Sei sulla pagina 1di 20

REVISITING WITTGENSTEIN ON KHLER AND GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY

JOHN G. BENJAFIELD
In an article in this journal, Nicholas Pastore rejected Ludwig Wittgensteins critique of
Wolfgang Khler and Gestalt psychology. Pastore appears not to have appreciated
Wittgensteins argument that Khler mistook conceptual questions for factual ones. A simi-
lar confusion seems to underlie at least some aspects of contemporary neuroscience. Be that
as it may, Wittgenstein has had minimal influence on the research practices of psychologists
while Khler remains influential. This outcome would not have surprised Wittgenstein, who
predicted that scientists would not see his work as relevant to theirs. 2008 Wiley
Periodicals, Inc.
Nicholas Pastore (19161998) was a deeply knowledgeable student of the psychology of
perception (Winnick, 2001). His history of the nativism-empiricism controversy in perception
(Pastore, 1971) has been cited continuously since its publication (e.g., Allik & Konstabel,
2005). Pastore (1991) published an article in this journal considering some of Ludwig
Wittgensteins (18891951) remarks on Wolfgang Khler (18871967) and Gestalt psychol-
ogy. Pastores paper was an important illustration of the way in which Wittgensteins philoso-
phy has tended to be assimilated by those psychologists who have taken an interest in it.
PASTORES CRITIQUE OF WITTGENSTEIN
Pastore focused on Wittgensteins treatment of reversible figures such as the famous
duck-rabbit (Figure 1; Brugger, 1999; Kihlstrom, 2006), versions of the Necker cube (Figures 2
and 3) and the double cross (Figure 4). Figures such as these were used by Wittgenstein to
illustrate how seeing a figure in one way (e.g., as a duck) can change into another way of see-
ing the same figure (e.g., as a rabbit). Pastore observed that Khler did not think that sensory
organization was determined by learning in any essential way. By contrast, we have
Wittgensteins (1958, p. 207) statement that you only see the duck rabbit aspects if you are
already conversant with the shape of those two animals. Pastore (1991, p. 349) concluded
that Wittgenstein did not fully appreciate Khlers rejection of empiricism, and that
Wittgensteins objections to Khler . . . are . . . unfounded.
Pastore did not claim that Khler was a nativist, as indeed he should not. The Gestalt
psychologists were not nativists (Henle, 1977/1986). As Pastore (1971, p. 269) correctly
observed, the Gestalt psychologists were opposed to both nativism and empiricism as these
terms are usually understood. For them, perceptual organization is governed by the same laws
that regulate all phenomena and does not require an evolutionary explanation. From
the standpoint of physics one feels at once inclined to conceive of the processes underlying
perception as a dynamic pattern that comes into existence in some field of the brain (Khler,
1930/1971a, p. 240).
Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, Vol. 44(2), 99118 Spring 2008
Published online in Wiley Interscience (www.interscience.wiley.com). DOI 10.1002/jhbs.20301
2008 Wiley Periodicals, Inc.
99
JOHN G. BENJAFIELD is Professor Emeritus at Brock University, St. Catharines, Ontario. His research
interests have included aesthetics, the history of the English language, and personal cognition. Both his
History of Psychology (2nd ed., 2005) and Cognition (3rd ed., 2007) were published by Oxford University
Press. Send correspondence to John Benjafield, 83 Glenridge Avenue, St. Catharines, ON, L2R 4X2,
Canada, (905) 6856039. E-mail: John.Benjafield@BrockU.Ca
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 99
a
a a
b b
b b
a
100 JOHN G. BENJAFIELD
As the preceding quotation shows, Khler believed that psychological facts have physio-
logical correlates, a notion that Pastore says is supported by a considerable body of evidence
(p. 343). Most neuropsychologists would surely agree, but Wittgenstein (1980a, p. 160) won-
dered, Why should there not be a psychological regularity to which no physiological regular-
ity corresponds? By asking such a question, said Pastore (1991, p. 343), Wittgenstein had
engaged in magical thinking.
Generally speaking, Pastore did not think much of Wittgensteins remarks, observing
that Wittgenstein does not formulate an explicit theory of seeing, and there is no appeal to
the empirical investigations by psychologists and physiologists (1991, p. 344). Moreover,
the systematic exposition of an argument is absent and the justification or intended signifi-
cance of some remark is not evident (1991, p. 343). Finally, Wittgensteins philosophy of
psychology expresses a pronounced hostility toward psychology as a science. This is evident
in his unusual ideas about physiological explanation (1991, p. 343).
Pastores view of Wittgenstein was particularly striking because it came from someone
steeped in the tradition of experimental psychology and contrasted sharply with the views of
many of those whose backgrounds were in philosophy. Indeed, Pastore (1991, p. 351) appeared
to discount the objections of Wittgensteinian philosophers (e.g., Budd, 1989; Stromberg,
1980) to Khlers psychology because they were philosophical.
One purpose of the present paper is to see if there might not be more to the philosophical
critique of Khler than Pastore allowed. In particular, recent scholarship on both Wittgenstein and
Gestalt psychology allows us to better appreciate the breadth and complexity of Wittgensteins
analysis. Pastore focused on the contrasting approaches to reversible figures taken by
Wittgenstein and Khler. We will also consider their contrasting approaches to memory (Bennett
& Hacker, 2003, p. 161f; Hark, 1995; Schulte, 1992, p. 114f). These two topics are intertwined.
Finally, we will consider the possibility that Wittgensteins famous remark about psychologys
barrenness may have been justified.
Wittgenstein was not hostile toward psychological science as such (e.g., Hark, 1990,
1995). Indeed, while a student at Cambridge, Wittgenstein collaborated on an experiment on
the perception of rhythm that he presented to a meeting of the British Psychological Society
in 1912 (McGuinness, 1990, p. 128). However, he did not think that Gestalt psychology in
general and Khlers research program in particular were going in fruitful directions.
Moreover, Wittgensteins attitude toward Gestalt psychology was colored by his profound pes-
simism about the drift of modern times, particularly with respect to its scientism (Monk,
1991, pp. 484486). Wittgenstein took scientism to be the smug and unexamined assurance
that what wants explanation is obvious, and that scientific tools are immediately applicable.
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
Figures 1 (the duck-rabbit), 2 and 3 (versions of the Necker cube), and 4 (the double cross). From N. Pastore.
(1991). Wittgenstein on Khler and Gestalt psychology. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 27, 344.
(1) (2)
(4)
(3)
FIGURES. 14
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 100
For Wittgenstein, scientism is just as misguidedly metaphysical as traditional, more transpar-
ently a prioristic, approaches (Goldfarb, 1989, p. 637).
It may seem odd for Gestalt psychology to be construed as scientistic, since many psy-
chologists of the day did not even think it was scientific (e.g., Watson, 1930/1962, p. 1).
However, the Gestalt psychologists attempts to extend the reach of science to cover every
conceivable aspect of human affairs including aesthetic and other values (e.g., Khler,
1938/1959) allowed it to be seen as scientistic (Harrington, 1996, p. 123). Although some as-
pects of Gestalt psychology may have been attractive to Wittgenstein (Hark, 1995), its scien-
tistic aspects provided a natural target for him.
WITTGENSTEINS CONNECTIONS TO KHLER AND THE BERLIN SCHOOL OF
GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY
Khler, Max Wertheimer (18801943), and Kurt Koffka (18861941) were the triumvi-
rate most closely identified with what came to be called the Berlin school of Gestalt psy-
chology. Khler was appointed director of the Psychological Institute there in 1922 (Ash,
1995, p. 203). According to Hark (1995, p. 116), Wittgenstein was familiar with several of
Khlers works, including The Mentality of Apes (1927/1956), Gestalt Psychology (1947), The
Place of Value in a World of Facts (1938/1959), and Dynamics in Psychology (1940/1960).
Hallet (1977, p. 691) suggested that Wittgenstein may also have read Koffkas (1935)
Principles of Gestalt Psychology. Whether Wittgenstein ever read anything by Wertheimer is
unknown, but it would not be surprising if he had not, since Wertheimer did not publish a
great deal during his lifetime.
If we only consider Wittgensteins connections to Khler and Koffka, we can easily see
that they shared quite a bit of common ground. A complete investigation of their mutual ac-
quaintances would go beyond the scope of this paper, but the following examples will suffice.
Each example is already well known, but they have not heretofore been presented as a whole.
