom more pain follows than pleasure hence a man
themselves.

of sense will abstain from things which


Diog. 87 says that the Cyrenaics denied a difference in
degrees of pleasure, but this is
'

undoubtedly a mistake. JDiog.


11. 90,
says that they taught
that bodily feelings of pleasure and pain were stronger

than mental ones. See p. 358, 3.


Pkito too, Phil. 45, A.
65 E.,
in the spirit of this School,
:

talks ot fieyi(TTai rtou rjSoyuu, nor


there the slightest reason
tor equalising all enjojTnents in
their system.
They could not
is

allow that there was an absolute difference of value between them, some being good
and others bad but they had
no occasion to deny a relative
aiiterence between the more or
less good, and they might even
;

hence they argue mibroken happiness

so hard to gain.^

is

did

con-

are

allow of different kinds of pleasure,

those of the body

mind

for

and

instance.

RiUer's
remarks on JJiog. ii. 103, do
not appear conclusive.
Just
as little can those of Wendt
(Phil. Cyr. 34, Gott. Aug. 1835,
789) be entertained.
According to Diogenes the Cyrenaics
only denied that anv object
taken by itself and independent ly of our feelings was more
pleasant than another
^ lHog. 90
Sib [?] kuI Kaff ain^v
a/per^s o^(n]s ttjs t)Uv7is ra noi-q:

riKh.

\6.kis

iviwv

^Sova,v

ox^mh

iuaunoOadat- iy

rarou avTo7s cpaiueaQai


a/^hu ru^u v5ouu,u
oOi^rwy.
bee t"
p
'

iro\.

Swcr/coAci-rhv

adpoi-

{j5aifioi>lai^ ttoi-

355

1
>

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOL^.

558

Chap.
XIV.

demned by the laws


Lastly,

of the state and public opinion.*

they also directed their attention to the

and mental

bodily

between

difference

pleasures.^

Holding bodily pains and pleasures to be more pungent than those of the mind ^ perhaps even attempt;

ing to show that

all

pleasure and

its

opposite are in

conditioned by bodily feelings;*

the last resource

Srepov 5e rh riBeffOai inreXd/x^avov


iivai.
(x-qUv
Diog. 93
o6V Kal irAeioya o'lKovofxiav irepi
KaKhv
al<TXP^v,
7)
dUaiov
^
^vffei
the value of every action de- 6drepov iiroiovpro.
* This is indicated by the expending on the pleasure which
above
follows it, aKXa vofxcp Koi eGet, pression oiKeidrepov in the
2.
See
359,
also.
p.
passage
&TOTrov
ovbi^
b ix4uT0i a-TTOvdaios
To say that not all pleasure and
7rpa|ei 5ia t^s 7rtKet;aeVas C''?^'*^^
Wendt (Phil. Cyr. pain is connected with bodily
Kal BS^as.
statement in states, may be harmonised
this
calls
25)
taking
question without reason. It is with this statement by
that not
meaning,
their
be
it
to
Aristippus,
in
consistent
quite
every feeling has its immediate
and is met with in Epicurus
object in the body, without,
is
he
but
&c.
Stoics,
Zeller,
remote
right {Ihid. 36, 42) in reject- however, denying more

ing Schleiermacher's hypotheii. 2, 18),


sis (PI. W. ii. 1, 183
that in the Gorgias Aristippus
is being refuted under the name
of Callicles, and in the Cratylus 384, Diogenes under that
;

of Hermogenes.
2

Which,

strictly

speaking,

they could only have done by


saying that one portion of our
impressions appears to us to
come from the body, another
not; for they had long since
given up all real knowledge of
things.

But their consistency

hardly went so far as this.


3 Diog.
ttoAu jx^vtol
90
ii.
:

ras (roo/xariKas afx^ivovs eJvai Koi ras oxA'^Jo'ets X^'P*^"^


ras (ToijfiariKas oQ^v koI ravrais

Tcov

;|/uxt/ccDi/

'

KoXa^^aQai [xaWov
poyras.

roiis afxaprd-

(The same, Jii^.x. 137.)

jfoAeTTwrepoj/

yap rh

irovilv, oiKei.'

connection between such feelings and the body. Joy for one's
country's prosperity might in
their minds be connected with
the thought that our own happiness depends on that of our
country. It can only be considered an opponent's exaggeration for Paneetius and Cicero
to assert that the Cyrenaics
made bodily pleasure the end
ac
(See p. 354, 3.)
of life.
Acad. iv. 45, 139 Aristippus
quasi animum nullum habea^
mus, corpus solum tuetur. Th(,
highest good Aristippus de,
clared consists not in bodih,
pleasure, but in pleasure gene
:

rally.

If

he regarded bodil;

pleasure as the strongest, an<


in this sense as the best, it b
no means follows that he ea
eluded mental pleasures froi

CYRENAIC THEORY OF PLEASURE.

S59

they nevertheless contended that there must be a


something besides sensuous feelings, or it would be

how unequal impressions

impossible to explain

produced by perceptions altogether alike

for instance, of the sufferings of others,

a painful impression

real, gives

the

Chap.
-^^-

are

sight,

they are

if

only seen on the

if

They even allowed that


and pains of the mind which have

stage, a pleasurable one.^

there are pleasures

no immediate reference to any states of the body.

The

prosperity, for instance, of our country

with as

much

our own.^

pleasiu-e as does

therefore pleasure

is

in general

made

fills

us

Although

to coincide with

the good, and pain with evil, the Cyrenaics are far

from expecting happiness to result from the mere


satisfaction of animal instincts.
For a true enjoy-

ment of

you not only need to weigh the value


and the consequences of every enjoyment, but you
need also to acquire the proper disposition of mind.
life,

The most essential help


not only because

which

is

it

never at a

loss for means,"* but,

to

the idea of good.


Indeed, his
remarks respecting the value
)f prudence make this probable.
see neudt, 22.
x4yov(TL Se yurjSe
iJioff.
90
cara \\/i\i}i/ rrjv Upairiu
r^v olko^v
Y'tpea-dai TjSovas, ruu yovv iii^iovUvuv 6pT]vovs Tjdeuis aKovofifv,
uv 54 kot' dA7)0iai/ arjScos. The
;ame is found in Mat. Qu.
'

y)

Jonv.

v. 1, 2, 7,

p.

)elono:s Cic. Tusc.


'^

Liog. 89

674.
ii.

is

prudence,^

supplies that presence of

how

3ause it teaches

to a pleasant life

Here

13, 28.

ov irdcras nivroi

make
tos

mind

mainly, be-

a proper use of the

y\ivxi^Ka.s

7]doms koI a\yr}56vas

eVi awfxariKols 7]Sot/a7s kuI aAyrjS6jl yheadai


Kal yap iirl \Pi\f)

Tf;s

T17

ttJ tSi'a

iraTpiBos

ciirj/xepia

Si(nrfp

x^P-^ iyyiveadai.

See p. 347, 2.
See the anecdotes and proverbs in JJioff. (JS 73 79 82,
and what Galen. Exhort, c. 5,
^

i.
8, K., and Vitruv. vi.
Pnef. i., say of his shipwreck.
Conf. Exc. e Floril. Joan. Damasc. ii. 13, 138.

vol.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS,

BO

(^AP.

good things of

life

freeing from the prejudices and

L_ fancies which stand in the way of success, such as


envy, passionate love, superstition

preserving from

regret for the past, from desire for the future, from

dependence on present enjoyment and guaranteeing


that freedom of soul of which we stand in need would
;

we

moment

at every

rest

contented with our present

lot.3

Hence the

mind is urgently
advocated by these philosophers,"* and philosophy in
cultivation of the

particular pointed to as the


life.^

They even

way

to a truly

human

assert that therein lies the essential

condition of happiness; for although

mankind

are'

too far dependent on external circumstances for the


wise

man

man

be invariably happy, and the

to

invariably miserable,^ yet as a rule so

foolishi

Nor

it is.

^ Bemetr. (Elocut. 296) mentions as an ^Mostov \6yov'Api<TTLTnre7ov '6ri ol 'duOpwiroi. xp^f^aTa

pus in Biog.

fieu aiTokelirova-i rols Traialv iiricr-

e Floril. Joan. Damasc. ii. 13,


146) as the author of the saj'ing, which Cic. Rep. i. 2 Plut.
adv. Col. 30, 2, p. 1124, attribute to Xenocrates, that the,
conduct of the philosopher
would remain the same, supposing all laws to be abolished.;
" Biog.
91 apioKH 5' aiirots
ju^re rhv (ro<phv irdura ^Seojs 0y,
irdvra
nijre
<pavKov
iirnrdyooSy
dWa Kard rh irKela-rov. In the:

Trifxr^v

Se

ov avvaTroXciTrova-i

Xpv(J^ofx4v7jv avTols.

See

is Socratic.
2

Biog.

t^u

The thought

91

p. 141, 2.
Thv aocphv

ix-i]Te

(on
point compare the Ianguage used by Aristippus respecting his relations to Lais)
^ Seto-iSatjUoj/Tja-etj/, whereas he is
not preserved from fear and
sorrow as being natural consequences.
^ See p. 355, 2.
* Many
expressions to this
(pQovhffeiv fiijTc ipaa6i](ra6ai

this

on record, particularly those of Aristippus, Biog.


ii. 69, 70, 72, 80.
Plut. Frag,
9, 1, and comment, in Hes.
5
See the saying of Aristipeffect are

72 Pint. Ed.
also mentioned
Diogenes ii. 68 (Conf. Exc.

Pu. 74.

by

He

ii.

is

same way the Cyrenaics would


not deny that the &(ppoves were
capable of
certain virtues.1
Probably this was only expressly stated by later members of the School in agreement with the Cynics and
Stoics.

PRACTICAL LIFE OF CYRENAICS.

361

this a departure

from the fundamental principle of


the School, the pursuit of pleasure,
but certainly
is

Chap.
^^^-

something very different has come of it from


what
might at first have been expected.
Herewith agrees all that is further known

c. Prac-

the views and conduct of Aristippus.

^^"^^^

'

as to

thought

His leading

^'/f

comprised in the adage, that life offers tmics:^'


most to him who, without ever denying
himself a
is

pleasure, at every

moment continues master of him-^


and his surroundings. The Cynic freedom
from
wants is not his concern. Prudent enjoyment
he says V
self

a greater art

is

than abstinence. He lived not only


comfortably, but even luxuriously.^ A
good table he
enjoyed,3 wore costly clothing,-^ scented
himself with
perfumes,^ and caroused with mistresses.^
Nor were
>

StoK

n^ov-ns

Floril. 17, 18

ovx 6

/cpareZ

airex6f.,uos, aX\' 6

according to Alexis; Ibid, viii


343, according to Soter Timon
:

Xfx^H-^'^os f..u

nTap,K<pep6f.epos

firj

'^^7'^'^'"^^^^

.
-^^^^^'^;J^=
VrTa(rdai
tjSouuv Kpariarou, ov rh

'*2^Zf"M
' Xen. Mem.

in

Dioff.

ii.

(i6

Ibid.

ii.

40; Lvcian. V. Auct


Clemens, Piedao- ii ije

iv.

69
12'

^'^^Pr.Ev.xivri8,31;4n^A:

.
.
already
Exp. Fid. 1089 A.; Steelefxi.
calls nim aKoKaffToripcos xovTa
41 71.
irphs T^ roiadra [irphs imdv^lav
'
See the anecdotes in Dion
apuTOv Kal iroTov Kal \ayveias^, ii. e6,
68, 69, 75 76
3tc He says himself then.
* Max.
1, 9,
Tyr. Diss, vii 9
'
that his object IS t) ^aard n Kal Lucian,
I. c.
Ibid. Cic. Ace 23
^biara fiioreveiu
and Socrates Tatia/i adv. Grac. c 2 Tert
isks whether he depended for
Apol. 46
lis homelcssness on
^ That
the cirhe made use of fra,
mmstance that no one could grant perfumes, and
defended

1
ii. 1, 1,

'

Ike to have him even as a


lave / ris yap hy iOeXoi &vepooTTov
V oiKia

^hu fx^Sh
yeAoz/ra, ry Se iroXvreA^ardrv
ialTT, xcipoura;
this picture
^^i^^wa;*^s iore deeply
!.f
oloured by later writers, and
ertainly not without exagge'ex^iu iTov,7u

atiou. bee Atheii. sii. 544,

6, e.

this practice, is told by Seneca,


Benef vii. 25, 1
Clem Pad
ii. 176 D., 179 B.,'
Z>i-fl<7. '76, all
.

apparently

from

the

same

source, the others mentioned bv


Stein, 43, 1, probably doini
likewise.
His relations
to Lais are

well known.

Hermesianax

in

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

362

Chap.
XIV.

the means neglected by which this mode of life was


rendered possible. On the contrary, he argued that
you.
the more of these you possess, the better for
Riches are not like shoes, which when too large can
He accordingly not only demanded
not be worn.^

but did not hesitate


this purpose to
to "^enrich himself by means, and for
submit to things which any other philosopher would

payment

for his instruction

have considered below his dignity.^


Athen.

xiii.

599, b, 588 c

173 Lact. Inst. iii. 15. A few


other stories of the same kind
may be found, Diog. 67 69
;

81

iv. 40.

Stol. Floril. 94, 32.

See

fear of

found in StoT). Floril. 3, 46,


and in a somewhat different
connection, Diog. 70 and 81.
Yet Svhleiei'viacher on Plato's

is

xii.

Cic. ad Fam. ix. 26


544, b, d.
Plut. Erot. 4, 5, p. 750 Diog. 74,
85 Clemens, Strom, ii. 411, C.
Theod. Cur. Gr. AfC. xii. 50, p.
;

The

p. 339, 5.

Here belong many of the


anecdotes which relate to Aris3

stay at the court of


Dionysius. According to Diog.
77, Aristippus is said to have
announced to Dionysius, on his
arrival, that he came to impart
what he had, and to receive

tippus'

what he had not or, according


to a more probable version,
Ihid. 78, when he wanted in;

struction he used to go to Socrates for it, now that he


wanted money, he had come to
Dionysius. To the same person,
too, according to Diog. 69, his
remark was addressed that the
reason why philosophers appeared before the doors of the
rich, and not the contrary, was
knew
philosophers
because
what they wanted, whilst the
rich did not. The same story

Kepublic, vi. 489, has no business to refer this passage to


this remark, because of Arist,
Rhet. ii. 16, 1391, a, 8, but he
is quite right in setting down
the Scholiast who wished to
attribute the remark of Socrates to Aristippus. Of the liberal
offer made by Dionysius to
Plato, he remarks in Plut. Dio.
19 aa^aXSiS /j-ey a\6\pvxoi^ eli/at
avTOLS iJ.v yap fXLKpb.
AiovixTLov
:

Sidouai TTKeiSvctiV

dioix^uois,

XlAdr

r-oWa jU7]5ei/ Xafx^duovri.


Dionysius at first refusing to,
give him any money because
the wise man, on his own showing, was never in difficulties,
he replied, Give me the money
this once, and I will explain to
you how it is; but no sooner
hadhe got it, than he exclaimed,
Ah was I not right ? Diog.
82, Diog. 67, 73, and Athen. xii.
544, tell further, on the authority of Hegesander, that once
having been placed at the
bottom of the table by Dionysius because of some free expression, he contented himsell

TUi/i Se

PRACTICAL LIFE OF CYRENAIC8.

303

death too, from which his teaching professed to deliver,


was not so fully overcome by him that he

Chap.
XIV.

could face danger with the composure of a Socrates.^


It would, nevertheless, be doing Aristippus a
great

him an

injustice to consider

ordinary, or at

most a somewhat more intellectual pleasure-seeker.


Enjoy he will, but, at the same time, he will be

He

above enjoyment.

possesses not only the skill of

adapting himself to circumstances and making use of


persons and things,^ not only the wit which is never at
with remarking, To-day, this

is

the place of honour which he

Another time he is
said to have taken it quite
assigns.

quietly

when Dionysius

spat in

fisher-

his face,

observing

man must put up with more


moisture, to catch even a smaller

Once, when begging a favour for a friend, he fell at the


feet of Dionysius, Diog. 71), and

fish.

when reproached

for so doing.
Wherefore, he asked, has Dionysius ears on his legs ?
It is a
lommon story that Dionysius
Dnce asked him and Plato to
ippear dressed in purple Plato
refused to do so, but Aristippus
icceded with a smile. Sext.
Pyrrh. iii. 204, i. 155 Diog. 78
:

Siiid.

i6

'Apio-r.;

Stob.

Floril.

5,

Greg, JVaz. Carm. ii. 10,


the latter unskilfully
places the incident at the court
of Archelaus.
Stein, 67.
The
observation in Diog. 81, is likewise referred to Plato, that Jie
;

324:

He

ests.

flatterer
sius, by

is

represented as a

and parasite

of DionyLucia n V. Aut. 12;


Parasit. 33, Bis Accus. 23 Men.
;

13.

See Diog. 76 at the same


the Cyrenaics consider
fear to be something natural
and unavoidable. See p. 360, 2.
^ On the occasion of a storm
at sea he was charged with displaying more fear than others,
notwithstanding his philosophy, to which he adroith' replied oh yap Tvepl o/ioias ^vxvs
'

time

ayoiviujx^v aficporepoi,

Gell. xix.
ix.
3

Diog. 71 ;
10; ^lian, V. H.

20.

Diog.

apiLLocraaOai

KoX

1,

66

^v

koI tSttco

iKavhs

koI

xP^^V

Traaav ncpiaraaiu
ap/xobiws vTTOKpivanOai 5ib Koi irapa
Aiovvaicc tcov
&A\wy eu5oi,uet
Trpo(Ta>Trct},Kal

IxaWou, del rh irpocrneahv


Siaridefxevos. A few instances of this

have been already seen


Here, too, belongs
what is told by (ralen. and Vi-

skill

(p. 362, 3).

allowed himself to be abused


by Dionysius for the same

truv.

reasons that others abused him


a preacher of morals after all
is only pursuing his own inter-

having suffered shipwreck, and


lost everything, he immediately
contrived in Syracuse or Rho-

(see p. 340), that after

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.


Chap,
XIV.

a loss for repartee,^ but he possesses also calmness of

mind and freedom

of spirit, which can forego pleasure

without a pang, bear


with what

it

His maxim

is

loss

with composure, be content

hath, and feel happy in any position.


to enjoy the present, leaving care either

for the future or the

past,

des to procure an ample supply


Further, it is
of necessities.
stated in Plutarch, Dio. 19,
that he was the first to notice
the growing estrangement between Dionysius and Plato. In
Dioff. 68, he answers the question, AVhat good he has got
from philosophy, by saying:

and under

dish of
avu iyu

fish

all

bpas

circum-

ovv

on

aXKa av ffi\apAnother time he argues


yvpos.
that if good living were wrong,
it would not be employed to
honour the festivals of the gods.
Another time, when
Ibid. 68.
some one took him to task for
his good living, he asked him
rh Svvarrdai iraai dappovvrojs Oju-iX- to dinner. The invitation being
ciu
and Bioff. 79, relates that accepted, he at once drew the
when brought as a captive be- conclusion that he must be too
fore Artaphernes, some one stingy to live well himself.
When Dionysius
76.
asked him how he liked his Tbid.
situation, to which he replied, offered him the choice between
that now he was perfectly three mistresses, he chose them
at rest. Well-known is the all, with the gallant observaanswer which he is reported to tion, that it had been a bad
have given to Diogenes (which, thing for Paris to prefer one oi
however, is told of others), three goddesses, but bade them
Ibid
etTrep yjSeis
all farewell at his door.
Diofj/. vi. 58, ii. 102
When attacked for his re^
67.
avdpJoirois 6fiiX7u, ovk tt.v Xdxo-i'OHor. Ep. i. lations to Lais, he answerec
Dio(/. 68
cTTAuj/es.
with the well-known x ko
Valer. 3IaxAv. 3, Ext. 4.
17, 13
See p. 362, 1 363, 2. In a OVK %x^P--'-' The same relatioi
similar way he could defend is said to have given rise t<
d\^0(pd'yos,

his luxuriousness. When blamed


for giving fifty drachmae for a
partridge, Aristippus asked if
.

he would have given a farthing


The reply being in the
for it.
afiirmative I, said Aristippus,
do not care more for fifty
drachmse than you do for a farthing.
Bioff. 66, 75 or with a
different turn in Athen. viii.
343, c, where the story is told
pi him and Plato apropos of a
;

it was all th
same to him whether the hous
in which he lived had bee:
occupied by others before h

other light jokes

did not care whether a fish likev


him, if he liked the fish. Th
Cynicism is betrayed by tb
anecdotes in Diog. 81, p. 34".
4, although they are not othei
wise at variance with Grecia'
morals.

