Sei sulla pagina 1di 18

Anaximander's "Apeiron"

Author(s): H. B. Gottschalk
Source: Phronesis, Vol. 10, No. 1 (1965), pp. 37-53
Published by: BRILL
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4181755 .
Accessed: 24/09/2013 11:18
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
.
BRILL is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Phronesis.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Anaximander's Apeiron'
H. B. GOTTSCHALK
Fifteen years ago W. Kraus began an article on the Apeiron by
saying that "It is now generally agreed that Anaximander's
Infinite is not material in any real sense".2 Since then a consider-
able number of studies have been published and several divergent
views of the Apeiron have been maintained.3 The problem arises from
the apparent inconsistencies in the evidence of Aristotle and Theo-
phrastus. Their statements fall into three groups:
1. At Metaph. 1069b22 and Phys. 207a21ff and b35ff4 Aristotle
appears to identify the Apeiron with his own completely potential
prime matter. It is obvious that Anaximander cannot have thought of
it in this way, but does Aristotle really claim that he did, as Cherniss
asserts?5 In the Metaphysics passage his object is to illustrate his
doctrine that all things come into being out of what is potentially, but
not actually. As an example of this he refers to those physical systems
in which the world is made to arise from a substance without any
specific character of its own, i.e., those of Anaximander and Demo-
critus, to whose first principles no sensible qualities could be assigned,
and of Empedocles and Anaxagoras, who are treated, for the purpose
of this argument, as if their first principles were respectively the
acop&poq
and the primeval mixture; looked at in this way they become
1
This article is a revised version of a paper read to the Northern Association
for Ancient Philosophy in March, 1963. I am grateful to the members of the
Association for their helpful discussion. This does not mean that they neces-
sarily agree with the views put forward here.
2 W. Kraus, "Das Wesen des Unendlichen bei A.", Rh.Mus. 93 (1950), 364ff.
8 The most important recent discussions are by G. Vlastos, "Equality and Justice
in Early Greek Cosmologies", C.Ph. 42 (1947), 168ff; F. M. Cornford, Principium
Sapientiae p. 159ff; U. H6lscher, Hermes 81 (1953), 257ff; 385ff; J. B. McDiar-
mid, "Theophrastus on Pre-Socratic Causes", Harvard Studies 61 (1953), 96ff;
G. S. Kirk, CQ 49 (1955), 21ff; C. H. Kahn, A. and the Origins of Greek Cosmology,
N.Y. 1960; P. Seligman, The Apeiron of A., London, 1962; and the relevant
chapters in Kirk and Raven, The Pre-Socratic Philosophers, and W. K. C.
Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy, vol. 1.
'Cf. VS 59A61, 12A14.
6 H. Cherniss, Aristotle's criticism of Pre-Socratic Philosophy, p. 366.
37
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
monists having an indeterminate substance as their first principle. If
these substances are completely indeterminate, it follows that they are
nothing in actuality but everything potentially, and so indistinguishable
from Aristotle's prime matter.6 But Aristotle does not pretend that this
accurately represents his predecessors' thought. On the contrary, the
very tentative language in which he states his conclusion shows quite
clearly that he was drawing his own inference from their writings.7
The Physics passage comes at the end of Aristotle's discussion of
infinity. Since every complete thing is determined and therefore
limited, Aristotle concludes that the infinite is essentially incomplete
and can only become something complete by being limited; in itself it
is only potentially anything, i.e., it behaves as matter rather than form.
Moreover, he goes on, all earlier thinkers appear to treat the infinite as
matter, therefore it is nonsense to speak of it as that which embraces
all things rather than that which is embraced.8 The last clause almost
certainly alludes to Anaximander's doctrine,9 but Aristotle does not
attribute his own doctrine of matter to him. What he says is that
Anaximander should have arrived at this concept, if he had thought
out the implications of his own statements about the first principle.
2. More important are two passages in which Anaximander is grouped
with the Pluralists. One of these is Phys. 1877a20 (= VS A 16), where
the early philosophers are divided into two groups, those who take as
their first principle a specific substance of which other substances are
modifications, and those who derive the other substances from the
papXy
by a process of 'separating-out' (?XxpEveaOxL), implying that these
substances pre-existed in the
apyn
in some way. The second group is
made to include Anaximander, Empedocles and Anaxagoras; but
Anaximander's principle is referred to as 'r gv, while it is said of the
others that they regard the one and the many as truly existing, and
6
Seligman (p. 24ff, 28ff) also compares Metaph. 983b6ff, but here Aristotle
only says that the earliest philosophers posited causes 'of a material kind' (&v
U%vj
e2et, cf. Ross ad loc.); all the thinkers to whom he refers, from Thales to
Anaxagoras, derived the world from one or more fully qualified substances, and
Anaximander is not even mentioned.
7
&(yre TG
q
0
7jq
&v elev
IA.vot,
1069b24; also the
PfX-nov
yap of b21.
8
poMVOEV0ML 8
7r&VTC4
XOa
0t &XXOL
&q
U\ XP
[VOL
')
&1rCEP(P.
8M
XaI
&TOWOV
T6
tepLtXoV
nOLvLm ik L 7
neptsX61ievov,
208a2-24. The word u'n is used in the
same wide sense as at Metaph. 983b7.
9
Cf. Phys. 203 b 1Off = Anaximander A 15; below, p. 39.
