Sei sulla pagina 1di 30

Econ 710

Lecture Slides 2
Consumer Choice, Preferences and Utility
Fei Li
University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill
August 29, 2013
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 1 / 30
Consumer Theory
Consumer is the DM,
Commodities (Goods) l = 1, ...L,
Consumption Set X
contains all commodity bundles that can be conceivably consumed,
reects physical constraints (cannot consume negative amounts of
food, discrete goods, survival needs, cannot work more than 24 hr per
day),
reects institutional constraints (zero pork consumption in Muslim
countries, cannot work 1 minutes per day in a regular position, cannot
buy gun in many countries)
Main example: X = R
L
+
.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 2 / 30
Consumption Set Assumptions
Nonnegative: X R
L
+
perfectly divisible good.
Not important.
Closed: X is a closed set
Not economically important.
Convexity: X is a convex set
any x, y X and (0, 1), we have x + (1 )y X.
Both technically and economically important.
lunch in DC and NYC at the same time.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 3 / 30
Competitive Budget Sets
Competitive Markets
all goods can be purchased in any amount at known prices,
p = (p
1
, ....p
L
)
all prices are positive: p 0
the consumer is a price taker
Walrasian (Competitive) Budget Set
Given the price vector p and the consumers income m _ 0, his budget
set is
B(p, m) := x X : p x _ m
B(p, m) is the consumers feasible set.
It reects the economic constraint.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 4 / 30
Competitive Budget Sets
Since we are in R
L
space and p 0, B(p, m) is compact (closed and
bounded).
B(p, m) = B(p, m) for > 0
B(p, m) is a convex set.
if x, y B(p, m), for any , x + (1 )y B(p, m).
it rules out some relevant case: many employment contracts require
working for no less than 8 hr per day.
Budget Hyperplane: x R
L
+
: p x = m
describes a family of (just aordable) consumption bundles,
budget line when L = 2, and the slop p
1
/p
2
captures the rate of
exchange between the two goods.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 5 / 30
Demand Correspondences
The consumers choice correspondence, dened on the set of all
budget sets, is called his (Marshallian) demand correspondence.
For all (p, m),
x(p, m) B(p, m) X
If x(p, m) contains a single points for each (p, m) R
L
++
R
+
, we
say it is a demand function.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 6 / 30
Demand Correspondences
Denition
A demand correspondence x(p, m) satises Walras Law i for all
(p, m) R
L
++
R
+
,
p x = m for each x x(p, m)
Demand only on the budget hyperplane. (expends all income)
At this point, Walras law is just a property our economic intuition
tells us should be plausible.
When we get to the preference-based approach to consumer theory,
we shall nd fairly weak conditions under which Walras law must
hold.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 7 / 30
Demand Correspondences
Denition
A demand correspondence x(p, m) satises Homogeneous of Degree
Zero i for all (p, m) R
L
++
R
+
,
x(p, m) = x(p, m) for all > 0
No framing eects since B(p, m) and B(p, m) are the same set.
No money or price illusion.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 8 / 30
Demand Correspondences
Example
Consider the following demand function.
x
1
(p, m) =
p
2
p
1
+p
2
m
p
1
, and x
2
(p, m) =
p
1
p
1
+p
2
m
p
2
Does it satises (1) homogeneous of degree zero and (2) Walras law?
1
yes for all , R.
2
yes only if = = 1 since
p x = [
p
2
p
1
+p
2
+
p
1
p
1
+p
2
]m.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 9 / 30
Demand Function Comparative Statics
The comparative statics properties of a demand function x (p, m)
consist of how it changes when its arguments change.
The most common comparative statics questions are about the signs
of changes, e.g., is x
l
> 0 if m > 0 and p = 0?
We often assume x (p, m) is dierentiable. Then the questions are
about the signs of the partial derivatives,
x
l
(p, m)
p
k
and
x
l
(p, m)
m
for l , k 1, 2, ...K.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 10 / 30
Income Eects
Normal (x
l
/m > 0) v.s. inferior (x
l
/m < 0) goods
these are local properties.
we shall see when we consider preference-based demand, that even
under standard assumptions goods can be inferior or normal.
Engel curves describe how household expenditure on particular goods
or services depends on household income.
Engels law:
It is an empirical observation in Engel (1857).
It states that the poorer a family is, the larger the budget share it
spends on nourishment.
Chai, Andreas, and Alessio Moneta. 2010. "Retrospectives: Engel
Curves." Journal of Economic Perspectives, 24(1): 225-40.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 11 / 30
Price Eects
A demand function x
l
(p, m) satises the Law of Demand i
x
l
/p
l
< 0.
We shall see that preference-based demand, even under standard
assumptions, may not satisfy the Law of Demand.
Good l is called a Gien good if its demand curve slopes up
x
l
/p
l
> 0.
Good k is a (gross) substitute for good l i x
l
/p
k
> 0.
Good k is a (gross) complement for good l i x
l
/p
k
< 0.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 12 / 30
Preference-Based Demand Correspondences
We start from the choice itself, and some of its desirable properties.
Question:
Where the demand function x (p, m) comes from?
Answer:
A consumers rational choice.
Basic problem in the preference-based Consumer theory:
to choose a feasible bundle x B (p, m) .
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 13 / 30
Preference-Based Demand Correspondences
Assume that for a rational preference relation _,
x(p, m) = C
+
(B(p, m), _)
In other words, the demand results from a rational choice.
Since B(p, m) = B(p, m), we have an immediate result.
Theorem
Preference-based demand correspondences are homogenous of degree zero
in (p, m).
Without loss of any generality, we can normalize the price of a good to be
one.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 14 / 30
Restrictions on the Consumers Preference
Denition
A preference _ on X is
locally non-satiated (NS) if any open neighborhood of any x X
contains a bundle y s.t. y ~ x.
monotone (M) if x y =x ~ y.
strongly monotone (SM) if x _ y and x ,= y implies x ~ y.
Immediately, we have
(SM) =(M) =(NS).
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 15 / 30
Restrictions on the Consumers Preference
More implications:
Theorem
If _ satises NS, then x(p, m) = C
+
(B(p, m), _) satises Walras law.
Proof.
Suppose not. x (p, m) p < m. Then > 0, such that \
x
/
N