PRACTICAL LIFE OF CYRENAICS.


stances to keep cheerful.

365

Come what may, there is


a bright side to things,^ and he knows how to
wear
the beggar's rags and the robe of state with
equal
^

grace.3

Pleasure he loves, but he can also dispense


therewith.^
He will continue master of his desires.*
His temper shall not be ruffled by any risings
of

Some importance

passion.^

is attached to riches,
but hardly any independent value,^ and therefore
the

want of them

felt.
He is lavish of them
because he does not cling to them.^
If necessary, he
can do without them,^ and is readily consoled
for

never

is

See pp. 355 and 360.


Hot.
Ep. i. 17, 23 omnis
\
Aristippum decuit color et sta'

tus at res,
fere,

ie

tentantem majora

prfesentibus .-equum. Plut.

Vit.

Horn.

150:

B.,

'A^fo--

Ti-n-nos KcCi

irepiaKOL irSvois avurjve-

IXP^aaTo.

Uioff.66. p! 163, 3;

355, 2.

said

.3

lim

See p. 360, 2 & 3. Plut.


N. P.
Suav. V. sec. Epic. 4, 5, p. 1089
:

KvpT)vaXKa\

01

According to Z>%. 67, Plato


to have remarked to

'

a saying of the same kind


which Aristippus uttered on
paying a visit to his mistress,
to the effect that there was no
need to be ashamed of going
there, but there was of not
being able to get away.
tells

aol fiSvcv dcborai Kai

PfpcLv Kal ^(XKos.

xAaviSa

The same

re-

acppodiaiois
(pwThs,

birws

TO.

)urple

Kis amKa'iri

Plut.

Virt.

way

Alex.

p.

8,

330:

ApiaTLirirou daujxd^oixai

^ariKhv

'6tl

Ai\T)a'ia

rhv Sw/cKai TpifiwvL Kircf koX

x^o-H-^^t-

H<\>OTfpwv

iT-npei

XP^^I^^^os

ri

5i'

(vnxvH-oi',

.nd Ilor. Ep. i. 17, 27, on which


)assage the Scholiast tells how
\.ristippus carried off

the suroat of Diogenes from the bath,


raying Ids purple cloak intead, which Diogenes refused

wear at any

price.

Liog. 67, p. 363,

'

^X ovK

ixo/^ai.

4.

nio(j.

ov^i

u/xiXe7}/

etSuXa

t^v

t'os

7)

rrpd^ews

rrjs

oi/^ews

Sidi/oia

iroWd-

Slo.

Cpe^iy.

The same

of thinking is expressed in
his definition of pleasure as a
gentle motion of the mind. The
storms of passion would change
this gentle motion into a violent
one, and turn pleasure into pain.
'

See
See

p. 347, 1

and the story


that he bade his servant who
was carrying a heavy burden
of gold cast away what was too
mucli for him. Ilor. Serm. ii
3, 99
IJwf/. 77.
' Finding himself
on board a
^

69,

^ilv
/uLerh
(tkotos irpod/j.4vovs

avaKaixfioLvovaa
evepycis eV avTij

and not the story of the


dress, is referred to by

nark,

oUvrai

aWa

IJ.7]

p. 363, 4,

Chap.
XJV.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

366

Chap.
XIY.

their

To him no

loss.^

appears

possession

more

valuable than contentment,^ no disease worse than

He

avarice.^

lives

an easy

life,

but he

is

not on that

account afraid of exertion, and approves of bodily


exercise.

His

'^

that of the flatterer, but he

is

life

often expresses himself with unexpected

candour.^

and hence will


neither rule nor be ruled, nor belong to any community, being unwilling to forfeit freedom at any

Freedom he esteems above

price.

"^

pirate

he threw his
into the sea with the

vessel,

money
words
rnrwov

&ix^ivov

diet

r)

ravra

raiira

5i'

'Apia-

'AplcXTiinrov

Diog. 77

airoXeffOai.

Cic. In-

ii. 58,176; Alison. Idyl. iii.


13 Stoh. Floril, 57, 13, taking
care to read with Menage and

vent,
;

Stein, p.

39,

rh

for

ap-yvpiov

InPM.Tranq. An.8,p.469,

Aristippus having lost an estate,


one of his friends expresses
sympathy with him, upon which
Aristippus replies Have I not
now three estates, whilst you
have only one ? Ought I not
rather to sj-mpathise with you ?
:

ii.
p. 365, 2, Biog
&pi(TTa vTreridero irj 6v-

Hor. see

72

yarpl

* Several free expressions of


his towards Dionysius are told
by Biog, 73, 77 Stob. Floril.
;

Naz. Carm.
voh ii. 430 Codd.;
not to mention the anecdotes
49, 22

TCI

^Rprjrrj,

awaaKccu

avrriv

rod irXeiouos eivai.


Hence the same story in Ep.
8ocrat. 29, the compiler of this
late and miserable counterfeit
not having used the earlier
genuine letters to Aret. menvTrepoiTTiKiiu

tioned by Suid 'Apiar.


^ See further details in Plut.
Cupid. Div. 3, p. 524.
^
See p. 365, 2, Biog. 91 tt)v
:

(jo^jxaTiKTiv

irphs apeTv)s

&(rKr)(nv crvfx^dW^crOai
a.ya.A.rixl/ii'.

conf

G7'eg.

10, 419,

ii.

in Biog. 75, repeated Ihid. vi.


32 Galen. Exhort, ad Art. c. 8,
:

i.

18, k.

On

the principle mentioned


i. 1,
18 nunc in
Aristippi f urtim prgecepta relabor, et mihi res, non me rebuf
subjungere conor. According
to the context, however, th(
principle should not be confined to Aristippus' relationst<
outward possessions. Here, too
the saying belongs Plut. ii
Hes. 9,"" vol. xiv. 296, Hu. (Tw/a
^

ay ^ihs.
>

all things,^

by Hor. Ep.

fiovXov

Se7a9ai

Trpoaaire7y.
^

Xefi.

x^ipdv elvai
Conf. p. 363, 3.

rO'

Mem. ii. 1, 8. In repl;


who asked whethe

to Socrates,

he considered himself amonj


the number of those who rule
or those who are ruled, Aris
tippus states: 67017' ov5" o\wsy
TctTTCo i/xairhv et9

ttjj/

raiu ^PX^^

For, as is ex
plained here and p. 17, there i
no man who is more trouble
fiovXofxevuv rd^iu.

than a statesman

ifiavrhv roi

PRACTICAL LIFE OF CYRENAICS.

367

did he allow himself to be restrained by


religious considerations or traditions.
have at
Still less

We

least every reason for asserting this

personally,

and of

bably the

first

his School.

both of Aristippus

Theodorus was progain notoriety for his wanton


attacks on the popular faith; 2 still a connection
between the Cyrenaic philosophy and the insipid
to

rationalism of Euemerus^

ought

it

make

life

ovdh eis

TT/;/

rarrco

aAA'

SovAday av ifxavrhv

TOVTCov

ehai ris
dShs, %v

/xol

So/ce?

ireipcvfxai

^aSi^eiu,

uvre

5i'

dpyf/y oijre dia

SovAeias,

aWa

5l'

eAevdepias,

fiaXicrra

irphs

ev^aijxoviau

rjTrep
ct.-yei.

And after further objections:


aAA' iyd) rot, 'Iva /xi] Trdcrxcc ravra
noKiniav ijxavrhi/ KaradAAd ^evos irai/rayov elfj.i.
Quite in keeping with this
homeless life is the language
used by Aristippus, according
oy5' els

K\eio},

to Teles in >Stob. Floril. 40,


8,
ii. 69, Mein., that to him it
was of no moment to die in his
CJountry; from every country
the way to Hades was the same.
vol.

His address

to

Dionysius in

Stab. Floril. 49, 22, is also quite


in harmony with Xenophons

iescription

lught
shake
sease.
-0

live

from
oft'

from

far

certain.

Nor

easy not only for himself, but also for

When Socrates met this by observing that those who rule are
better off than those who are
ruled, he rejoined dAA.' iyco roi

is

to be forgotten, that Aristippus strove


to

vvv rdrrco e? rohs $ov\ofx.evovs rj


P^ffTo. re Kol T^S^rra
Bioreveii/.

/ieVrj

Had you

learnt

me,

would

you

despotic rule as a di-

Being obliged, however,


under some form of ^ro-

vernment, a good one is naturally preferable to a bad one


;
and accordingly the saying
attributed

to

Floril.

18,

him

in

Stob.

touching the
difference between a despotic
and a monarchical form of government has about it nothing
improbable.
Nevertheless, at
a later period Aristippus may
have relaxed his views on civil
life to a certain extent. At any
rate he formed a connection
with a family with which he
would previously have nothing
to do. Certainly Dioff. 81, proves
nothing. Seep. 341, 4.
It was a natural consequence of their scepticism, that
they followed Protagoras in his
attitude towards religion; and
49,

'

by means of their" practical


turn that freedom from religious prejudices was decidedly
promoted, which they especially

required

man.

Dior/.

in

the

wise

91, see p. 360, 2.


Strom, vii. 722, D.

Clemens,
says more generally that 'they
rejected prayer.
2 Particuhirs of
this below.
^

See

p. 843, 5.

Chap.
XIV.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

368

Chap.
XIV.

man-

Possessed of pleasing and attractive

others.

an enemy of vanity and boasting,^ he could


comfort friends with sympathy,^ and bear injuries
ners,^

He

with calmness.*

could avoid

anger ,^ and conciliate an offended friend.'^


extraordinary spectacle to his thinking

have been a virtuous

man

in the midst of the vicious

shown by

his opinion is

may

It

therefore be

mitigate

strife,^

The most
is

steadily pursuing his course


;

and that such was

really

his reverence for Socrates,

that he congratulated

true,^

himself on having become, thanks to Socrates, a


capable of being praised in

word, with

all

his

to

said

love

all

good conscience.

man
In a

of enjoyment, Aristippus

the name which


Greg. Naz. 307, gives him, and

*
5

Pint. Prof, in Virt. 9, p. 80.


Diog. 70 Stoh. Floril. 19, 6.

Ihid. 323, he commends him for


rb eu xdpiaToy rov rponov Koi (XTpcc-

Stoh. Floril. 20, 63.

7]^L(rros is

fivXov.
^

Khet. ii. 23;


See also p. 363, 3.

Arist.

See

Diog. 71, 73.

3 Athe/i. V.
H. vii. 3. mentions a letter of sympathy addressed to some friends, who
had met with a severe misfor-

quotes from the introduction the words: dA\'


iycoye rjKu irphs vjut-as ovx ws
(XvKKvnovixevos vfuv,aKX'

'Iva iTavffo}

In theory,
Aristippus could only estimate
the value of friendship by its
utility, as Epicurus did at a
tIv <piKov
later time. Diog. 91
rris XPf's '(Ev^Ka^ Koi yap u4pos
AuTTou/xeVous.

o-wixaros,

H-^XP^^

"*'

'^'^PV^

aaira-

Something similar is
also found in Socrates, see pp.
151, 3 222, 3 and he employs
the same argument Xe>i. Mem.
C^a-dat.

i.

See the adventure with


^schines in Pint. Coh. Ira. 14,
p. 462, Diog. 82, which Stoh.
Flor. 84, 19, probably by mis'

take, refers to the brother of


Aristippus.
Stoh. Floril.
37, 25: 'hpi(TTtTTTTos ipcoTTjOelsri

a^io6avixaar6v

He

tune.

bfjius

i,

2, 5-1.

koI ixirpios,

elire,

on

['o?

or

'6(rTis1'\

eV 7r,)A\oij vTTdpx<^v p.oxQf)poh oV


Sic'trTpairTat.

Which

Few

is

told

by Diog.

71.

the anecdotes about


Aristippus rest on good authority. Agreeing, however, as they
all do, in portraying a certain
character, they have been usedt
as the material for a historicall
They may be spurious
sketch.
in parts, but on the whole they
give a faithful representation of'
the man.
of

PRACTICAL LIFE OF CYRENAICS.


appears to have been a

man of high feelings and a


cuhvated mmd, a man
knowing how to preserve
calmness and freedom
of mind in the
p rpetual

change of human affairs,


how to govern
and mcWions, and how
to

events of

make

Chap.
XIV.

his^ln

the best of all


""'-"''
the

The strength
str<>no-tV, of
^f -ii
uwill which
can beard
!
destin V the
th. earnestness
destiny
of high feelings intent
upon
g^eat ends, and strictness
of principles
life.

may not be
a proiicient in the
rare art of content
ment and moderation, while
the pleasing kindness
and the cheerful brightness
of his manners attract
fa
more than the superficial
and effeminate chara^r
hs moral views repel.
Nor are these traits
pm-ely
personal; they lie in
the very nature of
his systn
but he

his

IS

orudence.
,ui

e as

1?

much

"^^^^

From

with Aristippus as
with Diogener and
' ^^^'^ ^'^^
" -P'-ed by

indeed both are i^v ^


Hi. was a theory of a
kno^let

fT^

senses.

His was an insatiable


thirsting for know-

HS), that if Socrates


or
nstippus placed themselves
in
ilag-onism with tradition,
thcT
ght not to be imitated
the.e^
1.

magnis

-^

Socrates

emoved.

tie

Theory and practice


cover one another

iUi et divinis bonis

nc licentiam
assequebantur

oere audientib.

fflti^Zl

exS

schola
bu ed to ?!
d on ?he

^nnn^ r.

? I'

phiU^tos

'

^1 ""
rf

V" '^"'-

? """'^
,V'

SS^"!!

'^

-^'"- -'"S,

of Anti-

"^^ -"o mis-

;^^>r.t:ir

B B

"^"'o^'

^"^ " ^"'--'


'"""'' '^ ""ri-

-""
tX.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

370

CHAP,

XlV-_

exercise; theirs a tota


ledge, an untiring critical
indifference to al
renunciation of knowledge, an
a scrupulous conscientheoretical enquiries. His was
submission to moral retiousness, an unconditional
of man upon himquirements, an unceasing toiling
was a comfortable theory of
self and others ; theirs

and treatmg even


never going beyond enjoyment,
On his side
indifference.
the means thereto with
moral strictness,
were self-denial, abstemiousness,
were luxurious indulpatriotism, piety ; on, theirs
a citizenship of the
gence, mischievous versatility,
a rationalism needing
world needing no country, and
allowed that Aristippus
no Gods. Nor yet can it be
of Socrates, or that his
was only a degenerate pupil
surface-deep by that
teaching had only been touched

life,

of his master.

Not only was he

classed

among

fol-

unanimous voice of antiquity,


lowers of Socrates by the
immediate reference to
which, no doubt, had more
with him ; not only did h
his external connection
of Socrates and regard his
always call himself a pupil
devotion '-a proof stronge,
teacher with unchanging
showing that he was able tx
than the former, and
his friend ; but his phi
appreciate the greatness of
that the spirit of his teache
losophy leaves no doubt
at work. The intellect,^
had in him been mightily
intellectual aims of Socratesh
convictions and the
stramii);
^ Socrates, on the one hand,
did not share ;
,
1

~
o
v,
^^7 5
p. dJT, 8See above,

?'"t'd

Sed

Piat
to br ng

M^e

2^3), in:
intellectual

teaching of Aristippus in(


connection witli tliat
(,

whe,f supporK'
arguments
additional
the
by

fecC 'even

'

helation of cyrenaics to sochatus.


every nerve to attain to
knowledge
the other hand, denying that

in

Aristippus, on

knowledge was possible;

his Ges. Abh. 233, nor are


they
regarded as such by liiUer
Gesch. d. Phil. ii. 106. Hermann thinks that Aristippus
was only lacking in the religious and moral tone of
Socrates, but that he steadily
adhered to his logical principles.
Socrates declared all judgments
to be relative, and only
conceptions 'to be universally
valid
in the same way, the
Cyrenaics
denied only the universal validity of judgments,
but not
that of conceptions ; for
they
allowed that all men receive
from the same things the same

declared the corresponding crn-

ceptions for instance, that of


the good to be relative.
In

the next place it is equally


untrue to say that the
Cyrenaics
only denied the universal

validity of judgments but


not that
of conceptions; for they

declared most emphatically


that
all our notions only
express our
personal feelings. They did

impressions, as to the names of


which they were agreed. These
names, however, were identical
with the conceptions of Socrates, conceptions having
been
by them as by the Cynics
and

Megarians reduced to empty


Qames and deprived of all real
mbstance. There is indeed a
loticeable advance in entirely
separating conceptions from
ippearances, and in more preiisely deHningthe highest
good
ts

the

lirst

ally

valid.

lace

it

judgment univerBut in the first

never occurred to Soto deny the universal


ahdity of judgments and it is
s certain that he allowed
uniersally valid judgments as
that
e allowed universally valid
rates

3nceptions such, for instance,


'All virtue is knowledge,'
5
every one pursues the good
id if he called some
judgments
ilative such as, This is good,'
;

<

-it is

no

less certain that

he

even allow that

same impressions

way

all

feel

not
the

in the same
unless in this passage
we

are to understand by
impressions, feelings themselves,

which ca^e

in

this language

would
be as unquestionable as it
would
be unmeaning but they
main;

tained that

we cannot know

whether others have the same


feelings as ourselves. And
that
they practically admitted
tl
common meaning of names thee
use of which they could
not
of course deny, is of
little account ; for they left it an
open
question, whether common
impressions and notions
corresponded to these names. It
will
be seen at once what has
become of the advance

Hermann

which

finds

in Aristippus.
decided distinction
between

conceptions and
appearances
can least of all be attributed
to
tfie Cyrenaics, seeing
that thev
know of nothing but apnea/ances and it will appear,
after
what has been said, to
be
eqiially a mistake
to say that
Pleasure is the hio-hcst
good
IS the first
judgment univer;

'

sally valid.

n 2

Chap.
XIV.

THE SOCBATIC SCHOOLS.


Socrates taking

up a new

position and a

new method

no
Aristippus allowing of
of gaining knowledge;
serve a practical end.
knowledge which does not
inagreatmeasure indebted tohisteacher
Still

he was

credit
with which we can readily
chaunprejudiced sobriety which
him,^ and for that
bearing.
racterises his whole
and
his moral teaching
The same may be said of
respect he was below So-

skill
for that critical

How

conduct.

far in this

to lum
Yet in truth he was nearer
crates is obvious.
On the one hand,
believed.
than will be readily

Socrates, as

we have

seen,

utility the

made

ground

of:

believe
Might not Aristippus then
lo:atduties.
^
deviating from
that he was not
a diffei
held
respects
if he in some
iJnal end in view,

^-f ^^^^^

to a
instructor as to the means
ent opinion from his
about
other hand, there was
pleasant life? On the
Socratic-that comLstippus much which is truly
tha
rises above circumstances
posm:e with which he
master of himself an
Lependence with which he is
whicl
that unbroken cheerfulness
his surroundings,
feeling, that quiet assuranc
engenders a kindliness of
o
confidence in the strength
which grows out of
most importan
Knowledge is with him the
,ind.

element.

By
^t

or-coriiino-lT

^' -.^^RldualRSS.
^''^.^r^
agree with
'

Plnl.