Moritz Schlick (18821936) and Khler were both students of the physicist Max Planck
(18581947) at the University of Berlin. Schlick completed his dissertation under Plancks
supervision in 1904. Although Khler considered taking a degree in physics (Ash, 1995, p. 113),
he ended up completing his dissertation in psychoacoustics under Carl Stumpf (18481936) in
1909. Schlick became professor of the philosophy of the inductive sciences at the University
of Vienna in 1922 (Mulder & Velde-Schlick, 1979, p. xi). Schlick contributed to the Gestalt
psychologists journal, Psychologische Forschung (Ash, 1995, p. 217), and was supportive of
Gestalt psychology, saying that as to the psychological concept formation, it seems to me
beyond doubt that a holistic mode of presentation, such as that championed by Gestalt
psychology is the only promising one (Schlick, 1935/1979, p. 398).
Koffka completed his degree with Stumpf in 1908 and was briefly one of Oswald Klpes
(18621915) research assistants in Wrzburg in 1909 (Ash, 1995, p. 110). Karl Bhler
(18791963), who came to Wrzburg in 1905 (Eschbach, 1990, p. xviii), was also one of
Klpes research assistants (Weimer, 1974, p. 250). Bhler and his wife Charlotte Malachowski
Bhler (18931974) later became prominent members of the Viennese psychological scene,
with Karl becoming the Director of the Psychological Institute there in 1922 (Ash, 1987;
Brock, 1994).
In 1927, Schlick and Karl and Charlotte Bhler were invited to tea by Wittgensteins sis-
ter Margarete Stonborough (18821958), in order to be introduced to Wittgenstein (Engelmann,
1967, p. 188). For a picture of the sumptuous surroundings within which tea was taken, see
Wijdeveld (2000, p. 69). Schlick, who would become widely known as the leader of the
REVISITING WITTGENSTEIN ON KHLER 101
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 101
Vienna Circle group of philosophers of science, had long been desirous of such a meeting
because of the impression that Wittgensteins (1922/1977a) Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
had made on him (McGuinness, 1967, pp. 146147). Wittgenstein subsequently agreed to
meet with Schlick and a few other members of the Circle on a regular basis (Carnap,
1964/1967; Monk, 1991, p. 243).
Thus, Khler is connected to Wittgenstein through Planck and Schlick, and Koffka is
connected to Wittgenstein through Klpe and Bhler. Obviously, one does not have to play
Six Degrees of Ludwig Wittgenstein (cf. Guare, 1990) for very long in order to connect
Khler and Koffka to Wittgenstein. At most it requires two intermediaries to connect them.
By comparison with many other social networks, Khler, Koffka, and Wittgenstein belonged
to a very small world (Travers & Milgram, 1969; Watts, 2004; Watts & Strogatz, 1998) even
if they may not have known each other directly.
The Wrzburg Experiments and Wittgenstein
The connections among Klpe, Karl Bhler, and Wittgenstein are worth elaborating
further. Together with other members of the Wrzburg group, Klpe was responsible for con-
ducting experiments in which participants were given tasks after which they reported the
experiences they had while carrying them out (e.g., K. Bhler, 1908/1951; Klpe, 1912/1964).
Such experiments might require the participant to come up with the meaning of a word, for
example. The experiences that participants reported were far from being clear and distinct.
Often they were accompanied by no imagery whatsoever, and the participant could say little
if anything about them. What the participants were able to report did not lend itself to a
straightforward categorization of mental contents. Rather, the processes involved in thinking
are not amenable to any clear-cut classification, but actually consist of experience types merg-
ing one into the other with no clear line of demarcation (Humphrey, 1951/1963, p. 42).
Among other things, this made it difficult to see how any theory of linguistic meaning could
be tied directly to some sort of inner process.
Bartley (1985) and Bloor (1983) concurred that Wittgenstein made use of the Wrzburg
experiments in his later philosophy. Bloor (1983, p. 16) observed that Wittgenstein (1969,
pp. 155156) described a procedure very similar to a Wrzburg experiment in which a per-
son is given words from a variety of categories (e.g., house, dynamo) and asked to indicate in
each case whether or not the word was understood. The person then tried to describe the ex-
periences that accompanied the process of understanding or the lack of it. This description
followed closely that given by Klpe (1912/1964, pp. 209210) of the experimental procedure
that came to be called retrospection. In commenting on the results of such a procedure,
Wittgenstein (1969, p. 156) noted that it will elicit a wide variety of experiences including a
large class of cases in which I remember experiences (sensations, thoughts) which, as I should
say, had nothing to do with the word at all. In another context, Wittgenstein (1974, p. 45) stated
flatly that The psychological processes which are found by experience to accompany sentences
are of no interest to us.
GOETHE, WITTGENSTEIN, AND GESTALT THEORY
Scientific questions may interest me, but they never really grip me. Only conceptual &
aesthetic questions have that effect on me. At bottom it leaves me cold whether scientific
problems are solved; but not those other questions. (Wittgenstein, 1998a, p. 91)
In addition to the connections discussed in the previous section, there were other influ-
ences that helped Wittgenstein frame his exploration of Gestalt psychology. One of these was
102 JOHN G. BENJAFIELD
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 102
Johann Wolfgang von Goethe (17491832), who is best known in the history of psychology
for his studies of color (Boring, 1942, pp. 112116; Goethe, 1840/1970). Goethes work on
color was central to Wittgensteins (1977b) own investigations of that topic (Horner, 2000).
Equally important was Goethes (1790/1995) Metamorphosis of Plants and other works on
morphology that shaped important aspects of Wittgensteins approach not only to Gestalt psy-
chology but also to other topics (McGuinness, 2002; Schulte, 2003).
Goethes use of the word Gestalt is of particular interest. He noted that the word is often
used to mean an interrelated whole that is identified, defined and fixed in character, but that
in reality, especially in organic Gestalten, nothing in them is permanent, nothing at rest or
definedeverything is in a flux of continual motion (Goethe, 1817/1995, p. 63). This way
of seeing Gestalten seemed to the Berlin Gestalt psychologists entirely consistent with what
they had in mind.
Khler . . . mentioned Goethe in his discussions of the mathematics of physical Gestalten.
To underline what he took to be the ontological significance of the fact that similar series
of differential equations can cover a wide variety of physical facts, he called them affin-
ity series. . . . This was an allusion to Goethes novel . . . Elective Affinities, which tells
a story of human passion in the language of magnetism and chemical attraction. (Ash,
1995, p. 185)
For Wittgenstein, however, this would have been at best an incomplete way of taking
Goethes work. Goethe was not opposed to conventional science or mathematics but he was
opposed to scientism (Rowe, 1991, p. 285). Science had its place, but should not be allowed
to exceed its proper sphere of influence. Science had a tendency to oversimplify. This ten-
dency could be corrected by carefully considering the whole range of examples of various
phenomena. Seeing each instance in its various relations to all the others provided the intu-
itive observer with an understanding of phenomena not obtainable otherwise. This is the ap-
proach Goethe took to colors and plants, for example.
Physics quite legitimately searches for hidden mechanisms that explain phenomena.
However, following Goethe, we could eschew the search for hidden mechanisms and instead
arrange the phenomena of interest in different ways (Rowe, 1991, p. 295), searching for a per-
spicuous representation [that] produces just that understanding that consists in seeing con-
nexions (Wittgenstein , 1958, p. 49). Dont look for anything beyond the phenomena. They
themselves are the theory (Goethe) (Wittgenstein, 1980a, p. 157).
To the scientistic eye, both Goethe and Wittgenstein may seem to be making a distinc-
tion without a difference. It might be argued that scientists routinely survey the phenomena
of interest precisely in order to be able to formulate an explanation of them. However, while
such explanations have their place, they can never substitute for the understanding that comes
from the perspicuous representation itself. Goethe was lampooned for criticizing Newtons
explanation of the nature of white. However, the point of Goethes discussion of white is that
Newtons theory has nothing to say about it as an experience. Goethe may have been seeking
an alternative way of doing science, but Wittgenstein was not that nave (Vendler, 1995). What
Wittgenstein was doing was not prescientific. A perspicuous representation is not a prelimi-
nary to science. Rather, Wittgenstein provided a description of the relations between colors
that could stand on its own, illustrating the logic of colors.
We do not want to establish a theory of colour (neither a physiological one nor a psy-
chological one), but rather the logic of colour concepts. And this accomplishes what peo-
ple have often unjustly expected of a theory. (Wittgenstein, 1977b, p. 5) I am not saying
REVISITING WITTGENSTEIN ON KHLER 103
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 103
here what the Gestalt psychologists say: that the impression of white comes about in such
and such a way. Rather the question is precisely: what is the impression of white, what
is the meaning of this expression, what is the logic of this concept white? (Wittgenstein,
1977b, p. 7)
The Gestalt psychologist Adhmar Gelb (18871936; 1929/1967, pp. 207208) did an
experiment in which he projected light on a black disk in such a way that the disk appeared
to be white. When a white piece of paper was placed in front of the disk, the disk suddenly
appeared black. Such an experiment was of considerable interest as a part of the exploration
of color constancy. However, it would make no sense to do an experiment to determine
whether the statement White is lighter than black is true. That white is lighter than black is
part of the meaning of white and black (Lee, 1999, p. 218). We learn the meaning of color
words in the course of our social development, from and with other people. Color words take
their meaning from their use in a language. In this respect they are like any other words,
including such important words for our purposes as remembering and seeing.
