Sei sulla pagina 1di 17

Thomas Hobbes

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Jump to: navigation, search "Hobbes" redirects here. For other people called Hobbes, see Hobbes (disambiguation). For those of a similar name, see Thomas Hobbs. Thomas Hobbes

5 April 1588 Westport near Malmesbury, Wiltshire, England 4 December 1679 (aged 91) Died Derbyshire, England 17th-century philosophy Era (Modern Philosophy) Western Philosophers Region Social contract, classical realism, empiricism, materialism, ethical School egoism Political philosophy, history, ethics, Main interests geometry Modern founder of the social contract tradition; life in the state of Notable ideas nature is "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short" Influenced by[show] Born

Influenced[show]
Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury (5 April 1588 4 December 1679), in some older texts Thomas Hobbs of Malmsbury,[1] was an English philosopher, best known today for his work on political philosophy. His 1651 book Leviathan established the foundation for most of Western political philosophy from the perspective of social contract theory.[2]

Hobbes was a champion of absolutism for the sovereign but he also developed some of the fundamentals of European liberal thought: the right of the individual; the natural equality of all men; the artificial character of the political order (which led to the later distinction between civil society and the state); the view that all legitimate political power must be "representative" and based on the consent of the people; and a liberal interpretation of law which leaves people free to do whatever the law does not explicitly forbid.[3] He was one of the founders of modern political philosophy.[4] His understanding of humans as being matter and motion, obeying the same physical laws as other matter and motion, remains influential; and his account of human nature as self-interested cooperation, and of political communities as being based upon a "social contract" remains one of the major topics of political philosophy. In addition to political philosophy, Hobbes also contributed to a diverse array of other fields, including history, geometry, the physics of gases, theology, ethics, and general philosophy.

Contents

1 Early life and education 2 In Paris 3 Civil War in England 4 Leviathan 5 Opposition o 5.1 John Bramhall o 5.2 John Wallis o 5.3 Atheism 6 Later life 7 Selected bibliography 8 References o 8.1 Specific o 8.2 Bibliography 9 See also 10 External links o 10.1 Hobbes commentary online o 10.2 General works online

Early life and education


Thomas Hobbes was born at Westport, now part of Malmesbury in Wiltshire, England, on 5 April 1588.[5] Born prematurely when his mother heard of the coming invasion of the Spanish Armada, Hobbes later reported that "my mother gave birth to twins: myself and fear."[5] His childhood is almost a complete blank, and his mother's name is unknown.[6] His father, also named Thomas, was the vicar of Charlton and Westport. Thomas Hobbes Sr. had an older brother, Francis Hobbes, who was a wealthy merchant with no family of his own. Thomas Hobbes, the younger, had one brother Edmund who was about two years older than him. Thomas Sr. abandoned his wife, two sons and a daughter, leaving them in the care of his brother, Francis, when he was forced to flee to London after being involved in a fight with a clergyman outside his own church. Hobbes was educated at Westport church from the age of

four, passed to the Malmesbury school and then to a private school kept by a young man named Robert Latimer, a graduate of the University of Oxford. Hobbes was a good pupil, and around 1603 he went up to Magdalen Hall, which is most closely related to Hertford College, Oxford.[7][8][9][10] The principal John Wilkinson was a Puritan, and he had some influence on Hobbes. At university, Hobbes appears to have followed his own curriculum; he was "little attracted by the scholastic learning". He did not complete his B.A. degree until 1608, but he was recommended by Sir James Hussey, his master at Magdalen, as tutor to William, the son of William Cavendish, Baron of Hardwick (and later Earl of Devonshire), and began a lifelong connection with that family.[11] Hobbes became a companion to the younger William and they both took part in a grand tour in 1610. Hobbes was exposed to European scientific and critical methods during the tour in contrast to the scholastic philosophy which he had learned in Oxford. His scholarly efforts at the time were aimed at a careful study of classic Greek and Latin authors, the outcome of which was, in 1628, his great translation of Thucydides' History of the Peloponnesian War, the first translation of that work into English from a Greek manuscript. It has been argued that three of the discourses in the 1620 publication known as Horea Subsecivae: Observations and Discourses, also represent the work of Hobbes from this period.[12] Although he associated with literary figures like Ben Jonson and thinkers such as Francis Bacon, he did not extend his efforts into philosophy until after 1629. His employer Cavendish, then the Earl of Devonshire, died of the plague in June 1628. The widowed countess dismissed Hobbes but he soon found work, again as a tutor, this time to Gervase Clifton, the son of Sir Gervase Clifton, 1st Baronet. This task, chiefly spent in Paris, ended in 1631 when he again found work with the Cavendish family, tutoring the son of his previous pupil. Over the next seven years as well as tutoring he expanded his own knowledge of philosophy, awakening in him curiosity over key philosophic debates. He visited Florence in 1636 and later was a regular debater in philosophic groups in Paris, held together by Marin Mersenne. From 1637 he considered himself a philosopher and scholar.