11.

a,

mak

he would
culture and prudence

%, who

says

h^ neia
stippus appeals to
the im
that
tirm to the view
found
inustte
action
pulses to

Tntut ^I^S^Snr^Sfca:;

be known, to have arrived

at

conclusion opposite to that


Socrates.

^^^ ^^^

ved

.._

..J
^^^_

^^^^

ana

"

^.^

co^.^p^
^^ ^^
in his writings.

^^^,

^^^
'

CYRENAIC MORALS AND SOCRATES.


men

:i7[

as independent of external
circumstances as their

nature allows

Nay, so

of.

Chap
^^^-

far

does he go in this
direction that he not unfrequently
trenches on the
ground of the Cynics.^ In reality his
School

was also

internally connected with theirs.


pose to philosophy the same

Both Schools pro-

problem, how to acquire


practical culture,^ rather than
theoretical knowledge.
Both, therefore, neglect logical
and physical enquiries,
justifying their procedure by
theories,

'

based it is true
on different principles, but
leading in the end to the

same

sceptical results.

Both in their ethics compass


emancipation of man by means
of prudence, and the
raising him above outward things
ind events. One thing only
makes them opponentstheir pursuing this
common end by means the most
the

same

aimthe

opposite.

The Cynic

school follows the path of selfthe Cyrenaic that of self-indulgence;


the Cynic
hspenses with the outer world,
the Cyrenaic employs
t for Its own
purposes.^
The object of both Schools
)eing, however, one
and the same, their principles
:ome back again to the same
point. The C>Tiics deive the highest pleasure
from their self-denial ; Aritippus dispenses with
property and enjoyment, in
rder the more thoroughly
to appreciate them.^
lenial,

>

'

Ime Xr!^"

Si
TliP.

attributes

^""*^^^ Antisthenesand Arl

n^^^^^^^^^

cfor,.T

294an^to
To make

quotes the contradictory^ ate-

Antisthenes says that to philo-

^^^^ '
M'"^"^'' ,4 ^^
'^^ ^'^^^ P^"

^^^^-

'

Ihis -difference

HI

'''

^^

^^

THE SOCBATIC SCHOOLS.


towards politi-

CHAP
Xi'S'-

For a similar reason their attitude


traditions is a kindred one.
cal life and religious
the individual
Conscious of his mental superiority,
world, needing
withdraws himself from the external
fettered by the teno country, nor feeling himself
and troubling himself tar

liefsofhis countrymen;
attempt any mouldmg mtoo little about others to
of politics or that ot
fiuence on either the sphere
there
their sharp differences,

Thus, despite
between these Schools betraymg
is a family likeness
the Socratic philosophy
their common descent from

religion.

'

alloyed with Sophistry.

Certainly

it

must be granted that Aristippus


the^

original ground of
diverged far more from the
The utili-,
Antisthenes.
Socratic teaching than did
Socrates was only anj
tarian view of life, which with
commend to the reflecting
auxiliary notion in order to
here raised to be
mind the practice of morality, was
knowledge of Socrates bemg
a leading thought, the
Philosophy became witt
pressed into its service.
for further-

.
'

a means
Aristippus, as with the Sophists,
Instead o
individuals.
ing the private objects of
was pur
knowledge, only personal culture
scientific

knowledge

in
sued and regarded as consisting
enjoyment.
world and in the art of

The

ot th

scant

origin and truth ot


remarks of Aristippus on the
most part from Vxc
impressions, borrowed for the
oi:

to a wholly un-Socrat
tagoras and ultimately leading
were only intended
destruction of all knowledge,
If not altogether annih
helps to moral doctrines.
of the Socratic philosopl
lated, the deeper meaning
;

DELATION OF AlilSTIPPUS TO SOCRATES.

375

was here at least subordinated to what with Socrates


was a bare outwork, and ahnost an obstruction to his
leading thought.

Chap.

__^^^\

Grranting that Aristippus was not

a false follower of Socrates,^ he was certainly a very


one-sided follower, or rather he, among all the followers of Socrates, was the one

who

least entered into

his master's real teaching.

Side by side with this foreign element, the genuine


Pomts
'/^'''^'"^'
Socratic teaching cannot be ignored in the
^^
Cyrenaic

In that school there are in fact two elements,


the combination of which constitutes its
peculiarity.
One of these is the doctrine of pleasure as such, the
other, the limitation of that doctrine by the
Socratic
school.

demand for intellectual circumspection the principle


that prudence
pleasure.

the only means for arriving at true


The former element, taken alone, would
is

lead to the conclusion that sensual

enjoyment is the
the latter, to the strict Socratic
doctrine of morals.
By uniting both elements Arionly object in

life

stippus arrived at the

conviction which is stamped


his language, and on which his personal
cha-

m all

standing comment that the surest way


io happiness is to be found in the art
of enjoying the
3leasures of the moment with perfect freedom
of soul.
racter is a

i\niether this is

indeed possible, whether the two


eading thoughts in his system can be harmonised
at
11, is a question which it seems never
occurred to
Iristippus.
["hat

We

freedom of
'

can only answer

it

in the negative,

soul, that philosophic

As Schleiermaoher maintains, Gesch,

independence

d. Phil. 87.

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.


at which Aristippus aimed, can only be secured by
soaring above the impressions of the senses and the

Chap,

^^-

particular circumstances of life to such an extent that


happiness becomes independent of these surroundings

and

Conversely, when the enjoyment of the


the highest object, happiness can only be

feelings.

moment

is

proportion as circumstances give occasion to


agreeable feelings; all unpleasant impressions being

felt in

disturbers of happiness.

It is impossible to

abandon

prethe feelings freely to the enjoyment of what is


without at the same time being disagreeably
sent,

by what is unpleasant. Abstraction, whereby


forbidden ;
alone this might be done, is distinctly
to be
Aristippus requiring the past and the future
Apart
ignored and the present only to be considered.
suffers from
therefore from other defects, this theory

ij

affected

j
,

fundamental principles, the insystem could


jurious effects of which for the whole
they soon
not fail to follow. As a matter of fact
appeared in the teaching of Theodoras, Hegesias,and
contradiction in

Anniceris

E. The

Uter

Cy

'ir)'Tl'ieo'^'*''*''

its

hence the interest which the history of

the later Cyrenaics possesses.


About the same time that Epicurus was giving a
^^^^ ^^ the philosophy of pleasure, Theodoras.

^^^

School.
Hegesias, and Anniceris, within the Cyrenaic
those o1
were advocating views partly agreeing with

of pleaEpicurus, partly going beyond his doctrine


Theodoras, on the whole, adhered to the prinsure.
unscrupulous a(
of Aristippus, not hesitating,
ciples

consel
he was, to push them to their most extreme

LATER CYMENAICS. TIIEOBORUS.


The value of an

quences.i
its results

077

action depending upon

to the doer,

he concluded that any and


every action might under circumstances
be allowed.
If certain things pass for immoral, there
reason why this should be so, if the masses

is

a good

are to be

kept within bounds

:
the wise man, tied by no such
prejudice, need not, in suitable cases,
be afraid of
adultery, theft, and sacrilege.
If things

exist for use,

women and

beautiful

boys are not made only for


Friendship, it seemed to him, may be

ornament.2

dispensed with

for the

wise

man

is

self-sufficing

and needs no friends, and the fool can


make na
sensible use of them.^
Devotion to one's country he
considered ridiculous
of the world,

wisdom

and

'

for the wise

Gods and

vi. 97.

11.99.
ThatTheodorus said this and similar
things cannot be doubted after
,the dehnite and explicit testimonyot Diogenes. It is true
507, Theodorus complains
that his pupils misunderstood
p.

iim-a statement which,


I,

Itt

i^i>Sriv%TVP
''"L.^^^
Pasdag.
(^l^ie?is,
?\ andS yet

IK
S(|15, A.),
.

if it

be true probably refers to the


practical application of
his
lorinciples.
He may have led

'

have expressed

the logical consequences of


the

and his

of his School

Cyrenaic teaching.
But it is
undoubtedly an exao-o-eration
to charge him, 2I

kiZnZ

(Expos.

^i>t.^.

The views

religion were also expressed

'
apao-^raTos is the term used
of him by I)iog. ii. 116; and
this epithet IS fully justified by

a passage like that,

a citizen

is

will not sacrifice himself

to benefit fools.^

respecting the

man

Fid. 1089, AO doe?


with inciting to theft;pirjury:
P^^J^^y,

and robbery
3
1.

c.

jj^

in

.^g

still

h.-yaQhv ix6vov

'

^^^ Epiphanim^
stronge/ terms

%x.y. rhu evSa^uo-

Svarvxo'vura, kUv ,} fro<b6s- koX


alp.rhu .hai rhu &^po.a nKova^o^

6pTa nal i^^eidr, (anadri ') This


statement, likewise, seems to
be rather in the nkture of a
hasty conclusion, for Theodorus
makes happiness' depend on in!
telligence, and not on thin-s
without.

Dioff. 98,

Epiph,

1.

c.

Chap.
^J^-

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.


Chap.
XIV.

folwithout reserve;^ Bio^ and Euemerus^ herein


of
lowing his example. For all that, the theory
1

of Theodorus,

The atheism

which, besides

bringing down

him an indictment at
Athens, gained for him the
standing epithet 2t0eos (he was
called 0ebs according to Diog.
joke
ii. 86, 100, in allusion to a
of Stilpo's, but probably Kar
avricpaaii/ for at0eos), will be freIn JDiog.
quently mentioned.

on

97 he says

?iv

1089, A.) also asserts that he


denied the existence of a God.
In the face of these agreeing

testimonies, the assertion of


Clemens (Paedag. 15, A.), that
Theodorus and others had
wrongly been called atheists,
and that they only denied the

popular Gods, their lives being


otherwise good, can be of little
Theodorus no doubt
weight.
Gods of the people
the
denied
in the first place, but it was

iravrdiraaLV

avaipwv ras trepl 6ea>v 5(5|as


KoL abrov -nepiervx/'lJ-^v /3t^\iCf)
ovk
Oeav
irepl
iTnyeypafiixevcp
ijKaTa(ppovT]To:

e|

not his intention to distinguish


between them and the true God.
The anecdotes in Biog. ii. 101,
in116, give the impression of

(paaiv

ov

ra irAeTa-'^a
The last statement can
elirelu.
only apply to the criticism of
belief in the Gods generally,
for Epicurus' peculiar views
about them were certainly not
Sext.
shared by Theodorus.
Pyrrh. iii. 218; Math. ix. 51,
55, mentions him among those
who deny the existence of the
Gods, with the addition 5ta
Tov Trepl deuu awTdyfiaros ra
vapa Tols "E\\t](T1 deo\oyoviJ.eva

'ETTLKovpou

Aaj3oj/Ta

sincerity.

1,

2) says

The argument quoted


by Sen. Benef. vii. 7, 1, to
prove that every one and that
no one commits sacrilege is
more a rhetorical and intellectual work of skill.
3 The view of Euemerus respecting the Gods is briefly as
follows There are two kinds of
(3-odsheavenly and incorruptible beings, who are honoured
by men as Gods, such as the
sun, the stars, the winds and
dead men, who were raised to
the rank of Gods for their
benefits to mankind. Diodorus

ments.

Cic. (N.
nullos [Deos]

esse omnino Diagoras Melius


et Theodorus Cyrenaicus putaNonne
Ibid. 23, 63
verunt.
aperte Deorum naturam sustu-

IMd. 42, 117 Omnino


?
Deos esse negabant, a statement
which Miiiuc. Fel. Oct. 8, 2, and

lerunt

iromiA.us avaffKevaffas.
i.

Diog. iv. 54 : TroWa Se koi


aOeurepov Trpoaecp^pero ro7s o/xi\ovaL TOVTO eoScopetoj/ airoXava as but in his last illness he
was overcome with remorse,
and had recourse to enchant2

D.

Lact. Ira Dei, 9, probably repeat after him. Likewise Pint.


Comm. Not. 31, 4, p. 1075, says
Even Theodorus and those who
shared his views did not declare God to be corruptible,
a\\' OVK iiriffTevaav us icrri ri
Ujnjjh. (Expos. Fid.
&<pdaprov.
:

in Hits. Pr. Ev. ii. 2, 52. Tc


the latter class of beings Euemerus referred the whole oJ

Mythology, and supposed it t<


be a history of princes anc

LATER CYRENAICS. TIIEODORUS.

379

Aristippus did not altogether satisfy him.

He was
admit that pleasure and pain do not merely
depend on ourselves and our inner state, but also in
a great measure on external circumstances and he
fain to

therefore sought such a definition of the

good

highest

as should secure happiness to the wise

man,
and make that happiness dependent on his prudence.^
This result, he thought, would be reached if happiness were
sures,

made

to consist, not in individual pleabut in a cheerful state of mind and con-

versely evil, not in individual feelings of pain, but in


an unhappy tone of mind ; for feelings being the effects

of impressions from without, states of mind are in our


own power.2 Accordingly, Theodorus asserted that
in themselves pleasure

and pain are neither good nor


goodness consists in cheerfulness, evil in sadness
the former proceeds from prudence, the latter from
bad

folly; therefore pursue

prudence and justice, eschew

princesses,
Uranus, Cronus,
Zeus, Ehea, &c.
For further
particulars respecting this rationalising history of the Gods,
con^vli Steinhart,A.\\g. Encyclo.
Art. Euhemerus.
V. Sieruka,

De Euhemero.
These reasons are not mentioned in so many words, but
they follow from Theodorus'
positions about the highest
good, and also from the stress
which, according to Diof/. 98,
he laid on the avrdpKcia of the
wise mtin, and the difference
he made between wisdom and
'

,
, .
^
irobably
what Cic.
(Tusc.
13, 28
14, 31) quotes as

^^l^^A
111.

Cyrenaic doctrine belongs to


that not every evil
engenders sorrow, but only unTiieodorus

foreseen evils, that many precautions can be taken to pre-

vent sorrow by familiarising


ourselves with the thought of
future evils. What control of
outward impressions he considered possible by prudence,
appears also from the explanatory remarks in Stob. Floril
119, 16
the wise man has
never sutHcient reason to put
an end to his own life, and it
is inconsistent to call vile the
;

^^'^^' ^"^ ^l^en to put an


to life to avoid the suffcrings of life.

^^^y

end

Chap,

_^'

'

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.

380

Occasionally he him-

ignorance and wrong-doing.^

Chap.

and an indifference to
to a Cynic.
life 2 which would have done honour
Not that the theory of pleasure was therewith surrendered, but the older setting of that theory was
self displayed a fearlessness

__^^1l_

In place of individual pleasures, a state


mere
of mind was substituted, independent of the
Instead of a
feelings of enjoyment and pleasure.

changed.
(

cheerful resignation to the impressions of the moment, the highest good was made to consist in rising
superior to circumstances.

Hegesias went a step fmrther.

(2) Hegefivas.

to the general

maxims

He,

too, adheres

With him

of Aristippus.

identical with pleasure, evil with unhappiif.


ness: all that we do, we do only for ourselves;
because
services are rendered to others, it is only

good

is

advantages are expected in return.^


Diog. 98 riKos 5' hiteXifx^ave
r^v fi^ eVl
Xapav KoX Kvnr\u

'

(bpovi}<Ti,

r^v

5'

a(ppoavvri

eVl

^\<pp6v(\(riv koX 8iKaio(rw7)/,

kyaQ^
KaKx Se ras ivavrias

|6is, /xeVa

hk 7]^ou)]v Koi tT6vov. That justice


should be reckoned among
good things may be brought
into agreement with what is
quoted p. 266, 3. It is to be
recommended, because it protects us from the unpleasant
consequences of forbidden actions, and from the disquiet

which the prospect


.

of

these

alproduces,
consequences
though such actions are not in
themselves inadmissible.
2 When at the court of LyBimachus, he so enraged the
latter by his frankness (^Diog.

But on

looking:

Plut. Exil. 16 Philo, Qu.


Pr. Tib. p. 606, 884, C.)
that Lysimachus threatened to
crucify him, upon which Theo-

102

Omn.

uttered the celebrated


saying, that it was indifferent
to him whether he went to
corruption in the earth or
Cic. Tusc. i. 43, 102 ;
the air.
Phit. An.
Valer. Max. vi. 2, 3

dorus

.;

'

Stoh. Floril.
Vitios. 3, p. 499
saying
another
attribute
23,
2,
to him on the same occasion,
attributing to Anaxarchus the
above passage in Stoh. Floril.
;

2, 23.
^ Diog. ii. 93
oi Se HyrjertoKoi
MyS^i^voi aKoirovs fiv dxov tous
axWovs 7]Boutiu koL tthvov, ^rjre Se
:

x'^P"'

'''

^^""^

/^^7

"^'^/'"f

^T ^

euep7e(n'aj/,5idTb^r?5i auTOTauTfl

LATER CYRENAICS. HEGESIAS.

round to discover wherein true


pleasure is to be
found, Hegesias met with no
very consoling answer
Our life, he says, is full of trouble
;

sufferings of the
Its

peace

body

fortune

the numerous

affect the soul also, disturbing

in

numberless ways crosses our


cannot reckon upon a satisfactory
state
of mmd, in a word, upon
happiness.'
Even the
practical wisdom, upon which
Aristippus relied, affords to his mind no security
for perceptions,
;

wishes;

man

accord-

mg

to the old Cyrenaic

maxim, not showing us things

as they are in themselves, if

we

act according to probabilities,


our calculations will come true

cannot be

enough

if

had,

it

is

we can but

are always obliged to

who can be sure that


? ^
And if happiness

surely foolish to try for


it
fortify ourselves against
the'

sufferings of life; freedom


I

IS

our goal.3

8 world where
aipew-Sai

Ibid

from pain, not pleasure,


Yet how may this goal be
reached in

^ii^ts auTct,

<i^

JIT

so

much

ixxi

trouble and pain falls to


our

8n! ris

^""-''""'fXe'":^

p.

343

a,<|,s

i,K

i^ptgoi^a! thw

M.

""*' '"^'-. "nconditionally


Exp Fid Imo H tfff/
sJe. but less ac'cu^a,^"" "" guaranteeing for it this rela^

TtapKTOV

rt),,

ev5ai/iiouiau eJuai. i>ee

Chap
XIV.

81

THE SOCEATIC SCBOOtS.

J52

CHAP

Clearly not at

lot?

all

as long as peace of

minuj

and circumstances,
depends upon external things
when we are mdi&
contentment is only then sure,

_i^^
I

produces pleasure or pam.


ferent to everything which
depend ultimately!^
These, as Hegesias observes,

our attitude towards


not upon things, but upon
pleasant or unpleasant,
things ; in itself nothing is
according to our
but makes a varied impression,
riches nor poverty
tone and condition.^ Neither
bemg
life ; the rich not
affect the happiness of
freedom, nor slavery,
happier than the poor. Neither
dishonour, are condihigh nor low rank, honour nor
Indeed,
pleasure we receive.
tions of the

a fool ; to the wise


only appears a good thing to
No Stoic or Cynic could more
indifferent.'

life
^

amount of

man

it is

sternly

things than
denounce the value of external

With these prindoes.


the pupil of Aristippus here
and thoroughly Socratic
ciples is connected the noble
anger, nor human
maxim that faults do not call for

no

for instruction, since


beings for hatred, but only
what
is wrong ;^ desirmg
one intentionally does what

what is good
pleasant, everyone desires
his peace of
wise man does not allow

is

and

as,

mmd

to

the

neither does he allow


depend on things external,
of others.
to be ruffled by the faults
.

OTecedinc note.
S^fJ 9i T^J T omv
Sp<.

tX ^^o;

i,rv

which pro.

bably only bears


given in the te^t.

...^..,

Ma^^-

it,

sense
Similarl,

the

M-5.5.1?..

LATER CYRENAICS. ANmCEHIS.