SPENGLER, WITTGENSTEIN, AND GESTALT THEORY
Wittgenstein was born into an immensely rich Viennese family that ensured that he
was exposed to high culture. Brahms occasionally performed at the Wittgenstein home,
but Wittgensteins real affinity was for the music of Mozart and Beethoven (Monk, 1991,
p. 13). Wittgensteins ideal world . . . the one to which he would have liked to belong was
not that to which he actually belonged but one that had disappeared and had ended near the
middle of the nineteenth century (Bouveresse, 1991, p. 22).
During World War I, Wittgenstein served in the Austrian army for five years (McGuinness,
1967, p. 141). His family felt that he had become a different person as a consequence of his war
experiences (e.g., H. Wittgenstein, 1973/1981, p. 4), and could not understand why he wanted
to train to become a teacher in elementary schools. . . . On his arrival home from the war he was
one of the wealthiest men in Europe, . . . but within a month of returning, he had disposed of
his entire estate (Monk, 1991, pp. 170171).
Of course, Wittgenstein was far from being the only person transformed by the disaster
that was the Great War. The 1920s produced a range of responses to what was experienced as
a crisis in German culture. One of these responses came from
self-styled philosopher of history Oswald Spengler [18801936]. The first volume of
The Decline of the West has a subtitle, Gestalt and reality. This referred to a contrast
between the exact, deadening procedure of modern physics, which subjects its objects
to mechanical, numerical order, and a morphological or formative method, which
takes the creations of a culture as signs of its soul or life. (Ash, 1991, p. 398)
Although Wittgenstein did not put much faith in Spenglers reliability as a historian, he
did think that Spengler could teach us something about the age we were now living in (Drury,
1981). Wittgenstein (1998a, p. 16) listed Spengler (1918/1986) as someone who had influ-
enced his thinking. Useful analyses of Spenglers relation to Wittgenstein may be found in
Bloor (1983, pp.162165), Haller (1988, pp. 7489), Klagge (2005), and Wright (1982,
pp. 212 215). Spengler famously argued that all cultures have a distinct character and go
through periods similar to those of an individual life-cycle. Western culture has been in decline
since the nineteenth century. Indeed, Western culture was no longer even worthy of being called
a culture, but had become merely a civilization. This meant that it was disintegrating rather than
developing as a coherent whole. Such a message resonated strongly with Wittgenstein, who felt
104 JOHN G. BENJAFIELD
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 104
that he properly belonged to an earlier time when there really was a Western culture. The spirit
of this civilization the expression of which is the industry, architecture, music, of present day
fascism & socialism, is a spirit that is alien & uncongenial to the author (Wittgenstein, 1998a,
p. 8). Because he did not think of himself as being of his time, Wittgenstein thought that oth-
ers were unlikely to understand him.
By contrast with Spenglers pessimistic outlook, the Berlin Gestalt psychologists be-
lieved that their approach could contribute to a positive resolution of the postwar crisis. Both
Ash (1995, pp. 294297) and Harrington (1996, pp. 119121) pointed to a paper by
Wertheimer (1924/1967) in which he argued that the Gestalt approach could contribute to
overcoming the schisms of the time. This was possible by seeing that all phenomena, whether
natural or cultural, were expressions of the same Gestalt laws. Even values were objectively
present in Gestalten. This is a theme that Khler (1938/1959) developed further in The Place
of Value in a World of Facts. A science of values was not only a desirable but also a real pos-
sibility (Harrington, 1996, pp. 130132). The pessimism of Wittgenstein contrasted with the
optimism of the Gestalt psychologists, who were confident that their scientific work could
contribute to a resolution of the important problems of the day.
WITTGENSTEINS STYLE
Wittgensteins later writings are the most relevant for us because it is there that he began
to remark on Khler and Gestalt psychology. In the Collected Works (Wittgenstein, 1998b),
Khler and/or Gestalt psychology are referred to in seventeen separate remarks. One of these
is in the Philosophical Investigations (1958), fourteen in the Remarks on the Philosophy of
Psychology (1980a,b), one in Last Writings on the Philosophy of Psychology (1990) and one
in Remarks on Colour (1977b). These remarks were all composed between 1946 and 1951.
Of course, these are not all the remarks that are relevant to Khler and Gestalt psychology,
but only those in which they are explicitly mentioned in the Collected Works (1998b).
The distinctive style of Wittgensteins later writings has been extensively discussed
(e.g., Baker, 1999; Cavell, 1966; Peters, 2001; Stern, 1996). In part, Wittgenstein may have
acquired his style as a result of his experience as an elementary school teacher in rural Austria
from 1920 until 1926 (Wright, 1967, p. 20). Wittgensteins friend Paul Engelmann
(18911965; 1967, p. 114115) suggested that being a teacher compelled Wittgenstein to
seek to translate the questions he had to ask as a teacher into a language that he could assume
to come close to the childrens language. He would never have been forced to learn how to
do this otherwise. He thus acquired the art of asking questions with consummate skill, and
the crucial simplicity with which he accomplished this in his profoundest mental probing con-
stitutes his great new philosophical achievement (p. 115).
While it would be wrong to exaggerate the question-asking aspect of Wittgensteins
style, no one disputes its presence. Here is an example (Wittgenstein, 1980b, p. 63).
Am I doing child psychology?I am making a connexion between the concept of teach-
ing and the concept of meaning.
Wittgenstein posed a question, but did not provide a direct answer. The reader may be
prompted to ask, Is the connexion between the concept of teaching and the concept of mean-
ing a matter of child psychology? In ruminating about possible answers, the reader may con-
clude that while what Wittgenstein is doing may not actually be child psychology, his work
nonetheless has suggestive implications for child psychology. Indeed, one very influential
research program in cognitive and developmental psychology was instigated by just such a
REVISITING WITTGENSTEIN ON KHLER 105
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 105
reading of Wittgenstein. The example is Eleanor Roschs (1978) empirical investigations of
conceptual development. However, doing child psychology was not Wittgensteins goal.
Rather, it was to present a perspicuous representation of a series of phenomena pertaining to
the connexion between the concept of teaching and the concept of meaning.
Rosch (1987, p. 164) argued that psychology could begin where philosophy ended. For
empirical issues, perhaps this means rather that the problems are brought completely into
view. And that is the beginning of investigation. Roschs opinion of the relation between phi-
losophy and psychology is, of course, her own. She may not be reflecting Wittgensteins opin-
ion. Wittgenstein is at his most provocative when his view of psychology seems to be that it
is unnecessary, there being no reason to engage in it once a Goethean, perspicuous represen-
tation of the phenomena has been achieved. This is an aspect of Wittgensteins thought we will
consider further below.
WITTGENSTEINS REMARKS ON KHLER AND GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY
According to Joachim Schulte (1992, p. 76), Khler was the most important influence
on Wittgenstein during the late 1940s. The famous statement at the end of Philosophical
Investigations that The confusion and barrenness of psychology is not to be explained by
calling it a young science (Wittgenstein, 1958, p. 232), was probably directed at Khlers
(1947, p. 420) argument that psychology was a young science that needed to imitate the phys-
ical sciences in their youth, when their state of development was comparable to our own at
the present time. Wittgensteins statement had an earlier version in which Wittgenstein
(1980a, p. 180; Anscombe & Wright, 1980, p. iv) omitted and barrenness. This suggests that
Wittgenstein regarded the confusion of psychology and its barrenness as somewhat separate
issues, and in what follows they will be treated as such. What Wittgenstein might have meant
by the confusion of psychology has been extensively discussed over many years (e.g.,
Drury, 1973, p. 30; Gustafson, 1964, p. xiv; Harr & Tissaw, 2005; Schulte, 1992, p. 76f).
However, what he might have meant by its barrenness has received less explicit attention.
The Hffding Function and the Problem of Similarity
Wittgensteinians have not made as much of the Hffding function, sometimes called the
Hffding step, as they could have. Named after the Danish psychologist Harald Hffding
(18431931), it purported to state a necessary relationship between perception and memory.
Hffding (1891/1919) brought out what he took to be the central role of similarity in making
recognition possible. He observed that the law of similarity was seen by associationists such as
James Mill (17731836) as a special case of more fundamental laws such as contiguity.
However, Hffding reversed this relationship, and argued that similarity was more fundamental.