38
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
their original state is called a 'mixture'.10 This distinction is important;
it suggests that Anaximander regarded the Apeiron as a unity, even
though he held that the world came from it by a process involving
'separation'.1' This is confirmed by GC 314allff, where we find the
same division into monists and pluralists. But this time the criterion is
whether they believed in one elemental substance or many, and
Anaximander is not included among the pluralists.12
The second of these passages is Metaph. 1069b22, to which I have
already referred in a different connection. Here Aristotle speaks of
'ECuneaoxX6ouq
76
[LypX
xct 'AvsLxto?v8pou, and does not distinguish
Anaximander from the Pluralists proper. This however does not
invalidate the distinction drawn at Phys. 187 a20. The Physics passage
is part of a summary of earlier views which, within its limits, is clearly
meant to be historically accurate, while the sentence from the Meta-
physics is a mere aside, such as a modern writer would put into a
footnote, and is carelessly written.13 Moreover, to make his point
Aristotle had to emphasise the unity, not the plurality, of the &pcAt to
which he refers; they had to be actually one, in order to be potentially
many. He is not making a pluralist of Anaximander, but monists of
Empedocles and Anaxagoras.
3. There is only one other passage relevant to the present discussion
in which Aristotle mentions Anaximander by name. At Phys. 203b lOff
he says that "those thinkers who do not posit a further cause, such as
Mind or Love, besides the Infinite" speak of it as 'surrounding' and
'guiding' all things, and regard it as divine; "for it is immortal and
deathless, as Anaximander says". Strictly speaking only the last pair
of epithets is ascribed to Anaximander. But Hippolytus14 tells us that
he spoke of the Apeiron as 'surrounding' the universe, and this makes
it likely that he also used the word
xufpcpv&v
of the Infinite. The
10
o' 8 .CO5 iO
k
^6o V
k
kv
ovvaTL6^Tmq 3xxp&eoct, 6a7rcp
'Avoc[Lxv8p6q
pC7)L,
xxol 8aoL 8' Ev xlct 7ro&
ya9XaLV,
cr7rep
'Etvre8oxXq
xxot 'MAvx y6pot cx T-roU pAyFto
yoc,P
XMl o0ToL
&XXpklOUaL -r&XXo, 187a20-23.
ii Cf. Simpl. 24, 25 = VS A 9; Zeller Ph.Gr.6 I 203 n. 1, Holscher p. 261ff.
12
Cf. Holscher i.c.
18
The word
[Ty[a
seems to be used with special reference to Empedocles, as in
similar contexts elsewhere (cf. Bonitz Index Arist. 467b15; it is attached to
Anaximander loosely, as Zeller puts it, by a 'slight zeugma'. (E. Zeller, Ph.Gr.5
I, 204 n. 1; cf. Holscher p. 262).
14
Ref. 1.6.1
=
VS A 11, from Theophrastus.
39
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
preceding sentence,'5 however, cannot have come from him, although
it is generally included in the testimonia for his philosophy.'6 Very
similar reasoning is used by Melissus (B 2, 3), and the structure of the
argument in Aristotle with its intricate series of dilemmas is more
suggestive of Elea than Miletus. Probably it is Aristotle's own re-
statement of an Eleatic argument.'7
These are all the explicit references to the Apeiron in Aristotle. But
there are several places where he speaks of thinkers who posit an
infinite simple bodily substance different from the elements, because if
one element were infinite, it would long ago have destroyed the rest.
One is at Phys. 204b 22ff, and in his commentary (p. 479.33) Simplicius
tells us that Anaximander is meant; earlier in the same commentary he
attributes to Anaximander the reason Aristotle gives here for making
the infinite substance different from the elements.18 At GC 329 a8ff the
same view is criticised again in very similar terms, and Kirk is almost
certainly right in saying that Aristotle is thinking of Anaximander
here."' Finally, on nine occasions, Aristotle mentions a theory which
makes the
?&pyX
something midway between air and water or between
fire and air.20 Whether this refers to Anaximander or not has been
much debated; even in antiquity the commentators were divided,
Alexander and the majority accepting the ascription to Anaximander
while Nicolaus of Damascus and Porphyry denied it.21 The arguments
on both sides are pretty evenly balanced, but probably Aristotle had
15 203b4ff.
16
VS A 15, Kahn p. 42, Seligman p. 57f. But see Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy
p. 57 n. 2.
17
Aristotle has reversed Melissus' argument; he infers the eternity of the
infinite from its infinity, whereas Melissus infers its infinity from the fact that it
had no beginning in time. This is certainly how Anaximander would have argued,
if he reasoned in this way at all. Jaeger (Theology o the Early Greek Philosophers
p. 27f) suggests that Melissus borrowed his argument from Anaximander; but
this is very unlikely.
18 Simpl. Phys. 24.21ff
= VS A 9
,
Arist. Phys. 204b26ff. There is also a
resemblance between 204b33ff and the sentence quoted as Anaximander's own
by Thphr. Phys. Op. fr. 2 = VS B 1.
19
CQ 49.25ff.
20
Between air and water:Phys. 203a18, 205 a27, Cael. 303b 12, Metaph. 989a14;
between fire and air, Phys. 187a14, GC 328b35, Metaph. 988a30; both possi-
bilities are mentioned at GC 332 a 21. The reference at Phys. 189 b 3 to a substance
intermediate between water and fire may be a slip. Cf. Ross on Phys. 187 a 14;
0. Gigon, Der Ursprung der gr. Philosophie p. 68ff; Kirk CQ 49.24ff; Kirk and
Raven p. lOff; Kahn p. 44ff.
21
Cf. Simpl. Phys. 149.9ff, 151.20ff, and Zeller I (ed. 5), 209.
40
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Anaximander in mind when he wrote at least some of these passages.
All the same, his vagueness and his refusal to name Anaximander as
the author show that he was doubtful about accepting this as a true
representation of his doctrine.