In Paris

Thomas Hobbes

Hobbes's first area of study was an interest in the physical doctrine of motion and physical momentum. Despite his interest in this phenomenon, he disdained experimental work as in physics. He went on to conceive the system of thought to the elaboration of which he would devote his life. His scheme was first to work out, in a separate treatise, a systematic doctrine of body, showing how physical phenomena were universally explicable in terms of motion, at least as motion or mechanical action was then understood. He then singled out Man from the realm of Nature and plants. Then, in another treatise, he showed what specific bodily motions were involved in the production of the peculiar phenomena of sensation, knowledge, affections and passions whereby Man came into relation with Man. Finally he considered, in his crowning treatise, how Men were moved to enter into society, and argued how this must be regulated if Men were not to fall back into "brutishness and misery". Thus he proposed to unite the separate phenomena of Body, Man, and the State. Hobbes came home, in 1637, to a country riven with discontent which disrupted him from the orderly execution of his philosophic plan. However, by the end of the Short Parliament in 1640, he had written a short treatise called The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic. It was not published and only circulated among his acquaintances in manuscript form. A pirated version, however, was published about ten years later. Although it seems that much of The Elements of Law was composed before the sitting of the Short Parliament, there are polemical pieces of the work that clearly mark the influences of the rising political crisis. Nevertheless, many (though not all) elements of Hobbes's political thought were unchanged between The Elements of Law and Leviathan, which demonstrates that the events of the English Civil War had little effect on his contractarian methodology. It should be noted, however, that the arguments in Leviathan were modified from The Elements of Law when it came to the necessity of consent in creating political obligation. Namely, Hobbes wrote in The Elements of Law that Patrimonial kingdoms were not necessarily formed by the consent of the governed, while in Leviathan he argued that they were. This was perhaps a reflection either of Hobbes's thoughts concerning the engagement controversy or of his reaction to treatises published by Patriarchalists, such as Sir Robert Filmer, between 1640 and 1651. When in November 1640 the Long Parliament succeeded the Short, Hobbes felt he was a marked man by the circulation of his treatise and fled to Paris. He did not return for eleven years. In Paris he rejoined the coterie about Mersenne, and wrote a critique of the Meditations on First Philosophy of Descartes, which was printed as third among the sets of "Objections" appended, with "Replies" from Descartes in 1641. A different set of remarks on other works by Descartes succeeded only in ending all correspondence between the two. Hobbes also extended his own works somewhat, working on the third section, De Cive, which was finished in November 1641. Although it was initially only circulated privately, it was well received, and included lines of argumentation to be repeated a decade later in the Leviathan. He then returned to hard work on the first two sections of his work and published little except for a short treatise on optics (Tractatus opticus) included in the collection of scientific tracts published by Mersenne as Cogitata physico-mathematica in 1644. He built a good reputation in philosophic circles and in 1645 was chosen with Descartes, Gilles de Roberval and others, to referee the controversy between John Pell and Longomontanus over the problem of squaring the circle.