Caesar, Alexander, and Napoleon, are indeed often presented together in our thought; but
this is so just because they have so often been compared with one another. . . . So far
from association by similarity being resolvable into association by contiguity, every as-
sociation by contiguity on the contrary presupposes association by similarity, or at least
an immediate recognition. In order that A may excite the ideas of B, C, D, with which it
usually arises simultaneously in consciousness, it must first, so to speak establish its
identity. (p. 157)
One way of putting the Hffding function is to say that recognition precedes recall (Asch,
1969, pp. 9899; Rock, 1962). Hffdings argument is that, for example, I must recognize you
before I can recall your name. If I do not recognize you, then your name will not occur to me.
106 JOHN G. BENJAFIELD
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 106
The Hffding function received little attention in psychology until Khler took it up
again in a paper read before the International Congress in Copenhagen in 1932 (Koffka,
1935, p. 561). Khler (1940/1960, pp. 126130) subsequently made the Hffding function an
essential part of his theory of memory traces. In order for experienced events to be remem-
bered, they must leave behind traces of themselves (Khler, 1947, pp. 251252). Thus, after
being introduced to me, you will have a memory trace of me (a) associated with a memory
trace of my name (b). The theoretically important part occurs the next time you see me (A).
A has never occurred in conjunction with a, and so there is no association between A and a.
In order for recognition to occur, A must somehow make contact with the memory trace a, and
then b can be recalled. Following Hffding, Khler (1940/1960, p. 129) said that the connec-
tion between A and a takes place on the basis of similarity. However, Khler (1940/1960)
never said exactly what similarity means, although he did use nontechnical words such as
kinship (p. 127) as synonyms.
The argument that recognition takes place on the basis of similarity should be an easy
target for Wittgensteinians. The word similarity figures in some of Wittgensteins most influ-
ential arguments. For example, consider his rejection of the common assumption that what
is needed to justify characterizing a number of processes or objects by a general concept-word is
something common to them all (Wittgenstein, 1974, p. 75). Wittgensteins famous counter-
example was that games do not have something that is common to all, but similarities,
relationships, and a whole series of them at that. . . . I can think of no better expression to
characterize these similarities than family resemblances (Wittgenstein 1958, p. 31, italics
added). Here is another remark, this time bearing on so-called mental processes.
Understanding is not the name of a single process but of more or less interrelated
processes against a background of the actual use of a learnt language.We think that if
I use the word understanding in all these cases there must be some one thing that hap-
pens in all of them. Well, the concept-word certainly does show a kinship but this need
not be the sharing of a common property or constituent.The concept-word game.
By knowledge we mean these processes, and these, and similar ones. (Wittgenstein,
1974, p. 11; italics added)
Notice that the word similar is used to indicate that there may be other members of a se-
ries that are as yet unspecified. It is impossible in practice to predict what will be sufficiently
dissimilar so as not to be an example of a concept-word.
Then it might be objected that a transition can be made from anything to anything, and
so the concept isnt bounded. To this I have to say that for the most part it isnt in fact
bounded and the way to specify it is perhaps: by knowledge we mean these processes,
and these, and similar ones. And instead of and similar ones I might have said and
others akin to these in many ways. (Wittgenstein, 1974, p. 76, italics added)
Because similarity is such a flexible and accommodating concept, it does not in practice
add anything to say that We recognize things on the basis of similarity. We might as well
say that we recognize things because we recognize them. It is instructive to imagine two peo-
ple having the following dialogue.
Theyre brother and sister, but they dont look alike at all.I can see a similarity be-
tween them. (Wittgenstein, 1990, p. 24)
The foregoing is not intended to imply that similarity is not a useful word. On the con-
trary, it is a very useful word, precisely because of the innumerable contexts in which it can
help to express what one wants to say. It is just that it is not a very scientific concept-word.
REVISITING WITTGENSTEIN ON KHLER 107
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 107
However, psychologists of a Gestalt persuasion wanted it to become a scientific concept,
although precisely how this was supposed to happen was unclear. We know almost nothing
about the mechanism of similarity or about the character of memory trace arousal was the
way that Solomon Asch (19071996; 1969, p. 99) put the problem. The belief that the mean-
ing of a concept-word can be clarified by scientific investigation was (and is) by no means
peculiar to Gestalt psychology, and is a theme to which we will return throughout the
remainder of the paper.
Scholars of a Wittgensteinian persuasion generally agree that Khlers psychology was
conceptually confused (e.g., Bennett & Hacker, 2003, p. 161f; Budd, 1989; Hark, 1995;
Schulte, 1992). One way in which conceptual confusion manifests itself is through the belief
that the ordinary language meanings of words are unscientific and need to be given more
precise definitions. The psychologist often behaves like Humpty Dumpty, saying that When
I use a word, . . . it means just what I choose it to meanneither more nor less (Carroll,
1971, p. 190; Pitcher, 1965/1967, p. 328). However, as we have seen in the case of similarity,
any such cavalier approach would of necessity yield an artificial definition that would cover
only some of the cases in which we say of things that they are similar. It must be said that, to
the Gestalt psychologists credit, they never arbitrarily defined similarity, but, like Asch
(1969), had the integrity to remain puzzled by the problem.
Conceptual Confusion and Khlers Theory of Memory Traces
Khler believed that perception leaves behind a trace of itself. For Khler (1938/1959,
p. 249), memory traces are physiological entities, distributed throughout the brain. Wittgenstein
(1980a, p. 45) commented on this hypothesis as follows.
An event leaves a trace in the memory: one sometimes imagines this as if it consisted in
the events having left a trace, an impression, a consequence, in the nervous system. As
if one could say: even the nerves have a memory. But then when someone remembered
an event, he would have to infer it from this impression, this trace. Whatever the event
does leave behind in the organism, it isnt the memory.
The organism compared with a dictaphone spool; the impression, the trace, is the al-
teration in the spool that the voice leaves behind. Can one say that the dictaphone (or the
spool) is remembering what was spoken all over again, when it reproduces what it took?
The problem with any theory that equates memory with physiological traces is that it
makes no sense to say that the brain remembers, any more than it makes sense to say that a dic-
taphone spool remembers (Overgard, 2004). A brain is a part of a person, and it is the person
who remembers (Bennett & Hacker, 2003, p. 154). Traces can be part of an account of remem-
bering, but not the whole story. To say that memory traces are essential to memory disguises the
ways in which memory blends into imagination and thinking (cf. Schulte, 1992, p. 118).
Seeing-as
Seeing the figure as . . . has something occult, something ungraspable about it. One would
like to say: Something has altered, and nothing has altered. (Wittgenstein, 1980a, p. 170)
This was a phenomenon in which Wittgenstein was particularly interested, and was at the
heart of Pastores (1991) discussion. Following the method of creating a series of examples,
a perspicuous representation, Wittgenstein not only used figures from Khler, either repro-
ducing them or using analogs, but also some examples that Khler did not use.
We can arrange some of Khlers and Wittgensteins examples in a series. For now, we
will only consider three. At one end of the series are figures such as the double cross (Figure 4).
108 JOHN G. BENJAFIELD
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 108
Then there is the duck-rabbit (Figure 1), which is a more complicated case. Which aspect of
the double cross is seen could be indicated nonverbally, by pointing, for example. One could
quite well imagine this as a primitive reaction in a child even before it could talk
(Wittgenstein, 1958, p. 207). However, which aspect of the duck-rabbit was seen could not be
indicated simply by pointing. You only see the duck and rabbit aspects if you are already
conversant with the shapes of those two animals (Wittgenstein, 1958, p. 207). Now consider
the triangle in Figure 5. Wittgenstein (1958, p. 201) asked us to see it as something that has
fallen over. The fallen-over triangle is complicated in different way. It is possible to take the
duck-rabbit simply for the picture of a rabbit, the double cross simply for the picture of a
black cross, but not to take the bare triangular figure for the picture of an object that has fallen
over. To see this aspect of the triangle demands imagination (Wittgenstein, 1958, p. 207).
The series illustrates different ways in which the word see can be used when one sees
something as something. Pastore wanted to see Wittgensteins examples as part of an argu-
ment in favour of an empiricist theory of seeing-as. However, Wittgenstein was not arguing
for or against Khlers emphasis on perceptual organization as the determinant of what a fig-
ure is seen as. Wittgenstein was not psychologizing, but pointing out that there are many ways
of seeing seeing-as (Hark, 1990, p. 186). Certainly experience and education enter into at
least some forms of seeing-as. Seeing as . . . is not part of perception. And for that reason
it is like seeing and again not like (Wittgenstein, 1958, p. 197).
The visual examples with which we have illustrated seeing-as are by no means the only, or
perhaps even the most interesting, illustrations. Consider the following examples (Wittgenstein,
1974, p. 42).