Theophrastus mentions Anaximander's doctrine twice. In the
fragment of the
cpuatxxv A6ioa dealing with the Milesians, Anaximander
is described as a monist who regarded the first principle as an infinite
substance different from the elements, which is eternal and ageless and
surrounds all the worlds; he is criticised for not saying what kind of
thing it is, and for only naming the material cause.22 All this adds
nothing to what Aristotle has told us.
Another passage is more difficult. This apparently came from the
chapter on Anaxagoras and has been taken to prove that Theophrastus
equated the Apeiron with the primeval mixture of Anaxagoras.
XCL sarocke (p-aLv 6o
0Oe6ppa'YoC
7poC7XtaL(q
t4
'AvacLvLmMpy
Asys,V
'0 'Avcx~oy6pcav
'
eNvo yip cpat v o LxpLaL'o ciepu Ir v Avcaypc ?XL Oc
yAp
9TLV eV T- MetpC? T05Ob
MeCpOU
'r'
aUYYeVn ?p?pEaOaL 7Cpoq ,X?qX,
xxl 6't p?iv rV TF 7rO C pua
y
V,
yEVeaC^xL xPuV, OICL g yn, yiV'
6pLotwq
3 xal2 tuv &khv dvxa-rov,
(4 Ot)
YLVO~LCVcoV
&X
? pX6VT& 7p6-?pOV. 68 XLV7Sb Xal
ysVeae&( xatrov C'7?ara tov voVv 6 Avcxiy6po,
iUcp'
o6
aLtXptv6F.pLv
rOUq
re
xoaCou;
xad
T-qv
-ov WCOV
(PUlJLV &y\Vv)a0v.
XOaL ouo
[Lvy
qprCm, X?Pv6v@cov
ao'?LSV &v O
'Avoxy6paq
T'c& .LC?V Utx?acq
XpXa4
07UCLpOU;
1tOLeLV,
F(qV
e 'r7 XtLVYaeCo4 XOC
LJ
yevia4sc
aT(dcw
[LaLv
TOV
VOVV- eL t1?n T 1L0LV Th)V tr6 V T(v u7rOX&OL FJ.CXV ?eVML cUpt)av &OpLtaOV
xoa X(T' ?I806 xxa'L Xocr o?y0,
ta9g
aVO sag &pxaa v ?yetv
T- VTe TOU
GU?CpOU
(PUMV
XMCO TOV V05V
-
&CF'?
YOCEV?1XL
TXo'
acq0urmXX
atroLyeoX?
7oyourkraEw;
noWv 'AvL,oct&vapu."23
Only the last seven lines (17-23) contain Theophrastus' own words.
But it has generally been assumed that the remainder, from line 11
where Theophrastus is first named, to the beginning of the actual
quotation, is a paraphrase of something Simplicius found in Theo-
phrastus, and is meant to justify his assimilating Anaxagoras' theory
22
Thphr. Phys.Op.
fr. 2 =
Simpl. Phys.
24.13ff = VS 12A9; Hippol.
Ref.
1.6.1 = VS A 11; Aet. 1.3.3 = VS A 14. The different versions of Theophrastus'
report, with the Aristotelian parallels, are printed in parallel columns in Kirk,
CQ 49.22.
28 Simpl. Phys. 27.11-23 = Thphr. Phys. Op. fr. 4 = VS 59A41. The same
quotation is repeated by Simpl. 154.17-23 (= VS 12A9a); in this version Simpl.
inserts 7r&v'rco before cpocLvcrxL in the last line. This word is taken into the text
by Diels in the Doxographi and in VS 12A9a, but not in VS 59A41.
41
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
to Anaximander's.24 Controversy has centred on the word CXsZvon in
line 12. By the normal rules it ought to refer to Anaximander, but
parallels have been adduced to show that it could refer to Anaxagoras,25
and the point is unlikely to be settled in this way.26 What no one seems
to have done so far is to consider the purpose of these sentences. The
second one (lines 15-17), about the function of Mind in Anaxagoras'
system, has clearly been put in to enable the reader to understand the
allusions to Mind in the quotation from Theophrastus. This leaves the
first sentence; and we have to ask whether it too forms part of Sim-
plicius' summary of Anaxagoras' views, or whether it gives Theo-
phrastus' reason for assimilating them to Anaximander's. Now in the
earlier part of the same paragraph27 Simplicius describes Anaxagoras'
doctrines that all substances have always existed, that there is a
portion of everything in everything, and that things appear to be the
substance of which they contain most. At line 15ff he tells us that
Mind was the agency which brought about the formation of the world.
The intervening sentence tells how the original mixture of all things
was broken up and like substances came together. This sentence is a
necessary link in the exposition; without it the sentence about Mind is
left hanging in the air. It must therefore refer to Anaxagoras. This also
explains why Anaxagoras is not named right at the beginning of the
next sentence, as he should have been if there were a change of subject.
Presumably Simplicius used the strong demonstrative in line 12
because he was returning to Anaxagoras after referring to Theophrastus.
The yxp in the same line is difficult; it might be anticipatory, but I
suspect that it refers back to the sentence "6T& (leg. 6,Tv) nXeZa'a 9vL,
-a5mrx 'vaXXo6r'co &v 9xoca6v a-TL XOctL v" (= Anaxag. fr. 12) which
immediately precedes the first mention of Theophrastus.
These sentences, then, continue the outline of Anaxagoras' teaching
begun on the previous page. They may be partly based on Theo-
phrastus, but they have no more to do with the actual quotation than
any others on the same page of Simplicius' text, and they certainly do
not give the reason for the interpretation of Anaxagoras which the
24 Cf. Diels in the apparatus criticus to Simpl. I.c., Kirk CQ 49.27n, and the
literature quoted in the next note but one.