383

In the theory of Hegesias it is


seen more decidedly
even than in that of Theodoras,
that the doctrine of
pleasure is unsatisfactory.
It is even expressly admitted that human life has
about it more of sorrow

Chap

^^^
^I^''

than joy, and hence a perfect


indifference to things
outward is insisted upon. But

what right has Hegewith the good, and pain with


the good is that which is
the con-

sias to Identify pleasure

evil ?

After

all,

dition of our

well-being;

if this be indifference
rather than pleasure, indifference
and not pleasure
IS the good; the
doctrine of pleasure has come
round

to Its

opposite-the Cynic independence


of everything

external.

Not that the Cyrenaic school


could avow

this as its general principle

own

position

still it is

without sun-enderin<r

distinctly

its

avowed within that

school that pleasure

is not in all cases


the highest
Anniceris indeed maintained
that the aim (3) Anniot every action is the
pleasure resulting therefrom
"""'
and, like the older Cyrenaics,
he would not hear of a
general aim of life, nor substitute
freedom from pain
in the place of pleasure.'
He observed too that by
pleasure only our own pleasure
can be understood
;
for of the feelings of
others, according to the
old

motive.

'

'flemem, Strom,

ii.

417, B.

e^rala.,

statement in Bion

ii

or,

of S-

jpci^o,.

Sk
Ziri,n.ouv.dpxe..i.d.rvs
re'Ao,, rV

Hc^esia.-and also the^ser


tion (,V./^. -A^.r^.) that
Tnni

j5o.^., o^ro.
Kvpr,ua,.o\ rhy
8pov rvs 7,50.,. 'E...u.;pou,
tout-

ino- to

Suidas, in the'

Hme

of

rV

Alexander, was an EpiciSean


Cicero and Diogenes Akew'se'

iiroKaKovures.

affirm that his School


deol^Z
pleasure to be the ^^'^P-nod

^o^T.

roy aXyovuro, ^.e^aiP^jrj a^ero... .e^po,-) Kardcrraa.u

See p. 354, 1. This


would justify the inaccurate

THE SOCEATIC SCHOOLS.

3g4
CHAP,
^l^-

know nothing.^ Yet I


teaching of his School, we can
enjoyments of the
pleasure is not only caused by
"
with other men and by|
senses, but by intercourse
Anniceris allowed to|
honourable pursuits.^ Hence,
affection, and patriotism
friendship, gratitude, family
apart from the benefit
an independent value, quite
He even went so
from these relations.
,

resulting

wise man would make sacrifar as to say that the


happiness suffer from his
for them, nor would his
fices

remained to him but little


This admission brought him
actual enjoyment.3
life, to which he apround to the ordinary view of
less value to
proximated still further by attaching
in the Cyrenaic doctrine
prudence, the second element
had done. In fact, he
of morals, than Aristippus
is sufficient to make us
denied that prudence alone
above the prejudices of the
safe and to raise us
as well, to overcome
masses there must be practice

so doing, even if there

the effect of perverse use.*

apervi',

M^^e

^^ZTeTl
Clemens,^

c
o

i.

The expression

continues:

wv

an action, ^^^ J^n^thereimmediately bound up there

3ia, Kal

X^P- -' -P^^

arepeaeai

r^^.

vTvo\eL7rov<Ta>v t^h

1
,

t6v

,W

a7ro5e'xe(r0ai,

I ^^y^^^^l^^l^l^%^
<t,.Afat'f

Ibid. 97
Trpiy4vnrai aur^:.
..Vuov .^ 5.^ ras XP-S

abrr}s

g^cos

^Kova^a^s

96 ., .i.ai r. a...p^
hdyou ^phs rh 0ap^^(rat /col
rhu a^t
t5.
^J^^ 5^|//i^.pciv
'^^"^ ^'^

T ^^''

<rv.rpacl>..aay

,,.

LATER CrRBNAICS.
SUMMARY.
Thus the Cjrenaic doctrine
vanish away.

he on

is seen gradually
to
Aristippus declared
that

^W ^

, good, understanding by pleasu.'


actuTli;
joyment, and not mere
freedom from pain
and
moreover,

making the pleasure of


the moment and
^ '"'''''^'^ bethe

"S^oTVT

Itf

abandoned.

Theodoras denied the last


one, '^eg^esias
Heeesias
the second, and even th^ i
ceris

'* '^^' ''''^''^d

Tt tV

b
bme
"e the

by Anni-

'" '"P^^^^'^l^ ^* s!c"r "T"'


Socratic
demand for prudence and

--

indenen
dance o the external
world, with the
leading thought'
of the theory of
pleasure.
The Socratic elemfnt

r
OddlyTn^VL-^ry^nt

or;:Siiec?u:i^~ir:^^^^^^^
-ults Wrom.

drtotrrv^

-^ ^^-^

^^"^-

"""^^^pp-'-^'i^ other r:;ec:

C c

Chap.
XIV.

THE SOCBATIC SCHOOLS.

CHAPTER XV.
KETROSPECT.

have been common to


Inconsistencies appear to
an inIt was, without doubt,
the Socratic Schools.
confine
of the Megarians to
consistency on the part
same time o
conceptions, and at the
all

knowledge to
do away with

all possibility of

development and with


concep-

or definiteness in
anything like multiplicity
the
being is the good, and, at
tions ; to declare that
being
variety and motion to
same time, by denying
alone can
that creative power which

to deprive it of

with the Socratic


a position; to begin
unmeaning hair-splittmg.
wisdom, and to end in
on the part of Antisthenes
It was an inconsistency
fomidation
build all human life on a
to endeavour to
destroying all
at the same time
of knowledge, whilst
meaning
statements touching the

Ltify-h

knowledge by his

conceptions.

and connection of
and
Lsistency both in himself

It

was no small in-

his followers to

a^

world, and
independence of the outer
at a perfect
external
exaggerated value to the
yet to attribute an
war against
of life ; to declare
of the Cynic mode
to
and at the same ime
pleasure and selfishness,
the mos sacred
flounce the wise man free from
and yet
all enjoyments,
moral duties; to renounce

SOCnATIC SCHOOLS RELATEB


TO SOCRATES.

'

3,

to revel in the

enjoyment of a moral
self-exaltation.
In these inconsistencies
and in their unintentional
contradictions appears the
unsatisfactory nature
of
the principles from which
all these Schools
.started
It IS seen how far they
were removed from the
perfect moderation, from
the ready

Chap

^^

susceptibility of
the living versatility
of Socrates, all
clinging to particular sides
of his personal character,
but unable to comprehend
it as a whole

mmd, from

The same

fact will also,

tendency to Sophistry which


philosophers.

nans the

no doubt, explain that


is

B. rte,,

so striking in these '"^""^

The captious reasoning of


^he

Meg"

"'

wf^

indifference of the Cynics


to all speculative
tZTtJ
knowledge, and their contempt
for the whole theorv *-^*'-*-'
of conceptions, no less than
the doctrines of Aristippus relative to knowledge and
pleasure, savour more

the Sophists than of


Socrates.
Yet all these
schools professed to follow
Socrates, nor was there
one of them which did not
place some element of
the
Socratic philosophy at the
head of its system. It
IS therefore hardly
correct for
of

modern

writers to find

nothing but sophistical views


in their teaching,
supplemented and corrected by

what is Socratic, and,


instead of deducing their
differences from the manyl
sidedness of Socrates, to refer
them to the diversities
of the Sophists converging
from

many

the Socratic philosophy as


a centre.

aS

there .ays thaf the


in matter between these
schools
and the Socratic teaching ought

'

sides towards

With decided

^^'^^.^^^1'^''"'''^^
rived from

Z^

T"..'*''-

^:l^7o^^:.^^"i:^

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.


Antisthenes and Euclid,,
admirers of Socrates, such as
shadow of support for this
there can be not even a
at a faithSuch men conscientiously aimmg
view
Socrates
life and teaching of
ful reproduction of the
to him they were first
must have been conscious that
centre, and that from
indebted for an intellectual
germ of a true
him they had first received the living
be clearly observed in
philosophy ;-indeed this may
speak
In their case it is wrong to
their philosophy.
of Socrates on sophistical
of the ennobling influence
to speak of the influence
principles; we ought rather
treatment of the teachmg of
of sophistry on their
the substance of
Socrates, as it were, gave
Socrates.
only a narrower limitathe teaching, sophistry being
a School like that of the
tion of it ; for this reason
that
to connect itself with
Stoics was able in the end

of the Cynics.
With Aristippus the case

Yet even

of

respect

in

is

him

somewhat
it

,-

f
difterent..

has been already

he professed to be a fol-he really was one, although


lower of Socrates, but that
others into the deeper meanhe penetrated less than
and showed the influthe founder's teaching,
established, not only that

ing of

ence of sophistical

to act
sophistry, endeavouring
equipoise to bocratic

an
teaming &c
as

agrees

ill

Yet

J*

this

remak

'fi^s whicS

^^
ce ^^lSi:S^^\^:>fZ
f
^^^
^^
tte
i

Eost.e o

f .)

StSrf/^AS^s
and

a'il^Sime.

370, 2),

^^^

Far more correct and more

^'^-pinf

^^^^

t:^ :L'^toSsceruin
(see pp. 296, 1

If then,

views most, plainly.

w^^^^^^^^^

^.^ 257.)

IMPORTANCE OF SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.


besides lower capacities, previous
sophistical training
may be the cause which prevented the founders of
the imperfect Schools from entering
so deeply or
fully into -the spirit of their master
as Plato did, it

:^i

chap.

^^'

should also be remembered that Socrates


himself
gave occasion to this variety in the Schools
which

were connected with him.

On the one hand, his


personal character afforded so rich a field
as to invite
investigation in the most opposite directions
;
on the
other hand, the scientific form of his
philosophy was
so imperfect and so unsystematic,
that it gave scope
for many diverging modes of
treatment.'

This disintegration of the Socratic


Schools is c. imaccordingly not without importance for
the further ^^^"^'^
progress of philosophy.
Bringing out the separate th^oll
elements which were united in Socrates, and
connecting them with the corresponding elements
in the pre-

Socratic philosophy,

held them up for more careful


The problems were set for all subsequent thinkers to discuss. The logical
and ethical
consequences of the Socratic maxims
were brought
it

observation.

to light.

On

the other hand, it was seen what the


separation of the various elements in
the teaching
of Socrates, and their combination
with other
theories, would lead to, unless these
theories were
'

Cic.

de Orat.

iii.

16, Gl,

observes with some justice, but

somewhat

superficially

Cum

essentpluresortifereaSocrate,
quod ex ilhus varns et diversis
ct in

omnem partem

diffusis

'"^'"^ '"'"^^^ ''''

'^Xnf'.'^^'
prehenderat, proscminataj

sunt

quasi famili^e dissentientes inter se, &c.


For instance Pla"o
and Antisthenes,
pat en^

qS

tiam et duritiam in 8o?ra Lo


sermone maxime adamarSfan
also Aristippus, quem iliac ma
voluptari^' \lispu ation;s
delectarant.
'^'^

THE SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.


first

recast after the

mind

of Socrates.

In this way

schools
the one-sidedness of the smaller Socratic
was indirectly instrumental in enforcing the demand
connect
for a comprehensive treatment which should

more
the different aspects of the Socratic philosophy
systems, and
closely with each other and with earlier
to the
decide the importance of each one relatively
In both ways these Schools influenced Plato
rest.
and
for

basis
Aristotle, Euclid supplying to Plato the
his theory of ideas, Antisthenes

and Aristippus

good.
the groundwork for his theory of the highest
folOf greater importance is the fact that those
the course
lowers of Socrates prepared the way for
Aristotle.
taken by philosophy after the time of
systems are
True as it is that the post-Aristotelian
imperfect
immediately connected with the

not

Socratic

Schools,

and that

those

systems

would

Aristotle
have been impossible without Plato and
that these thinkers
still it must not be forgotten
,

Socratic Schools.
are also deeply indebted to the
intellectual
The predominance of practical over
dis-

which the post- Aristotelian philosophy


which the wise
plays the moral contentment with
external, falls
man, withdrawing from everything
freedom and
back upon the consciousness of his
which can disthe citizenship of the world

interests
;

virtue

interest all these


pense with a country and political
foreshadowed in the
peculiarities of later times are
Stoa adopted the moral
lesser Socratic Schools. The
their entirety, only
principles of the Cynics almost in
softening

them down and expanding them

in applica-

IMPORTANCE OF SOCRATIC SCHOOLS.


tion.

The same School

looks for

Megarians besides Aristotle.

its logic chiefly

From

39

to the

the School of

Megara too the scepticism of Pyrrho and the Academy


branched off, albeit in a somewhat different direction.
The teaching of Aristippus reappears in Epicurus,
only changed in some details.
In short, tendencies,
which at an
lified

earlier period could only secure a

recognition, obtained the

strengthened, recast,

qua-

upper hand when

and supplemented by other

elements.

Yet even

was not possible until the


tual strength of Grreece had abated, and her
this

intellecpolitical

condition had become so far hopeless as to favour


the

view that indifference to everything external


could alone lead to peace of mind.
Previously the

had been too quick, and the Grreek


spirit too keen, to allow the hard-won results of the
Socratic philosophy to be thus frittered away.
That
philosophy according to its deeper bearings must
intellectual sense

needs issue in a science of conceptions such as was


set forth

by Plato and

Aristotle.

Only by separating the various but inwardly connected elements of the Socratic teaching, only by

confounding the form in which Socrates clothed his


teaching with that teaching itself, and mistaking
defects in

manner

for defects in matter, could phi-

losophy be limited to metaphysics so abstract and


a criticism so

empty

as the

Megarian, to morals so

unintellectual and absolutely negative as

the Cynics

those of

or could the doctrine of Aristippus pass

for truly Socratic.

Whilst therefore these Schools

Chap.

THE SO CRATIO SCHOOLS.

)iJ

Chap,
'-

are

not without

importance

for

the progress

of

Grreek philosophy, their intellectual productions can-

not be valued very highly.

truer understanding

and a more comprehensive treatment of the Socratic


philosophy, was the work of Plato.

INDEX.
ACA

CADEMICIANS,

ANT
269

spirit alone

'A
i^cademy,
I

older,

with Plato, 61

50; connected
new, 4

Accusation, the, of Socrates, 103


Eschines, view of Socrates, 76
assigns the reason for the con-

demnation of Socrates, 211; a


disciple of Socrates, 245
his
prose preferred by some to that
;

of Xenophon, 245
Eschylus, illustrating the state of
thought in the fifth century, b.c,
6 ; on the boundary line between
two periods, 9; difference be-

tween, and Sophocles, J 2 con^trasted with Euripides, 16


pthiops, a pupil of the elder Ari;

stippus, 342

gatho, the dainty elegance of,

20
Icibiaxies, of

Plato's, 78
allows
that the discourses of Socrates
seem rude, 80; fascinated by
;

Socrates, 183, 184; his connec|tion with Socrates,


207, 214 '

219,221
lexinus, a native of Elis,
notorious
for

'

221
Ancient morality, relation of Socrates to, 226
Anniceris; a Cyrenaic, pupil of
Antipater, 343, 375, 379, 385
Antigone of Sophocles, 13
Antipater, a Cyrenaic, pupil of the
elder Aristippus, 342 Hegesias
and Anniceris his pupils, 343
Antisthencs, theory of, dangerous
to the popular faith, 229 founder
of a Socratic School, the Cynic,
;

247, 284, 291 ; a nativeof Atlien.s,


rejects every combination
;
of subject and predicate, 277

284

holds that the One alone exists,


279; the teacher of Diogenes,
286
his character, 291
expresses himself in favour of cul;

ture,

his
293;
nominalistic
theory, 297; prefers madness to
pleasure, 305
how led to his
views, 307
allows that some
kinds of pleasure are good, 308
makes virtue consist in knowledge, 310, 311 ; considers marriage unnecessary, 320 censures
;

liis

captiousness, 253; two


arguments of his known, 268;
attacked byMenedemus the Ere
trian,

282

laxagoras, his teaching referred


to

can make a world out

of matter, 42 ; teaching known


to Socrates, 57; extravagant
theories of, 135 ; his view of God
as the Reason of the world, 176
his atheism charged on Socrates!

by Euripides, 19; proves that

popular government, 322 doubts


;

INDEX.

394

ARI

ANY

doctrine his,

popular faith, 327 assails mysteries, 329; makes happiness


the end of philosophy, 346 deviates from teaching of Socrates,
374 inconsistencies of, 386
Anytus, the accuser of Socrates,
193; his dislike for Socrates,
203; based on some supposed
personal injury, 205, 206, 207
vioa leading democrat, 211 a
lent opponent of the Sophists,
218 supposed to uphold ancient
morality, 231
Aphrodite, story of, in Euripides,
;

344 studied Ethi(


;

thinks happi
exclusively, 346
34'
ness the end of philosophy,
;

considers enjoymer_
376 theory
developof highest good, 391
ment of his leading thought,
348 considers feeling produced
con\)\ internal motion, 352
duct and views of, 352, 361 a
greatly infree-thinker, 367;

375, 385;

an end in

itself, 347,

'

debted to Socrates, 368 not a


degenerate pupil of Socrates,
has many Socratic
370, 375
dispenses with
372
traits,
373
enjoyment,
and
property
;

ApoUonius

of

Cyrene, surnamed

Cronos, 251
Apology, 101;

the language ot

Socrates in, 79 sifting of men


described in, 125 cautious language of, on a future life, 153
moral considerations dwelt on
by Socrates in his, 185 proves
that popular opinion about Socrates agreed with the picture
drawn by Aristophanes, 215
;

Xenophon's, 205

deviates further from Socrates


than Antisthenes, 374 his scanty
remarks on the origin of im-,

Archilaus, teaches that the spirit


returns to the ether, 19 falsely
of
said to have been a teacher
Socrates, 57
Archipylus, an Elean philosopher,
;

pressions, 374; his principles'


adhered to by Theodorus, 379
and by Hegesias, 380 teaching,
;,

reappears in Epicurus, 392


Aristippus the younger, grandsotij
of the elder Aristippus, 341
his pupils, 342
Aristophanes, illustrating the proai
blem of philosophy, 29
108
29,
innovation,
enemy of
th;
114, 217, 218 his play of
|

jj

Clouds supposed to have bee]


20'
suggested by Anytus, 203,
So
considered
[see Clouds']
crates a dangerous teacher, 207
'

'

280

.
.
AriArete, daughter of the elder

stippus, 341
.
T
Arginusse, state of public feeling
Socrates
after battle of, 207
hazarded his life to save the
.

opposes him on patriotic ground


209 charges Socrates with Sc
phistic display, 221
;

distinction betwee

victors at, 225


Aristides, the time of, 231 supposed relationship of, to So;

crates, 62, n.

Aristippus, connection of his teaching to that of Socrates, 155 doctrine of, 392 founder of a Socratic School, the Cyrenaic, 247, 337
independent in character, 339 ;
his pupils, 341 ; the Cyrenaic
;

Aristotelian

philosophy and convention, 31^


Aristotle, his physical discussion
45 subordinate to metaphysic;
40; expands the conception,
philosophy of Socrates, 42, 4^
adheres to Idealism, 4|
128
criticism of Plat(|
his
49
4',
Ideas, 49 his ethical views,
philos
Greek
of
fruit
ripe
the
phy, 60 ; influenced by imp(
;

INDEX.