The different experiences I have when I see a picture first one way and then another are
comparable to the experience I have when I read a sentence with understanding and with-
out understanding.
(Recall what it is like when someone reads a sentence with a mistaken intonation
which prevents him from understanding itand then realizes how it is to be read.)
(To see a watch as a watch, i.e. as a dial with hands, is like seeing Orion as a man strid-
ing across the sky.)
One of the goals of education must be to enable people to see things they might not oth-
erwise. This may have nothing to do with psychology in particular or science in general, but
have everything to do with being fortunate enough to have had the right kinds (and amount)
of training and experience (Hamlyn, 1989).
REVISITING WITTGENSTEIN ON KHLER 109
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
FIGURE 5.
A triangle that has fallen over. From L. Wittgenstein. (1958). Philosophical
investigations (p. 200). Oxford: Blackwell.
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 109
I could say of one of Picassos pictures that I dont see it as human. Or of many another
picture that for a long time I wasnt able to see what it was representing, but now I do.
Isnt this similar to: for a long time I couldnt hear this as of a piece, but now I hear it
that way. Before, it sounded like so many little bits, which were always stopping short
now I hear it as an organic whole. (Bruckner) (Wittgenstein, 1990, p. 86)
Someone of a scientistic bent might seek a simple explanation for all these phenomena.
However, first one would need to understand and appreciate the phenomena him- or herself. The
acquisition of such an understanding might be sufficient in itself. Wittgensteins philosophy
betokens a trenchant attempt to protect and conserve a domain of knowledge and form of
understanding from erosion and distortion by the scientific spirit of the age. For one may
see Wittgensteins philosophical endeavours as a defence of humanistic understanding
against the illegitimate encroachment of the natural sciences. (Hacker, 2001, p. 42)
Isomorphism
Isomorphism was, of course, not Khlers invention (Madden, 1957). The term is used in
chemistry, mineralogy, mathematics, and biology, as well as psychology. It means something
different in each case. For example, according to the Oxford English Dictionary, in mathe-
matics it means an exact correspondence as regards the number of constituent elements and
the relations between them. Khlers version of isomorphism was that there was a corre-
spondence between the organization of experience and the organization of cortical processes.
The correspondence was not point-for-point. Rather the correspondence was structural, so
that any change in the organization of experience would have a corresponding change in the
organization of cortical activity.
Wittgenstein (1977b, p. 48), by contrast, did not attempt to tie experiences directly to
brain events. Psychology connects something experienced with something physical, but we
connect something experienced with what is experienced. Wittgenstein also wondered what
Khler meant by the word organization. The organization of the visual image changes has
not the same kind of application as: The organization of this company is changing. Here I
can describe how it is, if the organization of our company changes (Wittgenstein, 1980a,
p. 100). In the case of a change of aspect, can one describe the change in organization?
Khlers answer to this question relied on a process he called satiation. In the case of a
reversible figure such as the double cross, Khler (1940/1960, p. 70) claimed that over time
reversals occur more frequently. This meant that while a figure is inspected, the brain tissue
supporting the perception of a particular aspect becomes fatigued, or satiated. The result is
that a new aspect emerges, until it, too, is satiated, and so on. Satiation was assumed to be a
process that builds up over time and does not disappear immediately upon a change of aspect.
Consequently, when the aspect changes back to its previously satiated form, there is less time
to the next reversal.
[P]rolonged occurrence of the percept process in a given area changes the medium in
which the process is located, and . . . it does so gradually and continuously. . . . [W]hen
the change has reached a certain critical degree, the reversible pattern is suddenly trans-
formed. (Khler, 1940/1960, pp. 8283)
Michel ter Hark (1995) believed that Wittgenstein had been right to doubt the isomor-
phism hypothesis not only on philosophical grounds but also on empirical grounds. He said
that Wittgensteins rejection of Khlers theory has been proven correct empirically (p. 125)
and that Khlers theory is no longer taken seriously by neuroscientists (p. 134). Hark does
not cite anyone in support of this conclusion, but it is certainly true that neuroscientists no
110 JOHN G. BENJAFIELD
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 110
longer work with Khlers specific formulation. However, versions of Khlers satiation hy-
pothesis are still influential.
For the sake of historical accuracy, it is important to review the process whereby Khlers
theory was discredited. The usual narrative is that neuroscientific heavyweights such as Karl
Lashley (18901958; Lashley, Chow, & Semmes, 1951) and future Nobel prizewinner Roger
Sperry (19131994; Sperry, Miner, & Myers, 1955; Sperry & Miner, 1955) did experiments
that finished Khler off. Lashley placed strips of gold foil or gold pins in the cortices of two
monkeys in order to disrupt electric fields, but observed no consequences of this manipulation.
Sperry cut and inserted wires and nonconductive material into the visual cortex of cats in order
to disrupt the organization of visual perception, but he also observed no effects. Perhaps not
surprisingly, Khler (1958; 1965/1971b) never accepted these results, partly because they
relied on what he regarded as crude methodologies. However, logical argument proved to be
no match for experiments, however crude they might have been, and in the absence of any
experimental reply on Khlers part, Lashley and Sperry appeared to carry the day.
However, over time, Khlers ideas have crept back in (Scheerer, 1994). For example,
Steven Lehar (2003, p. 404) presented an elaborate model of perception that incorporates
many of the concepts and principles introduced by the original Gestalt movement. Lehars
model includes a version of isomorphism that explicitly owes much to Khler. Of course, one
swallow does not a summer make, but Lehar is far from being the only example of Khlers
continuing influence. There are several approaches to reversible figures that pay homage to
Khlers satiation theory. For example, Burton (2002, p. 292) stated that one of the predom-
inant contemporary approaches to ambiguous figure reversals . . . is the satiation theory,
which dates back to Wolfgang Khler. Satiation, regarded as a form of neural fatigue, is still
considered to be a possible explanation for figural reversals (e.g., Long & Toppino, 2004;
Toppino, 2003). Some experimenters explicitly say that their work is designed to assess the
conventional theory of neural satiation, which they identify as Khlers (1940/1960) theory
of neural fatigue (Aks & Sprott, 2003, p. 167).
According to Scholars Portal, there are 137 articles published since 1950 in peer-
reviewed journals that mention satiation and reference Khler. Twenty-four of these articles
have been published since 1995. Scholars Portal includes PsycInfo as well as several other
databases in the sciences and social sciences. While Hark (1995) is correct in saying that no
one adheres to a precisely Khlerian theory any longer, many contemporary researchers
acknowledge their indebtedness to Khler and his concept of satiation.
Wittgenstein, by contrast, appears to have had minimal influence on the psychology of
reversible figures. It was a hope of some Wittgensteinians that their attempts to clear up con-
ceptual confusion in psychology would result in psychologists behaving differently. Yet it is
now over 50 years since the publication of Part II of the Philosophical Investigations, often
called the foundations of psychology, and its effect on the behavior of psychologists is diffi-
cult to discern. For example, the scientific literature on reversible figures is not at all divisi-
ble into pre- and post-Wittgensteinian phases. Indeed a Scholars Portal search for either the
phrase reversible figures or ambiguous figures in articles citing Wittgenstein returned only
three results. A striking example of Wittgensteins lack of influence in psychology is a recent
study of the development of childrens understanding of reversible figures that used a version
of the duck-rabbit as a stimulus but did not cite Wittgenstein (Doherty & Wimmer, 2005).
As Dale Jacquette (2007) and Michael Maraun (1998) observed, there are few documented
cases in which psychologists have taken Wittgenstein to heart and changed their research
practices as a consequence. Ivan Leudar (2006) suggested that the possibility of Wittgenstein
having an influence on psychology was masked by the simultaneous occurrence of the cognitive
REVISITING WITTGENSTEIN ON KHLER 111
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 111
revolution. Gestalt psychology was a precursor of that revolution (Murray, 1995; Neisser, 1967,
pp. 5051; 8991; 245247). Had Wittgenstein been more salient for psychologists at that time,
perhaps we could have moved toward a discipline that understands people not in isolation, but
as living in the world with culture and history (Leudar, 2006, p. 852).
Wittgensteins style did not make it easy for psychologists to consider the possibility that
they should change their ways. In any case, Wittgenstein was not particularly interested in
writing a guide for psychologists. He was more interested in exposing the weaknesses of psy-
chology to the few sympathetic readers who might then be inclined to do something more
fruitful than psychology.
THE BARRENNESS OF PSYCHOLOGY
The word barrenness occurs only once in Wittgensteins (1998b) Collected Works in
English, and that is in reference to psychology. According to the Oxford English Dictionary,
barren has among its figurative senses bare of intellectual wealth, destitute of attraction or
interest, poor, meager, jejune, arid, dry. Has Wittgensteins harsh judgment of psychology
been borne out? In order to at least partially answer that question, we need look no further
than research on the prototypical reversible figure, the Necker cube.
