Sei sulla pagina 1di 114

D. D. Raphael 1970. 1976.

1990
All rights reserved. No reproduction. copy or transmission
of this publication may be made without written permission.
No paragraph of this publicotion may be reproduced, copied
or transmitted save wilh written permission or in accordance
with the provision! of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act
Iq8 or under the terms of any licence permitting limited copying
issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency. 33- Alfred Place.
Lndon WCIE 7DP.
Any person who does any unauthorized act in relation to
this pUblication may he liable to criminal prosecution and
civil claims for damages.
First published 1970 by Pall Mall Press Ltd
Revised edition published by Macmillan Education Ltd 1976
Reprinted 1977, 1978. 1979 (twice), 1981. 1982, 198.1. 1984, 1987,1989
Second edition 1990
Published by
MACMILLAN EDUCATION LTD
Houndmills. Basing .. toke. Hampshire RG21 2XS
and London.
Companie$ and representati\es
throughout the world
Pholotypeset by Input Typesetting Ltd. London
Printed in Hong Kong
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
Raphael, D. O. (Da\id Daiches)
Problems of political philosophy. - 2nd ed. rev. and enl.
1. Politics
I. Title
320
lBSN O-JJJ-QRSti-. (hardcover)
ISBN 1}-3JJ .... 9859-3 (paperback)
. -\
" .
) :
. ( Ii
04762
f'
I
Contents
Preface to the First Edirioll vii
Preface to rhe Second Edition vi i i
!. What is Political Philosophy?
1.1 An example
1.2 Scientific theory and philosophical Iheory 5
1.3 Critical evaluation of beliefs 8
1.4 Clarification of coneepls 15
1.5 Philosophy and ideology 21
1.6 Methodology of the social sciences 2}
2. 'Politics and the State 30
2.1 The scope of politics 30
2.2 Associations and communities 35
2.3 Patterns of regulalion 37
2.4 Siale and nation 41
2.5 Distinctive features of the Stale 43
3. Liberty and Authority 56
3.1 The idea of freedom 56
3.2 Libcrly and law M
3.3 The limits of State authori!\' 74
4. Oemolrac),
X.
4.1 Democratic ideals :
4.2 Democratic governll1t R7
4.3 Democracy in inlerllinnal society 45
4. 4 Human right
lin
vi Contents
5. Justice
5.1 A complex concept
5.2 Equity and impartiality
5.3 The right to equality
5.4 Equity and utility
5.5
Competing conceptions of justice
6.
Sovereignty, Power and Authority
6.1 State sovereignty
6.2 The power theory
6.3
Objections to the power theory
6.4 Power and authority
6.5 Sovereign authority
7. Grounds of Political Obligation
7.1
Prudential and moral obligation
7.2 Moral grounds for political obligation
7.3
The theory of social contract
7.4 The theory of consent
7.5 The theory of the general will
7.6 The theory of justice
7.7
The theory of general interest or
common good
7.8 Obligation and authority
7.9 The extent of political obligation
Index
113
113
119
130
139
145
153
IS3
ISS
158
165
172
175
175
179
182
189
192
197
201
202
205
211
f
Preface to the First Edition
This book is intended to introduce students to the problems (not
the history) of political philosophy without presupposing any pre
vious knowledge of philosophy. A relatively short introtluction
must leave many things half-said and others not said at all. The
frst chapter is one man's picture of thc subject. not a programmc
for what follows. In what does follow there is inevitable selcction
and limitation, most apparent perhaps on the topic of dCl11orracy,
adequate discussion of which would necd a book to itself.
Chapters I-IV [now Chapters 1. 2. 6. and 7) were written in
the second of two terms which I spent as a Visiting Fellow of All
Souls College, Oxford, and I wish to record my gratitude to the
Warden and Fellows for the opportunity of full-time scholarlv
work in beautiful and peaceful surroundings, The difference
i
t
made may be judged from a comparison: Chapters I-IV were
completed at All Souls in six weeks; the writing of Chapters V-VII
[now Chapters 3-5) amid the press of my usual administrative and
teaching responsibilities at GJasgow stretched over ten months.
1 wish to express my thanks also 10 Mr Michael Lessnnff. who
read the book in typescript and made a number of valuable criti
cisms; Mr J. C. Rces. who gave me some comments on the frst
chapter; and Miss Anne S. Hutton, \\ho typed the work and rc
read the proofs with her customary effciency.
Parts of Chapter VI, Sections 1 and 3 {ncM 4.1 and 4.31. toge
ther with a little of Chapter III. Section 3 [now 6.3], are a revised
version of an article entitled 'Equality, Democracy, and Inter
national Law', which has previously been published in NOMOS
IX, Equalitl'.
Glasgow 1969 D. D. R.
11
Preface to the Second
Edition
The frst edition of this book was published in 1970 and a revised
version in 1976, The present second edition is the result of more
radical change, Apart from the updating of factual information in
various places, it contains several substantial additions (new Sec.
tions L, 4.4, and 5,5, and added passages in 1.3, 3,1, 3,2, 6,1,
and 7,9), An equally important change is a rearrangement of the
chapters, In the frst edition, the chapters now numbered 6 and
7 appeared as 3 and 4, This was a logical arrangement: the intra.
ductory chapter was followed by analysis of positive political con.
cepts, and then the latter half of the book dealt with the appli.
cation of such ideas in normative concepts, But it made things
diff

uH for the elementary student, for whom the book was pri.
manly Intended, The analytical discussion of such concepts as
sovereignty and of theories of the ground of political Obligation is
rather abstract and remote from everyday thought. Philosophical
discussion of other concepts and problems is also abstract, but
readers new to the SUbject are familiar with ideas like liberty,
democracy, and justice, So I have decided to take these earlier in
this new edition, Philosophical isues about liberty and justice are
related to political controversy, so that it is easier to see the
point of thc philosophical discussion, Readers are then in a bctter
position to understand philosophical analysis of the less familiar
notions, They may >till fnd the last section of Chapter I hard 10
follow, and if so, I suggest that they skip it and perhaps take it
up again after thcy have heen through the whole book,
I would like to Ihank John Horton, Michael Lessnoff, and Peter
Nicholson for helpful advice about the revision,
LOlldoll /989 D, D, R.
\'iii
"
1
What is Political
Philosophy?
1.1 An example
Political philosophy, like philosophy generally. is an abstract sub.
ject and 8 description of it is not easy for a beginner to follow.
The best way of getting to understand philosophy is to see it at
work. So before describing what political philosophy is, I am
going to start with an example. one that might have occurred to
any of us,
Suppose you disapprove strongly of some established policy
that IS backed by the force of law, Maybe you are opposcd to the
posseSSIOn or deployment of nuclear weapons or to vivisection
experiments on animals, Or, on the other side of the political
spectrum, you may be opposed to libertarian legiSlation thai per.
mits abortion or gives social dr()pouts a subsistence income at
public expense, You can protest and demonstrate to try to change
the offcial policy, But suppose you think that is not enough,
Protest and demonstration take a long time to have any effect:
but meanwhile the nuclear weapons pile lp. making the world
(as you believe) more and more dangerous: the animals in the
laboratories continue to suffer; the unnorn children continue to
be destroyed: the social urornuts continue (as you believe) to
he encouraged and to infect others with their couldn't-care-les
altitude. So you think you ought to take some morc effcctive
action
,
than protest and demonstration. such as sabotaging equip
ment 10 a nuclear arms hase, or breaking inln a biological labora
tory and setting the animals frcc, or else wi!hholdin a part of
your taxes that you eslimate to be the proportion going to pav
for the things which YOU oppose. If vou take such action VOll wiil
. , -
2 Problems of Political Philosophy
be breaking the law, law which you think misguided but which
nevertheless is binding upon you.
In all such instances, there is room for argument about the
rights and wrongs of the pOlicy concered. If the argument is
about nuClear weapons or beneft payments to drop-outs, we
should naturally describe it as political argument. If it is about
experiments on animals or abortion, we are more likely to call it
ethical argument, but since the debate is not just the expression
of opinion on what 'is morally right or wrong but is also designed
to infuence government policy, it can be called political too,
though not necessarily meaning that opinion is divided on party
political lines.
Political argument is not the same as political philosophy: It
requires a working out and balancing of a complex set of facts
and issues, ethical, psychological, and (in some of my examples)
economic. Philosophy cannot be much of a help for this kind of
problem, except to the extent that it might clarify the ethical ideas
involved.
But there is another kind of problem that my examples have
raised, and this is a problem of political philosophy. I have sup
posed that the objector to current offcial policy may think it is
not enough to protest and demonstrate, as he is free to do. He
may think he should take stronger action which would mean his
breaking the law. He disapproves of the particular law concerned
and would vote for its repeal, but because it is now valid law he
is required to conform to it. Why? Why should he be obliged to
obey this particular law if he thinks it is wrong? That is a problem
of political philosophy.
The kind of example I have used might give personal concern
to any individual today, but the problem is a more general one that
can arise in other contexts too. Historically it has been discussed in
relation to rebellion and civil war. Is an oppressed minority (or.
for that matter, a majority) justifed in trying to overtur the
established order by unconstitutional methods? Or do its members
have an obligation to keep within the law, however just their
grievance; and if so, why? The problem is called the problem of
political obligation: why arc we obliged to obey the laws of the
State?
One answer to this problem that has been proposed in the past
by philosophers has been the theory of social contract. The idea
f
What is Political Philosophy? 3
is that a citizen owes allegiance to the laws of his country in return
for the benefts of citizenship; he is party to a sort of agreement
or business deal. If he was not prepared to accept the obligations
of the deal, he could have left the country and gone elsewhere.
There is another version of the theory which says that States owe
their existence to a presumed contract or agreement by all the
citizens to set up a political authority for the general henefit. If
an individual later nnds that things nre not working out well for
him, he is not entitled to repudintc the social contract. un)' more
than he would be entitled to repudiate a private contract which
has turned out to be unlucky for him.
This kind of theory is unconvincing. A person who is dissatisfied
with the regime into which he was born is, more often that not.
unable to leave and settle in another country that suits him better:
and so far as the second form of the theory is concered. the
citizen can reasonably ask why he shoule! be subject to a supposed
contract or promise which he himself has never made. Despite its
implausibility, however, the social contract theory had a serious
purpose and was based on a sound point. The purpose of using
the concept of a promise or contract was to suggest that. despite
disagreement on particular issues. citizens have all given their
agreement to the need for a stable social order: and although the
suggestion itself is dubious, it is hased on the sound point that a
stable social order is generally benefcial even though it may bear
hardly on some individuals.
A similar sort of line is pursued in the theory of the general
will, originally put forward by the French thinker Jean-Jacques
Rousseau. Here too the idea is to buttress the sound point about
the general benefit of a stable social order and to do so by means
of a hypothetical device. We all knmv what it is for an individual
to make something the object of his 'wilr. tn aim at it and try to
achieve it. What a person aims at is most often .for the good or
beneft of himself; but he can also aim at the good of other
individuals or at the common good. the interest of all. When he
does aim at the common good. his 'will' or aim is one that can
be shared by everyone, so that the common good can be regarded
as the aim of a hypothetical 'general will'. If we were all to seek
the common good all the time, there would be no conficts
between particular interests, but unfortunately that is not the case.
According to the theory. the joh of the Stlile is to express the
''
4 Problems of Political Philosophy
general will and seek the common good, although that often
means going against particular wills aimed at particular interests.
The theory says that what the State tells us to do is what we really
want or will, because it is an expression of the general will, which
is a more genuine, a more properly human, will than particular
wills seeking particular interests. This is rather like the suggestion
of the social contract theory that, despite disagreement on the
surface, we have really, or more fundamentally, agreed to what
the State requires of us.
You may well ask: Is not all this a fudge? Why talk about a
hypothetical contract, or a hypothetical general will, as though it
were real, instead of simply saying that the purpose of the State
is to pursue the common good or general interest, and that it
deserves our support for that reason? A fair question. There are,
as a matter of fact, some underlying reasons for not dismissing
altogether the ideas of social contract and general will, but in
principle the query is well founded. It leads to a third. more
straightforward, theory of political obligation, the utilitarian
theory. This says that right actions and policies are those that aim
to increase the general happiness or general interest as much as
possible. According to utilitarianism, maximizing general happi
ness is the standard of right action both for ethics and for politics.
So we ought to obey the laws of the State simply because they
are intended to give effect to this proper and admirable aim.
That sounds simplc and sensible, but it opens up another prob
lem: who is to judge whether official policy does in fact promote
the general intcrest? The objector with whom we started thinks
it is wrong to have nuclear weapons (or to do vivisection exper
iments, or to permit abortion. Or to pay social benefts to drop
outs). In terms of utilitarian theory, his opinion that the policy is
wrong means that he thinks it fails to serve the general interest.
As I have said earlier, debate on the rightness or wrongness of
offcial poliCies is a matter of political argument. But the person
who is bothered by our problem of political philosophy may well
ask: 'Why should I be expected to assume that the government
(or the medical establishment) knows best what policy is in fact
right (or best scrvcs the clleral interest)? People in authority are
not omniscient. Why should I havc to accept their opinion when
I believe it to be misguided'' You can begin to see now why the
social contract and general will theories were not so silly in adding

a reference to the agreement or will of the cItizen. If it can be
shown that he himself has accepted the offcial policy, he is no
longer entitled to complain that hc thinks the policy misguided.
There are other reasons for querying the utilitarian theory.
Not everyone will agree that maximizing the gcneral happiness is
always the criterion of right action, either in ethics or in politics.
Sometimes a policy that looks to the gcneral interest alone
involves an unfair sacrifce of t he rights of individuals or sma II
groups. The criteria for right action must therefore include justice
as well as promoting the general intcrest. Some theorists go fur
ther and say that the utilitarian criterion of maximizing general
happiness is a proper aim for ethics but not for politics, The State,
they say. has no business to try h" make its citizens happier; that
is a matter for themselves or for non-compulsory organizations
such as religious or philanthropiL bodies. The State ha5 a more
basic function. to protect its citizens from harm and interference,
in a word, to safeguard justly acquired rights.
In line with this train of thought. an alternative theory of politi
cal obligation says that we are rcquired to obey the laws of the
State because their purpose is to secure justice or protect rights.
This theory was in fact put forward earlier than the utilitarian
theory, the utilitarian idea of the function of the State being a
fairly late development. Since nowadays most of us would think
that the State should do more than protect existing rights. it may
be that a combination of the justke and utilitarian theories is the
best answer to our problem.
In this section I have given only a brief outline of the problem
of political Obligation. A fuller treatment of its complexitics will
be found in Chapter 7. The brief account hcre is intendcd simply
to illustrate what sort of thing goes on in political philosophy.
We can now proceed to consider more dircctly what political
philosophy is.
1.2 Scientifc theory and philosophical the,)!'Y
The terms 'political theory' and ' political philosophy' are often
used interchangcably. but there is a recognizable diffcrence
between the theoretical work of political scientists and that of
pOlitical philosophcrs. Similarly there is a recognizable difference
between sociological theory. as pursued hy theoretically minded
rroDlems of rollflcal YhllOsophy
sociologists, and social philosophy. In discussing the difference
between the two types of theory, it will be useful to consider the
social and the political together. There is of course a distinction
between the social and the political, but my initial purpose is to
distinguish philosophical theorizing about society and the State
from the kind of theorizing that is done by some political scientists
and sociologists.
A defnition of 'politics', or of what can be described as 'politi
cal', is the subject of controversy and will be considered in 2.1.
For the moment it is more relevant to note that the idea of 'social'
studies can be used in a wider or in a narrower sense. In the
wider sense, social studies include the study of politics, embracing
everything that has to do with the activities of men in society;
much sociological theory is of this character. In the narrower
sense, social or sociological studies are confned to those areas of
socia) activity that do not form the subject-matter of other, more
defnitely circumscribed, social sciences, such as political science
or economics: into this category come sociological studies of the
family, or of religion as a social institution, or of educational
institutions. Usually, when speaking of social or sociological
theory. and still more when speaking of social philosophy, one is
using the term 'social" in the wider and not in the narrower sense.
Social philosophy is of broader scope than political philosophy
and can indeed be said to include it. Likewise social or sociological
theory is of broader scope than the theory of political science.
Social and political theory as pursued by sociologists and politi
cal scientists is theory in the scientifc sense of the term. Its aim
is explanation. Tl1e social sciences, like the natural. sciences (i.e.
the physical and biological sciences), do not merely record individ
ual facts but seek to explain them as instances of general laws.
and the attempt to provide such general explanatory laws consti
tutes the theoretical aspect of a science. Up to now, sociology
and politicaJ science have not been as successful as economics in
cstablishing explanatory laws, but many interesting hypotheses
have been put forward as candidates for the status of explanatory
laws, and these hypotheses can be tested in the same way as the
hypolhescs of nalural science. Recent work along these lines has
taken the form of providing sophisticaled 'models' of group behav
iour. but for Ihe purposes of elementary illustration it will suffce
10 mention some older and well-known generalizations. One
WhOT is Political Philosoph)'? 7
example is Karl Marx's theory Ihat a change from one form of
society to another is always the result of clas! struggle, which in
turn is ultimately due to changes in the 'forces of production', i.e.
in the materials or tools or type of labour used to produce goods.
Another example is Robert Michels' 'iron law of oligarchy', the
thesis that any organization, including those that begin democrat
ically, must end up under the control of a small group. A third
example, this time from the sociology of law. is Sir Henry Maine's
generalization that the legal systems of progressive societies move
from the idea of status 10 thaI of contract. A still narrower hypoth
esis, taken from the feld of political science, is the suggestion
that a multi-party political system leads to unstable government.
It may be that none of these hypotheses is a genuine explanatory
law, but this is what they aim to be, generalizations based on
facts of experience and serving 10 explain further such facts. The
generalizations are formed and are tested in the same way as
hypotheses in the natural sciences. They rest on the evidence of
factual instances, and they can be disproved by pointing to other
instances which do not conform to them.
Social and political philosophy is different, but in what way? It
is often said that social and political philosophy, as practised in
the past by traditional philosophers, differs from the scientifc
type of theory in being 'normalive' instead of 'positive'. What is
meant by this is that scientifc theory deals with positive facts,
with what is in fact the case, while Ihe philosophical kind of
'theory' is really a doctrine, or an 'ideology'. setting up 'norms'
or ideal standards for society and government, telling \ what
ought to be in the case, or what we ought to do. A prime example
is Plato's Republic. which depicts an ideal society or utopia. I
myself think that this vicw of tr;lllitional political philosophy is
questionable. It is true that some of the classical political philo
sophers have set out ideal forms of society. but in my opinion this
has not been their central concern. Even in Plato, the purp0se of
depicting an ideal society is to criticize existing society and to
promote understanding of general social concepts such as justice.
Social and political philosophy can bc regarded as normative in a
less obviolls way. hUI first I musl describe whal it does.
Social and political philosophy is of course a branch of philO
sophy: il is an applicalion of philosophical lhinking to ideas about
society and the State. Philosophy has taken many different forms,
w'
8 Problem oJ /OllClCaI rnlluSvpny
but I fnd it useful to interpret the main tradition of wester
philosophy as having had two connected aims: (a) the_clarifcation
of concepts, for the purpose of (b) the critical_"v.,!"tion of
\ids. In explaining these two aims of traditional philosophy, I
shall deal frst with (b), since that, in my opinion, has been the
basic aim, whether or not it can in fact be fulflled. In traditional
philosophy, aim (a), the clarifcation of concepts, has been subsidi
ary and was pursued only as a necessary aid to the basic aim of
evaluating beliefs; but in the philosophy of the present day, aim
(a) is paramount and is often pursued for its own sake.
1.3 Critical evaluation of beliefs
On the interpretation of traditional philosophy that I am putting
forward, its fundamental purpose has been the critical evaluation
<f.b
e\iefs, the attempt to give rational grounds for accepting or
rejecting certain beliefs which we normally take for granted with
out thinking of any grounds for justifcation. Philosophy differs
from science in that science seeks explanation while philosophy
seeks justifcation. The word 'justifcation' can, however, be mis
leading if one takes it to mean positive justifcation only. One is
then led to suppose that traditional philosophy must be conserva
tive, always attempting to defend old ideas in the face of new
ones that would upset the existing order. This of course is not
true. Sceptical philosophy has been at least as common as con
servative. I use the word 'justifcation' to m . an the giving of
rational or justifying grounds either for accepting a belief or for
rejciilg .it.
This procedure naturally has an important place in science too,
as it must have in any enterprise that sets out to be rational.
When a scientist adduces evidence and logical argument for or
against a hypothesis, he is presenting rational grounds for accept
ing the hypothesis as true or rejecting it as false. His work differs
from that of the philosopher in the character of the hypothesis
itself, which usually takes the Iorm of a causal explanation. The
scientist seeks causes; and in that quest, because his enterprise is
a rational one. unlikc thc irrational positing of causes in super
stition, h also seeks justifying reasons. The philosopher is not
specially concerned with causal explanation (except when he turns
his interest to the proccdure of science itself in order to under-
stand its character), and is not specially qualifed, as those versed
in a particular science are, to offer causal explanations. The philo
so
.
pne..i_a_9Y to iquire into rational grounds for or against any
kind of belief, not just beliefs about causes.
This is not to say that philosophers in fact turn their attention
to any and ever belief at any and every time. Philosophical
problems about particular kinds of belief arise from historical
circumstances. The need to seek rational grounds usually arises
when something has happened to make us doubt the validity of
a belief that has previously been taken for granted, and this
something has usually bcen a new belief that appears to be incom
patible with the old one. For example, the emergence of modern
science appeared to challenge thc validity of certain traditional
religious beliefs. The Copernican theory of the solar system was
incompatible with the idea, apparently attested by COmmon-sense
observation and by the cosmology of Genesis. that the earth is
fxed and that the sun and moon move around it. Again, the
Darwinian theory of evolution by natural selection was inconsist
ent with the biblical account of ercation.
The new scientifc theories were based upon rational methods
that commanded the respect of those who understood them. Since
the new theories appeared to connict with traditional beliefs, the
demands of consistency required one of three possibilities:
(I) The traditional beliefs could be discarded as myth. based on
imagination or limited evidence.
(2) The new beliefs could be rejected. on the ground that the
evidence for them was less reliable than that of scriptural
revelation.
(3) One or other of the two sets of beliefs could be modified so
as to make them compatible with each other.
The second course was taken by diehards. but it could not last
for long. since the claims of the new beliefs were rationally con
vincing. Hence the frst and the third possibilities have won out.
It is here that the philosophy of knowledge (commonly called
epistemology and metaphysics) has played its part. In the first
place, philosophers have tried to bring out clearly the underlying
implications of the two sets of beliefs, so as to show just where
the incompatibility lies. Secondly, philosophers have then re-
10 Problems of Politicl Philosophy
,.
commended ways of resolving the incompatibility, and these have
taken the form either of method (1) or of method (3). Method
(1) produces iconoclastic or sceptical philosophy - sceptical, that
is to say, in relation to traditional or common-sense beliefs, for\
although scepticism of this kind can then lead to a more general
ized scepticism, total scepticism has in fact been rare and a ieu
d'esprit. Other philosophers have pursued method (3) and have
been led to suggest new ways of looking at the data, new concep
tual schemes, i.e. new frames of ideas for ftting on al the relevant
facts, so as to produce consistency; a consequence of this has been
a modifed version of either the old beliefs, or of the new, or of
both.
A parallel proccss occurs in the philosophy of practice (moral,
social. and political philosophy). This is concerned, not with
bcliefs about what is tre. but with beliefs or principles about
what is right or good, for man and society. Traditional principles
of right and wrong, good and evil, come to be questioned in the
face of ncw knowledge, such as the knowledge that different
societies have different rules, or new scientifc knowledge about
the causes or effects of some modes of behaviour. For example.
when the Greek Sophists travelled to non-Greek lands and found.
different customs and moral rules in different societies, they were
led to question the supposed natural or absolute character of
moral principles; in consequence they asked themselves which
rules, if any, wcre realll' right, or was there nothing to choose
between them. Again. advances in psychology have shown that
some kinds of socially harmful behaviour on the part of certain
individuals are determined by pathological abnormalities and are
better treated as illness than as crime; this leads one to ask how
far the reinterpretation of such behaviour should be carried, and
whether our usual ideas of crime and responsibility, and indeed
more generally of moral and immoral conduct, need to be revised.
When such questioning occurs, the philosopher tries to consider
how far, and on what grounds. the traditional ideas, and the
new ones, can be rationally justifed. As in the philosophy of
knowledge, he tries to bring out the underlying implications of
the old and the new, to locate the precise points at which there
is inconsistency. and to resolve the inconsistencies either by reject
ing the old beliefs or by proposing a revised conceptual framework
wna{ I QIILO! rllllOsoplty!
which will accommodate all the data but with a modifcation of
either or both of the conflicting sets of ide-as,
That, as I see it, has been the primary task of traditional philo.
sophy, whether in.the feld of knowledge or in that of action. Of
course, once a problem has been raised and has been met by
the propounding of a new conceptual framework or 'system of
philosophy', other thinkers are liable to tur their attntion to
that system itself. Philosophy lives by constant criticism. I t arises
from doubt and criticism of existing ideas, and it remains vigorous
and healthy only if it is self-critical also. So the emergence of a
new philosophical schema. in answer to a problem that frst arose
outside philosophy, tends to pn\duLt' a circle of philusuphical
discussion about that schema itsclf. as well as about the problem
which produced it. As in science, nil inquiry which originated
in external needs will then be pursued for its own sake. The
philosophical schema of one thinker will be revised by others or
succeeded by a different type of schema which avoids the defects
of the frst. In the course of this progression of philosophical
discussion, the original external problem is sometimes forgotten.
or else it is treated as still an intellectual problem when the doubts
and difficulties of real life that nrst produced it have long been
resolved; and then philosophical inquiry seems to the man in the
street an arid waste of time on things thal do not matter; it has
degenerated into an intellectual exercise that interests onlv a small
coterie of initiates. But in time there is liable to arise sme new
probl

m whiCh, like the original onc, really docs disturb long


s
.
tand1l1g behefs that we carry about with us and use in our daily
bfe, and then a new philosophical movement appears.
.
My account of the primary aim of traditional philosophy is an
lO?IVldual mtcrprctation, but I think a gond many philosophers
might agree that it is a fair description of one important function
of philosophy in the past. Now this aim of traditional philosophy
has come to be mistrusted for the following reason. If a belief is
to be rationally justifed. it must satisfy two criteria. The Rrst is
c

sistency, and the means of testing this is logic, the_chief tool


of tfepliilosopher. But consistency alone is not enough to make
a belief, or set of beliefs, rationally acceptable. Suppose we have
two or more sets of beliefs, each of which is internally consistent,
but which are inconsstent at some points with each other. like
alternative systems o( geometry. H{)w are we to know \vhich of
12 rroblems of roltucm rnuosopny
them ought to be accepted? We therefore need a second criterion.
In the case of beliefs about matters of fact, we need to know
which of the internally consistent alternatives is true, i.e. which
applies to, or accords with, the actual facts of the world. While
philosophers are well qualifed to test consistency, they are in no
special position to say what the relevant facts are. Their specialty
is clear thinking, not factual investigation. Orderly investigation
of facts is the business of science. Therefore many philosophers
today maintain that it is for science to say whether a belief is
true or false; and if a particular belief is such that no scientifc
investigation of it is possible, either as yet or in principle, then
we must not ask whether it is true or false. The philosophy of
knowledge cannot in either event determine whether a belief
passes the second test of accordance with fact.
With the subject-matter of the philosophy of practice (moral,
social and political philosophy) the diffculty is even greater. The
firsl crilerion. of consistency, can again be used by the philo
sopher. Bul in this inslance it is nOI clear whal is to take the place
of the second criterion of accordance wilh facls. It is not a queslion
of determining whal is true or false, but one of determining what
is right or wrong. good or bad. Values are not facts in the ordinary
sense of the word; and if there is a sense in which values can be
Ireated as facts, there is no recognized procedure for deciding
which among conficting sets of values is to be regarded as factual
or objeclive. There is no science which can tell us this, and it is
hard to say whal other kind o[ investigalion could do so. If, for
example, different people have different, and incompatible, ideas
of what would be a just order of society, how are we to decide
which is correct'? Or if some countries adopt democratic principles.
while thers adopt communist principles which appear to be
incompatible at some points with the democratic, how are we to
argue rationally in favour of the one as against the other?
I myself think that it is possible to do something about this
problem, or at least that there arc lines of inquiry which arc still
worth pursuing. Since the diffculty is especially acute with the
philosophy of practice, and since my major concern in this book
is with political philosophy, I shall confinc myself to the latter in
outlining my reply to the criticism of the traditional aim. The
criticism, in my opinion, underrates what can be done negatively
to disprove a set of principles. That is to say, critical evaluation
has to take the form, not of directly justifying one belief, but of
indirectly supporting it by the elimination of alternatives.
In the frst place, the criticism underrates the extent to which
the criterion of consistency can be conclusive as a negative test.
It is often possible to disclose inconsistency in a set of political
ideas, thereby showing that. in its existing form at least, it should
be rejected as irrational. Take as an example the conflict between
democratic and Nazi principles. Some philosophers said in the
1930s that there was no way of arguing rationally against Nazi
ideas; you just had to take your choice. depcnding no doubt on
your feelings and what you were used to. This is not true of
everything that the Nazis believed. They held. for example. Ihat
one group of human beings, the 'Aryan race'. was superior to
other human groups, the 'nonAryan races', This is the sort of
ideological belief that is supposed to be immune from r<ltional
refutation. But Nazi doctrine went on to refer to 'non-Aryans' as
'sub-human -, in order to justify thc view that 'non-Aryans' were
inferior to 'Aryans' In suggesling that 'non-Aryans' were inferior
because they were less than human. the Nazis implied that all
human beings were on the higher Inel of value. and this of course
was inconsistent with the claim lilal one group of human beings
was of higher value than other hUlllan bcings. The underlying
. implication of their use of Ihe lerm 'sub-huran' shows that at
heart they shared the view of democrats that it is wrong to place
different groups of human beings un different levels of \'tluc.
Inconsistency can be found in Marxism too. Marxist thenry
purports to be scientific explanation. owing nothing to the claim
of ethical principles. all of which. it says, reflect class conscious
ness. Yet much of the argumentation used by Marx and Engels
is plainly directed hy moral intii!llatinn which they expect readers
to share: and while they insist 1\1;11 moral thought cannot yet
transcend class morality. Marx himsllfl cOlllidcntly asserts tran
scendent. or truly human, moral principk, 'From each tlccording
to his ability. to each according to his needs', a principle Ih:1t was
in fact frst enunciated by a thinker. Louis Blanc, whom Marx
regard cd as 'bourgeois'.
It must not be supposed that the use of this criterion of Cllilsist
ency always favours democratic beliefs, Inconsistencies may he
I Critiqllt' (f the (;orlw PrnRrtlmlll(, I.
14 Problems of Politico I Philosophy
found wi thi n democratic ideas too. Some people t hi nk, for exam
ple. that there is an inconsistency between the pursuit of liberty
and that of equality, each of which is a principle of democratIc
thought. I f these two ends are in fact inconsistent, the demands
of reason require that we should abandon or modify at least one
of them.
Secondly, the criticism of traditional political philosophy
neglects the part that facts do play in the support of value-judge
ments. Although judgements of value cannot be directly tested by
the criterion of accordance wi th fact , they are susceptible to an
indirect test of thi s ki nd, for they often presuppose beliefs about
facts which can be subjected to the test of accordance. It is true
that philosophers are in no special position to discover facts, but
they can makc use of facts which have been established by scien
tists or which are attested by common observati on, in order to
show that a political principle depends on factual assumptions
which arc false. I again take as an example the Nazi doctrine
about the superiority of the 'Aryan race' . This presupposes that
there is such a thing as an Aryan race in the biological sense of
the term; and we can use data from the sciences of ethnology and
philology to show that this factual presupposi tion is false and
that the only sound distinction between ' Aryan' and 'non-Aryan'
relates to languages. If there is no such thi ng as an Aryan race,
any judgements about the Aryan race, be they judgements of fact
or judgements of value, have no genuine application. This kind
of argument of course does not prove that di fferent groups of
people are of equal value. but i t removes a prop that was used to
support the Nazi doctrine and thereby helps to discredit that
doctrine. Again. we can sometimes disprove a political doctnne
by showing that it rests on factual assumptions which are knwn
to be false from the familiar daily experience of everyone, not Just
of scientists or of philosophers. Some important political doctrines
presuppose that human bei ngs are motivated only by self-interest,
and a relevant comparison of political authority with authority in
some other forms of social organization. a family. a church. a
school, can easily show that the presupposition is mistaken and
that i t has acquired plausibility only because attention has been
confined to certain areas of behaviour and authority. The example
is explained more fully in 2.S.
I t is no defect in philosophy that the progress of critical evalu-
WhO! is PO/ificat Philo.wJlhy? 15
ation should depend on negative refutation rather than nn rositin
estahlishment of beliefs. Science too progresses by the di spro\`f
of false hypotheses rather than by the di rect proof of those that
are taken to be true. I do not wish to suggest. however. Ihn! all
the problems of critical evaluation in political phi losoph\ can bc
solved in this way. A conflict between two sets of political prin
ciples. e. g. between the principles ()f liberal democracy and those
of communism. or between the principles of the Conservative and
Labour Parties in Bri tai n, often rests on the balancing of two or
more ideals and the comparative rating given to each; i t may be
a question of how we rate liberty against fraterni ty or equality.
In conSidering the rival claims i n such a conflict. the philosophical
methods of showing up i nconsistency or false factual presuppo
sitions are apt to leave unresolved the central issue of disagree
ment on comparative value. Nevertheless those methods can be
effective for some of the problems of political philosophy.
At nny rate. thl' point of CriliLall'vuluation. if it is practicable.
will be clear enough. I tur nnw to the second function tlf
philosophy.
1.4 Clarification of concepts
According to my interpretation of traditional philosophy. the clari
fcation of concepts has traditionally been undertaken as a slJbsidi
ary function serving the primary aim of evaluating beliefs. I n order
to know whether 3 belief is tenable . and in parti cular whether it
involves any inconsistencies, ei ther wi thi n itself or between it and
other accepted beliefs. it is necessary to understand just what the
belief is and what i t implies. We need to know clearl v what is
meant by the terms used in i t . Consequently a goo1 deal of
philosophy is concerned with the meaning of general ideas or
concepts. Those philosophers of the present day who consider
that the critical evaluation of beliefs is a misguided or i mpracti
cable pursuit for philosophy. also hold that the clarifcation of
concepts is the sole task that philosophy call successfully perform.
For them, therefore. this is no longer a subsidiary fUllction but
the central business of philosophy. Whether or not it is the onlv
job that philosophy can usefully Io, i t occupies the mai n part ;f
much philosophical inquiry, and i t will oecupv t he mai n part of
what I have to say in this book.
16 Problems oj YolIItcal rnllosopny
A concept is a general i dea or notion that applies to a number
of tbings. It i s often helpful to think of concepts as the uses of
general words. At any rate the examination of concepts can only
be carried out by considering the uses of words. When I speak of
'general words' I mean words that refer to a number of things,
by contrast with names, which are intended to identify individual
things. Sometimes names fail to identify. I once asked an Amer
ican woman student, at a philosophY course, what was her name,
and thought she was pulling my leg when she replied 'Socrates';
she was in fact of Greek origin and was called Persephone
Socrates. But at any rate i n that group the name 'Persephone
Socrates' referred to one person only, while the general term
'student' applied both to her and to all her colleagues. There is
no diffculty i n understanding what is meant by 'student' or by
most other general words. Philosophical problems are usually
concerned with concepts that are very general, like the concept
of a person, of mind, matter, space, ti me. Many of the ideas of
social and political thought, such as the concept of society, of
authority. social class, justice, liberty, democracy. are not only
highly general but also vague.
In trying to clarify general ideas, philosophy has three related
purposes, analysis. synthesis, and improvement of conce
p
ts. By
analysis of a concept 1 mean specifying its elements, often by way
of defnition; for example, one can analyse or defne sovereignty
as supreme legal authority, specifying the three essential elements
which make up the concept. By synthesis of concepts I mean
showing the logical relationships whereby one concept implies
or is implied by another; for example, one can show a logical
relationship between the concept of a right and that of an obli
gation by pointing out that whenever A has a right against B, this
implies that B has an obligation. By improvement of a concept I
mean recommending a defnition or use that wi l l assist clarity or
coherence: for example. one ran recommend. as I do, that the
concept of sovereignty should be used only of the legal authority,
and not of the coercive power, of a State.
The t hrce tasks of analysis. synthesis, and improvement go
together. In order to analyse or defne a concept, you often. if
not alway,, have to note implications, logical relations. To take
a sim
p
le example for purposes of illustration: if you defne man'
liS n rntionnl nnimnl, you nn' m'l only tiistinRuishing Iwo eleillents
4114 8-J 4 I 1,4 tts\.+g++_
of the concept, being rational and being an animal; you are also
subsuming a species under a genus and differentiating i t from
other species. Consequently YOll can make the simple inference:
i f anything is a man, it must be an ani mal . You have the begin
nings of a l i ttl e pattern of synthesis or logical system. which can
be pictured as the inclusion of one class of things, men, among
the wider class, animals, or else as the branching out of the general
idea, animal. i nto two divisions. rational and non-rational, the
frst division comprising men and the second al l other animals.
You are also improving, or at any rate refning, the concept of man
as compared with its use in ordinary life: for when we normally use
the word 'man' in an everyday context. we are not thinking
explicitly of the idea of a rational animal, or of a class of animals
that excludes elephants, emus, and echinoderms.
Many modern philosophers would reject the improvement of
concepts as a proper purpose of philosophy. just as they would
reject the critical evaluation of bcliefs, and for the same sort of
reason, namely that it is not the business of philosophy to decide
what is better or worse. or to say that a change i n the use of an
idea would be an improvement . I think this i s because these
philosophers are usually more interested i n t he philosophy of
knowledge than in the philosophy of practice. The concepts that
are studied i n the philosophy of knowledge tend t o change slowly,
or in some instances perhaps not at al l . ancr such changcs as do
occur are usually the result of scientific advance. It is therefore
reasonable enough, at frst sight. to say that a philosopher is not
specially qualifed to recommend the improvement of a concept:
his task is to elucidate the ways in which i t is commonly used or
the signifcance of a change that has already come about as a
result of scientifc progress. ( 1 say it is reasonable ' at frst sight',
because I think that in fact this view of the philosopher's function
should be qualifcd evcn for the philosophy of knowledgc. )
The thesis. however. i s less plausible wi th some of the concepts
studied i n the philosophy of practice, and especially i n social and
political philosophy. In many tribal and peasant societies of the
pasl, social institutions and the ideas that go along with them have
remained relatively stable over a long period. But societies that
engender philosophical refection on their structure and on the
ideas associaled wilh il are socielies which are subjeci 10 quite
perccptihlc change. and this is liahle 10 lead to changes in the
18 Problems of Political Philosophy
meaning of some of the ideas. For example, the ideas of 'justice'
and 'merit' or 'worth' do not have the same meaning in the
literature of ffth-century Athens as they have in the Homeric
poems relating to an earlier, aristocrati c, form of Greek society.
On the other hand, although Athenian democracy was in certain
respects more democratic than modern democracies, the Athen
ians' concept of justice included little or nothing of an explicit
notion of the 'rights' of the individual, a notion which plays a
large part i n modern social and political thought. In our own ti me
we can see not only that the scope of application of thi s notion is
being widened, but that its meaning is to some extent being modi
fed. A philosopher may think that his task is simply to chart the
old and the new meanings, but i t seems to me that the process of
clarifcation must often inevitably carry with i t a sharpening, and
so a sli ght change, of the meaning of the concept as habitually
employed.
. .
The point of the primary ai m of traditional philosophy, the
critical evaluation of beliefs, was plain enough - provided that the
aim could be realized. If the secondary ai m, the clarifcation of
concepts. is pursued in the service of evaluating beliefs, i ts point
likewise will be apparent. Thus, for example, jf we want to con
sider possible mcthods of justifying a preference for democracy
over its rivals. we need to know clearly what is meant by the
concept of democracy and by such concepts as liberty and equal
i ty, which are commonly taken to be an essential part of demo
cratic doctrine. Btlt if, as many philosophers thi nk nowadays, the
evaluation of beliefs is impracticable. what is the point of going
on wi th the clarifcation of concepts?
I must leave it to others to defend the antics of philosophy in
general when confned to the analysis of concepts. So far as social
and political philosophy is concerned, it is not hard to justify a
purely conceptual treatment . We all use terms like 'democracy' ,
'freedom', 'social justicc', and nowadays 'the Welfare State' . We
have a rough idea of what we mean, and more often than not we
have no difficulty in understanding these terms when used by
others; e.g. by a democracy we may mean a State in which the
rulers are chosen by popular election. But then we are liable to
contrast a democratic with a totalitarian State; and so we may be a
little puzzled when we find communist countries calling themselves
'people's democracies'. We are inclined to ask: 'Isn't our demo-
What is Political Philosophy? 19
eracy too a democracy of the people? What on earth do those
communists means by distinguishing their form of government as
a "people's democracy"? They don't sound as i f they had their
tongue in thei r cheek. ' Or again, suppose you were to hear, as I
have heard, New Zealanders saying that the British system of
university education is 'undemocratic'. Well, i n a way. we see
what they mean; or at least we see it if we know that university
education in New Zealand is open to a wi der section of the
population than ours i s. But then we may refect: 'Democracy
surely relates to government, to the fact that every adult has a
vote, not to education. Why does the New Zealander say
"undemocratic" when he means "unequalitarian"? Yet . on the
other hand, democracy does have something to do wi t h equality;
but what exactly?' Already we have begun to try to analyse the
concept of democracy, and to consider its logical relation to the
concept of equality. We have begun, in a small way, to think
philosophically about a political concept.
Here i s another example. The history of political philosophy
since the sixteenth century contains a good deal of tedious-looking
di scussion about the concept of sovereignty. Much of it is indeed
tedious enough. Yet there are important historical reasons why
philosophers of the sixteenth and seventeent h centuries should
have placed the idea of sovereignty in the forefront of their
thought; and further historical devclopment has now made thi s
concept a part of our intellectual and lingui sti c equipment for
discussing some question of politics. You will often fnd. in politi
cal discussion about joining or developing an international or
supranational organization such as the European Community
(Fe), that people talk about 'giving up our sovereignty' and debat
ing whether we should or should not do so. Rightly or wrongly,
this was and is regarded as an important issue, to be taken into
account along with economic or With other political questions,
when deciding whether Britain should have joined the EC or
should agree to the extension of the EC"s powers and functions.
Well. if we have no clear idea of what is meant by 'sovercignty'.
we simply do not know what we are talking about our 'national
sovereignty' becomes a sacred cow that must not be tOllched, and
wc have no idea "'ily it should not he touched or what ki nd of
animal it is anyway,
These are the sort of reasons why the clarificati on of concepts
"U Yroblems OJ rOllClcal rnuosopny
is worth doing for its own sake, even if one thinks that it cannot
be used for the further purpose of evaluating beliefs. It is perhaps
worth giving a word of warning that the results of a conceptual
inquiry sometimes seem disappointingly meagre. The clarifcation
of concepts is like cleaning the house. When you have cleaned
the house, there is not much to be seen for your work. You have
not acquired any new possessions, though you wi l l have thrown
out some things that are not wanted and are just a nuisance. What
you have at the end of i t is a tidier house, in which you can move
around more easily and i n which you can fnd things when you
need them.
The analogy is apt i n another respect also. Cleaning the house
is not a job that can be done once and for all. You have to do i t
every week. The mere business of l i vi ng continues to produce
more rubbish. which has to be cleared regularly. Philosophy seems
to go round and round the same old problems and to make no
progress. This is in fact an illusion; progress is made, though it is
gradual. The mai n point, however, is that phi losophy i a mental
clearance, not the acquisition of new i nformation. The clearance
needs to be done again i n every generation with improved tools,
the vacuum cleaner, so to speak, taking the place of the sweeping
brush. And i t needs to be done every so often i n the li fe of an
individual. If one feels, at the end of reading a particular work
of philosophy, that a few things have been tidied up, one should
not suppose that this is the end of the matter. In a few years'
time, one may well fnd that the earlier conclusions themselves
need to be tidied up or even discarded. The chief thing that we
should hope to acquire from the study of political philosophy is
not a fnal answer to problems but the habit of careful thought.
The distinctions made i n the clarifcation of concepts are often
simple enough, once they are understood, but the initial under
standing may require time and effort. Yet it i s well worth while.
Without the simple distinctions of social and political philosophy.
we are likely to talk and act confusedly i n social and political
affairs and are liable to follow blind alleys i n social and political
science.
1.5 Philosophy nnd ideology
Having stated what political philosophy is. I can now turn back
to a question raised earlier, whether or i n what sense political
philosophy is normative. I said in 1.2 that traditional political
philosophy i s often described as being normative or ideological ,
setting up norms or ideal standards for society and government.
This is supposed to be the main difference between political philo
sophy and political science, which is positive, explaining how
governments in fact conduct their affairs and how men in fact
behave in the pursuit of actual political objectives. instead of
prescribing what governments ought to do and what ought to be
our political objective. The account of political philosophy which
I have given also makes it normative but in a rather different way.
In particular. my account does not i mply that political philosophy
is ideology, if ldeology means. as it is usually taken to mean, a
prescriptive 'doctrine that is not supported by rattena
l
argument.
The critical evaluation of beliefs is of course nonnative i n that
i t evaluates; but by 'critical evaluation', as I have explained. I
mean seeking rational grounds for accepting or rejecting beliefs.
and i n this respect philosophy is no more (and no less) normative
than explanatory theory, whether i n social or i n natural science.
When explanatory theory provides evidence (with or without SllP
porting logical argument) for or against a hypothesis, it is giving us
rational grounds for accepting the hypothesis as true or rejecting it
as false. Critical evaluation in the philosophy of knowledge i s
doing the same thi ng. though usually relying more heavily on
logical argument than on the presentation of factual evidence.
The result of critical evaluation of a proposition i n the philosophy
of knowledge is to give us grounds for accepting the proposition
as true or for rejecting it as false. The result of critical evaluation
in the philosophy of practice is rather different. Instead of seeking
rational grounds for accepting a proposition as worthy of assent
( i .e. as being true), or for rejecting it as unwMthy of assent (i.e.
as being false), the philosophy o[ praclice seeks rational grounds
for accepting a proposition as worthy of being followed in action
(i . e. as being right or what we ought to do). or for rejecting it as
unworthy of bcing followed in action (i. e. as being wrong or what
we ought not to do). Neverthel ess. in the philosophy of practice,
as in the philosophy of knowledge and i n explanatory thenry. the
22 Problems oj Political PhliOSOPflY
decision to accept or reject a propositi on does not depend on
emotive preference but on the presentation of reasons. I have
already illustrated how the logical test of consistency and the
empirical test of accordance wi th fact both have their place in the
elimination of political doctrines as irrational.
There i s ample scope for rational argument about judgements
of value, and argument of the same ki nd as is used in the dis
cussion of judgements of fact. I am far from suggesting that all
disputes about value can be settled rationally, but i t should not
be supposed that rational argument has no place at all i n the
discussion of values. The poi nt is that the philosophical discussion
of values is a discussion by means of rational argument, and
rational argument of the same ki nd as is used i n the philosophy
of knowledge and in scientifc theory. It is normative, in that i t
aims t o justify ( t o give reasons for) t he acceptance or rejection of
doctrines; but so are the philosophy of knowledge and scientifc
theory i n aiming to justi fy (to give reasons for) the acceptance or
rejection of beliefs about matters of fact . The subject of the posi
tive or negative justifcation in the former instance is a jUdgement
of value, and if one of two conficting alternatives is successfully
eliminated, this means that the philosophical inquiry can be said
to have given support t o the remaining value-judgement . But the
fact that the better supported alternative is a value-judgement
does not in itself add to or alter the normative character of the
philosophical process. That process i s normative only i n the sense
that it gives reasons for accepting or rejecting a proposition. The
reasoning process in the philosophy of knowledge or in scientifc
theory does exactly the same thi ng and is normative in the same
sense. Neither is ideological. A set of value-judgements which
have not been subjected to rational scrutiny by the tests of consist
ency and accordance may be called ideological. The conclusions
of political philosophy. as I have described it,.cannot.
What of the clarifcation of concepts? Those who discard the
primary function of traditional political philosophy on the ground
that i t is normative or ideologi cal, would say the same of the
improvement of concepts but not of analysis and synthesis; and
therefore they practise the latter, usually under the name of
'analysis' "lone, and clai m that they do not suggest any i mprove
ment of the concepts they analyse. Plainly the improvement of
concepts is normative, since it recommends certain usages or
I
\
11 'J J 1444 1 ,jJjVJUP"
)
"1 &,
deftions. nalysis and synthesis are positive, i n that thcy ai m
simply at maki ng plain what is already the case. However, I thi nk
that i t is hardly possible to pursue analysis and synthesis without
at the same ti me suggesting some improvement of concepts. Even
the simplest ki nd of analysis or defni ti on, as in my trite example
of defning man as a rational ani mal, tends to refne a concept,
to pare off some of its associations and to bring i nt o a clear light
what is taken to be its essential meaning. As a result, the concept
when analysed does not have quite the same meani ng as i t has in
ordinary use. The very fact that i t is now relatively clear, where
before it was relatively vague or blurred. means t hat it has been
refned. In social and political studi es especially, the
.
clarification
of concepts is liable to include improvement of them. For the
general concepts of social and political thought change with
changes in the form of society, and the social philosopher, in the
course of his analysis of concepts and his review of thei r history,
can often see that concepts arc undergoing an i mpli ci t change
which he wants to make explicit. His clarifcation therefore pre
sents us wi th something that is not quite the same as the concept
actually in use at the ti me.
If I am right , the second ai m of political phi losophy, which is
retained by those who discard the first ai m, is also, i n part. a
normative pursui t . Like I he critical evaluation of beli efs. however.
i t need not be ideological. i . c. nonrationally normative. I said i n
1 .4 that the improvement of conccpts is pursued i n t he interests
of clarity or coherence, and each of these is a rational objective.
Coerence me