25 E.g., Arist. de an. 404a27, also in a comparison.
26 For recent discussions see McDiarmid pp. 100, 142 n. 64, who makes it refer
to Anaximander, and Kahn p. 41f, who refers it to Anaxagoras.
27
P. 26.31-27.11
=
VS 59A41.
42
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
quotation contains.28 The ambiguity arose because Simplicius intro-
duced his quotation before he was ready for it, and then interrupted it
without erasing what he had already written. Once this is grasped its
meaning becomes plain. There are two ways of looking at Anaxagoras'
system: if we stress the fact that all substances have existed from all
time and were already present in the primeval mixture, we must say
that he posits an infinity of material oipxxL and one moving cause. But
if we regard his primeval mixture as a unity, his material principle
turns out to be a single infinite substance, and in this respect his teaching
is the same as Anaximander's. This is exactly what Aristotle had said,29
and it is also what Simplicius understood Theophrastus to mean, if we
may judge by the words with which he introduces the fragment of
Theophrastus when he quotes it a second time.30
The evidence of Aristotle and Theophrastus, then, can be summarised
as follows:
1. Anaximander's
4py)
was a principle 'of the material kind' and he
did not assume the existence of a further 'moving principle' such as
the Mind of Anaxagoras.
2. It was called 6 &7reLpov, in the singular.
3. It is 'divine', eternal, indestructible, and 'governs' the world.
4. It is corporeal but not identical with any of the elements or any
other known substance.
5. The universe was derived from it by a process involving 'separation',
and in this respect it resembled the primeval mixtures of Empedo-
cles and Anaxagoras.
6. Theophrastus classified Anaximander as a monist.
Most historians have followed Theophrastus and assumed that
Anaximander started with a single undifferentiated substance. But
this view has been attacked by Heidel and more recently by Cherniss
and McDiarmid, who believe that the Apeiron was a mixture like that
28
Diels (Doxogr. p. 479) was wrong to print them in widely-spaced type, as if
they had come directly from Theophrastus' book.
29
See above, p. 37.
0
xoct 86(ppmaTo 8i T6v 'AvaEmy6poxv et6 '6v 'AvmcELavopov auvsoJv xal oVSto5
XXoqLpiVeL
TX' D6 'Avaoy6pou
Xey6[evo,
C sVVxcOoL
VAXv
ocM-r6v 9uaLv ?kyCLV 9.
u7roxcLtevov, Simpl. Phys. 154.14ff = VS 12A9a, cf. Holscher p. 263, n. 5.
43
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
of Anaxagoras.31 They argue that Aristotle tried to read his own
doctrine of qualitative change into the Pre-socratics, and therefore
treated their
&pXoL
as single substances which could be starting-points
for differentiation according to his own rule; this tendency so domi-
nated his interpretation that he even tried to make the pluralist theories
conform to his pattern, But in spite of his bias he had to admit that
Anaximander was closer to the Pluralists than to the Monists in some
respects; from this they conclude that Anaximander was really a
Pluralist, and his 'monism' an invention of Aristotle's. Theophrastus,
according to this view, was too much under his master's influence to
contradict him, but he is refuted by his own paraphrase of Anaxi-
mander's doctrine; in the sentence "' Jv 8& N
y?veatq
zarL t0oz oaL, xaL
'rv qOopa
v ek
i toc5' yNvaOa" (= VS 12B1) the plurals J)v... rockoc
"imply that the material principle of existing things is not a single
entity but a multitude of some kind."32 The last argument is obviously
inconclusive.33 But quite apart from that, Cherniss' interpretation as
a whole misrepresents Aristotle. Aristotle was perfectly aware of the
distinction between monistic and pluralistic systems, and admitted
the existence of both. Why, then, should he insist on making a monist
of Anaximander, if he was really a pluralist? And where does he
attribute his own doctrine of &iX)oL%'a& to Anaximander? What he says
is that the elements evolved from the Apeiron by a process of 'separa-
tion' and not as a result of 'alteration', but that Anaximander, unlike
Empedocles and Anaxagoras, did not believe 'v xcri to?a& icn.34 This
is a very precise statement, which can only mean that Anaximander's
doctrine was essentially monistic, in spite of some resemblances to
those of the later pluralists; we have no reason at all for rejecting it.
On the other side there are some positive indications that the
Apeiron was conceived as a single entity.
8B
A. W. Heidel, "Qualitative Change in Pre-Socratic Philosophy", Arch.
Gesch. Philos. 19 (1906), 344ff; id. "On Anaximander", C.Ph. 7 (1912), 230ff;
Cherniss pp. 366f, 375f; McDiarmid lOOf. Contra Holscher p. 267f.
32
Cherniss
p.
377.
88
Though accepted by Vlastos (C.Ph. 42.170) it has been dismissed by Kirk
(C.Q. 49.35) as "too improbable to merit discussion". Cf. McDiarmid p. 141 n. 57.
84 Phys. 187a20ff. Cheriss' paraphrase of this passage (p. 375), "Aristotle
associates Anaximander with Anaxagoras and Empedocles, opposes this group
to the 'monists', and says that Anaximander as well as the other two posits a
mixture from which he derives other objects by a process of separation", distorts
the meaning of the text.
44
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
1. It was endowed with the characteristics of divinity: it was said to
be immortal and to govern the world. These statements are im-
possible to reconcile with the concept of a mechanical mixture all
of whose constituents have their separate identities from all time:
oix &yOCOv
7o?0uxoLpovc7].