395

ART
<ct Schools, 50

CLE

introduces inductive method, 129 his notices


of Socratic philosophy, 101, 104,
137 agree with those of Plato,
181, 182
and supplement tho.se
of Xenophon, 183 his view of
the chief merit of Socrates, 132
attacked by Eubulides, 251 denies that any proi)o.sitions are
false, 301
gives logic to the
Stoics, 391
ristotle of Cyrene, a contemporary of Theodore, 344
ristoxenus, account of Socrates,
58, n.
disparaging, 70, 2
sceticism of Neoplatonists, 46;
of Antisthenes, 305; of postAristotelians, 45
sclepiades removes Elean School
f

Attic prose, models of, 245 philosophy, 32


Authorities for the philosophy of
;

Socrates, 101, 105, 181, 184

for

Megarian philosophy, 249

"DACCH^,

of Euripides, 17

to Eretria,

280

Bacchylides illustrating the problem of philosophy, 21


Bacchus, story of birth of, 17

Being and Becoming, Megarian


view of, 259
Bio, the Borysthenite, a Cyrenaic,
pupil of Theodore, 343, 378
Brucker's time, a turning point in
estimate of authorities for Socrates' life, 99
Bryso, son of Stilpo, 255

the state of Xenophon an


A. kingdom, 244
;pasia, teacher of Socrates, 57 a
friend of Socrates, 166
henian polish, 73 taste, 80 de-

pAPTIOUSNESS

mocracj', 169, 194, 223; popular


men, 29; people victims, 30;
tragedians, 4
heuians, 198, 211, 228 guilt of,

Cato's view of the condemnation


of Socrates, 205
Cebes, 246

<iatic,

233, 234

repentance

of,

201

hens, central position of, 3;


^legendary history of, 28; plague
3f, 28
citizens of, 31
their advantages, 31
state of, after
;

Peloponnesian war, 28, 29, 30


ntellectual

movement going on

183 the abode of So:;rates, 193, 230; state of public


pinion, 234 political intrigues
!f, 51; not governed
by Sophists,
!04; fall of, 218; old constitu[ion re-established by enemies
f Sophists, 219
ancient glory
f, 219 Gods of, 214 Aristippus
ed to Athens, 337
mists, views of, known to Socraes, 57
It,

54, 55,

eus, story of

house

of,

[see

EHstic\

Character of Socrates, greatness


of, 70
peculiar featiures in, 77
Grecian peculiarities in, 74, 95
Characteristics of the Socratic philosophy, 102
Charges, unfounded, against Socrates, 220
charges against his
political views, 213
against his
moral and religious views, 214
Charmides, a disciple of Socrates,
212
Chronology of the life of Socrates,
;

53,

//.

Chrysippus,

blames Menedemus
and Stilpo for plausible fallacies,
282

Civil

life,

165; renunciation of,

by Cynics, 319
Cleon, 210, 30

;;

; ;

INDEX.

396

CYR

CLI
Clinomaclius, 251
ClytEenmestra, of ^schylus, 13
of Euripides, a doubter, 18
' Clouds,'
the, of Aristophanes,

ing
301

in, 215, 61, n. 1.

Comedians, illustrating the pro-

of philosophy, 29

Conceptions, theory of, characteristic of the Socratic Era, 39,


importance of, for So40, 109
comdefined, 41
crates, 131
mon to Plato and Aristotle, 42
formation of,
developed, 47
128 proof by, 128, 130; rejected
by Euclid, ^259 developed to
Nominalism by C}Tiics, 297 [see

Dialectic~\

Socrates, 198
causes of, 202 not the work of
not due to
the Sophists, 202
real
personal animosity, 205
causes of, 213 justice of, 220
Connus, reputed teacher of So-

Condemnation of

crates, 56, 1

Contemporaries, relation of Socrates to, 231


Conviction, personal, insisted on
by Socrates, 227
Corinth, 251
Corybantic mysteries, 33
Crates, a pupil of Diogenes, 288
speaks approvingly of culture,
293 displays art, 334
-ritias, Sophistic moralising of,
211 fascinated by the wisdom
a pupil of
of Socrates, 183
the most imscruSocrates, 221
pulous of the oligarchs, 211
* Crito,' the, of Plato, 152
'Cronos, surname of Apollonius,
251 and of Diodorus, 252
Custom, distinction between, and
philosophy, 312
Cynicism, traces of, in Stilpo's
moral teaching, 276, 277
;

blem

of,

suggested by Anjiius, 203, 206


attack Socrates as a Sophist,
210, 215 scope of, 214 portrait
;

284 history of 284 teacl


morality of, 16(
291
practice of, 314 influence
on the world, 331 go back to
Eleatic doctrine, 248 depreciate
Nominalism
knowledge, 295
declare contradiction
of, 300
negative side
impossible, 301
of morality, 310 positive side,
312 good and evil, 301 virtue,
310 wisdom and folly, 313 renunciation of self, 315, 358, 370
renunciation of society, 319,
379 the family, 320 civil life,
322 immodesty, 326 rejection
of religion, 276, 327 their views
combined with those of Megasaid
rians by Stilpo, 275, 284
to have studied Ethics exclusively, 344
Cjmic "^School, a development of
the Socratic, 50,162,247 follows
the path of self-denial, 373
history of, 337
Cyrenaics, 337
go back to
teaching of, 344
Protagoras, 248; practical life
of, 361 position of their system,
369 relation of their philosophy
of their
to Socrates, 369, 374
of theii
moral teaching, 372
political views, 374; later, 376
vie\\
general position of, 346
of happiness, 45, 346 importance
attached to feelings, 346, 352
358 doctrine of pleasure, 160
the highest good, 354
352
modified view of 356 conside:
as
all notions relative, 348;
sumed a sceptical attitude to
wards knowledge, 348, 351 den;

CjTiics,

any pleasures are bad ii


admit degree
themselves, 356

tliat

of pleasure, 357 happiness no


the satisfaction of animal in
;

359; philosophy hoA


connected with Euemerus, 367
employ outer world for thei
stincts,

own

ends, 373

INDEX.

397

CYR

ELE

Oyrenaic School, a development


of
the Socratic, 50, 247
separate
branches of, 343 views advocated within, 876

Dialectical tendency
Socrates, 39

Cyrene, 251

C)Topa2deia,

the,

of

245

Xenophon,

^AIMONION,

of Socrates, 66, w. 1,
81 false views of, 82 ; not a
genius, 82
regarded as a private oracle, 84, 89, 96 its
field
limited, 90 ; instances of its
intervention, 86 not the same
as
conscience, 91;
philosophical
;

Didactic poetry illustratingphiio.


sophy in fifth century.
Be 21
Dike,^schylus' conceptions
of 8
'
Dioclides, 251
Diodorus, captiousness
of, 269views on Motion,
269; on Destruction, 272
on the Possible,
ji^; surnamed Cronos,
2b2
teacher of Philo, 254
,

Cyrus, expressions of the


dying-,
179 242 intimacy of Xenophon
with, 212

Diogenes initiates Stilpo


into
Cynic doctrine, 253 a
native of
;

Smope and pupil of Antisthenes,

-S7

uses expressions in
;
favourculture, 293;
recommends
justice, 308;
his asceticism,
320 ; averse to marriage, 321
of

A'lew of, 94
said to be substituted for God, 220 its position
in relation to the popular
belief,
;

Damon, reputed teacher of So-

crates, 56, n. 1

Death of Socrates, 200, 201


results of, 235
- Socrates' view of, 179
defence of Socrates, 196, 197
:)elos,
sacred ship, delavs the
execution of Socrates, 201
)eli3hic oracle confirms Socrates
in
his course of life,
60, and w. 3.
122, 01. 1
God, 108
)cmctrius Poliorcetes, 277
)emosthenes,apupil of Eubulides,

cpreciationjof knowledge by
Cynics, 291
limits to, 293
'ostruction, views of
Diodorus
on, 272
;

etails of the trial of


Socrates,

194-200
ialectic,

a criticism of what is,


133; the art of forming conceptions, 39: a characteristic
of Socratic period, 40
the foundafion of Plato's system, 39
[see
Conccjtfwm, Knowledge]
;

supreme in

322''?!?^''^^^^ f relations;
o22, Plato s view of,
331 ; theory
and practice overlap with,

369
testimony of, to line of
arg-ument pursued in Euclid's
time.
,

Diotima, teacher of Socrates,


57,
Uissen, view on
authorities for
Socrates' life, 100

Dodona, doves of, 26


Droyosen, view of
Aristophanes,
^L

I y

7},,

EDUCATION of Socrates,

55, 56,

J^

"1''^.4; 57, 7i. 1, 3


Egyptian priestesses inHerodotus,

Eleaii-Eretrian School, 279-983.


history of, 279;

teaching"

of,'

Eleatic doctrine of the


One and
All, 264, 265;
difference be
tween sensual and
rational
knowledge, 260; revived
bv
C^-Bics,

248

also

by Megarians,

Elcatics, subtleties of, 255doc


triricsof, 284
'

Elcctra of Euripides,
16, 17

INDEX.

398

GOD

LI

of Parmenides, 262 ;
rejects explanation by analogy,

for the

Elis, 253

Elysium,

notions

received

re-

265

specting, 24

Empedocles, views

known

of,

One

eristic of, 265

tion, 272

to

makes

denies

mo-

virtue consist

in prudence, 304

Socrates, 57

Epicharmus, 21
Epicurean view of happiness, 45

Eudsemonism of Socrates, 158, 160


Euemerus, the Greek rationalist,
;

a pupil of Theodore, 343, 378 ;


connection with Cyrenaics problematical, 367
Eumenides of ^schylus, 9, 13, 16
Euphantus, a pupil of Eubulides,

apathy, 46
an outcome ot
Epicureanism,
50
School,
Cyrenaic
of
Epicureans, on the attainment
personal
make
45
knowledge,
conviction the standard of truth,
116 fond of slander, 70
good
Epicurus, placed the highest
354
pain,
from
in freedom
philothe
to
form
new
a
gave
sophy of pleasure, 376 doctrine
in, 391
of Aristippus reappears
that of
Eristic, Megarian, 285;
Euclid, 266 of Eubulides, 268
Diodorus,
of Alexinus, 268 of
of Stilpo,
273
Philo,
of
269
;

252
Europa, rape

Euripides,

of,

in Herodotus, 26

illustrating the state

of thought in the fifth century,


sceptical verses of,
B.C., 6, 14
spirit of the
kindred
a
232

better Sophists, 15 contrasted


with iEschylus, 16 a rationalising poet, 17 despiser of prophecy, 17 tragic movement
;

'

Euthydemus, his view

274
a

Eros,

aesthetic feeling,
described, 124, 125, 165

grounded on
76

crates, 56, 1

Eretrians, 283
.
^
, ,
the teachEthics, the substance of
ing of Socrates, 132-148, 172,
exclusively
242 [see Morals'\
345
Aristippus,
by
studied
Eubulides, captiousness of, 267;
;

writes against Aristotle, 251


251
the teacher of Demosthenes,
156
thinker,
intelligent
Euclid, an
of
fascinated by the attractions
;

of a
Socrates, 183; founder
Megarian,
Socratic School, the
use ot
247, 249, 266; makes
265;
259,
doctrines,
Eleatic
influenced by Heraclitus, 259;
incorporeal
sees true being in
a counterpart to
species, 259
Platonic
Plato, 259 rejects the
capacity
Ideas, 260; denies that
exerexists beyond the time of
the Good
cise, 261 ; substitutes
;

of injustice

130
Evenus, reputed teacher of bo

attachment

passionate

20

renunciation of, b
Cynics, 320
Fichte, idealism of, not the idea,
ism of Plato, 43 criticism c
Kant, 158
Freret, view of the condemnatio
of Socrates, 203, 204
Cynic
Friars, resemblance of, to

FAMILY,

335
Friendship, 163-165 [see Eros]
'

Frogs,' 215

the oneness of, recognisj


by Socrates, 175 conceiv
world
as the Reason of the
forethought
176;
Socrates,
Go
177; identified with the

GOD,

by Euclid, 263

;;

INDEX.

390

GOD

IDE

<Jods,

Socrates charged witli rejecting the, of his country, 213

Cynic views of, 327


Good, the object of knowledge,
147 practically determined by
custom and utility according to
Socrates, 149; Megarian doctrine of, 262 placed in apathy
by Stilpo, 277 identified with
God by Euclid, 263 Cynic doc;

trine of

Good and

Evil,

301

Cyrenaic view of the highest


good, 354
Gorgias, Plato's, 152
doubts of, 189, 218, 265;
criticism of, 265 a teacher of
Antisthenes, 285, 295, 327
Grecian peculiarities in the teaching of Socrates,'74, 320
Greece, sweeping" changes in,
2
free states of, 3
gods of, in,

sulted by Persian expedition, 8


;
mental development of, 35
change in inner life of, 1 84
moral life of, 226 ; attention of,
directed to logical criticism,
;

265
Greek, mode of, thought, 186, 230
morality, 226, 229, 242 faith,
229 problem proposed to philosophy in Socrates' time, 2;
life involves a contradiction,
7
morality debased, 76 peculiarity, 166
progress of, 392 prejudice against manual labour,
242

Grote, view of Socrates


Sophists, 187, 188, 189
Gyges, story of, 26

EECTJBA

and the

to Sicily

by

Sophists, 4
views
to Socrates, 57 idea
of God, 176; early scepticism
of, 243 view of the
phenomenal
world, 259 his doctrine of the
perpetual flux of things, 350
Hercules, patron saint of the Cyof,

known

nics,

306

a doubter in Euri-

pides, 18

Hermas, mutilation of, 207, 214


Herodotus, exemplifying the state
of culture in Greece in fifth
century, b.c, 24; piety and
credulity of, 25, 27 a friend of
Sophocles, 24 but a doubter, 26
Hesiod, verses of, quoted by Socrates, 222
Hiero, the, 244
Hipparchia, a Cynic, wife of Crates.
288
;

Historians, illustrating the problem of philosophy in the fifth


century, B.C., 24
Homer, verses of, quoted by Socrates,

212;

stories

by Herodotus, 26;
by Antisthenes, 330

criticised

explained

Horned, the, fallacy, 269


H3^othetical Sentences, view of
Philo on, 274

in

Euripides, 17;
18
Hegel's view of the SaifiSt^iov, 96
view of the relation of Socrates
to the Sophists, 187, 190;
considers attitude of Socrates opposed to old Greek morality, 226

doubts

Hegesias, a Cyrenaic pupil of Antipater, 343, 376; adheres to


the maxims of Aristippus,
380
considers life full of trouble,
381 identifies pleasure with the
good, 383 denies the position
of Aristippus, 385
Helen, story of, 26
Hellas united, 3
Heraclitus, doctrines of, conveyed

of,

ICHTHYAS,

the successor of
Euclid, 250
Ideal, Socrates not an insipid,
of
virtue, 74, 203

Idealism, 39
crates, 42

beginnings

of, in Soof Aristotle, 43 of


;

INDEX.

400

MEN

IDE
Plato, 48

Fichte's subjective,

43
Ideas of Plato, 48, 137
Ignorance, consciousness of, the
first result of self-knowledge,
121

Immortality of the Soul, Socrates


view of, 178
Importance of Socratic teaching,
185
Individual independence insisted
on by Socrates, 161 by Cynics
and Stoics, 162
Induction necessary to form conce^Dtions, 129
Influence of Socrates explained, 186
lo, wanderings of, 26
Iphigenia of Euripides, 16
Irony of Socrates, 126
;

Ixion, story of, 8

Love for enemies in Socrates, 170


Lyco, the accuser of Socrates, 194
Lycurgus, 230
fxaievTiKT) rexvv of Socrates, 125

Socrates' view of
MAX,nity
of, 178

the dig-

Marathon, stem race fought


the remembrance
10, 230

at,.

of,

inspires Aristophanes, 29
Meaning of words, Philo's view
of, 274
Means, relation of, to ends in nature, 172
Megara, plunder of, 277 Idealism
of School of, 42
an
Megarian School, 253, 284
imperfect expansion of Socratic
foimded by
principle, 50, 247
Euclid, 249 primarily critical,
doctrine253 history of, 249
approximated to Cyniof, 255
cism, 279 merged in Cynicism,
283; teaching, 255, 258, 269;
starting point of, 259 development in, 264
Megarians, go back to Eleatic
doctrine, 248 captious logic of,
their views of
160, 265, 266
Being and Becoming, 259 of
tlie Good, 263 agree with Plato,
260; attack popular notions,
264; fond of fallacies, 267;
later, indebted to Cynics, 275,
277 inconsistencies of, 386
Meiner's \-iew of sources of Socratic authority, 99
;

the condemnation
JUSTICE
of Socrates considered, 218
of

immortality of
soul by utilitarian argument,
157 resembles Socrates in po-

KANT

proves

sition, 138, n. 1
in,

contradiction

157
true, only

gained by

conceptions, 42, 109 [see Conceptions] virtue consists in, acdecording to Socrates, 140
So292
Cynics,
by
preciated
cratic search for true, 124, 108,
moral value of,
109, n. 2
n. 1
;

Self, the Socratic, 121


^
the fallacy called, 273

KyptetJcoj/,

Meletus, the accuser of Socrates,,


said to have
193, 203, 205, 206
suggested the Clouds to Aristophanes, 203 hesitates to accuse Socrates of Sophistry, 221
a defender of ancient morality,
231
Memorabilia,' the, of Xenophon,
72, 75, 78, 102, 132, 167, 183
attempts of
Menedemus, 281
;

'

'

story of, 8
Leonidas, 77
Life of Socrates, 52
Literature, the problem of philosophy solved by, 4

LAIUS,

145

of

Knowledge,

'

INDEX.

401

MEN
Alexmus
cies,

269

PER

to entangle, in falla;

prc-Socratic
46

removes Elean School

to Eretria, 280 directs


attention to moral questions,
;

Orreek philosophy, 51
Neoplatonists, resort to
higher
revelations, 45; their
asceticism,
46 ; later philosophers, 105

later Cynic, 290


a later Cynic, 290

Menippus,
Meno's question whether virtue
is
obtained by exercise or instruc-

Neopythagoreans, 35
time of, 4
Nicias, superstition of,
28
Niobe, story of, 8

tion, 3 13

New Academy,

Method

of Socrates, 113
Metrocles, brother of
Hipparchia,
a Cynic, 289
Military service of Socrates,
^Q,
n. 2
Miltiades, time of, 231
* MiiTor,'
the, of Cebes, 246

Nominalism

Modesty

Coloneus' of Sopho13
Olympic goddess, 9
Olympus, inhabitants of, derided,
^<J^

'

suppressed by

of Cynics, 297, 300

^rpDIPUS

Moderation, the, of Socrates,


72,
74, 161

39

Neoplatonism the coping-stone


of

281

Menedemus, a

philosophers,

cles,

Cynics,

Orphic traditions, 19

Monimus, a Cynic, expresses him-

mysteries,

self in

favour of culture, 294


theory of
conceptions, 113
particular
moral relations discussed
by
Socrates, 160

Moral importance of

PAN^TIUS,

rejected writings
of Simmias and Cebes,
246
Paris, story of, questioned
in Euripides, 17 ; in Herodotus, 2C,

Morality, practically determined,


according- to Socrates, by

Parmenides, teaching known


to
Socrates, 57, 58; followed
by
Euclid, 260; reduced
action
and passion to the sphere of the
Becoming, 260; discovered
a
contradiction in the Becoming,
261 attributes assigned bvhim
to real being, 262
proved his
position directly, 265
Party, Socrates not tlie
victim of
a political, 21
Pasicles, a Megarian, younger
than

cusutility, 149; inconsistency of Socrates, 151


sucer;
hcially treated by Socrates,
151
relation of Socrates to
torn

and

older
morality, 226; relation of
Socrates to cotemporary
morality,

Morals of the Cynics, 301


Moschus, an Elean philosopher,
280
Motion, view of Diodorus on,
269
Myrto, the supposed wife of
So-

crates, 61, 62, n.

Mysteries, spread of, after


Pelo-

ponnesian war, 32

Eubuhdes, 251

Peloponnesian War, Thucydides'


history of, 27 increasing
spread
ot mysteries about time
of, 32
views of Socrates fixed
about
time of, 61 fall of Athens
in,
218; period after, 231
Pericles, art in the time
of, 3 10
the age of, 28, 54
;

VTATURE, view

of, foreign to
Socrates^ 135, 137; held by
Socrates, 172-175; studied

i-l

by

'

Peripatetic School, 50;


connected

D D

; ;;

INDEX.