Civil War in England

The English Civil War broke out in 1642, and when the Royalist cause began to decline in the middle of 1644 there was an exodus of the king's supporters to Europe. Many came to Paris and were known to Hobbes. This revitalised Hobbes's political interests and the De Cive was republished and more widely distributed. The printing began in 1646 by Samuel de Sorbiere through the Elsevier press at Amsterdam with a new preface and some new notes in reply to objections. In 1647, Hobbes was engaged as mathematical instructor to the young Charles, Prince of Wales,[13] who had come over from Jersey around July. This engagement lasted until 1648 when Charles went to Holland. The company of the exiled royalists led Hobbes to produce an English book to set forth his theory of civil government in relation to the political crisis resulting from the war. The State, it now seemed to Hobbes, might be regarded as a great artificial man or monster (Leviathan), composed of men, with a life that might be traced from its generation under pressure of human needs to its dissolution through civil strife proceeding from human passions. The work was closed with a general "Review and Conclusion", in direct response to the war which raised the question of the subject's right to change allegiance when a former sovereign's power to protect was irrecoverably gone. He also criticised religious doctrines on rationalistic grounds in the Commonwealth.

Frontispiece from De Cive (1642) During the years of the composition of Leviathan he remained in or near Paris. In 1647 Hobbes was overtaken by a serious illness which disabled him for six months. On recovering from this near fatal disorder, he resumed his literary task, and carried it steadily forward to completion by 1650. Meanwhile, a translation of De Cive was being produced; there has been much scholarly disagreement over whether Hobbes translated the work himself or not. In 1650, a pirated edition of The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic was published. It was divided into two separate small volumes (Human Nature, or the Fundamental Elements of Policie and De corpore politico, or the Elements of Law, Moral and Politick). In 1651 the translation of De Cive was published under the title of Philosophicall Rudiments concerning

Government and Society. Meanwhile, the printing of the greater work was proceeding, and finally it appeared about the middle of 1651, under the title of Leviathan, or the Matter, Forme, and Power of a Common Wealth, Ecclesiasticall and Civil, with a famous title-page engraving in which, from behind hills overlooking a landscape, there towered the body (above the waist) of a crowned giant, made up of tiny figures of human beings and bearing sword and crozier in the two hands. The work had immediate impact. Soon Hobbes was more lauded and decried than any other thinker of his time. However, the first effect of its publication was to sever his link with the exiled royalists, forcing him to appeal to the revolutionary English government for protection. The exiles might very well have killed him; the secularist spirit of his book greatly angered both Anglicans and French Catholics. Hobbes fled back home, arriving in London in the winter of 1651. Following his submission to the council of state he was allowed to subside into private life in Fetter Lane.

Leviathan
Main article: Leviathan (book)

Frontispiece of Leviathan In Leviathan, Hobbes set out his doctrine of the foundation of states and legitimate governments originating social contract theory. Leviathan was written during the English Civil War; much of the book is occupied with demonstrating the necessity of a strong central authority to avoid the evil of discord and civil war. Beginning from a mechanistic understanding of human beings and the passions, Hobbes postulates what life would be like without government, a condition which he calls the state of nature. In that state, each person would have a right, or license, to everything in the world. This, Hobbes argues, would lead to a "war of all against all" (bellum omnium contra omnes). The description contains what has been called one of the best known passages in English

philosophy, which describes the natural state mankind would be in, were it not for political community: [14] In such condition, there is no place for industry; because the fruit thereof is uncertain: and consequently no culture of the earth; no navigation, nor use of the commodities that may be imported by sea; no commodious building; no instruments of moving, and removing, such things as require much force; no knowledge of the face of the earth; no account of time; no arts; no letters; no society; and which is worst of all, continual fear, and danger of violent death; and the life of man, solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short. "Chapter XIII.: Of the Natural Condition of Mankind As Concerning Their Felicity, and Misery.", Leviathan In such a state, people fear death, and lack both the things necessary to commodious living, and the hope of being able to toil to obtain them. So in order to avoid it people accede to a social contract and establish a civil society. According to Hobbes, society is a population beneath a sovereign authority, to whom all individuals in that society cede some rights for the sake of protection. Any abuses of power by this authority are to be accepted as the price of peace. There is no doctrine of separation of powers in Hobbes's discussion.[15] According to Hobbes, the sovereign must control civil, military, judicial, and ecclesiastical powers.