ns either consistency or, morc strongly, positive


logical connection: and clarity is an aid to understanding and t o
t he 3VOIdance of intellectual confllsion. Both of t he traditional
functions of political phi losophy arc normati ve. and neither is
ideological.
1.6 Methodolngy of the social sciences
One should not try to make a rigid separation between social
and political phi losophy. Some of the ti me-honoured Subjects of
politIcal phIlosophy, such as the nature of the State, sovereignty,
and thc grounds of political obligation. clearly belong to the
spher of the
.
pli t ical; but others, such as authori ty, liberty,
equality, and JustIce, have a wider application and are best eon-
.=`
24 ProbLems oj r01Wcat rnuosopny
sidered as belonging to the sphere of the social in the sense of
that term which includes the political. A more recent branch of
philosophical inquiry, often called the methodology of the social
sciences, is likewise part of sodal philosophy in thi s comprehen
sive sense. I do not propose to discuss any of its problems in
this book, since its relation to the narrower subject of political
philosophy is less close than is the philosophical treatment of the
concepts of authority, liberty, equality, and justice. It i s appropri
ate, however, to say something here about its relation to the
traditional functions of philosophy.
The methodology of the social sciences i s a branch of the philo
sophy of science. Many of the sciences have arisen out of philo
sophical questioning, and this i s certainly true of the social sci
ences. Psychology originated both in epistemology (the theory of
knowledge) and i n moral philosophy; political science, economics,
sociology, and social anthropology arose directly from moral,
social, and political philosophy. This historical relation between
the sciences and philosophy has led to the suggestion that science
should be regarded as taking the place of philosophy.
The chi ef exponent of this view was Auguste Comte, often
called the father of sociology. Comte' put forward a 'fundamental
law of mental development', according to which all branches of
human understanding go through three stages. In the frst stage,
the theological or fctive, men try to explain things by reference to
supernatural forces. This becomes outmoded when philosophers
question the validity of explanation by reference to mythical
beings, and we then reach the second stage, the metaphYSIcal or
abstract, when explanation refers instead to reifed abstractions,
i . e. supposed real entities named by abstract terms such as 'absol
ute reality', 'absolute justice', or 'absolute motion' (Comte would
say that Newtonian physics, which uses the concept of absolute
motion, is not yet fully scientifc). Once it is seen, however, that
such termS are only abstractions from the language used to
describe our experience of individual phenomena, and that there
is no reason to suppose abstract terms to be the names of entities,
we reach t he third and fnal stage, the scientifc or positive. (It
should be noted that the transition [rom the metaphysical stage
to the scienti fc, like the transition [rom the theological stage to
' COlrs di phi/owpltk posifil't', lecture 1.
7 #41 4,| 4 1444.4a4 # #44+J1*}71* _
the metaphysical, is similarly due to the critical work of philo
sophers, the chief architect of the later transition being David
Hume. ) In the third, positive or scientifc, stage, explanation takes
the form of showing correlations between the observed phenom
ena themselves; there is no longer any attempt to go behind
phenomena to hypothetical entities that cannot be observed.
Comte called this kind of explanation 'positive' because it confnes
itself to positive or empirical fact, to what is known by observation
to exist. (This use of the term 'positive' is obviously related to,
though not quite the same as, t he use noted earlier when the
positive or factual was contrasted with the normative or i deal . )
According to the posi tivist interpretation of science, the real point
of Newton's theory of gravity is not to explain motion as caused
by an unobservable force, but to relate together apparently differ
ent kinds of motion (e . g. that of the planets and that of a falling
apple) by showing that they follow the samc mathematical for
mula. In the feld of social phenomena, explanation takes the
form of showing how one species of social behaviour is correlated
with another (e. g. style of life with occupation) or wi t h factors in
the environment (e,g. certain kinds of crime with poverty). There
is no longer any point in explaining the rules of justice as being
a refeetion of absolutc Justice , any more than as being the com
mands of superatural beings. Thesc supposed explanations either
say nothing or else assume the existence of entities for which there
i s no evidence. Instead the rules of justice in a particular society
are explained by showing how thcy ft in with some other social
fact such as the survival of the group.
From this account of theology, metaphysics (or traditional phil
osophy) , and science as successive moues of explanation. it follows
that theology is outmoded by philosophy ami that traditional phil
osophy in its tur is outmodcd by science. Philosophy has been
useful in its day, by helping scicntifc explanation to emcrge: but
once science has appeared, philosophy should disappear. Traces
of this kind of view about the relation between philosophy and
SCIence may be seen in some later currents of thought. For exam
ple, the view that philosophy should conMnc itself to conceptu"1
analysis and abandon critical evaluation may be regarded as a
variant of the Comtean position. It says that the discovery of truth
is a matter for science and not for philosophy: before the sciences
were est"blishccl, philosophcrs tried, in an amateurish way, to
10 troblems of rOWICal rnuosopny
fnd out the facts; but now that the professionals are here, philo
sophy should leave the feld to them. Philosophy still retains the
task of examining the meaning of words, but according to some
exponents of the view) thi s is only because there is not as yet, in
their opinion, a sound science of language. Philosophical attention
to the various dimensions of meaning will in ti me enable a proper
science of language to arise, and then philosophy wi l l really be
out of a job or wi l l have to t hi nk of a new one.
To the extent that theology and philosophy in the past did
try to provide explanations of observable phenomena (as they
undoubtedly did), their role in thi s regard has certainly been
superseded by that of science. The development of the sciences,
however, has itself provided phi losophy with a new feld of
inquiry. The sciences are not static; they are developing al l the
time. And as a science or group of sciences develops, i t is apt to
change its use of general concepts, sometimes without explicitly
recognizing why or how the change has been made. This can lead
to some confusion, at least in the minds of laymen, and at times
pcrhaps i n the minds of scientists themselves, between the new
use of a concept and the old one which is sti l l familiarly applied
in ordinary life. The confusion, which is some instances depends
on an apparent inconsistency, makes i t necessary to clarify the
concept. This is a philosophical task, though that is not to say
that i t is necessarily better undertaken by people called philo
sophers than by the scientists themselves.In place of prescientifc
philosophy, we now have the philosophy of science.
If a philosopher, as distinguished from a philosophically minded
scientist, is to be any good at the philosophy of science, he must
not only be trained in logic and versed in conceptual analysis. He
must know something of the concepts he is trying to clarify, and
that means that he must have a fair knowledge of the relevant
science or group of sciences. I t is no use going in for a philosophi
cal critique of the social sciences unless one has a reasonable
acquaintance with two or three of them.
Although the philosophy of science requires specialized know
ledge, it i s not a new kind of philosophy but an application of the
existing functions of philosophy to a new feld. I have spoken
so far of the c1arilieation of Changing concepts. In addition, the
philosophy of science includes the critical evaluation of beliefs. I
do not mean by this that the philosophy of science can or should
I
1
I
I
I
** * *+++ # I!11-+!1_!
try to usurp the function of science itself in testing the truth or
falsity of scientifc hypotheses. That would be absurd. What the
philosophy of science subjects to critical evaluation are certain
presupposi tions that underlie the work of scientists. The need to
do so arises i n the way i n which i mportant phi losophical problems
usually arise. The development of a science is apt to produce
apparent inconsistency, or lack of coherence, wi th beliefs of
common sense or with the assumptions of another science or of
some well-established special order of ideas which is not a theor
etical or explanatory science. For example, is the general scientifc
assumption of causal necessity compatible with the assumption by
common sense and by the wellestablished discipline of law that
men are responsible for many of their actions? For that matter,
do the biological sciences assume the same notion of causation as
the physical sciences? Reflection on problems of this kind requires
the kind of thing that I described in 1.3. The implications of the
apparently inconsistent views need to be brought out so as to
show whether there really is or is not an inconsistency and i f
there is, just at what point; then one or other or botl; of the
conficting views need to be revised so as to remove the incon
sistency.
The very fact that the philosophy of science, or one part of i t ,
is called methodology confrms that i t s business i s not solely t he
clarifcation of concepts. The term ' methodology' means t he study
of method (though some people, rather foolishly, use it simply
as a supposedly learned synonym for the word 'method' itself).
Scientists. including social scientists. often use the term to mean
the study of particular methods of research that are appropriate
for particular kinds of investigalion. Phi losophers use the term in
a broader sense to mean the study of methods of inquiry that are
common to all the sciences. i . c. Ihe kind of reasoning and testing
that are commonly used. This i s regarded as a philosophical prob
lem ?ecaue t he idea that the main scientific method of reasoning
was tnductlOn rather than deduction raised the phi losophical ques
tion of how induction could be justified.
[ myself think that the expression ' mcthodology of thc social
scienccs' is too narrow to cover the philosophical questions that
arise about the social sciences. and I prefer t o speak of examining
presuppositions and method. In the social sciences the number of
presuppositions that are apt to produce difficulties is greater than
in the natural sciences, and this for two reasons. First, the social
sciences, as sciences, are relatively young disciplines and nothing
like so well established as the natural sciences. They are still
fnding their feet and need the critique of philosophical question
ing in a way that the natural sciences once did but do not now.
Secondly, because the social sciences have human behaviour as
their subject-matter, it is more diffcult for them to keep consist
enlly to positive facts and avoid implicit judgements of value. In
addition to the problems raised by the assumption of causal laws,
an assumption which the social sciences have derived from the
natural sciences, there is a further set of problems concering the
question whether social studies can, or should try to, be 'value
free'. Even when an investigator thinks he is avoiding value
judgements, he may be unconsciously presupposing them in a way
that affects his work; and this can be spotted by an outsider who
is trained to look out for presuppositions.
The so-called methodology of the social sciences is approved
of, as thoroughly respectable, by those philosophers who would
say that the traditional aim of critically evaluating beliefs should
be abandoned. They would also agree that 'methodology' in this
connection includes the critique of presuppositions as well as of
method proper. 1 have tried to show that the critique of presuppo
sitions is simply a form of the critical evaluation of beliefs, so that
in this new feld at least the traditional aim of philosophy is agreed
to be both practicable and desirable.
In fact, what is done by philosophy in the critical evaluation of
beliefs is in principle the same as what is done in the clarifcation
of concepts. The precise meaning, and the implications (including
presuppositions), of a complex idea are analysed; its relations to
other ideas.are examined so as to draw attention to inconsistencies
on the one hand and logical connections on the other; and, in
order to remove the inconsistencies and produce a coherent syn
thesis, revision or improvement of one or morc of the ideas is
liable to be suggested.
The methodology of the social sciences is not part of political
philosophy. It belongs to the wider subject of social philosophy.
I have discussed it here in general terms in order to show that
what is allowed on all hands to be a respectable function of
philosophy is in fact an application of traditional functions. This,
together with the analogy that can be drawn between critical

evaluation and conceptual clarification, may help to remove the
prejudice that critical evaluation is not philosophy.
2
Politics and the State
2.1 The scope of politics
Moder writers on political science tend to distinguish between
' government' and 'politics'. 'Government' concerns the insti
tutional framework of rule i n a State, that i s to say. the structure
and procedure of the legislative body ( i n Britain, Parliament), of
the executive and administrative bodies (roughly, the Cabinet,
other holders of ministerial offce, and the civil service), and of
the analogous institutions i n local government. 'Politics' concernS
the behaviour of groups and individuals in matters that are likely
to affect the course of government, e.g. in voting, in formi ng and
running political parties. or i n exerting infuence in other ways on
those responsible for the conduct of government. I shall be using
the term 'politics' more widely so as to cover 'government' as
well, and for this purose I include under 'government' the insti
tutions for interpreting and enforcing the law i n addition to those
for making and applying i t .
How should one mark out the sphere of the political so as to
distinguish it from the 'social' , i . e. from all those activities in
different forms of relationship between individuals which are not
political? The old way of doing this is to say that the political is
whatever concerns the State, and on the whole thi s way of delimit
ing the sphere of
. the political still seems to me the clearest. Of
course we then need to say what is meant by the State, a question
that I shall be discussing later in this chapter. It may be thought.
however. thnt slIch an attOUll1 or the political is too narrow. In
the frst place, it seems to cover only 'government' (including the
procedures for interpretation and enforcement of law) but not the
political behaviour of individuals and groups in voting, political
.0
Polifics and the Slale 31
parties, etc. Secondly, there are societies which are not States but
which contain activities that we are bound to call poli ti cal. Let us
look at each of these objections i n turn.
(1) The frst objection is t hat , even i n societies which are organ
ized as States, not all political activity has to do wi th making,
applying, i nterpreting, or enforcing the law. I t hi nk thi s objection
is mistaken. When we vote in an election, we are deciding which
persons shall form the legislature. When we join in the activities
of a political party, or form a new one, we are seeking to give
that party political power, and thi s means to give i t the dominant
voice i n deciding what the law shall be. The policy of a political
party is a set of proposals for organizing the affairs of the State,
and that policy can be given effect only if i t i s adopted by the
legislative and executive powers. Likewise, pressure groups or
individuals who seek to infuence Members of Parliament or Min
isters or civil servants or public opinion are trying to cause their
views to be given effect i n legislation or in the application of the
law. The whole process of pol i ti cal behaviour turns on the fact
that there is the set of institutions called government for regulating
the affairs of the society.
(2) The second objection is that there arc societies which are
not States but which nevertheless exhibit political activity. The
objector may be thi nki ng of primitive forms of society. such as
tribal societies, which do not have the sophisticated political struc
t ure that we call the State. Such societies of course do have some
pattern of regulation that is analogous to law and government i n
societies t hat are States. I t is quite true that. strictly speaking. we
cannot defne the pOlitics of such a society as that which concerns
the State. The notion of a State has implications not only for the
character of governmental regulation wi thi n the society but also
for the relation of that society to others. As we shall see. the idea
of a State in the modern world i ncludes that of sovereignty. which
concerns the relation of the State to other States as well as i ts
relation to groups and individuals who are part of i t. Nevertheless
a tribal society has a form of government . such as a chief or elders
recognized as having the authority to lay down rules and to give
decisions on disputed matlers. So that, i f we want to talk aboul
the politics of such a society, we ought to speak of goverment
(or. i f that too suggests a more complex form of organization than
is found. we may speak simply of rule) ralher than of the State .
32 Problems of Political Philosophy
Even in such societies, however, there is a system of law, at least
i n the form of customary rules or of authoritative decisions backed
by power; and the politics of such a society, like the politics of a
State. consists of thc activities of making, applying, interprcting,
and enforcing the system of law or rule, and the activitics of
inRuencing the former kind. For the purposes of political philo
sophy. the politics of such societies can largely be ignored, for
thc problems of political philosophy arise only i n societies wi th a
sophisticated set of ideas about their politics, and those societies
usually have the form of organization that we call the State,
though we do need to remember that not all the features of the
modern State applied to the States of the past.
Thc objector may also be thinking, however, of a di fferent type
of instance. In ordinary parlance we may speak of 'politics' when
talking about certain kinds of behaviour i n a social uni t that forms
pari of a larger soci cty. organized as a State; and when we do
talk, for example. of 'university politics' or 'church politics'. we
do not mean thal the activities i n question concern the larger
society and i ts State organization. Members of a university or of
a church may indeed campaign against some law that affects their
activities. or against a policy that the Government of their State
proposes to apply to them; and this is political behaviour of the
usual ki nd. But within the university or the church there is as
much scope for the conduct of affairs as the smaller society itself
may choose. and often of course there is difference of opinion
among its members about the choices to be made. In such circum
stances, some members take a leading part in infuencing the
decisions reached. while others clo not. I t may be said of one
university teacher that he is active in 'university politics'. and of
another that he keeps out of 'university politics'. What is called
'politics' in this sort of context has to do wi t h the framing of
policies and the taking of decisions 'but not with the policies or
decisions of the wider society of the State. I t i s called politics
because, as i n the political activities of the wider societ y, i t can
cerns mat ters that arc the subjcct of dispute.
I t hi nk that this use of the term 'politics' is metaphorical, para
sitic on the normal use. Because political affairs include the seck
ing of power and the exercise of infuence _ the introduction of
these features into other spheres of l i fe is called 'politics'. Evi
dcnce of the metaphorical character of the expression can be
found. I think. in the fact that the use of i t is often as a term of
abuse. suggesting that decisions on matters of university or church
policy ought 10 be reached i n a more 'rational' and 'objective'
way. eyery member making up his mind on the issues as he sees
them without being infuenced behind the scenes, and everyone
being content to count as onc without seeking to dominate.
Whether or nul this ideal picture of rational. objective decisions
is sensible, the pejorative use of the word 'politics' in such contcxts
implies that log-roiling and power-seeking arc alien importations
from politics proper, which is where thcy really belong. Although
people are thereby led to speak of university or college or church
politics. they would not nnd i t natural to add t hat univerSity or
college or church politics is concered with pOlitical matters.
People who are impressed by the objections that I have just
considcred are apt to defne the sphere of the political either i n
terms of power or in t erms of conflict. Politicians often say, nat
urally enough. that 'politics is about power' ! t hat 'politics is t he
seeking and the exercise of powcr. Sueh statements arc qui te
clear when made i n the speeches of practising politicians. and
there is no reason to say that they misleau, But it is misleading
to suggest that they can form a deAnition of politics i n theoretical
discussion. For we need to ask: with what kind of power i. politics
concerned? I t is not mechanical power. such as the power of a
steam engine. And if we confne ourselves to the powers of human
beings, it i s not their physical power. c. g. to run a mile or to twist
literally one another's arms. Nor is i t their will-power, e . g. to try
to stop smoking or to work an e'tra hal fhour each day. We shall
have to distinguish the kind of power we mean, by specifying it
a political pfl\vcr; but of course it would be circular to defne the
political in terms of something else described as 'political". [f we
then explain that the kind of human power we are talki ng about
di ffers from physical power or will-power i n being the ability to
get other people to do what one wants them to do, the definition
becomes too wide, for this kind of power is exercised i n many
contexts other than the politicaL It can be seen not only in politics
proper and in the so-called 'politics of non-political societies such
as a university or a church. bUI also in any effective exercise of
authority. An army officer is usually able to get his subordinates
to carry out his orders: so is a factory manager Of a foreman. A
parent is often (or should I say sometimes?) able to get his chi!
%-`
34 Problems of Political Philosophy
dren to do what he says; so i s a teacher wi th his pupils. Nor
need we confne ourselves to instances where we may speak of
authority. An armed bank-robber or a blackmailer i s often able
to make his victims hand over the cash. Al l these examples may
be called instances of the exercise of power i n the sense explained
(though for some of them the use of the actual word 'power'
seems odd. for reasons which will emerge when we discuss the
ideas of power and authority in 6. 4), but it would b absurd to
say that they are examples of political power. Political power is
indeed thi s kind of power, when exercised i n a political context.
If a politician says that politics is concerned with power, he means
this ki nd of power, but he can take it for granted that we know
he is referrng to the seeking or exercise of i t in a political context.
What makes the context political cannot be explained by the idea
of power.
The samc goes for the alternative suggestion of defning the
political in terms of confict. There is a political conflict, and there
"rc also other kinds of conflict: armed confict, which may or
may not be connected wi th a political dispute; unarmed physical
confict, either in sport or in earnest; confict of ideas, sometimes
political. often not; and so on. Political confict is usually not
physical, though i t may at t i mes lead to physical confict. It is a
confict of ideas as to what should be done when a decision needs
to be taken for joint action, but such a confict is political only i f
i t occurs i n a political context . I have heard one political scientist
say that any conflict of the ki nd I have just described is political,
irrespective of context; that i n fact (the example was his. not
mine), if two friends proposing to take an afternoon trip together
On a tandem bicycle disagree as to whether they should go north
Or south, they are engaged in political confict. This is absurd. We
should similarly have to call political a disagreement between
husband and wife whether they should spend a saved 300 on a
washing-machine or a refrigerator. or between a group of children
whether they should play ti g or hop-scotch. If every disagreement
between friends or associates about joint action is to be called a
political conflict. the word 'political' is robbed of its distinctive
meaning. Power and confict arc indeed key ideas for the under-'
standing of political activity. but they cannot be used as defning
terms in order to distinguish political from other social
relationships.
Politics and rhe Swre 35
I therefore prefer the old method of defni ng the scope of
politics in terms of the State. The objections to i t are not important
for the purposes of political philosophy, and are in any case less
strong than the objections to a definition in terms of power or of
confict, which in fact presupposes the older view. We must now
consider the concept of the State itself. and in order to do so we
must frst distinguish two ki nds of social groups.
2.2 Associations and communities
Ferdinand Tennies drew a distinction between Gemeinschaft
(community) and Gesellschaft (society or associ ati on). Gemeill
schaft is the earlier form of social group; i t involves an attitude
of natural friendship and is not deliberately organized: i t is based
on 'natural wi ll'. Gesellschaft comes at a later stage of develop
ment; i t involves an atti tude of deliberate planning or calculation:
it is based on 'rational wi l l ' . To say that Grsellschaft occurs later
does not imply that Gemeinschafl then ceases to exist: when we
have come to make plans and form deliberate associations, we do
not on that account cease to form friendships.
Tonnies' word Gesellschaft can be translated as 'society' or as
'associati on'. In ordinary English usage there is often li ttle di sti nc
tion between these two words. We may speak. for instance. of
the Royal Society and the Law Society, but equally of the Associ
ation of University Teachers and the Political Studies Association.
If I wanted to set up an organization to protect lecturers from
catcalls, backchat, or paper missiles, I might call i t i ndi fferently
a Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Lecturers or a Lecturers'
Plotection Association. For the technical purposes of sociological
theory, however. a good many sOt-inlogists nowadays use the word
'society' in a very broad sense for the whole of the subject -matter
of sociology_ and therefore lend to usc the word 'association'
alone for wlHlt Tannies had in mi nd. I propose to follow their
practice and to treat ' association' as a technical term wi th a sharply
defned meaning. There is of course no suggestion that this is how
the word i s. Or ought to be. used in ordinary life.
I defne an associ ation as a group of persons organized for the
pursuit of a specified common purpose or set of common pur
poses. This definition lays down two conditions for aprlving the
technica; label of 'association
' to a social group. Fi rst. the mem-
36 Problems of Political Philosophy
bers of the group must have a specifed common purpose or set
of common purposes, and secondly, they must be organized for
t he pursuit of that purpose. I use the word 'purpose' rather than
'interest' because t he latter term commonly means something that
one wants or that wi l l give satisfacti on, whi le a purpose may i n
addition be t he objective or ai m of a rational decision to do
something t hat is not necessarily dependent on wanting or on
gai ning satisfacti on.
Not al l social groups have a common purpose, and not al l those
that have a common purpose are organized for its pursui t . A
number of people travelling together i n a bus form a temporary
group but not lrsually an associ ati on. They form a social group,
i n the sense in which that expression is used by sociologists,
because their behaviour or disposition i s liable to be affected to
some extent by their awareness of each other. On entering or
leaving the bus, for example, they wi l l take care not to tread on
the toes of other passengers; and i f one of them happens to be
the sort of person who does not care a hoot for other people's
feelings and so treads firmly On all t he toes i n his path. he will at
any ratc be prepared for black looks and nasty remarks. so that
his disposi ti on, i f not hi s actual behaviour, is affected by his
awareness of the presence of others. But the group i s not an
associ ation, because the passengers probably do not all have the
same purpose ; one is travelling i n the bus i n order t o reach his
place of work, another i n order t o see the beauties of the town.
If they all happen to have the same destination, then to that
extent thei r presence i n the bus i s due t o a common purpose, but
they have not made deliberate arrangements t o travel together to
achieve thi s purpose. If, as occasionally happens, they have i n
fact arranged that they should al l travel together to a concert or
for a day's outing, they form a temporary association.
We usually speak of associations when t he group, deli berately
organized for a common purpose, is not of such short duration.
The organi zati on. and the common purpose; usually last for some
length of ti me. It need not be for very long. A group of tenants
may form an association to try to get their rents reduced. If
they should succeed after a month's campaigning, they may then
disband the associ ation. having achievcd their purpose. On the
other hand, the purpose of an association may be a continuing
one. The members of an associ ation for the prevention of cruelty
to animals would l i ke t o thi nk that thc day wi l l come when their
associ ation will no longer be needed, but Ihey do not regard this
as li kely. A university, which has as i ts purposes t he educati on of
young people and the advancement of knowledge, call set no
terminus on its pursuit of those purposes, since every new gener
ation will need to be educated. and since the range of potential
knowledge is presumably i nfni t e.
I n contrast to an associ ati on. a community does not have a
specifed set of purposes and need not be deliberately organized.
Some examples are a family, a vi llage, a nati on. The Nat i on-State
is highly organized for the pursuit of fairly defni te purposes, but
we shall fnd reason to distinguish the nati on from t he State. I
have said that a community need not be deliberately organized.
and 1 am thereby qualifying Tonnies' di sti ncti on between the two
kinds of group in terms of ' natural wi l l ' and 'rational wi l l ' . A
religious community may be ready to pursue all sorts of common
purposes and not just those few which somc people would label
as specifically 'religious'; and certainly we are inclined 10 call i t a
community rather than an associ ati on; yet often i t wi l l exhi bi t
deliherate organization. The same i s true of a communisti c settle
ment such as an Israeli kibbutz. The close ti es produced by a
shared life in such a group. Hnd the common possession (If ideal
istic sentiments. are manifested i n a loyalty that TanniCs would
call an expression of 'natural wi ll' ; but this does nol preclude the
existence also of the 'rational wi l l ' of organi zati on.
2,3 Patterns of regulation
Di fferent patterns of regulation arc tn he found i n organized social
groups. We are fnmiliar wi th the terms dmocracy y 'monarchy'.
'dictatorship' . 'nristocrncy' . 'oligan:hy' . to describe di fferent pat
ters of political rule, derendi ng on whether decisions arc taken
after general discussion and agreemci lt . or by t he fat of one
person or a fc\, i n a position of authority. These di fferent forms
of regulati on. however. arc not confined In t he St at e. Contrast
Ihe atmosphere of Ihe Viclorian fami l y, or the patria {lolestas of
the Romans. with the WDy i n which mas I families arc run in
modern wcsler society. Contrast the 'democratic' procedure of
a religious communilY l i ke Ihe Quakers wi th Ihe hierarchical struc
ture of the Roman Catholic Church. and wi th I he many gradations
----
38 Problems of Political Philasophy
between these two extremes. Or contrast the usual scheme of
authority in a factory, where managers give orders and workers
take them, wi th proposals for consultation between managers and
workers or. as i t i s sometimes called, lindustrial democracy' . A
school is usually conducted as the head and other teachers decide,
but occasionally a reformer like A. S. Neill may experiment wi th
the democratic method of giving pupils an equal voice with teach
ers i n regulating discipline or even i n deciding the curriculum.
These examples wi ll make it plain that the democratic pattern
of regulation, which most of us favour when we thi nk of politics,
is not necessarily the best one for organizing the affairs of every
association or community. In a family, it is obvious that parents
must be in a position of authority over young children because
the latter are not yet able to decide wisely for themselves; and
most of us would say this also about teachers and pupils i n a
school. I t may be argued that the same is true of the other exam
ples, even though most of the members of the group are adult.
Some members are wiser than others for the purposes i n hand;
spiritual matters require wisdom: even political matters require
educated judgement. On the other hand it may be argued that
collective wisdom can be better than individual wisdom when the
decision to be reached is not on a specialized matter requiring
expertise; or that people resent having decisions taken for them
by others, and prefer to make their own decisions and their own
mistakes, Whichever set of arguments one prefers, they cannot
be transferred without question from one type of association or
community to all.
Aristotle' frst drew attention to this matter when he classifed
different types of rule. He began with a familiar division of three
types, rule by one man, by a few. and by all (or by the majority).
But then he added that the question of who rules was less import
ant than the aim of the ruler or rulers. Rule could be conducted
for the common good of all or for the sectional good of the ruling
party, The traditional classifcation needed to be duplicated, with
one set of three 'right' or proper 'constitutions', in all of which
the end pursued was the common good, and another set of three
'perverted' or i mproper 'constitutions', in which the end was
restricted to the good of the rulcr or rulers. Aristotle used the
Nicomnchenn Ethics. Vl I L 1: Eut/emi(n Ethics. VII. 9: Politics, I. 1 . 7. 12: ! I I .
bR.
Politics and rht' ,ilnte 39
names 'royalty' and 'aristocracy' for 'right' rule by one man or a
few, and the names 'tyranny' and 'oligarchy' for the 'perverted'
forms. When i t came to fnding labels for the two forms of majority
rule, he tendentiously called the 'perverted' ki nd 'democracy' and
used the names 'ti mocracy' and 'polity' for the 'right' ki nd. He
thought that royalty and aristocracy were the best constitutions
for a State, i f One could be fortunate enough to secure these forms
instead of their perversions. But he added that a di fferent choice
should be made in deciding thc bcst forms of rule in a family;
royalty was right for the relation of a father to his children, 'polity'
(in his ethical works Aristotle said aristocracy) for the relation
between husband and wife, and tyranny (or despotism) for the
relation between the head of the family and its slaves. Needless
to say, he gave reasons for his view that in the last example i t
was proper (and not. as i n the State. a perversion) for the master
to seek his own interest only i n his rule over his slaves. We shall
not expect to agree with Aristotle's arguments for this position or
for the view that it is 'natural' or proper for anyone to be a slave.
The point of interest for our present discussion is that Aristotle
realized that the kind of organization that is best for a State may
not be thc best for a different type of association or community.
A further point worth noting i n Aristotlc's discussion is this.
Since the 'perverted' forms of rule aim only at the interest of the
ruler or rulers, oligarchy and 'democracy' , he says, are examples
of ruJe i n the interests of particular classes, namely the rich and
the poor respectively. It so

happcns. Aristotle adds, that the rich


are always a minority and [he poor a majority: but if one were to
fnd a State in which there were f110re rich men than poor, then
rule by the rich in their own interests would be essentially I he same
as oligarchy (even though. strictly speaking. the word 'oligarchy'
means rule by the few) . and rule by the poor i n their Own interests
would be essentially the same as what Aristotle calls democracy
(even though, strictly speaking. the word 'democracy' means rule
by all or most of the people). The character of a constitution is
bestowed on i t . in Aristotle's opinion. less by the number of rulers
than by their ai m. This means that the traditional frst classifcation
i n terms of the number of rulers has been completely replaced,
in Aristotle's final view. by his second classifcation in terms of
t he purpose of t hc ruler or rulers and, where there i s more than
one ruler. i n terms of the social character of the ruling class. Since
40 Problems of Poll/leal nwosopny
the essence of oligarchy is not rule by a few but rule i n the
interests of the wealthy, i t would be better to call i t plutocracy;
and since the essence of democracy, as Aristotle understands i t ,
i s rule i n the i nterests of t he poor, one might suggest (though he
himself does not) coining a new name for i t , 'penetocracy' (from
penes, the Greek word for 'poor').
Aristotle did not thi nk that al rule is carried on i n the i nterest
of the ruling class or ruling group. He believed that it was possible
to fnd 'constitutions' or forms of rule in which the rulers pursued
the i nterest of the whole soci ety. He acknowledged that we were
unlikely to fnd political associ ations in which the ideal forms of
royalty and aristocracy would be realized, and so he was ready to
settle for 'polity' as the best that could be secured in practice. But
this is true only of the State. In a fami ly i t is perfectly possible
for a father to rule 'royally', i . e. taki ng the decisions alone but i n
the i nterests of the family as a whole. One often hears i t said that
in Marxist theory (l am not competent to express an opinion
whether thi s was the view of Marx himself) all rule is class rule,
conducted only in the i nterests of the ruling group. It is presup
posed that selfinterest is the sole motivc of action, and that a
member of a ruling group wi l l joi n in seeking the interest of the
group because that is the best way to secure his own interest. The
thesis has a certain plausibility and appearance of hardheaded
realism when we are asked to look at the actual conduct of politi
cal partics. whcthcr i n power or out of i t , or at the behaviour of
bosses and workers in a factory. One may doubt whether it is
always true of a factory. though it often is and though it was
generally taken for granted i n the nineteenth century with its
concept of economic man (hence perhaps the Marxist generaliz
ati on). But i t is certainly not true of most families or religious
communities or schools. (I f Mr Squeers were a typical school
. master. Dickens's portrayal of hi m would have lost its point.) A
comparison between the State and other organized groups, such
as Aristotle i ni t iated with his comparison and contrast between
State and family, can show us that the psychological presuppo
si ti on of the class theory of rule is unsound. A concern for the
general good is less likcly to show itself i n a large associ ation than
in a small one. such as a school , or than i n a community such as
a family or a church. Sel fi nterest and c1assinterest do count for
a lot i n politics. But thi s cannot be because selfinterest is the sole
motive of action. Those who have a position of power in a family.
a church. or a school, rarely exercise i t i n the i nterests or thC!1l*
selves alone.
2.4 State and nation
I t seems best to regard the State as an associ ati on rather than a
community_ The Stale is certainly organized. i ndeed the most
highly organized of all forms of association. It i s not casy. how
ever. to specify a defni te , l i mi ted set of purposes that may be
attributed to i t . The Greek cityslate had a vi rtually unl i mi ted set
of social functions: those of the modern State have been much
extended i n the course of the ni neteenth and twenti eth centuries.
I n a famous passage near the beginning of his P((itics ( 1 . 2 ) . Aristo
tie says that the polis comes into being for the sake of life. but
that once i t exists i t has as its purpose thc good l i fe . It is customary
to translate 'polis' as ' the Slate" : and so some phi losophers, i nnu
enced by Aristotle. have said that the purpose of the State i s the
good life. the good life as a whole . all purposes that men think
worth pursuing. But the Greek f'olis \vas more of u community
than the moder State . 'The good l i fe' . that is to say. the sum of
all approved common purposes. may be regarded as the function
of community. The Greek citystate. so called, was not a State i n
the modern sense, which leaves much of 'the good life' t o other
social agencies and to i ndi vi duals.
One mi ght argue that the whole of the li fe of a community
should be organized by the State . that the State should i denti fy
itself wi th the community whose membership i t shares, as was
true of the Greek citystatet where religion. morals, and art , as
well as order and defence, were all part of the business of the
polis. On the other side, one may argue that i t i s impossible in a
large communi ty, or that i t is undesirable in any communi ty, to
organize all social purposes centrally and to leave no scope for
private i ni ti ati ve. But at any rate the fact is that the moder State.
except for the totali tari an Slate . dpcs not even try to take upon
itself the organization of all cnmllltllwi purposes, so that its pur
poses are in practice l i mi ted.
The State i n the modern world is often a Nat ionState. i . e. a
nation organized as an associ ati on. The nation is a communi ty, a
group with all the conditions for a COmmon life and giving rise to
42 Problems of Political t'htlosophy
natural sentiments of loyalty and identifcation, but not limited to
a specifc set of purposes. In order to see the difference, consider
two senses i n which the word 'nationality' i s used. The Visitors'
Book at a hotel often has a column headed 'Nationality'. Some
Scotsmen tend to write 'Scots' or 'Scottish' in this column, others
'British'. In the legal sense of the term, which i s what the Visitors'
Book is after, they all have British nationality. This legal concept
may also be called citizenshi p. A Scot, like an Englishman, has a
British passport. The law does not recognize any such thing as
Scottish nationality. Apart from the legal concept, however, there
is also what has been called the concept of 'personal nationality'.
This consists in a feeling of 'belonging' to a group which inhabits
(or, as with Scots Canadians, once inhabited) a common territory,
shares a common language and common traditions, has the
memory of a common history, and looks forward to a common
future. In this sense of nationality, a man may think of himself
as having Scottish or English or Welsh nationality. A 'nationalist',
e.g. a Scottish nationalist. is one who feels personal nationality
strongly and who urges that his nation be organized as a separate
State.
As my example shows, nation and State do not always coincide.
Some nations are divided into, or distributed among, more than
one State; some States comprise more than one nation. The
United Kingdom includes most members of the English nation.
the Scttish nation, the Welsh nation, and - well, I do not know
whether one should call the people of Northern Ireland a separate
nation or part of the Irish nation. The concept of a nation is
imprecise. The people of Northern Ireland share with their sou
ther neighbours affection for the landscape, way of life, and
perhaps even the weather, of I reland. but a history of religious
and political cnflict divides them in sentiment, just as the border
divides them i n legal status. A nation can be formed into a State.
but equally a State can give rise to a nation. Should we say that
the people of the United Kingdom form a nation in a looser sense
than that in which England and Scotland are nations? At any
rate they form a community. made so, i n part, by the political
organization, and the consequent economic organization, that link
together the three nations inhabiting Great Britain and the fourth
nati on. or part of a nation, inhabiting Northern Ireland.
Even when the nation and the State have the same territorial ,.
! tII I I.\ tt tr:t r11l
boundariesl membership of the two is not necessarily ickntical.
An immigrant who becomes natural ized and so n citizen or the
State, with all the rights and obligations of thc natural-bor ci ti
zen, wi ll not, for some time at least. feel himself to be a member
of the nation and may not be accepted as such by others. I n
general, nations and States i n the modern world tend to coincide
i n membership. if only because nationalism g.ives rise to new
Nation-States and the ties of statehood give risc t o the feeling of
being a nation, Yet the di fference i n character between nati on
and State remains. The nation is a community. the State an associ
ation; membership of the nation is a matter of sentiment. depend
ing on common experience and history! while membership of the
S
t
ate is a matter of legal status.
2.5 Distinctive features of the State
If we want to defne the concept of the St at e. we mllst di ffcrl. nt i at c
t he State from other species of the samc genus. The St at c i s an
association. but how does i t differ from other associations? Let
us consider some suggestions.
(a) Unh:ersal jurisdiction within territorial houndaries
We have already seen that, even where nation and Statc have
the same territorial boundaries, membership of the two is not
absolutely identical. A person may be a member of the State but
not of the nation; and conversely. Membership of the State applies
to nearly everyone who lives within its boundaries. I say
'
nearly'
everyone. because the rights and privileges of a citizen are not
automatically and at once grnnl Vd t n everyone who comes I n li ve'
wi t hi n the boundaries of the Slate. t
'
v lany Sl at eS accord ci ti zt. nshi p
to anyone born within t hei r territnry. but a foreigner who i mmi
grates and wants t o become a citizen has tn wait for a t i me
and to show that he is worthy of citizenship by naturalization.
Citizenship, or membership of the State. carries obligntions as
well as rights and privileges. Ccrtain of the obligations imposed
and of the rights protected by the State. however. apply to all
persons who happen to be within its boundaries. whether perma
nently or temporarily, irrespectivc of whcthcr they are citizcns.
For example, a foreign resident docs not have the right to vote.
4 Problems of Political Philosophy
and i f he is a temporary visitor he may not be obliged to pay
some of the taxes levied on citizens and on foreigners domiciled
in the country; but he is obliged to obey the ordinary laws of the
land, and can be punished if he does not. (There is the exceptional
case of diplomatic immunity, which is granted by mutual agree
ment between States and for the sake of mutual convenience; but
this need not concern us here.) Conversely, he is equally entitled
to protection of common rights under the criminal and civil law
of the land. Just as he will be liable to punishment for stealing
from a citizen or anyone else, so a citizen or anyone else will be
liable to puniShment for stealing from him. The jurisdiction of the
State is applied universally to all persons who happen to be within
its bounds.
The bounds of jurisdiction are limited, roughly to the recognized
territory of the State (with some extension to territorial waters,
air space, and ships fying the State's fag in international waters).
These bounds are defned by the general agreement of States in
international law, designed to mitigate potential sources of con
fict. States divide the population of the world between them, and
each exercises universal jurisdiction within its boundaries. This is
true of no other form of association. I do not mean that i t is
impossible in principle for any other type of association, e. g. a
Church, to possess the feature of exercising universal jurisdiction
within a territory, but only that this feature i s i n fact confned to
States in the world'of today.
(bl Compulsory jurisdiction
The second feature of the State to be considered is closely linked
with the frst. The universal jurisdiction of a State within a terri
tory means that everyone in that territory is subject to its rules.
A universal statement is often equivalent to a statement of ncces
sitY and i t is so in this instance: anyone within the borders of a
State mut b subject to its rules, whether he likes it or not+
A univeral statement is not always equivalent to a statement
of necessity
:
'
Sometimes ' All ! 's are B's' does not imply 'Anything
that is ' an' A must be a B'. There may be a society in which
everyone is, as a matter of fact, a member of a particular Church,
as perhaps was once true of the inhabitants of Utah, It would not
necessarily follow that one could not be a member of that society
f'olitics and the ,)((/(C .
without belonging to t hat particular Church. The inhabitants may
all have chosen to be members of the Church; or at least . i t may
be that none have chosen not to be members of the Church
although they could opt out if they wanted to do so. Wi t h the
jurisdiction of the State, however, there is no choice about i t . If
you reside in, or even visit, a certain territory, you are willy-nilly
subject to the jurisdiction of the State which controls i t . You
cannot say that you choose not to be subject to its laws. If you
are in the country, you are necessarily bound by i ts laws, and i f
you disobey any of t hem you will be liable to punishment on the
assumption that you are bound by them.
Compulsory subjection to the juriscliction of a State is of course
dependent on the condition of remaining within t he State's bound
aries. Once upon a time. if a group of people preferred not to be
subject to the laws of thei r State, they could leave it and found a
new community elsewhere with rules of their own choosing. Today
it is still possible, for some peopl e. to emigrate from a country i f
they do not like i t s laws. But i t i s not possible for t hem to set up
an entirely new community with its own laws. All i nhabitable
parts of the earth (and nearly all the uninhabitable parts too) have
been commandeered by now and organized i nto new States or
brought under the jurisdiction of existing States. If you do not
like the laws of Britain, and if you can ,,[ford to emigrate. you
can escape the jurisdiction of the United Kingdom but not the
jurisdiction of any State. If you emigrate to Australia, you are at
once subject to the juriSdiction of t hat State, Thi s apart from the
fact that many people who would like to leave thei r State do not
have thf' money to do so, or. in some countries. require and
cannot obtain an exit visa. or cannot acquire permission to enter
or to reside permanently i n the country of t hei r choice.
The frst feature of the State that we considered, universal
jurisdiction, I! now true of no other type of association and can
therefore serve as a distinctive characteristic di fferentiating the
modern State from other associations. Does this apply also to the
second feature" It is often said that thc State is distinctive i n heing
a compulsory association while all othcrs arc voluntary,
If we may, for the moment, consider communities along with
associ ations. i t is not in fact true thut joining any other society
than the State is a matter of choice. One is born a member of a
family, and sometimes of a religion. Nor can one choose tn leave
46 Problems of Political Philosophy
a family, i n the sense of renouncing biological kinship. But one
can choose to leave a family considered as a social group; that i s
to say, one can choose to renounce consorting with the other
member or acknowledging any obligations towards them. Pre
sumably the same is true of religious communities. There may be
some religious communities which say that if one i s bor into them
one remains a member despite apostasy or deliberate fouting of
their rules and practices but since they cannot give effect to this
doctrine of continued bonds of allegiance, as the State can, the
recalcitrant may treat it as myth.
Some people are more or less compelled to join a trade union
if they wish to follow a particular occupation. They can choose to
leave, but only at some sacrifce, by abandoning that occupation
for another one. This is not unlike the possibility of escaping the
trammels of a particular State at tbe cost of emigrating to anotber.
Similarly, in some districts a failure to act as a member of the
church or chapel may involve sacrifce of a kind, such as facing
social and perhaps economic ostracism. The compulsion to con
form which is exercised by the State is greater i n degree than that
cxercised by some other social groups, including associations like
trade unions, but it does not appear to be different in ki nd so far
as its compulsory character is concerned.
(c) Functions
Different associations have different functions. I have already
noted, in 2.4, the view that the State should undertake all
communal purposes. Some philosophers have accordingly held
that the State differs from other associations in that it is omnicom
petent in its functions; indeed that it includes all other associ
ations, being an association of associations, the whole community
organized in all its aspects as a comprehensive associati on. This
view has been i nfuenced by undue concentration on the theory
and practice of ancient Greece, where the city-state really was the
whole community organized, and where Plato and Aristotle, i n
consequence, regarded the polis as omnicompetent. Some later
philosophers have followed them and have considered the more
limited functions of the modern State to be a defect, neglecting
the di fference that is made by the size of the two kinds of State
and by the di fferent character of religion among the Greeks and
f'olitics and the State 47
in the modern world. A further influence has been the analogy
between the State and an organism, again owing much to Greek
theory and especially to Aristotle.
To say that the State is omnicompetent may mean any of three
things: that the State may, or that it does, or that it should,
undertake any and every possible function. We shall consider i n
the next chapter (3.3) the views that it may or that i t should. In
practice, no State does. What are called totalitarian States may
claim to do so, but they do not altogether succeed, e. g. in regard
to religion. It is worth noting that the claim to identify the State
completely with the community tends to go along with making
religion, or a substitute for religion, a part of politics. This was
true of ancient Greece, and i t is true of communist ideology today;
communism may be regarded as a kind of religion as well as a
political system.
What, then, are the functions, in practice, of the modern State?
Its primary function is to settle find prevent confict, or to put it
i n another way, the keeping of order and the maintenance of
security. Two kinds of security are involved, security within the
community and security against injury from external sources.
Security within the community means security against deliberate
i nfringement of rights in respect of person or property (e.g.
against assault or theft), and against non-deliberate damage (e.g.
owing to negligence). Security against external i njury likewise
covers both deliberate harm (as i n acts of war by other States)
and non-deliberate damage (as when a home industry suffers from
the dumping of excessively cheap foreign goods). Internal security
is maintained by the keeping of order, that is to say, the incul
cation of regular modes of behaviour that will guarantee such
security. The criminal Jaw, and m'uch of the civil law, of a State
are designed to produce this. It is often said therefore that the
primary purpose of the State is to prcserve 'law and order', but
strictly speaking this confuses purposc and method. The prcser
vation of order is the aim or purpose; law. with its sanctions, is
the main method used by the State to give effect to this and some
of its other purposes. Security against external injury is pursued
by the maintenance of armed forces, the making of treaties and
alliances with foreign States, and economic measures such as trade
agreements and tariffs.
The primary function of the State that I have just describcd
^V IILLl<1+ VJ 4444R +AA<<_. ._
may be called a negative function, in the sense that i t is the
prevention of harm t o existing rights or existing well-being, as
contrasted wi th a positive function of adding to well-being or of
adding new rights or redistributing old ones. The aim of the
negative function i s to preserve the status quo of rights and oppor
tunities. In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, l i beral
democratic theory held that this was the sole function of the State.
The promotion or pursuit of further positive good was thought to
be the business of the individual. He should be left with as much
liberty as possible for that end. State action, which takes the form
of laying down and enforcing laws, restricts liberty, in that its
requirement to do or not to do this or that limits our freedom to
do as we please. The purpose of such laws, i t was said, was to
prevent individuals from encroaching on each other's rights or
liberties. The business of the State was to leave to each individual
as large an area of liberty as possible. Its interventions should
therefore be mi ni mal, limited to the negative function of prevent
ing one individual or group from encroaching on the liberty of
another. As for the pursuit of positive good - happiness, culture,
moral improvement - that was a matter for the individual hi mself.
He was free to promote his good if he chose and if he had the
ability. If he failed, whether through lack of effort or lack of
ability or sheer misfortune. that was a pity, but it did not call for
remedies by the Stote. A voluntary association, such as a chari
table organi7ation. might do something about i t ; but nOt the State.
The State should keep out of such matters. Its laws might be said
to echo the sentiment sati ri7ed by Arthur Hugh Clough:
Thou shalt not ki l l . but need'st not strive
Officiollsly to kcep alive.
This doctrine of the minimal State is at the opposite extreme
from the doctrine that the State should undertake all possible
social functions. As I have said, the minimal view was popular in
the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. Nowadays almost all
States add a positive function to the negative one of proteeting
established rights. There is a considerable difference between
liberal democracies and communist States in the extent to which
they pursue the positive function. And among the li beral demo
cracies themselves. some have moved further than others from
the idea of the minimal State. The USA. for example, has moved
less far than Britain. Even i n the USA. however, the State does
not confne itself to the negative function of prcserving order and
security.
The newer. positive function of the modern State may be
described as the promotion of welfare and justice. It i s now
regarded as a responsibility of the nati onal communi ty as whole.
in its organized capaci ty, to increase i n some degree the well
being of its members and to make more fair the distribution of
rights which they enjoy. Since the notion of justice is used to
cover anything that has to do with rights, one may say that the
minimal State too has justice 8! its ai m, Its practice of justice.
however. is a conserving (one can even say conservative) funct i on,
while the positive function is one of reformi ng the order of legal
rights so as to accord more closely with current moral ideas of
justice (often called 'soda 1 justice' ) .
'Welfare' i s a vague term. I t may refer only t o means t o physical
well-being. such as food. houses, and medical care. Or it may
include also some means to menIal or spiritual well-being. such
as educati on, art galleries. museums. and theatres, It would be
generally agrccd nowadays that a State should be responsible for
seeing that some measure of material well bei ng is available for
all its members. that , for example. no one should be left to starve
by reason of unemployment or sickness. But there is not general
agreement about the extent to which thi s should go. In Bri tai n
we have a National Health Service. but many people i n the United
States arc opposed t o the idea of socialized medicine'. The
modern notion of the ' Welfare State' in manv countries of West
em Europe and the Commonwealth is that the State should he
responsible for providing a bask mi ni mum of material welfare for
all. and that the individual should himself be responsible for tryi ng
to rise above that basic mi ni mum; but there i s di fference of
opinion between di fferent poli ti cal parties and other groups on
where the line of the basic minimum should be drawn. When it
comes to non-material well-being. there is even less agreement
about the role of the State. Communi st States include a great
deal. All States make some provision for educat i on, but in liberal
democratic countries it is generally thought that education should
not be a monopoly of the State. Once we go beyond education.
and facilities such as museums and art galleries which among other
50 Prblems of Political Philosophy
things contribute to education, we are on delicate ground. In
Bri tai n, most of us would thi nk that the State should be very little
concerned wi th aesthetic enjoyment (to say nothing of religious
activities), though in fact a certain amount of fnancial support is
given by the State nowadays not only to art galleries but also to
drama, music, opera, ballet, and even, in a small way, to the
writing of literature. But apart from education, these things would
not be regarded, outside communist countries, as essential
responsibilities of the State.
Do the functions of the State serve to differentiate it from other
associations? The negative function does, when taken as a whole,
but the positive does not. Part of the negative function can be a
function of other associations too. An organization l i ke Securicor,
which offers to guard money or other valuables i n transit, has
security as its function, though only in a limited feld of activity.
An associ ation of a different ki nd, a school or a university for
example, may have a disciplinary procedure to keep good order,
but this i s subordinate to the actual purpose of the association
and is i n any case restricted to order within the association. Only
the State has as its actual purpose internal order within the associ
alion, and only the State deals both with internal order and with
security from external injury.
The positive function, however, is not exclusive to the State.
Many associations and communities seek to promote the welfare
and just treatment of their members; this is true of the family,
religious communities, charitable organizations, trade unions. and
similar occupational associations. In fact the Welfare State has
simply taken over a part of a social function that was formerly
left entirely, and is still left to a considerable extent, to voluntary
effort by charitable organizations and individuals. The di fference
is that when responsibility to aid the poor and the weak is taken
over by the State, it is no longer a voluntary matter but is made
compulsor by law. This leads us to the next distinctive feature
of the State, the methods whereby its functions are carried out.
(d) Methods
The mai n..method whereby the State carries out its functions is
the system of l aw, that is, rules backd by coercive power. This
method plays relatively little part, however, i n the pursuit of
`
Politics and the Slate 5 1
security from exteral injury. There coercive power alone, i n the
shape of the armed services, and agreements with other States
that may not have the force of law, are more prominent. But even
i n this feld law has some place, both the rules of international law
and such domestic laws as relate to the raising and maintenance of
the armed services or to the imposition of tari ffs and quotas. To
preserve internal security, and to fulfl the positive function of
promoting welfare and justice, the State relies almost entirely on
the method of law.
All three 'powers' of the State. legislative, executive, and
judicial, are concerned i n the employment of this method. The
Legislature makes the law, or more properly. makes part of i t ,
namely statutes. The Executive (which i n this context may be
taken to comprise not only the Government but also the vast host
of public servants, i . e. the civil service, the police and prison
services, and the armed services) gives effect to the law by apply
ing and enforcing it. The judiciary interprets the law and also. i n
fact though not i n formal theory, helps t o make l aw i n the feld
of common or case law. So central and pervasive i s law to the
concept of the State that one theorist, Hans Kelsen, has held that
the State is best understood as simply being the system of law.
How does law distinguish the State from other associations?
All, or nearly all , associations regulate the conduct of their mem
bers by a system of rules, and often these are set out formally i n
a constitution. The di fference between the rules lai d down by the
State, which we call laws, and the rules of other associ ations lies
in a combination of two things.
First. the rules of the State arc backed by force. The decisions
of the courts are backed by the power of the police and prison
services. and in the last resort the Executive can if need be. use
the power of the armed forces. It should be noted that the differ
ence does not lie simply in sanctions, i . e. in penalties for the
breach of rules. but in the power to enforce the sanctions. Any
associ ation may impose penalties for the infringement of its rules
by a member. A trade union, the head and other teachers i n a
school, a bod
y
like the General Medical Council that regulates
the conduct ot a profession. may all prescribe penalties ( stich as
fnes. deprivations of various kinds. suspension. or expulsion) for
the breach of rules. I n some of them. the school for instance, the
penalties can be enforced to a cerlain extent. but only to a certain
extent. If the erring member of the association refuses to accept
the penalty, or, i n the case of the child at school, can get some
responsible adult to question the propriety of enforcing i t , the
association must appeal to the authority of the State's laws, from
which its own authority is derived, and i f necessary the disciplinary
decision of the associ ation can be tested before a court, whose
judgement i s susceptible of enforcement by State power.
The mere use of coercive power is, of course, no monopoly of
the State. Armed robbers and bullies use it too. I have been
speaking of the place of coercive power in enforcing the rules of
an association, not just in enforcing the will of an individual or
body of men. Occasionally, however, the latter can tum into the
former, as when an unlawful gang like the Mafa in Sicily virtually
acts as if it were exercising the functions of a State. To bring out
fully the difference between the rules of the State and those of
other associations, we must add a second feature of State law.
This has already been mentioned by implication in what I have
said about the authority of State law in relation to that of other
rules. The rules of other associations within the jurisdiction of a
State, and the authority which those associations possess to make
and apply their rules, are subordinate to the rules of the State.
The State's rules are the supreme rules. This i s what is meant by
State sovereignty. a concept so important for the ideas associated
with the modern State that it needs to be listed separately.
(e) Sovereign tv
To say that the State is sovereign is to say that the State has
supreme or fnal authority in a community, that its rules override
the rules of any other association. Other associations within the
State's territory, e. g. a borough, a factory, a trade union, a univer
sity, are subject to the authority of the State. Such legal powers
as they have are granted to them by the legal authority of the
State. They may make rules only to the extent that the laws of
the State permit or require them to do so. Any internal dispute
within such an association (e.g. between a member and the presid
ing bodyl. or any dispute between one such association and
another (e. g. between a borough and a university), is subject to
jurisdiction by the State's courts. But the legal powers of the State
itself are for the most part not subject to any higher authority -
in the world as now constituted.
In earlier times the authority of a King could be held to be
subject to the higher authority of a universal Church and one can
imagine that at some future time the authority of States may be
subject to the higher authority of an international organization,
just as now the authority of a non-sovereign state like Alabama
or Michigan, which is a constituent member of a federal union,
is in many felds of action subordinate to the authority of the
federal State. That is why people talk of 'giving up our sover
eignty' when there is discussion about membership of a supra
national political organization such as a United States of Europe
(or, for that matter, the European Community if the political
aspirations of the Treaty of Rome become a reality), or such as
a revised form of the Uni ted Nations Organization. But at present
the sovereign State is a fnal authority.
You may ask: What about international law? Is not that
superior i n authority to the law of an individual State, and is not
the International Court of Justice at The Hague superior to the
courts of England or Scotland? For that matter. what about a
body of law that is intermediate between State law anel inter
national law, like the European Convention on Human Rights
which is under the jurisdiction or O European court at Strashourg.
or the European Treaty of Rome which is under the jurisdiction
of a European court at Luxembourg?
The answer to these questions is rather complicated. Let us
take international law frst. It is not entirely clear whether one
should say that international law is superior i n authority to State
law. Interational law does serve to defne the bounds of jurisdic
tion of sovereign States. and in other respects the authority of
international law is developing markedly in our own ti me. Never
theless, the short general answer to the question is ' No' . from a
legal point of view. From a moral point of view, the answer may
be 'Yes. That is to say, we may think that international law ought
to count as superior to municipal ( i . e. national) law. But the
present legal position is that many (though not ali) rules of inter
national law are binding on a State only i f that State voluntarily
accepts them as binding; and if i t docs, a method frequcntly used
is to i ncorporate the relevant part of intcrntional law within its
own municipal law. The relation of an international court to