[x (p, m)], x
/
p < m. By (NS), there is a x
/
~ x, which is a
contradiction!
Lemma
Suppose a rational preference _ is monotone and it is represented by u.
Then u is nondecreasing.
Proof.
Exercise.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 16 / 30
Continuity
Denition
A preference _ on X is continuous i for any sequence [x
n
[ with x
n
x
and x
n
_ y for all n, we have x _ y.
a
a
The denition is dierent from Denition 3.C.1 in MWG.
Example (Lexicographic preferences)
x
n
= (1/n, 0) and y = (0, 1). For each n, we have x
n
~ y. But
y = (0, 1) ~ (0, 0) = lim
n
x
n
.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 17 / 30
Continuity
Lemma
The following statements are equivalent:
1
A preference is continuous,
2
the upper and lower contour sets, y X : y _ x and
y X : x _ y, are closed.
3
the strict upper and lower contour sets, y X : y ~ x and
y X : x ~ y, are open.
4
if x ~ y, then neighborhoods, N
x
exist s.t. x
/
~ y for all x
/
N
x
.
Intuition on BB.
Proof.
Key: NWT (y) = x[x _ y and BT (y) = x[x ~ y.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 18 / 30
Utility Representation Theorem
Theorem (Monotone Representation Theorem)
A continuous rational preference _ on R
L
+
that is monotone is
representable by a continuous function u.
When L = 1, trivial!
Suppose L = 2, see the graph on BB for intuition.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 19 / 30
Proof: construction
Let x R
L
+
. Dene two subsets of R
L
+
:
A
+
(x) := R
+
: e _ x, and A

(x) := R
+
: x _ e
where e = (1, 1....1).
by monotonicity A
+
(x) is nonempty. Since (0, ...0) A

(x), A

(x)
is nonempty too.
By continuity, both sets are closed.
By completeness, A
+
(x)
S
A

(x) = R
+
,
Since R
+
is connected, A
+
(x)
T
A

(x) ,= ?. (otherwise, one of


them is open)
(x) = A
+
(x)
T
A

(x) is a singleton. (if there are two: , , then


~ , but then by monotonicity = )
so there exists a unique (x) s.t. (x)e ~ x.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 20 / 30
Proof: Representation
(=) Suppose u(x) _ u(y). There are two cases:
1
If they are equal, then x ~ (x)e ~ y, so x _ y.
2
If u(x) > u(y). then u(x)e ~ u(y)e by monotonicity. Since
x ~ u(x)e and y ~ u(y)e, x ~ y.
(=) Suppose x _ y. Then
u(x)e ~ x _ y ~ u(y)e.
Hence u(x)e _ u(y)e. By monotonicity, we must have u(x) _ u(y).
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 21 / 30
Proof: Continuity
Recall that u is continuous if for any a R, the sets u
1
(a, ) and
u
1
(, a) are open in the domain of u.
Since u(a, ...a) = a, these sets are strict contour sets:
u
1
((a, )) = x : u(x) > u(a) = x : x ~ a
and
u
1
((, a) = x : u (x) < u (a) = x : a ~ x
Hence, the proof is complete.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 22 / 30
Debrue Theorem
Monotonicity is not necessary for the utility representation but makes the
proof intuitive. In general, we have
Theorem (Debreus Representation Theorem)
1
For any a and b > a in R, a continuous rational preference on a
connected set X _ R
L
is representable by a continuous function
u : X [a, b].
2
If a continuous function u represents a preference _, then _ is
continuous.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 23 / 30
Debrue Theorem: Proof
The proof of the rst part is mathematically technical and not very
economically based. See Rubinstein (2013) for the proof of most of the
theorem. We provide the proof of the second part here.
Proof.
Suppose the preference is not continuous. There exists a sequence
x
n
x, and x
n
_ y for any n but y ~ x. Since _ is represented by
u (), u (x
n
) _ u (y) and u (x) < u (y). By the continuity of u (),
> 0, s.t. \x
/
N