Opposition
John Bramhall
Hobbes now turned to complete the fundamental treatise of his philosophical system. He worked so steadily that De Corpore was first printed in 1654. Also in 1654, a small treatise, Of Liberty and Necessity, was published by Bishop John Bramhall, addressed at Hobbes. Bramhall, a strong Arminian, had met and debated with Hobbes and afterwards wrote down his views and sent them privately to be answered in this form by Hobbes. Hobbes duly replied, but not for publication. But a French acquaintance took a copy of the reply and published it with "an extravagantly laudatory epistle." Bramhall countered in 1655, when he printed everything that had passed between them (under the title of A Defence of the True Liberty of Human Actions from Antecedent or Extrinsic Necessity). In 1656 Hobbes was ready with The Questions concerning Liberty, Necessity and Chance, in which he replied "with astonishing force" to the bishop. As perhaps the first clear exposition of the psychological doctrine of determinism, Hobbes's own two pieces were important in the history of the freewill controversy. The bishop returned to the charge in 1658 with Castigations of Mr Hobbes's Animadversions, and also included a bulky appendix entitled The Catching of Leviathan the Great Whale.

John Wallis
For more details on this topic, see Hobbes-Wallis controversy. Beyond the spat with Bramhall, Hobbes was caught in a series of conflicts from the time of publishing his De Corpore in 1655. In Leviathan he had assailed the system of the original universities. Because Hobbes was so evidently opposed to the existing academic arrangements, and because De Corpore contained not only tendentious views on mathematics,

but an unacceptable proof of the squaring of the circle (which was apparently an afterthought), mathematicians took him to be a target for polemics. John Wallis was not the first such opponent, but he tenaciously pursued Hobbes. The resulting controversy continued well into the 1670s.

Atheism
Hobbes has been accused of atheism, or (in the case of Bramhall) of teachings which could lead to atheism. This was an important accusation, and Hobbes himself wrote, in his answer to Bramhall's "the catching of the Leviathan" that "atheism, impiety, and the like are words of the greatest defamation possible".[16] Hobbes always defended himself from such accusations.[17] In more recent times also, much has been made of his religious views by scholars such as Richard Tuck and J. G. A. Pocock, but there is still widespread disagreement about the exact significance of Hobbes's unusual views on religion. As Martinich (1995, p. 31) has pointed out, in Hobbes's time, the term "atheist" was frequently applied to people who believed in God, but not divine providence, or to people who believed in God, but also maintained other beliefs which were inconsistent with such belief. He says that this "sort of discrepancy has led to many errors in determining who was an atheist in the early modern period". In this extended early modern sense of atheism, Hobbes did indeed take positions which were in strong disagreement with church teachings of his time. For example, Hobbes argued repeatedly that there are no incorporeal substances, and that all things, including human thoughts, and even God, heaven, and hell are corporeal, matter in motion. He argued that "though Scripture acknowledge spirits, yet doth it nowhere say, that they are incorporeal, meaning thereby without dimensions and quantity".[18] (In this view, Hobbes claimed to be following Tertullian, whose views were not condemned in the Nicene creed.) He also, like Locke, stated that true revelation can never be in disagreement with human reason and experience,[19] although he also argues that people should accept revelation and its interpretations also for the reason that they should accept the commands of their sovereign, in order to avoid war.

Later life
In 1658, Hobbes published the final section of his philosophical system, completing the scheme he had planned more than twenty years before. De Homine consisted for the most part of an elaborate theory of vision. The remainder of the treatise dealt cursorily with some of the topics more fully treated in the Human Nature and the Leviathan. In addition to publishing some controversial writings on mathematics and physics, Hobbes also continued to produce philosophical works. From the time of the Restoration he acquired a new prominence; "Hobbism" became a byword for all that respectable society ought to denounce. The young king, Hobbes's former pupil, now Charles II, remembered Hobbes and called him to the court to grant him a pension of 100. The king was important in protecting Hobbes when, in 1666, the House of Commons introduced a bill against atheism and profaneness. That same year, on 17 October 1666, it was ordered that the committee to which the bill was referred "should be empowered to receive information touching such books as tend to atheism, blasphemy and profaneness... in particular... the book of Mr. Hobbes called the Leviathan".[20] Hobbes was terrified at the prospect of being labelled a heretic, and proceeded to burn some of his compromising papers. At the same time, he examined the actual state of the law of heresy. The results of his