54 Problems of Political Philosophy


national courts i s not that of a court of appeal to that of a court
of frst instance. Some day it may be, and the beginnings of a
move i n t hat direction may be seen i n the authority of the Euro
pean Court of Human Rights to give a decision on a complaint
brought by an individual against his own State after he has exhaus
ted all the remedies available to him in the courts of that State.
Even i n this situation, however, the decision of the European
Court of Human Rights is legally binding upon the State only if
that State itself has formally adopted the European Convention
on Human Rights as part of its own municipal law. The United
Kingdom has not done so, as yet anyway, but has voluntarily
accepted the practice of generally abiding by decisions of the
European Court of Human Rights. In the case of the Treaty of
Rome, all member States of the European Community have
decided, by legislative acts of their own, to adhere to the treaty
and to accept the jurisdiction of the European Court at Luxem
bourg. This court therefore does have superior authority over the
courts of a member State. At present the law of the European
Community i s largely confned to economic matters, but there are
moves to widen the scope of the Community, and so of its law.
Debate on this potential development continually includes dis
cussion of the 'transfer of sovereignty'. If the European Com
munity were ever to become a fully-fedged political enti ty, a
United States of Europe, then sovereignty would have passed
completely to it from the member States, which would then be
constituent units of a federal State, as is true of the United States
of America. If that were to happen, the new European entity
would be the sovereign State and the constituent units would be
subordinate to i t and no longer States in the full sense of the
word.
Of course the law of a State i s not held to be superordinate
over i nternational law or over the law of another State. To say
that the law of the State has supreme authority is not to say that
it has no equals, that it is the only fnal legal authority in the
world. States recognize the equal sovereignty of other States, and
they also recognize that international law has its own independent
form of a\thority. To say that the State has sovereign or supreme
authority i s to say that its legal authority is not subordinate to
any other authority, while at the same time it is superordinate
I
POlifics alld fhe S'wle .5
over the authority of other associ ations which carry on their affairs
within the territorial boundaries of its jurisdiction.
This survey of suggested distinctive features of the State has
shown that the State is differentiated from other associ ations by
its universal j urisdiction. its negative function, and the special
character of law i n being backed by force and having sovereign
authority. The compulsory nature of State jurisdiction. and the
State's positive function, di ffer in degree but not i n kind from
similar features of some other associations, We may therefore
defne the State as an associ ation designed primarily to mai ntai n
order and security, exercising universal jurisdiction wi thi n terri
torial boundaries, by means of law backed by force and recognized
as having sovereign authority.
3
Libert
y
and Authority
3. 1 The idea of freedom
'Freedom' means the absence of restraint. A man is free in so far
as he is not restrained from doing what he wants to do or what
he would choose to do i f he knew that he could. The idea of
choice itself implies a kind of freedom. Choice is the selection of
one possibility among others. More than one possibility must be
open to us before we can be said to have a choice. If we were
always bound to do the one thing that we in fact do, we should
not be free to choose: there would be no freedom of the will. The
concept that I wish to discuss, however, is not the freedom of the
will or freedom of choice. but the freedom to carry out what one
has chosen to do. This is what is commonly meant by freedom or
liberty i n social and political discussion.
Having distinguished freedom of choice from freedom of action
or social freedom, we may defne the latter as the absence of
restraint on doing what one chooses or what one would choose
to do jf one knew that one could. We must add, however. that
the restraint must either be due to the deliberate action of other
persons or be removable by the deliberate action of other persons.
A man who is locked up in prison is not at liberty, because he is
restrained by the action of other persons. And we may speak of
freedom fom want, or of freeing mankind from the scourge of
cancer, when we mean that the impediments to which we refer,
although not imposed by human action, are capable (we hope) of
being removed by human action. But we should not say that a
man is unfree because he is restrained by a natural impediment
which cannot be removed by human action. If I do not have the
natural physique to run a fourminute mile, we should say that I
am 'unable', but not that I am 'not free' , to do so.
The defnition that I have given is, of course, a very general
one. When freedom is mentioned in any particular context, it is
always relevant to ask two questions: freedom from what? and
freedom to do what? The frst question asks what sort of restraint
is to be removed or prevented. The second question asks what
sort of actions are to be unrestrained. During the Second World
War President Roosevelt and Mr Churchill drew up, i n the Atlan
tic Charter, a declaration of 'Four Freedoms' as their war aims.
The four freedoms were: freedom of speech, freedom of worship,
freedom from fear, freedom from want. You will notice that two
of these are freedoms 'of' and two are freedoms 'from'. The frst
pair of freedoms specify two kinds of action which should be free
or unrestrained; they answer the question, freedom to do what?
'Freedom of speech' is freedom to say what one likes. 'Freedom
of worship' is freedom to practise whatever religion one chooses.
The second pair of freedoms i n the Atlantic Charter specify two
kinds of restraint which should be removed or prevented: they
answer the question, freedom from what? 'Freedom from fear'
claims that men should not be prevented by fear from doing
whatever they choose to do. fear of a Go\ernment with serret
police such as the Nazis used, or fear of war and insccuritv.
'Freedom from want' claims that men should not be prevented by
want from doing what they would choose to do. want or poverty
due to unemployment, the lack of a living wage. or the inability
to work because of sickness or old age.
Two further features of the defnition should be noted, since
they are relevant to certain traditional criticisms of the common
sense concept of freedom. ( 1 ) In thc frst place, the defnition is
a negative one. It describes freedom as a negative concept , as the
absence of restraint on doing what one chooses. (2) Secondly,
something needs to be said about the word 'chooses' i n the defi.
nition. Usually, what we choose to do is what we wan I to do.
Sometimes it is not. Sometimes a man will choose to do one thing
although he ' would like to do something else instead. I n such a
case he chooses the one action because he thinks it is the right
thing to do. For example, he may choose to stand out for an
unpopular cause, which he believes to be right , although it would
be easier and more comfortable for him to go along with the
58 Problems of Political Philosophy
majority. He chooses to follow his conscience rather than his
inclination. In these circumstances freedom to do as we choose is
freedom of conscience. But more often, as I have said, what a
man chooses to do is what he wants to do; and then freedom to
do as we choose is freedom to do as we wish. Doing what we
want to do may happen to coincide wi th doing what we think
right , or i t may go against what we thi nk right, or i t may be quite
irre1evant to questions of conscience. The main point is that doing
what we choose to do i s usually doing what we want to do, so
that freedom. as I have defned it, is most often a matter of being
unrestrained i n doing what one wants.
The defnition of freedom that I have given i s fairly simple, and
I think that it, or something like it, is obviously what we normally
mean by the term. This common-sense concept of freedom, how
ever, has been criticized by a long li ne of philosophers on two
grounds connected with the two points that I have just noted.
(1) First, objection has been taken to the negative character of
the common-sense notion of freedom. Freedom, it i s said, is too
precious a thing to be merely negative. Freedom is one of the
highest values of human life, and therefore it must be something
vital and positive. This criticism has come mainly from philosophi
cal Idealists, in the technical sense of that term. Philosophical
Idealism is a metaphysical doctrine which holds that the mental
or spiritual is real and the material is not. It i s called 'Idealism'
because i t regards 'ideas', the contents and activities of minds, as
the stuff of reality. This metaphysical doctrine is not directly
relevant to social and political theory. But it so happens that the
most infuential school of philosophical Idealists has also held the
ethical theory of Self-Realization, the theory that the end of
human life is to realize the 'true' or 'higher' self. Since these
philosophers think that self-realization is the ultimate value, they
have argued that freedom must have a close connection with self
realization if freedom is to be a value. A man is truly free. they
have argued, when he has realized his true self. Freedom is to be
defned i n terms of self-real ization, which is a positive notion, not
a mere negative one.
I do not thi nk that this objection to our common-sense defnition
of freedom need worry us greatly. All that it comes to is this: if
freedom i s a negative concept . then freedom cannot be the ulti
mate value. That consequence can be accepted. Whether or not
1
l
l
;
!
I
i
' ''`' '. ^ ' ',
we agree that the ultimate value is selfrealization, OUf common
sense definition of freedom does imply that self-realization or self
development has a value. If we attach importance to freedom,
understood as I have defined i t . this means that we thi nk it import
ant that a man should not be restrained from giving effect to his
choices. We can think that important only if we attach value to
choice and the exercise of choice. Liberty i s a necessary condition
of self-development or self-fulfilment and is valued as a means to
self-fulflment. This does not mean, however. that self-develop
ment or self-fulflment is the same as liberty. Nor does it imply
that freedom is of little account because i t is only a means to an
end. The fact that something is a means to an end. and not an
end i n itself. does not make it of comparatively small i mportance.
If i t is a necessa,:. means to a vilal value. then i t i s itself vital.
(2) The common-sense concept of freedom is also criticized on
the ground that it makes freedom a means to doing what we
,
ant; the end which it serves is 'mere desire', But , the argument
proceeds, there is nothing of value i n mere desire. The kind of
action that has value is moral action, the doing of what is good
or right. An individual's desires often go against thi s. Freedom to
do as one likes is not liberty but licence . Thi s second criticism i s
a very ol d one, and goes right back to Plato and Aristotle. But ,
l i ke t he frst criticism, it i s also common i n t he work of the
philosophical Idealists and is ticu lip with their notion of self
realization.
I have in fact defned freedom in terms of choice, nnd not
simply i n terms of what a man wants Of desires to do. But I have
agreed that usually i t is a matter of desire. Desires may be bad
and they may be good. Whal makes a bad desire bad? 'I suggest
it is the fact that the desire in question is hostile to other desires,
of the agent or of other persons. The satisfaction of any desire,
considered simply as a satisfaction or pleasure, i s to th

t extent
good, and a right action would not be right unless, among other
conditions. it was intended t o promote someone's intercsl. i . e. to
sati sfy desires whether in the short or the long run. When the
satisfaction of a particular desire is thought bad or wrong, this is
because i t thwarts the satisfaction of other actual Or potential
desires, in the agent or in others. which are regarded . for one
reason or another, as more i mportant than the frst desire. The
goodness and badness of desires is carried over to the means of
6 rroblemOJ rDIUleal rnuosopny
satisfying them. I f the satisfaction of any desire, considered simply
as a satisfaction, has some degree of goodness, so has the freedom
to obtain that satisfaction. But if the satisfying of a particular
desire thwarts t he satisfaction of others, the thwarting i s a restric
tion of freedom, so that freedom to satisfy the one desire i nvolves
a lack of freedom to satisfy the others. 'Licence', or freedom that
is disapproved, is freedom of this kind. Considered simply as an
instance of freedom i t has an initial cl ai m to be considered good,
but i f the freedom that it restricts has a stronger claim, then its
badness as a cause of unfreedom outweighs its goodness as being
an instance of freedom itself.
In the light of their two criticisms of the common-sense concept
of freedom, Idealists have been led to i denti fy 'true' freedom
wi th the doing of one's duty. This is positive and always good.
Occasionally, to be sure, a duty is felt to be a form of restraint
on doing what we should like, but thi s, according to the Idealists,
does not mean that we are unfree in doing our duty. For when
we perform a duty we exercise freedom of choice (or free will),
which is the true form of freedom. The freedom to do as we like,
which may be restrained by the requirements of duty, i s not a
true or real freedom. Indeed, a man who feels t he call of duty as
a restraint is already in bondage to his desires, his 'lower self' . He
has not fully realized the 'higher self', i n which perfect freedom i s
to be found.
This line of argument fails to make the necessary distinction
between freedom of choice and freedom to give effect to one's
choices. It also confuses freedom of choice with what may be
called the 'freedom of inner harmony'. When a man fnds that
the following of duty involves no tension wi th his desjres he has
rcached a harmony between conscience and desire. Since there is
no confict between them, neither is felt as a restraint upon the
other, and the following of either motive is free from internal
restraint . Such a freedom of inner harmony, when perfectly
developed, may be a form of necessity, i n the sense that the agent
has no choice; he necessarily does what conscience and desire
alike move hi m to do. He is not restrained, but he also has no
choice. A sai nt (or, i n the language of Immanuel Kant, a person
wi th a 'holy will') would have this character. It is proper to say
that he would exercise a form of perfect freedom, and religious
doctrine so describes i t . But it di ffers from freedom of choice. for
I
i
the 'holy will' necessarily follows one path while freedom of choice
is freedom to adopt ei ther of two (or more) possibilities. Freedom
of moral choice is freedom to choose either right or wrong. A
free choice of what is wrong is no less free, in thi s sense of 'free',
than is a free choice of what is right.
The Idealist, therefore. reaches his view of 'true' freedom by
confusing together three di ffercnt things, freedom of inner har
mony, freedom of choice, and freedom to give effect to our choi
ces. The sa
i
nt who necessari l y docs what is right possesses the
freedom of inner harmony but does not have freedom of choice.
The man who has freedom of choice may exercise that freedom
in choosing what is wrong as well s1> in l'hooj ng what is righl. I f
he also possesses the socicl freedom of not bei ng restrained from
giving effect to his choice. thi s sodal freedom may be bad (when
he does what is wrong and harmful tl. others) just as easily as it
may be good. The freedom of inner harmony may be called
'perfect' i n that its exercise is never bad. It is not what is meant
by the word 'freedom' when used in social and political contexts.
Social freedom is not always and unreservedly a good thi ng; some
restraints upon i t are essenti al . The fact that we usually thi nk it
good should not mislead us into supposing that it is always so and
thereby into confusing i t wi th a different form of freedom which
is relevant to ethics and religion but not to politics.
Although the idealist concept of freedom confuses different
senses of the term, i t does have a point in directing our attention
to the potentialities of human nature rather than to actual present
desires. There are circumstances in which a man's present desires
do not form the determining factor for saying whether or not he
enjlYs freedom. Consider the example of a slave who is contented
with his lot and genuinely docs not want any di fferent status. I f
freedom is defined as t he absence of restraint 011 satisfying present
desires. it follows that the conlented slave is not unfree. A di scon
tented slave who wunts to be released from hi s present state is
unfree. because the legal conditions of his status are a restraint
upon hi s wishes. The contented slave is subject to the same legal
conditions, but they arc not a restraint upon hi s wishes since he
doCs not want to change his si tuati on. Or take the example of
someone who has been 'brainwashed' i nto acceptance of a rcrress
ive political regi me. l i ke Wi nston Si lli th in George Orwel l ' s novel
Ninefeen Eighty-Four. Before he was brainwashed. Winslnn Smith
W
Ii
i'
!
62 Problems of Political Philosophy
certainly felt unfree. By the time the manipulators have fnished
with hi m. he loves Bi g Brother and does not want things to be
any di fferent. We need to remember that there are two ways in
which a man may be rid of an obstacle to the satisfaction of a
desire. The obvio
'
us way is for the obstacle to be removed, so that
the desire may be fulflled. The less obvious way i s for the man
to stop, or to be made to stop, desiring what he cannot attain. I f
he ro longer has the desire, i t may be said that the lack of freedom
which was presented by the obstacle no longer exists. The obstacle
itself remains, but it is no longer, for hi m, an obstacle to the
satisfaction of desire. He is content to be as he i s, and therefore
he has what he wants. Yet we should not be inclined to say of a
contented slave, or of a brainwashed Winston Smi th, that he
ceases t o be unfree just because his present desires are not
restrained by his legal or political situation. In thinking of freedom
we assume a norm of human nature in which the desire for self
fulflment IVQuid be restrained i
-
y the conditions of slavery or of
the political regime of Nineteen Eighty-Four. We assume (and, I
think, on good evidence) that if the contented slave were given a
taste of emancipation and were then asked to choose between it
and his former status, he would prefer emancipation. Although
some slaves are contented with their lot if they are well treated,
and although some cmancipated slaves may at frst feel over
whelmed by the responsibility of having to fend for themselves,
one would have to go far to fnd a slave who would choose to
remain in slavery if offered his freedom, and further still to fnd
one who. having been emancipated. would choose to return to
slavery, preferring the fleshpots of Egypt to the hardships of Si nai .
Likewise we are certainly justifed i n contrasting natural choice
with the suhmission i nduced by brainwashing or similar tech
niques, and prisoners of war who have been subjected to such
treatment soon revert to a normal frame of mind after their release
from the prison camp.
The defnition of freedom which I have given is intended to
allow for what I have just called a norm of human nature. I have
defned freedom as the absence of restraint on doing what one
chooses or what one would choose to do i f he knew that he could.
Our 'norm of human nature' , when we think of freedom, is not
a visionary ideal to be atlained only by exceptional persons; it is
the human nature that we atlribute to normal human beings. A
I
Liherry and Authority 63
slave has been, in a sense, dehumanized: 'Zeus takes away half
the virtue of a man when the day of slavery comes upon hi m. '
I
Still more obviously is this true of brainwashing. The norm of
natural choices and desires that we take as standard i n Ollr concept
of freedom is not a 'higher' or 'best' self, as the Idealists suggest,
but the natural character of an average human being in normal
circumstances.
I have written of the common-sense and the idealisl concepts
of freedom. The distinction between them was emphasized and
explored by Sir Isaiah Berlin in a celebrated leclure,' in which he
described the two concepls as 'negative freedom' and 'positive
freedom'. I have avoided those names because I thi nk the term
'positive freedom' is misleading: i t had not previously been used
even by the advocates of the idea. Berlin himself was severely
critical of the notion of positive freedom, hut it has fOll nd more
favour i n some later discussion, Richard Norman. for example.
reiterates the old complaint that a negative concept of freedom
as the absence of restraint fails to show why freedom i s highly
valued. He fastens upon choice as 'Ihe core of our idea of freedom'
and claims that ' freedom consists in being able to make choices'.
He argues that the absence of restraint concerns freedom only if
i t is understood as the absence of coercion, a restraint upon
choice, ' A rock or a stone docs not become free by being left
alone.
It is certainly true that the value of freedom is derived from
the value that we set on choice. There is ample provision for this
valid point when freedom is defined, as 1 have defned i t . as the
absence of restraint upon choice. 1 1 is, however, nnt true that
'freedom consists in being ahle to make choices'. As in earlier
idealist theory, this statement fails to distinguish the ability to
make a choice from the freedom to give effect to one's choice.
Homer, {)drJSI'\. XVI I . ;22-.1.
' Two C(t1cl;f f Lf>rrf. (Oxford. j()5H): reprinted !I) Fa/lr Fs.w.n If Uherl),
(Oxford. 19691
-' Idealists often entlNI their concepl ',ruc' frct'tlom. One of them, T. H. Green,
used the lerm 'pos.itin: in a definition of freedom hut l1t as nn adjective altachell
to the word 'freedom' itself; he tlescrihed freedom a< 'n positive power or capacity
of doing or enjoying something worth doing or enjoying'. 1 once discussed rhis
with Sir Isaiah Berlin nnll hc agreed that his own lise of the term 'positivc freedom'
had probably been suggested \ hi m hy Green's phrase 'a posi!i \'c power or
capaLity +
Free and Equal (Oxford, 19R7). pro .5-X.
<
I'
1
t
6 Problems of Political Philosophy
Norman notes that the degree of freedom varies with the range
of choice, and he thinks that this supports his case; someone who
lives in a country with severe travel restrictions is less free than
someone who lives i n a country without such restrictions. But the
difference i n their degree of freedom lies i n the presence or
absence of restrictions, not in the ability to make a choice. Each
of the two people has the ability to choose to emigrate, but the
frst is not free to carry out that choice, and his lack of freedom
lies in the restraint placed upon his acting in accordance with his
choice. Norman would no doubt say that he is talking about
effective choice and that the frst of the two people does not have
an effective choice. Even so, it is a lack of opportunity, not a
lack of ability; it is due to the external restraint imposed by the
authorities, not to some defciency in the internal capacity of the
individual to make a choice,
3,2 Liberty and law
I argued in 2.5(c) that it is the function of the State to preserve
order and security and to promote welfare and justice. Direct
State action, that is, the use of law and its sanctions, is applied,
in a democratic society. only where these purposes cannot be
adequately secured without i t. Law restricts liberty in requiring
us to do things that we might otherwise not want to do, and in
requiring us to refrain from actions that we might otherwise want
to do, The restrictions upon liberty imposed by the law may be
intended to protect the liberty of others (or sometimes of oneself)
which would be impeded by the behaviour that the law restricts.
or alternatively the restrictions of law may be intended to promote
other values than liberty (though. as we shall see. it is often
possible to regard those values as including the promotion of
liberty in some respects), For either of these reasons the restric
tions of law may be desirable. indeed essential. Nevertheless they
are restrictions upon liberty, and therefore a democratic society,
which sets a high value 011 maintaining a maximum of liberty,
deliberately limits the scope of State authority, Just where the
limits should be placed, however, is a matter of controversy.
There is considerable di fference of opinion, not just about details
of application, but even about the general principles that should
mark the houndary hetween the scope of law and that of individual
freedom, We may illustrate the di ffculties in four felds of State
action.
(a) Crime
The prevention of much harmful action, of a minor kind, is left
to agencies other than the State. It is left to the instruction of the
family or religious institutions or schools, and to the infuence
exerted by public opinion. The force of law is brought in only
where a type of socially harmful action is felt to be seriously
harmful to society (e.g, murder, theft), or is likely to be wid
spread without the sanction of State action (e. g. parking a motor
car i n such a way as to be a nuisance or a danger). Such action
is what is meant by a criminal offence and is dealt with by that
branch of the law which is called the criminal law, People some
times talk of a distinction between crime and si n, But since the
concept of sin is a religious one . meaning a wilful breach of
divine command, and since many people nowadays would not be
prepared to give morality a religious interpretation, it is more
appropriate, for the purposes of social discussion, to speak of a
distinction between crime and moral wrongdoi ng. Not all wrongful
action is forbidden by law and so regarded as crime. Generally
speaking, wrongful action is made subject to criminal law only i f
i t meets one of the two conditions thal I have specified, namely,
either if it is seriously harmful to society, or if it is likely to
cause widespread social harm when left without legal control even
though the degree of harm in any particular instance may not be
very great . Thus we have Jaws against nuisance as well as against
murder and theft.
If this criterion were always strictly applied. it would follow
that action which is harmful only 1 0 the indivi dual agent himself
shOUld not be made the SUbject of law, i . e. should not be regarded
as crime. This position is strongly advocated by John Stuart Mill
in his essay On Liberty. a classic document of liberal-democratic
thought. According to this view. if a man chooses to drink himself
silly in his own home. so long as he does not make himself a
nuisance to others, and so long as his behaviour does not bring
any harm upon others. such as his dependants. then it is his own
business and not the business of the State. We may deplore the
fact that he is allowing himself to become morally degraded, but
L 'fUVJ"l. UJ rUHHCUI rnllUSUjJfly
we should not use the sanctions of t he criminal law t o prevent i t .
Other examples would be drug-taking (vhich i s i n fact subje:t to
legal control i n most countries) and sUIcIde or attempted sUIcIde
(which were regarded as crimes in English Law unti l 1961).
Of course, many people would disagree with Mil l ' s position.
Objection may be taken to i t on either of two grounds. ( 1 ) I t may
be argued that no action is without social effects. For example,
very few drunkards will be adversely affectIng no one other than
themselves; most will have wives and families who will suffer from
their squandering their money and from their brutishness: in the
ot her cases, there is at least the harmful i nfuence of example.
This objection is not to the principle of Mi l l ' s position, but to its
unreality, its lack of application. (2) Other people, however, may
object to the principle itself. arguing that the State ought to be
concerned wi t h the moral welfare of the individual agent.
Here i s one respect
i n which there can be di fference of opinion
about the limits to be set to the functions of t he State. The
argument conceJs the limits of State authority and those of indi
vidual liberty. How far should a man be left free to do as he
chooses with regard to his own l i fe'?
(b) Civil displltes
Civil law deals with disputes between individuals or corporate
bodies. In so far as the civil law concerns wrongs, they are wrongs
which are not treated as crimes, i . e. as deliberate harm to the
fabric of the organized society itself. They are acts which have
caused harm to individuals, e.g. because of negligence, and for
which a man is held liable to pay damages but not liable t o
punishment. There can also be disputes as to who has the right
on his side. e.g. i n actions for alleged wrongful dismissal, breach
of contract. divorce, and so on. Here the apparatus of the State
is brought i n to arbitrate on a dispute. It is not clear where the
rights and wrongs lie, and somebody has to decide.
Many disputes of this kind must be decided by the State because
the principles at stake are basic to the ordering of society, and
indeed a breach of these principles may at times impinge on
matters tat are subject t o the criminal law. For example_ some
breaches of contract , if deliberate. may involve or come near to
sllch crimes as fraud. Some cases of negligence (e. g. in driving a
Liherty and A /I(hority 67
motor car) may be 50 serious as to warrant a criminal charge, and
in consequence the criminal law does not al ways insist on the
doctrine of mens rea. the doctrine that wrongful action cannot be
criminal unless i t is done wi th deliberate i ntenti on.
Not all civil disputes which require arbi trati on, however. need
be referred to the courts of law. I do not mean simply t hat disputes
can be seuled 'out of court' by lawyers who have a good idea of
what a court woultl do if called up,)n to decide. I mean that the
parties to a dispute may agree tn accept the verdict of an arbitrator
who has nothing to do wi th the State and its courts of law. For
example. an insurance policy may say that in some circumstances
a disagreement about liability shall be referred to an independent
assessor for adjudicat i on. No doubt one of the reasons for prefer
ring the voluntary procedure is t hat it costs less than recollrse to
the courts: but this i s not the only reason. Compulsory arbitration
need not mean arbitration by ordinary courts of law and need not
be as costly, If it were thought necessary. insurance companies
could be required by statute to submit disagreements to a special
arbitration tribunal, the operation of which could be as inexpen
sive and as speedy as a voluntary procedure. The reason why this
i s not done is that i t is unnecessary. In n democratic societYt
voluntary methods are preferred t o State i ntervention so long as
the subject of dispute is one that can be settl ed by voluntary
methods with justice and stability.
On the o
{
le hand. then, there arc disputes that clearly must be
decided by the courts or other agencies of the State. and on
the other hand there are disputes that clearly do not need State
intervention. Between the two groups there i s an area of lIncer
tainly. an area of disputes or disagreements which SOme people
will regard as calling for State intervention whi l e others wi l l not.
[ shall give two examples.
One obvious example is furnished by some industrial disputes.
The general question how for the State should exercise control
over employers and workers in wage-bargaining is more appropri
ate for my next subheading. economic control, than for the pre
sent one of disputes under civil law. Issues of civil law do arise,
however, when strike action is in breach of a contract of employ
ment . Some people thi nk that such strikes should be made illegal,
others that this would be an unwarranted i nterference wi th the
freedom of workers to obtain i mproved conditions for I hemselves.
68 Problems of Politicl Philosophy
The one side argues in favour of State intervention i n order to
protect the rights of contract in the interests of justice and the
common good. The other side argues against State intervention
on the ground that it would li mit essential liberties of individuals
and of social groups such as trade unions.
My second example concerns the liberty of the press, i n relation
to the general interest or to the liberty of individuals. In 1953 the
proprietors and editors of newspapers in Bri tain set up a voluntary
Press Council to consider complaints of improper conduct. The
freedom of the press is of course restricted by law to some extent.
for instance in regard to libel. But many things appear in the
newspapers which, while not illegal, may be thought to overstep
the bounds of a proper decency; for example, intrusion into the
private lives of people who happen to be connected with some
event, perhaps a tragic one, that has come into the news. The
decisions of the Press Council on complaints brought before it are
recommendations only, and some people thi nk it is insuffciently
effective. It could be given statutory recognition, like the General
Medical Council, so that its decisions would have to be followed
on pain of legal sanctions. Those who would li ke to strengthen
the hand of the Press Council may say that this is required in the
public interest or i n order to safeguard some of the rights or
freedoms of the individual private person. On the other hand, i t
can be argued that a maximum of freedom for the press i s itself,
despite possible abuses, a bulwark for the protection of the public
interest. Here again, then, there is room for di fference of opinion
about the limits of State authority.
(c Economic control
I have already mentioned wage-bargaining as a feature of eco
nomic life which may or may not be subject to State control. Of
course the very idea of wage-bargaining only applies where there
is a free market economy. Under a communist regime wages are
fxed by governmental agency: there is no bargaining between
employers and workers, and no threat of strike on the one side
or of declaring redundancies on the other. Where there is a system
of wage-bargai ni ng, one cannot expect that solutions to disputes
will be reached by sweet reason alone. Employers and workers
will not usually agree on what a frm or industry can afford, or
on what would be a just division of earnings i nto wages and profts.
It therefore seems to be inevitable that the workers must retain
a right to strike and the employers a right of dismissal. Yet it
does not need to be an absolute right i n either case. The indis
criminate use of the right to strike can be so harmful to the
community at large that some measure of State control seems
justifable. How far State intervention should go, however. is a
matter on which there will be many di fferent opinions. Drawing
a li ne between a completely free cconomy and a completely con
trolled one is an excessively ticklish business.
Industrial relations are of course not the only aspect of eco
nomic l i fe in which this problem arises. The nineteenthcentury
Utilitarians held that the State ought not to interfere at al l i n the
economic life of the nalion. and especi al l y that there sh"nild be
complete freedom for manufacturers and traders: laissez-loire,
laissez-passer. They took the view that a completely free market
led to the greatest contribution to the general interest. In the
period between the two World Wars, economic depression and
mass unemployment led to wide support for a planned economy.
Then disappointment with its results brought laissez-j"ire i nto
fashion again. Wholesale Stale planni ng of the economy i n com
munist countries certainly seems to have been less effcient than
the free market system. Even so. di fference of opinion remains
whether a completely free market is always the best way to serve
the general interest. Socialists tend to think that the proft motive
militates against the public interest. in rcgard to health and safety,
for example, and that some basic industries and services should
therefore be under public ownership or at least pUblic control.
Conservatives think that effciency, and so the best contribution
to the publ ic i nterest. depends on the incentives of proft and
competi ti on.
In some mal t ers. questions of justice to particular interests.
rather than contri buti ons to the general illterest, may afford a
ground for Stote intervention. An example is the provision of ai r
services to the SCOl ii sh Highlands and Islands, or of rail services
in sparsely populated areas. Thc`e services cannot pay their way;
but in order that the inhabitants of those areas should have a
reasonable share of the speedy transport facilities that are avail
able to people in other parts of the country, the Government
may require airlines and railways to provide services. Si mi larly,
1

70 Problems of Political Philosophy


manufacturers may be induced by the State to build new factories
i n areas where there is chronic unemployment, although i t might
be more economical, from the point of view of the manufactu
!
ers
at least, to a'dd to their existing factories elsewhere. Consider
again the system of taxation, A heavily gradu
,
ate
,
d sChe

e of
taxation and of death duties, which 'soaks the nch , curtaIls the
possi bilities of amassing private property, It may thereby reduce
incentives and so result in a lower total natlOnal product than
would otherwise be realized, The reason for such measures is a
conception of justice or fairness, There will be differences of
opinion on the extent to which this idea of fairness should be held
to outweigh liberty and scope for Initiati ve. In the Bntam of
todav. the Conservative and Labour Parties both agree that some
weig
l
l l should be given to incentive for the sake of individual
freedom and of a high IOtal national product, and that some
weight should be given to the reduction of inequality for the sake
of social justice: but conservatives tilt the balance more 11 favour
of the former, while socialists ti lt it more towards the latter.
All govermcntal action in the feld of economics

estricts the
liberty of some people, They are not allowed to do Just as they
please, If some types of strike are made illegal, workers have less
freedom of action in the tactics of wage-bargalOlOg, If the lfon
and steel industry is nationalized, the owners of foundries and
steel mills are no longer free to conduct thei r business as they
wish for their own proft. They must sell out and either betake
themselves to a different form of business or else, i f they choose
to remain as managers, they must accept orders from a State
appointed board and work for a fxed salary, The airline that is
required to provide uneconomical services to sp

rsely

opulated
areas as a condition of being allowed to contmue With other
services, is not given thc freedom that i t would like to make as
large a profit as possihle, And everyone who is required to pal'
taxes, large or small, is not free to spend that money as he would
like to do. Governmental restrictions on economIC freedom are
imposed for the sake of the general moral objectives of the
common good and justice: and while everyone nowadays would
acccpt the nccessity of somc governmental intervention i n the
economic sphere. there is disagreement on the extent to whIch the
moral objectives of the State justify the curtailment of individual
liberty, Often. on economic matters, the disagreement i s about
Lihert)' and Authority 71
means. on whether public control, e, g, of t he gas and electricity
supply industries, will i n fact serve the general interest better than
private enterprise would, BUI at ti mes. as in the system of tax
ali on. it is disagreement about ends, about the comparative weight
to be given to one moral objective as against another.
(d) Provision of soCial "elfare
Freedom and control in economic life have wider repercussions.
At frst sight it seems obvi(1uS that complete freeclom for
employers would allow starvation wages that grind the faces of
the poor. But one of the most stri king features of Adam Smith's
economic thought was his demonstration of the unintended public
benefts of competition in a free market. \/ hen engaged in eco
nomic activity, individuals think only of thei r own i nterest. but i n
practice their behaviour promotes the general i nterest: among
other things, an increase i n the wealth of the rich means an
increasc i n employment for the poor as the rich spend their wealth
on more goods and services. Present-day advocates of n free
market economy argue that such desirable social effects are rnore
successfully fostered by the spontaneous w(rking of a free eco
nomy than by govermental planning, The economist F, A, Hayek
carries the argument further so as to reject not only socialist ideas
of planning but the whole concept of 'social justice', Even Hayek,
however. is ready to allow that it is proper for a goverment to
ensure that al l citizens are protected from severe deprivation, He
rejects the view that such protection is a right of the needy,
something owed to them as a matter of justice. Instead. Hayek
thinks, i t can be justifed either as serving the general interest or
as a moral duty of everyone to help pe(ple who cannot help
themselves. His distinction between the two forms of justifcation
does not differ substantially from the distinction I have drawn
between two mond objectives or the cnmlnon good and justice.
Whether you call the second a duty of justice or simply a moral
duty. in ei ther event you differenti ate it from genernl utility and
think of it 3S something owed to the individuals who receive the
help,
Whichever way you look at it, in ll1t\st modern societies the
Lall'. l.rgtdali{lll find l.iber/. \'{ll II. TIl MiTt/gl' of Social lustief ( Lon(\(ln.
197nl. p. R7
72 Problems ol Political rhuosopny
State does provide a subsistence beneft to meet basic needs when
a person cannot earn his living owing t o unemployment or old
age or illness. There may be, in addition, State provision for
medical care. Some of these matters are controversial. But every
civilized nation regards i t as a responsibility of the State to provide
educational services, at least at the elementary level, and although
this is not usually regarded as an aspect of the 'Welfare State' it
is i n fact the same sort of thing, meeting a basic social need. The
provision of social welfare i n some degree is acknowledged by all
to be a proper function of the State.
As with other forms of State action, the laws that give effect
to this function restrict individual liberty. They obviously do so
in their fnancial requirements. Social security schemes and edu
cational services have to be paid for, by way of social insurance
contributions and general taxation, and, as I said a little earlier,
the legal requirement to give up a proportion of one's income to
the State means that one is not free to do as one likes with
the money. Other restrictions on freedom are involved too. For
cxample. the State may make it compulsory for parents to have
their children educated. or, in order to prevent epidemics, it
may require everyone to be i mmunized against certain i nfectious
diseases. The degree of compulsion can vary. While making i t
compulsory for every child to be educated up to the age of, say,
16, a State may leave parents free to choose between public
and private education. Vaccination sOOn after birth used to be
compulsory i n Britain now i t is only recommended, but if an
epidemic of smallpox were to break out i n a particular area the
people living there might be required to undergo vaccination.
Some of these restrictions on liberty are made for the sake of
the common good, others for the sake of justice. Educational and
health services are established partly for the sake of the general
interest; an educated and skilled citizen is more useful to the
community than an ignorant one, and a ft worker i s more useful
than a sick one. The same sort of thing may perhaps be said of
unemployment beneft. But it cannot be said of old-age pensions.
A person who i s too old to work cannot make a return to the
community for the beneft he receives. Justice, not the general
interest, i5 the ground hcre. It is felt that the community owes it
to everyone, as a moral right, that he should not be left to starve
in old age. Similar considerations of justice, or human rights, in
fact come into the other provisions also. When we judge that
everyone ought to be given a reasonable education, the services
of doctors and hospitals when needed, and the means of subsist
ence in times of sickness Or unemployment, we are surely thinking
of what is due to them as individuals and not simply of the
potential beneft to society.
In the feld of social welfare. as i n the other felds of State
action. there is difference of opinion about the extent to which
the State should makc legal requirements, thereby restricting lib
erty, for the sake of its general moral Objectives of justice and the
common good. Some people think that there should be ample
scope for a choice of private education or privately paid medical
services alongside the public system. Others think that the
inequality of treatment which this allows as between the rich and
the poor is an offence to social justice. Some think that social
security benefts should be cut to a minimum, Icst they sap initiat
ive and encourage sponging on the State; others think that i t is
better to run these risks than to permit hardshi p.
When the State restricts liberty. it can often be said to do so i n
order to enhance liberty i n other respects. 1 have spoken of the
moral objectives of the State as thc promotion of justice and the
common good. 'Justice' here includcs the old function of protect
ing established rights as well as the newer function of making a
more fair distribution of rights. and since a man's rights can often
be regarded as freedoms the protection or granting of a right is
often a protection or granting of freedom. For example. \\'hen the
criminal law restricts freedom \t) take Dtller people's goods. in
protecting security it protects freedom. since theft is a restraint
on the freedom of the property owner to make use of his property
as he wishes. Again, a redistribution of rights. whether i n terms
of opportunities. as i n education. or in terms of income, as i n a
scheme of social security, reduces the freedom of SOme people to
do as they would like and increases the similar freedom of others.
The same goes for the objectivc of the common good or general
interest. The general interest means the interest of most members
of the community. and a policy which advances the interest of
most people is one that gives them mare scope for doing as they
would like to do. So that while law restricts liberty, it is also true
to say that a decent mCilsure of liberty for all can only be secured
within the framework of a system of lilw. Nevertheless the fact
M
74 Problems of Political Philosophy
that one kind of liberty can confict with another. or that more
liberty for some people means less for others, often raises diff
culty and dispute in determining the propcr limits of State action.
3.3 The limits of State authority
We are thus brought back to a question that was raised by impli
cation i n 2.5(c), where I discussed the State's functions and
referred to the opposed ideas of the omnicompetent and of the
minimal State. Can one lay down any general principles about the
proper limits of State authority? The examples that I have given
of disagreement on issues in the different felds of State action
show that one cannot hope to fnd a clear-cut answer. I t would
be a foolish philosophy which rushed in where practice treads
delicately. A man's vicw on these disputed matters will depend
on his g
-
eneral political and moral outlook, and that cannot be
determined by philosophy alone.
One thing that philosophy can do, however, is to show, by its
clarifcation of concepts, that some limits on State action are
necessary and that the idea of the omnicompetent State often
neglects certain essential distinctions. From a practical point of
view this may seem a trivial task, since few people, in liberal
democracies at least. would want to advocate omnicompetence
for the State. Yet the idea of omnicompetence has had its attrac
tions even fOf thinkers of a democratic cast of mi nd, and it is
important to expose theoretical errors that are liable to recur.
There is a strong temptation for political philosophy to suppose
that it can give poitive guidance for practice, and the influence
of attempts to do so is far from negligible. If one thinks that these
attempts are misguided. the remedy is to show them up and not
just to desist from further attempts oneself.
I wrote i n 2.5(c) that to say the State is omnicompetent may
mean any of three things: that the State may, or that it does. or
that it shul d, undertake any and every possible function. I added
that, i n practice, no State does, and I reserved for further con
sicleration the views that it may or that it should. I deal rst with
the idea that it 11111.".
I f we t hi nk. not only of totalitarian States. but of a democratic
State l i ke Britain that does not have a fxed constitution, we arc
inclined to say that the powers of the State are unlimited. This is
Lihl'rry and Authority 75
not true of a country which has n flxed const itution setting limits to
what may be done. Such a const itution. 11OWC\er. usually contains
provision for its own amendment. If Hmcndrnent without limits
can be carried oul by legisJati\'(' process. lht'n the State may be
said to have unlimited powers after all: what is limited is the
power of a particular branch or arm of the State. In Britain,
however. i t would seem that one arm of the State, the legislature.
has unlimited powers. It has been said: 'Parliament can do any
thing except tUfn a man into a woman: In one sense it is false to
add the exception: in another sense it is false to make the general
statement . 'Parliament can do anythi ng' . unless this i s qualifed
by exceptions of a more radical character. The word 'can' is used
both of what one is able to do and of what one is permitted or
authorized 1 0 do: the second meani ng is more clearly expressed
by the word may' . I f we arc thinking (,f legal possi bilities. of
what Parliament may do. thel l Parliament is indeed omnicom
petent. and there is no need to add any exceptions at all. But i f
we are thinking of practical possi bilities. of laws that Parliament
can make effectively, the exceptions are far wider than the old
tag suggests. If Parliament were so foolish as to pass a Bill provid
ing that, as from a specifed date. a certain John Jones shall be
deemed to be a woman, this would not contravene any rule of
consti tutional law and so would not exceed Parliament's legal
powers but it would be thought crzy. and neither the comic Act
nor the Parliament which made it would retain any respect. Legal
powers. like legal 'bonds'. are artilicial fictions, not natural facts.
But if they are to be effective. thcy must be of such a kind that
most people \vill choose tn al. 't as i r they were facts. I f they fy
too flagrantly in the face of facts. and especially i n the face of the
psychological facts of what pcnpk are prepared to put up wi th.
they wi ll have no force. There are no legal l i mi tations on what
Parliament may enact; there are substantial practical limitations
on what it call enact effectively.
The practical limitations do not depend only on the natural
facts of physics or biology, as is suggested by the statement that
Parliament can do anythi ng except tur a man i nto a woman.
They depend aiso, and indeed more. on the natural facts of psy
chology, In Alief ill lVonderland, the Ki ng of Hearts tries to get
riel of Alice at the trial of the Knave by inventing thc rule. ' Al l
persons marc l illln a mile high to leave the court'. Suppose a
76 Problems of Political Philosophy
Parliament consisting of se1fconsciously small men were to pass
a Bi l l stating that all persons more than fve feet ten inches i n
height should be executed. This would be a val i d l aw, and there
would be no physical or biological impossibility in trying to put it
into effect. But i t would be psychologically impossible. If such a
Bill were passed by the Parliament, there would be a revolution.
On the other hand. if a majority of the populace shares the views
of the legislature on a measure, it can sometimes be given effect
even if it fies in the face of some biological facts, e. g. if laws
concerning racial discrimination presuppose that different 'races'
have di fferent brain structures.
Even in a totalitarian regime there are some things which people
will not stand for. No State has unlimited practical or political
power to make any law that it pleases, even though it may possess
unlimited legal power. A legislature that has any sense and that
wants to remain in offce will pay more regard to political than to
legal possibilities, to what it can effectively do than to what it
may legally do.
I turn now to the remaining sense of the doctrine of omnicom
petence, namely. that the State should undertake all the functions
that it can perform. The word 'can' here needs to be understood
as meaning 'effectively can' and not as meaning 'may' . If I am
not able to do something, there is no sense i n considering whether
[ ought to. The fact that there is no legal bar i s irrelevant. So it
would be pointless to ask whether the State ought to do everything
that i t may do. The question that matters i s whether i t ought to
undertake all the functions that it can, practically or politically.
perform.
The advocate of State omnicompetence i n this sense can put
his position very simply i n the first instance. The State exists 'for
the sake of the good life', as Aristotle said. It exists i n order to
forward moral objectives, justice and the common good. There
fore it ought to do everything possible to forward those objectives.
On the other hand it can be argued, again in moral terms. that
State action inhibits the morally good life. The methods used by
the State are those of compUlsion, law backed by sanctions. The
point of bringing i n State action to secure some ai m is that thi s
ai m wotd not be followed by all unless some were compelled.
Now compulsion is morally objectionable, because i t is of the
essence of moral action that it should be freely chosen. Hence,
the argument proceeds, the use of legal compulsion to secure
moral aims destroys the possi bility of acting from a moral moti ve.
So that i f the State tries to makc itself responsible for the good
life, the l i fe so produced ceases to be the morally goocl life. The
argument can be summarized as saying that legal compUlsion
inhibits the cxcrcise of moral freedom, the free choice of right
action for moral reasons.
This objection can, however . be carried too far. If the law
requires or forbids some kind of action, this does not imply that
everyone is going to conform under compulsion, instead of from
moral motives. Bill Sykes refrai ns from burgling only because he
sees the policeman on hi s bcat and is afraid of being caught and
imprisoned. But most people refrai n from burgling because they
thi nk i t would be wrong anyway. The authority of t he l aw,
although it docs depend on and make use of sanctions. coul d not
be effective unless most people accepted i t on moral grounds. I f
most people recognize a moral obl igation to obey the l aw, they
arc act i ng from a moral motive and not under compulsi on.
The objection t hat State acti on i nhi bi ts moral freedom, a form
of freedom of choice, is therefore not a particularly strong one.
A more telling objection is the obvious one that legal compulsion
restricts social freedom, freedom of action. This is also a value,
an essential part of ' { he good life', and i f State action restricts
social freedom more than it need, t hen the St at e di mi ni shes the
good life.
As against this. of course. it may be rcplied that frecdom is not
the only constituent of the good life and that the value of freedom
may have to be ,ecrifced for the sake of a greatcr or more
fundamental value. But this reply will not suffce to defend the
doctrine of Stte omnicompetence . For it allows that freedom i s
one value among others, and therefore it must admi t the possi
bility t hat at times the value of freedom may outweigh competing
values such as security. The authority of the State will need to be
limited by this possi bi li ty.
Most pOlitical theorists recognize that individual li berty and
State authority conflict with each other. and that a balance has to
be struck bctwecn them ancl the valucs they rcpresent . Some, like
Thomas Hobbes. fearful of the risk of anarchy. are prepared
to say that liberty must be severely limited to make way for
the bcnefits of State authori ty. Others. li ke John Locke and
78 Problems of Political Philosophy
J. S. Mi l l , thi nk that State authority should be markedly li mi ted so
as to leave as much room as possible for liberty. Both Hobbes on
the one side, and Locke and Mi l l on the other, agree that liberty
and authority can confict; it is not possible for complete liberty
and complete authority to exist together. There is, however, a li ne
of thought which tri es to say that the two do go together and that
omnicompetence for the State i s the only way to secure full and
genuine freedom. The arguments used for this conclusion are
derived from Plato. developed in Rousseau's theory of the general
will. and continued by the idealist phi losophers to whom I referred
in 3. I . The conclusion reached is the paradoxical one that com
pulsion by the State can make a man more free, not less, that i n
fact a man who is constrained by the l aw for the sake of moral
ends can be, i n Rousseau's phrase, 'forced to be free' .
This extraordinary view depends on the Idealist's interpretation
of 'true' freedom as the performance of one's duty. Freedom of
choice may be exercised in situations of moral confict, i . e. confict
between what is morally right and what one desires to do. Now
sometimes, when a man is carried away by desires, we speak of
his being a slave to his desires. If this happens in a situation of
moral confict, the agent does not have freedom of choice.
Because of this, some theorists. from Plato onwards, have held
that any action motivated by desire is not freely chosen but is
determined. By contrast. they have argued, action which is motiv
ated by the sense of duty is rational (reason being contrasted with
desire) and free. Thus they have reached the view that the only
kind of free action is morally right action. A man who 'chooses'
to follow his desires, against his sense of duty, is not acting freely;
a man who does what he likes or wants, irrespective of whether
it is i n confict with duty or not. is not acting freely. I t is action
determined or compellcd by desire. Only the doing of what is
right is free, because i t is rational. Obedicnce t o the State is right.
because the State's aim is the common good. and this is both what
we ought t pursue and what we really want. So that we are really
free. doing what we really want and acting rightly (the two are
identical, it is claimed). when we pursue the common good. And
i f a particular i ndi vidual wants to pursue some particular private
interest of his own. this can only be his 'apparent' wi ll. It is what
Cnmrm .weili. 1_ 7.
Uherty (nd Awhlll'ity 79
he thinks he wants, not what he really Wants. If he follows this
apparent will, he thinks he is free, he thinks he is doing what he
wants. But i n reality he is not frce, for he is not pursuing what
he really wants, the common good. He is enslaved by desire for
particular interest, instead of acting freely for the common inter
est. When the State compels him to act so as to serve thc common
good, it i s compelling him to do what he rcally wants. and so
compelling hi m to be free.
Some of the confusions inherent in this vi ew will already be
apparent from my discussion of the idealist theory of frccclom in
3. 1 . I shall now elaborate them. beginning with a comment on
the argument that motivation by desire is a form of bondage.
( 1) From the fact that we somelimes speak of a man as being a
slave to his desires, the theory infers thaI motivation bv desire is
a/ways a form of bondage. If this were a dcdllctive argument . it
would of course be fallacious; the proposition that some mcn have
red noses (or that some desires enslave) does not imply that all
men have red noses (or that all desires enslave). Presumably the
argument is meant to depend on induction or analogy. and to
yield a conclusion of probability only. But then our use of the
language of enslavement or bondage in relation to desires is lim
ited to a narrow range of actions. which appear to be discernibly
different from others. and which therefore cannot be used as
evidence for a generalization about all action motivated bv desire.
A man who is addicted to drugs or to smOking may kno\' that he
would prefer to get out of the habit but is unable to clo so. He
feels hclpless, anel certainly docs not regard himself as being free
to do as he wishes or chooses. Our experience is quite different
in the case of an ordinary sort of desire. when we do nn action
because we prefer i t . Both in our thought and in OUr language
about such experience we presuppose that we exercise choice.
The kleptomaniac feels that he is suhject I n compulsi ve urge: the
ordinary thief does not. That is why we cnn distinguish between
kleptomania and normal theft. Since aClioll due to the force of
addiction or neurosis feels di fferent from normal act i on. the fact
that the former may be described as enslavement to desire does
not justify us i n saying that all action mot ivatcd by desire is
enslaved or unfree.
(2) The theory confuses frecdom of c1lOice with frcedom of
action or social freedom. Enslavemen! by desi re implies tilal there
80 Problems of Political Philosophy
is no freedom of choice. But when we speak of having or not
having liberty or freedom in a political context, we are referring
to freedom of action or social freedom, i . e. the absence of
restrai nt or compulsion by human agency. including compulsion
by the State. No doubt compulsion by the State can prevent
compulsion by desire from being effective i n
.
acti