2. Whatever the exact terms he used, Anaximander certainly believed
that things come into being and are destroyed. What could he have
meant by this, if all substances always existed in the Apeiron?
'Recomposition', Heidel thinks.35 But the notion that "there is no
coming into being or destruction, only the combination and
dissolution of substances which exist for ever" is propounded as a
novelty by Empedocles (fr. 8) and Anaxagoras (fr. 17).
3. The natural tendency of the Greeks was to explain the world by the
smallest possible number of causes. The pluralist systems were
devised as an answer to Parmenides and seem always to have been
regarded as second-best; the only one of them to have any lasting
influence was Atomism, which succeeded better than the rest in
maintaining the essential unity of the world. But there is no reason
why any thinker earlier than Parmenides should have adopted such
a theory, and no evidence that any philosopher between Anaxi-
mander and Parmenides was aware of this possibility.36
There remains the difficulty of reconciling the belief in a single first-
principle with the view that other substances are 'separated-out' of it.
As Aristotle states it, this implies that the things which are separated-
out pre-exist in the Apeiron before their separation.37 One solution
which has been put forward is that the Apeiron was a perfect fusion in
which the opposites were "so thoroughly mixed that none of them
appear as single, individual things".38 But it seems odd to speak of a
fusion with a separate identity existing before its constituents, and the
fundamental problem remains. If the source is genuinely one, in what
sense can the opposites pre-exist in it?
3
If they do pre-exist in the
35
Arch. Gesch. Philos. 19 (1906), 343.
38
Cf. Zeller I (ed. 5), 207f; Vlastos p. 171ff; Holscher p. 261f, 268; Kirk and
Raven p. 431.
a ot 8' &x roi &v6q &voiva4 -Ta&
kvmvn6rjTac
&xxptvcaOmt, Phys. 187a20.
38 Vlastos p. 171, Cornford Princ. Sap. p. 178; criticised by Seligman p. 46ff.
39
Vlastos (p. 171f and n. 147) tries to differentiate between the theories of
Empedocles and Anaxagoras, and the "unreformed doctrine of krasis" found in
some Hippocratic treatises, which he identifies with Anaximander's doctrine.
As an example of the latter he quotes Hippocr. VM 14 (not 16) TrXV5X
tiv
45
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
source, where is its unity, and is it legitimate to speak of their emer-
gence as 'coming into being'? In fact the concepts of pre-existence in
and emergence from a mixture or fusion, and of coming into being, are
incompatible. Putting the same thing historically, a philosopher who
believed that coming into being is possible and indeed natural would
not have conceived the (much more sophisticated) alternative, which
would have seemed pointless to him.
Now Aristotle's discussion of the pluralist thesis at Phys. 187a24ff
deals only with Empedocles and Anaxagoras, and evidently these
thinkers were in the forefront of his mind when he wrote about the
opposites being 'separated-out' of their source. The word vou'act in
particular seems to have come from Anaxagoras.40 But there is some
doubt also whether Anaximander used the term 'separate-out'
(CxxptVeAOxL) or 'separate-off' (abtoxpLveaOcL), and what exactly was
separated from the Apeiron.41 Simplicius repeats Aristotle's account,42
but in the only extant description of Anaximander's cosmogony, based
on Theophrastus, we find that something "capable of producing the hot
and the cold" was separated off from the Infinite and out of this a
sphere of flame grew round the air surrounding the earth like bark
round a tree." From this simile it would appear that Anaximander
[LetLeyCvm
xczl eX
pn
O CXX iOLGLV OOT?(rOCVep&
i'LV 05're XU74EL T&V &VOpco7OV, 6'rov
i 'r OU&rcav &d7oxpLO xmX mu'-6 &9' kwvrou ykvrmt, 'r6re xac qaxvep6v &a-t xoc XuTreL
'r6v &v6pw7rov. But this is no different from Anaxag. fr. 4 rplv 8U &7oxptOivoct 'roi-roc
n&v-rov 6?O6 &6v'r.v ou'
Xpot
1V8nXOq
iV OU8te( & r*xXWuE y&p 4
au'L0LLgLq
7TCVrcoV
Xp%m,sv,
and so Vlastos' distinction breaks down.
40
See the index to VS p. 161a43ff; cf. Holscher p. 261f. Vlastos (p. 171 and
n. 139) claims that "the same word occurs frequently in the pre-Socratics...
with the very sense required in the present context"; but it does not occur in
this sense in writers earlier than Parmenides.
41
Cf. Holscher l.c., Kirk and Raven p. 129ff, Kahn p. 40ff.
42
Verbatim at Phys. 150.22 (on 187a20); on p. 24.24 (== VS A9) he grafts a
reminiscence of Aristotle on to Theophrastus' account to produce,
"o&roq
86
OUX &OUOLO 4LOU ro) ( (OU ''V yfVeaLV Mtel, &)XX &.TOXpLVOjkVGV 'C&)V 6VONTE
43
Ps-Plut. Strom. 2 = VS 12A10, cpraal 8i 'r6 (? rt) &x 'ro5 at8ou
y6VL[OV
OCpFLoi3
-re xocd
4uXpo5
xoT-r& '?v
y&JcaLv 'roVe 'ro
x6a[Lou &.'roxpL"VOxL
XE 'MLVa iX 'Or&rOU
9?)OY56 a9OCtPOav
7repLtpurXVML T& 7repl 'V y?v &fpL
64
Tlw
V&gpy
cP?ot6v.