What Hath Necker Wrought?
Consider Figure 6, which is taken from Louis Albert Neckers (17861861; 1832/1964)
paper presenting the phenomenon that bears his name. Necker observed that drawings of
crystalline forms . . . will undergo sudden and involuntary change, such that sometimes
the angle at A will appear nearer than the angle at X, and sometimes the reverse. Thus, the
face ABCD will recede behind the face XDC, which will come forward; which effect gives
the whole solid a quite contrary apparent inclination (p. 78). Necker observed that he could
reverse the figure by focusing on either angle A or angle X, thus being able by my will to
see the solid in which position I chose (p. 79).
Notice that Figure 6 should properly be called Neckers rhomboid rather than Neckers
cube (Boring, 1942, p. 268). However, Neckers figure has typically been presented as a cube,
of which Figure 3 is an example taken from Wittgensteins Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
(1922/1977, p. 54). E. G. Boring (1942, p. 268) said that Neckers original rhomboid is re-
versed more easily than the cube, for the rhomboid stands upon an edge and is prejudiced for
neither perspective, whereas the cube is seen more easily flat upon the ground (as near)
than in the alternative peculiar uptilted position (bs near).
If that were all there was to it, then we could treat Neckers cube as an interesting diver-
sion in the history of psychology. However, according to Scholars Portal, since Borings
112 JOHN G. BENJAFIELD
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
A
B D
X
C
FIGURE 6.
Neckers rhomboid. From L. A. Necker, (1832). An apparent change of position
in a drawing or engraved figure of a crystal. Philosophical Magazine, 1, 329.
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 112
(1942) discussion there have been 424 studies in peer-reviewed journals in which the phrase
Necker cube or Neckers cube occurs, a rate of over 6 studies a year. The word voluntary oc-
curs in 49 of these articles, all published since 1985. The question of whether or not the re-
versal could be voluntary was what originally intrigued Necker. We are still trying to answer
Neckers question by means of experiments.
How would one determine if Necker cube reversals were voluntary? It is the person who
acts voluntarily. Naturally, one can ask someone to do something voluntarily such as sign up
to be a participant in an experiment. However, it is confused to believe that there is an inner
process, whether mental or physiological, that causes a voluntary act (Bennett & Hacker,
2003, pp. 223228). Nevertheless, experimental investigations of the Necker cube typically
bind what is called voluntary control to an inner process with a neural basis (e.g., Ee, Dam, &
Brouwer, 2005, p. 52).
Obviously, an experiment that purports to compare voluntary and involuntary rever-
sals of the Necker cube must have at least one condition in which the participants reverse
the cube voluntarily and another condition in which the cube reverses involuntarily. The
participants need to be told when to act voluntarily and when not. There have been a wide
variety of ways in which participants have been told how to act voluntarily. For example,
participants may be instructed to use concentration and mental effort in order to
control reversal (Mathes, Strber, Stadler, & Basar-Eroglu, 2006, p. 146), or to reverse or
maintain the cube when given the appropriate cue (Slotnick & Yantis, 2005, p. 99), or to
speed up the alternation as much as they could (Brascamp, Ee, Pestman, & Berg, 2005,
p. 291), or to attempt to perceive the cube from the [top or bottom] view for as long as
possible (Meng & Tong, 2004, p. 541). Concentration, mental effort, reverse, maintain,
speed up, and attempt are all perfectly good English words and phrases, but how exactly
are they related to voluntary? In the corresponding involuntary conditions, participants
obviously cannot be instructed to act involuntarily. Rather they are told to gaze at the
figure in a passive manner (Mathes et al., 2006, p. 146), or to to view a stimulus in a
natural way without attempting to control the alternation rate (Brascamp et al., 2005,
p. 291), or to just look at the cube passively (Meng & Tong, 2004, p. 541). Sometimes
an involuntary reversal was simply defined as one that occurred in the absence of a cue to
maintain or reverse the cube (Slotnick & Yantis, 2005, p. 99). Here again, how exactly do
gazing passively, or viewing in a natural way relate to involuntary? Indeed, is it not per-
fectly good English to say that someone is voluntarily gazing passively or voluntarily
viewing the cube in a natural way? Cant rest be just as voluntary as motion?
(Wittgenstein, 1980a, p. 150).
But there is not one common difference between so-called voluntary acts and involuntary
ones, viz, the presence or absence of one element, the act of volition. (Wittgenstein,
1969, pp. 151152)
Thus also, acting voluntarily (or involuntarily) is, in many cases, characterized as
such by a multitude of circumstances under which the action takes place rather than by
an experience which we should call characteristic of voluntary action. (Wittgenstein,
1969, p. 157)
Einhauser, Martin, & Knig (2004, p. 2817) noted that the question of the voluntary
nature of Necker cube reversals engaged some of the best minds of the nineteenth century, in-
cluding Charles Wheatstone (1838), Hermann von Helmholtz (1867/1962), and Wilhelm
Wundt (1897/1969). Yet here we are 175 years after Neckers publication still unable to give
anything even remotely like a conclusive answer to the question Necker originally posed.
REVISITING WITTGENSTEIN ON KHLER 113
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 113
Rather, we continue to modify our experimental methods in the hope that someday all will be-
come clear. In the end, perhaps all we have been doing for 175 years is making up new and
improved ways of using voluntary. If that is not barrenness, what is?
Psychologists tend to approach such questions as whether or not something is voluntary
by pursuing a research program of systematic observation and experiment. . . . [However,
we cannot] discover the nature of our psychological concepts by experimental investiga-
tions (Baker & Hacker, 1982, pp. 229230). Psychologists persist in using words such as
voluntary in a metaphysical way. The essential thing about metaphysics is that the differ-
ence between factual and conceptual investigations is not clear to it. A metaphysical ques-
tion is always in appearance a factual one, although the problem is a conceptual one
(Wittgenstein, 1980a, p. 167). Without realizing it, psychologists often do metaphysics
rather than science. This leads to some psychological studies resembling the sort of meta-
physical inquiries described by Wittgensteins friend and colleague at Cambridge, John
Wisdom (19041993).
In the labyrinth of metaphysics are the same whispers that one hears when climbing
Kafkas staircases to the tribunal which is always one floor further up. (Wisdom, 1957,
p. 282)
SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION
We saw that Khler and Wittgenstein were connected through common acquaintances.
These acquaintances were themselves important figures in early twentieth century thought
and illustrate the extent to which Khler and Wittgenstein shared common ground. This com-
mon ground made it relatively straightforward for Wittgenstein to use Khler as a vehicle for
philosophizing about psychology just as he used Goethe to inspire him to philosophize about
color (Lee, 1999, p. 216f; Monk, 1991, p. 561).
Although there is no evidence that Khler ever read Wittgenstein, it is not difficult to
imagine how Khler might have responded. To a very large extent, Pastore has already done
this job for us. His argument that Wittgenstein did not offer any coherent alternatives and was
hostile toward psychological science would surely have found echoes in any reply Khler
might have made. Khler (1938/1959, p. 185) might also have been prepared to discount
Wittgensteins attitudes toward physiological psychology because many philosophers dislike
to hear much about the brain when philosophical problems are discussed. Khler (1938/1959,
p. 193) unabashedly tried to upgrade physiological events so that they would be equivalent
to and exactly as good as are mental facts. Of course, Wittgenstein regarded such a move
as confused.
Wittgensteins trenchant analysis of Khlers neuropsychology did not have an apprecia-
ble impact on the behavior of psychologists. Indeed, an examination of some current research
on reversible figures suggests that, while his specific theories are no longer central, Khlers
general approach is still influential. Wittgensteins criticisms of Khler and, by extension,
contemporary neuroscience may be as valid now as they ever were. However, there is no
evidence that Wittgensteins arguments have any more traction now than they had in the past.
Nothing seems to me more unlikely than that a scientist or mathematician, who reads me,
should be seriously influenced thereby in the way he works. (In that respect my warnings
are like the posters on the ticket offices at English railway stations [during World War II]
Is your journey really necessary? As if anyone reading that would say to himself On
second thoughts, no.) (Wittgenstein, 1998a, pp. 7071)
114 JOHN G. BENJAFIELD
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 114
REFERENCES
Aks, D. J., & Sprott, J. C. (2003). The role of depth and 1/f dynamics in perceiving reversible figures. Nonlinear
Dynamics, Psychology, and Life Sciences, 7, 161180.
Allik, J., & Konstabel, K. (2005). G. F. Parrot and the theory of unconscious inferences. Journal of the History of the
Behavioral Sciences, 41, 317330.