n , as wh
:
n the
law controls the sale of addictive drugs; but this IS Just substltutmg
one form of unfreedom for another. I t does not give the drug
addict freedom of choice (though it may be a necessary step
towards restoring freedom of choice i n due course), and it cer
tai nly does not give hi m freedom of action.
(3) When discussing freedom of choice in situations of moral
confict, the theory supposes that moral freedom applies only i n
one direction, as t he freedom t o do what i s right. But i f moral
freedom did not allow of genuine alternatives, to do what i s right
or not to do so, i t would not be choice. The theory i nfers that we
can be forced to be free, because i t equates 'being free' with
'doing what is right'. The paradoxical conclusion simply means
that we can be forced to do what i s right. This may well be
justifable, but not on the ground that it gives us freedom. If we
are forced, we arc not free. We do what is right, but not freely.
(4) Whi le a person may not always know what he wants, usually
he does: and when he does, there i s no reason whatever for saying
that he is mistaken and that the State can know better than he
what he himself wants. What he wants to do may be wrong,
because harmful to others, or perhaps because harmful to himself:
and if so, it may be justifable to restrain him by legal compulsion,
on the ground that what he wants to do is wrong. But i t cannot
be justifable on the ground that he is now enslaved and that .the
legal compulsion will make hi m free. Compulsory fre

ml IS a
self-contradiction. Freedom is not the only value, and It IS often
justifable to restrict a man' s freedom for the sake of other values
or for the sake of the freedom of other people. But if we do thi nk
it is justi fabl e. we should recognize that i t is a restriction of
freedom and to that extent bad.
The one positive conclusion that emerges from our criticism of
the idea of the omnicompetent State is there ought to be some
l i mi t to the exercise of State authority, simply because legal com- .
pulsion restricts freedom and freedom is desirable. Even the advo
cate of omni competence agrees that freedom IS a value: that IS
LIVtllJ TJ J,4_& _
why he tries to make out that State omnicompetence cnhances
freedom. On the other hand, frecdom i s not the only value. and
therefore we cannot follow the doctrine of the mi ni mal State i n
holding that the sale criterion for the bounds of State authority
is securing a maximum of freedom. If we coule do so, the criterion
would still be diffcult to applY. since one man's freedom may
confict with another'S. Restricting the freedom of factory owners
can extend the freedom of workers: for the freedom that the
factory owner once had, to hi re and fre as he pleased. meant that
the worker often di d not have the freedom to earn a l i vi ng. One
could say that all extensions of State activity restrict freedom for
some i n order to increase freedom for others. But then thi s implies
a principle of justice, that everyone has an equal claim to a
maximum of freedom. So I thi nk it is more sensible to acknow
ledge the complexity of moral objectives to be pursued by the
State, and to say that justice and the common good are not
identical with freedom, although they are all closely related.
The idea of using a maximum of freedom as the sale criterion
of the limits of State action seems most feaible i n the realm of
criminal law. There was some tillle "go " brisk debate in England
about the proper scope of the crilllinal law, the main protagonists
being Professor H. L. A. Hart' and Lord Devl i n. ' Hart argued,
i n the spirit of 1. S. Mi l l , that the mai n business of the criminal
law is to prevent harm to other people. Devlin thought that the
criminal law docs and should go further in preventing 81so some
conduct that is commonly considered i mmoral even though it may
not cause harm to other peopk. I t hi nk that Hart undoubtedly
had the best of this debate in his criticism or Devl i n' s position,
but h<: did not really lay down \ flrm cri terion hi mself. for he was
not prepared 10 go all the way \\' l l h Mi l l . He accepted the pro
priety of some 'paternalistic' legislation. e .g. on the control of
drugs or on harm done to people with thei r own conscnl. < A
criterion i n terms of maximum freedom alone does not suffce
even for the criminal law.
Apart from thi s, it i s not clear that one could sensibly try to
apply the same cri teri a to all ficlds lf State acti vi ty. In the liberal
democracies of the western worl o. the older branches of the crimi-
7 Sec especially Law, Lib('rr.'. {nd MIITlliiry ( { .ondll!l, 1l)6J).
The Eflforcemem of Morats ( London. 1 %5 1 .
Cf. Devlin. The Etrforcemef of Maraf 1 essay 7 .
82 Problems of Political Philosophy
nal and civil law retain a strong tradition of emphasizing the
protection of established rights and freedoms of the individual
against interference by the executive arm of the State as well as
by other individuals, while the newer branches of the law that
deal with economic control and the provision of social welfare are
more directed towards the ends of the common good and of justice
i n a reformative sense. As we have seen i n 3.2, in all these felds
of State action there is room for difference of opinion about the
limits of State authority and about the balance to be struck
between the ends of freedom, justice, and the common good. This
is one respect in which the distinctions of political parties show
themselves; and their disputes on such matters cannot be resolved,
though they can be clarifed, by philosophical analysis.
However _ if we agree that freedom is at any rate one highly
important objective, we can say that the State ought not to inter
vene in social life to the utmost extent in order to serve the
objectives of justice and the common good. And i f we also agree
that freedom is not the only objective, then we can say that the
functions of the State ought not to be limited simply to the old
negative function of holding the ring for freedom.
4
Democracy
4. 1 Democratic ideals
The distinctive .features of dcmol.'ratic governrnent , at least us we
understand it in the wester world, arc intended to secure a
maximum of liberty for citizens. Government wi th its rules of law
restricts our freedom to do as we please. Democrats recognize
the necessity of this. but they believe that, so far as possible, the
rules should be self-imposed or at any rate should be i n accordance
with the will or COnsent of the citizens. I f a man imposes a rule
on himself, or agrees to its imposition by another, he is not being
compelled but is acting voluntarily. Democracy i s a doctrine of
'do i t yoursel f ' , and. as someone has remarked. 'do it yourself'
often comes to 'rue it yoursel f ' . The democrat i s prepared to
make his own mistakes rather than to be directed bv someone
else who may have superior wisdom. The underlying idea is that
self-direction, choosing for yourself. is rar preferable to having
deciSIOns made for you, and imposed upon you, by another. This
is why liberty is valued.
For the democrat, liberty goes along with equality. He believes
that everybody, or at least every adult, is capable of exercising
the power of self-direction and should be given the opportunity
to do so. The democrat holds that all men have an equal right to
liberty and self-direetion.
- ^
Liberty and equality are what distinguish I he democratic ideal
from other political ideals. A notion of equality of some sort must
fgure i n any concept of justice. but it fgures most prominently
i n the democratic concept of justice: Liberty and equality are the
distinctive aims of democracy. That this has always been so may
84 Problems of Political Philosophy
be seen from the criticisms of democracy made by Plato.' Plato
describes the ends o[ democracy as liberty, equality, and variety,
and he criticizes democracy precisely because these are its leading
[eatures. Liberty, in the sense of doing what you like, is attractive,
Plato says, but it cannot last; and it i s furthenore less desirable
than doing the right thing, even though most people, not being
wise enough to know and to choose for themselves what is right,
have to be directed by others. Equality, in his opinion, is wrong
because it goes against nature; men are unequal in their capaciti es
and should be given different [unctions i n accordance with thei r
different capacities. (Vari ety he considers objectionable because
i t runs counter to an integrated society+ )
I have been speaking of democratic aims or ideals, and we often
do use the words 'democracy' and 'democratic' to refer to these
ideals, or even to one of them alone, especially equality. The
latter tendency is particularly common i n a country like New
Zealand which is strongly imbued with equalitarian sentiments.
When J spent some years in New Zealand after the Second World
War, J found people there rcady to call the British civil serice
'undemocratic' because i t had a di rect entry of university gradu
atcs to its policy-maki ng grade, the Administrative Class. Or
agai n, a good many Ncw Zealanders were inclined to say that the
British system of university education was ' undemocratic' because
i t was more selective than thei r own in its qualifcations for entry.
By 'undemocratic' they meant unequalitarian. But they are not
alone in this usagc. When J frst read a well-known History of
Poiiricai Theon' by an American scholar, Professor George H.
Sabine, J was puzzled by his statement, i n the chapter on liberal
ism. that John Stuart Mill's essay On Liberty 'was in a sense a
defense of liberty against democracy' . ' This struck me as virtually
sel f-contradictory until I ecalled Alexis de Tocqueville's charac
terization of Democrac." in America as the cult of equality more
than of liberty. I n other circles or in other contexts, however, the
adjectives 'democratic' and 'undemocratic' may refer rather to the
prevalence or curtailment of liberty. That is why it seems so odd
to us that communist regimes shOUld call themselves 'peoples
democracies', Tht' romlllUnists themselves would no doubt justify
, Republc. VI I I (557-Q5).
: 1st cd. (New York and London. 1937), p. 667; apparently omitted in the revised
edition.
their use of the term on the grounds that thei r form of society is
equalitarian and that it serves the i nterests of the masses instead
of (as they t hi nk western democracy does) the i nterests of 'the
bourgeoisie' .
There is, then, one usage of the words 'democracy' and 'demo
cratic' which connotes certain social ideals. As contrasted with
this usage, however, there is another, in which 'democracy' means
a set of political i nsti tutions& People who disagree wi th the so
called ' democratic ideal', and espccially wi th the ideal of equal i ty.
sometimes protest sharply against the use of the words 'demo
cracy' and 'democratic' to descrihe general social aims; democracy.
they insist, is a form of governmcnt. Etymologically the word
'democracy' undoubtedly began as the name for a form of rule .
'rule by the people'. as contrasted wi th 'aristocracy or 'oligarchy'
(rule by the best men, or by a few). and wi t h 'monarchy' (rule
by one man). My reference to Plato. however. shows t hat . al most
from the start, the word 'democracy' was associated wi th a set of
ideals as well as wi t h a form of government. This is intelligible
enough. for democratic forms of government wi l l have been
adopted onl y because i t was thought that al l citizens equally had
a claim to self-di recti on, i . e. because of a bel i ef i n a ri ght to
liberty and equal i ty. The concept of ariston<lcy can be si mi l arl y
used to mean a social ideal as well as a form of government. The
'aristocratic' ideal values culture (by which I mean the pursuit of
knowledge and beauty) more t han nn equal i tari an conception of
justice. A modern example of t he expression of aristocratic values.
such as Plato hel d. is to he found i n Clive Bell's book Civilization,
but there have been plenty (If other people who share t hi s outl ook.
although i t i s not often boldly acknowledged i n opposi ti on to
equalitarian ideas of justice.
I have spoken of 'soeial' rather than of 'political' i deal s. The
'democratic' values of liberty and equality are not si mpl y political
principles. I mean by thi s that they do not apply solely to the
organization of the State. We may t hi nk thcrc should be equality
of opportunity in education. without necessarily i mpl yi ng that the
whole of the educational system shoul d be run by the State. We
may thi nk there should be equal i ty hctwccn the sexCs. not onl y
i n political Olatters l i ke having the vote or i n legal ri ghts ti l prop
erty. but also i n regard to opport uni t\' for careers or to equal pay
for equal work Of to the position of husbands and wi ves (or sons
86 Problems of Political Philosophy
and daughters) i n the family. Similarly, questions about freedom
arise in communities and associations other than the State. Just
as the laws of the State may restrict freedom (or enlarge it for
some by restricting i t for others), so the rules, customary practices,
and beliefs of churches, educational institutions, industrial and
commercial bodies, and of families, may restrict or enlarge free
dom for their members. As we saw in 2.3, when discussing
patterns of regulation, it cannot be taken for granted that i f one
thinks a democratic form of organization best for the State, one
must necessarily think it best for every ki nd of association or
community. An equal voice for each adult member of a church
or a university or a factory is not necessarily the best way of
running its affairs. Sometimes a non-political association or com
munity can give its members more freedom. sometimes it must
be satisfed with less, than we think it proper and practical for
citizens to have in the State. The fact remains, however, that i f
we accept 'democratic' ideals, liberty and equality are values for
us i n other spheres of social life too. They may have to be qualifed
for the sake of other values, just as happens in political affairs;
but they remain values to be taken into account.
There is another concept that goes along with liberty and equal
ity in at any rate one strand of democratic thought. the concept of
fraternity. The slogan of the French Revolutionaries was 'Liberty,
Equality. Fraternity'. The concept of fraternity, the brotherhood
of mankind, and a fortiori of the members of a particular national
community, expresses the idea of common responsibility,
responsibility for others, while the concept of liberty expresses
the idea of responsibility for oneself. There can be a tension
between these two responsibilities, and I think it is fair to say that
i f we take communism at its best i t emphasizes fraternity. while
the traditional western notion of liberal democracy emphasizes
liberty. This, however, is treating communism as based on ethical
principles. an interpretation which would be rejected by orthodox
Marxism, which distinguishes itself from what it calls 'utopian
soci alism'
Wi thi n the western conception of democracy, we may say that
democratic socialism emphasizes equality and fraterni ty, and is
apt to lay less stress nn liberty than do liberalism and conserva-
Cf. Friedrich Engels. Soc"Jam: Utpillll (lilt! Scieniic.
.
tism. Modern democratic socialism also shares with communism
a doctrine of economic organizati on. It accepts the Marxist thesis
that the way to reach social improvement i s to abolish certain (not
all) forms of private property; i t advocates public ownership of
the means of production, distribution, and exchange. How then
does i t differ from Marxist communism? The difference is that
modern democratic socialism shares the conviction of pre-Marxist
socialists or communists that political policy should be rooted in
ethical ideals, and especially i n a notion of social justice. Like
other democrats, socialists found political aims on ethical aims.
Marxist communism takes the view that a socialism of this charac
ter is useless. unrealistic, 'utopian'. Instead Marxist theory pur
ports to derive its political policies from a 'scienti fc' sociology; i t
tries t o found politics on science .
4,2 Democratic government
Abraham Lincoln i n his Gettysburg Address dcscribed democracy
as 'government of the people by the people for the people'. But
al l government is government of the people; and a benevolent
despotism. as much as a democracy, may be government for (Le.
in the interests of) the peopl e, though the political experience of
Europe, i f not perhaps always of Asia. leads one to doubt whether
a despotism can for long remain benevolent. The essential idea
of democratic government is government hy the people. Strictly
speaking, government by all the people should mean unani mous
decisions. But this, of course, is impossible i n political matters.
Democracy in practice has to mean followi ng the view of the
majonty. Perhaps Lincoln
's addition of 'for the people' means, as
i n Rousseau's theory of the general will, that the decisivc view,
which for practical purposes must be that of the majorit y. should
seek to serve the interests of all even though i t does not have the
agreement of all: otherwise there is the danger. so much feared
by de Tocqueville and John Stuart Mill, thai majority rule may
become majority tyranny.
Pure democracy, a system in which all citizens may join in
taking governmental decisions, is rarc. I t is i mpracticable except
in a very small polity. It was practised, more or less, in the city
state of Athens over a relatively short period. Decisions were
taken by the Assembly, memhership of which was open to all
m rroOlems OJ rOltClcal nwosopny
adult male citizens (but not to women or slaves or resident aliens).
Even in Athens many matters of detail had to be left to appointed
offcers, but these were, for a time, selected by lot, thus preserving
the idea that everybody was capable of doing the job and that
there was 'no damned merit i n it'. Important decisions were taken
by the Assembly as a whole.
In most democratic States, however, democracy has meant re
presentative government. The ordinary citizen comes into the pro
cess only by casting a vote in favour of a representative or of the
broad policy of a party. Decision on concrete issues i s left to the
body of elected representatives, the Legislature, or to a smaller
group, the Government or 'Executive', acting with the consent of
the Legislature. So what we have in practice is oligarchy, govern
ment by a few, but an oligarchy elected by the people as a whole
and responsible to the people as a whole, responsible i n the sense
that it can be turned out at the next election and replaced by a
differenl group of rulers. Vesliges of pure democratic procedure
are found in some Stales where a popular referendum is held on
cerlain basic issues. bul generally speaking democracy in the
modern world means representative government, the democratic
element consisting in popular election and the possibilily of
dismissal.
The original idea of a representative was of a person elected to
express or refect (10 re-present) the views of his constituents. BUI
this i s not practicable either, for i t would require t he representa
tive to gather together a meeting of his constituents and ascerlain
the majority view among them before he voted on any issue in
the legislative assembly. Every issue would need to be voted on
twice. frst at the various constituency meetings, where debate on
i l would take place, and then secondly at the legislative assembly,
where the representatives would simply act as rubber stamps rec
ording the majority decisions of their electorates. This is what now
happens at the election of an American President. though it was
not the original intention of those who drafted the Constitution.
A voter i n the American Presidential election i s really casting his
vote i n favour of one of the candidates for the Presidency, but
formally he votes in favour of a candidate for the Electoral Col
lege. Te Electoral College Ihen meets to elect the President, but
this is simply a process of rubber stamping, since the Democratic
and Repuhlican memhcrs nr thc Electoral College arc respcctively
pledged to vote for the Democratic or Republican candidate for
the Presidency, so that the popular election has already deter
mined the issue. Of course this means that there i s really no need
for the Electoral College; the popular election might as well be
formally, as it is in fact. a choice bctween the candidat for the
Presidency. On such a clear-cut issue, coming up fo
:
deCISion
.
nce
in every four years, there i s usually no diffculty ' ascertammg
the voice of the people. But i t would obviously be Imposslble to
refer every concrete issue of policy to the votes of constltucncles
throughout a country. The idea therefore arose that the represent
ative was chosen. not as a mirror of electoral oplmon t o hI S
constituency, but as a man of good judgement who could be
trusted to make up his own mind conscientiously; he was not to
be a postman for the majority of ordinary citiz

ns i n his constitu
ency, but a reasonable example of how the ordmary cl ll zen wo
.
uld
(or should) decide on a disputed question. The case for tillS VICW
is put most strongly i n a speech of Edmund Burke to the electors
of Bristol in 1774. Burke drew a distinction between a 'represent
ative' and a 'delegat e' . As he used the words. a delegate merely
mi rrors and records the views of his constituents. whi le a represent
alive is elected to judge according to his own conscience. (The
members of the Electoral Collcge in the United States were orig
inally intended to be representatives in this sense, but have come
to act simply as delegates. )
.
Now if the members of a legislature arc representatives m
Burke's sense of the tcrm. thcrc will be no fxed body of majority
opinion. On onc issue A will vote with B. and o another issue
he will vote against B. just because they are different people
with differing experiences and t herefore differing
,
views. In thee
circumstances t he Government. the body uf polley-makers, will
have no guarantee of a majority in the legislative assembly for
all, or even most. of ils proposals. I t will be a weak, unstable
Goverment. On the other hand. n well-disci plined party system
makes for a strong, relatively stable Govermcnt. The growth of
the party system has meant the decline of Burke's idea of the
representative. A member of a legislative assembly who I S elected
on a party ticket is neither a delegate, acting as a rubber stamp for
his constituents. nor a representative in Burke's sense, cxcrclsll1g
individual judgement on all issues. To a considerable extent at
least. he is simply a yes-man for his party. A nearly always votes
9() Problem.l" of Political Philosophy
with S, Tweedledum with Tweedledee. Occasionally the Members
of Parliament i n Britain are allowed a 'free vote' on a major issue
where the division of opinion cuts across party lines, but the
frequency of the occasions seems to be dwindling. The situation
of voting according to party is accepted because it makes for more
effcient government. But i t seems that a large minority, both of
elected representatives and of electors (indeed the minority party
may have received a majority of the total of votes in the country
as a whole, though not a majority of seats), will fnd their opinion
pretty constantly outvoted by the party in power, so that their
views seem to count for nothing i n the actual decisions of
government.
The traditional defence of democratic government tells us that
the opinion of the minority does have some effect. The function
of the minority in the legislative assembly, it is said, i s to voice
their opposition, to criticize, to show the possibility of an alterna
tive policy, so that the dominant opinion should be required to
produce a reasoned case for its alleged superiority to the minority
view. An essential feature of democratic government, the argu
ment proceeds, is that it i s government through discussion, by
persuasion instead of by force. When the discussion has gone as
far as it usefully can, and some are still unpersuaded. a vote is
taken and the majority decision followed, again instead of resort
ing to force: 'we count heads instead of breaking them'_ Voting
is, i n a sense, a confession of relative failure, the ideal being to
reach unanimous agreement, but since that i s unattainable the
second best course is to follow the majority view.
This picture of parliamentary debate as a genuine attempt to
pcrsuade would be all very well i f the participants really were
representatives in Burke's sense. It does apply, in the British
Parliament, to debates i n which there is a free vote and to some
of t he discussions of details of Bills at the Committee stage. But
where there is a strong party system, the broad pattern of voting
on any major issue is a foregone conclusion. In the British system
of government , the real decisions on major issues are taken by the
Cabinet , not by the majority of elected members of the legislative
assembly. Sti l l , opinion within the majority party, at least, has
its efect on Goverment policy. The effective criticism is not
ncccs""'ily that which takes place in public at the open dcbates
of the legiSlative assembly, though this does count for something
vemocr(/cy U l
despite the fact that the critics within the dominant party usually
end up by voting for the Govermcnt. In a democratic system of
government there is always the possibility of revolt within the
dominant party, and (to take Britain again as an example) the
Cabinet has to carry with i t most of the back-bench MPs of its
own party i n the discussions that take place off the foor of the
House of Commons. The leaders of a party can exercise a good
deal of control. but it is by no means absolute. I n March 1 967.
the Prime Minister, Mr Harold Wilson, tried to threaten Labour
MPs who abstained from supporting the Goverment i n a vote
on an important issue of foreign policy. 'Every dog is allowed one
bark,' Mr Wilson told them, 'but i f he barks too often he won-t
get his licence renewed'; a remark which provoked the riposte:
'The Prime Minister does not license us, we license hi m. ' The
mere fact that MPs can and sometimes do abstain from voting for
the party line , even if they rarely vote against it nowadays. shows
that a Government can go too far i n treating its back-benchers as
lobby-fodder.
Yet although a Government has to take account of opinion
within its own party. it need not take much notice of the views
of other parties i n its dayto-day business. Criticism of Govern
ment policy by a party in opposition is not made with any expec
tation of persuading the Government t o mend its ways, but rather
in the hope of persuading the public to make a different choice
at the next election. The Opposition takes the opportunity at
every important debate of Showing where it stands and what i t
would try t o do i f it were i n power. Parliamentary elections are
not won and lost in the brief period of the electoral campaign,
but over the life of a Parliament between one election and
another; and whi l e the loss of popular support for a Government
is due to its Own mistakes or bad luck or the sheer feeling that i t
i s time for a change. rather than to the criticism of Government
policy by the Opposi tion, nevertheless that criticism does help to
focus the shift of public opinion and to give it concrete shape. I t
i s still fair t o say, therefore. that discussion i s an essential part of
the democratic process.
The various devices of democratic government - decisions by
majority vote: periodical popular elections. with the possibility
of throwing out the group now in power: regular meeti ngs of
representatives, with continual tIiscussion and criticism. the voic-
_---
'Z Problems oJ rOllllcal /tluosopny
ing of grievances and alternative lines of policy - al l these devices
are intended to prevent governmental action from restricting lib
erty more than i t need. They give opportunities to those who do
not gover to say what they would like to be done. It is recognized
that government must be carried on by a small group, to whom
considerable authority is entrusted. But it i s also recognized that
the wielder of authority is always liable to suppose that he knows
best what is good for the people, or even what the people want;
he is apt to suppose that they must want what he thinks will be
best for them. The devices of democratic government act as checks
on this tendency; they ensure reference back to the people or
their representatives at frequent intervals.
A further device, not necessarily 'democratic' i n form but simi
larly serving the democratic aim of checking authority and protect
ing liberty, i s the so-called separation of powers. Government
works by law. This entails the making of laws, the application and
enforcement of the laws, and at times the interpretation of the
law. We may therefore speak of three functions i n connection
with the exercise of governmental power: the legislative function,
the executive function. and the judicial function. (I) LegiSlative
function: some body of persons must be authorized to make new
laws and revise or repeal old ones, to declare what the law shall
be. (2) Executive function: some body of persons must be author
ized to give effect to the laws and to their enforcement. Offcials
( i n the civil service or in local government) must be authorized
to tell individual citizens that a particular law applies to them in
such and such a way. e. g. to sent out income-tax return and
assessment forms. to put up 'No Parking' notices, and so forth.
Other offcials (the police) must be authorized to warn and arrest
t hose who app(' ar h) han' broken t he l aw. Others again (i n t he
penal services) must be authorized to carry out the penalties
prescribed for lawbreaking. ( 3) JudiCIal functi on: some body of
persons must bc authorized to interpret the law. to decide whether
or not someone uccuseu of a crime or a civil wrong has Or has
not broken the law. and to decide also. i n disputes between citi
zens (or between a citizen and a branch of the Executive), whose
clai m shal l be hel d to be legally valid. These three functions can
of course all be carried out by one and the same body of persons.
I n a monarchy properly so called, the Ki ng has authority t o do
al ! I hcSl I hi ngs: :lnd in a 'const i tutional monarchy' . such as wc
have in Britain. the forms of the older situation are sti l l preserved.
as when the last act in the process of legislation is called 'the
Royal Assent'; the Executive acts in the name of ' the Crown' ;
and the judges are said t o reprc!ent ' the Queen's justice'. I n
democratic constitutions. however. there is a certain degree of
separation of these functions. which are allotted to different auth
orities relatively independent of each other.
In the eighteenth century. when the liberty enjoyed in Britain
was much admired and envied on the Continent. the French theor
ist Montesquieu put forward the doctrine of 'the separation of
powers' . i . e. of the three 'powers' or authori ti es. legislative.
executive. and judicial. Montesquieu's thesis was that such a sep
aration was the best guarantee of liberty for the subject. and he
argued that the relatively high degree of liberty i n Bri tai n was
due to the fact that the three powers were there kept separate
from each other. The British COIl!titution was a system of checks
and balances, i n which each of the t hree powers had its allotted
place and could prevent either of the others from going beyond
its proper role. Montesquieu concluded that a separation of
powers ought to be practised in any State seeki ng a maximum of
liberty. The inl1ucncc of his theory is to be seen especially in the
Constitution of the Uni ted States. where there is a clear separation
of powers together with a systcrn of checks and balances. In
Britain there i s not at the present t i me a separation of all three
powers, anti there is some dispute whether Montesquieu was right
in believing that the Legislature and the Executive i n the Britain of
his time were effectively separate authorities. What MOl1tesquieu
regarded as most important. however. was that the Judiciary
should be independent of the other two powers. and there is no
doubt I l wl thi s hnth was then al ld is now t rue of the Iritish
Constitution. Today at least. what cvcr the pusi t i on may havc been
i n the eighteenth century, the men at the top of the Executive.
the Goverment. arc not only I1lcrhers of the Legi sluture but
nmtro\ it. Pari i amcnt has only a moderate degree of independence
from the Cabi net. But the Judic
'
iary really does act independently
from Parli ament and Executive al i ke. The fact t hat some of the
j udges <lrc members of the House of Lords i s not si gnifcant. \'hen
the;' t ake part in dcbates. c. g. on law reform. they re<lk with
complete independence: and or course when they sit in their
[udicial capacity. Ihe pronouncelllent s of t he House of Lords as
94 Problems of Political Philosophy
the highest court of appeal have nothing at all to do with the
proceedings of the House of Lords as the second chamber of the
Legislature. A more signifcant fact i s that judicial decisions quite
often have the effect of revising and not only of i nterpreting the
law. Law is made by j udges as well as by Parliament. But the
law-making activities of Legislature-cum-Executive in the feld of
statutes and statutory instruments on the one hand, and of the
Judiciary i n the feld of common law on the other, are kept
separate from and independent of each other. What is most
important of all is the independence of the Judiciary vis-a-vis the
Executive i n interpreting the law as i t is applied by civil servants
to individual citizens. This has undoubtedly been a bulwark for
preserving the liberty of the subject against the excessive exercise
of power by the Executive.
To some extent Members of Parliament perfonn a similar func
tion in certain activities in which they remain representatives i n
Burke's sense and are not restrained by party allegiance. I am
thi nki ng chiefy of Parliamentary Questions and Debates on the
Adjournmcnt. ' When thcse concern general issues of Government
policy. the Minister who replies will usually give no ground; the
situation di ffers little from a debate on a Bi l l or on a motion
sponsored by an offcial Government or Opposition spokesman.
But when they concern grievances of private citizens, there is
some room for probing criticism that may have an effect on the
decisions of senior civil servants, at least for the future if not for
the case under discussion. The Parliamentary Question, followed
up by a shrewd supplementary question, can be particularly effec
tive at times, since the Minister may be made to look foolish on
the foor of the House, and no senior civil servant, let alone the
Minister himself. is content to let that happen without a blush.
But as the Execlltive. both Cabinet and civil service, grO\vs
Readers whD are unfamiliar with British parliamentary practice may wish tn
know what these two things fire. Pflrliamentary Questions are questions put 10
Ministers. with advance notice. bv Members of Parliament and are answered al
Ouest i on Time. often the li\'e!ie1 pari of the day's business in Ihe House of
Commons. Debates on the Adjournment take place during the las I half-hour tlf
the day's business in the Commons and may be initiated by any MP. unlike most
of the other debates, which are arranged offCially on behalf of the Government
or of
.
lhe Opposition Front Bellch. Eflch of the two procedures Hffords opportunity
for ad hoc criticism of govcmmentnl administration, but i n an Adjournment
Debate both the criticism and the reply can of course be developed at greater
length than at Question Time.
I
f
I
I
I
i
I
l
,
f
1
}
inevitably more powerful wi th the increasing scope and complexity
of governmental action i n a moder society, it ecomes mor
.
e
.
a
,
nd
more diffcult for the ordinary Member of Parhament to CrItICIze
effectively the details of administration as it applies to individual
citizens. He 'does not have all the necessary information, and he
fnds i t harder to wheedle this out of Mi nisters or to make them
change their tune. That is why Britain i n 1966 took a leaf out of
the book of some other democratic constitutions by instituting the
Ombudsman or Parliamentary Commissioner for Administration.
The Ombudsman in Scandinavian countries performs the same
sort of role as the British Member of Parliament in the Parliamen
tary Question or the Debate on the Adjournment: but the
Ombudsman has the advantage of being authorized to call for the
relevant departmental fles and to interview the civil servnnts
.
who
have been concerned. The powers of the Ombudsman conSl l tute
an additional device to protect the liberty of the subject from the
excessive or inequitable exercise of authority by the Executive.
I said in 4. 1 that liberty and equality are the distinguishing
principles of democracy. Most of the proedures or
.
institutions
which I have described in the present section. as being speCially
characteristic of democratic forms of government, are intended to
promote the principle of liberty in particular. The principle of
equality fnds expression in the general idea of govrment by
all the people. which in practice does not mean partlclpatJn If)
government proper but participation in the process of electll1g a
Government. The opportunity In take part is given to every adult
citizen equally: one man, one vote: and one vote, one value.
4. 3 Democracy in international sodety
I said in 4. 1 that the democratic principles of liberty and e4uality
do not apply solely to the organization of the State, and this is
true likewise of the democratic procedures that give expression
to the principles. Both the ideas and the procedures of democracy
are applied to communities and associations other than t he State
and to the relations between Sl al cs. Democratic notions appear
especially i n the legal aspects of international relations. ' Demo
cratic ideals' in the relations between States owe somethlllg to the
analogy of democracy within the State itself, and something to
analogy from non-political communi l i es, notably the family.
3 UUfCM OJ 1OMM1U TIUIVOVJHly
The idea of an international society of States is at times
described by the phrase 'the family of nations' (where 'nations'
mens States). As i n the language of religion, which speaks of
the fatherhood' of God and the 'brotherhood' of man, a metaphor
drawn from the most close-kni t form of human community is felt
to be best ftted to express the notion of a universal soci ety. To
l arge extent
;
of course, this metaphor depicts an aspiration or
Ideal of the fnendly relations that ought to exist, not an account
?f the actual relations that do exist. Apart from the question of
Ideals, however, the notion of a family does imply something
about facts, namely a common outlook and common traditions.
Earlier international societies have not been world societies but
they could often be called a family of States in this sense. Thc
Greek city-states, for example, despite frequent wars, formed an
mternational society with a common language, common tra
ditions, and s

1me common religious practices such as a respect


for the Delphic oracle and participation in the Olympic Games.
Although they never formed any stable federation, they dis
lOgulshcd tcmsclvcs as Greeks from 'barbarians' (which meant,
the frst Instance, people who spoke a foreign language). In
some degree thi s affected thei r behaviour. For example, they were
prepared to make slaves of conquered barbarians but not, usually,
of conquered Greeks. Similarly the world of medieval Christen
dom was an international society with a common religion and
a common legal system (derived from Roman Law). Modern
international society has developed from the medieval one, with
the tradition of natural law providing a foundation for i nter
national law. This means that modern international society follows
the traditions and structure of European society. Now the coun
tnes of Europe can be called a 'family' of nations or States pre
c.sely because they share a common tradition, primarily that of
international law. Other States which have entered this inter
national system have had to accept the European tradition. Oftcn
this has been no hardship. for the former colonies of European
countries have legal systems which are themselves founded on thc
legal systems of the colonizing States. Thus the United States of
America and all the countries of the Commonwealth have legal
sysfems based on English Law, while the former French colonies
have systems based on French Law. and so on. In some instances,
however. States have had to adapt themselves to the European
I
I
I
tradition. China and Japan. for example. are not i n any sense
members of the original European family.
The European tradition explains why the international society
of States includes certain democratic procedures. and why these
procedures arc accepted by non-democratic countries, One exam
ple of democratic procedure arises from the doctrine of the sover
eign equality of States. In international law all sovereign States
are treated as equal, regardless of size or power. Following from
this, each member State of the Uni ted Nations Organization has
one vote in the General Assembly. and the view of a majority of
States i n any vote taken in the Assembly is held to be the view
of the Assembly as a whole. In some ways this is a misleading
practice, but it is accepted by all States as being 'democmtic' and
is built into the structure of interational society.
I have said that international law arose from the medieval Euro
pean tradition of natural law. There is a di fference . however,
between the medieval international society and the modern one.
The world of Roman Christendom i n the Middle Ages was not a
single State. but neither was it a collection of sovereign States in
the modern sense of the term. Up to the ti me of the Reformation,
the secular ruler of a European country did not possess sovereign
(i . e. supreme) authority; he was subject to the superior authority
of the international Church. When the national State arose as a
sovereign autonomous uni t, it was recognized that there still was
and must be some form of loose associ ation between States, and
this was represented by thei r common acceptance of international
law.
In the thought of political phik)sophers of the seventeenth cen
tury, like Hobbes and Locke . the notion of natural law. or a law
of nature. was connected with the notion of a 'state of nature'
that preceded civil society and the positive law of civil society.
Consequently Emerich de Vauel . an international jurist of the
eighteenth century_ put forward the i dea that Statcs. whose
relations with each other are regulated by something like natural
law and not by an i mposed and enforceable positive law, are in
a state of nalure. And because thc earlier theorists had spoken
of individuals in a state of nature as being free (or independent)
and equal. Vattel thought thc same must be true of States. States
are independent. and must be regarded as equal.
The transfer of the concepts of liberty and equal ity to inter-
98 Problems of Political Philosophy
national law from the ideas of political philosophers about individ
ual persons, indicates that the interational society of States is
conceived as analogous to a society of individuals. States are
considered, in a sense, as persons. This doctrine has advantages,
though it also has dangers. The dangers are familiar to students
of the history of political theory, but I think that in legal theory
they are slight. Some pOlitical philosophers who have thought of
the State in terms of an organism have reached the conclusion
that the State is an end to which its individual members are means;
and so they havc regarded the State as a real super-person. But
when one says that States are considered i n interational l aw as
(legal) persons, this emphatically does not mean that they are
considered to be real persons. States are purely legal entities; one
can even say they are fctions. Lawyers know how to get along
with convenient fctions, and are not misled by them. A corpor
ation, for example, can be regarded i n law as a person, i , e. as a
subject of legal rights and obligations (which can themselves be
regarded as fctions if compared with physical powers and bonds);
but no lawyer is thereby misled into thinking of a corporation as
a real super-person, existing alongside the natural persons who
act as the offcers of the corporation. Similarly the notion of a
State as a person in international law simply means that the State
is a subject of rights and obligations - the State, as contrasted
with the nation, or with the individual who is the Head of the
State, though of course certain individuals, such as the Secretary
of State (or Minister) responsible for Foreign Affairs, act in the
name of the State when exercising the rights or fulflling the
obligations.
The advantages of the concept of States as persons are that this
concept helps to ensure stability. Governments come and go, but
i f the State, and not a particular Government or a particular Head
of State, is regarded as the subject of rights and obligations, then
successive Governments inherit the position of their predecessors.
It is less eas), for a new Government to repudiate obligations
undertaken by its predecessor; and likewise it is not legitimate
for a foreign Government to say, 'We made a treaty with your
predecessor, not with you, and so you have no rights under i t . '
The usefulness of the notion of conti nui ty, however, does not
itself require that the analogy between States and persons should
be extended to include the ideas of liberty and equality. In matters


I
t
!
r
i
I
!
Vemocrac), '
other than sovereignty (i , e. supreme legal authority) States are
neither free nor equal. Even a Great -Power does not have com
plete freedom of political action unless it controls a world crnpire.
and the freedom of other States is more obviously limited by the
policies of powerful neighbours. States arc plainly unequal in
military or economic strength and consequently i n political i nflu
ence and freedom of action. But then individuals too arc unequal
in their abilities and consequently i n some aspects of freedom of
action. The question is whether there is good reason to ascribe to
States a right i n international law II a certain kind of indepen
dence and equality. as there is presumed, in a democratic State,
to be good reason to ascribe to individuals a legal right t o certain
kinds of freedom and equality.
So far as independence is concerned, I think there is good
reason so tong as we do not have a form of international organiz
ation that can properly be called World Government. The settle
ment of disputes by legal procedures rather than by force requires
that there should be supreme Iogal authorities. Any movement
towards strengthening the authority of international law and inter
national courts as being superior to the authority of national law
and national courts is obviously to be welcomed. But i n the pre
sent condition of international society the doctrine of State sover
eignty is needed to preserve a measure of respect for law and
order, based on some principles of justice. and to make less
frequent the resort by powerful States to force and the threat of
force.
What of equality? Thc concept of States as legal persons of
course implies equality before the law. That is to say. an i nter
natIOnal court. adjudicating on a dispute between two States must
treat them impartially and pay no regard to their unequal status
in power or anything else, just as a court adjudicating on a dispute
between individuals must be impartial and pay no regard to their
unequal status in wealth or anything else. A right to equality
before the law is built into the conceptions of natural justice
under which the law operates, I n addition to this, the concept
of sovereignty implics equality of freedom or independence, A
sovereign State is legally free o independent i n the sense that i t
is not subject t o a superior authority except i n so far as limitations
are placed 011 sovereignty by international law. Now i f different
States had different degrces of this freedom. it would mean ei ther
10 Problems of Political Philosophy
that some States were partially subject to the authority of others
and so were not sovereign, or that they were not impartially
treated by international law. A State can of course give up its
sovereignty by agreeing to become a constituent member of a
federal union and transferring to the federal power some parts of
its sovereign authority, e.g. in exteral relations, It then ceases
to be a sovereign State in international law. The legal freedom of
sovereign States must be an equal freedom.
The sovereign equality of States is a legal concept, which fts
well enough into juridical questions that may arise under inter
national law. What is more dubious is its use for purposes in
which political power is bound to count for more than legal status.
L. F. L. Oppenheim, i n his standard textbook on Interational
Law,' writes of four important consequences of the equality of
States in international law. They are: (1) In questions that have
to be settled by consent, every State has a right to a vote and
only to one vote. (2) ' Legally - although not politically - the vote
of the weakest and smallest State has . . . as much weight as the
vote of thc largest and most powerful . ' (3) No State can claim
jurisdiction over another. (4) The courts of one State do not
normally question the validity of the legal acts of another State.
The third and fourth of these principles i n fact relate more to the
independence of States. i . e. to sovereignty itself, than to their
presumed equality. (Oppenheim himself partly recognizes this
when he describes the fourth principle as a 'consequence of equal
ity -or i ndependence - of States'.) The frst and second, however,
are i mplications of equality and are direct analogues of democratic
voting procedures: 'one State, one vote' (like 'one man, one
vote') and 'one vote, one value', According to Oppenheim. these
principles can be qualifed by agreement, and i n the case of the
vital second principle he explicitly distinguishes between the legal
and the political weight of Yotes.
In the political institutions of the United Nations Organization.
the doctrine of the equality of States i s accepted for membership
of. and voting in, the General Assembly. but not for the Security
Council. The General Assembly follows the democratic principles
of 'one State. one vote' and 'one vote, one value'. The Security
Council. however, tries to make proper allowance for the special
, Rth cd. ( London. 1955). edittu hy H. Lauterpacht, vol. i, 1 15.
J
i
i
I
position of the Great Powers, or at any rate for those States that
were leading powers at the ti me when UNO was set up. The
constitution of the Security Council gives expression to the real
political facts, namely, that leading powers have always had, and
are bound to have. more of a sal' in the conduct of international
affairs than smaller powers have. Consequently, the rules for
voting in the General Assembly are misleading i n hiding the inevi
table facts about decision-making. and are liable to bring inter
national organization into disrepute. Because of the facts of inter
national affairs. a majority vote in the UN Assembly does not
bind those who arc outvoted, as does a majority vote in a national
parliament. The resolutions of the UN Assembly constitute re
commendations only. Nevertheless it would not be true to say that
the democratic procedures of the Assembly are simply a sham.
concealing the realities of power. Although the vote results only
i n a recommendation, a heavy vole in the UN Assemb!y against
a powerful State (as i n 1956 against the Soviet Union's inter
vention i n Hungary, and against the action of Britain and France
in the Suez operation) does on occasion have some infuence on
the policy of that State. One should not exaggerate the limited
infuence that it has. The Soviet invasion of Czechoslovakia in
1968 suggests that memories of 156 did not greatly a[fect the
decision of the- Soviet Government twelve years later. Still,
majority opinion can to a small extent act as a check against the
reliance on power alone. The position is not altogether dif[erent
from the effect of opinion in a national assembly. There, under
a democratic system. the vote is formally decisive, but with the
modern party system a Government can usually rely on receiving
a majority vote; the effective decision is taken by the Goverment
itself before the debate i n the legislative assembly. A strong body
of dissident opinion in the assembly. whether expressed openly i n
debate or i nformally at a meeting of back-benchers, will usually
not cause the Government to alter the decision already taken: but
i t will have some inlluence on future policy. Of course there is a
vital di fference between the usc p[ democratic procedures at the
national and at the internationul \CvCL in that a bui!dup of
majority opinion against a Goverment in a democratic Slate can
unseat that Government at the next election. while in interational
affairs a Great Power remains a top dog despite adverse world
?- .
102 Problems of Political Philosophy
opinion. Bearing all these qualifcations i n mi nd, world opinion i s
not without some effect.
Still, the presumed equality of States is not a very satisfactory
way of gauging world opinion. A State with 100 million inhabitants
has one vote, and a State with 10 million inhabitants has one vote.
H ten States, each having a population of 10 million, outvote a
single State having a population of 100 million, the vote is 10 to
I but the populations represented on the two sides are equal. The
situation in the UN Assembly became even more ridiculous when
membership was extended to a number of newly independent
countries with tiny populations. For example, Grenada and Sao
Tome e Principe, which became independent States in 1975, have
populations of 1 1 2,000 and 1 18,000 respectively; and St Christo
pher-Nevis, which became independent in 1983, has a population
of 45,000. The principle of one vote for each State gives each of
these the same voting power in the UN Assembly as China with its
population of 1 ,072 million. So when countries that were formerly
subject to colonial rule vote together on a resolution, the result
refects a general sentiment conditioned by similar historical
experience. but the actual number of the votes has no real sig
nincance.
It is not easy, however, to fnd a more satisfactory alterative
to the principle of 'one State, one vote'. I have spoken as i f world
opinion would be best gauged i n terms of world population. At
frst sight this seems sensible, because the principle of 'one State,
one vote' is formed on the analogy of the democratic principle of
'one man, one vote'. Now i f we were to drop the analogy between
a man and a State, and instead were to carry the original principle
of 'one man. one vote' into international affairs, we should have
to give States voting strength in proportion to thei r populations.
Suppose we were to allot one vote for every group of to million
peopl e. Then (taking the latest population fgures. from census
feturns or estimate:;, available i n 1989) the Uni ted Kingdom, wilh
57 million inhabitants. would have six votes: the United States.
with 239 million people, would have 24 votes; the Soviet Union,
with 284 million, would have 28 votes; India, with 748 million.
would have 75 votes; and China, with I ,on million people, would
have 107 votes. Would we be prepared to stomach this? If not.
why not' The reason is not simply because we disagree with the
communist doctrines of China. We should be uneasy also about
f
!
I
r
\
LemOCfac), lUj
granting 75 votes to India, even though we preferred the demo
cratic regime of Indi a to the communism of China. We should be
be uneasy because we should feel that most of the 1 ,072 million
Chinese or the 748 million Indians are not i n a position to express
an opinion on world issues, while on the other hand quite a large
number of the 57 million Britons or the 239 million Americans
are i n such a position. World opinion cannot be gauged in terms
of world poplilatioll.
I f we accept this line of argument. we arc presupposing the
idea, commonly thought to have been abandoned by modern
democrats. that a person is entitled to a vote only if he or she has
a reasonable measure of knowledge and education. In other
words. our idea of democracy in the international sphere is One
of a limited or qualifed democracy. Perhaps this is a sOllnd view
i n the national sphere also. I imagine that British democrats would
not be so ready to give a vote to all adult British citizens if Britain
had not had f reasonable system of universal education i n force
for some time. This prompts the refection that we shollid not
expect a country like China to practise democracy until the
Chinese have had a reasonable system of universal educHt i on i n
operation for some time.
At any rate we can sec that the transrer of democratic insti
tutions to the international society of Statcs is not a simple matter.
The concept of 'one State. one vote'. while manifestly unreal and
illogical. flls a gap i n the meantime. but onc cannot expect i t to
command much respect . So far as " oting goes, the supposedly
democratic procedure of the UN Assembly is a bit of a sham. But
not so far as disClIssion goes. Democratic procedure means not
only decision by majority vote but also decision after discussion.
In the UN Assembly. as in a national parliament . sensible opinion
and criticism can make themselves felt. irrespective of the num
bers of votes that they can command. Dcmot:Tacy is a matter of
liberty as well as equality. and liberty includes the freedom to
express nne's npininns and nne's criticisms of those who have the
whip-hand.
4.4 Human rights
Another important feature of democratic thought that has spread
from the European tradition into international affairs i s the Con-
cept of human rights. The present form of this concept is relatively
recent, dating from the end of the Second World War, but in
principle i t is a revival and extension of ideas associated with
natural law i n the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries under the
name of 'natural rights' and then ' the rights of man'. In some
European l anguages human rights are still called the rights of man
(the meaning i s, and always was, the same), but they have turned
into 'human rights' for English-speaking countries to avoid an
alleged misunderstanding. The appalling excesses of the Nazi
regime i n Germany before and during the Second World War led
to a proposal for an international bill of rights, and a United
Nations commission was set up to examine this. According to the
chairman of the commission, Mrs Eleanor Roosevel t , at an early
stage of the proceedings the delegate from one benighted country
said he trusted that suggestions about the rights of man meant
what they said, since his government could, of course, not agree
to extent these rights to women. Whether or not he was speaking
with his tongue i n his cheek, Mrs Roosevelt promptly got the
commission to replace 'the rights of man' by 'human rights'.
A Universal Dcdaration of Human Rights was adopted by the
General Assembly of the United Nations Organization i n 1948.
It was followed by proposed covenants or conventions designed
to give it practical effect. They have included both universal and
regional conventions, and the one that has made most headway
is the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights
and Fundamental Freedoms, adopted by member States of the
Council of Europe i n 1950 and actively operated under the juris
diction of a European Court of Human Rights. This particular
convention has made solid progress because it is confned to the
kind of constitutional rights that were familiar from the European
tradition of natural rights and that could plainly be given legal
protection. A regional convention for Latin America does not
seem to have achieved anything much. On the other hand. a
different kind of treaty, the Hclsinki Final Act of 1975, has had
a greater impact on respect for human rights than might have
been expected. It was agreed and signed by thi rty-fve States,
comprising all but one (Albania) of the countries of east and west
Europe together with the USA and Canada. I t is concerned in the
frst instance with security and co-oper.ation, but i t also includes a
section on human rights, emphasizing freedom of thought, con-

i
!
t
I
i
;
science, and religion (the emphasis was extended to freedom of
movement in a subsequent agreement). The Act empowers any
participating State to complain of breaches of human rights by
any other such State. Consequential agreements at later meetings,
notably the Vienna Concluding Document of 1989, have prOVided
for monitoring mechanisms to back up the complaints. The Hel
sinki Act has also strengthened the hand of dissidents in the Soviet
Union and other communist countries when protesting against the
abuse of human rights.
Philosophical analysis can usefully address two related questions
about human rights. First, what is meant by a natural or human
right as contrasted with other sorts of right? And second, was it
sound and sensible to extend the scope of thc Uni versal Dcclar
ation of Human Rights beyond the scope of the infuential declar
ations of the eighteenth century sU!. h as the American Declaration
of Independence and the French Declaration of the Rights of Man
and the Citizen?
To answer the frst question, we need to begin with the general
notion of a right. This comes from the law and was extcnded to
ethics by analogy. Legal senses of the noun 'a right' were usefully
classifed by an American jurist. W. N. Hohfcld, into four categor
ies. Only two of these, I thi nk. arc normally found in the non
legal use of the term. One is the idea of having a right to do
something, and the other is the idea of having a right to receive
something.
Having a right to do something means the same as not having
any obligation to refrain from doing i t ; one is free to do i t . one
nlay do it, there is nothing wrong i n doing i t . Having a right to
receive umething is also called a right against someone else, who
has an obligation to provide that to which thc frst person is said
to have a right. Thus if Joncs has a right to the 5 that Robinson
owes hi m, i t is a right to receive 5, i t is a right against Robinson,
and it corresponds to Robinson's obligation to pay up. In this
sense of the noun 'right'. a right is a claim to something due.
Clearly, the two senses of 'having a right' arc quite different. The
frst is an absence of obligation (>n the part of the person having
the right, while the second implies the presence of an obligation
on the part of someone else.
In giving names to the legal originals of these two kinds of a
right, Hohfeld called the first a liberty and the second a claim.
1\L "roD/ems OJ rOil/teal rnaosophy
He called the frst a liberty because i t is a freedom from obligation,
but since there are other kinds of freedom, too, we can avoid
confusion by speaking of a 'liberty-right' and contrasting this with
a 'claim-right'. Before I knew anything of Hohfeld's analysis of
the legal senses, I used to distinguish the two non-legal senses of
'a right' by calling the frst a right of action (because it is a right
to do something) and the second a right of recipience (because it
is a right to receive something), An advantage of my usage is that
it avoids the risk of confusing ' a liberty' (or 'liberty-right') with a
claim-right to liberty. The frst is called a liberty because it is a
freedom from obligation, a legal or moral freedom to do what
you want to do. The second is one kind of claim-right, a claim
against someone else to be left freet that is to say, a claim that
he i s obliged to leave you alone.
Natural or human rights are a species of claim-rights or rights
of recipicnce. They were called 'natural' because, like natural law,
they do not depend on man-made law. Medieval phi losophers
who described the general principles of ethics as natural law
undcrstood it to be law laid down by God, and the thinkers of
the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries took the same view when
they said that natural law implies natural rights, with which men
were endowed by their Creator. The idea was that natural law
imposes a number of duties on all human beings towards all other
human beings, and some of those dUlies have rights corresponding
to them, The duty not to kill other people, for example, implies
a right of those other people not t o be killed. Natural rights do
not include all moral rights. Some moral duties and rights depend
on particular circumstances. such as the special relationship
between members of a family or between friends. Natural or
human rights depend simply on the fact of being human and so
are held by all human beings against all other human beings; they
are universal moral rights. A further l i mi tation needs to be added.
Some uni versal moral rights are more fundamental than others_
For example, there is a universal moral right to be given truthful
(or at any rate non-deceitful) answers to questions, but this i s less
fundamental than universal rights not to be killed or enslaved.
The doctrine of natllral rights was crystall ized in documents (treat
ises ad declarations) that had a political ai m, to vindicate import
ant rights in the face of arbitrary rule. These documents therefore
concentrated on those universal moral rights that were regarded
,
I
i
I
l
,
Democracy I l l !
as basic and as liable t o abuse. They spoke of natural rights to
life and liberty, but not of a natural right to the truth.
I t is not essential to associate this doctri ne. or the idea of
natural l aw generally, wi th theological preconceptions, and that i s
probably why the phrase 'natural rights was succeeded by 'the
rights of man', which is non-committal about the theoretIcal
ground of the idea. 'Natural law' was simply :l way of descl bJ J1g
principles of morality. These pril1l'iples involve duties an