402

PLI

PER

shallowness of his discourses,


Sat/xoi/tov of
80; speaks of the
speaks
Socrates, 84, 85, 87, 89

strictures
with Aristotle, 51
on Socrates, 70
Persian War, achievements of, 3
unexpected result of, 8 Socrates
born in last years of, 53
;

Socrates' attitude towards


natural science, 137 veils the
shallowness of Socrates' theory

of

',

Persians, battles with,


*Pha3do,'Plato's, 59, 137
Socratic
Phsedo, the founder of a
247,
Elean-Eretrian,
School, the
the
279
Elis,
of
native
a
279 ;
his
280;
Socrates,
favourite of

what
of virtue, 155 mentions
at
Socrates
a2:ainst
told most
asso20^5,
217;
207,
trial,
the
Socrates with Aristociates
phanes, 210, 216 his language
about Anvtus, 203, 205, 206;
;

opinions, 281
Phfedrus,' the, 79
Philo, a Megarian

value of Plato's testimony considered, 91, 92 his agreement

<

and pupil

Diodorus,254, 273

ot

with Xenophon, 92, 154, 171,


137
181, 188 with Aristotle,

his captious-

ness, 273

puPhilolaus, Simmias and Cebes


pils of, 246

PhiUsojjhy of, considered Sohis


crates a deep thinker, 96
Socrates,
of
fruit
system the
developed,
138, 187 but more
influenced by im41, 141, 392
perfect Socratic Schools, 50, 51

Philosophic Schools, permanence

Philosophy, problem proposed


problem
in fifth century, B.C., 2
reliand
art,
politics,
by
solved
fifth
in
of,
progress
o-ion, 2-34
seq.
35
B.C.,
century,
Physical Science not dispensed
with by Plato, 45
for, by
Physics, ethics substituted
43
philosophy,
post-Aristotelian

to,

regards species as living forces,


founda260 dialectic, 270 the
his
tion of his system, 40;
advance
49;
48,
42,
idealism,

from sensible beauty

his

problem
Pindar, illustrating the
respect
23
22,
of philosopher,
for natural talent, 23
his diaPlato, Writings of, 99
hislogues, 100, 181, 183 most
Apology,
his
torical of, 170
on the Megarians,
215

Xeno257 agrees with, 260 and


;

authorities,

99;

Greek philosophy, 49
influenced by imperfect Socratic
Schools, 50; his description
24b;
of Simmias and Cebes,
definition
Cynic
of
speaks
knowledge as tautological, 312;
his view of Diogenes, 331
cusPlatonic distinction between
ideas,
312
philosophy,
tom and

bloom

'

phon as

concerning the

teaching

his physical inState, 46, 169


of concepreality
quiries, 45
between
diflierence
59
47,
tion,
the
him and Aristotle, 49

179,

moral

to

beauty, 46; essential conceptions foimd in all things, 131

de-

265
scribes Euclid's method,
101
Sonrates,
poHrait
of
~, Ilia
wisest and
calls Socrates the
his
best of men, 73; praises
him
social virtues, 75 describes
;

of

speaks
as a perfect thinker, 105
75 ;
moderation,
peculiar
his
of
Eros, 76
his use of the term
outward
his singularity, 77 ; his
;

appearance, 78;

the apparent

Platonist,

been

a,

Menedemus said

to have

283

philosopher,
Plistanus, an Elean
successor to Phsedo, 280

INDEX.

403

POL

SOC

Politics, little

importance attached
to, by 8ocrate.s, 228
Polyeuctus, said to have taken
part in accusing Socrates, 1 94,

Keisig, his view of the character


of Socrates, 215
Keligion, the position of Socrates

subversive of, 229; denied by


the Cynics, 327
Republic, Plato's, 152
Rousseau's wild fancies, 32

n.2.
Poseidon, intervention of, 2G
Possible, the view of Diodorus on,
272 view of Philo, 273
Post-Aristotelian philosophy, substitutes Ethics for Physics, 44
one-sidedness of Schools, 47;
extreme individualism of, 117'
Predicate, combination of subject
and, rejected by Stilpo, 275
Pre- Socratic philosophy resting on
tradition, 38
a study of nature,
3i), 46
aided by Plato, 51
Prodicus, teacher of Socrates, 57
Progress, rapid intellectual, of So;

OCEPTICISM

of Socratic era,
117; in Euripides, 16, 18; in
Herodotus, 26
in the masses,
an outcome of Megarian
34
School, 50

KJ

Sceptics,

knowledge,
;

cratic age, 2, 3

Prometheus of ^Eschylus,

1)

Protagoras, doubts of, 18, 181), 248


negative teaching of, 248 makes
man the measure of all things,
116; considers all notions relative, 350
considers feelings the
result of internal motion, 352,

Self-renimciation, the, of the Cy-

374
Providence, belief in natural, 174
Providential care of God, 177

nics, 315
Sextus criticises the arguments of
Diodorus, 271

Prytaneum, Athens the, of the wis-

Sicily visited by Sophists, 4


Sifting of men, the Socratic, 124
Silenus, appearance of
Socrates

of Greece, 4
Socrates deserved to be publicly entertained
in the, 200
Pyrrho, his pliilosophy of doubt,
;

255
branched oft" from the
School of Megara, 391
Pythagorean traditions, ] 9 league,
164
;

EEALISM, knowledge of conceptions

of

dom

desjDair

45 imperturbability, 46 resolve
truth into probability, 116
Schleiermacher, his view of the
haiix6vLop, 84
protest against tlie
preference shown for Xenoj^hon,
99; canon of, 100, 104 his objections to Xenophon jis a sole
authority, 183
discovered Megarian
views in Plato, 256
^
Self-knowledge, the Socratic, 43.
121

expanded by Plato

into,

298
Reason, God conceived as the, of
the world, 176, 262; the only
thing which gives a value to
life, 310

compared by Alcibiades

to, 78,

184

Simmias, a Theban, described by


Plato as a philosopher, 246
Simon the shoemaker, writings
circulated under the name of,
spurious, 247
Simonides, illustrating tlie pro-

blem

of philosophy, 21

his epi-

taph on Leonidas, 77
Sinope, the birthplace of Diogenes.
287
Societj', renunciation of, by tlie
Cynics, 319 influence of Cynics
on, 331

D D 2

;;

;; ;

INDEX.

404

soc

soc

quire independence from wants,

Socrates, age of, its inheritance,


36 ; characteristics, 40 ; authori-

315
155

104
Character of, 52, 212 respected
by antiquity, 70 greatness of
character, 70 supposed mental
abpurity, 72
struggles, 71
161
74,
72,
stemiousness,
courage,
political courage, 73
pious
363
201,
201 composure,
senfaith, 235; greatness, 235
74
society,
of
love
sible, 83

ties for,

Socrates, followers of, one-sided


followers, 44, 45, 51, 236, 375;
favourite follower, 280
language of, 151, 152, 163,
,
184, 185 apparently ridiculous,

79
Life of, youth and early manhood, 52, 53 date of birth and
death, 53, n. education of, 55

his instructors, 56, n. manhood


reached before the Sophists in-

love of friends, 194, 211, 164,


imbued with Greek pecu76
abstraction,
liarities, 74, 76;
of
81 not an insipid ideal
;

troduced systematic education,


life begun in trade, 159
55

contentment and simplicity of,


married relations, 61, 62,
64
63 avoided public life, 66 his

not a dry moramany-sided sympa;

serious side in, 73


cultivated tact, 94 inward concentration, 81, 96, 97 a Greek
eccenand Athenian, 74, 95

respected by
70
Xenophon, 72 military service,
personal habits, 105
66, 2, 70
dis230
teaching,
simple
society, 210 ;
courses, 102, 184

detractors,

meditativeness, 78
tricity, 77
absence, 81 modesty, 67 simof
plicity of, 338 consciousness
ignorance, 121, 122, 126; flexiimier life, 94
bility, 317
strength of will, 292; importance attaching to his person, 52,

enemies, 207; attacks on, 193,


206, 210, 211, 232; charges

his ^aiixoviov, 81, 66, n. 1,


his aim to train
82, 84, 89, 96
105, 240
portrait,
263
men, 114,
;

accuracy
his appearance, 77
chaldescription
of Xenophon's
;

fatal,

comedy

contemporaries

of,

185

Ethics of, 134, 172, 240 amoral


ethical princireformer, 114
ples derived from the Sophists,
doctrine of
scientific
149;
morals, 174; defends friendutility highest
ships, 163, 164
standard, 147, 372 value of instruction, 222; highest object
of knowledge, the Good, 147,
262, 263 the oneness of virtue
;

and knowledge,

113,

different

from pre-

to take a
Socratic, 38;
comprehensive view of science,
4 had no system, 47, 119, 160 ;

able

on, 203, 214

crisis,

lenged, 135

most

211, 220, 229;


217 his trial, 196,
213 condemnation, 200, 202
greatness
fate, 235
guilt, 202
of, 236; death, 200, 235, 285;
place in history, 186
_, Philosophy of, 250, 253 appearance at a philosophical
210,

against,

116

108;
thies, 45

list,

78,
virtue, 74, 203

of,

description

Plato's

312

re-

beo-ins with self-knowledge, 43


aims at life, 52 philosophical
;

platform, 104 breaks away from


pre\dous philosophy, 112; how
led to the study of philosophy,
92 ground occupied by, 104, 240
understood the tendencies of
the age, 114 breaks away from
value
current opinions, 112
assigned to them, 111, 129;
;

INDEX.

406

soc

SOC

restricted to ethics, 184, 139analytical,


131 ; opposed to
doubting, 123; his deviation
from original ground of Greek

thought, 231 ; free enquiry of,


291 new mode of thought, 182
did not discourse on the All,'
134
explanation by analogy,'
265 maxim that virtue consists
in knowledge, 241 makes
the
highest business of man knowing the Good, 248 few definite
opinions, 189; method, 120,
182,
240, 241
methodical pursuit of
;

knowledge, 106, 124, 169, 259,


372 narrowness of position of,
240 enunciated a new truth to
;

his contemporaries,
165; convinced men of ignorance, 206
spirit of,
246, 248;
always
goes back to conceptions, 93

120,

121,

48,

264,

292,

295,'

overrated knowledge, 260; introduced dialectic, 39; idealism of, 42; view of injurinoothers, 170; theory of
proof^
131; chief merit, 131; jjhilosophical greatness, 191
Socrates, Political views
of, 228
anti -republican sentiments, 168,'
211 high ideas of the State, 167
prejudice against, 205, 208
principles of, developed bv
^
J
Plato, 49, 169
-, pupils of, 211, 236, 237, 370
relation to the Sophists,
,
55, 67

tempts to expand Socratic prin-

ciple, 50, 391

starting points
;
tor Stoicism, 50,
1, 247 ; diverge
from Socrates, 248 ; disintegra-

tion

of, 389; cover the


same
ground as Socrates, 50; doctrine

of pleasure finds a place


in, 160
friendship defended bv, 163'
founders of, 247; inconsisten-'

cies of, 386

40; different from what had


preceded, 39;
developed bv
Plato, 42, 391 leads to
Idealism,
42
peculiar character of, 43
imperfectly represented in
Socratic Schools, 51;
different
aspects of, 390, 389;
scanty
notices of, in Aristotle,
101knowledge the centre of, 44,'
106; disputes about the character of, 117; moral
views of,
45, 109
comprehensive character of, 47; developed,
47subjective character of, 116two branches of, united
bv
Zeno, 258
Socratic School, a loose
association
of admirers, 68; a
branch of,
established by Euclid,
250; Cyrenaic branch of, 887
Socratic Schools, imperfect
at-

169,187,188,189, 190,203,216,

natural science, 124 value


,
of
geometry, 134 science foreign
to, 137, 172; relation
of means
and ends, 137
~, Theology of, an appendix to
ethics, 139; Reason of the
world,
175; providence, 177; divine
;

element in man, 178


Writings of, 98

-,

ocratic

What

philosophy, 374; asks


things are in themselves,

followers of So-

^^^^^ importance,
So^^on^^^i,
i5J,
390; doctrine of oneness
ot virtue and knowledge,
312
independence of wants, 315

Socratic dialogues, 159, 184doctrine of morals, 159


education,
243; Eros, 124, 126; Ethics,
;

^40

idea

of

ruler,

242

knowledge of self, 121: method,*

1^5
mode of teaching, 241
search for conceptions,
48
thoughts, 244; teaching,
I59'
182 245; view, 48; t>-pe
of
virtue, 74
doctrine of virtue
140; conception of virtue, 147circle, 327
traits in Aristippus,'
;

372

;;

INDEX.

406

STO
required pay296;
name,
liar
ment for instruction, 339 views
on knowledge and pleasure, 387;

soc
teaching, various ele391
ments
T
T
Solon's constitution re-establisliecl,

Socratic

in,

diversities of, 387


Sophistry, a narrower limitation
of Socrates' teaching, 388 ten'dency to, 387
Sophocles, illustrating problem ot
philosophy, 6, 10; difEerence
between, and iEschylus, 12
Sophroniscus, father of Socrates,

31
Sophist, Socrates taken for a, 210
meaning of the term, 190 Anot,
tisthenes in the capacity
;

285
'

Sophistes,' the, of Plato, 26b


practical
tendencies,

Sophistic

2 teaching, 2, 114
ot,
influence
2
enquiries,
views, 311, 338
quesSophists call everything
to
related
Euripides
1
tion,
the better, 16; rationalising
avow selfish prinspirit of, 26
effect of,

54 1
Sorites, the, of Megarians, 266
attributed to Eubulides, 268

Sparta, 230
Spartan education, 243

Spartans,

Cyrus

the

friend

ot,

230

introduce systematic
education, 55 public teachers,
m,
67 little dependence placed
dogmatism
66;
by Socrates,
overthrown by, 112; beheve
real knowledge impossible, 112;
meet the want of the age with
recognise unsatisskill. 113
factoriness of older culture, 114
caprice of, 116, 117 destroyed
natural
the contending views of
ignorance
124
philosophers,
contheir leading thought, 124
made education
tests with, 133
a necessary for statesmen, 169
impart an electritravellers, 4
age, 186 their
their
cal shock to

ciples, 28

on,
State, the, views of Socrates

165-168
a Megarian philosopher,
260; friend of Thrasymachus,
good in
252; placed highest
apathy, 277; his captiousness,
277 rejects every combination
of subject and predicate, 276
denies that general conceptions
can be applied to individual

Stilpo,

wonthings, 260 an object of


der to his contemporaries, 253
learnt Cynicism from Diogenes,
253 united teaching of Megarian and Cynic Schools, 284;
his free views on religion, 283^
;

of, 253.
Stoa, Stilpo the precursor
principleSf
Cynic
the
took
284

Socrates, 187, 188,


moral teaching of older,

relation to

333
190;
;

philosophy away
from nature to morals, 191
their hatred of
failure of, 191
did not take part
Socrates, 203
in his accusation, 203, 205
small political influence of, 204
of,
216
display
rhetorical
Schools of, 218 pernicious incorrupters ot
fluence of, 218
the people, 218 arguments of,
265 hold that every object can
only be called by its own pecu-

draw

335 390
of Dioj^
Stobffi'us, quotes the words
genes, 308
Stoicism, an outcome of Cynicism

50

know
Stoics, hold a standard of
ledge to be possible, 45 thei
apathy, 46, 117 later philosc
;

105; consider Socrate


phih
the inaugurator of a new
declai
100;
epoch,
sophical
personal conviction the standai

phers,

INDEX.

407

SUB

XEN

of truth, 116; views of


individual independence,

161, 882
comprehensive system of, 283
secure freedom by suicide,'
iJlO
in advance of Cynics,
381

Subjective character of the theory


of Socrates, 116, 117
^

Superficial

treatment of morals
Socrates, 155
Silvern, theory of, on the
scope of
the * Clouds,' 216
Symposium of Plato, 101, 210 of
Xenophon, 74, 79; Plato's 'description of, 215

by

Tragedy, Greek, involves


a con-

tradicfion, 7; analysis
Tribon, the, 816

Trojan War, legend

TJXITY,

of, 5

of, 3

Greek, in Socratic age.

Utility, the practical


test of virtue, 124
with Socrates,

134

VIRTUE,

Socratic type of, 73


Socratic doctrine that
virtue

J'ALTHYBIUS,
Tartarus,

notions

Teiresias explains birth of


Bacclius
17

Test science of truth, 44


'Thejetetiis,'the, 125
Tliobans, Simmias and

Cebes

won-

tonly attacks popular faith, 367


considers pleasure and pain

neithei- g-ood nor bad in


themselves, 879, 388
Phcssaly, visited by Sophists,
4

'hessalian legend of Poseidon,


^hrasybulus, 211, 225

Corinth,

'^6

of,

Folly,

Cynic

Wolf, 215
1

75

VANTHIPPE,
ol,

-^-*-

wife of Socrates,

bo

Xenophanes, his doctrine of


the
One, 278
Xenophon, 179, 289; a pupil
of
Socrates, 212; his account
of
Socrates, 72, 78, 76,
89, 91, 137

155:
![^'V_VfI'182,184,'l85
116, lo9.

161; of Xhe ha^t^SuJ,


Memorabilia,' 72 75
78,102 182, 167, 183: objection
raised by 80; SAonposium,
79,
74 and Plato bs authorities
98
84; his

'

251

'hucydides illustrating the problem of philosophy, 27 ; a matter-of-fact writer, 27


imams of Plato, 137
imon, 255
itan in ^schylus, 9, 13
ragedians, illustrating the philo-

sophy

and

ideas of, 818

tA^o,

TJieodorus called the Atheist,


a
pupil of Aristippus, 842, 876
not altogether satisfied
with
Aristippus, 879 his pupils
Bio

of

WISDOM

Worship of God,

246

and Euemerus, 348, 878

or, 8i()

re-

specting-, 24

'hrasymachus
Jo2

IS
knowledge, 140; Socratic
conception of, 156 ; CjTiic
notion

in Euripides, 18

received

JJO,
.' ;

100,

Ph.y

101,

102; writing.' of;

supposed popular
of,

99;

pliilosodescrii:)tion chal-

lenged, 135, 183

true, 161, 181

on nature, 134 agreement


with
Plato and Aristotle,
181 vindi;

cat^ed

against

Schleiermacher,
18.>; Apology of, 205:
reply to
charges 221 .-sketch of an
ideal
ruler, 243

INDEX.

408

ZEN

ZEN

branches of Socratic philosophy, 253, 283, 284


Zeno, iEschylus' conception ot, 7,
9 Sophocles' conception of , 11
Euripides' conception of, 18

conZENO, the Eleatic, supposed


Socrates, 58,

nection with
270; criticism of,
266
united
Stoic,
Zeno, the
269,

265,

two

LONDON PRINTBD BT
SPOTTISWOODE AXD CO.. NEW-STREUT SQUARE
AND PAULIAMENT STREET
:

JTJL-Y"

1884.

GENERiU. LISTS OF

WORKS

PUBLISHED BY

Messrs.

LONGMANS, GEEEN, &

CO.

PATERNOSTER ROW, LONDON.


o>fr;o

HISTORY, POLITICS, HISTORICAL MEMOIRS, &c.


Arnold's Lectures on

Modem

History.

8vo. Is. 6d.

Bagehot's Literary Studies, edited by Hutton. 2 vols. 8vo. 38i.


Beaoonafleld's (Lord) Speeches, by Kebbel. 2 vols. Svo. 32*.
Bramston & Leroy's Historic Winchester. Crown Svo. Qs.
Buckle's History of Civilisation. 3 vols, crown Svo. 24*.
Oheaney's Waterloo Lectures. Svo. 10a. 6d.
Cox's (Sir G. W.) General History of Greece. Crown Svo. Maps,
Doyle's English in America. Svo. I85.

Epocha

of

Ancient History

7^.

Qd.

Beesly's Gracchi, Marius, and Sulla, 2s. 6d.