Anscombe, G. E. M., & Wright, G. H. von. (1980). Preface. In L. Wittgenstein, Remarks on the philosophy of
psychology (Vol. 1, p. iv). Oxford: Blackwell.
Asch, S. E. (1969). A reformulation of the problem of associations. American Psychologist, 24, 92102.
Ash, M. G. (1987). Psychology and politics in interwar Vienna: The Vienna Psychological Institute, 19221942. In
M. G. Ash & W. R. Woodward (Eds.), Psychology in twentieth-century thought and society (pp. 143164).
NewYork: Cambridge University Press.
Ash, M. G. (1991). Gestalt psychology in Weimar culture. History of the Human Sciences, 4, 395415.
Ash, M. G. (1995). Gestalt psychology in German culture, 18901967: Holism and the quest for objectivity.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Baker, G. P. (1999). Italics in Wittgenstein. Language and Communication, 19, 181211.
Baker, G. P., & Hacker, P. M. S. (1982). The grammar of psychology. Language and Communication, 2, 227244.
Bartley, W. W. (1985). Wittgenstein (2nd ed.). Chicago: Open Court.
Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Oxford: Blackwell.
Bloor, D. (1983). Wittgenstein: A social theory of knowledge. New York: Columbia University Press.
Boring, E. G. (1942). Sensation and perception in the history of experimental psychology. New York: Appleton-
Century-Crofts.
Bouveresse, J. (1991). Wittgenstein and the modern world. In A. P. Griffiths (Ed.), Wittgenstein centenary essays
(pp. 1139). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Brascamp, J. W., Ee, R. van, Pestman, W. R., & Berg, A. V. van den. (2005). Distributions of alternation rates in
various forms of bistable perception. Journal of Vision, 5, 287298.
Brock, A. (1994). Whatever happened to Karl Bhler? Canadian Psychology, 35, 319329.
Brugger, P. (1999). One hundred years of an ambiguous figure: Happy birthday, duck-rabbit! Perceptual and Motor
Skills, 89, 973977.
Budd, M. (1989). Wittgensteins philosophy of psychology. London: Routledge.
Bhler, K. (1951). On thought connections. In D. Rapaport (Ed.), Organization and pathology of thought (pp. 3957).
(Original work published 1908)
Burton, G. (2002). Successor states in a four-state ambiguous figure. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 9, 292297.
Carnap, R. (1967). From his Autobiography. In K. T. Fann (Ed.), Ludwig Wittgenstein: The man and his philoso-
phy (pp. 3339). New York: Dell. (Original work published 1964)
Carroll, L. (1971). Alices adventures in wonderland and Through the looking glass. London: Oxford University
Press.
Cavell, S. (1966). The availability of Wittgensteins later philosophy. In G. Pitcher (Ed.), Wittgenstein: The later phi-
losophy (pp. 151185). New York: Anchor. (Original work published 1962)
Doherty, M. J., & Wimmer, M. C. (2005). Childrens understanding of ambiguous figures: Which cognitive develop-
ments are necessary to experience reversal? Cognitive Development, 20, 407421.
Drury, M. OC. (1973). The danger of words. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Drury, M. OC. (1981). Conversations with Wittgenstein. In R. Rhees (Ed.), Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal recol-
lections (pp. 112189). Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield.
Ee, R. van, Dam, L. C. J. van, & Brouwer, G. J. (2005). Voluntary control and the dynamics of perceptual bi-stability.
Vision Research, 45, 4155.
Einhuser, W., Martin, K. A. C., & Knig, P. (2004). Are switches in perception of the Necker cube related to eye
position? European Journal of Neuroscience, 20, 28112818.
Engelmann, P. (1967). Letters from Wittgenstein, with a memoir (B. F. McGuinness, Ed., L. Furtmller, Trans.).
Oxford: Blackwell.
Gelb, A. (1967). Color constancy. In W. D. Ellis (Ed.), A source book of Gestalt psychology (pp. 196207). New York:
Humanities Press. (Original work published 1929)
Goethe, J. W. von. (1970). Theory of colors (C. L. Eastlake, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Original work
published 1840)
Goethe, J. W. von. (1995). The metamorphosis of plants. In D. Miller (Ed. & Trans.), Scientific studies (pp. 7697).
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Original work published 1790)
Goethe, J. W. von. (1995). The purpose set forth (from On morphology). In D. Miller (Ed. & Trans.), Scientific studies
(pp. 6366). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Original work published 1817)
Goldfarb, W. (1989). Wittgenstein, mind, and scientism. Journal of Philosophy, 86, 635642.
Guare, J. (1990). Six degrees of separation: A play. New York: Vintage Books.
Gustafson, D. F. (1964). Essays in philosophical psychology. New York: Anchor.
Hacker, P. M. S. (2001). Wittgenstein and the autonomy of humanistic understanding. In R. Allen & M. Turvey (Eds.),
Wittgenstein: Theory and the arts (pp. 3974). London: Routledge.
Haller, R. (1988). Questions on Wittgenstein. Lincoln, NE: University of Nebraska Press.
REVISITING WITTGENSTEIN ON KHLER 115
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 115
Hamlyn, D. W. (1989). Education and Wittgensteins philosophy. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 23, 213222.
Hark, M. ter. (1990). Beyond the inner and the outer: Wittgensteins philosophy of psychology. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Hark, M. ter. (1995). Electric brain fields and memory traces: Wittgenstein and Gestalt psychology. Philosophical
Investigations, 18, 113138.
Harr, R., & Tissaw, M. (2005). Wittgenstein and psychology: A practical guide. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Harrington, A. (1996). Reenchanted science. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Helmholtz, H. von. (1962). Treatise on physiological optics (R. Southall, Trans.). New York: Dover. (Original work
published 1867)
Henle, M. (1986). The influence of Gestalt psychology in America. In M. Henle (Ed.), 1879 and all that: Essays in
the theory and history of psychology (pp. 118132). New York: Columbia University Press. (Original work
published 1977)
Hffding, H. (1919). Outlines of psychology (M. Lowndes, Trans.). London: Macmillan. (Original work published
1891)
Horner, E. (2000). There cannot be a transparent white: A defense of Wittgensteins account of the puzzle propo-
sitions. Philosophical Investigations, 23, 218241.
Humphrey, G. (1963). Thinking: An introduction to its experimental psychology. New York: Wiley. (Original work
published 1951)
Jacquette, D. (2007). Review of R. Harr and M. Tissaw, Wittgenstein and psychology: A practical guide. Journal
of the History of Philosophy, 45, 169170.
Kihlstrom, J. F. (2006). Joseph Jastrow and his duckor is it a rabbit? Retrieved 1 May, 2007 from http://socrates.
berkeley.edu/~kihlstrm/JastrowDuck.htm
Klagge, J. C. (2005). Wittgenstein in exile. In D. Z. Philips & M. von der Ruhr (Eds.), Religion and Wittgensteins
legacy (pp. 311324). Burlington, VT: Ashgate.
Koffka, K. (1935). Principles of Gestalt psychology. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.
Khler, W. (1947). Gestalt psychology. New York: Liveright.
Khler, W. (1956). The mentality of apes (Rev. ed., E. Winter, Trans.). New York: Vintage. (Original work published 1927)
Khler, W. (1958). The present situation in brain physiology. American Psychologist, 13, 150154.
Khler, W. (1959). The place of value in a world of facts. New York: Meridian Books. (Original work published 1938)
Khler, W. (1960). Dynamics in psychology. New York: Grove Press. (Original work published 1940)
Khler, W. (1971a). The new psychology and physics. In M. Henle (Ed.), The selected papers of Wolfgang Khler
(pp. 237251). New York: Liveright. (Original work published 1930)
Khler, W. (1971b). Unsolved problems in the field of figural aftereffects. In M. Henle (Ed.), The selected papers of
Wolfgang Khler (pp. 274302). (Original work published 1965)
Klpe, O. (1964). The modern psychology of thinking. In J. M. Mandler & G. Mandler (Eds.), Thinking: From
association to Gestalt (pp. 208216). New York: Wiley. (Original work published 1912)
Lashley, K. S., Chow, K. L., & Semmes, J. (1951). An examination of the electrical field theory of cerebral integra-
tion. Psychological Review, 58, 123136.
Lee, A. (1999). Wittgensteins Remarks on Colour. Philosophical Investigations, 22, 215239.
Lehar, S. (2003). Gestalt isomorphism and the primacy of subjective conscious experience: A Gestalt bubble model.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26, 375444.
Leudar, I. (2006). Wittgenstein and psychology? [Review of R. Harr and M. Tissaw, Wittgenstein and psychology:
A practical guide]. Theory and Psychology, 16, 851852.
Long, G. M., & Toppino, T. C. (2004). Enduring interest in perceptual ambiguity: Alternating views of reversible
figures. Psychological Bulletin, 130, 748768.