Earlier in the
same chapter it is said that the 'innumerable worlds' were separated off
(&7roxexp[aOmL) from the Infinite, but this seems to be due to the compiler
(against Holscher p. 265). The language of this sentence is certainly his own
(e.g. xczO6Xou, cf. Diels Doxogr. p. 156n) and Simplicius and Hippolytus have
ytveaOat
in the
corresponding place
of their
reports. Presumably Theophrastus
used the vague expression y(vcaOmL 'rob
o4pmvo6q
in his chapter on the Apeiron,
46
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
imagined the formation of the world as an organic process like the
growth of a plant or embryo, and the Apeiron as something capable of
producing seed; both exxp(veoaOo and &toxpELvaou were regularly used
of the bodily secretions, and could have had this sense in Anaximander's
book.44 The whole matter is very obscure, but at least we can say that
these expressions donot necessarilyimply thatwhateverwas 'separated-
off' from the Apeiron must have existed in it beforehand. If we take
the simile at its face value this becomes very unlikely.
Aristotle and Theophrastus may have misunderstood Anaximander's
use of &rroxpLveaOat, but they were certainly right to treat the Apeiron
as a single entity. But neither tells us what it was. To account for this
gap in their information, Kirk has supposed that they obtained their
knowledge of Anaximander's teaching from a collection of excerpts
from his book and did not have a copy of the original.45 There certainly
is a good deal of evidence to support this view. But if Anaximander's
book was lost beyond recovery by the middle of the fourth century, it
must have gone out of circulation considerably earlier; and it is not
easy to imagine anybody in the fifth century writing a summary of an
obsolete book of natural philosophy which was probably quite short
already.46 On the other hand, the verbatim quotation preserved by
Theophrastus shows that he had access to some original document, and
Theophrastus censured Anaximander for not specifying the nature of
the Apeiron.47 Probably therefore Aristotle and Theophrastus had read
his book, and if they could not give a precise account of the nature of
his first-principle, this was because Anaximander himself did not do so.
Nor is it difficult to see the reason for this. However he conceived
the 'opposites', Anaximander must have shared the common belief of
his time that they are in permanent conflict with one another, and that
the continuance of the universe depends on there being a certain balance
or 'equality' between them. To say this is not to read Aristotelian
notions into Anaximander.48 True, the opposites played an important
and the more accurate duroxplveaOcL when he came to explain how the universe
was derived from it.
"4 Cf. H. C.
Baldry, CQ 26 (1932), 29f, Guthrie p. 90f.
'r
CQ 49.37f; Kirk and Raven pp. 101, 105.
46 If the putative compiler was a pupil of Anaximander (cf. Kirk and Raven
p. 101) he would hardly have neglected the Apeiron.
47
Ap. Aet. 1.3.3. = VS 12 A 14.
48 As Cherniss (pp. 28, 376) and McDiarmid (p. 99) claim. Contra Vlastos p. 168f
and n. 121, and passim.
47
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
part in Aristotle's system, but he did not invent them. Similar ideas
were held by Alcmaeon and Heracleitus and were commonplace by the
time the 'Ancient Medicine' was written; they are clearly implied
already by Anaximander's fr. 1. This meant that anything infinite, or
even anything large enough to surround all things and to be their
source, must be completely impartial.49 It was not enough that it
should be different from any of the obvious
8uv&[uLSq
such as the hot
or the cold, light or darkness. It could not have any sensible qualities
at all, any more than the atoms of Democritus. It could only be
described as the source of all things, everlasting and indescribably vast;
these were its only properties. Like the atoms, it was a metaphysical
construction, devised to account for the origin of the world. Anaxi-
mander's originality lay in his ability to conceive such a thing without
clothing it in mythical attributes.50 Yet there was a limit to what he
could do. Democritus could abstract qualities from the substances in
which they inhere, and was thus enabled to relate the world of sense to
his first principles. This degree of abstraction was beyond the power of
Anaximander, hence he was unable to describe the relationship of
sensible things to their source in a coherent way; as Guthrie puts it
(p. 87), "In applying the ancient formula 'everything came into being
out of one thing', Anaximander virtually cheated." The result was a
dangerous gap in his system, but one that Anaximander apparently did
not notice. Presumably he just said that "in the beginning was the
Apeiron, existing from all time, etc", and then went on, rather like
Hesiod, to give a cosmogony of a kind that had already become in
large part traditional.51
It may seem bold to attribute abstract reasoning of this kind to
49
This is the reasoning attributed to Anaximander by Arist. Phys. 204b24ff,
Simpl. Phys. 479.34, 24.21ff (= VS 12A16, A9). According to McDiarmid i.c.
this 'reconstruction' is completely unhistorical, being based on the metaphor
8L86vact y&dp aiOT&
8txiqv
xxl tLaLV
&)XYXuOLq ~q6
&&8xEa later quoted by Theophrastus
(Phys.Op. fr. 2 _ VS B1). It is difficult to see why Aristotle's account should
be any the worse for that. Its only unhistorical feature is that he speaks of
elements rather than opposites, but this should not upset anyone. Aristotle does
not ascribe the doctrine of four elements to Anaximander.
50
Cf. Deichgraber Hermes 75 (1940), 15; Gigon p. 61.
51
If the greater part of Anaximander's book was taken up with detailed cos-
mology, it would explain why Aristotle and Theophrastus knew so much more
about this than the Apeiron. Chaos is described later in the Theogony (736ff),
but only because, unlike the Apeiron, it apparently became identified with a
part of the universe after its creation (cf. Theog. 700, 814). Cf. F. Solmsen
"Chaos and Apeiron", Stud. It. Fil. 24.1950.242ff.