1 nghts.
as does positive law, and the adjec.tive 'natural' was used III order
to contrast moral principles and rights with artifcial or man-made
laws and rights. Some rights are plainly man-made , such as the
right of certain persons in Britain to nn old
-
age pension of a fxed
amount of money per week. The right would not exist i f the State
did not grant it. When it is said that the right to life or the right
to libertv is a natural right. this means that it does not depend on
man-made laws but is a right irrespective of whether the State or
any other organization guarantees it. However, the point of issu
ing a declaration of natural or human rights is to try to get thesc
rights guaranteed i n some way. john Locke in the seventeenth
century and the authors of the American and French declarations
i n the eighteenth century argued that the primary purpose of
government was to protect natural rights or the rights of man,
The Universal Declaration of Human Rights had a si mi l ar aim
and hoped to achieve i t by spelling out i n detail what these rights
require i n the world of the twentieth century.
This brings us to the second question I mentioned earlier: was
it sound and sensible for the Universal Declaration to extend the
scope of human rights beyond that of the earlier formulations?
The earlier specifcation of natural or human rights was brief and
rathCf vague. Locke gave list of I hr<: .. ' natural rights. 1 0 life.
liberty, and estate (meaning by the last the right t o acquire prop
erty). The American Declaration of Independence followed hi m
but replaced 'estate' by ' the pursuit of happiness' ( no doubt
because property rights seem to be man-made and quite different
from the biologically basic conatus to go on living and to act as
one wishes). The French Declaration of the Rights of Man listed
'the natural and i mprescriptible rights of man' as liberty, property,
seeuritv, and resistance to opprcssi on, I t wcnt on to specify what
was i nolved in liberty, especially in relation to the role of law,
but the document remained brier. succinct. and confned to funda-
18 Problems of Political Philosophy
mentals. There is a di fferent favour in the English Bi l l of Rights
of 1 689 and the American Bi l l of Rights of 1791 (the latter being
the frst ten Amendments of the American Constitution). They
were much more specifc, being conditioned by the recent history
of the two peoples concerned; but precisely for that reason they
could not suitably be repeated in a document intended for all
States. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights tries to
embrace the virtues of both types of the earlier documents, com
bining the universally applicable rights of the American and
French Declarations with the more detailed character of the con
stitutional requirements of the English and American Bills of
Rights.
In this regard the Universal Declaration is on the whole SUCcess
ful. After suitable preliminaries, it begins with a universal right
'to life. liberty and security of person'. It then i mmediately goes
on to specify what this means in terms of legal protection: the
prohibition of slavery and likewise the prohibition of torture and
of 'cruel, inhuman or dcgrading forms of punishment' ; equal pro
tection of the law for all, with a clear statement of just legal
procedures (no arbitrary arrest or detention, impartial hearings
open to the public, presumption of i nnocence until proved guilty);
protection of privacy and reputation. Then there i s a frm assertion
of the right to freedom of movement, both within a State and in
leaving or returning to one's State. This i s followed by affrming
the right of everyone to a nationality (citizenship), the right to
marry, but only with free and full consent , the right to own
property, the right to freedom of thought , expression, and
association.
That brings us down to Article 20 of the Declaration. All the
rights listcd so far spell out the kind of thing that was meant by
the earlier doctrinc of natural rights. Article 21 adds political
principles that have the effect of making democratic government
a part of the doctrinc of human rights. I t says that everyonc has
the right to take part in the government of his country. either
directly or through freely elected representatives, and that 'the
will of t he people shali be the basis of the authority of govern
ment' , to be exprcssed in regular elections conducted with univer
sal suffrage and free voting procedures.
Al l these articles, constituting the frst two-thirds of the Univer
sal Declaration, are commonly said to specify 'civil and political
I
I
rights', about which there is no controversy. at least in liberal
democratic countries. There is controversy. however, about the
rights specifed i n six further articles and described i n Article 22
as 'economic, social and cultural rights'. Before discussing them,
I should like to comment on the term 'civil and political rights'
used as a name for the initial. non-controversial set of human
rights.
The adjective 'political' is clearly appropriate for the right to
participate i n government that is sct out in Article 21 . The preced
ing rights are not political and need a di fferent name. but the
adjective 'civil ' is not really appropriate since it suggests that these
rights arc concerned with cit izCIl!;hip. nnd that i s truC only of
Article 1 5, which says that everyone has 'the right to a nationality'
(citizenship). and one part of Article 1 3. which refers to freedom
of movement and which says in its second clause that 'everyone
has the right to leave any country, including his own. and to
retur to his country'. The right to return to 'his' country applies,
of course, only to a citizen of that country (though the earlier
part of thc clause explicitly includes the right of non-citizens. as
well as citizens, to leave a country). Apart from those two. all
the rights set out in Articles \ -20 arc not confned to citizens. I n
any civilized country t he protection of the law applies to evervone
who happens to be within the bounds of the jurisdiction, as does
the obligation to obey the law. Some rights apply only to citizens.
notably the right to participate i n goverment . induding the right
to vote so do some obligations. such as the obligati on. where
there is conscri ption. to serve in the armed forces. In general.
however, the so-called civil rights are not related to citizenship.
They are rights which. i n liberal t\clllocfntic societies. have been
guaranteed oy law to evcry individual.
I lurn now to the controvcf5Y about the subsequent social.
economic, and cultural rights i n I he Uni versal Declaration. They
arc as follows: the right to social security; the right to work
(meaning thc right to be given a job) . with a just wage. including
equal pay for equal work. and the right to form and join trade
unions: the right to rest and leisure, with reasonable hours 'ancl
periodic holidays with pay' (a provision that has provoked much
ridicule): the right to an adequate standard of living: the right
to education: the right 'to participate in the cultural life of the
community' and to protection or 'the moral and materia! interests
I tO Problems of Political Philosophy
resulting from any scientifc, l iterary or artistic production' of
which one is the author (meaning. I suppose, protecti on of patent
rights and copyright ) .
No one would deny that these are al l desirable objectives. But
should they be classed as human rights, comparable to t he natural
rights of the eighteenth century? Do they all have that same
degree of basic importance for human life? More crucially still,
can they be protected by l aw, and i f not, what i s the point of
listing them as human rights? As i t happens, some of them were
regarded as rights by a few people in the eighteenth century. In
France, Turgot and Rohespierre both spoke of a right to work,
while a declaration of 1793 and a socialist manifesto of Babeuf
and his associates i n 1 796 spoke of a right to education. An
English thinker, Thomas Paine, writing in support of the principles
of the French Revolutionaries in his book The Rights of Man
( 1 791-2) and again in Agrarian Jutice (1797), proposed a fairly
elaborate plan of social securi ty, to be treated as a right and not
a matter of charity. If the Universal Declaration had confined its
economic and social rights to education and social security, it
would seem less starry-eyed. Both of these are fundamental to a
l i fe of reasonable human dignity, and both, if only in a bare
measure, can be insisted upon and publicly provided in almost
every State. One cannot say that of the right to work. It may be
fundamental for the preservation of human dignity, but who can
be charged with the obligation to provide i t? Economists know
something nowadays about ways of reducing unemployment, but
not much, and one cannot charge governments with an obligation
to provide full employment if nobody knows how they are to do
i t . As for holidays with pay and proprietary rights in cultural
productions. these are visionary dreams for vast numbers of
human beings. many of whom have no assurance of having enough
food to stay alive or of being taught to read and write for basic
requirements. The inclusion of luxuries. however estimable, in a
list of human rights puts at risk the chances of getting illiberal
regimes to bestir themselves in implementing fundamental and
attainable rights.
When the United Nations Commission on Human Rights was
set up on 1946 to consider an 'International Bi l l of Rights', the
British delegation proposed a draft convention listing specifc
rights which could be protected by explicit legal procedures. This
uemocracy I ! I
was supported by the delegates from India and Australia, the
latter adding a detai1ed proposal for an international court of
human rights. The representative of the Soviet Union objected to
these proposals as 'premature' ; hc took a 'bill of rights' to be a
manifesto of principles, not a law that would give binding auth
ority to a court ' The upshot was that the Commission decided to
formulate a declaration of principles i n the frst instance, to be
followed by a binding covenant. I f the drafting of the declaration
had been tied to the need for legal enforcement . i t could not have
strayed into the unrealistic realm of a 'right' to work or into the
starry-eyed aspirations of universal holidays with pay and benefts
of authorship. Needless to say. once it came to drafting n coven
ant, the economic, social , and cultural rights could not be accom
modated within a justiciable proccdure. So the covenant for imple
menting t he Universal Declaration became two covenants. one
for civil and political rights, the other for economi c, soci al , and
cultural rights. Both covenants go bravely into further detail of
what is involved i n the particular rights of the Universal Declar
ation, but when they turn to implementation they are singularly
uni mpressive. The covenant on civil and political rights proposes
an international Human Rights Committee. which would try to
get agreement by discussion jf one State complained that another
was failing in its obligations. If the committee did not slicceed i n
getting agreement . it would make a report tn that effect. The
covenant on economic. soci al . and cultural rights does not even
go that far. It simply requires States to suhmit reports of progress
on these rights and enables the Economic and Social Council of
the United Nations Organization t o comment on the reports.
The European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights
and Fundamental Freedoms took t he path proposed by the British
and Australian delegates t o the UN Commission. it confned itself
to civil rights which are justiciable: it set up a Commission to give
preliminary consideration to complaints. and a Court to reach
defnitive decisions: it allows both member Slates and individuals
to submit complaints, but a complaint from an individual is
admissible only if he has already exhausted all the facilities avail
able for complaint i n the courts of the country concerned. The
rulings of the European Court of Human Rights have had a
t. See Mauril'c CranslOn. HI/man RighH Til-day ( London, 1962). pp . .4-5; or
Maurice Cranston. Whm are Hilma!! RighH? (Lontlon. llJ7J). pp. 52-.,
. ... . A .A+ .p
*J
. ww .. + . - + .. &.+. +
signifcant effect on the law and practice of the member States,
who may at times feel that they have got more than they bargained
for when they ratifed the convention. Some of those States,
including the United Kingdom, have prided themselves on the
liberal tradition of their legal system and have been surprised to
fnd the European Court ruling that certain of their practices were
in breach of the convention.
The original European Convention of 1950 says nothing about
political, economic, social, or cultural rights, but a subsequent
protocol (or addition) of 1954 includes a right to education and
an undertaking by member States to hold free elections to their
legislatures at reasonable intervals by secret ballot. Apart from
the right to education, the members of the Council of Europe left
economic and social rights to be commended i n a 'European
Social Charter', which came into force in 1965. This, l i ke the UN
International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights,
simply requires reports to be submitted for consideration by a
special committee and then by the Committee of Ministers, which
'may make recommendations to the member State concerned. The
European Social Charter says nothing about cultural rights.
There is some point in announcing social aspirations i n a declar
ation or 'charter', and in asking for reports on progress, since
States can be shamcd thereby into making some effort to 'keep
up with the Jonese'. But it was a pity that the Universal Declar
ation put such aspirations together with basic 'civil' rights which
can be given more effective protection under frm legal
procedures.
5
Justice
5.1 A complex concept
To call something just is to express approval of it as being right
i n a specifc way, but to pin down the sp

cifc character is not at


all easy. Justice is a complex concept . I t I S used both of law and
of social morality, and al though the ideas of legal and

oral
justice share certain common principles they do not
.
stand 1 0 the
same relationship to thei r respecti ve felds of operation, law and
morals. Then again. justice may bc regarded on the one hand as
a concept concerned with the ordcr of socicty as a whole, and on
the other hand as an expression of the fights of mdlvlduals 111
contrast to the cl ai ms of general social order. Finally, justice is a
Janus-l i ke concept . looki ng both 10 past and to future. conservi ng
and reforming.
.
( I ) In the law, the term 'justice' is used to cover the whole field
of principles and procedures that ought to be followed. The system
of law as a whole is often called, in legal parlance. the system of
justice. Lawyers wi l l distinguish ' t he pri nci ples of natural justice',
as a relatively small. though fundamental. part of the legal system,
from the rest of it. but the distinction here is not between justice
and something other than just ice : i t is a di sti ncti on between a ?

sic
part of justicc which may bc called 'natural' and the remalOl Ig
superstructure which is also justice but dependent on custo.
precedent, and enactment. I n social morality, how
,
ever, Justice
does not cover the whole feld of principles and aeUons that are
considered right. Justice is the foundation of social morality, and
without it the rest would eollapsc: but it is certainly not the whole
of social moral i ty. We contrast justice with generosity or chari ty,
which we regard as going beyond mere justice. What a man is
1 1 .
entitled to as a matter of justice we call his rights. Corresponding
to these rights of the potential benefciaries of just actions, there
are duties for the potential agents. Generosity or charity implies
duties for agents but not rights for the potential benefciaries.
The law does not concern itself with the moral duties of generos
i ty. The law protects rights and enforces the duties which corre
spond to rights. This is not to say that the scope of the law takes
in the whole domain of moral justice (or moral rights). We saw
in 3. 2 that a democratic society, at least, tries to restrict the area
of legal (i . e. State) authority in order to leave as much room as
possible for liberty, and that many forms of moral wrongdoing
can be suitably restrained without resort to legal prohibition. In
other instances (e. g. i n the discouragement of deceit) the 'rough
engine' of the law, as Si r James Fitzjames Stephen called i t , is not
a practicable method of protecting moral rights, and to invoke it
would do more harm than good. However, the moral scope of
the law is confined within the area of moral justice. A system of
law (illS) is concerned with the protection of rights (illra). I t is
therefore intelligible that law should use the ter
m
'justice' to
describe the whole of its operations.
Of course this docs not mean that anything which goes on in a
court of law has to be called just. It can be criticized as unjust
either from a moral or from a legal point of view. A law can be
called unjust for failing to meet moral ideas of justice; and the
administration of law (i rrespective of whether the particular law
applied to a case is itself morally just or unjust) can be criticized
as unjust for failing to meet the standards of fairness required by
the procedures of the legal system.
(2) The idea of justice. both i n legal and i n moral thought, is
plainly concerned with the general ordering of society. A breach
of that order is called a breach of justice, and penalties for the
breach are invoked in the name of justice. The criminal law
especially is designed to protect the order of society as a whole.
The punishment of crime is not a matter of giving satisfaction to
the victim but one of protecting the social fabric. In so far as the
victim of a crime is able to vindicate a claim against the criminal
in respect of the wrong he has suffered (and generally speaking
the legal provisions for this are far from adequate), it takes the
form of obtaining reparation or compensation for loss or damage.
and is i n no way a satisfaction of any natural desire to see the
aggressor paid back i n his own coin. I n a system of criminal law
(as contrasted with a system of vendetta). that natural desire of
a wronged individual i s merged into the general desire of society
as a whole to be protected from such harmful conduct, and punish
ment is imposed by the authority of the organized society and for
the sake of the whole society.
The concept of justice is also used. however, to uphold the
rights of the individual. i f "necessary against the claims of general
social order. Often there is no opposition between them; the two
go together. Most of the transactions of the civil law , for example.
protect the smooth working of society. i n matters of contrac!.
avoidance of negligence. and so forth. and at the same time the
judgements that are given i n the case of disputes or breaches are
vindications of the rights of individuals. But sometimes. notably
in the work of the criminal law and in the framing of governmental
policy, there can be a confict between general social i nterest and
the rights of individuals. and when that happens it is the latter
notion which presents itself to us under the banner of justice.
Thus. for instance. no person who is innocent of breaking a law
may be justly subjected to punishment. although there are circum
stances in which this might be conducive to the general interest
and the maintenance of public order. For example, if a particular
type of crime is prevalent . and i f
.
circumstantial evidence would
lead many of the real criminals to thi nk that the persall accused
has been implicated. then his conviction and imprisonment would
aet as a deterrent for them to the same extent as the conviction
and imprisonment of one of themselves: but though useful. this
would be unjust. Again, a man who is guilty of a crime ra}' not
justly receive punishment i n excess of that merited by his degree
of guilt.
This is not to say that the claims of social i nterest must always
give way to those of justice. onl y that the idea of justice stands
up for the rights of the individual. even of a guilty individual,
against the demands of uti li ty. The principle that an i nnocent
individual should not be subjected to criminal penalties is made
absolute in any civilized system of niminal 1aw by defni ng 'punish
ment' as the consequence of ( usually wilful) breach of a law.
Nevertheless. considerations of general social i nterest may in
exceptional circumstances be held to warrant the detention of a
person who has not broken anI' law. In Bri tai n at the beginning
1 10 rrollems OJ rOltllcal t'losopny
of the Second World War, people of Genan nationality were
confned in detention centres. It was called detention, not <impris
onmen!', but for those detained there was not a great deal of
difference. For that matter the enforced isolation of people suffer
ing from dangerous contagious diseases is not altogether different
from the deprivation of liberty that imprisonment involves. Every
body knows that the measures taken in such i nstances are dictated
entirely by the general social interest and that questions of justice
or individual rights are simplY swept aside. Hence there is no
possibility of linking these deprivations of liberty wi th ideas of
punishment. But even within the penal processes of the criminal
law, although the logically necessary connection between the ideas
of punishment and guilt places an absolute bar on punishing the
innocent for reasons of utility, we do sometimes allow utility to
override justice where this absolute bar i s not present. If a person
is guilty of committing a crime of a kind that is becoming wide
spread, we tolerate the imposition of 'exemplary' punishment that
goes beyond his individual deserts, i n order to deter other poten
tial offenders. In admitting that it 'goes beyond his individual
deserts we recognize that there is an clement of i njustice or
unfairness i n the degree of the penalty, and we i mply some meas
ure of compunction in allowing the claim of utility to prevail over
that of justice. The same sort or thing can happen in the formation
of a governmental policy which involves questions both of utility
and of justice. If a scheme of military conscription i n ti me of war
exempts from the call-up men i n civilian occupations (such as
engineering) that are especially important to the war effort, or if
a scheme of demobilization at the end of the war gives priority to
those whose civilian occupations (such as building) are especi ally
important for post-war reconstruction, we allow that the national
interest requires discrimination, but we do so with some reluctance
and we admit that it is unfair to the men who are called up to the
forces early and are released late. Justice or fairness to the individ
ual is contrasted with utility or general interest, and whichever of
the two i s hel d to prevail i n a particular situation, the opposition
of principle remains.
In thc thought of Ihc ancient Greeks (and no doubt the same
is truc_of most primitivc societies), the idea of justice almost
always had a reference 1 0 social order. or. by a natural transfer
cnce nf i deas. h cosmic order. .fustice did not connote the same
kind of order for a democratically minded person as it did for one
who favoured aristocracy, but for bOlh it had to do wi th social
order. Although ancient Athens was a morc radical democracy
than modern democracies, and al though the Athenian democrat
prized liberty and equality, the idea of the rights of the individul
does not seem to have developed so as to be given exphclt
expression i n language. If one wanted to translate the noun 'rights'
into ancient Greek, no single word would be entirely appropriate
and onc would need either to make do with a word meaning
'privileges' or else to use a periphrasis.
In Plato's Republic there is an idiosyncratic notion of 'justice in
the soul' which is compared and contrasted wi th justice in society.
This does not really form an exception to the generalization I
have made about Greek thought. Plato's idea of 'justice in the
sour is conceived as analogous to justice in society and still relates
to a form of order, harmonious order between the different
elements of the soul. as justice in society is, according to Plato,
harmonious order between di fferent social classes. Plato's view of
justice is in facl an aristocratic nne. and part of the point of
hi s analogy between society and Ihe individual is to support hi s
preference for aristocracy, There is no such thi ng as just ic within
an individual . When the concept of jllstice relates to an individual .
i t concerns relationships becl1'een hi m and other individuals or
between him and a group (including the l arge group that consti
tutes the organized society of the State). The rights of the individ
ual that are comprised in one aspect of justice are rights visa vis
other persons.
Plato's concept of 'justice in the souJ'. ho\vcvcr. is not designed
solely to bolster an aristocratic view of j ustice in society. I t also
gives expression to the idea of a spirit nf conscientiousness i n all
forms of moral acti on. From this point (If \'iew i t Hpproaches
Judaeo-Christian idea5 about the authority of conscience anti the
value of the individual soul . though without the equalitarianism
that was implicit i n those i dcas. They were the notions which
eventually brought into full consciousness the aspect of justice
that is concerned with the rights of the individual. The idea of
rights as such mHde its first appear;l!ll'c, of cnurse, i n the l anguage
of the l aw. and the concept of moral or 'nalural' rights. under the
rubric of moral or 'natural' justice . was an extension of that. The
attachment of the idea of moral or natural rights to the notion of
l I t t'roblem. of t'ollfICO/ t'hllosophy
the individual person came t o full fruition only i n the seventeenth
century, when Protestantism upheld the authority of the individ
ual's conscience in matters of religion and morals, and in conse
quence individualism spread into social and political thought also.
(3) A thi rd dichotomy that needs to be noted is that between
justice as a conservative and as a reformative principle. I have
already referred to this in 2.5(c) and 3. 2(d), when speaking
of the functions of the State. Conservative justice protects the
established order of society wi th its established distribution of
rights, and i n the event of breaches i t requires restitution of the
status quo so far as that i s possible. Reformative justice calls for
revisions of the social order and a redistribution of rights to suit
current ideas of fairness. The second of these concepts is, I t hi nk,
what people usually have i n mi nd when they speak of 'social
justice'. The term 'social justice' tends to issue from t he mouths
of reformers, and to be regarded with suspicion by those who are
satisfed with the existing order. It i s not in fact a suitable term
for expressing the differences of opinion between these two
groups, for the adjective 'social' has misleading implications i n
suggesting t hat reformative justice i s socia1 while conservative
justice is not. As we have seen, justice always has a social refer
ence in that it concerns the order of society as a whole or relation
ships between individuals or groups of persons pace Plato, justice
nevcr means a virtue that affects an i ndividual agent alone. as the
virtues of selfrespect and prudence can. And i f the intention. i n
speaking of social justice. i s t o contrast t hi s wi th legal justice, i t
i s a mistake t o suppose t hat t he justice of t he law i s always
conservative. Quite apart from reform of the law i ntroduced by
political process, the system of legal justice is itself apt , in civilized
countries, to include procedures for seIfcriticism and reform.
The Supreme Court of the United States has had its periods of
conservatism and its periods of remarkable reform. In the history
of English Law, the courts of Equity modifed the rigidity of
common law, and while the courts of today leave it to Parliament
to make major reforms by way of statute, judges are not averse
from reinterpreting old laws to suit modern conditions and modern
ideas. It is in gencral true that common law conserves moral ideas
of the past, and that statute reforms the law in the light of moral
ideas of the present , but this is not a universal rule.
The fact is that none of the three dichotomies which I have
~ *=
made coincides with any of the others. Thc distinction bctwcen
legal and moral justice is not the o;<lI11C as that between the justice
of the social order and justice for individuals. nor i s ei ther of them
the same as the distinction between (ol1scrvalivc and reformative
justice. Legal and moral justice are each concerned both with
an equitable order of society and with protecti ng the rights of
individuals against the demands of society. if need be, as well as
against other individuals. Each of the two again has its conscrva
tive and its reformative aspect: both law and morals regard it as
unjust to violate expectations based on long-standing arrange
ments; yet both recognize that an established order i s always liable
to ossify conceptions which have bccome oul of date. and that
changes in the character of human life. both m<terial and spiritual .
require changes of the social structure. It is )bvious. fnally. that
the distinction between conservative and reformative justice is
quite differcnt from that betwecn thc just icc of the social order
and justice for individuals. Conservative justicc i s concerned both
with the preservation of established social norms and wi th the
protection of the freedom, person. and property of individuals.
Reformative justkc is undoubtedly intcnded t o produce a more
equitable society. as the common term 'social justice' implies. but
it is equally intended to secure for needy or meritorious i ndi\'id
uals the rights to which it thi nks they arc enti tl ed.
5. 2 Equit}, and impartiality
The idea of justice is often . though not always. roughly equivalent
to the idea of fairness or equity. Equity is frequently constrasted
with equality. ' Fair shares'. for example. are not t he same as
'equal shares'. thw do they differ? 'Fair shares' depend on me_rit .
need, anu capacity. which of course arc not equally distributed.
It is not fair that idlers should receive as rnul'h as the industrious.
that those with greater need should he given no more than those
with less need. that opportunities should go to those who cannot
beneft from them rather than tn those who can. (l say ' rather
than', meaning that the unfair distribution would actually dcprive
the capable of opportunities that tbey could use . We speak of fair
and unfair dislributinn only in the allocation of resources that are.
scarce. If there is more than enough for everyone to take what
he wants, no question of justice arises.) Yet the Latin word
1 LV rrOlem Of rOIlIlCa/ rtlllosopny
'aequita' is simply the noun corresponding to t he adjective
'aequus', and i t originally meant no more and no less than simple
equality. Furthermore everyone agrees that equality in some sense
is central to the idea of justice; equality before the law, for
instance, is fundamental to legal justice.
Plato and Aristotle tried to explain the connection between
equity and equality by distinguishing 'arithmetical' equality from
'geometrical' or 'proportionate' equality. Arithmetical equality
gives equal shares to all ali ke, irrespective of worth. In the langu
age of Plato and Aristotle, it gives equal shares both to equals
and to unequals; or, to echo Jeremy Bentham, it says that 'every
body is to count for one, nobody for more than one'. Plato and
Aristotle regard this as a mistaken principle, which they would
replace by geometrical or proportionate equality, giving equal
shares to equal persons and unequal shares to unequal persons.
What they mean is that benefts or responsibilities should be
proportionate to the worth (the merit or ability) of those who
receive them. As Aristotle puts i t , ' if futes are to be distributed,
they should go only to those who have a capacity for fute-playing;
and similarly, a share in ruling should be given only to those
who arc capable of rule. Arithmetical equality represents the
democratic concept of distributive justice) proportionate equality
the aristocratic concept. The latter is called a form of equality by
Plato and Aristotle because i t equates benefts and responsibilities
with the worth of the recipients, but of course the distribution
which it calls for is an unequal distribution. It is (at least part of)
what is commonly meant by equity.
Most moder theorists, even when their political sentiments are
democratic rather than aristocratic, seem to agree wi th the view
of Aristotle (Plato is less often cited) that equity is entirely a
matter of proportionate distribution and that it does not include
any principlc of strict cquality. Equity allows, or rather requires.
discrimination by reference to morally relevant di fferences, and
forbids discrimination in the absence of such di fferences. It is fair
to discriminate i n favour of the needy, or the meritorious, or the
able, and it is unfair to discriminate between people who are
equally nccdy, cqually mcritorious. or equally ablc. Thc rule is
to treat l i ke cases alikc and unlike cases di fferently. Within a
Politics. HI. 1 2.
particular category of people who are al l alike i n t he relevant
respect, equity requires equal or impartial treatment. According
to those who follow the view of Plato and Aristotle, there is no
positive principle of justice which requires that all human beings,
as contrasted with all members of a particular relevant category.
should be treated equally. The only thing that needs to be said.
they argue, i s that i n the absence of a known relevant difference,
we should presume that people belong to the same category. But
one may well ask why. If humanity itself is not a relevant category
for equal treatment. why should we presume, in the absence of
detailed knowledge. that the people affccted oy our action are
equal i n respect of need. merit, and capacity. when we know i n
general that men are apt to be very unequal i n these respects'?
What would the supporters of Aristotle say about the principle
of equality before the law? Here. so it seems at frst sight. is a
form of strict equality which everyone accepts as required by
justice. A judge should be no respecter of persons. He should not
favour the rich, or the noble, or the clever, or even the meritori
ous, because they are rich, noble, clever, or meritorious. Nor
should he favour the poor because they are ' poor, the lowly
because they arc 1owly. Favour for the rich. etc . . would be privi
lege; for the poor. charity or compassion . Neither would be jus
tice. A judge must be impartial. I mpartiality is undoubtedly a
requirement of justice, and our example suggests that it is a form
of equality as contrasted wi th the discrimination of equity.
In fact, however, the impartiality of a judge fts into the rule
of equity. It does not mean that the judge should treat everyone
ali ke, sheep and goats, i nnocent and guilty. The judge has a duty
to discriminate. but only by reference to 'relevant' di fferences;
and for the judge. relevance is i n terms of guilt and innocence
(or, in eases of civil law. liability and non-liability), not in terms
of rich and poor. noble and lowly. clever and stupid, beautiful
and ugly. or even of deserving and undeserving as a general
moral category (bv contrast with Ihe specifc legal merits of an
individual's case as shown by the evidence). The relevant di ffer
ence for just discrimination has 10 be relevant to the matter in
hand. For the judge in a criminal court. whose business it i s to
imprison or set free . the relevant difference is guilt or innocence.
For the man who is handing out Autcs (or. to modernize Aristo
tle's example, for the committee which is awarding scholarships
lIZ rrUUIt:rT1. UJ rUflllLUI rnuu.vpny
to an Academy of Music). the relevant difference is capacity or
incapacity for fute-playing. The judge follows the principle of
equity that like cases be treated alike and unlike cases di fferentl y,
with the necessary proviso that the onl y unlikeness to be taken
into account is the one relevant to his function. His impartiality
requires that he ignore all differences other than proved guilt.
Before a verdict has been reached, he must treat equally all
persons charged with an offence, because the law presumes that
every such person is innocent unless and unti l he has been proved
guilty. During the hearing of cases, therefore, al l accused persons
are alike, i n the eye of the law, i n respect of the relevant quality
of guilt or innocence, and consequently they are to be treated
alike.
I t has been suggested' that impartiality i s a purely formal prin
ciple, a principle of logic, rationality, consistency, one that is
not specially concerned with ethics but applies to rationality in
theoretical as much as in practical matters. The principle requires
us to treat like cascs alike and unlike cases differentl y. It is
irrational tD accord different treatment to persons who are alike
i n respect of a relevant quality, just as it would be irrational to
call one sheet of paper white and another green when they were
in fact alike in colour. Ethical questions may come i n, it is said,
only whcn we decide what qualities to regard as relevant for a
particular purpose. We make a moral judgement when we decide
that need, or merit, or ability shall count as the relevant quality
for di fferentiating the like and the unl i ke; but the rule of impar
tiality that like cases be treated alike is purely formal .
This view seems to me to be mistaken. There is more to t he
impartiality Df justice t han t he ratiDnality Df logic. We should say
that it is dotty, and confusing, to call one sheet of paper white
and another green if they are alike in colour, or to kick one of a
row of similar chairs and to bow to another; but we should not
say i t is unjust. I njustice is never simply the same as irrationality.
We do not talk about justice, or even impartiality, i n describing
what we do to material things. Nor, I thi nk, in describing what
we do towards animals. I t may be inconsistent to pick out for
slaughter one flne ox ilnd not another; but would we sny it is
: NlllAbiy by Chaim Perelman. See, ror example, his book The Idea of1m/ice and
III, /'ro)MI'11! {If Ar,lm/('I1f (l .lllHlon. 196J); essay I. 'Concerning JUSlice"; essay J.
'The Rule of Justice'; CSSilY 7. 'Opinions and Truth' (especially p. l.2l .
I

\
I
\

JU./ICC I &O
unjust? We may feel it is hard on oxen that t hey, and not horses.
are killed for meat, and we may t hi nk there is something unethical
about killing any animals for food: but would we say that men
are unjust to oxen as compared with horses in eating the one and
not the other? The concept of just ice relates only to our dealings
with human beings, and so must presuppose an idea that there is
something special about human beings as contrasted with material
things or animals. If the Queen of Hearts in Alice in Wonderland
were to say 'Off with his head! ' of every second gardener or every
second croquet-player. that would be unjust: but not if she said
i t of every second rosebush or every second flamingo. In either
event she would be acting irratiollCl l l y. Irrational or inconsistent
action towards members of the same category becomes unjust
action only if the category of those affected by i t i s a category of
h

an beings.
/ :"' "tven in our dealings with human hcings, nol all forms of differ
. ential treatment are regarded as unjust or as showing partiality.
Suppose l owe 1 0 to the mi l kman and 10 to the butcher. Each
of them is in the same category of people to whom l owe 1 0, so
that I ought to treat them alike in paying my debts. I have several
[0 notes and lots of 1 coins. I should be treating the two men
i n exactly the same way i f I gave a I [ note to each or i f J gave
ten 1 coins to each, alld 1 should be treating them differently i f
I gave a note to one and coins t the other. Would we say that
the second course of action was unjust or parti al as compared
with the frst? No, because the value received would be the same
in either event. A difference of treatment which does not involve
a di fference of benefit is immaterial. The point is that the equality
of treatment for l i ke cases that justice requires, is a material
equality. not a forma! one; and what makes my di fferential lrcat
ment of the two men materially equal is the amount of beneft
as contrasted with rhe different forms in which the benefit is
conveyed.
In the same way as the conkrring of bel l eft is a material
consideration for just distribution . so is the opposite process of
conferring burdens. Suppose John and James are two of mv stu
dellts. in the same cia" and of similar ability. I f I set each of
thcm an essay on a differcnt subject but of roughly equal diflicul t y,
t hi s i s not unjust. 1 1 may not even be irrational . though i t \,':1n well
he called inconsist ent . There is more to rationality of aClion than
a
' `''':'' *1
+ . .+. w+ + +~==@. _
logical consistency. I may have good reasons for my di fferenti al.
and inconsistent . treatment of John and James. I may have thc
perfectly good altruistic reason that if they were to write essays
on the same subject they could not easily consult t he same books
at the same t i me. since duplicate copies are not available. Alterna
tively I may have thc self-interested reason that I do not want to
be bored by hearing the same subject discussed twice. We might
hesitate to call this. li kc the altruistic reason, a 'perfectly good'
rcason. but the fact rcmains that self-interest can provide reasons
for action and can make a pair of inconsistent actions rational.
At any rate my di fferential treatment of John and James is not
unjust. If the two essay sUbjects are equally diffcul t, and equally
distasteful, neither John nor James will thi nk me unjust or partial.
They may thi nk me a beast for setting them essays at all, but not
an unjust beast. On the other hand, if I were to set John two
essays to James's one, or if I were to give an obviously more
diffcult subject to John than to James, then John could regard
mc as unjust. A di ffcrcntiation of burdens is not unjust i f they
arc cqually burdensome. The discrimination i s unjust only if it
involves a materi al. not a formal, di fference, and what counts as
material l i keness or unlikeness i s the weight of the burden.
Justicc and injustice, impartiality and partiality, arise only in
our treatment of human beings and only in relation to the confer
ment of benefts or burdens upon them. No question of justice
arises over thc action of the crackpot who treats his chairs di ffer
ently, or of the farmer who treats hi s cattle differentl y. No ques
tion of justice arises over my differential treatment of the mi lkman
and the butcher, so long as they receive equal benefts. or over
m)' di fferenti al treatment of John and James, so long as thcy
receive equal burdens. I mpartiality. then, is not a purely formal
concept. It i s not just a rule of treating like cases al i ke. I t is a
rule of treClti ng l i ke persons al i ke in the distribution of heflc/irv or
burdens. Even in its principle of i mparti ali ty, justice goes beyond
logic to ethi cs. It presupposes a particular ki nd of evaluation of
human beings as persons. and i t has regard to what they them
selves value and disvalue as henefts and burdens.
There is a further limitation on the requirement to be impartial.
We are so conscious nowadays of the evils of di scrimination that
we tend to forget that discrimination does not always call for
disapproval. M. Rene Maheu. then Director-General of
UNESCO, was reported. by an official puhlication of his own
organization ` to have sai d. at an International Conference on
Human Rights held in 1968. that the Uni vcrsal Declaration of
Human Rights 'denounces all discrimination of whatever ki nd
among human hei ng" The Uni vcrsal Declaration does no such
thing. Its mOSt general statement al."out discrimination or distinc
tion is the frst sentence of Artirk 2. which rcads: 'Everyone is
entitled to all the rights and freedoms set forth in this Declarati on,
wi thout di sti ncti on of any ki nd. urh as ralc. colour. sex, langu
age. religion. political or other opinion. national or socia! origin.
property, birth or other status. ' The article does indeed require
the absence of 'distinction of any kiner, but only in reference to
'all the rights and freedoms set forth in this Declaratioll .
I t would be absurd t o denounce ' al l discrimination of whatever
kind among human beings'. The exercise of discrimination is not
always wrong. To say of someone that ' he is a di scri mi nati ng sort
of chap' is a mark of praise. and to say that 'he has no sense of
discrimination' is a mark of dispraise. It is v/ong for a judge to
discriminate except in terms of guilt and innocence, but it would
be equally wrong for him to fail tn discriminate in those terms. I t
is wrong for a university teacher, marking the examination papers
of his pupils, to diseriminntc CXCCjl in terms of nbi l i ty and indus
try, but it would be equally wrong. I \ him to fail to discriminate
in those terms. so long as he is required to assess students by
examinations. People who have duty to be i mparti al also have
a duty to discriminate for relevant reasons. Apart from t hi s. t here
are many contexts in which a duty of impartiality simply docs not
arise. There i s nothing wrong in being discri minating i n the choice
of onc's friends; and having chosen them, it is not unjust to be
partial to one's friends. On the contrary, il would be thought
pretty poor i f a man treated his friends Il() di fferenl l y from the
way i n whil'h he treated strann" ` Iff/h'ss he wefe cleali ng \vi t h
both by virtue of holding some orl. 'c or role of authority. i n which
event he would have a duty to C'xercise the role i mparti ally.
The genera! rule of impartiality or non-discrimination applies
only in virtue of holding an oflicc or role of authority or guardian
ship. Such roles arc of course not confned to offcial appoint
ments. A parent is in such a rty"ition in relation to hi s chi l dren,
' UII('sn Chmnidt', JUI. I(M\. \'01. .'1\'. \\\ . p_ 2 1 7
lLO rroDtems OJ roll!teal t'htIosophy
and consequently, even though he may, li ke Jacob, love one of
his children best, it is unjust or unfair of him to show special
favour to one child over another; but here again, as in other
instances, it is proper to discriminate for relevant reasons, e. g. to
pay university fees for the one who has the capacity to beneft
from a university education.
We are not only apt to forget that the general duty to be
impartial applies solely to the exercise of a role of authority or
guardianship. One can also forget that this duty is built into such
a role. It was, for example, completely superfuous to suggest, as
did the British Home Secretary in 1968, that the Race Relations
Bill should be accompanied by a special clause i n the police discip
linary code requiring police offcers not to discriminate against
coloured persons. Police offcers are already obliged by virtue of
their offce or role to be impartial, except as between those who
appear to be breaking the law and those who do not. To tell a
police offcer that it is an offence for hi m to discriminate against
a coloured man is like telling the same thing to a judge or to a
Home Offce offcial. The excuse given was that many coloured
people think, rightly or wrongly, that police offcers do discrimi
nate against them. But many coloured people t hi nk the same of
Home Offce offcials. If any policeman or civil servant does i n
fact discriminate against a coloured man, he is already violating
a duty of his offce and can be penal ized for doing so. If, on the
other hand, some coloured people mistakenly imagine discrimi
nation where it does not exist, their misapprehension will not be
cured by repeating i n a special clause a duty that is already built
into the general provisions of the police disciplinary code.
This does not mean that there is no point in legislating against
discrimination. Not all roles have duties of impartiality built into
them. It would be outrageous to legislate against discrimination
i n the choi ce of onc's fricnds. but there can be good reasons. in
some circumstances. to legi slate against discrimination i n the
choice of one's customers, A shopkeeper does not exercise a role
of authority or guardianship: and if he chooses to give credit to
his friends and not to other customers, that is his affair. He does
not violate any duty of his rolc (as he would if he were to give
short weight). So too. if an employer, or a hotelier, or a properly
owner discriminates in favour of one group or against another i n
offering jobs accepti ng clients. or selling houses, he is not viol at-
JliJ/lCe I L
ing any duty of hi s role as a businessman. Nevertheless, if for
special reasons serious social harm is caused by leaving complete
freedom to employers, hoteliers. property owners, etc . . in their
choice of applicants for jobs or clients for rooms and houses, the
State may well be justifed i n laying upon them by statute a duty
of non-discri mination, which they do not have by virtue of their
function, as police oflicers, judges. and civil servants do.
What sort of social harm justi fics such legiSlation? There will
not be universal agreement about the answer to this questi on. As
we saw i n 3.2, there is liable to he di fference of opinion on the
extent to which the State should restrict freedom for the sake of
worthy social aims, I suggest that legislation against discrimination
is justifed where the discrimination i n question has the effect
of depriving a group of people of benefits t hat are generally
acknowledged to be common rights. That is why the Universal
Declaration of Human Rights l i mi ts its denunciation of discrimi
nation to the feld of human or common rights, rights that are
considered essential for tolerable human life in civilized society.
For example, i f there is a widespread practice of discriminating
against coloured people i n accepting applicants for employment ,
or i n letting rooms i n hotels, or i n selling houses. this causes grave
hardship for a coloured man in finding a job. a bed for the night.
or a place to live in. On the other hand. if the discrimination
results i n annoyance and resentment, but no real diffculty in
meeting essential needs, there is i nsufficicnt warrant to legislate.
For example, i f a private golf club discriminates against coloured
people (or other minority groups. such as Jews) in accepting
applications for membership, thi s. though morally offensive. does
npt deprive anyone of common rights or essential needs. Thc
excluded applicants can play thcir golf on a public golf course:
\ if they can afford to join a private golf dub. they L1 l1 presum
ably afford t sct up one of thl'ir c,)\vn: or. at the worst , i f no
alternati ve methods of playing g.\.)lf afe opn to them, they can
take up a different form of exercise or sport. But the coloured
man who is excluded from a job. or from a hotel room when
travelling, does not have a tolerable alternat i ve. The man who is
prevented from playing golf can pl ay tennis instead, or go for a
wal k. without suffering any scriol1s deprivation: but unemploy
ment or a bench in the park i s no substi t ut e for a job or a bed.
Some people will say this does not go rar enough. I t is all very
ILt t'roDler of t'OllttcaJ rtillosopny
well to value freedom and to be chary of extending legal restric
tions on i t , they will argue; but the freedom to exercise prejudice
is worse than worthless. Even if a form of discri mi nati on, as in
entry to a golf club, does not deprive a man of essent i al needs, i t
does harm t o t he social fabric and should be restrained on that
account in the name of justice. But then, where is the line to be
drawn, if not at the protection of human or common rights? A
group of whi te Protestant businessmen who set up a golf club may
want to keep themselves to themselves and their like i n their
recreational activities; and so they exclude from membership col
oured people, Jews, Roman Catholics, parsons, and lawyers. If
such discrimination i s to be made illegal, what are we to say of a
club set up by Jewish or Catholic teenagers, which restricts its
membership to young people of the same religion? Is it to be
compelled by law to admi t Protestants, greybeards, or tiny tots?
For that matter, is an individual to be required by law not to
confne his friendship to those whom he fnds l i ke-minded or
congenial? Of course this is absurd. Making friends is a two-way
process, and generally speaking, a man whom I do not want as a
friend wi l l himself not want me as a friend. Yes, and i f a golf club
practises discrimination against Jews or Roman Catholics, any
self-respecting Jew or Roman Catholic will not want to be seen
dead i n the place. Equally, i f a hotel discriminates against col
oured men, any self-respecting coloured man wi l l not want to be
seen dead in the place - provided that he has a reasonable alterna
tive. The trouble arises when there i s no reasonable alternative,
when many hotels discri minate, so that the coloured man has no
assurance that he can fnd a room.
St i l l , the argument about harming the social fabric deserves
some further consideration. Suppose there were adequate but
separate hotels for coloured people only. Suppose there were
adequate but separate schools, swimming baths, factories, for
coloured people only. Is it a satisfactory state of affairs to have a
social apartheid, with 'equal but separate' faci lities for white men
and black? A caste system may avoid social tension but it is
morally offensive none the less. Since justice concerns the social
order as wel l as the rights of the i ndi vidual, should we not agree
that 'equal but separate' faci lities are unjust even when the faci l i
ti es for individuals really are equal?
The weakness of this objection is its unreality. When i t is
claimed, i n southern states of the USA or i n South Africa, that
black men are, or will be. given equal but separate faci l i ti es. the
truth is that the faci l i ti es neither arc nor can be reaUy equal . That
they are not is obvious to anyone who looks. That they cannot
be is due to the fact that there i s no equal i ty of choice. The
separation is i mposed by a more powerful group on a less power
ful. However sincerely the white men may ai m at equali ty of
faci li ties, the mere fact that they are the top dogs politically, and
have made the decision that faci l i ti es should be separate, means
that there cannot be true equal i t y. A caste system is morally
offensive, not just because it separates di fferent groups. but
because it is a hierarchy in which some groups are counted as
superior to others. If black men had equal facilities of choice with
white men, and i f both groups voluntarily decided that they would
prefer to have separate schools, hotels. etc. , would the result be
morally offensive? It might be morally unsatisfactory in weakeni ng
the sense of fraternity, but i t woul d not be IInjIlst. We might well
feel that such a society had become 'two nations" and that a
unifed society was preferable. The fact is that if my hypothetical
example were to be realized, there lVolild be 'two nations', which
would probably want to dispose themselves geographically and
politically so as to form two States, but perhaps combining in a
federation for some purposes, such as defence and trade, for the
sake of mutual advantage.
A more realistic example of equal but separate facil i ti es is to
be found i n the educational arrangements which religious minorit
ies can make for themselves, i f they choose , in Britain. In a city
such as Gl asgow where there is a large Roman Catholic mi nori t y.
the Catholics have the facility of setting up thei r own schools
maintai ned or supported by the Statc_ Not al l Catholics choose
to send their children to thosc schools. but a great many do. and
no one would deny that the education received is as good as that
of si mi lar non-Catholic schools. Some people may deplore the
separation as bei ng ini mi cal to civic fraterni t y. and may advocate
that religion should be kept out of the schools altogether. On the
other side, religious people, whether Catholic or Protestant , wi ll
argue that religious education and religious practice are an essen
tial part of education as they see i t : and they might well add that
thi s is the best way to foster a spirit of fratcrni ty_ However that
may be, would anyone say that the separate but equal facilities
&"
1& # I UUH:rlJ UJ rUIlUCUJ rnllosopny
are unjust or unfair? Unfair to whom? The social dimension of
justice is a matter of protecting the fabric of social norms that are
accepted by most members of the society as generally advan
tageous to them alL Where there is mutual agreement to a diver
sity of arrangements for different groups i n order to meet their
several interests, there is a departure from uniformity but not
from justice.
5.3 The right to equality
I have said that persons exercising a role of authority or guardian
ship have a duty of impartiality built into that role. For persons
acting in other capacities there is no such built-in duty of impar
tiality or equal t reatment hut for special reasons such a duty may
be laid upon them by statute, as by the Race Relations Act, 1968,
to prevent racial discrimination i n things l i ke employment and
housing, or as by the Equal Pay Act, 1970, and the Sex Discrimi
nation Act . 1975. to promote equality for women. Whenever there
is a duty of impartiality, whether it is built into a role or i s i mposed
by statute, those affected by the actions of persons having the
duty are held to have a right to equal treatment. I f I favour my
friends i n the giving of Christmas presents, I do not breach any
one's rights. for we should not say that anyone had a right to
receive Christmas presents. But if discrimination has the effect of
depriving some people of faci lities that are normally available to
anyone, we should be inclined to say that their right to equal
facilities with others should be recognized and protected by l aw.
What are the grounds of the belief that al l human beings have
a right to equal facilities of some sort, and to what sort of equal
facilities do they have a right? It is said, e. g. in the American
Declaration of I ndependence, that ' al l men are born equa!'. Are
they? Men are unequal in capaci ties, whether of physical strength
or of brain, as they are in beauty. It may be 'unfair' of nature to
endow them so differentl y. but the fact is that they are not born
with equal endowments. Of course, nobody supposes that they are.
The statement 'All men are equal' (or 'All men are born equal')
is meant primarily. not as a statement of fact, but as a statement
of righI' all men have a right to equal treatment (in some sense).
What i s the justifcation for this statement? If men are not in
fact equal i n their endowments, needs, or merits, why ought they
JMft i
to be treated equally? Some philosophers argue that there is no
right to positive equality of treatment. and nn factual c4uality
among men on which to base such a right . ' The claim for so-called
equality. they say. i s a negative cl ai m for the removal of arbitrary
or unjustifed inequality. For example. the French Revolutionar
ies. i n demanding equality. were demanding a removal of arbitrary
privilege. such as that which confined political rights to the rich
and the well born. But how can one judge that discrimination is
arbitrary or unjustifed, based on irrelevant grounds, unless one
presupposes a basic equality? To give futes to those with a
capacity for fute-playing is discrimination on relevant grounds.
So is giving the \'ote to those who arc capable of exercising it . To
give the vote only to the wealthy is arbitrary. because the pos
session of wealth has nothing to do with the capacity to vote. Now
i f the French Revolutionaries had urged that votes should be given
only to the intelligent and educated, it could be said that they
would have been asking for discrimination on irrelevant grounds
to be replaeed by discrimination on relevant grounds. But i f one
asserts that voting should not be a privilege of any limited group
(except in terms of age), that it should be available to every adult,
this surely presupposes the view that all adults have the capacity
to exercise the vote. So that one is implying a belief i n a form of
factual equality. One is implying that every adul t has the capacity
to form a political judgement. The helief may not i n fact be true.
The democrat who advocates votes for all adults may be mistaken
in his presupposition. as one would be i f one advocated the dislri-
.
bution of Rutes (or music scholarships) to everyone. And I have
already suggested i n 4. 5 that the democrat's view perhaps carries
the proviso that capacity to form a politieal judgement requi res
some measure of education to be added to universally innate
ability. It is clear enough. however. that he presupposes. rightly
or wrongly_ that the innate ability is universal. Likewise if one
says that all persons, irrespective of eolour. should be treated
equally i n regard to opportunities for employment or housing,
one is implying. not only that COIUUf is irrelevant to the ahility to
perform a job o to pay rellt for " house. but also that everyone
needs a livelihood and a homc.
To be sure. people are unequal i n their capacities and needs:
See, fllr example. S.I Benn and R. S. Peter". Slll'ial Principles and fhe Oem(lcrafic
Slalr {London. jQWl. I'p. IOH- I I .
i