Madden, E. H. (1957). A logical analysis of psychological isomorphism. British Journal for the Philosophy of
Science, 8, 177191.
Maraun, M. D. (1998). The nexus misconceived: Wittgenstein made silly. Theory and Psychology, 8, 489501.
Mathes, B., Strber, D., Stadler, M. A., Basar-Eroglu, C. (2006). Voluntary control of Necker cube reversals modu-
lates the EEG delta- and gamma-band response. Neuroscience Letters, 402, 145149.
McGuinness, B. F. (1967). Editors appendix. In P. Engelmann, Letters from Wittgenstein, with a memoir
(pp. 137148). Oxford: Blackwell.
McGuinness, B. F. (1990). Wittgenstein: A life: Young Ludwig, 18891921. London: Duckworth.
McGuinness, B. F. (2002). In the shadow of Goethe: Wittgensteins intellectual project. European Review, 10, 447457.
Meng, M., & Tong, F. (2004). Can attention selectively bias bistable perception? Differences between binocular
rivalry and ambiguous figures. Journal of Vision, 4, 539551.
Monk, R. (1991). Ludwig Wittgenstein: The duty of genius. London: Vintage.
Mulder, H. L., & Velde-Schlick, V. F. B van de. (1979). Editors note. In H. L. Mulder & V. F. B. van de Velde-Schlick
(Eds.), Moritz Schlick: Philosophical papers (Vol. 1, P. Heath, Trans., pp. xixii). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
Murray, D. J. (1995). Gestalt psychology and the cognitive revolution. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Necker, L. A. (1964). An apparent change of position in a drawing or engraved figure of a crystal. In W. Dember
(Ed.), Visual perception: The nineteenth century (pp. 7880). New York: Wiley. (Original work published 1832)
Neisser, U. (1967). Cognitive psychology. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Overgard, S. (2004). Exposing the conjuring trick: Wittgenstein on subjectivity. Phenomenology and the Cognitive
Sciences, 3, 263286.
116 JOHN G. BENJAFIELD
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 116
Pastore, N. (1971). Selective history of theories of visual perception: 16501950. New York: Oxford University Press.
Pastore, N. (1991). Wittgenstein on Khler and Gestalt psychology. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences,
27, 341351.
Peters, M. (2001). Philosophy as pedagogy: Wittgensteins styles of thinking. Radical Pedagogy, 3. Retrieved 16 July,
2007 from http://radicalpedagogy.icaap.org/content/issue3_3/4-peters.html
Pitcher, G. (1967). Wittgenstein, nonsense, and Lewis Carroll. In K. T. Fann (Ed.), Ludwig Wittgenstein: The man
and his philosophy (pp. 315335). New York: Dell. (Original work published 1965)
Rock, I. (1962). A neglected aspect of the problem of recall: The Hffding function. In J. M. Scher (Ed.), Theories
of mind (pp. 645659). New York: Macmillan, 1962.
Rosch, E. H. (1978). Principles of categorization. In E. Rosch & B. Lloyd (Eds.), Cognition and categorization
(pp. 2748). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Rosch, E. H. (1987). Wittgenstein and categorization research in cognitive psychology. In M. Chapman &
R. A. Dixon (Eds.), Meaning and the growth of understanding: Wittgensteins significance for developmental
psychology (pp. 151166). Heidelberg: Springer.
Rowe, M. W. (1991). Goethe and Wittgenstein. Philosophy, 66, 283303.
Scheerer, E. (1994). Psychoneural isomorphism: Historical background and current relevance. Philosophical
Psychology, 7, 183211.
Schlick, M. (1979). On the concept of wholeness. In H. L. Mulder & V. F. B. van de Velde-Schlick (Eds.), Moritz
Schlick: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, P. Heath, W. Sellars, H. Feigl, & M. Brodbeck, Trans., pp. 388399).
Dordrecht: D. Reidel. (Original work published 1935)
Schulte, J. (1992). Experience and expression: Wittgensteins philosophy of psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schulte, J. (2003). Goethe and Wittgenstein on morphology. In F. Breithaupt, R. Raatzch, & B. Kremberg (Eds.),
Goethe and Wittgenstein: Seeing the worlds unity in its variety (pp. 5572). Frankfurt: Peter Lang.
Slotnick, S. D., & Yantis, S. (2005). Common neural substrates for the control and effects of visual attention and per-
ceptual bistability. Cognitive Brain Research, 24, 97108.
Spengler, O. (1986). The decline of the West: Volume oneForm and actuality (C. F. Atkinson, Trans.). New York:
Knopf. (Original work published 1918)
Sperry, R. W., & Miner, N. (1955). Pattern perception following the insertion of mica plates into the visual cortex.
Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 48, 463469.
Sperry, R. W., Miner, N., & Myers, R. E. (1955). Visual pattern perception following subpial splicing and tantalum
wire implantations in the visual cortex. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 48, 5058.
Stern, D. G. (1996). The availability of Wittgensteins philosophy. In H. Sluga & D. G. Stern (Eds.). The Cambridge
companion to Wittgenstein (pp. 442476). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Stromberg, W. H. (1980). Wittgenstein and the nativism-empiricism controversy. Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, 41, 127141.
Toppino, T. C. (2003). Reversible-figure perception: Mechanisms of intentional control. Perception &
Psychophysics, 65, 12851295.
Travers, J., & Milgram, S. (1969). An experimental study of the small world problem. Sociometry, 32, 425443.
Vendler, Z. (1995). Goethe, Wittgenstein, and the essence of color. Monist, 68, 391410.
Watson, J. B. (1962). Behaviorism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Original work published 1930)
Watts, D. J. (2004). The new science of networks. Annual Review of Sociology, 30, 243270.
Watts, D. J., & Strogatz, S. H. (1998). Collective dynamics of small world networks. Nature, 393, 440442.
Weimer, W. B. (1974). The history of psychology and its retrieval from historiography: I. The problematic nature of
history. Science Studies, 4, 235258.
Wertheimer, M. (1967). Gestalt theory. In W. D. Ellis (Ed.), A source book of Gestalt psychology (pp. 111).
NewYork: Humanities Press. (Original work published 1924)
Wheatstone, C. (1838). Contributions to the physiology of vision: Part the first. On some remarkable, and hitherto
unobserved, phenomena of vision. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 128, 371394.
Wijdeveld, P. (2000). Ludwig Wittgenstein, architect. Amsterdam: The Pepin Press.
Winnick, W. A. (2001). Nicholas Pastore (19161998). American Psychologist, 56, 265.
Wisdom, J. (1957). Philosophy and psycho-analysis. Oxford: Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, H. (1981). My brother Ludwig. In R. Rhees (Ed.), Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal recollections
(pp. 113). Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield.
Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations (2nd ed., G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, L. (1969). The blue and brown books (2nd ed.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, L. (1974): Philosophical grammar. (R. Rhees, Ed., A. Kenny, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, L. (1977a). Tractatus logico-philosophicus (B. McGuinness & D. F. Pears, Trans.). London: Routledge
& Kegan Paul. (Original work published 1922)
Wittgenstein, L. (1977b). Remarks on colour (G. E. M. Anscombe, Ed., L. L. McAlister & M. Schttle, Trans.).
Oxford: Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, L. (1980a) Remarks on the philosophy of psychology (Vol. 1, G. E. M. Anscombe & G. H. von Wright,
Eds.). Oxford: Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, L. (1980b). Remarks on the philosophy of psychology (Vol. 2, G. E. M. Anscombe & H. Nyman, Eds.).
Oxford: Blackwell.
REVISITING WITTGENSTEIN ON KHLER 117
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 117
Wittgenstein, L. (1990). Last writings on the philosophy of psychology (Vol. 1, G. H. von Wright & H. Nyman, Eds.,
C. G. Luckhardt & M. A. E. Aue, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, L. (1998a). Culture and value: a selection from the posthumous remains. (Rev. 2nd ed., G. H. von
Wright, H. Nyman & A. Pichler, Eds., P. Winch, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, L. (1998b). Collected works. [CD-ROM]. Charlottesville, VA: InteLex Corporation.
Wright, G. H. von. (1967). Biographical sketch. In K. T. Fann (Ed.), Ludwig Wittgenstein: The man and his philos-
ophy (pp. 1329). New York: Dell.
Wright, G. H. von. (1982). Wittgenstein. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Wundt, W. (1969). Outlines of psychology (C. H. Judd, Trans.). St. Clair Shores, MI: Scholarly Press. (Original work
published 1897)
118 JOHN G. BENJAFIELD
JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF THE BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES DOI: 10.1002/jhbs
jhbs442_01_20301.qxd 4/2/08 1:18 PM Page 118

Potrebbero piacerti anche