investigation were first announced in three short Dialogues added as an Appendix to his Latin translation of Leviathan, published at Amsterdam in 1668. In this appendix, Hobbes aimed to show that, since the High Court of Commission had been put down, there remained no court of heresy at all to which he was amenable, and that nothing could be heresy except opposing the Nicene Creed, which, he maintained, Leviathan did not do. The only consequence that came of the bill was that Hobbes could never thereafter publish anything in England on subjects relating to human conduct. The 1668 edition of his works was printed in Amsterdam because he could not obtain the censor's licence for its publication in England. Other writings were not made public until after his death, including Behemoth: the History of the Causes of the Civil Wars of England and of the Counsels and Artifices by which they were carried on from the year 1640 to the year 1662. For some time, Hobbes was not even allowed to respond, whatever his enemies tried. Despite this, his reputation abroad was formidable, and noble or learned foreigners who came to England never forgot to pay their respects to the old philosopher. His final works were a curious mixture: an autobiography in Latin verse in 1672, and a translation of four books of the Odyssey into "rugged" English rhymes that in 1673 led to a complete translation of both Iliad and Odyssey in 1675. In October 1679, Hobbes suffered a bladder disorder, which was followed by a paralytic stroke from which he died on 4 December 1679. He is said to have uttered the last words "A great leap in the dark" in his final moments of life.[21] He was interred within St. John the Baptist Church in Ault Hucknall in Derbyshire, England.

Selected bibliography

1620. Three of the discourses in the Horae Subsecivae.[12] 1629. Translation of Thucydides's History of the Peloponnesian War 1640. The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic 1650. Treatise on Human Nature 1642. De Cive (Latin) 1651. Philosophicall Rudiments concerning Government and Society (English translation of De Cive)[22] 1651. Leviathan, or the Matter, Forme, and Power of a Commonwealth, Ecclesiasticall and Civil 1651. Pirated Edition of The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic, repackaged to include two parts: o Human Nature, or the Fundamental Elements of Policie o De Corpore Politico 1655. De Corpore (Latin) 1656. De Corpore (English translation) 1658. De Homine (Latin) 1654. Letters upon Liberty and Necessity 1656. The Questions concerning Liberty, Necessity and Chance 1668. Latin translation of the Leviathan 1675. English translation of Homer's Iliad and Odyssey 1681. Postumously A Dialogue between a Philosopher and a Student of the Common Laws of England (written 1666)

1681. Posthumously Behemoth, or The Long Parliament (written in 1668, unpublished at the request of the King)

References
Specific
1. ^ book title Tracts of Mr. Thomas Hobbs of Malmsbury : Containing I. Behemoth, the history of the causes of the civil wars of England, from 1640. to 1660. printed from the author's own copy: never printed (but with a thousand faults) before. II. An answer to Arch-bishop Bramhall's book, called the Catching of the Leviathan: never printed before. III. An historical narration of heresie, and the punishment thereof: corrected by the true copy. IV. Philosophical problems, dedicated to the King in 1662. but never printed before, publ. 1682 2. ^ "Hobbes's Moral and Political Philosophy". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.. Retrieved 11 March 2009. 3. ^ Pierre Manent, An Intellectual History of Liberalism (1994) pp 2038 4. ^ "Hobbes: Moral and Political Philosophy". 5. ^ a b "Thomas Hobbes Biography". Notablebiographies.com. Retrieved 24 July 2009. 6. ^ http://www.jstor.org/pss/3791051 7. ^ "Philosophy at Hertford College". Philosophy.hertford.ox.ac.uk. Retrieved 24 July 2009. 8. ^ "Thomas Hobbes Hertford College". Hertford.ox.ac.uk. Retrieved 24 July 2009. 9. ^ "The Galileo Project". Galileo.rice.edu. Retrieved 24 July 2009. 10. ^ Thomas Hobbes: Politics and law Google Books. Books.google.co.uk. Retrieved 24 July 2009. 11. ^ "Hobbes biography". Groups.dcs.st-and.ac.uk. Retrieved 24 July 2009. 12. ^ a b Hobbes, Thomas (1995), Reynolds, Noel; Saxonhouse, Arlene, eds., Three Discourses: A Critical Modern Edition of Newly Identified Work of the Young Hobbes, University of Chicago Press 13. ^ "NNDB". NNDB. Retrieved 24 July 2009. 14. ^ Gaskin, "Introduction", Human Nature and De Corpore Politico, Oxford University Press, p. xxx 15. ^ "1000 Makers of the Millennium", page 42. Dorling Kindersley, 1999 16. ^ p.282 of Molesworth's edition. 17. ^ Martinich (1995, p. 35) 18. ^ Human Nature I.XI.5. 19. ^ Leviathan III.xxxii.2. "...we are not to renounce our Senses, and Experience; nor (that which is undoubted Word of God) our naturall Reason". 20. ^ "House of Commons Journal Volume 8". British History Online. Retrieved 14 January 2005. 21. ^ Norman Davies, Europe: A history p. 687 22. ^ Modern scholars are divided as to whether or not this translation was done by Hobbes. For a pro-Hobbes account see H. Warrender's introduction to De Cive: The English Edition in the Clarendon Edition of the Works of Thomas Hobbes (Oxford, 1984). For the contra-Hobbes account see Noel Malcolm's 'Charles Cotton, Translator of Hobbes's De cive' in Aspects of Hobbes (Oxford, 2002)