Oapes's Age of the Antonines, 2a. Gd.
Early Roman Empire, 2s. 6d.
Cox's Athenian Emphe, 2*. 6d.
Greeks and Persians, 2s. 6d.
Curteis's Rise of the Macedonian Empire, 2s. 6d.
Ihne's Rome to its Capture by the Gauls, 2t. 6d.
Merivale's Roman Triumvirates, 2s. 6d.
Sankey's Spartan and Theban Supremacies, 2*. 6d.
Smith's Rome and Carthage, the Punic Wars, 2s. 6d.

Epochs

of

Enghsh History, complete

in One Volume. Fcp. Svo. -6*.


England, 1820-1874, 9d.
Creighton's Shilling History of England (Introductory Volume)

Modem

Browning's

Fcp. Svo. Is.


Creighton's (Mrs.) England a Continental Power, 106^1216, 9d
Creighton's (Rev. M.) Tudors and the Reformation, U86-1608, 9d.
Gardiner's (Mrs.) Struggle against Absolute Monarchy, 16031688, 9d.

Rowley's Rise of the People, 1215-1485, 9d.


Rowley's Settlement of the Constitution, 1689-1784, 9d.
Tancock's England during the American & European
1765-1820, 9rf.
York-Powell's Early England to the Conquest,

Epochs of Modern History


Church's Beginning

*^

Wars

It.

of the Middle Ages,


Cox's Crusades, 2s. 6d.
Creighton's Age of Elizabeth, 2*. 6d.

London,

LONGMANS &

2s. 6d,

[Continued on page

CO.

2.

'

General Lists of Works.


Bpochs o Modern History continued.
Gairdner's Houses of Lancaster and York,

2s. 6d.

Gardiner's Puritan Revolution, 2s. 6d.


Thirty Years' War, 2s. 6d.
(Mrs.) French Revolution, 1789-1795, 2s. Qd.
Hale's Fall of the Stuarts, 2s. 6d.
Johnson's Normans in Europe, 2s. 6d.
. -rrr
a c^
6d.
Longman's Frederick the Great and the Seven Years War, 2.
2s.
6d.
Independence,
Ludlow's "War of American
M'Carthy's Epoch of Reform, 1830-1850, 2s. 6d.

Age of Queen Anne, 2*. 6d.


Seebohm's Protestant Revolution, 2s. 6d,
Stubbs's Early Plantagenets, 2s. 6d.
Warburton's Edward III., 25. 6d.
vols, crown 8vo. 18*.
Pwmde's English in Ireland in the 18th Century. 3
8vo. 3*. 6d. each.
History of England. Popular Edition. 12 vols, crown
to the Outbreak
James
I.
of
Accession
the
Gardiner's History of England from
Morris's

War. 10 vols, crown 8vo. 605.


Fcp. 8vo. 25. 6d.
Outline of English History, B.C. 55-a.d. 1880.
Edinburgh.
of
2 vols. 8vo. 365.
University
the
of
Story
Grant's (Sir Alex.) The
8vo. d65.
vols.
IV.
William
3
&
Qreville'a Journal of the Reigns of George IV.
of the Civil

vols. 8vo. 285.


Hickson's Ireland in the Seventeenth Century. 2
1700-1760. 8vo.36i. Vols. III.
Leckys History of England. Vols. L & II.
1760-1784. 8vo. S65.
8vo. 165.
History of European Morals. 2 vols, crown
Svo. 16j.
crown
vols,
2
Europe.
in
__
nationalism
__

& IV.

Svo. 32*.
Lewea'B History of Philosophy. 2 vols.
of England.
History
the
on
Lectures
Longman's

Svo. 155.

Svo. 285.

Liie and Times of Edward IIL 2 vols.


Edition. 8 vols. Svo. 5.
Library
Works.
Complete
Macanlay's
Cabinet Edition. 16 vols, crown Svo. *4. 165.
__
History of England :

o ^ 48i.
ao.
post Svo.
8 vo
65.

4.

s.
Cabinet Edition.
125.
Student's Edition. 2 vols. cr. Svo.
Library Edition. 5 vols. Svo. ^g*.
165.
Svo.
cr.
vols.
4
Edition.
pSple's
Cheap Edition. Crown Svo 25 6d.
Mscaulav's Critical and Historical Essays.
vols, post Svo. 245.
^^!^Lt'a raftinn 1 vol cr Svo. 85. Cabinet Edition. 4 vols.
Svo. 365.
Library Edition. 3
voScr.8vo. 85.
I

pSpS

BSSon.''2

numerous

Austria. Library Edition, with


Maxwell's (Sir W. S.) Don John of
2 vols. Royal Svo. 425.
Illustrations.
1760-1870. 3 vols, crown Svo. I81.
Constitutional History of England,

0,0

May's

Democracy in Europe.

2 vols. Svo. 325.

12mo. 75. 6d.


^
^^
763-a.d. 476. Crown Svo. 75 6d.
485.
Svo.
post
vols,
Empire.
8
History of the Romans under the
Sassanians. Svo. 285.
Monarchy-The
Oriental
Rawlinson's Seventh Great
Erasmus, & More. Svo. 145.
Seebohm's Oxford Reformer^Colet,
Crown 8vo. 75. U.
England.
of
Church
the
snort's History of
Svo 105.6d.
Crown
Carthaginians.
smith's Carthage and the
bi.
of India. Crown Svo. 75.
History
the
of
Manual
Taylor's
Svo. 65.
Crown
Fox.
James
Charles
of
Twvelyan's Early History
2. 14.
W^^Hi^t^r^ of England, 1815-1841. 3 vols. 8vo.

Merivalc's Fall of the

^ 1

Roman RepubUc.

General History of

Rome,

London,

B.C.

LONGMANS &

CO.

'

BIOGRAPHICAL WORKS.
Bagehot'B Biographical Studies.
Bain's

1 vol.

8vo. 12.

Biography of James Mill. Crown 8vo. Portrait,


5*.
onticism and Recollections of J. S. Mill.
Crown 8vo.

2s. 6d.
Oarlyle'8 Reminiscences, edited by J.
A. Frcude. 2 vols, crown 8vo. 18*.
(Mrs.) Letters and Memorials. 3 vols.
8vo. 36.?
Oates'a Dictionary of General Biography.
Medium 8vo. 28*.
Froude's Luther, a short Biography. Crown
8vo Is

'^^TlTte?"'32f^'

"^^^^ ^ '^ 2, 1795-1835.'

Oleig'8 Life of the

Duke of Wellington. Crown 8vo.


Halliwell-PhiUippe's Outlines of Shakespeare's
Life"
Lecky'3 Leaders of Public Opinion in

8vo

^'^'?-^-'
^^f
Library Edition, T?^2 vols. 8vo. 36.

Marshman's Memoirs

of Havelock.

Mendelssohn's Letters.

7s

Crown

6.

8vo.

Gd
G. Otto Trevelyan,

Edition, 2 vols, ioet

8vo' 3s 6d

Translated by Lady Walla^^e.

Mm s (John Stuart) Autobiography.

and

8vo! 7s 6d.

MP'^ Pon,^*,^^^>-^'''1^"f^^^yo^y ^^ Nephew,


'^'^ ^^^
Cabinet

Svn '19:
8V0.
12i.

Portraits

Qs.

Crown

Ireland.

8vo. with

'

2 vols. or. 8yo. 5s. each.

6d.

7s.

Mozley's Reminiscences of Oriel College.


2 vols.'crown 8vo 18*
Newman's Apologia pro Vita Sua. Crown 8vo. 6j.
Skobeleff & the Slavonic Cause. By
0. K. 8vo. Portrait 14*
Bouthey's Correspondence with Caroline
Bowles. 8vo. 14*
Spedding's Letters and Life of Francis
Bacon. 7 vols. 8vo 4 4*
Stephen's Essays in EcclesiaBtical
Biography.

Crown

8vo. 7s. 6i.

MENTAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY.


*^ Science of Jurisprudence. 8vo. 18*
S*^ ^
Years of the BngUsh Constitution, 1830-1880.
^ty
Crown Svo
Primer
of the English Constitution.
Crown 8vo: 6*.

^'**'^

Bacon's Essays, with Annotations by Whately.


8vo 10* 6d
Promus, edited by Mrs. H. Pott. Svo. 16*
Works, edited by Spedding. 7 vols. 8vo. 73*.
6rf
Bagehot'B Economic Studies, edited by

'

Hutton.

Bain's Logic, Deductive and Inductive.

^^^"'^o"' *'
^ ..l^^"^,^'
Holland
& Lang s Aristotle's Politics.

T,

Part
Crown

Induction,

6*.

M.

Svo. 7* Gd

Greek Text, English Notes.


;
Philosophy of Reflection. 2 vols. Svo. 21*.

Kalisch's Path and Goal.

'

6d

10*

II.

Grant's Ethics of Aristotle

Hodgson

fiA

Svo. 10*. Sd.

Crown Svo

'

10*

'

2 vols Svo 32*

Svo. 12*. Gd.

Essays In Political and Moral Philosophy.


Svo. 10*. Gd.
Lewis on Authority in Matters of Opinion.
Svo. 14*.
Blacaalay's Speeches corrected by Himself.
Crown 8vo 3* Gd
Macleod's Economical Philosophy. Vol. L Svo.
15*.
Vol 11 Part I 12*
Mill's (James) Analysis of the Plienomenaof
the Human Mind. 2'vols!8vo
28*
Mill (John Stuart) on Representative
Government. Crown
Leslie's

Mill's

on Liberty. Crown Svo. 1*. id.


(John Stuart) Dissertations and Discussions.

London,

LONGMANS &

Svo. 2*.

4 vols. Svo. 46*. Gd.

CO.

Mill's

(John Stuart) Essays on Unsettled Questions

Miller's (Mrs.

of Political

8vo.

Economy.

6i. 6d.

of Hamilton's Philosophy. 8vo. 16.


8vo. 25.
Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive. 2 vols.
l vol.
30J.
Principles of PoUtical Economy. 2 vols. Svo.
crown Svo. 6.
Subjection of Women. Crown Svo. 6*.
Utilitarianism. Svo. 5j.
Readings in Social Economy. Cro-mi Svo. 5s.

Examination

Fenwick)

Bandars's Institutes of Justinian, 'with English Notes.


Seebohm's English Village Community. Svo. 165.
SuUy's Outhnes of Psychology. Svo. 12?. Cd.
Swinburne's Picture Logic. Post Svo. os.

Svo. 18j.

Thomson's Outline of Necessary Laws of Thought. Crown Svo. 6i.


vols, crown 870.
Tocqueville's Democracy in America, translated by Reeve. 2
Svo. 21*.
TwlflB'B Law of Nations in Time of War.
it, 5d.
WlateIy'B Elements of Logic. Svo. 10s. 6d. Crown Svo.
Rhetoric. Svo. 10*. 6d. Crown Svo. 4*. 6d.
English Synonymes. Fcp. Svo. 3*.
Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle translated. Crown Svo.

16*,

_ _

7s.

Williams's
History of Eclecticism in (Jreek Philosophy. Crown Svo. 10*.
Plato and the Older Academy. Crown Svo. I85.
Pre-Socratic Schools. 2 vols, crown Svo. 30s.
Crown Svo. lOi. M.
Socrates and the Socratic Schools.
Crown Svo. 16j.
Stoics, Epicureans, and Sceptics.

Zeller'B

6d.

M.

MISCELLANEOUS AND CRITICAL WORKS


Arnold's (Dr. Thomas) Miscellaneous Works. Svo. Is. Sd.
(T.) Manual of English Literature. Crown Svo. 7s. 6d.
Bain's Emotions and the WiU. Svo. 15*.
Mental and Moral Science. Ch-own Svo. lOi. 6d.
Senses and the Intellect. Svo. 15*.
Practical Essays. Crown Svo. 45. 6cl.
Beaconsfield (Lord), The Wit and Wisdom of. Crown Svo. 3*. ed.
(The) Birthday Book. ISmo. 2s. 6c?. cloth 4s. 6d. bound.
6d. each.
Becker's Charicles and Gallut, by Metcalfe. Post Svo. Is.
Is.
6d.
Svo.
Post
Dictionary.
English
Blackley's German and
Posx Svo. 3i. 6d.
Oontanseau's Practical French & EngUsh Dictionary.
Pocket French and English Dictionary. Square 18mo. is. 6d.

Pamir's Language and Languages. Crown Svo. 6*.


10s. M.
French's Nineteen Centuries of Drink in England. Crown Svo.
24*.
Fronde's Short Studies on Great Subjects. 4 vols, crown Svo.
vols. Svo. 36*.
Grant's (Sir A.) Story of the University of Edinburgh. 2
Hobart's Medical Language of St. Luke. Svo. 16s.
Home's Essays, edited by Green & Grose. 2 vols. Svo. 28*.
vols. Svo.
Treatise on Human Nature, edited by Green & Grose. 2
Latham's Handbook of the English Language. Crown Svo. 6*.
4to. 36*.
Liddell & Scott's Greek-English Lexicon.
_ -^ -. - .
Abridged Greek- English Lexicon. Square 12mo. 7*. 6d.
Longman's Pocket German and English Dictionary. ISmo. 5*.

28*.

....

I vol. crown Svo. 4*. 6d.


Macaulay's Miscellaneous Writings. 2 vols. Svo. 21*.
_ _
.
Miscellaneous Writings and Speeches. Crown Svo. 6*.
Rome, dw.
Miscellaneous Writings, Speeches, Lays of Ancient
Cabinet Edition. 4 vols, crown Svo. 24*.

London,

LONGMANS &

CO.

General Lists of Works


Mahafly'B Classical Greek Literature.
Vol. II. the Prose Writers, 75. 6^.

Crown

8vo.

Vol.

I.

the Poets ' 7j 6d

Grammar of Elocution. Fcp. 8vo. 3s. 6d.


Milner's Country Pleasures. Crown 8vo. 6s,

Millard's

MUUer'B (Max) Lectures on the Science of Language. 3 vols,


crown 8vo.
Lectures on India. Svo. 12*. 6d.
Rich's Dictionary of Roman and Greek Antiquities.
Crown Svo. 7$. 6d.

16*.

Rogers's Eclipse of Faith.

Fcp. Svo. 5*.


Defence of the Eclipse of Faith

Roget'B

Theeanms

Selections

of

Fcp. Svo.

EngUsh Words and

Phra-sea.

from the Writings of Lord Macaulay.

SImoox's Latin Literature, 2 vols. Svo. 32^.


Tyndall'B Faraday as a Discoverer. Crown Svo.

Floating Matter of the Air.

Crown

3*. 6cU

Crown Svo. lOi.


Crown Svo. 6#.

3*.

6d.

6d.

Svo. 7s. 6d.

Fragments of Science. 2 vols, post Svo. 16<.


Heat a Mode of Motion. Crown Svo. 12*.
Lectures on Light delivered in America, Crown Svo.

7i. 6d.

Lessons in Electricity.

Crown Svo. 2s. 6d.


Notes on Electrical Phenomena. Crown Svo. 1<. sewed, Is.
6d. cloth.
Notes of Lectures on Light. Crown Svo. 1*. sewed, 1*. 6d. cloti.
Bound, with Frontispiece

Von Cotta on Rocks, by Lawrence.

&

203 Woodcuts.
Post Svo. 14*.

Cro\vn Svo. 10*. 6d.

White & Riddle's Large Latin-English Dictionary. 4to. 21*.


White's Concise Latin-English Dictionary. Royal Svo. 12*.
Junior Student's Lat.-Eng. and Eng.-Lat. Dictionary. Sq.
12mo. 5*.
?^5"s^-I^ Dictionary, 36.
Separately
JJ^ Latin-English Dictionary,
' jI The
3^.
Wit and Wisdom of the Rev. Sydney Smith, Crown Svo. 3*. 6d.
Witt's Myths of Hellas, translated by F. M.
Younghusband. Crown Svo. '3*. 6i.
The Trojan War. Fcp. Svo. 2.s-.
Wood's Bible Animals. With 112 Vignette^. Svo. lOt. 6d.

Common

British Insects. Crown 8vo. 3,?. 6d.


Homes Without Hands. Svo. 10*. 6d. Insect* Abroad. Svo. 10*.
Insects at Home. With 700 lUustrationa. Svo.
10*. 6d.
Out of Doors. Crown Svo. 6*.
Petland Revisited. Crown Svo. 7s. 6d.
Strange DwelUngs. Crown Svo. 5.. Popular Edition,
4to. 6d.

Gd.

Yonge's Knglish-Greek Lexicon. Square 12mo. 8*. 6d. 4to.


21*.
The Essays and Contributions of A. K. H. B. Crown Svo.
Autumn Holidays of a Country Parson. 3*. 6d.
Changed Aspects of Unchanged Truths. 3*. 6d.
Common-place Philosopher in Town and Country. 8*. M.
Counsel and Comfort spoken from a City Pulpit. 3*.
6d
Critical Essays of a Country Parson.
8*. 6d.
Graver Thoughte of a Country Parson. Three Series, 3*.
6d. each.
Landscapes, Churcnes, and Moralities. 3*. 6d.
Leisure Hours in Town. 3*. 6d. Lessons of Middle
Age. 3*. 6d
Our Little Life. Essays Consolatory and Domestic. 3*.
6d
Present-day Thoughts. 3*. 6d.
Recreations of a Country Parson. Three Series, 3*. 6d.
each.
Seaside Musings on Sundays and Week-Days.
3*. 6<i.
Sunday Afternoons in the Parish Church of a University City.
3*. 6d.

London,

LONGMANS &

CO.

General Lists of Works.

ASTRONOMY, METEOROLOGY, GEOGRAPHY,


8vo. 3l5.
Freeman's Historical Geography of Europe. 2 vols.
8vo. 12*.
Herschel's Outlines of Astronomy. Square crown

&c.

6d.
.

General Gazetteer. 8vo. 42*.


Keith Johnston's Dictionary of Geography, or
8vo. 5.J.
Merrifield's Treatise on Navigation. Crown
6d.
Nelson's Work on the Moon. Medium 8vo. 31*.
ri.^,^ b in. ,?
Proctor's Moon. Crown 8vo. lOi. 6i.
Proctor'B Essays on Astronomy. 8vo. 12*.
ba.
12*.
only,
or
Maps
15*.
Folio,
Atlas.
Larger Star
Myths and Marvels of Astronomy. Crown 8vo. 6*. Crown 8vo.
7*. d.
Star Atlas. Crown 8vo. 5*. Orbs Around Us.

New

Other Worlds than Ours. Crown 8vo. 10*. 6(i.


6<f.
Sun. Crown 8vo. 145. Universe of Stars. 8vo.l0*.
Venus-Transits, 8vo.
Transits of Venus, 8vo. 8*. 6d. Studies of
,
Smith's Air and Rain. 8vo. 24*.
Imperial 8vo. 7*. ea.
The Public Schools Atlas of Ancient Geography. Imperial 8vo. 5*.
Modern Geography.

Webb's

Celestial Objects for

Common

NATURAL HISTORY

Telescopes.
8c

Crown

6*.

8vo. 9*.

POPULAR SCIENCE.

'.

and their Pedigrees. Crown 8vo. Woodcuts, 7*. Gd.


8vo. 12*. Bd.
of Physics or Natural Philosophy. Crown
Elements
Ar
8vo. 63i.
medium
vols,
Art.
and
3
Literature,
Science,
Brande's Dictionary of
of Botany. Imperial 8vo. 81*. 6d.
Decaisne and Le Maout's General System
Allen's Flowers
lOtt's

lUustrations, 5*.
Dixon's Rural Bird Life. Crown 8vo.
Edmonds's Elementary Botany. Fcp. 8vo. 2*.
8vo. 25*.
Evans's Bronze Implements of Great Britain.
crown 8vo. 15#.
Elementary Treatise on Physics, by Atkinson. Large
Gftnot'B

Natural Philosophy, by Atkinson. Crown 8vo.