1
j
:
I
i
I
i
1O TFOOI<M UJ rUHUf. 'UJ rfltlusup"y
but certain basic capacities and needs are possessed equally by
al l . When i t is said that al l men are equal, this means not only
that they have an equal right of some sort but also t hat , despite
the many natural inequalities between human beings, they are all
equally endowed with certain basic capacities and needs, and that,
in some of these shared qualities, they difer radically from other
animals. What i s thi s di fference? Human bei ngs share wi th all
animals the need for sustenance, and with many animals the
capacity to enjoy pleasure and to suffer pai n. We also regard
some animals as capable of thinking to a certain extent. What we
suppose animals do not have is the capacity for rational choice.
This. added to the capacity to enjoy pleasure and to suffer pain.
is what we suppose distinctive i n human beings. And because
every man also has the capacity for imaginative sympathy, for
putting himself in other people's shoes, he can understand that
other people, like himself, want to live their lives in their own
way. Some people are cleverer or stronger than others, so that
they can make better use of their capacity for choice. But all can
choose. and all can enjoy and suffer. This is what makes our
common humanity. and thi s is the factual basis for the claim that
all men have an equal right of some sort.
I turn now to the question, to what do al l men have an equal
right. Certainly not to equal treatment i n al l respects and i n all
circumstances. 1 shall consider three suggestions, ( 1 ) that the right
to equality is a right to equal consideration; (2) that i t is a right
to equal opportunity: and (3) that i t is a right to the equal satisfac
tion of basic needs.
( 1) The frst suggestion. that the right to equality is a right to
equal consideration. seems to me plainly unsatisfactory, for i t is
too vague to give any substance to the answer we are seeking. To
say that someone ought to receive consideration is to say that he
ought not to be just ignored. Suppose that I happened to dislike
red hair and that, in exercising an offce which requires impar
ti al i ty, I were to discri minate against someone because he had red
hair. I could say: ' I considered you al l right; I considered you just
as carefully as the rest. I made a special point of inquiring whether
your red hai r was natural or dyed. and since I found that it was
natural I turcd you down.' It will be said that the possession of
red hair is not relevant to the choice I had to make. But in one
sense i t is relevant. A man's likes and dislikes are relevant to the
choices that he makes. The point i s that when I am choosing in
the exercise of an offce of authority. I ought to put aside my
private likes and dislikes because my duty i s to choose as a public
and not as a private person. So i t i s not enough to say si mply that
I ought to give equal consideration to the people affected by my
choice. Thi s might mean si mply that I should spend an equal
amount of time or effort i n considcring them. What is important
is that I should consider only those qualities that are relevant to
the purpose of the public duty laid upon me. To say that all
those who will be affected by my dccision havc an equal right to
consideration. is simply a way of savi ng that I have a duty to be
impartial. to discriminate only in terms of qualities relevant to t he
role I exercise.
(2) A right to equal opportuni ty i s more substantial and seems
more promising as an answer to Ollr question. The suggestion is
that everyone has a right to equal opportunities for self-develop
ment. to make the most of the capacities wi th which he is
endowed. The idea of equal opport uni ty can be illustrated
especially in education. If all equall\' are given the opport unity
for self-development by way of education. some (those who are
better endowed by nature) wi ll bc better able to take ad" antage
of i t , whi le others will not; and some (the ambitious and the
industrious) wi l l choose to take advantage of the opportunity
offered, while others will not. The opportuni ty will be equally
distributed but the resulting benefts will be unequal owing to
diversity of talent and of effort (to sal' nothing of l uck).
Equal opportunities need not be identical opportuni ti es. and
civerse talents need not be unequal talents. If two different things
are to be called unequal. the di fference must be a quantitative
di fference i n a qualitative li keness. ^ that they can be placed on
the same scale. It makes sense t say that ten years of education
are unequal to twenty. or that an I ntel ligence Quoti ent of 100 is
unequal to an IQ of JSO. We arc rating two thi ngs of the same
sort on the Sime scale. But it tines not make sense to say that
lechnical education is unequal Il} academi c education , or that a
talent for carpentry is unequal to a talent for mathematics. They
arc di fferent ki nds of eclucation or tal ent. ancl si nce thcy cannot
be put on the same scale they cannot in themselves be called
unequal. But if the one talent and the one form of education lead
to an occupation bringing i n a wage of nOD per week. whi le the
) t . *, .
i
i

1
- I
I
j
1
I
1
134 Problems oj Political Philosophy
other lead to an occupation bringing i n a wage of 0 per week,
the monetary receipts are unequal, and that inequality tends to
produce a rating of the two occupations, and of the two types of
talent and education, in terms of the monetary receipts. The
inequality is due to social arrangements, not to the sheer differ
ence between the occupations, talents, and forms of education.
And the inequality of pay and status i n the social arrangements
is due to economic considerations of utility and scarci ty. High pay
and high status are given to surgeons because the work of the
surgeon is highly useful and because relatively few people are
capable of doing it. Consequently a distribution of opportunities
that are equally suited to different (but not unequal) natural
talents may result i n unequal (not just different) rewards.
When people speak of equal opportunity, they often have in
mind, not the di fferentiating of opportunity to suit different
capaci ties, but rather the equalizing of opportunity to compete
for relatively scarce positions of high pay and status. In particular,
they have i n mind the removal of those restrictions on opportunity
that are due, not to di fferences of natural capacity and the social
arrangements that follow from the utility and scarcity of certain
capacities, but to other social factors. Two boys may have roughly
the same degree of the same sort of ability which could lead
to well-paid jobs. But they may receive di fferent, and unequal,
educational opportunities because the father of one boy is rich,
knowledgeable. and keen on giving his son a good education,
while the father of the other boy i s poor, ignorant, and uni n
terested i n education. Hence the advocacy of ' equal opportunity',
meaning that educational opportunities should be related to ability
and not to social background.
But is not this idea of equal opportunity liable to be self
defeating' Suppose it could be arranged that al l the children of
one generation in a particular society should start equal in the
race. Those who have greater ability (in terms of socially useful
and relatively scarce talents), and who put forth greater efforts.
wi l l become better off and more knowledgeable. What about their
children? The successful man, wealthy and knowledgeable, will
wish to give bcttcr opportunities to his children, and hc will be
in a better position to do so than the unsuccessful man. Even if
private. fcc-paying schools have been abolished, the wealthy man
wi l l be able 1 0 give hi s child more books. more travel. morc
JUSfice 135
culture generally. Is the Government to strip him of his wealth in
order that his child shall not have these advant ages? If so. and if
he knows beforehand that the fruits of his success will be taken
from hi m, he wi l l have little incentive to make the most of his
abilities. In any case, even if he is stripped of his wealth. he
cannot be stripped of his knowledge. which in itself gives his child
an advantage.
Another feature of this idea of equal opportunity is that it
implies a notion of competition. I said just now: suppose all the
children of one generation were to start equal ' i n the race' . The
idea of equal opportunity seems to be tied to that of a race to get
to the top, a race for the 'glittering prizes' of wealth and prestige.
It is one thing to speak of ftti ng opportunities to talents so that
everyone can realize his capacities for a full and enjoyable life. I t
is another thing t o speak of equal opportunities t o compete for
the prizes of society as we know i t , and notably for wealth. Is this
really the sort of thing that equalitarians are after, when they
advocate 'social' or reformative justice? Do they object to the
prominence that is given to the social prizes of wealth and pres
tige, or only to the way in which these are at present distributed?
Do they, like Plato, want the 'naturally superior' people to be
socially superior?
Then agai n. if it is thought unfair that social arrangements
should favour some rather than olhers, why stop at social arrange
ments? Is it not unfair that nature gives morc brains or more
beauty to some than to others') Why should it be considered
particularly just or fair to accommodate social arrangements to
those of nature? We do not always think it right to follow nature.
If disease can be cured or prevented, we think i t ought to be.
though that means going against nature. If a child is born blind,
we arc not content to let him bear the whole brunt of the disability
with which nature has endowed hi m. but we try. so far as we can.
to mitigate his natural 'inferiority' by making special provision for
hi m.
(3) The i dea of equal opportunities is therefore not qui te such
plain sailing as appears at frst sight. Is it i n any case enough to
satisfy the idea of a right to equali ty" If owing to ill fortune an
individual is unable to take auvantage of his opportuni ti es. ; s it
right to let him starve to death" Is it even just? In the days of
old-style laissez-/aire liberalism it was thought that the husiness
4 &"." x_ z ........ . . ... < <<. _.
J
of the State was to hold the ring clear for competition, glvmg
everyone equal liberty (a minimal form of opportunity) to do the
best he could for hi mself, and leaving the weak to go to the wall.
Charity might rescue the weak, but that was not a matter of justice
or rights. The modern Welfare State, however, gives expression
to a signifcant change of outlook. Everyone is thought to have a
right to subsistence, even if he has not earned it. In fact the
arrangements of the Welfare State imply a right to subsistence
not only for the man who has been unfortunate but also for the
idler who has chosen not to take advantage of his opportunities.
We should not say that the latter deserves help, as the former
does, but i t is sti l l thought that the satisfaction of basic needs is
due to everyone as a matter of right or justice, and as a duty of
the organized community to all its members.
The communist idea of distributive justice is that the distribution
of burdens should depend on abilities, while the distribution of
benefts should depend on needs: 'from each according to hi s
abi li ty, to each according to his needs'. Merit does not come i nto
the pi cture. Benefts are not to be the reward of contribution to
the common good. It is presupposed that reward is unnecessary,
that ideally men can shed their selfshness and contribute to the
general interest without thought of a return. In a communist
society. i t is imagined, men will work for the common good as
hard as they can, i n the way that their different abilities allow.
and that they will be content to receive what they need, not what
they have earned. Of course, their needs differ to some extent,
and therefore they will not receive identical benefts. A scholar
needs books, a scientist needs equipment, and each needs a good
deal of leisure and peace. These are needs both for fulflling their
communal function and for the personal satisfaction that comes
from realizing one's potentialities. But i n many respects all men
need the same sort of things and have the same sort of capacities
for enjoyment . Thus i n a communistic settlement like an Israeli
ki bbutz, there arc no wages. Everyone is given the use of a house.
access to communal meals, the same ration of clothing, and the
same amount of pocketmoney to spend as he will on books,
holidays, or whatever else he chooses.
The-communist notion of distributive justice is idealistic and
can be practised only by relatively unselfsh people such as the
members of a ki bbutz or of a monastery. It is not practised i n
: f
1
I

i
j
t
communist States, where li p-service is paid to the idea of equality
while incomes can be highly unequal. In George Orwell's Animal
Farm, 'all animals are equal but some are more equal than others' .
The communist slogan may be contrasted wi th what Marx
regarded as the principle of distributive justice i n a socialist
society: 'from each according to his abili ty. to each according to
his work', Here benefts are distributed i n accordance with a form
of merit. Those who work hard receive more. those who take i t
easy receive less. This idea makes concessions to the natural
selfshness of most men as we know them. The incentive of reward
is required to make them give of thei r best for the common good.
If they are rewarded accordi ng to desert . instead of receiving
benefts according to need. this will be useful to the society as a
whole since it wi ll be an incentive to them and to others to put
forward their best efforts. The 'socialist' concept of justice cli ffers
from that of laissez-Joire liberalism in that it expects men to can
tribute intentionally to the common good and to obtai n their
reward in terms of that contribution and not in terms of effort
made for their own private good.
The Welfare State is an amalgam of ideas drawn both from
liberalism and from communism. ( Historically it is the heri tage of
radical liberalism, ) It assures a basic mi ni mum. the satisfaction of
basic needs of subsistence, to al l equally. irrespective of merit or
work. But above the l i ne of the basic mi ni mum it leaves individ
uals free to compete for higher rewards. Just where the line of
the basic mi ni mum should be drawn is. of course. not clear.
Di fferent countries, and di fferent political groups wi thi n a coun
try, will take di fferent views of what constitutes the basic necessi
ti es of human existence that ought to be provided for all and that
can be afforded. For the purpose of our conceptual discussion,
however, the point is that the hasic mi ni mum is regarded as a
right, something rcquired by justice, while above the l i ne of the
basic mi ni mum there remains scope for the older liberal idea of
leaving a man rree t rise or fall by his own effort or lack of i t,
and by the good or i ll fortune or his natural endowments and the
chances of personal history and envi ronment.
The equal satisfaction of basic needs docs not always imply
an equal distribution of the n1(lterial means to such satisfacti on.
Everyone needs food to li ve. but the diabetic needs i nsuli n as
well. Every child needs education. but the bl i nd child cannot be
educated by means of the normal provision made for other chil
dren and has to be given special, more costly, facilities. The needs
of the diabetic and of the blind child are greater than those of the
normal person, and so the provision for thei r needs is greater
than normal. The distribution of benefts i s therefore i n one sense
unequal . It i s an equitable, not an arithmetically equal, distri
bution, and is intended to be proportionate to unequal needs.
Nevertheless this differential distribution is not in accordance with
nature, like the differential distribution of opportunities and
rewards proportionate to talents and efforts. It goes against nature
and implies the view that natural handicaps should be mi t igated
so far as possible. There is clearly presupposed an idea that every
one has a right to the equal satisfaction, at least up to the point
of a basic mi ni mum, of the desire to go on living and to exercise
specifcally human capaci ties. even though nature does not give
everyone the endowments to do so by normal methods. So there
is a sense in which the distribution of benefts, of satisfaction
received. i s equal, although the distribution of means to benefit
is unequal because of special needs. The right to equality proper,
as distinguished from equity as a whole, is a right to the equal
satisfaction of basic human needs, including the need to develop
and use capacities which are specifcally human.
It may be asked how far should this go? When does a general
desire become a basic human need? The blind man would li ke to
have the advantages of sight. The ugly sisters would like to have
the beauty of Cinderella. Since everyone wishes to be beautiful,
i s plastic surgery for the ugly to be called a basic need? The
answer to thi s i s: suffcient unto the day is the decision thereof.
Provision for basic needs as a matter of right is made, in the mai n,
by politically organized societies for thei r members, and what a
particular society counts as the level of basic needs, to be publicly
met, depends on i t s evaluation of competing claims and what it
can economically afford. In Britain at the present ti me, children,
students, and adults suffering from certain i llnesses or in poverty
can obtai n spectacles as of right under the National Health Ser
vice, but i f they thi nk that a standard frame wi ll i mpai r thei r
appearance and they ask for a more stylish frame, whi ch i s more
expensi'e, or for contact lenses, which are more costly sti ll. they
are expected to pay for these aids to beauty. The public authority
judges, on behaleof the organized society, that aids to good vision
\
are a basic need whi le aids to good appearance are not. There
are more pressing uses for the taxpayers' money. In many other
countries, some richer, some poorer than Bntam, the supply of
spectacles of any ki nd i s not macle a pblic charge. If and when
a particular society can afford to provide plastiC surgery
.
for all
people wi th ugly noses, and if the majority
.
of people In that
society should come to think tlwt the unhappl

ess of hav

ng an
ugly nose makes a decent standard of life impOSSible, then. I n that
soci ety. plastic surgery for the ugly will be cOlll1t?d a as!c ne

d.
But we cannot lay down a prinri a level of satiSfactlOns which
shall be counted as basic needs for all men everywhere. Some,
such as protection from bodily harm, are acknowledged by the
laws of all civilized States as both necessary and practtcable. We
can add that if the right to l i fe is everywhere acknowledged as a
human right, i ts fulflment requires not only that

rder be pro
hibited but also that starvation be prevented. ThiS IS not always
practicable, however, aqd a need cannot becoe a righ (of ecipi
ence, implying a duty on the part of others) I f the satisfaction of
i t i s not possible. In practice, therefore, the standard of baSIC
needs to be met by public action has to be set by each poirtlcally
organized society for itself, ' i n the light of its own economic situ
ation and its evaluation of competing claims.
Philosophical ana1ysis cannot provide us with a s18
.
ndard of asic
needs that i s universally applicahle. What I have tned tn do IS to
show that the idea of just distrihution according to need implies
a positive notion of equality of right and a positiv
.
e 1I0tion
.
of
factual equality among men. It i s 1I0t true that the clalln of Justl:e
for equa1 treatment ( i n the absence of relevant reasons for diS
crimination) is a purely formal claim of rationality or consistency,
nor that i t is a purely negative claim for the removal of arbitrary
inequalities. It does include both of these. b
.
ut i
.
n addition t
.
is
substantive and positive. relnting to a comhlllation of quahtl cs
possessed by all human beings and to a I

lcasllre
.
of equal st isfac
tions that are considered clue to them III the light of the 1 pos
session of common human quali ti es.
5.4 Equity lnd utility
An equitable distribution may depart from e4ual distribution on
grounds of need, meri t . or abilit\'. We ha\'e seen i n 5.3 that
~ - =+ + & U
&&y,+ .++. .
discri mination on grounds of special need is in fact an attempt to
lessen inequalities and presupposes a right to equal satisfactions
up to a basic level. The actual distribution i s unequal, but the ai m
of i t i s to reduce inequality. This is not true of unequal distribution
on grounds of merit or ability.
Wi th all three grounds for discriminatory treatment, one may
ask how far the justifying reason for discrimination i s one of
utility. Uti l i tarians hold that all principles of justice derive their
moral force from being means to the general interest. The uti l i
tarian vi ew may be most easily illustrated i n the case of distri
bution according to merit. Actions and dispositions that are called
meritorious, or deserving of reward. are usually benefcial to
society, and those that are said to deserve punishment are usually
harmful to society. If a particular meritorious act does not i n fact
beneft anyone, as when a heroic attempt to save a drowning man
is unsuccessful and perhaps results i n the death of the would-be
rescuer too, it may still conform to a version of the uti l i tarian
theory because it is an example of a type of action that usually
has beneficial results. The Uti litarian further holds that reward
and punishment arc themselves warranted by their utility. The
one encourages, the other discourages. repetition of the kinds of
actions that are rewarded and punished.
Much the same would be said by the Utiltarian about discri mi
nation i n favour of people wi th unusual ability, who are in fact
often said to 'merit' or 'deserve' their special benefts or oppor
tunities. Generally speaking, it is useful scarce abilities that
receive special treatment. A person with a bent for mathematics
wi l l be offered a university education to develop his talent and a
well-paid job in which to exercise i t. A person with a bent for
strangling or for blowing safes wi ll fnd no such encouragement.
Even discrimination on grounds of need depends on utility,
according to the Utilitarian. People who are not at work, either
because no suitable job is available or because they are tempor
arily sick or permanently disabled, are not at present contributing
to the general welfare of society. There i s a good chance of their
making such a contribution in the future, i f they are given enough
money to keep alive, and if meanwhile the unemployed arc
trained for a new kind of iob, the sick are given medical attention,
and the disabled are provided with special equipment. If their
needs are not met , there is no chance of their being useful to
society. They wi l l either be a continuing burden or will simply die
off and be neither useful nor burdcll!()ITC.
Such i s t he utilitarian thesis. I t i s strongest on meri t and weakest
on need. To see its weakness on need, consider the example of
people who are too old to work. or of people who ae permanently
disabled in such a way that they cannot
.
be equipped to do a
socially useful job. Would we think that they have no right to
provision for basic needs?
.
Some people would say that the elderly have a fight to an old
age pension only i f they have eared i t by the work they have
done in the past (or else a strnightforward contractual flght
.
1 O
return for monetary contributions ) . and that the chsabled l i keWIse
have a right to a pension only if the)' have merited i t , e. g. i f the
disablement is due to war service: hut that the elderly and the
disabled who have not earned the right by publicly useful work
or service have 11(1 right at al l . ACl
'
ording to thi s vi ew, t he rights
of need are rights of merit. and where there is no merit there is
no right: to provide for needs in the absence of merit is an act of
charity. not of justice.
If this position is taken ur on behalf of Uti l i tari ani sm, we must
of course add that the rights of the oklagc pensioner and of the
disabled exserviccran are to be understood in ut i litarian terms:
the service which they performed was socially useful. and it is
sociallv useful to reward them pnlfr enCOlfrager les autres. Does
the Utilitarian then thi nk that the ex-serviceman who is not i n
need has as much right as t he ex-serviceman who is? The ex
serviceman who is disabled or too old to work has a greater claim
on the community than the disabled or elderly man who i s not
also an exserviceman: for the former has a cl ai m of merit as well
as a claim of need. But i t is als() plain that the e:-serviceman who
is disabled or otherwise i n need has a greater cl ai m than the cx
serviceman who is not: for the former has a cl ai m of merit and
need, the latter onc of merit alone_ I t would be very odd to say
that the meri! of a soldier is redoubled by the i l l fortune of
disablement during service. His chlim on society is redouhlcd. and
it is now a cIim of two di fferent ki nds. merit and need.
We must thercfore rejcct the slIg!LSl i on t hal l hc clai ms of need,
when they are claims of justice <lnd nOI appeals to Ch .. Hity, are
claims of merit. This being so, there i s l ess reason to accept the
further thesis thai need without merit. though a proper subiect
142 Problems of Political Philosophy
for charity, gives rise to no claim of justice. For i f we say that the
congenitally disabled man has no claim of justice simply i n virtue
of hi s need, we must also say that the disabled ex-serviceman has
no greater cl ai m than the ex-serviceman who is not disabled. I
have assumcd al l along that the judgements we commonly make
i n terms of equity or fairness do make special provision for need
as welt as for meri t, i . e. that need can give rise to a c1aim of
justice. The theory of Ut i l i tarianism itself does not deny this, but
tries to i nterpret the claim of need i n t he same sort of way as the
claim of merit. That, we have seen, will not do.
What the utilitarian account omi ts i s the thought that a human
being has a claim on fellow human beings simply by reason of
human nature and fellowship. When we judge that equi ty requires
special provision for special need, we are thinking of what is owed
to someone as a person, as an 'end-in-himself' (to use the langu
age of Immanuel Kant). This means that the fellow members of
his society, whether it be a family, a religious community, or a
Welfare State, thi nk that they have a strict duty to hi m as one
like themselves and one of themselves, a being wi th ends or
purposes which they, in a measure, adopt as part of their own
ends, Justice. unl i ke some other moral virtues, does not require
social responsibility for need to go beyond a certain mi ni mum.
What i t does require, i t requires as due to the i ndi vi dual person
and not as a means to the future beneft of the whole society.
Regard for the claim of ability l i kewise includes the thought
of what is due to the individual person as an end-in-himself.
Undoubtedly there is also thought of social uti l i ty. That is why
special provision is readily made for talents that are useful to
society while no provision at all is made for those that are harmful
to society. But social uti l i ty cannot account for the whole of our
regard. In a school . for example. provision wi l l be made. if it can
be afforded, for developing (a) talents which are highly useful to
society, such as the ability to do mathematics or engineering, (b)
talents which are not particularly useful in the ordinary sense,
although they givc pleasure to others as well as to the possessor,
such as the ability to make music or to pai nt, and (c) talents which
do not seem to be socially useful at all, though not socially harmful
ei ther, such as the ability to play a good game of chess. No doubt
the provision for (a) is chieAy motivated by the thought of uti l i ty,
but t he provision for (b) is made primarily, and for (e) wholly,
because the possessors of talents obtain enjoyment and self
fulflment from the development and exercise of them. Flutes or
music scholarships are provided by puhlic authority for those who
can use them. not i n order to give the populace the pleasure of
future concerts, but in order that individuals wi th talent may
obtain the happiness and self-fulflment of using their talent. If
the tal ent i s a socially useful one, !n much the better, and then
the cl ai m of uti l i ty i s added to the cl ai m of i ndi vi dual potenti al i ty.
I f the talen.t is a socially harmful one, the claim of uti l i ty overrides
the claim of individual potentiality. If the talent is nei ther useful
nor harmful, i ts cl ai m stands as a cl ai m that has nothing to do
with social uti li ty and yet has a place in the scheme of equi ty.
The claim of abi li ty is di fferent from that of meri t , since a man
is not responsible for his abi li ti es o disabilities and cannot strictly
be sai d to deserve the benefts or burdens which they are apt to
bring hi m. When we say that the most talented performer in a
competition merits the prize, there is an clement of desert proper,
since talent must -be matched by effort , for which the performer
is responsible. Sometimes. however. as in a beauty contest. there
is no question of effort but only of ood fortune in natural endow
ments. We may still say that the winner 'merits' the prize, meaning
simply that si

ce a ' c{
;
ntest" ( i n fnct. a comparison) in beauty has
been set up ancl since thi s candi date i s t he most beautiful. she
ought to be given the prize. This use of ' meri t' and 'contest' is
parasitic on the primary use, which refers to effort and its due
reward,
As with ability. the clai ms of merit arc most readily acknow
ledged when the meritorious achievement is socially useful . 'Meri t
aW3lds' for industrial products arc palentl y of thi s charncter.
Effort in itself is not necessarily meritorious. anti no rewards wi l l
be given to a man who works himself to the bone on a thoroughly
useless occupati on, such as digging holes for the sake of fHling
them i n again. The Uti l i tari an seems to be on pretty strong ground
when he argues that the claim of merit depends on uti l i ty. What
counts i s not simply useful consequences i n the parti cular case but
the usual tendency of the ki nd of effort expended. In a particular
instanee a man may be lucky and reap a rich harvest wi th l i ttl e
dfort. In another instance he may be unl ucky and fnd that hard
work leads to no valuable result. Society often judges by actual
and not merely probable results, just as its cri mi nal law punishes
."
1^ 1 I VUlt"' VJ t VUUI.Ul flUV,Vp/IY
more severely the evil intention which is followed by evil conse
quences than the evil intention which fortunately miscarries. Yet
it will be agreed that merit and demerit depend on intention and
effort rather than actual consequences. The Utilitarian accounts
for this by reminding us that in general a man is more likely to
produce a good or bad consequence by intention and effort than
by chance, and that i t is intentions and efforts which can be
infuenced by reward and punishment.
Even with merit however, where the utilitarian case i s most
persuasive, the claim of equity does not always coincide with that
of social utility. The merit of industriousness can, I think, be
treated as wholly utilitarian, but not the merit of moral endeavour.
To the extent that moral virtues are social virtues, one can say
that the praise given to moral endeavour depends on its general
tendency to beneft society. This can certainly be said of benevol
ence, which is always directed towards the good of others, and i t
can also be sai d of most instances of other moral virtues such as
courage, honesty g and conscientiousness. There are times, how
ever, when praise for these virtues is not connected with the
beneft to society but simply expresses the idea that they exhibit
human excellence; and this must always be true of praise for the
virtue of self-respect. Just as the claim of talent includes a claim
for specifcally human potentiality on its own account, so the claim
of merit includes a claim for specifcally human achievement on
its own account.
The conclusion that merit and i ts due reward or praise cannot
always be bound up with social utility is confrmed if we look at
the other side of the coin, demerit. The punishment or blame that
is deserved may be less, or more, than that which utility pre
scribes. To follow the rule of utility rather than that of desert
strikes us as inequitable when the result is to deal with an offender
more severely than he deserves, though not when the result is to
deal wi th him more leniently. As we saw in 5. 1 , 'exemplary'
punishment that goes beyond desert is warranted by utility but
conficts with equity. On the other hand, to lighten or waive
deserved punishments that would do no good, i s not felt to be a
breach of justice. For example, one may think that a man who
has deliberately taken the life of another deserves to lose his own
life, but that the death penalty ought not to be used because it is
not an effective deterrent. Then the abolition of the death penalty
because it serves no useful purpose means that deliberate mur
derers are punished less severely than they deserve, but it would
be absurd to say that abolition is unfair or unjust (presumably to
the murderer's victim or else to previously executed murderers),
Since justice protects the rights of the individual as well as the
order of society, justice and social utility can confict as well as
coincide. Of course. rights relate to essential interests. and the
interest of society is made up of the i nterests of its me,
:
,bers, so
that justice and utility may be said to concern the same sort of
ends. But because in practice Ithe interest of society' has to mean
the i nterest of the majority, there is a tendency for the i nterests
of minority groups and of particular individuals to go by the board
if we concentrate our attention upon securing the general Interest:
and we arc apt to forget that 'the genera! interest' a

qur

s its
value only from being made up of the interests of 'nd,vld

al
persons. The concept of justice helps to
,
remio
:
' u
:
hat all SOCIal
values depend ultimately on OUI valuation of lI1d,v,dual peson
ality with its needs, desires, and enjoyments. its potent,ahlies,
aims, and achievements.
5,5 Competing conceptions of justice
Two recent theories of justice have caught attention for their
novel features. The frst is that of John Rawls in his book A
Theory of lustice. It tries to give a rational proof or justification
of ideas of justice so as to remo\' dispute and puzzl

menL In
essence this is what the utilitarian account of justice tned to do.
Rawls was originally attracted to Uti li tarianism as a general theory
of ethics. but then came to think i t defective i n its account of
justice and rights. His own theory attempts to explain justice in
terms of rational self-interest, linking the two wi th a novel use of
the idea of social contract, This does not mean that Rawls assumes
self-interest to be the only possible motive for action. He merely
assumes that there is no problem about the idea of acting from a
rational calculation of selfinterest. while the idea of justice does
pose a problem because there are apparently conficting concep-
tions of justice. especially of distrihutive justice.
.
There is one strong tradition. dating back to Plato and Anstotle,
which says that a just distribution of benefts and responsibilities
follows 'worth' (merit or ability). while another, equally ancient,
146 Problems of Political Philosophy
tradition says that a just or equitable distribution follows equality.
The idea of allocating benefts according to need is ancient enough
as a precept of ethics but was not called a principle of justice unti l
the Middle Ages. Controversy has continued since that ti me on
the question whether the relief of need should be classifed as a
duty of justice or of charity. I have shown in 5. 3 that i f the claim
of need i s regarded as an aspect of justice, it is linked to the older
idea that justice stands for equality. So the controversy about the
scope of distributive justice i s between the rival claims of merit
on the one hand and of equali ty-cum-need on the other. They are
seen as rival claims because they will often confict in practice: a
distribution of benefts according to merit will usually be very
different from a distribution according to equality and need.
Advocates of the merit concept of justice do not deny that there
are good ethical reasons for alleviating need, but they say that
this is a matter of charity or generosity, not of justice. Advocates
of the equality-need concept do not deny that there can be good
ethical reasons for rewarding merit. but they say that this is a
matter of social uti li ty. nOl justice.
[s there any rational method of deciding between these rival
conceptions of distributive justice? I myself think that attention
to the history of the concept of justice can give us good reason to
accept both, though we have to recognize that they are not easily
accommodated to each other and remain the focus of competing
political ideologies. John Rawls's theory of justice, however, is in
effect a supposedly rational method of deciding the confict in
favour of the equal ity-needs conception of justice. He does not
himself present his theory in these terms. but I think it is in fact
an underlying theme.
Dispute between advocates of the two conceptions tends to get
bogged down in appeal to intuitive feelings of what is just or fair.
Rawls wants 1 0 avoid that and to produce instead an objective
argument which everyone will accept. The most novel and most
striking feature of his theory is his use of the idea of social can
tract. In the earlier history of political philosophy, the social
contract has been used to justify political obligation, the obligation
of a citizen to ohey the laws of his State. The social contract
theory said that citizens are obliged to obey because they have
promised to do so. ( l gave a brief account of the theory i n 1 . 1
and shall discuss i t ml're flilly i n 7. 3. ) Rawls adapts the idea to
Justice \47
an agreement about justice. He suggests that we can best lInder
stand the notion of justice by thinking of it as a set of principles
that would be agreed upon by everyone if they had to decide. in
a hypothetical 'original posi tion'. what should be the rules for
distributing benefts and burdens in societ y. The hypothetical orig
inal position is one i n which the participants are all faced wi th a
'veil of ignorance' about particular facts. They are supposed to
have knowledge of the general laws of psychology and the social
sciences. but they do not know thc historical date or geographical
location of their society, nor do they know anything about the
individual capacities or social position of themselves or others.
Rawls asks us to assume that they will form their judgement wi th
an eye to self-interest. Since nobody knows whether he wi ll be
lucky or unlucky, ri ch or poor, clever or stupid, everyone will
think i t prudent to provide adequately for the worst possible case.
since i t might turn out to be their lot. And that. Rawls concludes,
is justice. a set of rules which everyone would accept as 'fnir'. The
rules would be accepted by everyone. thinking only of their own
self-interest, because the veil of ignorance puts everyone i n the
same boat when planning for the future. At the same time the
planning would have regard to all possible positions i n society
because the veil of ignorance makes any such position equally
possible for any individual.
What principles would be agreed upon in thi s hypothetical situ
ation? According to Rawls. the contractors would i n the frst place
go for equality of rights and duties. and notably equality of liberty
since they would regard liberty as the most basic of rights. Then
secondly, departures from equality would be approved if they
brought benefit to people in al l social positions but espccially to
the least advantaged members or the society. With this second
principle Rawls is thinking of the fact that economic enterprise
can bring large fortunes to a few. together with an increase of
employment and prosperity for the many: although the change
i ntroduces or enlarges inequality. it is justifed l)ecause the poorer
group are better off than they were before. It is plain that Rawls's
analysis of uistributive justice is v\ version of the equality-needs
concept. It makes equali ty basic ancl then emphasizes the needs
of the poor when justi fying departures from equality. Merit does
not come into the picture.
Apart from the theoretical interest of Rawls's social contract
1 1! 41 J f+1 x_ 144 +%44 ,, .._.. _
with its veil of ignorance. the theory has seemed attractive (to
many economists. for example) because it acknowledges the
strength of the capitalist argument for economic growth despite
inequality. while at the same time i t emphasizes the moral claims
of the poor. It also conducts the argument in terms of a calculation
of rational self-interest. the standard procedure of classical eco
nomic theory.
But do Rawls's conclusions in fact come simply from a rational
calculation of this kind? An i nitial principle of equality is rational
for contractors faced with the veil of ignorance. for it wi l l ensure
that they are not disadvantaged i f they land up i n one social
position rather than another. It is also rational for them to accept
departures from equality for the sake of an increase of beneft i n
al l social positions. But why should the departures focus especially
upon the least advantaged members of society as being most
essenti al for the receipt of additional beneft? Rawls calls his
criterion 'maxi mi n', the maximum of welfare for those who have
the least, the mi ni mum. i n society. There is of course no doubt
that a decent compassion (incorporated into one i ntui ti ve notion
of justice) approves of maxi mi n. giving special emphasis to the
needs of the poor. But why should a rational calculation of self
interest do so? Because. Rawls supposes. rational self-interest
counsels a policy of playing safe: you might land up at the bottom
of the social hierarchy. so it is prudent to make that position as
comfortable as possi ble. But why should rational self-interest play
absolutely safe and go for maximi n? It would indeed be irrational
to leave open the possi bility that you might land up i n a harsh
situation of starvation. But suppose you have the choice between
(a) a rather dull. roughly equalitarian. society. where nobody is
badly off and nobody has the excitement of real wealth either,
and (b) a mixed welfare-capitalist society. where nobody will fall
below the standard of basic subsistence. many will be i n a position
of adequate comfort . and a few lucky people will strike gold and
have the excitement of enjoying whatever luxuries appeal to them.
Why i s it more rational. i n terms of self-interest. to choose the
frst rather than the second? If you are unlucky, you wi ll be less
well off in the second society than in the frst . but l i fe will be
tolerabl". and the possibility of that measure of disadvantage has
10 be sci against the chance of winning one of the glittering prizes.
Is il irrational 10 have a bil of a gamble. so long as you will nol
suffer greatly if you arc unlucky') Why would a rational person
always play safe?
The supposition that the contractors will do so is i n fact incon
sistent with Rawls's version of the initial principle of equality.
where he gives priority of value to liberty. Rational self-interest
would say that the most basic value is staying alive and so would
put the means of subsistence before liberty. Ra)'/ls acknowledges
this but says that. once a certain level of malerial satisfaction has
been reached, human beings will prefer liberty to material benefit.
This implies that the participants to the social contract are pre
pared to run a bit of a risk. They will hope that priority for liberly
will enable them to preserve at least the necessary minimum of
material comfort. but they cannot be sure. They could be Slife
only if they played safe and gave priority to material comfort. In
any event it is by no means certain Ihat rational self-interest would
necessarily rate liberty above malerial comfort. The tradition of
modern western society puts liberty al Ihe lop of our scale of
values, but perhaps thi s is becausc Ihe spokesmen of values in
our society have not had to face starvation: Ihey have known
i ntolerance and persecution but not famine. If you were to ask
people in underdeveloped countries of Africa whether they value
liberty (meaning freedom of movement. freedom of expression,
democratic government) more than I ht: certainty of food. shelter.
and health, their answer is likely tn he No .
Rawls's version of both the i ni t ial equalilY principle and the
qualifying inequality principle seems 1 0 be i nRuenced by his own
cultural background rather than to refect the choice of a person
under the veil of ignorance. wi l h no knowledge of hi s particular
psychology and society. Maybe it i s senseless 10 tal k of a choice
made by such an abstraction. At any rate wc cannot say that the
result which Rawls gives us is the vnice of p\re reaSOn with no
predileclions fed i n.
The second recent theory of justice which has at t racted particu
lar attenlion i s that of Robert Nozick in his b"ok Anarch\,. State.
and Utopia. The primary aim of this hook is 10 advocate a minimal
State, confning itself 10 the old negative funclion of protecting
liberty, while lcaving Ihe positive rromotion of welfare to private
initiative. This altempt to put the clock hack has won little support
from other scholars. But in the course of the argument Nozick
has a long chapter on justice which has impressed many readers.
1)U rroDlems OJ rotlflCal rnuosopny
The chapter i s connected to his general theme because i t denies
that the State needs to go beyond the protection of liberty in order
to achieve distributive justice. Nozick argues that the common
conception of distributive justice as a requirement to shape society
according to a predetermined pattern (of equality, or of rewarding
merit, or of meeting needs) i s mistaken. Justice i n society i.s not
a matter of imposing a pattern or pursuing an 'end state' , a fxed
goal. Justice i n society is to be understood historicaly; it is the
result of free choices that individuals have made.
This highlights an aspect of justice that has been neglected i n
the theorizing of the past century or so. The law's conception of
justice connects the concept with rights or entitlements. Nozick
regards thi s as the essence of justice and brings out its specifc
historical character. Entitlements depend on what has been done
in the past. Justice, according to Nozick, i s concered wi t h 'hold
ings' (meaning property, but not necessarily material property).
A holding i s just if (a) it has been justly acquired without having
been prcviollsly held by someone else, or (b) i t has been justly
transferred from one person to another, or (c) it i s the rectification
of an injustice. the correction of an acquisition or transfer which
was not itself just. All holdings are just if they are the result of
just acquisition or just transfer or the rectifcation of injustice.
What is a just acquisition? As in his theory of the State, Nozick
revives, wi th some modifcation, the views of the seventeenth
century thinker John Locke. If a thing i s not already 'held' by
someone else, i t may justly be 'appropriated', provided that this
does not leave others worse off than they were before,
What is a just transfer? Anyone who has a just holding is
entitled to transfer it so as to become a holding of someone else,
The owner is entirely free to make whatever transfers he pleases.
If, however, he acquired the holding unjustly, then any transfer
that he may make is unjust.
As for rectifcation, Nozick is presumably thinking of decisions
by courts to restore to the rightful owner holdings which have
been unjustly taken from hi m, by fraud or theft, for example.
Noziek appreciates that often i f would be i ntolerably diffcult to
determine whether a particular holding was justly acquired or
transferr-ed i n the past .
Despite the acknowledged practical diffculties of giving any
thing like full effect to the theory, the conception of jllSt entitle-
ments has been more clearly spelled out by Noziek than by any
earlier thinker. It should certainly be included i n any adequate
account of justice. Nozick. however. goes further and claims that it
should be the whole of the account; acceptance of the entitlements
conception leaves no room for the addition of a patterned plan
of distributive justice. He explains why by means of an impressive
illustration.
Suppose that a patterned form of distributive justice has been
achieved. I t might be any form, but for the sake of simplicity let
us suppose that i t is an equal distribution. Everybody has an equal
amount of money or other goods, to be thei r own, to use as they
please. Now suppose that a champion basketball player, Wilt
Chamberl ai n, contracts t o join a particular lear for a year, on
condition that 25 cents from the price of each entry ti cket should
go to hi m. Lots of people want to see Wilt Chamberlain play;
they gladly put 25 cents of the admission charge i nto a special box
for Wilt Chamberlain. At the end of the year, one million people
have paid to watch him play, and he has earned $250,000, a much
larger income than anyone else has. There i s no equality now.
But i f the original distribution was just, is not the fnal position
also just? Everyone was given his equal shure t o use as he pleased.
Nobody can complain because some have chosen t o act in such a
way as to make Wilt Chamberlain rich.
The argument provides confrming evidence I h
i
H the enti tlement
conception is a vali d feature of justice, and therefore i t refutes
any suggestion that distributive ju
'
>tin: is ni l that need be con
sidered. But the argument does nOI prove that a distributive con
ception cannot also be a valid feature of justice. In Noziek's
example. the departure from the preferred 'end state' i s just,
because the actions which cause the change are themselves just.
But i f a great disparity i n good fortune comes about by chance
and not as the result of deliberate choice on the part of those
involved, we might well think of it as unfair or unjust. We often
say, for example, that nature is unfair when we see a striking
disparity in the taients or physical appearance of different mem
bers of the same family. This idea. of course. does not imply that
the State should take on the job of ironing out such disparities,
which is what Nozick assumes to be the point of a concept of
distributive jU!tice. There are. however, circumstances i n which
some responsible person or body may feel an Obligation to try to
>"
1OX IIOOMIt V) tt&&.4 t t +-x _-_y
reduce or compensate for an unfairness that is not the result of a
just deliberate choice. I f one child i n a family happens to be less
well endowed or less fortunate than another, the parents may feel
a special obligation to redress the balance so far as they can. I t
i s perfectly proper for them to t hi nk of i t i n terms of justice or
fairness. And i f a responsible authority in a wider society is judged
to have a duty to help those who, through no choice of their own,
are relatively disadvantaged, there is nothing in Nozick's argument
to stop us from thinking of the duty as one of justice or fairness
rather than of simple charity. Justice certainly includes Nozick's
conception of entitlement, but it also includes ideas of conser
vation and ideas of reformation on grounds of fairess,
6
Sovereignty, Power, and
Authority
6. 1 Stnte sovereignty
In the modern world we speak of 'sovereign States', Not all states
are sovereign States. Those that are constituent members of a
federal commonwealth or union do not possess sovereignty, since
they are subject. except in certain limited felds of action, to the
sovereignty of the federal State or union. The sovereignty which
is attributed to States that are not constituent members of a
federal sovereign State. is particularly important in regard to inter
national relations, State sovereignty ha not always been a feature
of international society in the past. and it may not always be so
i n the future. For three or four ccnturies. however, State sover
eignty has been an essential factor of politics, and that position is
likely to remain for some ti me to come. I t is. therefore of some
importance to be clear what the concept means and what it does
not mean,
A much disputed question in political science is where the
sovereignty of a State is located. Does i t reside in a legislature
which is empowered to make statutes that can override rules of
common law or rcpeal earlier statutes? Or i n a supreme court
that can determine whether an Act of the legislature is consti
tutional? Or does it reside in the constitution itself, or in the body
that is empowered to amend the constitution? Hence we hear of
'the sovereignty of Parliament' Or sometimes of 'the sovereign
people'. I shali not be concerned with this tricky question. but
with the meaning of 'sovereignty" when applied to the State as a
whole. The activities of the State are divided among different
bodies. none of which may be sllpreme in all respects. In relation
L rrOOtems OJ romlCUI rnliuJupny
to other associations, however, and t o other States, the State as
a whole is regarded as sovereign.
Sovereignty means supremacy. But supremacy of what? In 2.S
(el I defned sovereignty in terms of legal authority. To say that
the State is sovereign is t o say that its rules, the laws, have fnal
authority; there i s no appeal from them t o any more ultimate set
of rules, while the rules made by other associations are subordi
nate to the authority of the State's rules. A number of political
theorists would say that although this concept of legal sovereignty
is doubtless of use to lawyers, it has little relevance to politics, for
which we need a di fferent concept, that of political sovereignty, to
be defned in terms of power instead of legal authority.
I t is certainly a mistake t o suppose that legal sovereignty has
little relevance to politics, as may be seen from debate about the
loss of sovereignty on joining a combination of States like the
European Community. It affects the legislature as well as the
courts. People i n Britain who are worried about giving up part of
our sovereignty to the European Community are concerned that
Parliament should retain its independence i n being able to legislate
for the particular conditions of the United Kingdom. I n accepting
the Treaty of Rome and the subsequent Single European Act, the
UK Parliament agreed to limit the exercise of its own legislative
authority over a range of economic affairs. I t also agreed to accept
the European Court, set up by the Treaty of Rome, as the fnal
authority, superior t o all British courts, on European Community
Law as applied to the United Kingdom. The partial loss of sover
eignty that is i nvolved is therefore both political and juridical .
Constitutionally the UK Parliament retains its sovereign authonty
i n that it could. i f it chose. repeal its acceptance of the Treaty of
Rome; but for all practical purposes it has divested itself of a part
of its sovereignty, understood as meaning unlimited supreme legal
authority.
This example makes it perfectly clear that legal sovereignty is
not just a mailer for lawyers but is very much concerned with
politics also. However, 1 think we must go further than that.
The so-called concept of political sovereignty, defned i n terms of
power, is simply a confusion. Power is undoubtedly essential for
polit ics;- and for law too. but I do not think that State sovcreignty
can be understood as anything other than legal sovereignty.
f
i
)
i
I
,
,
6.2 The power theory
Let me put the case for a power theory of sovereignty by consider
ing why the legal concept may be supposed defective for the
purposes of politics. Legal sovereignty treats the Stat e. or the
State's system of law, as a fnal legal authority. The concept is to
be understood from a legal point of view. From a moral point of
view, one may say that the laws of the State do not have fnal
authority. If an individual's conscience tells him that he ought not
to obey some particular law, then, from a moral point of view _
he is entitled to disobey, for in most matters of morals (some
would say. in all matters of morals) the flnal authority is con
science. But he i s not legally entitled to disobey. If he were,
then the law which i s i n question would not have ultimate legal
authority; to say that he is legally entitled to disobey is to imply
that there i s a superior law which permits disobedience t o the
particular law.
We can illustrate the difference by the example of conscientious
objection to military service. When there is conscription. a law
makes all ft men of certain ages. and perhaps women too, liable
to be called up for military service. If an individual has a properly
conscientious objection to military service. he i s moraHy entitled
to refuse to perform i t. Is he also legally entitled t o refuse'? That
depends on the law of the country concerned. I f. as i s the case i n
some countries. the law makes no provision for conscientious
objection. he is not legally entitled to refuse to serve: but it is a
matter of conscience. i . e. of moral judgement. for hi m to decide
what, morally. he ought to do. taki ng account of the fact that
there is, i n general, a moral obligation to obey the law. though
this obligation may on occasion conflict with some other moral
Obligation. If the individual decides that his moral duty is to
disobey the law, the State is still legally entitled t o subject hi m
to the penalties prescribed for breaking thi s l aw; and i n some
circumstances the individual may even consider that he is morally
as well as legally obliged to accept the prescribed penalties. In
Britain, however. when we havl conscri ption. it is accnmpanied
by legal provision for conscientious objection. Our conscription
law has said that all ft men of certain agcs are liable to be
called up for military service lin less (among other exceptions)
they establish to the satisfaction bf a tribunal that they have a
156 Problems of Political Philosophy
conscientious objection. An individual i s therefore legally, as well
as morally, entitled to refuse to serve because of a conscientious
objection. But the legal provision covers only such conscientious
objection as i s recognized by a tribunal. If an individual fails to
satisfy a tribunal that he has a conscientious objection, he i s legally
obliged to obey a calling-up notice, but he himself may decide
that he is morally obliged to refuse, in which case he is legally
liable to the penalties prescribed by the State.
I t wi ll be seen, then, that the assignment of fnal authority is
made from a certain point of view. I t may be t he legal point of
view or it may be the moral point of view. Now the idea of State
sovereignty as I have previously described it, the idea that the
laws of the State are a fnal authority, i s taken from the legal
point of view, and this means from the point of view of the State
itself, since the law simply i s the set of rules whereby the State
conducts its affairs. Clearly i t i s possible for a different association
or community to hold similarly that, from its own point of view,
it is the fnal authority. Just as an individual may say that, from
the moral point of view, his own conscience is the fnal authority,
so a Church may say t hat , [rom the religious point of view, its
own rules are the fnal authority. Furthermore, a Church may also
say that there is no aspect of life that falls outside the scope of
religion. Consequently, it i s possible for a Church to maintain
that political decisions are subordinate to religious judgement ,
and that the rules of t he Church are more authoritative t han those
of the State.
This is what was claimed by the Pope in the Middle Ages. The
confict between Pope and Emperor was one i n which each side
claimed to be the superior authority. At that time there would
not have been general agreement that States were sovereign. i .e.
supreme authorities. When all the Kings of Christendom acknow
ledged obedience to the Pope, their own authority was not
supreme: it was a subordinate authority. But when the medieval
structure of societv broke down, there was a need for recognition
of a new form of