Bibliography

Macpherson, C. B. (1962). The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Malcolm, Noel. (2002). Aspects of Hobbes. New York: Oxford University Press. Malcolm, Noel. (2007). Reason of State, Propaganda, and the Thirty Years' War: An Unknown Translation by Thomas Hobbes. Oxford University Press. Manent, Pierre. (1994) An Intellectual History of Liberalism Martinich, A. P. (2003) "Thomas Hobbes," The Dictionary of Literary Biography, Volume 281: British Rhetoricians and Logicians, 15001660, Second Series, Detroit: Gale, pp. 130144. Martinich, A. P. (1995), A Hobbes Dictionary, Blackwell Martinich, A. P. (1997) Thomas Hobbes, New York: St. Martin's Press. Martinich, A. P. (1992) The Two Gods of Leviathan: Thomas Hobbes on Religion and Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Martinich, A. P. (1999) Hobbes: A Biography, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999. Martinich, A. P. Philosophy and Government, 15721651, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Oakeshott, Michael (1975), "Hobbes on Civil Association", Oxford: Basil Blackwell Robinson, Dave & Groves, Judy (2003). Introducing Political Philosophy. Icon Books. ISBN 1-84046-450-X. Shapin, Steven and Shaffer, Simon (1995). Leviathan and the Air-Pump. Princeton: Princeton University Press Strauss, Leo (1936). The Political Philosophy of Hobbes; Its Basis and Its Genesis. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Strauss, Leo (1959). "On the Basis of Hobbes's Political Philosophy," in What Is Political Philosophy?, Glencoe, IL: Free Press, chap. 7. Skinner, Quentin. (1996). Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes's. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Tnnies, Ferdinand (1925). Hobbes. Leben und Lehre, Stuttgart: Frommann, 3rd ed. Vieira, Monica Brito. (2009) The Elements of Representation in Hobbes, Leiden: Brill Publishers. Zagorin, Perez. (2009) Hobbes and the Law of Nature, Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.

See also

Natural and legal rights#Thomas Hobbes Natural law#Hobbes

External links
This article's use of external links may not follow Wikipedia's policies or guidelines. Please improve this article by removing excessive or inappropriate external links, and converting useful links where appropriate into footnote references. (May 2012) Find more about Thomas Hobbes at Wikipedia's sister projects Definitions and translations from Wiktionary

Media from Commons Learning resources from Wikiversity News stories from Wikinews Quotations from Wikiquote Source texts from Wikisource Textbooks from Wikibooks

Hobbes commentary online


Thomas Hobbes on In Our Time at the BBC. (listen now) Thomas Hobbes nominated by Steven Pinker for the BBC Radio 4 programme Great Lives. (listen now) Thomas Hobbes at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Hobbes Moral and Political Philosophy at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Hobbes at the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Hobbes at The Philosophy pages Hobbes at the History of Economic Thought website. Brief biography at Oregon State University A Brief Life of Thomas Hobbes, 15881679 by John Aubrey at Oregon State University A short biography of Thomas Hobbes