48
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Anaximander, but fortunately we have a parallel which is attested
beyond any doubt. According to Aristotle he argued that the earth is
suspended at the centre of the universe without being supported by
anything else, because there was no reason why it should move in one
direction rather than another.52 In his recent book Kahn has rightly
stressed the rationalistic character of Anaximander's thought, which
marks him off from the other Milesian thinkers. Perhaps it is significant
that these two doctrines, the Apeiron and the free suspension of the
earth, were rejected by his successors, while his more empirical
cosmology became very influential.
If this is how Anaximander conceived the Apeiron, it becomes
possible to see why Aristotle treated it as he did. Not only was there a
gap in Anaximander's theory, but his first principle could not be
meaningfully described in Aristotelian terms. As an actually existing
corporeal substance it must, for Aristotle, be identical with one of the
four elements or a
compromise
between them
-
whether we call this a
mixture or an 'in-between' substance makes no difference.53 In reality
it was neither. No doubt this is why Aristotle made no attempt to
give a complete account of it. But sometimes he mentioned Anaxi-
mander's theory in order to illustrate some point he wanted to make.
On these occasions he always emphasised one aspect of it at the
expense of the rest, and to that extent distorted it. However, his
apparently contradictory statements can be reconciled if they refer to
an entity such as I have described. The Apeiron gave rise to everything
but was not identical with any conceivable sensible substance; there-
fore from Aristotles' point of view it must be everything potentially
and so appears simply as matter. At some stage in the evolution of the
world something was separated off from or out of the Apeiron; to this
extent it behaved like the primeval mixture of Anaxagoras. It was a
single substance actually existing and distinct from any of the elements;
this would make sense if it were an intermediate between the elements,
and Aristotle was probably thinking of Anaximander when he mention-
ed this as a possible basis for a monistic system. His procedure may
seem unsatisfactory to-day. But Aristotle was not writing as a
historian and did not have footnotes in which to deal with incidental
problems. Theophrastus, who was aiming at historical accuracy, told
us all there was to tell when he described the Apeiron as
ypu'V
TLVOX
52
Arist. Cael. 295 b 1Off
=
VS 12 A 26.
53
Cf. GC 1.10 and H. H. Joachim, J.Ph. 29 (1904), 72ff.
49
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
&6pwLaov."
Significantly he apparently did not refer to it as an 'inter-
mediate substance', made no attempt to identify it with prime matter,
and defined more precisely in what respect it resembled Anaxagoras'
mixture.
Modem scholars who have tried to say more about the nature of the
Apeiron have inevitably fallen into the same error as Aristotle. To say
that it was a mixture or complete fusion of the opposites is no different
from the kind of statement Aristotle made about it. The same is true of
the idea that it was not really a material substance at all. It was not
identical with any known or conceivable material substance. But the
notion of immaterial being was almost certainly unthinkable in the
sixth century B.C. Moreover, the Apeiron was the source of all physical
things, and this implies that it was itself a body of some kind. No
Greek ever accepted that the material world could arise from some-
thing non-material, though they were prepared to believe that the
original substance might be very different from what came out of it.
All these attempts to define the Apeiron more or less distort the truth,
and the reason is the same in every case. Like Aristotle, the writers
who make them are trying to describe the Apeiron in terms which
make sense to themselves and their audience.
We cannot describe the
Apeiron
as such. What it meant to Anaxi-
mander can only be gauged by considering its function in his system.
This function was a dual one. It was that from which all things have
sprung and to which they will ultimately return; and it 'embraced
and
governed' all things. The former role it took over from the first
principles of the mythological cosmogonies. These entities only acted
as the first parents of the universe. Once it had developed, they had no
more part in it. But the Apeiron has also usurped the function which
the mythographers gave to the later gods who seized power after the
creation of the world was complete. This unification was an important
feature of the philosophical as against the
mythological
world-picture,
and makes it quite impossible to reduce Anaximander's teaching to a
re-statement of the old myths, for all that they had some common
features.55 It implies a continuing relationship between the world
and
its source much more intimate than anything envisaged by Hesiod or
writers like him. For the same reason I should hesitate to join Selig-
man56 in describing Anaximander's thought as dualistic. Seligman
is
54Phys. Op. fr. 2 = FV 12A9.
55
There were other differences also; see above, p. 48 n. 51 and Holscher p. 411.
56
Pp. 54ff, 113; Deichgrdber (Hermes 75.17) is more cautious.
50
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
thinking primarily of the contrast between the changing physical world
and the permanence of the Apeiron, and within these limits he is
perfectly right. But the expression makes us think of 'matter' and
'spirit', and a modem reader might forget how closely the world was
linked with the Boundless in Anaximander's system. An idea of what
was in his mind can perhaps be gained by comparing the 'rational fire'
of the Stoics, in spite of the obvious differences. In one respect at least
the Stoic doctrine is closer to his than any other. In both systems the
originating substance did not give birth to the world directly but
produced first a moist seminal mass, from which everything else
later developed.57
From the foregoing it will be clear that Anaximander used the word
&7retpOV in its obvious sense of 'spatialy infinite'. This is how Aristotle
and Theophrastus understood it, and the meaning is well attested for
all periods of Greek literature; Anaximenes described the air as
&=erpos and according to Xenophanes the earth extends downwards
?&E7tLpOv.5 Nevertheless many scholars believe that for Anaximander
&,tepov meant primarily 'without internal boundaries or distinctions'
and hence 'qualitatively indeterminate'59 There is, however, not a
scrap of evidence that the word could have this meaning. Not only are
there no early parallels, as Kirk says.60 Aristotle and Porphyry, who
were interested in the concept and collected the meanings of the word,
do not mention any such usage.61 According to these authorities the
word could have three senses: infinite in extent or number; inescapable
(of fetters, etc.); and as an epithet of perfectly circular or spherical
objects, such as rings without a bezel, uninterrupted. The second
meaning is irrelevant to our purpose, the third is obviously derived
from the first.62 Thus it is illegitimate for Cornford to infer from this
67Diog.