upreme authority, and each State claimed such


authority for itself: that is to say, i claimed to be i ts own master
and subject to no dictation by any higher authority. Thus the
doctrine of State sovereignty arose together with the rise of separ
ate national States, owing to the breakdown of the universal
organized community of Christendom.
In the confict between Church and State. each side claimed
authority, but in practice the State won out because of its superior
power. It should be noted that 'power' in this connection means
not simply the ability to have one's will carried out, but the ability
to do so by the threat of force. The superior power of the State
was the power of force of arms. Consequently some people would
say that the only concept of State sovereignty that really counts
is a matter of power in this sense, and not a matter of authority.
Any associ ation or community mny claim to be a fnal authority
from its own point of view, and any individual may claim the
same for his own judgement of what he ought to do. The thing
that really counts. however. i t would be sai d, is the power to
enforce such a claim. The individual may claim that he is entitled
to disobey the law, but the State has the power to force him to
comply with its requirements. I said earlier that a conscientious
objector who has not been able to satisfy the State authorities
may think himself morally enti tled or obliged to disobey the law,
and also morally obliged to accept the \egal penalties. He will
take the latter view if he acknowledges that he has a general
moral obligation to conform to the State's requirements evcn
though he thinks that thi s general obligation is overridden, i n
regard t o the performance of military service. by the obligation
not to take human life. But of course an individual's conscientious
objection may be wider than that . and he may consider that he
has no moral obligation to accept the legal penalties. In that
event. if he is imprisoned. the penalty is forcibly i mposed on hi m.
Similarly a Church may consiucr that the State does not have the
right to restrict its activities; but the State has power. while the
Church has not; and so the Church, it may be said, is forced into
SUbjection to the State.
It i s for such reasons as these that some theorists speak of a
concept of 'political sovereignty' distinct from legal sovereignty.
The argument i s designed to show that the sovereignty of the
State should be defined. for the purposes of politics, as supremacy
of coercive power rather than of legal authority. Does the argu
ment succeed in showing this" That the possession of coercive
power is essential for a State goes without saving. The question is
whether State sovereignty or supremacy is a supremacy of coercivc
power. The argument certainly docs show that sovereignty cannot
be defned as the caim to supreme authority. for different associ-
158 Problems of Political Philosophy
ations or communities may make conficting claims t o thi s effect,
and the one that i s sovereign is the one that can substantiate its
claim. The question then becomes, what substantiates a claim to
supreme authority? And the answer now suggested is, supremacy
of coercive power.
6.3 Objections to the power theory
I do not thi nk i t can be correct to say that State sovereignty
consists in supremacy of coercive power, and that thi s and only
this substantiates the State's claim to supreme authority. Supreme
power i s neither ( 1 ) a necessary nor (2) a suffcient condition for
substantiating the claim. Let us look at each of these objections
in turn.
( l ) Supremacy of coercive power is not always necessary to
substantiate a claim to supreme authority. This can best be seen
in international relations. I grant that the State's claim to supreme
authority wi thi n its own domain can usually be effective only if
the State has at its command coercive power superior to that of
any other association or group wi thi n its jurisdiction. There are
occasional exceptions, but generally speaking the authority of the
State and its laws will not last unless backed by superior power.
This, however, was true also i n the days before States were
thought of as sovereign States. The idea of sovereignty has its
point chiefy i n regard to a State's relationship to authoritative
bodies that are not located wi thi n its own domain, namely, other
States and international authorities such as a universal Church or
an i nternational legal or political organization. I t is therefore
perfectly proper to point out that, in international relations, the
concept of State sovereignty docs not require a supremacy of
coercive power. To say nothing for the moment of great and small
powers, a few States. such as Liechtenstein and San Marino, have
virtually no power at all. so far as international relations are
concerned, yet they are sovereign States, No doubt they would
not remain so if powerful neighbouring States chose to invade
them and take over. Still, they do i n fact exist as sovereign States
with very little power by international reckoning.
Advocates of the power theory of sovereignty may say that
these are not reaJ or effective States; they are toy States. mere
pretenees that depend fo t hei r existence on the good pleasure of
SOI'ereigllly. Power, and Authori!), 159
States proper, i . e. of powerful States. But consider where this
line of argument would lead. The power theory is the view that
sovereignty consists in supremacy of coercive power, that is to
say, of power suffcient to allow a State to formulate and carry
out its policies without having its freedom of action limited by
any other body capable of exercising power. This wi ll imply that
the only States possessing sovereignty are those that used to be
called Great Powers and are now more often called Superpowers.
I recall a discussion. at an international political science con
gress in 1 96 1 , between Professor Hans J. Morgenthau and Pro
fessor Raymond Aron. It was about the notion of a 'viable' State
not about sovereignty. but it can be applied to the power thear;
of sovereignty. Morgenthau had written that Britain and France
were no longer viable States, as they had been before the Second
World War, because their freedom of action (e.g. in the Suez
operation of 1956) was limited by the policies of the USA and
the USSR. Aron retorted that this implied that, of the 100 or
more States existing at that time. only two were 'viable' while the
rest were 'non-viable'. Morgenthau's thesis, he pointed out. was
simply a novel and misleading way of saying (what everyone would
accept) that therc were now only two Great Powers and that
Britain and France had ceased to be Great Powers. Nevertheless,
ATOn added. Britain and France, and most of the others, managed
to carry on as States and so were viable.
A holder of the power theory of sovereignty i s obliged to say
the same sort of thing as Morgenthau said. Britain and France
used to command enough power to give them freedom of action
i n carrying out their policies. but now their freedom of action is
limited by the superior power of the USA and Soviet Uni on; so
that only Superpowers nre really sovereign powers. The so-called
s

vercignlY of other States is a prctcl1Cc, depending on the good


Will of States that rcally have sovereign power.
Even a Superpower does not nurmally have complete freedom
of action. Each of the two Superpowers in the present-day world
has its freedom of action limited by the power of the othr. That
is what is meant by 'the balance of power'. The only ki nd of State
that would have complete freedom of action would be one that
controlled an empire over all those peoples with whom i t had any
effective contact. as Rome did in the frst centuries of the Christian
era. Rut the kind of limitation i mposed by a balance nf power is
>
'
`
16 Problems of Foliflcaf rnllosopny
comparable to the territorial l i mi tation on legal sovereignty. The
legal authority of each State is confned to its o;n territory and is
balanced by the equal authority of other States 10 theIr temtones.
Supremacy of legal authority does not mean an authority that is
superior to any other existing authority, but one that is not inferior
or subordinate to any other. In the same way the freedom of
action of a Superpower is limited to its own sphere of infuence
and is balanced by the equal freedom of other Superpowers in
their spheres of infuence. Supremacy of power will mean power
that is not inferior to that exercised by another State. It wi l l
accordingly be confned to Superpowers.
Obviously Superpowers do have a key position in world politics.
and i f the power theory were simply telling us that the formal
equality of the legal sovereignty of all States is unreal when it
comes to determining political issues in international relations. we
should all agree. But this is not to explain the meaning of the
concept of State sovereignty, which is not restricted to Super
powcrs and is not intended to be so restricted by those who
interpret it in tcrms of cQcrcive power.
(2) I turn now to the second leg of my criticism of the power
theory. Supremacy of coercive power is not sufcient to substan
tiate a claim to supreme authority. This too can be i l lustrated
from international relations. i f we think of the circumstances in
which a State will be given or refused recognition by other States.
The exercise of effective control over a territory is a necessary
but not a suffcient condition. The point of the criticism can be
seen more clearly. however, i f we look this time at the internal
situation of a State.
Thomas Hobbes' i n the seventeenth century employed an argu
ment to the effect that power alone is not suffcient to substantiate
political authority, or. as he put it, to constitute 'dominion'.
Hobbes is often supposed to have held a power theory of sover
eignty, but it scems to me that the main point of his theory is that
both power and the acknowledgement of authority are necessary.
Hobbes does take the view that the dominion of God is constituted
by power alone; or at least he does so i n some of his remarks
about God. He says that the power of God is irresistible, and that
this in itself both explains and justifes God's dominion over the
See especially l,et'iarhan, chapters 20, 3 1 .
whole world of nature. including mankind. But i n the relations
between man and man, 110 one person and no body of persons is
in the position of God. namely of being able to exercise irresistible
power everywhere all the time: alld this fact is what makes the
possession of pover insuffcient for rolitical dominion.
Not that Hobbes is blind to the importance of power i n politics.
In one of his books' he compares the exercise of political authority
to playing a trump at cards. and adds, 'save that, i n matter of
government, when nothing else is turned up. clubs are trumps.
(Hobbes probably thought of this trenchant epigram i n recollect
ing a story about his father, who was a parson but not a shining
example of the dot h. Cards were morc to his taste th<111 books.
After sitting up late one Saturday night playing cards. he fell
asleep during the church service next morning and apparently
dreamt of card-playing. for he suddenly called out loudly. ' Clubs
are trumps. ' ) Notice that Hobbess own use of the phrase is that
dubs are trumps in politics 'when nothing else is turned up' , If
nobody has a regular trump card, a regular claim t o political
authority, such as popular consent or hereditary succession. then,
but only then. power flls the vacuum.
Although Hobbes is fully apprised of the importance of power.
he thinks it is essential to distinguish between power and
dominion. He says that a captive or a slave is i n his master's
power, but is not thereby a subject, as i s a citizen or a servant. A
subject is one who acknowledges that his master has the right.
not just the power. to issue orders. and that he himself is obliged,
not just compelled. to obey. A captive or a slave obeys because
he must. but i f he is not chained and if he has the chance to
escape when his master' s back is turned. there is no reason why
he should not take i t . A servant. unlike a slave, works under a
contract of service and is thereby obliged to do his master's wi l l
even when he is not bei ng watched; and according to Hobbes. a
citizen differs from a captive i n the same way. Of course men
may become subjects of a new sovereign as the result of conquest.
and Hobbes went so far as to say that i r the people of a country
are conquered in war and submit to the superior power of the
conqueror. they become subjects. i . e. they are obliged to obey
their new ruler. only because they can be presumed to have
Di(lo/le f,((II'r'fI D Phi/o.ropher and a Swdrm of fhe Common Laws of Englrmlf,
162 Problems of Political Philosophy
tacitly promised obedience and to be morally obliged through that
promise. They have made the presumptive promise through fear
of being killed, so that the promise has been extorted by force.
But without the promise. Hobbes held, there would be no obli
gation and no dominion.
This looks like a distinction without a di fference. Hobbes says
that the subjects must be supposed to be obliged by a promise.
made through fear of the conqueror's power, and that without
the promise they would not be subjects. But i s there any real
di fference between a captive who obeys from fear of his masters
power, and a subject who is said to have given a tacit promise
from fear of the conqueror's power? The distinction seems to be
one of words only, as i n John Harington's epigram:
Treason doth never prosper: what's the reason?
For if i t prosper, none dare call i t treason.
In fact . however. there is more to Hobbess distinction than
that. I t would be a distinction without a difference only i f t he
ruler could exercise his power all the time over everyone. that i s.
i f he had the sort of universal, irresistible power that Hobbes has
described God as having. Consider what coercive power usually
means i n a political context. It i s not actual physical forcing, as
when a stronger man presses a weaker man's fnger on the trigger
of a gun. thereby causing a third person to be shot. Some use of
this kind of enforcement is made by offcers of the State. as when
a man who resists the police is dragged off to the police station,
and as when convicted criminals are forcibly confned i n one place
by prison walls and bars. But more frequently the exercise of
coercive power in a political context is inducing a man to obey
your will from fear of the consequences i f he does not. Most men
who are arrested 'eome quietly'. because they know that the police
can frogmarch them if they do not. Now a ruler (or a body of
rulers) who possesses coercive power, i . e. who has the means to
make people obey him from fear of unpleasant consequences if
they do not , cannot be applying that power to all of them all the
ti me. He cannot havc armed soldiers or burly policemen standing
guard o
v
er all his subjects continually i n order to compel them to
obey his commands. \Ve all know that i n a crime thriller the villain
is knocked out as snon as his eye or his gun wavers. If a ruler
j
S(w('n'I'lty, Pl1\r, and AllflJrirr 163
were to rely on coercive power alone, he would need to have a
gun pointed vigilantly all the time at each of his subjects. As in a
closed prison, there would need to be a permanent deterrent to
escape or revolt. Even in a prison. unless the cells were never
unlocked, the governor could not exercise power over the pris
oners if he did not have the willing ohedience of the warders.
Even i f a tyrant could have armed soldiers standing guard over
every citizen. the obedience of f he soldiers themselves could not
be an enforced obedience. As D.n-id Hume' sai d, he must lead
the soldiers, at least. by thei r ""pi ni on'; and as Plato' said long
before. a band of robbers ean be successful in terrorizing the
populace only jf there is an unforced loyalty among themselves.
But in any event, a State. even a totali tari an State, cannot be run
like a prison in most respects. To some ext ent at any rate. there
must be a willing. o at least an uncompelled. obedience. which
means an aCknowledgement of authori t y. The laws of the State
do indeed have the threat of force behind t hem; but if it were
necessary to use that force on every occasion when there was the
possibility of disobedience to the law. the system would break
down. In fact. most people conform to the law because they
recognize its authority and accept that they ought to obey.
A claim to authority may be acknowledged for di fferent
reasons. One rcason (and it often applies) is t he effective exercise
of power. This is the truth that lies behind the theory t hat power
substantiates authority. 1 f a ruler (or a group) seizes power, he
(or they) may at frst be called a usurper. and later be acknow
ledged as sovereign. Those who are in his power may sa\: 'We
submit: we accept your jurisdiction because you have t'he power:
This is what Hobbes has in mind with his tacit promise at the
establishment of dominion by cnquest . His point can be seen
clearly i n the signing of an ins.t rument of surrender by the re
present atives of a nati on defeated i n war. That document re
presents Hobbes's 'L'O\'Cnant ' . The defeated nation is commi tted,
by a sort of promise. to abi di ng bv condi t i\n> lai d clO\"'11 bv the
conqueror. The conditions arc cepted under duress. hut the
i nstrument of surrender is ne\'crtheless expected to remain binding
after the conqueror has withdrawn his troops.
_
S

ere

_.

:.
methi ng in t il(' power t heory. But the effective
" Of the First Principles of Goverl1l{' l l l ' J.Hl.\'\. A1om'. Political. ami Literary.
ltfIIh/ic, I (.151c-j.
16 Problems of Political Philosopny
control of power i s not th, only reason for acknowledgng a claim
to authority. Authority
m
ay be acknowledged on other grounds,
such as hereditary succession or general consent (this last without
any thought, because i t may not be true, that the consent of a
majority means the support of their power if i t comes to a fght).
And although the control of coercive power wi l l often cause
people to acknowledge a claim to authority, it does not always
do so. If the power i s exercised i n a thoroughly brutal and unjust
way, many of the people within the country may refuse to
acknowledge the claim to authority, preferring resistance to sub
mission even though the chances of successful resistance are slight.
Other States similarly will tend to refuse de jure recognition to
the new regime even though they may allow that de facto i t has
effective controL
It remains true nevertheless that the kind of authority whieh
the State exerts cannot be exercised without some use of coercive
power and without the ever-present possibility of falling back on
enforcement when need arises. If men could be trusted always to
act on decisions reached as among the Quakers, by fnding 'the
sense of the meeting' , the exercise of power would not be necess
ary. This is what is implied in Marxist theory when it is said that
eventually the State will 'wither away', i . e. that when men reach
the stage of always guiding their action by reference to the
common good, they will agree of their own accord and will not
need to be compelled. In a religious community, and often i n a
well-conducted family, authority, whether i t be the authority of
one person or that of majority opinion, can be acknowledged and
followed without the backing of power to enforce i t . But in the
general affairs of society this is not so, and therefore the State
needs to possess coercive power to back its authority.
The authority of the State is of course the authority of law, and
the laws of the State, as I said in 2.S(d, differ from the rules of
other associations and communities both by depending on force
and by having sovereign authority. Force or coercive power is
essential for law as well as for other aspts of politics, but the
sovereignty of the State is an attribute of the authority of State
law, not an attribute of thc force or power that the State must
wield i n order to make its svstem of law or its policies effective.
6.4 Power and autbority
It is important to be clear about the distinction between power
and authority, since they are often confused, in language as well
as in thought. We speak of a statute giving a Minister 'power' t o
do this or that, when we mean giving hi m authority. Similarly we
speak of going beyond one's 'legal powers or acting 'ultra vires' ,
where again the word 'authority' would express our meaning more
clearly. The looseness of usage appears right at the beginning of
the theoretical discussion of sovereignty. in the work of Jean
Bodin' in the sixteenth century. Bodin writes: 'Sovereignty is the
absolute and perpetual power (plIi.<sance) of a State, . . . that is
to say, the supreme power to command. It is here necessary to
formulate the definition of sovereignty, because there is no jurist
or political philosopher who has defned it. although it is the
principal feature and the one most necessary to be understood in
the treatment of the State.' He goes on to speak further of 'puiss
ance souverlline' and 'puissance ahsolue'. and so gives the
impression that sovereignty is a matter of power i n the ordinary
sense of the word. Now anybody has the power or ability to issue
a command, but not everyone is authorized or entitled to do so
in particular circumstances. and nol everyone is either able or
entitled to have his commands carried out. Does Bodin mean by
'absolute power' the ability to issue effective commands, i . e. the
ability to have onc's commands carried out? This would be power,
properly speaking. Or does he mean the entitlement or right to
issue commands and to have them obeyed? This would be auth
ority. A reading of the whole of hi s account of sovereignty makes
it dear that he means the second, but his use of the expression
'absolute power' suggests the first.
The most general meaning of 'p" wer' is simply ability. This may
be seen from the French term '"ot'oir and the Latin 'polestGs' !
both of which are derived from the verb ' to be able' (pall voir,
posse) . It is because of this general meaning of 'power' that we
can use the same word for the power of a dynamo, willpower,
or political power. Let us call this meaning of the word, senSe
( I ) . When we speak of power in a social context, however. we
are usually thinking of a specific kind of ability, the ability to
Le Six U's de In repilbliq/le. 1 . R.
I
I
166 Problems of Polirical Philosophy
make other people do what one wants them to do, Let us call
this, sense (2). Power in sense (2) may depend on different things,
A man may be able to get others to do what he wants, because
he has the gift of the gab, or because they trust hi m for his wisdom
or his integrity, or because he holds a special offce, or because
he has the strength to make things unpleasant for them if they
refuse. All four of these reasons have a place in the exercise of
political power, but Ihe last of the four is especially prominent i n
situations of confict. This last i s coercive power, using the threat
of superior force to make others do what you want them to do
when they are unwilling, Let us call this, sense (3). Because
coercive power is so prominent in political confict, the word
'power', which al frst simply meant ability of any ki nd, comes to
acquire associations with enforcement. One can see this in the
two French words pouvoi" and puissance'. Both nouns come
from the verb 'pOI/voir', but they have rather diferent conno
tations. ' POI/voir', like the English word 'power', can be used
either without or with associations of enforcement, having senses
( I ) and (2), as well as sense (3); but 'puissance
'
has a more
defnite tendency to carry overtones of might and the possibility of
coercion. Similarly Latin has the two nouns 'potestas' and 'poten
ria', both derived from the verb 'posse' , but 'potentia' often,
though not always, carries overtones of might, like 'puissance' ,
On the other hand, 'potestas' is often used to mean 'authority',
just as 'power' is, when we speak of giving someone legal 'powers'.
The reason for this should be apparent from what I have said of
the different grounds on which power in sense (2) can depend.
One of those grounds i s the fact that the person with power holds
a special offce. This means that he has authority in virtue of his
offce. If a man holds a position of authority, and i s able i n virtue
of that position to get others to do what he tells them to do, his
power in sense (2) is the exercise of authority. That is why the
word 'power' can be used to mean authority,
To have authority to do something is to have the right to do i t.
Here I must recall the distinction drawn i n 4. 4 between two
senses of the noun 'right'. When we say that a person has a right
to do something, we often simply mean that he may or is permitted
to do it, that his proposed action is not forbidden by any law or
moral rule, or that he has been expressly licensed under some law
to do actions of this kind. In this sense of the noun 'right', a right
SOI'ereigtlt)', /"'m ^ er. and Alii/lOr/I) lol
is a freedom, a permitted or licensed faci lity. I call i t a right of
action (Hohfeld called it a liberty). But secondly, we speak of
having a right when it is a right 1 0 receive something, a claim
against someone else that he has an obligation to provide what
the right-holder is entitled to receive. 1 call this kind of right a
right of recipiencc (Hohfeld called it a clai m), The French langu
age marks the distinction by usually employing the expression
'droit de' for a right of action, and 'droit I' for a right of recipience,
Now a right of recipience need not be a right to receive something
material. It may be a right to be left undisturbed, to freedom
from restraint on doing whatever one chooses to do. This is the
right to liberty, the right to be left alone by other people, It needs
to be distinguished from a right of action, a freedom or licence
to act, though usually, when we have a right of action, a freedom
to act, we also have a recipient right to freedom from interference
by others in the doing of what we are legally or morally permitted
to do. Another non-material thing to which one may have a right
of recipience is obedience, One may have a right to have one's
orders carried out . Since this is a right of rcci piencc, it is a right
against some other person or persons, and the obligation which
corresponds to the right is the obligation to carry out the orders.
Authority to give orders is this kind of right of recipience. We
do sometimes speak of being authorize

d (less often of having the


authority) to do something when we mean simply having a right
of action, but with the implication that we also have a recipient
right to be left undisturbed. If I have a driving licence, I have a
right, or have been authorized, been given formal permission, t o
drive a car. Here ' 1 have a right to' simply means ' I may'. But
when a Mi nister of the Crown is authorized (or 'empowered') by
a statute to make regulations. this not only allows him to do
something but also imposes an obligation on citizens t o conform
to the regulations that he may make. Thus it gives hi m a right to
receive obedience to his regulations and not just a right to issue
them. The authority to issue commands i s not simply a right or
permission to do something. as is a licence (or being authorized)
to drive a car: it is also a right against those to whom the com
mands are addressed that they should do what they arc com
manded to do. It is a right to receive obedience , and it corresponds
to an obligation on the part of others to give obedience.
In bolh senses, ' 3 right' or 'heing authorized' may be thought
j
I

"
!
\
I
I
I
I
I
of as a facility and so a power. I have already explained that the
power to make other people do what you require may depend on
the fact that you hold a special offce. In virtue of holding that
offce you have the authority to make certain requirements of
other people, and they do what you require because they acknow
ledge your authority. Your authority, and their acceptance of i t,
are what give you the power to make them do what you require.
We can therefore think of authority as being one species of power
in sense (2) , a species which is co-ordinate with power i n sense
(3). The possession of coercive force is one way of getting people
to do what you require, one specifc form of power in sense
(2): the possession of authority, provided it is acknowledged, is
another. It is therefore not surprising that the word 'power' should
often be used to mean authority.
A right of action may be thought of as a power in sense ( 1 ) . I t
is a facility, and so a sort of ability, to do something. We express
a person's right or permission to do something by saying that he
may do i t, and in colloquial speech 'may' is often replaced by
'can'. I n French, 'puis-je' is the regular way of saying 'may 1 ' . I n
'correct' English, however, a distinction i s made between 'may'
and 'can'. The child who asks i f he can have some more cake is
sometimes told: 'You don't need to inquire whether you can.
What you mean is to ask whether you may.
'
There is point in the
linguistic distinction. One often has the ability to do something
(whether i t be to eat cake or to borrow or steal someone else's
possessions) when one does not have permission to do i t , and at
times one has the permission without having the ability (e. g. to
ride a friend's bicycle). Nevertheless a facility or permit may be
thought of as a ki nd of ability because it signifes the absence of
a barrier that might otherwise prevent one from doing an action
and so make one unable to do it.
The barrier is, however, usually a metaphorical one. A notice
that says ' Unauthorized persons are not allowed to enter these
grounds' may be ac
c
ompanied by the physical barriers of a high
gate and walls, but the legal barrier referred to in the notice does
not actually render me unable to enter, as the gate and walls do
(unless I am agile enough to climb them). The barrier that the
notice onveys is a legal fction, and likewise to regard a permit
or licence as conveying an actual ability is a legal fction. Any rule
that says one must or may not do this and that, may be understood
as setting up a fctitious or metaphorical barrier or bond, 'obliging'
or 'binding' those to whom it is addressed, limiting their freedom
of action and so making them 'unable' to act otherwise than
prescribed. Thi s applies to moral as well as to legal obligations.
When Martin Luther said 'Here I stand: I cannot do otherwise' ,
it was not literally true that he could not. but he regarded hi s
moral commitment as a bond which left him unable to act differ
ently. Similarly the absence of a restrictive rule, or the waiving
of a rule by the grant of permission. may be understood as the
fctitious or metaphorical lifting of a fctitious or metaphorical
barrier that might otherwise limit [reedom of action, and so as
'enabling' One to do what otherwise one would be 'unable' to do.
Since legal rules are backed by cDcrcive power. the notice which
forbids me to enter private grounds carries with it the threat that
i f I do enter. I may later be subjected by imprisonment to a real
barrier on freedom of movement: but at the moment, i f the notice
is not accompanied by the real barrier of gate and wails, I can
enter the grounds if I am prepared to risk the consequences. The
fact that I may not enter is the fction that I cannot.
Legal, moral, and conventional rules (including the rules of
language) all convey fctitious bonds and absences of bonds, 'obli
gations' and 'rights', 'necessities' and 'possibil ities'. I t is not liter
ally true that one is 'obliged' or 'bound', i . e. necessitated, to
follow a rule of l aw, morals, etiquette. logic, or grammar, as one
is literally bound to
.
one place by rope, or as one is nhliged or
necessitated by a landslide to make a detour in order to reach
one's destination. These fctions of human thought and language
have their point precisely because human beings are not and
cannot be strictly necessitated in the whole of their behaviour but
have. over an area of thought and action, the ability to choose
between alternatives. It is only when one can in fact do (or
believe) either of alternative possibilities that i t makes sense to
put up or remove fctive barriers with the words 'ought' and 'may',
The relationships between the Cllncepts of power and authority
that I have so far considered arc illustrated in the ordinary lise of
language. A further source of possible confusion, however, has
been introduced into theoretical discussion by the frequent refer
ences of sociologists to a classification made by Max Weber of
. . ,

The Theory of Social and Economic Or}nniZl1lion. trans. A. M. Henderson and


Takon Parson! ( London. IW7), chapler .
1
I
I
170 Problems of Political Philosophy
three types of authority, or dominion (Herrscha[t), rational-legal,
traditional, and 'charismatic'. Rational-legal authority i s the
explicit form of what I have been talking about, a right to give
orders and to have them obeyed, i n virtue of an offce held within
a system of deliberately framed rules setting out rights and duties.
Traditional authority exists where a person such as a King or a
tribal chief holds a superior position of command in accordance
wi th long tradition, and is obeyed because everyone accepts the
sanctity of the tradition. The idea of charismatic authority is an
extension of the meaning of the Greek word 'charisma' (the gift
of divine grace) in the New Testament. As Weber uses the term, i t
means authority resting on the possession of exceptional personal
qualities that cause a person to be accepted as a leader. They may
be qualities of saintly virtue, giving their holder religious auth
ority; or they may be qualities of outstanding heroism, intellect,
or oratory, that bring a fol lowing of loyal devotion in war. politics,
or other kinds of enterprise.
Some writers on social theory have supposed that the thi rd of
these is authority in a different sense from that of the frst and
second, that it is a power or ability to command obedience, while
the other two types are examples of a right to command. I think
this mistakes the kind of difference that exists between the three
types. Weber is describing different sources of authority, not di f
ferent senses or meanings of the word. I n each of the three types
the person exercising authority is thought to have the right to
issue commands, edicts, or precepts, and the right to be obeyed,
but the right arises from different grounds. With rational-legal
authority, the right comes from a set of rules that explicitly defne
rights and duties. With traditional authority. it again comes from
a set of rules, but this time the rules are crescive'. not 'enacted'
that is to say, they have not been deliberately formulated as being
desirable or necessary, but have grown up gradually over a period
of time in which a customary practice, what is usually done, has
hardened into a normative fule, what ought to be done. With
charismatic authority, the right comes from the idea either that
the leader's special qualities make him flted to lead, or that they
are a sign that he has been authorized by a supernatural being
who is already credited with the right to command and to depute
this right to vice-gerents on earth. A person who is thought to
So\'ueignty. POH'er, and AuthorifY 1 71
possess this kind of authority has the power or ability to command
obedience only because his followers think he has the right to i t .
Whenever authority i s effectively exercised, t he person i n auth
ority possesses power i n sense ( 2) . He is able to make other
people do as he requires. But his power is not identical with his
authority, nor is it the consequence of hi s mere possession of
authority. It is the consequence rather of the acknowledgement
of his authority by those whom he commands. In the cnse of
charismatic authority such aCknowledgement is a necessary con
dition of the existence of authority, so that one who has charis
matic authority does also have power. This is not necessarily true
of rational-legal or of traditional authority. Sometimes a man is
invested with the authority of an offce i n accordance with formal
rules or with tradition, but for some reason (e . g. popular rebellion
against a King or a Government ) his nUl hority is not acknow
ledged by the majority of those who arc supposed to be subject
to i t . He then has authority without power: he has the right to
issue commands and to have them obeyed. but he is not able to
acquire obedience. Authority therefore can exist without power
it is ineffective but it answers to the concept of having a right.
Power can exist without authority. It may then be that species
of power i n sense ( 2) which i s also power i n sense (3). coercive
power. One who exercises coercive power is able to make others
do as he wills. not because they acknowledge a right, still less
because he has a right, but because they fear the consequences
of disobedience. They are obliged or 'forcee!' to obey, in the sense
i n which a driver is obliged by a landslide to make a detour.
Strictly speaking, they are not necessi tated. They stiH have the
choice of refusing to obey and taking the consequences, just as
the driver need not make the detour i f he is prepared to give up
his purpose of reaching his desired destination. But since the
consequences of disobedience, or of not making the detour, are
usually thought to be even more undesirable than the alternative
course of action, the latter is often said to be 'inevitable' or
' forced' upon us. We choose to adopt i t . though unwillingly. but
because the alternative offered is so much more contrary to what
we should willingly choose. we think of it as not being ; genuine
alternative at all and say that wc are compelled or obliged. The
robber who brandishes a gun and snys 'Your money \ vour life',
compels his victim to give up the money because the lterative
t

r
!
~^
1 I1 rruuter/. uJ ttt x U1 4 rrtLoL]-
is one that most people would not dream of accepting. Efectively
the threatened man is left with no real choice. He obeys because
he must.
Obedience from the acknowledgement of authority is also said
to be due to obligation, but here the choice i s less reluctant,
may indeed (i n the case of charismatic authority) be made with
enthusiasm, and i s a genuine choice. Where it is not so, as i n
conforming to an unpopular l aw, i t wi ll commonly be found that
the acknowledged authority goes along with the threat of coercive
power, so that the obligation to obey authority is accompanied
by the obligation ( i n the sense of compUlsion) to avoid unpleasant
consequences. The word 'Obligation' has, in part, the same mean
ing i n both uses, a requirement or 'necessity' to choose obedience.
Strictly it i s not a necessity i n either case, since there i s a choice.
But the obligation of compulsion i s much more like a necessity
because we can hardly regard the choice as a genuine one. Where
the obligation is purely due to the acknowledgement of authority,
there is an open choice, and the idea of necessity or of being
'bouno' . suggested by the word 'obligation', i s fctitious or meta
phorical. Apart from this difference, there i s also a partial differ
ence in the meaning of the word 'obligation'. When I am obliged
to do something from fear of unpleasant consequences, 1 am
simply obliged to act. But when I am obliged by the aCknowledge
ment of authority, 1 am not only obliged to act but am under
obligation 10 someone. My obligation to him corresponds to his
right against me. The fctitious 'bond' not only limits my freedom
of action but 'ties' me to another person, who has the fctitious
'power' of a recipient right or claim. When I am compelled, the
wielder of coercive power has a real power over me, but we do
not say that I am under an obligation to him or that he has a right
against me.
6.5 Sovereign authority
Although i t makes sense to speak of authority without power,
political authority which ceases to be effective tends to lapse after
a time even as authority. Since the prime purpose of political
authority is to maintain order and security i n matters of potential
confict, there seems no point i n ascribing a right to issue orders
unless they have a fair chance of attaining their purpose. If a
system of State law is to be valid law, it must in general be
effecti ve. I do not of course mean that a failure to apprehend and
convict some law-breakers renders a law invalid, but that the
system as a whole must be effective. And since one cannot expect
unanimous acknowledgement of legal authority or universal
obedience i n consequence of such acknowledgement, the auth
ority of the law has to be joined with coercive power.
Why does the authority of the State have to be supreme? Why
do we need the concept of sovereign authority? The answer to
this question that is given by Hobbes is that i n the absence of a
supreme authority there will be chaos. If two persons or bodies
of persons, each claiming authority. disagree. there is no way to
resolve the disagreement except by setting up a supreme authority
to decide disputes. Hobbes assumes that people cannot settle
disagreements by rational disclission and by mutual consideration
for each other's point of view. As we have seen, this is not always
true. It is not true of a Quakers meeting, or of any association
or community based on love, or friendship, or mutual respect.
Nevertheless it is true of much that goes on in social life, and this
is why a fnal arbiter of disputes is needed if they arc not to be
settled by fghting, i . e. by seeing who has the greater coercive
power.
It i s not always necessary, however. 10 appeal to State arbi
tration for the settlement of disagreements. Consider an industrial
dispute about wages. Employers and employees may be able to
reach agreement among themselves through discussion. If they
cannot reach agreement, then they may either resort to the use
of such coercive power 3S the law allows. a strike on the one hand
and a threat of dismissal on the other. or they may choose the
method of arbitration, agreeing to accept the decision of an arbi
tration tribunal as authoritative. I t should also be noted that there
are matters i n which dispute may be allowed to continue, without
harm and perhaps with beneft. These are matters i n which the
dispute is i n belief. with no immediate effects on action, or at
least with no practical effects that constitute conjict in acti on. I t
may even be argued, as by John Stuart Mi ll, ' that continuing
<lisagreement and dispute in matters of belief is healthy, since i t
is the onl y way of approximating to the truth"
, On Librr/)'. chapter 2.
174 Problem oj YOlltlCat rnuosopny
The argment for sovereignty i n fact points beyond the Nation
State. The reason for having a supreme authority is to settle
disputes without the use of force. The region in which we chiefy
need this tOday is i n the settlement of internationa1 disputes,
and so there would be an overwhelming case for giving up State
sovereignty on external affairs i n favour
'
of a form of international
sovereignty if a suitable one could be devised and could receive
the agreement of all States. Here we again come up against the
question

of authority and power. We have seen that although i t


is possible to have authority without power, yet i n practice, for
political affairs, authority usually needs to be backed by coercive
power. Hence the great diffculty of setting up interational insti
tutions with authority overriding that of the State. States may
agree to accept certain international conventions, but when i t suits
a particular State to fout a convention, what sanction is there to
prevent the convention from being treated merely as a piece of
paper'! The international authority needs to have the threat of
coercive power in order to protect the rule of international law.
But States arc much marc reluctant to place coercive power i n
the hands of an international authority than they are to sign
conventions.
At the same ti me. so far as international law is concerned, it is
by no means certain that the chief desideratum is the power of
sanctions for enforcement. Domestic law does indeed depend on
sanctions, but i t depends more on the general acknOWledgement
of its authority for other reasons. Some international lawyers tell
us that the general acceptance of conventions and of the jurisdic
tion of international courts i s more important than the establish
ment of an adequate international force to give effect to judicial
decisions .. Building up political institutions without regard to the
realities of power is a risky business, but the acknowledgement
of the authority of law and its procedures for settling disputes
can go some
'
ay towards making i t effective, and is certainly
conceptually distinct from effectiveness by the use of coercive
power.
7
Grounds of Political
Obligation
7. 1 Prudential Rnd moral ohligation
The authority of the State implies that those who exercise it have
the right (of action) to issue orders and the right (of recipience)
to have those orders obeyed. and that. corresponding to the
second right. the citizens have a duty or obligation to obey the
orders. In this chapter I shall consider the question: IVhy does the
citizen have a duty to obey the laws of the State? This is the
problem of the grounds of political obligat i on.
Of course, there is one answer to the question that i s simple
and obvious: the citizen is obliged to obey the laws of the State
because the State has sovereign authority. It follows logically that
if the State is authoritative, i . e. has the right to issue orders to its
citizens and the right to receive obedience from them, the citizens
are obliged to obey those orders. The recipient right of the State
to be obeyed by the citizens, and the obligation of the citizens to
obey, are simply two di fferent ways of expressing one thing. the
metaphorical tie or bond between the two parties. This answer is
formally correct but tells us virtually nothing. as when Hamlet i s
asked by Polonius ' What do you read. my lord?" and replies
'Words', The answer evades the point of the question. In the case
of our question about political obligation the answer takes the
question to mean, 'Why is the citizen legally obliged to obey the
law'?' This question would indeed have no point at all, and could
only be answered by a statement of the formal implications of the
terms 'law' and 'legal obligation. The citizen is legally obliged to
obey the law because the law just is that which i mposes legal
obligation. To what else could there be a legal obligation except
the law? But the original question. ' Why does the citizen have a
t 75
176 Problems of Polilical Philosophy
duty or obligation (or, why ought he) to obey the law or the
StateT was not meant in that sense. It meant, 'What reasons can
be given for accepting the legal jurisdiction of the State?'
I n 6.3 I said that a claim to authority can be aCknowledged
for di fferent reasons. One reason is fear of the coercive power
exercised by the person or body claiming authority; but there are
other reasons too, such as general consent, or a rule of hereditary
succession, or the possession by the claimant of special personal
qualities. We now need to make a distinction of kind between
reasons for acknowledging a claim to authority. (1 ) To acknow
ledge the claim from fear or dislike of the consequences of not
doing so, is to admit a prudential obligation. It is to say that I
ought in my own i nterest to obey; I 'had better' do so, or else i t
will be t he worse for me. (2) To acknowledge the claim from the
thought that it is right to do so, is to admit a moral obligation. It
is to say that I have a moral duty to obey. So the question, 'Why
ought I to (or. why should I) obey the law?' may be asked from
either of two standpoints, and consequently it may be understood,
and answered, in either of two ways. It may be asking for either
of two kinds of reason for action. ( 1 ) It may presuppose the
question, 'Is it in my interest to obey the law?' and so be under
stood to ask how it is in my interest. (2) Or secondly, it may
presuppose the question, ' Is it my moral duty to obey the law?'
and so be understood to ask why it i s a moral duty.
Writers on moral philosophy used often to say that the word
'ought' has different meanings or senses when expressing pruden
ti al and moral obligation respectively. Nowadays it is more
common to hold that the word has the same meaning but depends
on different sorts of reasons in the two ki nds of situation. This
particular dispute i n moral philosophy does not affect the distinc
tion that I have drawn. It does not matter whether we say that the
question 'Why ought I to obey the law?' has different meanings or
the same meaning when asked from the two standpoints. What
does matter is that different sorts of reason can be given in answer
to the question. It is, however, worth noting that while the ques
ti on i n i ts present and in some alternative forms ('Why should
I . . . ?' 'Why am I obliged to . . . ?') can be asked from either
standpoint, this is not true when the noun 'obligation' is used.
The question 'Why have I an obligation . . . ?' or 'Why am I
under an Obligation + 7' cannot. so it seems to me, refer to a
prudential Obligation but only to a moral or a legal obligation.
have used the noun i n speaking of a 'prudential obligation' to
describe the situation where we may say a man 'is obliged' in hi s
own i nterest to do something. But as I sai d i n 6. 4, such an
'obligation' i s not an obligation to someone else, as is a moral or
legal obligation. Not all moral or legal duti es are of this kind,
obligations to specifed persons. For our present purpose, how
ever, i t i s important to notice that some are.
I also said i n 6.4 that the terms 'obliged' and 'compelled' are
often used of action performed under duress, because the choice
offered cannot be regarded as a genuine or effective choice when
one of the alternatives is too unpleasant to be seriously enter
tained. We must not suppose. however, that this is always true of
prudential 'obligation' , or that i f it is true for most people in a
particular situation it is true for alL We certainly have a choice
whether to follow a doctor's advice on diet even though we believe
his prediction of the consequences of neglect. Most people threat
ened by an armed robber will feci that they have no choice, but
a few will thi nk di fferently. The fact that we often use the words
'ought' and 'should' to express prudential obligation shows that
we think there is a choice. There would be no point in employing
these terms i r we thought that onc course of action was inevitable.
The armed robber does not say 'You really ought to hand over
the money' (though he may well say 'You had better . . . ' ) , as
the doctor says 'You really ought to keep orf alcohol'.
The question 'Why ought I to obey the law?' may be asked
from the standpoint of prudence, and in that event it will be
sensible to answer <Because you will run the risk of imprisonment
i f you disobey' or 'Because the law is intended to protect your
interests along with those of other people'. There is no di ffculty
in providing an answer to the question in terms of self-interest,
and one tloes not need the reasoning of a philosopher to di scover
i t. Nevertheless answers to the question in terms of selfinterest
have fgured in philosophical discussion of the grounds of political
obligation, and the reason for thi s is that the standpoint of pru
dence has been confused with the moral standpoint. Because the
same form of words can express different types of question, an
answer in terms of selfinterest has often becn given instead of,
or alongside, an answer in terms of moral duty.
Some people may be inclined to deny that political obligation
178 Problem of Political rhllosOph)'
has anything to do with moral duty. Let me try to show, then,
that an answer to Our question in terms of interest will not deal
with the problem that has arisen in consequence of the discussion
of the preceding chapter. Our problem is to fnd reasons for
acknowledging the authority of the State. Authority implies two
things: ( 1 ) it implies an obligation to obey the commands issued
by the person or body vested wi th authority; and (2) it implies
that that person or body has a right to issue the commands and
a right to be obeyed. Now if we approach the problem from the
standpoint of selfinterest and say that the citizen ought to obey
the rulers because it wi l l be the worse for hi m if he does not, then
we do indeed show that the citizen i s obliged; we give hi m a
reason why he ought to, or why he should, obey. But we do not
show that the rulers have a right to make their demands or a right
to receive obedience. We have pointed out that they have might,
that they have the power to make things nasty for the citizen if
he does not do what they require. But might is not right. Power
may be said to oblige but not to confer a right. Furthermore, i f
we recall a point made earlier, we can note t hat the 'obligation'
imposed by coercive power is not an obligation to the rulers,
corresponding to a right against the citizen to receive his obedi
ence. We can say that the citizen 'is obliged' to obey, but we
should not fnd it natural to say that he 'has an obligation' or ' i s
under an obligation', and i t would be clearly i nappropriate to say
that he is under an obligation to the rulers or that they have a
right against hi m. On the other hand, if we give the citizen moral
instead of prudential reasons for obedience, these can t ake the
form of showing that he is not only obliged but is under obligation
to the State, which correspondingly has a right to his obedience,
And since we are seeking reasons for acknowledging authority,
we need an account in terms of moral obligation and not i n terms
of prudential.
We can now see more Clearly the point of the statement made
in 6,3 that power alone i s not suffcient t< constitute authority,
Power may make people feel (prudentially) Obliged to obey, but
it does not confer a right to obedience and so does not confer
authority. We can also now see more clearly the point of Hobbes's
contentien, at frst sight a curious one, that a conqueror acquires
dominion only i f his vassals are understood to have tacitly prom
ised obedience. Their fear of his power does not make them
\
1
+
&. .....-.. . _ .. ,- = ,
@
, . . .
subjects, or give him authority, unlcss there is the intermediate
link of moral obligation created by a promise,
7.2 Moral grounds for political ohligation
Granting that prudential reasons for obediencc cannot constitute
reasons for acknowledging authority, does it follow that only
moral reasons will suffce? If recipient rights and corresponding
obligations towards those who have the rights may be either legal
or moral, cannot reasons for acknowledging authority be legal as
well as moral? Legal reasons may be given for acknowledging the
authority of a particular law or of a particular ruler or offici al .
but not for acknowledging the authority of the State as such or,
to put i t i n another way, of the system of law as a whole, We
have already noted that it is a mere tautology to say that we are
(legally) obliged to obey the law because the law is what imposes
legal Obligation. The reasons for accepting legal obligation at all
must be drawn from outside the system of legal obligation, We
can, however. give reasons from w.i thin the system to justify obedi
ence to a particular holder of authority.
1 said earlier that . apart from fear of coercive power, one
might acknowledge a claim t o authority because the claimant had
popular support . or satisfed a rule of hereditary succession. or
had some special personal qualities, Popular support and special
personal qualities may give rise l'i l hcr 1 0 prudential or to moral
reasons. One may regard popular support as potential coercive
power which it would be imprudent to oppose. or one may think
that the consent of the majority constitutes a moral reason for
accepta
n
ce, Likewise the success which is likely to attend a leader
with outstanding personal qualities of character or intelligence
may give rise to prudential or moral reasons for accepting his
leadership; I may consider that his success will ensure my safety
and prosperi ty. or I may consider that his ai ms, say a maximum
of prosperity and justice for the whole sociely, are moral ends
and that his personal qualities afford the best chance of achieving
them. The case is different , however, when we take as ollr rCason
for acknowledging authority SOflle rule like that of hereditary
succession, Needless to say, ml' list of possible reasons was not
an exhaustive one, ancl hereditary succession i s not the only exam
ple of a reaSOn provided by a constitutional rule, Now if one ruler
.
18 Problems of Political Ihllosopny
succeeds another as his heir, or a having been duly appointed
under some other constitutional rule, he is entitled to be obeyed
because there is a law, a constitutional rule, to that effect. This
gives us a legal reason for acknowledging the authority of the new
ruler. Similarly a particular law has authority because it has been
passed i n accordance with the constitutional rules for making
individual laws. But we may also ask why we should accept the
constitutional rules themselves, and then we are asking for reasons
outside the system of law for accepting the authority of the system.
And in answering this question we may want to faU back on one
of the reasons mentioned earlier, such as the consent of the
majority or the best means of securing moral ends.
I have mentioned this complication in order to say just a word
about the theory of divine right. In former days, one theory of
the ground of political obligation was the theory that the sovereign
was given his authority by God. There is little point in discussing
the divine right of Kings nowadays because nobody in a modern
State (leaving out of account pre-communist Tibet and some tribal
kingdoms) would want to claim i t. I shall therefore omit it in
surveying theories of the ground of political obligation. The one
matter that is still worth noting is that the theory of divine right.
like others, made the legal authority of the King dependent upon
moral authority. If it is assumed, as it was by the proponents of
that theory, that morality depends on the will of God, then to say
that a King is divinely invested with authority is to imply that his
authority is moral and not merely legal. The basic problem in
considering grounds for political obligation is to fnd moral reasons
for obedience. It is felt that unless moral reasons can be found,
there is no justifcation for acknowledging the State's authori ty.
And once i t was no longer thought plausible to say that a sovereign
was invested with authority by God, it became necessary to fnd
or return to other ways of giving a moral justifcation for political
authority. The notion of charismatic authority likewise was orig
inally one of divine authorization. The exceptional personal qualit
ies of a religious leader like Moses or Jesus of Nazareth were
taken to be signs that he had been invested with authority by
God, and it was assumed lhat the will of God was the source of
morali ty: A secularized idea of charismatic authority attributes to
the leader himself superior capacities of moral judgement and of
success in attai ni ng what are taken to be moral ends.