(x), u (x
/
) < u (y) or y ~ x
/
. Contradiction!
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 24 / 30
Dierentiability
We often assume the utility function is dierentiable for tractability.
A classical non-dierentiable utility is Leontief utility function,
min x
1
, x
2
.
However, there is no generally accepted justication for the
dierentiability of utility functions.
See Rubinstein (2013) for some justications.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 25 / 30
Homotheticity
Denition
A preference _ is homothetic i x _ y implies that for any _ 0,
x _ y.
Theorem
A rational preference is continuous, monotone, and homothetic i they can
be represented by a continuous and homogenous utility function:
u(x) = u(x).
Proof.
\ =
//
For any x, there exists a(x), s.t. x ~ (, , ....). We let
u(x) = (x). Since the preference is homothetic,
u(x) ~ (, , ...). So u(x) = = u(x). \ =
//
, obvious.
Notice that u may not be a linear function. For example,
u (x
1
, x
2
) = x

1
x
1
2
for (0, 1).
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 26 / 30
Separable Utility
In many applications, we always assume the consumers preference is
separable.
Example
1
In Macro, U(c
1
, c
2
, ....c
t
) =

t=1

t
u(c
t
) where (0, 1),
2
In labor, U(c, h) = u(c) +v(h)
3
In IO and auction theory, U(q, m) = u(q) +m
It captures the idea that agents preference over dierent goods are
somehow independent.
What implicit assumptions we made by assuming separable utility?
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 27 / 30
Separable Utility
Consider a two-goods world.
Denition
A preference _ on X satises double cancellation property i
(x
1
, x
2
) _ (y
1
, y
2
) and (y
1
, z
2
) _ (z
1
, x
2
) implies that (x
1
, z
2
) _ (z
1
, y
2
).
Lemma
Suppose _ is represented by U(x
1
, x
2
). U(x
1
, x
2
) = u
1
(x
1
) +u
2
(x
2
) only
if _ satises double cancellation property.
Proof.
Since (x
1
, x
2
) _ (y
1
, y
2
), (y
1
, z
2
) _ (z
1
, x
2
) and U = u
1
+u
2
represents
_, we must have u
1
(x
1
) +u
2
(x
2
) _ u
1
(y
1
) +u
2
(y
2
), and
u
1
(y
1
) +u
2
(z
2
) _ u
1
(z
1
) +u
2
(x
2
). Adding two inequality together yields
u
1
(x
1
) +u
2
(z
2
) _ u
1
(z
1
) +u
2
(y
2
), so (x
1
, z
2
) _ (z
1
, y
2
).
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 28 / 30
Quasi-linear Utility
Theorem
A rational preference _ on X = R
2
satises the following three conditions
1
(t is valuable) (t, y) _ (t
/
, y) i t _ t
/
,
2
(compensation is possible) For every y, y
+
R, there exists some
t R s.t. (0, y) ~ (t, y
+
).
3
(no wealth eects) if (t, y) _ (t
/
, y
/
) then for all d R,
(t +d, y) _ (t
/
+d, y
/
).
if and only if it can be represented by a utility function of the form
u(t, y) = t +v(y).
In application, the rst good is interpreted as money, wealth or numerate
good.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 29 / 30
Proof
the proof of if part is simply to verify three conditions, so we only show
the Only If part. Fix a y
+
,
by condition (2), dene a function v(y) s.t. (0, y) ~ (v(y), y
+
).
by condition (3), for any (t, y), (t
/
, y
/
), (t, y) ~ (t +v(y), y+) and
(t
/
, y
/
) ~ (t
/
+v(y
/
), y+).
by transitivity, (t, y) _ (t
/
, y
/
) i
(t, y) ~ (t +v(y), y+) _ (t
/
, y
/
) ~ (t
/
+v(y
/
), y+).
by condition (1), this is equivalent to
t +v(y) _ t
/
+v(y
/
)
so (t, y) _ (t
/
, y
/
) i t +v(y) _ t
/
+v(y
/
), and the proof is
complete.
Fei Li (UNC) Lecture 2 August 29, 2013 30 / 30

Potrebbero piacerti anche