General works online


Works by Thomas Hobbes at Project Gutenberg The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury; Now First Collected and Edited by Sir William Molesworth, Bart., (London: Bohn, 183945). 11 volumes. Can be found on the internet:

Volume 1. De Corpore translated from Latin to English. Volume 2. De Cive. Volume 3. The Leviathan Volume 4. TRIPOS ; in Three Discourses : I. Human Nature, or the Fundamental Elements of Policy II. De Corpore Politico, or the Elements of Law III. Of Liberty and Necessity An Answer to Bishop Bramhall's Book, called " The Catching of the Leviathan"

An Historical Narration concerning Heresy, and the Punishment thereof Considerations upon the Reputation, Loyalty, Manners, and Religion of Thomas Hobbes Answer to Sir William Davenant's Preface before " Gondibert" Letter to the Right Honourable Edward Howard Volume 5. The Questions concerning Liberty, Necessity and Chance, clearly stated and debated between Dr Bramhall Bishop of Derry and Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury. Volume 6. A Dialogue Between a Philosopher & a Student of the Common Laws of England A Dialogue of the Common Law Behemoth: the History of the Causes of the Civil Wars of England, and of the Counsels and Artifices By Which They Were Carried On From the Year 1640 to the Year 1660 The Art of Rhetoric Plainly Set Forth. With Pertinent Examples For the More Easy Understanding and Practice of the Same The Art of Sophistry Volume 7. Seven Philosophical Problems Decameron Physiologicum Proportion of a straight line to half the arc of a quadrant Six lessons to the Savilian Professors of the Mathematics , or Marks of the absurd Geometry etc. of Dr Wallis Extract of a letter from Henry Stubbe Three letters presented to the Royal Society against Dr Wallis Considerations on the answer of Dr Wallis Letters and other pieces Volume 8 and 9. The Peloponnesian War by Thucydides, translated into English by Hobbes. Volume 10. The Iliad, and The Odyssey, translated by Hobbes into English Volume 11. Index.

Contains Leviathan, lightly edited for easier reading The Latin works can also be found

Volume I. Biographical and Elementorum Philosophiae I: De Corpore Volume II. Elementorum Philosophiae II and III: De Homine and De Cive Volume III. Latin version of Leviathan. Volume IV. Various concerning mathematics, geometry and physics. Volume V. Various short works.

[show]

Links to related articles

Authority control View page ratings Rate this page What's this? Trustworthy Objective Complete Well-written

WorldCat VIAF: 59083895 LCCN: n79059190

I am highly knowledgeable about this topic (optional) Categories:


1588 births 1679 deaths 17th-century Latin-language writers 17th-century philosophers Alumni of Magdalen Hall, Oxford Early modern philosophers Empiricists English philosophers English political philosophers Materialists People from Malmesbury Philosophers of law Political theorists Political realists

Navigation menu

Create account Log in Article Talk Read View source View history

Main page Contents Featured content Current events Random article

Donate to Wikipedia

Interaction

Help About Wikipedia Community portal Recent changes Contact Wikipedia

Toolbox Print/export Languages


Afrikaans Aragons Azrbaycanca Bn-lm-g Bosanski Brezhoneg Catal esky Cymraeg Dansk Deutsch Eesti Espaol Esperanto Estremeu Euskara Franais Galego Hrvatski Ido Bahasa Indonesia slenska Italiano

Basa Jawa Kiswahili Kurd Latina Latvieu Lietuvi Magyar Nederlands Norsk (bokml) Norsk (nynorsk) Occitan Piemontis Polski Portugus Romn Shqip Sicilianu Simple English Slovenina Slovenina Soomaaliga / srpski Srpskohrvatski / Suomi Svenska Tagalog Taqbaylit /tatara Trke Ting Vit Winaray Yorb This page was last modified on 19 January 2013 at 10:43. Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. See Terms of Use for details.

Wikipedia is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization. Contact us Privacy policy About Wikipedia Disclaimers Mobile view

Potrebbero piacerti anche