8vo. 6*.
Goodeve's Elements of Mechanism. Crown
Principles of Mechanics. Crown 8vo. Gs.

7*. 6d.

8vo. 16*.
Grove's Correlation of Physical Forces.
Polar World. 8vo. 10*. 6d.
Hartwig's Aerial World. 8vo. 10*. Cd.
Sea and its Living Wonders. 8vo. 10*. 6d.
8vo. 10*.
Subterranean World. 8vo. 10*. 6d. Tropical World.
8vo. 15*.
Haughtcn's Six Lectures on Physical Geography.

M.

2 vols. 8vo. 12*.


Beer's Primieval World of Switzerland.
Subjects. 2 vols. cr. 8vo. 7* 6d. each.
Helmholtz'8 Lectures on Scientific
of Modern Music. 8vo. 8*. 6d.
Hullah's Lectures on the History
Transition Period of Musical Historj. 8vo. 10*. 6d.
Crown Svo. Ss. 6d.
Jones's The Health of the Senses.
by Lee. 2 vols, royal 8vo. 42*.
Keller's Lake DweUings of Switzerland,
Lloyd's Treatise on Magnetism. 8vo. 10*. 6d.
Loudon's Bncyclopffidia of Plants. 8vo. 42*.
8vo. ir,
18*.
Man. o
Lubbock on the Origin of Civilisation & Prunitive Cordition of
6d.
Animals.
10*.
8vo.
Vertebrate
of
Morphology
Zoology and

MacaUster's
Puzzle of Life.

Nicolfl'

Crown

Svo.

3*. 6d.

Owen's Comparative Anatomy and Physiology


8vo. 73*. 6d.

.......

.
,
,
, ^,
of the Vertebrate Animals. 8 volt.

Experimental Physiology. Crown 8vo. 5*.


Hours. 3 Series, crown 8vo.
Proctor's Light Science for Leisure
Edition. Crown 8vo. 5*.
RIvers's Orchard House. Sixteenth
Rose Amateur's Guide. Fcp. 8vo. 4*. 6d.

Stanley's Familiar History of British Birds.


Swinton's Electric Lighting I ts Principles
:

London,

Crown

8yo.

6d. each.

6*.

and Practice.

LONGMANS &

7*.

CO.

Crown

Svo. 5*.

General Lists of Works.

THE 'KNOWLEDGE' LIBRARY,


Edited by Richard A. Proctoi!.

The Borderland

The Poetry

of

By R A. P.octor. Crown Svo.


R. A. Proctor. Crown Svo. 6s.

of Science.

Scienc3Bjway3.

By

Astronomy.

Cro^ Svt'e^"^'^'

Tlie stars in their Seasons.

By

R. A. Proctor.

'^'"^ ''''''''''''

By

6s.

Crown Svo. 6..


^' ^^-^ ^"-' ^^-- ^-

R. A. Proctor.

Imperial Svo.

6*.

CHEMISTRY AND PHYSIOLOGY.


Buckton'B Healtli in the House, Lectures
on Elementary Physiology. Cr
Svo is
s Inorganic Chemistry,
Theoretical and Practical. Fop Svo 2s
Ko be Short Text-Book of Inorganic Chemistry.
Crown Svo. 7.*. 6d
Mill^B Baements of Chemistry, Theoretical
and Practical. 8 vols 8vo Part T

Jago

fl

^^^^SS&i^''- ^^^^^^- Chemist^/jJ/fart^Yl. o^g^

^'IIaU.^^T"'''^

Chemistry.

Fcp. Svo.

Pt.

I.

1,.

Tilden's Practical Chemistry. Fcp.


Svo. 1* 6d
Wattfl'B Dictionary of Chemistry.
9
vols,

m'ediim Svo. 15.

THE FINE ARTS AND ILLUSTRATED


Dresser's Arts

6d.

Pt. II. 2s.

6A

2s. 6d.

EDITIONS.

and Art Manufactures of Japan.

Square crown Svo. 31* 6d


2 vols, crown Svo 16*

Eaatlake's (Lady) Five Great Painters.


Notes on the Brera Gallery, Milan.
Crown Svo. 5*
Notes on the i^ouvre Gallery, Paris.
Crown Svo. 7*. 6d
Hulme's Art-Instruction iu England. Fcp. Svo.
3*.

6c?.

Jameson's Sacred and Legendary Art.

L^ends

of the

~ ~

6 vols, square
1 vol. 2ls.
Orders. 1 vol. 21i.

Madonna.
Monastic

crown

Saints and Martyrs. 2 vols." 31*.


6d
Saviour. Completed by Lady EasUake.

Svo.

2 vols iSs

Macaulay's Lays of Ancient Rome. iUustrated


by Scharf. Fcp. 4to. 10* 6d.
The same, with Ivry and the Armada, iUustrated
by Weguelin. Crown Svo. 3* 6d
Macfarren's Lectures on Harmony. Svo. 12*.
Moore's Irish Melodies. With 161 Plates by
D. Maclise, R.A.

LallaRookh,

illustrated

by Tennicl.

New Testament
Masters.

Super-royal Svo "'*


11.

Square crown Svo

lo7^

'

(The) illustrated with Woodcuts aft^r Poinf{r, u' ^C


^^^^tmgs by the Barly
4to. 21.?. clatb, or 42*. moroSo

Perry on Greek and Roman Sculpture.


Wood. Square crown Svo. 81*. 6d

London,

With 2Rn" lUustrationa


Tiii,a+,o*i^
engraved on

LONGMANS &

CO.

General Lists of Works.

THE USEFUL ARTS. MANUFACTURES.


Steam Engine.
Bourne's Oatechism of the

Fcp. Svo.

Gas Engines.
Examples of Steam, Air, and
Engine. Fcp. 8vo.
Steam
the
of
Handbook
the Steam Engme.
Recent Improvements in
4to.42<.
Engine.
Steam
the
on
Treatise

_
~

6*.

4to. 70i.
9*.

Fcp. Svo.

8vo. 25*.
of Civil Engineering.
Cresy's Encyclopedia
16*.
Practical Telegraphy. 8vo.
of
Handbook
Gnlley's
Square
Taste in Furniture, &e.

iSe^Household

^Ss

3 vols,

Engineers.
Useful information for

ScC

6i.

crown 8vo 14,


crown 8yo. 31,. 6d,

1 vol. 8vo. 25,.


8vo. 52,. 6d.
Architecture.
Qwilt's Encyclopaedia of
19*.
and Rbhng. 3 vols. 8vo. 4.
Metallurgy, adapted by Grookes
Agriculture. 8vo. 21,.
Loudon's Encyclopaedia of
Gardening. 8vo. 21,.

__

Mills

and Millwork.

__

Assaying. 8vo. 31,. 6d.


MltchelTs Manual of Practical
^^''
Northoott's Lathes and T^^^^g-^.f^^;
p^,
Edited by B. H. Paul, i-n.u.

p^^

Paven's Industrial Chemistry

42,.
gvo. **
Jo-

Square crown 8vo. 21,.


Perfumery. Fourth Editx^on.
Ste^Engne^
Marine
Bennett's Treatise on the
voia. medium 8vo. 7.7,.
^^s. Tvo^'

Sst"f

Manufactures, &.
Ure's Dictionary of Arts,
Manures. By Crookes, 8vo.

on

Ville

Artificial

2U

RELIGIOUS AND MORAL WORKS.


Ahbev

&

the Rev. C. P. Eden.

Calvert's Wife's Manual.

10 vols. 8vo. 5.

Crown

5*.

8vo. 6s.

MoaMte Stone.
Crown 8vo.

the
Si^tTlSSi^ '^^Pelteuo. andJhna

SS oX

Pentateuch and Book oj


ot the Bible. Poet 8vo.
Handbook
Oondert

7..

'1^{eSSe'&o?:v!?th*'a ^^iction

'udS?rESS,'r:^S''and

8,0.

__

ot Mape,

Map., I-ndpe. .

Pla^, and Woodcnf.

.d Map..
oondeneed, with 46 Ulnetration,

O.lS^o'^^i^tT.'lpa^a-.in.the^^o^a^^^^

ot the ^ew Te^ten'^


Davidson's-Introdnetion to the Study
Messiah. 2 vols. STO.
the
Jesus
ot
Times
and
Lite

Edersheim-s

London,

1^

6,.

M.

^^SSf Sot'^i^^aS't^'S^^a' iSaon,,


'

36,.
2 vols. 8vo.

the Eighteenth Century.


Overton's English Churchin

LONGMANS &

CO.

'

fKZ;&S. ?^SiTS: 6'^

J-hUippia.,.

'"

CCcelins and

Ellicotfs Lectures on the Life Of


our Lord. 8vo 12<
Bwald's Antiquities of Israel, translated
by SoUy. 8vo. 12* 6d
of Israel, translated by Carpenter
& Smith. 6 vols. 8vo. 79*.
OnZ.1 (The) for the Nineteenth
08pel
Century. 4th Edition. Svo. 10*. 6d.
Hopkins s Christ the Consoler. Fcp.
8vo. 2*. 6d
Jukes's New Man and the Eternal
Life.
Crown 8vo. 6*.
Second Death and the Restitution of all
Thinga. Crown 8vo. 3* d
Types of Genesis. Crown 8vo. 7*. 6<i.
Kaliflch'B Bible Studies.
Part L the Prophecies of Balaam. 8vo. 10*.
6d.
^^"^ ^' *^ ^^ * Jonah. Svo. 10*. 6cZ.
~~
IT-

^!^^7

N. J'^^*'^
tt't
*

To IV

Critical

Commentary on

ihe Old Testament; with a


''' ^^ ^'^^'^ ^^ ^^^^"

'''''

HeLer^2!
Vol

^d

^1f or adapts

J
Vi^

V^l II^^'
'd
";,^^^^"''

^"^

;
^^''

'

1^'-

'

"^P^^

'^'' ^

for the General Reader. 12*.


t^ C^eneiBl Reade
8*
.

^^

"* ^"- ^ ^^^^^^^ ^^ '^' G^e^eral Reader. 8*.


Keary s Outlines
Kear^'s
O,^;
?S'
of
Primitive Belief. 8vo 18*
Ljja Germanica Hymns translated
by Miss Wink^Torth. Fcp. Svo.
5*
:

^^^^^" '' *^^ ^^y G^^*- Crown Svc^S*.


6^
Martineau's Endeavours after the
Christian Life. Crown Svo. 7* d
Hymns of Praise and Prayer. Crown Svo. 4*.
6d. 82mo. 1* 6d
Sermons. Hours of Thought on Sacred
Things. 2 vols. 7*' 6d each
M.n."~T..
Mill
B Three Essays on
Religion. Svo. 10* 6d

M^r/ ^T'"'
.

^^'

^"^*^" *"^ Holidays. Fcp. Svo. 5*


of Religion.
Crown 8vo 7c ej!
Science of Religion. Crown Svo.
7s. Sd
Newman a Apologia pro Vita Sua. Crown
Svo. 6*
SeweU's (Miss) Pacing Thoughts on
Religion. Fcp. Svo. 3*. 6d.
Preparation for the Holy Communion.
32mo.

^hIT^"'',,?^^^"*^
MUlIer's (Max) Origin

"

^^'^

& Growth

c
Seymour's Hebrew Psalter. Crown
Svo.
Smith's Voyage and Shipwreck
,

Wha tely's

3*.

Complete Edition.

Crown Svo. 7* 6d.


3 vols. 8vo. 36*.

Lessons on the Christian Evidences.


18mo. 6d
White's Four Gospels in Greek,
with Greek-EngUsh Lexicon.

TRAVELS, VOYAGES,
Aldridge's

Ranch Notes

'

6d

2*.

of St. Paul.

Supernatural Religion.

ISmo f

in Kansas, Co:oraaa, &c.

Baker's Eight Years in Ceylon.


Crown Svo.
-Rifle and Hound in Ceylon.

Crown

32mo.

6*.

See.

Crown Svo

5,

6*.

Svo.

5.-.

aH"v^- ^^^-- - r 1^-k-^A^tr^- - w-m

BaU on Alpine

Travelling, and on the Geology


of the Alps 1*.
Sunshine and Storm In the East.
Crown Svo 7* ed
Voyage in the Yacht 'Sunbeam.' Crown
Svo 7s R,i
fcp. Svo. 2*.
Popular Edition, 4to. 6d.
Cra^N-ford's Across the Pampas
and the An.les.

Brassey

Crown

London,

LONGMANS &

Svo.

CO.

7.-.

q^>,~vi
^^*^^

U.

r-^v*
Edition,

General Lists of Works.

10

Crown 8vo.
Freeman's Impressions of the United States of America.
55.
8vo.
Crown
considered.
Climatically
Hassall's San Remo
lUustrations. 7 J. 6i.
Miner's Wintering in the Riviera. Post 8vo.
The Alpine Club Map of Switzerland. In Four Sheets. 42*.
Three in Norway.

By Two

of

Them.

Crown

WORKS OF

8vo. Illustrations,

6s.

Gs.

FICTION.

S^^^. ,
Brabourne's (Lord) Higgledy-Piggledy. Crow 8^0;
6<i.
Whispers from Fairy Land. Crown 8vo. 6t.
Beaconsfield, K.G.
Edition of Novels and Tales by the Earl of

11 vols.

Cabinet

Crown 8vo. cloth extra,


Tales by Miss SeweU.
:
each
gilt edges, price 3. 6d.
A Glimpse of the World.
Amy Herbert. Cleve Hall.
Katharine Ashton.
The Earl's Daughter.
Laneton Parsonage.
Experience of Life.
Ursula.
Margaret Percival.
Ctertrude. Ivors.
Lang. 2 vols, crown 8vo. lis
Andrew
Mrs.
By
Novel.
A
View?.
Dissolving
E.G. Hughenden Edition with 2
Novels and Tales by the Earl of Beaconsfield,
11 vols crown 8vo. 2 2^
Wood.
on
Vignettes
11
^""^fo^aZonsdei and

OabiS7dfJon^?1tSrir and

crown 8vo.
Novelist's Library. Each Work
clotn :
complete in itself, price 2*. boards, or 2s. 6d.

The Modem

By Major

Earl of Beaconsfield, K.G.


Coningsby.
Sybil. Tancred.
Venetia. Henrietta Temple.
Contarini Fleming.
Alroy, Ixion, &c.
The Young Duke, &o.
Vivian Grey. Endymion.

By the

Bret Harte.
In the Carquinez Woods.

By

Mrs. Oliphant.
In Trust, the Story of a
and her Lover.

By Anthony

Single

Vomme,

Whyte-Melville.

Digby Grand.

Lothair.

By

General Bounce.
Kate Coventry.

The Gladiators.
Good for Nothing.
Holmby House.
The Interpreter.
The Queen's Maries.

By
Lady

Trollope.

Various Writers.
The Atelier du Lye.
Atherstone Priory.
The Burgomaster's Family.
Elsa and her Vulture.
Mademoiselle Mori.

The Six

Barchester Towers.

Sisters of the Valleys.

Unawares.
Mori.' Crown 8vo.
Mademoiselle
of
Author
the
In the Olden Time. By
G^.
8vo.
Crown
Thicker than Water. By James Payn.

6i

'

POETRY AND THE DRAMA.


12i. 6d.
BaUey's Festus, a Poem. Crown 8vo.
oi.
8vo. Us. 6 vols. fcp. 8vo. 21i.
Bowdler's Family Shakspeare. Medium
translated. 8vo. 12*. 6*.
Cayley's Iliad of Homer, Homomctrically
English Verse. Crown Svo.
into
Oonington's ^neid of VirgU, translated
Crown 8vo.95.
Prose Translation of Virgil's Poems.

Large crown Svo. 12*. 6d.


Goethe's Faust, translated by Birds.
translated by Webb. 8vo. 12*. 6d.

edited

by

Selss.

London,

Crown

8vo. 5.

LONGMANS &

CO.

9i.

General lists of Works.


Hom.s

IW.

11

-ekTc.xtwahYerseT,an,tat,onbyW.C.Grea.

iDgelow-s Poem..

New

BditiOB.

T, i

cown

vob. (cp. 8to. 12,

"'"%%.r*'-> --'r^tfo:;. 'rvor:-r^:;rSonthey's Poetical Works.

Medium

8vo. 14,.

RURAL SPORTS, HORSE AND


CATTLE ''^''^^^'^^NT,
MANAPPMpm-t

Dead Shot (The), by Marksman.


Crow. 8vo. lo/e,
Jitzwygram's Horses and Stables.
8vo. IO5 6cf

Miles 8 Horse's Foot, and


Plain Treatise on

How to Keen i*

Remarks on Horses' Teeth.

--

Stables

Milner'fl

~~

Work on
--

Ox a Manoi

the Dog.

WORKS OF

Crown8vo.6,.
^f

\,

8vo. 6s'

Horse.

8vo.

UTILITY

7,. 6d.

AND GENERAL INFORMATION


^^^^^

Acton's Modern Cookery for


Private Families.

Bnckton's Pood and Home


Cookerjr. Crown
BuU on the Maternal Management
of pmm

Burtons

My Home Fa.

Fcp 8vo

8vot

4,

a,

fi^ '

t,

^In Z^',. Z^' "- " '*

Longman's Chess Openings.


Fcp.8vo.2,W
Macleod's Elements of Banking.
Fourth E^tion.

'^' '''' '''

pLsTue'd
8vo.T

Hteel s Diseases of the

Youatt's

and Stable-Fittings.
Imperial 8vo 15,
Country Pleasures. Crown

M. r^^'*^^^^-

qnnn

Ho.^-sSg ^"t Svo T?.^

0'

Economics.
^rf
Theory and
Banking.

'

Crown 8vo

. vols, small

'

Practice of

Loudon,

^^^-

^^'O.

U.

6,

crowL sTo. Vo^ I 7, .


^*^'
2 vols. 8vo.
Vol.1 12.

LONGMANS &

CO.

8cC.

8730M
Fop. 8vo

Treasury.
Sannaer-S BiograpMcal

6..

Hi.toyFcp.8vo^::
i^v>^ ' Natural
Game
3^eut^^
Modern
Pol^B Theory ol the

a I*P^^ i!'^^^^^
THo Cabinet Lawy^,

. ,,.

'
.

,^ ^

vols.

M>.

gvo. 2l5.

JOHN HULUAH,
MUSICAL WORKS BY

LL.D.

oloth

Hullah-=Meth^o.Te.l^g^^|ing^Xoa^e1;orl..M.^
Large

Slioote.opnWiimgtt'6Bx^^eoli.

r^lS^^^^l-^-

B.al8vo.prioo...ewo.au......clot.;

^,^ of counterpoint. "'^"''J .V each or together,


^'^" '^T^JL^'iSJTf^I-^ n. o, WUhe.. Manual.

or

5..

erf.

Boo..

-~"'-"^'
r^SSC^ontah..-^
Wnhn.
^^??S*.'
'

^^^^,

wx

Hymns for the young,


infant Scho^Song^ 6^^

,^ Bxerd^s

in part 1.0.

"

Ay

Crown 8vo6d.

^ o^iged. Qd.
for
Old BngUsh Songs
^^^' f "^0,^1 8vo. 3*.

Musical
Notation, tte

of MuBicaiar^^.
f^^^i^, g.^. each 6<i.
for 3 Mid 3 yoi^3.J^
Songs
School
Mu^^^^^gvo. 8.. 6d.
o^^odem
S-^o?
^.^^^^^ ^^^^ ,0. 6d.
Lectures on the
o
Transition Penoa
Lectures on the

Rudiments

London.

LONGMANS &

CO.

Zeller E. Socrates and the Socratic


Schools, (tr. by Heichel)

LIBRARY

r"^
Ef>ntifical

Institute

113 ST.

TORONTO,

of Med;ae^'c^l %fu<i\ei

J03EPM

ONT.,

:-J7

CANADA

^678

u.

Potrebbero piacerti anche