Laert. 7.135f = Stoic.Vet.Fr. 2.580 VS 12A10.
68 Anaximenes VS 13 A5, from Theophrastus; Xenophanes fr. 28. For the later
Pre-Socratics see the index to VS; cf. Kraus p. 366ff, Kahn p. 231ff.
9
Tannery, Pour l'histoire de la science helldne, p. 94ff; Cornford, e.g., Princ. Sap.
p. 178; Guthrie p. 85ff. For other early supporters of this view, see Zeller I
(ed. 5),
199 n. 3.
60 Kirk and Raven p. 109. A. Rey (La jeunesse de la science grecque, p. 59) after
Rivaud (Probleme du devenir pp. 89 and 193) claims
&(7reEpoov arpr6v
from
Pindar as an instance of this use. He does not specify where it occurs, but
presumably he means 01. 11.18
uTy6teLvOv
mTpm&6v
V'
&.netpctov xM)'V.
61 Arist.
Phys.
I 4-8; Porph. Quaest. Hom. in Iliad.
p.
189ff Schrader = Schol. B.
in Iliad. 14.200, Schol. E in Od. 1.98.
*'
Cf. Arist. Phys. 207alff.
51
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
that &=LpOV could mean 'without intemal boundaries' and therefore
'indistinct'. Even if it could be translated 'without internal boundaries
or distinctions', this would simply denote a single, homogeneous
substance as opposed to a mechanical mixture or emulsion; it would
tell us nothing about the character or lack of character of the substance
to which it was applied, or about the relation of that substance to
others. There were no internal boundaries in Thales' water or Anaxi-
menes' air.
Such expedients can only be justified if there is no possible alter-
native. But the arguments used to show that Anaximander cannot have
intended the word to have its ordinary spatial meaning are not at all
convincing.
1. Tannery (p. 95f) argues that the 'eternal motion' of the Apeiron
was identical with the rotation of the heavens, and a rotating infinite
mass is impossible; and also that, since the earth rests at the centre of
the universe, the extension of the Apeiron must be limited. The second
of these arguments rests on a confusion between the extension of the
universe and of the primary substance, though they are by no means
the same. As for the first argument, this explanation of the 'eternal
motion' was already refuted by Zeller and scarcely anyone accepts it
to-day."
2. It is said that Anaximander did not have the Euclidean concept of
space and so could not have conceived of an infinite extension. Though
probably true, this is irrelevant. It is possible without having read
Euclid to imagine something going on and on without any limit. This
must have been what Xenophanes meant by saying that the earth
extends downwards
k
&zt?pov; presumably he thought it impossible
that there should by anything underneath.64 The same reasoning could
have been used by Anaximander; the Apeiron surrounds all things,
therefore there cannot be anything outside it to limit it, and so it must
be infinite.65 Cornford's alternative suggestion, that Anaximander"may
have thought of his Unlimited as an immense sphere" (p. 176f), is
much less likely. In all the passages where
t7Lpoq
or ObreLp6W refer to
63 Zeller I (ed. 5), 199 n. 3, 221 n. 2; cf. Burnet p. 61. R. Mondolfo,
L'Infinito
nel pensiero dell' antichita classica p. 320ff, tries to show that Anaximander
would not have looked on rotation as incompatible with the notion of infinitely
extended substance.
64 Was this intended as an attack on the existence of Tartarus?
65
Cf. Arist. Phys. 203bll, 20ff; Cornford (Princ. Sap. p. 175 n. 1) thinks that
this argument may go back to Anaximander. A similar argument is attributed
to Xenophanes at (Arist.) XMG 978 b 1.
52
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
circular or spherical objects, they are used as adjectives; their meaning
is still something like 'uninterrupted', and the notion of circularity is
contained in the nouns to which they are attached.66 There is no reason
to believe that this notion can attach to the word
&7tLpoq
by itself,
particularly when it is used as a noun.
3. Many interpreters feel that Anaximander ought to have given his
first principle a name which would convey something of its character;
in Kirk's words, "We might expect any such single description to refer
first to the kind of substance, not to its commonly assumed vastness
of extent."67 Now if Anaximander had wanted to indicate that his
apxn was an 'indefinite substance' there are words in Greek which
would have conveyed this unambiguously;68 he would hardly have
chosen a word whose ordinary meaning is quite different and which, as
far as we can tell, no Greek ever understood in that way. But
'indefinite substance' is not a suitable appellation for the parent and
ruler of the universe, and the word 'indefinite' is meaningless unless we
consciously abstract qualities from things, something that Anaxi-
mander probably could not do. The term &xuLpOv had the advantage of
predicating something positive of the
oCppn
without committing
Anaximander to any view of its nature. He chose it precisely because
it did not refer to the kind of substance but only to its vastness of
extent.
Leeds University.
66
Emped. fr. 28; Arist. Phys. 207 a 2; and the passages quoted by Porphyry l.c.
67
Kirk and Raven p. 109.
68
E.g.
&6pLaToq,
Thphr. ap. Simpl. Phys. 154.20
=
VS 12 A9a;
Mx8LxpL'roq,
Anon.
in Alcman fr. 5 p. 24.23 Page.
53
This content downloaded from 193.205.6.111 on Tue, 24 Sep 2013 11:18:48 AM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Potrebbero piacerti anche