i
Why does this problem of fndi ng moral grounds for acknow
ledging authority apply specially to political obligation? Philo
sophers have not debated similarly the reasons for obeying the
rules of other associations. They have produced theories to justify
obedience to the laws of the State, but not to justify obedience
to the rules of a club, or a school, or a trade union. The reason
why the problem arises for political Obligat ion is because of the
universality and compulsory character of the State's jurisdiction.
We saw i n 2.5(b) that compulSory acceptance of rules can appl y,
to a degree and for some people. i n certai n other associations.
but the universality of the States jurisdiction makes its compulsory
character more pervasive and more evident. Membership of most
associ ations is voluntary. I can decide for myself whether to join
and to accept the rules. If I do not like the rules, I need not join.
If I decide to join, I do so freely. and in joining I promise to abide
by the rules. But in the case of the State I have had no choice. I
am a member, or at least am subject to the rules, whether I like
i t or not. It is therefore natural to ask why I should obey these
rules i f I have not freely chosen to do so. We should also note
that some theories try to answer the question by saying t hat ,
despite appearances to the eontmry. the situation is no different
from membership of a voluntar" associ ation. They have argued
that the obligation to obey the rules of the State arises from a
sort of promise such as one gives when joining a vo1untary associ
ation. Some other thCori es. now outmoded l i ke the theory of
divine right. have compared the authori ty of t he state wi th t hat
of t he head of a family: for mcmbl.'rship of a fami l y, l i ke member
ship of a Stale. is not something we choos1 but something that is
thl ust upon `.
We are now i n a position to survey those theories of pol i tical
obligation which still retai n. i n il" opinion. philosophical interest.
I shall deal with five answers to Ihe question: what are the grounds
of pOlitical obligation? They arc:
( I ) The State rests on social contract.
(2) The Stte rests on consent .
(3
)
The State represents the general will .
(
4) The State secures justice.
(5) The State pursues the general intcre>! or common good
182 Problems of Pol;t;cal Philosophy
7.3 The theory of social contract
The theory of social contract tries to justify pOlitical obligation as
being based on an implicit promise, like the obligation to obey
the rules of a voluntary association. A theory of contract proper
has been held i n di fferent forms. I shall discuss three kinds of
contract theory, and shall then turn in the next section to the
theory of consent, which depends on a similar idea but i s perhaps
not intended to imply a contract or promise.
(a) Contract of citizenship
Theories of social contract go back a long way in history. Two
explicit versions of the idea are formulated by Plato, and no doubt
hints of i t can be found in earlier writings too. The frst form of
supposed contract that I want to consider may be called a contract
of citizenship, a contract made by each individual citizen wi th the
State or the law. An implicit contract of this ki nd i s described as
the ground of political obligation i n Plato's dialogue, erito. The
argument is put forward that i f a man remains i n a particular
political society and enjoys its privileges, he i s bound for his
part to accept the obligations too. Socrates draws a metaphorical
picture of the laws of the State saying to hi m that a bargain has
been struck between them; by living in Athens he has implicitly
promised to obey the laws in return for the privileges of an
Athenian citizen.
A literal version of this doctrine applies to a man who acquires
citizenship by naturalization. He applies for membership of the
State, just as one may apply for membership of a voluntary associ
ation. He has weighed up the privi leges and the obligations, and
is prepared to accept the second along with the frst. In many
countries he is i n fact required to give an explicit promise to
accept the obligations, in the form of an oath of loyalty. Now
since his legal position, once he has become a citizen, is supposed
to be exactly the same as that of a citizen by birth, i t seems
reasonable to think that the basis of obligation is similar for both;
and since the basis of ohligation for the naturalized citizen i s
manifestly a promise 10 accept the obligations i n return for the
privileges, it seems reasonable to say that for the natural-born
citizen too, al though he has not given any explicit promise. the

basis of obligation must again be quasi-contractual, the Obligations


being a fair return for the privileges.
Actually, however, the analogy does not hold good. Although
the naturalized citizen i s told that he has the same privileges and
obligations as the citizen by bi rth, hi s consequent pOSition is not
precisely the same. In Britain. and i n many other countriest a
certifcate of naturalization may be revoked i f the person holding
it is convicted of a serious crime. This means that hi s acquisition
of the privileges of citizenship is conditional on reasonably good
behaviour, and that fits in with the idea of a contract or hargain.
But a citizen hy birth ; s not, in most civilized countries. liable to
be deprived of citizenship as part of the penalty for seriolls crime.
And this refects the i dea that one cannot rightfully withdraw what
has not been granted. The citizen by birth has not been granted
citizenShi p: he has acquired i t automatically.
Even i f the two classes of citizens did have precisely the same
status i n regard to privileges and obligations, it would not follow
that the ground of obligation was the same for both. This may be
illustrated by a similar duality, in Britain at least, in the special
mili tary Obligations of volunteer and conscript members of the
armed services. A volunteer takes an oath of allegiance: he has
chosen to accept the obligations of a soldier (or sailor or airman),
and i n signing the mi li tary oath of allegiance he explicitly promises
to obey his superior offcers. A conscript does not take an oath
of aJIegiance; he has not chosen tn serve. and so cannot reasonably
be expected to give a promise; his mili tary obligations are imposed
on him by statute and are founded on his general Obligation to
conform to the laws. Yet once they are in the army, the volunteer
and the conscript have exactly the same obligations and fights,
although the grounds of obligat ion are clearly di fferent.
What would the theory of contract of citizenship say Df a man
who thought that he received nn benefit from being a member of
the State, that he wanted neither the privileges nor the obli
gations? As Plato states the theory, it would Say that in that case
the man should have gone off to live elsewhere. Socrates re
presents the laws as arguing that . by remaining i n Athens, he has
shown that he prefers Athens tn other city-states and therefore
that he wants its privileges. This line of argument could not be
applied sO easily today. when many people are not free, as
Socrates was. \0 become a citizen of a different State.
There are therefore two objections to the theory of contract of
citizenship. First, it does not apply to natural-born citizens as i t
does t o naturalized citizens. Secondly, the theory presupposes
freedom to accept or reject the contract, and this freedom does
not exist for many people nowadays.
(b) Contract of community
A second form of contract theory is discussed by Plato in the
Republic (Book I I ), but not as a view that he himself accepts.
This theory depicts men as being by nature egoistic, everyone out
for himself. Everyone i s therefore liable to suffer harm as well as
to cause it, and so men make a compact or agreement with each
other to set up laws for the regulation of their conduct. This, it
i s claimed, i s the origin of society and of justice. The laws restrain
our liberty to do as we li ke, but give us protection from injury by
others. It is therefore in our interest to join in the compact.
Having done so, we are obliged to obey the law because we have
promised this i n the agreement.
A similar version of the social contract theory is developed in
more detail by Hobbes.' He too sees the natural man as largely
an egoist seeking his own advantage. In consequence, if there
were no organized political society, men would be i n a state of
war, in which everyone would be in danger of losing his life. We
may suppose that i n order to obtain security, men have made a
contract with each other to give up their natural right to do as
they please, and have invested a sovereign person or body of
persons with authority to make laws regulating their action. The
citizens are obliged to obey the law, both because they have
promised to do so, and because the alternative to a politically
organized society is the 'state of nature' in which every man goes
in fear of losing his life. As held by Hobbes, the theory combines
moral with prudential obligation. There is a moral obligation to
obey the law because we have implicitly promised to do so. There
is also a prudential obligation because the alternative is chaos:
however restrictive the laws of the State may be, says Hobbes,
any form of order is preferable to the chaos that results from the
brc

kdown of the State. As i n Plato's version of the theory,


Hobbes represents the contract as having been made for pruden
l.el'inthnn. (hRpter 13-18.
I
!
I
i
I
I
I
:
!
!
!
r
;
tial reasons, but he adds that our consequent obligation to obey
the law rests both on the moral ground t hat we have promised
and on a continuance of the prudential ground that led us to make
the promise.
Several stock objections are made to this form of the social
contract theory. One of them is more relevant to a contractual
theory of ethics than of poli ti cs. If it is supposed, as the Platonic
version of the theory in the mout h of Glaucorl seems to suppose.
that the idea of moral obl i gati on i tsel f dcpcncls on an agreement
to observe moral rules, that in fact. as Glaucon says/ laws and
agreements can come into existence only after a social cont ract
has been made, then the theory is involved in a vicious circie. If
agreements cannot be made in the ' natural ' slate of man before
society has been organized by a social contract, i t is impossible
for a social contract to be made: if the idea of moral Obligation
depends on the conventions of l aw, men in the 'natural ' state will
have no conception of obliging themselves by a contract. There
is, however, no need for a social contract theory to land i tsel f i n
this difficulty i f i t s ai m i s simply t o expl ai n political obligation. It
can assume, as Hobbes docs assume, that men i n a state of nature
are perfectly capablc of maki ng promises and contracts, and there
fore of knowing what it is to put oneself under obligation: but
because there is no securi ty. without the organization of political
society, that men wi ll keep thei r promises when they can break
them with i mpunity. it is desi rable t set up a sovereign authority
by means of the special device of social contract. For our present
purpose, therefore. we can ignore the objection that a contractual
theorv of morl obligation is ci rcular.
We can also ignore a second stock objection to the theory of
social contract . namel y t hat il is historical ly unsound because few
States have in fact come i nt o existence as the result of a social
contract. Some of t he phi losophers who have hel d a social contract
theory did t hi nk of it as an expl anat i on of the way in which
organizcJ States flrsl arose. bUI such an accoll nt, apart from being
historically f<lse, misconceives the purpose of a phi losophical
t heory. An account l)f how t hings have come to be as they are,
is a causal explanation of the type sought i n sci ent i Hc theory.
A philosophical theory attempl 5 to supply just i fyi ng rcasons for
186 Problems of Political Philosophy
accepting a belief (i n this instance, the belief that we ought to
obey the law), not explanatory causes of the belief or its objects.
As the proposed answer to a philosophical problem, the social
contract theory should not be regarded as a theory of historical
genesis. Hobbes at least i s quite clear about this. He knows very
well, and says so, that most States have come into existence as
the result of conquest, not of social contract . But he adds, as we
have seen in 6. 3. that those who submit to a conqueror can
become his subjects. i . e. can be under an obligation of obedience,
only i f they are assumed to have implicitly promised obedience
so long as their lives are spared. Such subjects have placed them
selves under a contract of citizenship (except that Hobbes regards
it as a one-sided promise, which binds the subjects only and not
the sovereign) . Hobbes draws the admittedly mythical picture of
a contract of community because this brings out more clearly the
logical implications of sovereign authority and of the obligations
of subjects. The purpose of the social contract theory in Hobbes
is to illustrate what sovereign authority and political obligation
mean, not to explain how States i n fact arise.
A third objection. however, i s more to the point. The theory.
as put forward by Glaucon i n Plato's Republic and by Hobbes.
assumes that all forms of society are artifcial, deliberately set up.
and that man is by nature a solitary individual who thi nks only
of his own interests. The objection i s that thi s assumption is
psychologically untrue. Man is by nature ' a social animal'. Men
have natural dispositions to associ ation with their fellows, and to
affection for kindred and other close associ ates.
The objection i s sound i n so far as the theory purports to
account for the bonds of all forms of society. That form which
Tunnies calls communitv :l rests on 'natural wi1l'. on bonds of
affection and concern th
'
at grow up naturally among people who
are close to ench other. as for example in family relationship.
But the main point of the theory is to account for the bonds of
deliberately organized society, and especially the bonds of legal
obligation in the State. We may agree that community is natural.
but it does not follow that the State is natural. The real defect of
the theory as presented by Glaucon and Hobbes is that it does
not-ciistinguish between community and the deliberately organized
\ See 92. 2. aho\e.
I
!:
I
t
I
f
!
i
\
I
i
I
I
f
I
\
I
I
!
Gmlll/ds of Poiifical Obligatioll 187
association of the State. I t assumes Ihat the only alternative to an
organized State is a collection of psychologically isolated individ
uals, each Ollt for himself and liable to come into cOntact with
others only by way of hostile social relations. This i s why I have
given the name 'contract of community' to this version of the
theofY. As such it must be rejected. It can. IH1wever. be modifed
so as
-
to Hvoid the objection, and it thcn becomes a different form
of the social contract theory.
(c) Contracl ofgovernment
Some social contract theorists hu\'e in fact disti nguished between
community (or 'society') and the State . and have spoken of a
double contract. which we may l
'
all contract of community and
contract of government. According to this form of the theory,
men frst contract with each other to join together i n community
(or 'soci ety' ), and then make a second contract i n which they
agree tn set up a State and promise to obey its laws. A double
contract theory of thi s ki nd was held notably by Samuel Pufendorf,
writing a little later than Hobbes. The distinction between the
two kinds of social union was nn! Tonnies' distinction between
community and association. i n \'hich the very description of com
munity implies that it is natural. not artificial. Pufendorf's distinc
tion is between society. i n a loose sense of the term, and that
speCifc form of associ ation which we call the State. Since 'society'
in this loose usage includes community. the objection to a contract
of community applies equally tn the !irs! half of Pufendorf's
double contract. But we call drop this hull' of the idea. and simply
retain the contract of government . which no doubt is what Glau
con and Honbes were really after, The ohject of our inquiry is to
nnd reasons for the ohligation 10 obey the State. and i f \"c think
that the idea of contr\t can givc us the answer. the only contract
that we need to posit is a contract or government . We may say
that community is a natural form of uni on. depending on the
social tendencies and needs of men. but thilt the organization of
the State is sci up deliberately. and that the obligations of law
depend on an implied contract.
When so modified. the social contract thenry avoids the objec
tion I have madc to a cOntract of community, but runs into a
different one. The idea of a COlltract of government dnes apply
~
to some instances of political rule. The founding fathers of the
original American colonies did subscribe to a sort of social con
tract, because they supposed, under the infuence of the political
philosophy of the ti me, that this was the rational method of setting
up a new State. Agai n, i f we think of Hobbes's second category.
a covenant of obedience made towards a conqueror by all the
members of the conquered society, this answers well enough to
the signing of an instrument of surrender by the representatives
of a nation defeated i n war. But then we need to ask, how can
the promise of one generation bind later generations. The found
ing fathers of a State have voluntarily agreed to set up a form of
government and to abide by its rules; and the leaders of a country
defeated i n war have, by signing the instrument of surrender.
given a promise on behalf of all the citizens that the conditions
laid down by the conqueror wi l l be obeyed. Their acceptance of
obligation has been voluntary, and in the second instance we may
suppose that the general body of citizens have already agreed to
accept decisions made on thei r behalf by their leaders. But the
descendants of the generation which has promised are supposed
to be equally obliged although they have not given or agreed to
any promise. They have not freely chosen to accept thei r
obligation.
It does i n a way seem proper to say that the descendants of a
defeated nation are bound by the conditions of surrender which
were accepted by the earlier generation. The diffculty is that their
Obligation is not l i ke that of a normal promise, which must have
been freely given by all persons who are said to be obliged by
i t . For that matter, the original generation which accepted the
conditions of surrender is in much the same boat. Normally a
promise extorted under duress is not held to be binding. but this
one is. It seems necessary to conclude that the agreement is not
really a promise. as normally understood. but an analogous device
of human invention to produce a continuing obligation aftcr the
coercive means of inducing prudential obligation have been with
drawn. At any rate the analogy which the social contract theory
is designed to draw. between political obligation and the obli
gations of membership of a voluntary associ ation. has brokcn
dowl. Hobbes docs, however. have a sound point about the
obligation to obey a conqueror: i t cannot rest simply on fear of
his coercive power, once the major part of his armed forces has
been withdrawn: and just as promises and contracts arc devices
for the smooth running of society. so surrencier is a si mi l ar. though
not identical, device for future peaceful relations. This means that
the ultimate reason for abiding by the conditions, as for having
the two kinds of device i n the frst instance. is general uti li ty. Stil l .
i t does seem to me that t he immediate ground of obligation to
abide by the conditions of an instrument or surrender i s si mi l ar
to that of the obligation of promises. Although the obligation is
not undertaken with that full [reedom which applies to the giving
of a normal valid promise, the actual device. like that of promis
ing, is specifcally designed as " mcans whereby obligations are
undertaken.
In the case of the American colonies. the device used was
literally that of social contract. The obligation of the original
members. therefore, arose from a promise proper , and we cannot
say that the obligation of their dcscendants is one of promise
keeping. since the descendants were not parties to t he original
contract. The obligation of an American citizen today to obey the
laws of his State is no di fferent from the corresponding obligation
of a British subject. The theory of contract of government faces
the same sort of diffcult) as the theory of contract of citjzenship
i t can cover only a minority of relevant instances. The theory
of contract of citizenship accollnts for the political obligation of
naturalized citizens. who accept i t voluntarily by means of a prom
ise, but not for the obligation of natural-born ci t izens. who have
not accepted it voluntarily. Similarly the theory of contract of
government accounts for the obligation of the founder generation
of a particular State which happens to have been set up by this
device, but not [or the obligation of their descendants or of any
citizens in States that were nnt founded in this way.
7,4 The theory of consent
The doctrine of consent is II watcreddowll version of the social
contract theory and i s designcd in part to <Ivoid the di fficulties
facing the l al l er. It is simply thai the authoritv of the State rests
on the consent ,,[ the subjecis. The idea "I' popular consent has
played an important part in the development o[ parliamentary
institutions in England. The proccss originated in the Middle Ages
with the notion that property {1Wl1crS could not be taxed by the
3
190 Problems of Political Philosophy
King without thei r agreement or consent . This led i n the course
of time to the appointment of representatives, who consented On
behalf of the property owners to the raising of taxes and who
took the opportunity, when they met for that purpose, to make
grievances known to the King. Elements of this procedure are
still retained in thc usages of the UK Parliament today. All Acts
of Parliament state that the Queen legislates 'by and with the
advice and consent' of Parliament. The idea is that the require
ments of a statute are valid only if the representatives of the
people have agreed to them.
Thi s means that a form of consent is essential for the authority
of a particular law. The notion that consent supplies the ground
of political obligation in general, is commonly associated with the
political philosophy of John Locke; though i n fact Locke's theory
includes also a kind of double contract (strictly, a contract and a
trust) together with the idea. to be discussed in 7.6, that the
State's purpose is to secure natural rights. However, he does talk
as i f the real point of the social contract lay i n consent when he
says that men remain i n a state of nature, i . e. outside the bonds of
political society. 'till by their own consents they make themselves
members of some politic society',' and again when he says that
'no one can be . . . subjected to the political power of another.
without his own consent . '
Locke i n fact thinks of this act of consent as an act of promising.
so that his theory is still one of contract. The diffculty with thc
contract theory, as we have seen, is that most members of a State
cannot be said literally to have given any promise. A watered
down theory of consent can try to meet thi s diffculty with the
view that if a citizen acquiesces in the laws i mposed on him. he
may be taken to have consented; i f a man, being born within a
certain State. does not choose to leave, he may be taken to have
consented to abide by its laws. This of course is the point that
Socrates makes in Plato's Crito when he puts fOl"lard what I have
called the theory of contract of citizenship. As stated i n the theory
of bare consent. however. the citizen is not regarded as having
made a contract or given a promise.
The question thai I now want to raise is thi s: if consent docs
S(COlld rre((isf' of Gvnr/l1/('fIf. especially chapter 8 .
Chapler 2, 1 5.
I < 'haplt'r H. l5.
not imply a promise, can i t impose an obligation? It seems to me
that the answer to this question i s 'No'. Promising i s a device for
putting oneself under obligation by the use of a particular form
of words.' To make a promise is to 'bind' oncself fguratively to
the performance of an action or series of actions: it is to undertake
an obligation. But mere failure to protest or resist surely does not
create an obligation. I t may perhaps be taken as an indicntion or
sign rhar one has accepted authority but it does not afford a reason
lllly one has done so. The idea of a cont ract does afford such a
reason, since it is implicit in the notion of a contract that one
promises to do something i n retur for an anticipated benefi t . I
am not saying that the beneft reccived or anticipated constitutes
the reason why one is obliged to fulfil the promise: i t is the reason
why one has made the promise. The reason why one is obliged
to fulfl the promise is simply thc fact that the promise has been
made. Nor do I imply that all promises are made for reasons of
self-interest. A one-sided promise to beneft ei ther the person to
whom the promise is made or a third party. may be given for
altruistic reasons: and for thai malter, the beneft anticipated in
return when one joins in the mutua! promises of a contract, may
be a beneft for a thi rd party. The point is that the obligations
incurred i n making a contract are intelligible by reason of the
benefts expected to accrue. But i f we say that mere acquiescence
imposes an Obligation, so that bare consent of thi s kind is under
taking an Obligation. as is the giving of a promise. it is not intelli
gible why the person who acquiesces should be supposed to have
undertaken an obligation. Of course , if he acquiesces because he
fears the unpleasant consequences of resistance or protest. it might
be said, as by Hobbes, that his acquiescence can be interpreted
as a tacit promise, made for reasons of self-interest. But his acqui
escence may be due to apathy or sheer failure to consider whether
there is any alternative. and we cannot then say that he has a
reason and that his acquiescence consequently may be interpreted
as a promise. The device of promising has a purpose, and while
it does sometimes make sense to speak of a tacit promise even
though the device normally operates by the actual use of words
expressing a promise. it surely docs not make sense to speak of
a tacit promise. or of undertaking an Obligation without overt
, This was flrsl illack ('lear l"y Hum". Tn'atiJI' of /-IwtITI Nature. 1 1 1 . ii. 5.
O*
1VX rruvu:rQ vJ Ut J' fIltLLr_
signs, i f no reason can be assigned. A man might make an explicit
promise without thi nki ng of what he was doing and without having
reasons for making i t , and he might then be nonetheless obliged
because of the conventions associated wi th this use of words. If,
however, he has not actually made use of any form of words that
would conventionally be called promising, we cannot attribute to
hi m the undertaking of an obligation unless we know of good
reasons why he may be supposed to have undertaken one.
In short, to say that no man can be subjected to political power
without hi s own consent is a way of drawing the distinction
between being compelled by coercive power and accepting auth
ority. It i s a way of saying that acceptance of authority is volun
tary. while being coerced i s not. As such, it has its point. But it
does not give us reasons why we should accept the authority of
the State, which is what we are looking for in seeking the grounds
of political obligation. The theory of consent does not supply a
ground of obligation unless consent is understood, as it is by
Locke, to mean the making of a promise. If 1 am right, the
doctrine of consent does not avoid the di ffculties of the social
contract theory. Either it is simply a form of social contract, or it
cannot afford a ground of obligation at al l .
7.5 The theory of the general will
I take next the theory of the general wi l l because thi s, like the
theories of contract and consent, tries to make out that our obli
gation to obey the law is voluntarily assumed. It must not be
supposed that this theory i s either historically prior to, or logically
simpler than. the theory of natural rights or justice, which .follows
in my order of trcntment. The idea of the general wi l l frst appears
in he work of Jean-Jacques Rousseau in the eighteenth century.
while the thcory of natural rights came into prominence in the
sC'venteenth ccntury. Furthermore. an important feature of the
theory of the general or 'real' wi ll i s the view thut moralitv.
including rights. depcnds on the existence of organized socict y:
in the hands of some of its advocates, such as T. H. Green. thc
thcory begins as a criticism of the idea of natural rights.
Practically all versions of the general or 'real' will theory,
whether in Rousseau Or Hegel or the English Hegelians. Green
and Hosanquet. are higJlly complex and rather obscure . The
sketch of the theory that I shall give here may wel l be accused of
being an oversimplifed and even distorted parody, if taken to
represent the view of any important philosopher. This book is not
a history of political philosophy but a si mpl i fed indication of
problems and attempted solutions. It should not be thought that
what I say in this section is an accurate interpretation of the view
of any one pOlitical philosopher, or that the i mportant insights of
Rousseau or Hegel are disposed of by my criticism. In the case
of Rousseau, indeed, it may be held that hi s theory is not intended
to give the grounds of political obligation in actual States. since
his purpose i s the di fferent one of working out a hypothetical or
ideal state of affairs which would, if it were practicable, reconcile
freedom wi th authority.s As against that interpretation, however,
there are features of Rou&seau's main work on political philo
sophy, Du Conrrat social, which suggest that he i s dealing wi th
the actual as well as the ideal. The fact i s that he i s not a consistent
writer. However. I am not claiming to give an accurate interpret
ation of Rousseau or of the other philosophers I have mentioned,
but only an outline of an interesting type of answer to the question
of why we are obliged to obey the l aw.
The vi ew is that we ought to obey the laws of the State because
they represent the general wi l l . What is meant by the general
wi ll? One might suppose that it means ei ther the wi l l of all the
citizens or the wi l l of the majority. but obviously the frst of these
wi l l not do. If the general wi ll meant the wi l l of al l , the theory
would not have given us an answer to our question. For if every
one wanted the same thi ng to be done, there would be no prob
lem. 'Everyone' includes me, and if the State i s doing what I want
to be done, I shall not ask why I should join i n. The question is
raised only because the demands of the State often go against the
wishes of an individual. who i n consequence is disposed to ask:
'Why should I do what the Slate requires. when I do not want
to?' In any event, if the Slate is t o act only when there is unanimity
among all the citizens, it wi ll have to wait unti l the mi l lenium
before it does anything at al l .
Let us turn to the more promising alterative suggestion that
the general will means the will of t he majori t y. Why does majority
opinion
.
Iay an obligation upon the dissident minority? Suppose
See, for example. the admirable dis{tlsion hy John Plamenatz in Man and
Soci<y (London. 1 96J] , vol. i. pp_ J9Jff

J7 1 I UV'CHh Vj 1 UIUU Q flUU'UYHJ


that most people want the State to do something or other, e. g. to
build earthworks so as to prevent fooding, but I do not, because I
live on the top of a hi ll and do not want to pay taxes for earthworks
that will be of no beneft to me personally. Why should I fall i n
wi t h t he majority? What is t he justifcation for accepting a majority
view? One reason that might be suggested is that a majority is
more li kely to be right than a minority. I f two heads are usually
better than one, then thirty million heads are probably better than
twenty mi lli on. Probably, but not certainly. Two heads are not
always better than one. Some heads have better brains in them
than others. If ffty sheep take i t i nto their heads to go one way
when thei r shepherd thinks they should go the other way, the
shepherd is not likely to be impressed by the argument that ffty
heads are better than one. Sti ll, when all the heads belong to
human beings, it is not easy to say who are the sheep. There is
often no means of knowing, especially i n political affairs, who is
likely to be right. We also need to ask, right about what? In my
example of building earthworks to prevent foodi ng, the di fference
of opinion arose from what people wanted. I f politics is to be
concerned wi th what people want, then, brains or no brains, a
man can usually be expected to know what he himself wants; so
that i f the i deal, but unattainable, ai m i s to satisfy the wishes of
all, we shall come nearer to it by satisfying the wishes of a majority
than by satisfying the wishes of a mi nority.
In fact, however, the theory of the general wi ll i s not referring
to the wishes of the majori ty. Rousseau, for example, says that
the general will is always right.' This sounds as if he accepted the
view that 'ffty million Frenchmen can't be wrong' . But he does
not mean that the majority are always right. He knows they are
not, and he wants his general wi l l to be something superior to the
fallible opinion of the majority. If we ask 'right about what?' the
answer that we receive is 'right about the common good (or
common interest)
,
. The object of the general wi l l is the common
good, not what any particular people happen to want for them
selves. The common good is taken to be the aim of moral volition,
and the general will is the wi ll that each man has as a citizen or
moral agent, not the sum of particular wills or wishes that each
ContraJ social. II. 6. He qualifies this statement {in the second, revised \'ersion of
the book} by adding 'but [he judgement which guides it is not always enlightened'_
$fLIflLO UJ ILIIIILMt VV"lUHUH *
has as a non-moral individual thi nki ng of his own interests i n
isolation from the interests of others.
Now if the theory of the general will were simply saying that
we ought to obey the laws of the State because they seek to
promote the common good and that this is the proper ai m. or one
of the proper aims, of each of us as a moral agent. i t would be
nothing more than a version of the common good theory. which
I have placed last on my list, and which is a strai ghtforward
uti li tarian theory of political obligation. But in talking of a general
or real will, the theory goes further than that. It holds, not simply
that the common good is what we morally ought to aim at, but
that this i s what we 'really' wal/f, and that therefore the State, in
pursuing a moral ai m and i n requiring. sometimes forci ng. us
.
to
give effect to that ai m, is getting us to do what we want. despIte
appearances to the contrary. How does the theory reach thi s
paradoxical conclusion?
I said earlier that we might justify the following of majority
preference if we thought that political decision should approach
as near as possible to an ideal aim of giving everybody what he
wanted. Now a person may want something which is not good for
hi m; and it might be argued that what is good for someone i s
what he would want i f he had complete wisdom about the conse
quences of satisfying alternative possible wishes. He thinks that
what he now wants wi ll satisfy hi m, but this i s because he is
ignorant of some consequences. In fact i t wi ll not give him lasting
satisfacti on. It i s only an apparent good. His real good, what
would give hi m real or lasting satisfaction, i s what he would want
i f he had more wisdom. Holders of the general or real wi l l theory
then take the step of saying that hi s real good is what he 'really'
wants though he does not know i t . They also argue that a man's
real good or i nterest must be in harmony with that of other men,
since a confict of i nterests i s harmful t o all concerned. Such a
harmony could be secured if the interests of all were the ai m of
each. This common good, or general i nterest, i s what we ought
to pursue; i t i s the object of a rational, real. or general will , and
so is the real good of each i ndi vi dual. Si nce the State ai ms at
securing the common good, the State or the law is the concrete
expression of the general wi l l . We ought therefore to obey the
State, and if we do so we are following our real wi l l , a will that is
general or common to all the members of the State. If a particular
4VM rrUVIrru UJ TLMMUt rttt t.:w_r _y
individual does not understand what he 'really' wants and i s
unwilling to fall into line, the State i s justifed i n forcing hi m to
conform.
There is more than one unwarranted jump in thistrain of argu
ment, but I shall confne myself to three objections. First, the
theory assumes that the Goverment knows better than the indi
vidual what he really wants.' 'The man in Whitehall knows best . '
Now t he man i n Whitehall may now more than I about the causal
effects of different policies. His knowledge of economics, for
instance, may enable him to say that if the rail services are electri
fed they will be twice as quick and will cost twice as much. I
know little of economics and am prepared to defer to hi s superior
knowledge i n accepting his conclusion. It says nothing about my
wants. But suppose the man in Whitehall then adds that a quick
service i s 'preferable to a cheap service, and that therefore the
railways ought to be electrifed. There i s no reason for me to treat
his opinion on this issue as being knowledge of what I really want.
If I do want a quick service rather than a cheap serice, i t wi ll be
rational for me to agree that the railways ought to be electrifed
and that I ought to pay higher fares or more taxes. But i f I decide
that I want a cheap serice rather than a quick one, it is no use
saying that I 'really' want a quick one because the man in White
hall thinks i t will be best for me. Perhaps it will, or perhaps most
people want i t , and ei ther of those circumstances may be a good
reason for going ahead with the policy and requiring me to join
in the cost. The fact remains that I do not want i t .
Secondly, t he theory holds t hat everyone really wants the same
things; it makes no allowance for differences of taste. I t assumes
that fundamentally human nature is always the same. But if, as
is presupposed by the theory itself, people di ffer in their know
ledge, why should they be supposed not to di ffer in their wishes?
Indeed the mere fact that they differ i n their i ntellectual capacities
makes it likely that they wi ll have different tastes in consequence
of their di fferent capaci ties, and this of course is what we fnd.
Thirdly, the theory identifes moral obligation with interest. It
says that what I ought to do i s what I really want to do. It assumes
that there can be no obligation other than prudential obligation.
and this is why i t has to make the absurd assumption that everyone
CL objection (4) on p. 80, above.
i
f
wants the same things. Now there is nothing absurd i n saying that
everyone shares a common set of moral obligations. It i s perfectly
sensible to say that everyone has a moral obligation to promote
the common good, i . e. to serve other people's i nterests as well as
his own, so far as he can. We can make this moral obligation the
ground of political obligation, as is done by the utilitarian theory.
In a way, the general will theory is doing the same thing. as I said
earlier, but this simple, straightforward thesis is confused and
distorted i n the general will theory because it i s supposed that
one can be obliged to do something only i f i t is i n one' s own
interest, a means to what one chiefy wants. The mistake is a
common one, but in the case of the general will theory it is
aided by the further supposition that a solution to the problem of
political obligation must take the form of showing that somehow
the State is a voluntary associ ation.
7.6 The theory or justice
The three theories that I have so far considered all try to make
out that political obligation is voluntarily undertaken and is
grounded on this voluntary acceptance itself. independent of aims
or consequences. The two theories that remain take a di fferent
line. They concentrate simply on the purposes of the State and
hold that we are morally obliged. generally speaking, to obey the
State because the State i s a means to the fulflment of moral ends
which are themselves the objects of moral obligation for everyone.
In principle, therefore, the theory of justice and the theory of
general interest or utility take the same sort of form, and my own
opinion is that they need to be combined. They have, however,
been held separately, partly because carlier ideas of the purposes
of the State were confned to the negative function as I explained
in 2.5(c), and partly because the utilitarian theory takes the
concept of justice to be comprehended in that of uti li ty. It will
therefore be convenient to consider them separately in the frst
instance.
According to the theory of justice, our obligation to obey the
laws of the State depends on the fact that these laws arc intended
to secure justice or moral rights. One version of the theory speaks
of 'natural rights' , a conception that plays an important part in
the political philosophy of Locke. who also. as we have seen, held

u~
I 't rrODlems OJ rOlmCOI rnuosopny
a doctrine of social contract or consent. II i s of cOurse possible to
think that there is more than one ground of political obligation,
and thus t o combine two or more theories.
I have given a brief account of the concept of natural rights, as
the precursor of human rights, i n 4.4. Natural right. were
regarded as fundamental moral rights possessed by every human
being. Locke's view was that the State is desiged to guarantee
and protect natural rights. If we thi nk that the noti on of justice
includes more than what Locke had in mind as natural rights
(rights to life, liberty. and 'estate'), we may expand his doctrine
and say that the State is designed to guarantee justice, i . e. estab
lished rights plus the promotion of fairess. We may then say that
i f the State effectively carries out thi s functi on, we are thereby
under an obligation to support it and obey i t s rules. On this view,
political obligation depends on our moral obligation to pursue
justice.
So-called 'natural' rights are a species of moral rights of recipi
cnce, which go along wi th 'natural', i . e. moral, obligations. To
say that a man has a moral right t o l i fe and liberty i s simply an
alternative way of saying that other people have a stringent moral
obligation not to take his life or i nterfere wi th his liberty. 'Natural
rights' or 'rights of man' or 'human rights' are moral rights attri
buted to every human being and corresponding to 'natural' or
moral obligations which everyone has. But since some people do
not in fact respect the rights of others, i t is expedient to have an
agency, the State, which wi l l protect rights, if need be by force.
The theory takes for granted that everyone has a moral obligation
to respect rights and promote justice. In consequence it is morally
obligatory to take the necessary means to that end. I f the State
serves as such a means, it is morally obligatory t o give the State
our support. Political obligation i s treated as a form of moral
obligation. the State being regarded as a necessary means to a
moral end, the securing of justice.
It should be noted that thi s theory of the ground of political
obligation implies that our obligation holds good only if the State
does secure justice. If the State acts unjustly, it is not a means t o a
moral end and it forfei ts its right to be obeyed. Locke deliberately
i ntended thi s consequence. He wanted to show that it was justif
able to rebel against the existing rulers i f they were pursuing
unjust policies. Locke would also say, however, that, human
nature being what it i s, there i s l i ttl e chance of securing justice to
any appreciable degree unless we have a State t o enforce i t . So
that, if we live under an unjust government, his view would be
that we are enti tl ed, indeed obliged, to replace it by another
government which wi l l aim at securing justice. Mere rebellion
by itself i s not warranted, but only rebellion which aims, wi th
reasonable hope of success, to replace an unjust by a just regime.
The theory of natural rights has been criticized on the ground
that no rights are absolute and that natural rights are a myth.
There is i n fact no need for the theory to maintain that natural
rights are absolute , i . e. that there are no circumstances in which
a man loses them. Most of us would agree that a criminal forfei ts
hi s ri ght to liberty for a ti me; and i t may be argued that a murderer
who deliberately and coolly takes the l i fe of another thereby
forfeits his own right to life! though this does not necessarily
imply that the State or anyone else ought to execute hi m. Locke
undoubtedly thought that natural rights are forfeited by one who
breaches the natural rights of others. Some advocates of the doc
trine of natural rights have called them ' i nalienable' or ' i mpre
scripti ble', but what they have meant is that moral rights cannot
be lost merely by legal enactment. A man may forfeit moral rights
if he deliberately breaches the si mi lar moral rights of others. and
the law may give effect to this by listing crimes and i mposing
punishments. What i t cannot ( morally) do, according to the
theory, is t o deprive a man of hi s moral ri ghts for non-moral
reasons. All this is simply reiterating that moral rights and obli
gations do not depend on law and that legal obligations must
depend on moral reasons if they are to be morally acceptable.
The second objecti on. that natural rights are a myth. may take
either of two forms. ( I ) [ t may mean that the theological or
metaphysical presuppositions of Locke and others are mythical.
To thi s we may reply that. as I said in 4.4. the natural rights
theory can stand without such presuppositions; the word ' natural'
here simply means non-artifcial. and the rights concerned are
moral as distinct from legal rights. (2) The objection may be
understood, however, as a denial that there can be such thi ngs as
moral rights distinct from legal ones. It may be said that 'rights'
is a legal term and cannot properly be used to refer to anythi ng
other than legal rights. I n reply t o the objection i n thi s form, we
must allow that the term 'rights' is i ni ti ally used i n the context of
.'
law, but it has come to be used, by analogy, outside t he feld of
law, and I do not see why the extended use should b called
i mproper. We should all agree that there are moral as well as legal
obligations. Legal obligations often correspond to legal rights, and
therefore it is quite natural to thi nk of certain stringent moral
obligations as corresponding to moral rights. This is hardly more
than saying that the obligations are stringent obligations and that
they are obligations to other persons. To say that A has a moral
right against B is just another way of saying that B has a stringent
moral obligation to A. The meaning of the two statements is
perhaps not quite the same, for often the point of saying that A
has a moral 'right' is to express implicitly the view that it ought
to be tured i nt o a legal right, i .e. that t he obligation of B towards
A ought to be enforceable by law. Certainly one of the main
points of issuing declarations of 'the rights of man' or 'human
rights' i s t o urge that these moral rights be given legal protection
and so be turned i nto legal rights. In that case, the objector may
thi nk, it would be less misleading to speak of i nterests that ought
to become rights instead of calling them moral rights. But if he
agrees that B does have a stringent obligation towards A, this is
all that i s required by the natural rights theory. As an account of
the grounds of political obligation, the theory says that the State
i s a necessary means t o the fulflment of certain moral Obligations
that we all have, and therefore we are morally obliged to give i t
our support.
In any event, all these objections to the idea of natural rights
disappear if we extend the natural rights theory, as I have done,
into a theory of justice. Few philosophers will deny that justice i s
a moral as well as a legal noti on. Utilitarians would Object t o the
theory of natural rights and t o the theory of justice al i ke, on the
ground that these notions are both concealed forms of the idea
of utility. The ultimate and comprehensive principle of morality,
i n their view, i s the promotion of the general happiness; and
justice is a means to that. My own opinion is that the idea of
justice cannot wholy be subsumed under that of utility for the
general happiness, as ! have explained i n 5. ! and 5. 4. Even so,
we need to take account of the uti l i tarian theory of the ground
of political obligation.
7.7 The theory of general interest or common good
This theor is held by Uti litarians, who take the view that all
moral obligations depend on their utility for promoting the general
happiness or interest. The State is a necessary means to secu
,
nng
a substantial part of this moral end. and t herefore we are oblIged
to obey the law as an essential condition of fulflling our general
moral obligations. The State carries out its purpose by laymg
down laws, backed by force. requiring everyone to refralO from
actions (crimes and torts) that harm the common good. and to
contribute i n taxes and other imposts to the upkeep of services
(such as defence, public uti l i ty, and social services) that promote
the common good. As with the theory of justice, i t follows from
the utilitarian theory that if a particular Government is harming
instead of helping the promotion of the common good, it loses its
right to obedience.
I imagine that everyone would accept the common good theory
as providing one of the grounds of political obligation. Objection
would be raised only to the thesis that it provides all the grounds
needed. We have seen that the general will theor includes the
idea of the common good as the object or ai m of the State. Both
the general will theory and the theories of contract and consent ,
however
7
would say t hat t hi s is not suffcient because political
obligation must have been voluntarily undertaken. It is not i n fact
true of most citizens that they have, in any straightforward sense,
voluntarily undertaken their obligation to obey the State, but
there i s point i n the contention that consent i n some sense is a
necessary addition both to the theory of common good and to the
theory of justice. I shal l consider thi s i n the next section. Mean
while we may turn t o an objection to the common good theory
that naturally suggests itself from our discussion of the theory of
justice.
Both the theory of justice and the theory of t he common good
ground political obligation on the functions of the State in pursu
ing a moral end. When I dealt with the functions of the State i n
2.5(c), I said that its negative function WaS to preserve order and
security, and that its positive function was to promote welfare and
justice. Each of the two theories that we are now considering
would claim to cover the negative function. The theory of justice
would say that this function is the protection of established rights,

:t
I
II
202 Problems of Political Philosophy
one aspect of justice. The common good theory would say that
the negative function is to prevent harm to the common good.
What of the positive function? I do not think it can be said that
the further promotion of welfare is an aspect of justice, so that if
we accept the theor of justice as giving one ground of political
obligati on, we must add the theory of common.good as specifying
another similar ground. We should then have the composite
theory that political obligation is grounded on

the moral character
of the functions of the State, these being both the securing of
justice and the promotion of welfare. The common good theory,
however, would say that i t already provides for al l functio
n
s, since
the concept of justice is comprehended under utility. Just as the
protection of established rights is a method of preventing social
harm, so the redistribution of rights in terms of fairness is a form
of promoting the general happiness. Take reward and punishment,
for example. According to utilitarian theory, reward i s appropriate
only for such achievements as are useful to society
7
and it is
appropriate because they are useful and because the encourage
ment of them by this incentive is useful ; punishment is appropriate
only for such actions as are harmful to soci ety, and it is appropri
ate because they are harmful and because the diseouragement of
them by this sanction is useful. This view obviously has a certain
plausibility. As I have already mentioned in the preeeding secti on,
I myself do not thi nk that utility can account for al l the ideas
included i n our concept of justice, and therefore I consider that
both the theory of justice and the common good theory need to
be eombined in giving the grounds of political obligation. Those
who thi nk that justice is comprehended in utility can adopt the
common good theory alone.
7,8 Obligation and authority
Both theories, however, still have to meet the contention of the
contract, consent, and general wi ll theories that it is not enough
to refer to the moral functions of the State. We have seen that
i t is a mistake to say, of most citizens, that they have, i n any
straightforward sense, voluntarily undertaken their obligations to
the Sta1e. The State is not a voluntary associati on. Nevertheless
the contention has point, which may be brought out in the follow
ing way. Authority. or a right to give orders, it may be said, must
have been granted by people in a position 10 grant i t. The fact
than an agency pursues a moral end does not by itself oblige
others to give it their support. Otherwise we should have to say
that our general moral obligation to be charitable implies an
obligation to support any and every charitable association. instead
of leaving us free to fulfl our moral obligation in whatever way
we choose.
The theories of justice and the common good can give a partial
answer t o this objection by reminding us that they treat the State
as a necessary means to fulfilling some of OUf general moral obli
gations, and it is thi s necessity which di rects our general obligation
into the channel of political obligation. The State, with its system
of enforceable law. is a necessary de\'ice for securing essential
rights and interests, and this fact, together with our acknowledged
moral obligation to promote justice and the common good. obliges
us to give the State our support.
This i s not, however. a complete answer 1 0 the Objection since
it does not meet the point about authority or a right to give
orders. I said in 97. 1 that the problem of the grounds of political
obligation could not be solved i n terms of prudential obligation
because that would show only that we were obliged to act, not
that the State had the right, implied by the idea of authority, to
give orders. Now an account of political Obligation i n terms of
the moral functions of the State does not indeed make politieal
obligation prudential, but it does show only that we are obliged
to act and not that the State has authority. The answer to the
objection which I have put forward comes to saying that we have
moral obligations to the members of our national community (as
we have, though often i n a di fferent degree, to other persons
also). that some of our moral obligations to other members of
our national community can be fulflled onl y through using a
necessary device, and that therefore we are 'obliged' to use the
device, just as a man is 'obliged' ttl make a detour if, owing to a
landslide, that is the only way to reach his destiation. The 'obli
gation' to use the device of the State is not a prudential obligation,
because the end which i t serves is not self-interest but the common
interest together with justice. Nevertheless its Obligatory character
is that of being obliged by the exigencies of a situation and not
that of being under an obligation to some person or body that has
a corresponding right. Of course we are under an obligation to
W ' VVltrr .. V) VUUt. UI f rUIV.Vp"y
the other members of our community, but when we are obliged
to obey the State as a necessary device for fulflling some of our
presupposed obligations to others, this does not mean that the
State has been given a right to issue order and to have them
obeyed.
We can see therefore that it was not superfuous for the theory
of the general will to add something else to the idea of promoting
the common good, or for the theories of social contract and
consent to fx their attention upon the idea of authorization. An
account of political obligation purely in terms of the moral func
tions of the State is not enough. What should be added? If we
were to add the idea of a social contract, we could say that the
contract is an agreement to use the device of the State for promot
ing moral ends; it would constitute a form of authorization that
the State should act on our behalf. But the objections to the
contract theory will hardly allow its reintroduction at this point,
though I shall suggest i n the next section that the idea of social
contract does have some place in the institutions of a democratic
society.
What of the weaker notion of consent in the sense of acquiesc
ence? I think the addition of this suffces for giving the State a
right to act as it does. I said in 7.4 that the theory of consent i n
the weaker form does not afford a ground of obligation, but i n
the composite theory t hat I am now building up, t he obligation
does not come from consent. The obligation comes from the
presupposed moral obligation to promote the ends of justice and
the commOn good together with the recogn
I
tion that the State is
a necessary means to those ends. Al l that consent is required to
do is to allow the State to act as the agent of the citizen body.
This need not involve an explicit contract. For most of us, the
State is a fait accompli, already exercising its functions; but if we
recognize the necessity of it for the securing of moral ends, and
acquiesce in its continuing to exercise its functions, we thereby
permit it to act as the agent or channel through which we are to
fulfl part of our moral obligations. The consent adds to the State's
power the authority or right to give orders, and since i t is acting
as an agent or channel for moral obligations, our Obligations to
fellow-citizens are channelled into an obligation to follow the
arrangements made by the State.
7.9 The eltent of political obligation
What follows in regard to the extent of political obligation? Obvi
ously it does not follow that political obligation is absolute, i. e.
that subjects are obliged to obey anything at al l that the State
may decree. On the contrary. since their political obligation
depends on pursuing the ends of justice and the common good,
they are not obliged unless the States laws are effectively di rectly
towards these ends.
But who is to judge whether the State's laws are effectively
directed towards securing justice and the common good? The man
in Whitehall, the majority, or each individual for himself? If any
individual thinks that a particular law is unjust or harmful to the
common weal, is he morally entitled to disobey it? If we answer
that he i s. the whole system will become unworkable. I f the State
must win the approval of all citizens for every law, no laws will
be passed; and yet i t wi l l be plai n to everyone that a number of
rules of some sort need to be made and accepted, although there
is not unanimity on the details. We are faced again with the
problem of the general wil l . And here I thi nk we may say that,
in a democratic society, something l i ke a social contract can prop
erly be assumed. If the State's system of law as a whole is directed
towards the approved ends of justice and the common good,
there is a convention that whatever is decided in detail should be
accepted as binding. This convention is acceptable only if those
who take the decisions are authorized to do so by the general
body of the citizens, and since unanimity is i mpossible even for
that, maiority opinion (either i n the community as a whole, or,
with large States, in constituent units) is taken to be the best
approximation to the general wi l l .
I am suggesting that something like a social contract does oper
ate, in a democracy, for the acceptance of particular laws, pro
vided that these can properly bc said to represent the general wi ll,
as being authorized by the majority, with due regard to the di ffer
ing views of the minority. The minority may be taken to have
consented to accept decisions so reached, as representing the
general will . My suggestion is that the general obligation to accept
the authority of the State depends on thc State's pursuit of the
moral objectives of justice and the common good; and that the
particular Obligation to obey a specifc law. with which one may
2 Problems of Political Philosophy
disagree, can be regarded as contractual, depending on the con
vention of accepting majority decision.
Now I objected to the idea of social contract, when offered as
the ground of political obligation in general, that one could not
properly speak of a promise in the case of most citizens. Cannot
the same objection be made again? Where is there a promise to
abide by the decision of a majority of representatives, or of a
Goverment? I think we can say that such a promise is implicit
in the procedure of an election (or of a referendum). If one takes
part in an election, or in a vote (whether it be a referendum of
the whole populace or a vote in a legislative assembly), one can
be assumed to have agreed to the presuppositions of voting pro
cedure, namely that the majority opinion will b treated as decis
ive. To take part in an election is implicitly to promise to accept
the majority verdict. If this is correct, i t will follow that a compul
sory requirement to vote in elections is contrary to the necessary
condition of a promise that it be given voluntarily. Compulsory
voting has occasionally been adopted in some States, and someone
may say that this fact is an argument against the hypothesis that
taking part in an election presupposes a promise. I think, on the
contrary, that the rarity of the practice of compulsory voting is
an indication of an obscure feeling that a compulsory requirement
to vote is improper, even though one can argue in favour of it
that, as with compulsory military service, it makes every citizen
more fully aware of his responsibilities as a citizen. If participation
in an election or a vote of any kind presupposes a promise, this
would explain the general feeling that voting ought not to be
compulsory.
What of the individual who chooses not to exercise his right to
vote? Is it reasonable to impute to him an acceptance of the
convention that the majori ty view shall be binding? Here I think
we can only fall back again on the doctrine of consent. The man
who abstains from voting has not given any promise; but i f he
does not actively protest against the whole business or try to leave
the country, he may be assumed to acquiesce. The point is that the
procedures of democratic government give him the opportunity of
protesting and, if he can persuade enough people to agree with
him, of changing thc Government and the laws. If he lives under
a system of government in which no genuine alteratives are made
available to the electorate, I do not think we can attribute to him
]I1JQIOO 1_ 44A44& . . . . . ...
any willingly accepted obligation to obey a partic

lar Govern
ment. Of course a citizen in such a State who thInks that the
Government is pursuing the proper aims, will approve of the
Goverment for that reason and will record his approval by a
willing vote in its favour. But a citizen in such a State who rec

rds
a vote in favour of the Government from fear, or who abstams.
and who is prevented from leaving the country, cannot be said
to have .accepted the Government's authority or to be morally
obliged.
Under a democratic system, does acceptance of governmental
authority imply that it is never morally justifable to refuse to
obey a particular law? It is certainly justifable, indeed it is part
of the democratic process, to campaign against a law, i . e. to try
to persuade a majority to agree with you and so to have the law
changed. Is it also justifable sometimes to ael contrary to a law
when you know that you are still in a minority? Yes, it may
be. Political obligation does not exhaust the whole of our moral
obligation, unless we take the view that the State is omnicom
petent. There can be a conflict hctwcen political obligation and
some other moral obligation, This is true, for examplc. of the
conscientious objector who has failed to convince a tribunal, or
of the supporter of nuclear disarmament who thinks he ought to
protest in a forbidden area or to refuse to pay part of his taxes.
Such a person. however, before deciding that he ought to disobey
the law. needs to weigh up carefully the point and the extent of
political obligation, refecting that the State does in a large meas
ure secure justice and essential interests as nothing else could.
But i f he considers that his conficting obligation (e. g. to refrain
frum taking human life) is absolute or is otherwise clearly para
mount, he is moral1y justifed in disohedience. At the game time,
if he agrees that in general his State attempts t o secure justice
and essential interests, and is therefore to be supported. he may
conclude that he is morally obliged to accept whatever penalties
the State decrees for disobedience. That is why I said i n 4.2 that a
conscientious objector may think he ought not to perform military
service but that he ought to accept without protest the penalty of
imprisonment. The same thing would apply to a supporter of
nuclear disarmament who refuses, on conscientious grounds, to
pay part of his taxes or who attends a protest meeting in a forbid
den area.
208 Problems ofPolitical Philosophy
My conclusion is that the gounds of political obligation in
general depend on the moral ends or objectives of the State (with
the proviso that consent must b added to give the State its
authority). One is morally obliged to obey tbe law because one
has a moral obligation to promote justice and the common good,
and because State action is an essential means to the pursuit of
those ends. When one disapproves of a particular Goverment or
a particular law, one is nevertheless obliged, in a democratic
society, to conform, if the policy followed has the assent of the
majority; and one is then obliged because participation in the
democratic procedure of election implies a promise to accept
majority decisions. The convention of accepting majority decisions
is followed because it is the only practicable approach to the ideal
of universally ageed policies. Thus there is some truth in each of
the theories I have considered, and that is why each of them still
retains philosophical interest. But I should say that the theories
of justice and the common good, when combined with the theory
of consent, give the correct account of the grounds of political
obligation in general.
I began this book with a brief sketch of the subject-matter of
the present chapter, as an example of the problems of political
philosophy. The detailed discussion that we have now completed
can again be used as an example to illustrate the character and
the results of political philosophy. It shows that the problems
which political philosophy takes up are much more complex than
they seem at frst sight. Nevertheless, despite the disclosure of
complexity, philosophical analysis brings a clearer understanding
of puzling concepts. Our example also shows that, in addition to
clarifying concepts, philosophy can have some success in the criti
cal evaluation of beliefs. In this instance we are led, by our own
experience or by that of other people, to wonder whether the
common assumption that we always ought to obey the law is
justifed, and if so. why. Critical argument about the various
theories enables us to reach a pretty defnite conclusion. My own
conclusion is that the common assumption is justifed, subject to
limitations which can be specifed, and that the justifcation is
perfectly rational. You may not agree entirely, or perhaps at all,
with my conclusion, but 1 hope you will agree tbat the philosophi
cal discussion shows how you can set about justifying your own
view. In any event you will, I trust, have reached your view by
thinking about the problem for yourself. The primary aim of
philosophy is independent critical thought. If this book has helped
to encourage it. I shall be well satisfied.
I
f
Index
Numerals i n bold type denote chapters
Ability, 1 1 9-26, 130-3, 145
Absol ute, 69, 199, 205
Accordance, 12. 14. 22
Acknowledgement of authority.
160. 163-0. 168. 1 71 -. 176.
178-8 1 . 192
Adjourment Debate, 94-5
Alice in Wonderland. 75 , 123
Analysis. 16-19, 22-3. 25-8. 82.
139. 208
Arbitration. 66-7. 173
Aristocracy. 37-40, 85. 1 1 7, 120
Aristotle. 38-41 . 46. 5'1. 76. 1 2fl-2.
1 45
Arcn. Raymond, 159
Art . 4 1 . 49-S0
Aryan, 13-1 4
Association, 3S-4 I . 43-6. 48,
5(}-2. 54-S. 86. 95-7. 156-7.
164, 1 81-2. 186-8. 197. 202
Athens. 1 8. 87-8. 1 1 7, 1 82-3
Authority, 1 4, 16. 23-4. 3 1 . 33.
38, 52-5, 64-8. 74-82. 92-3.
97, 99, 1 1 4-15, 1 1 7. 125-6.
130. 133. 6. 175-8 1 . 184. 180.
1 89-93, 202-7
Authorize, 92, 9S, 1 67-8. 170.
184, 204-5
Babeuf. F. N. (,Grncehus). 1 1 0
Beliefs. evaluation of. B-1,, 22,
208
Bel l . Clive. 85
Benn, S. I . , 1 3 I
Bentham. Jeremy. f20
Berl i n. Sir IS<t ; ah, 63
Bible, 9, 170
Blanc. Louis, 1 3
Bodin. Jean. 1 65
Bond, 75. YR. 169. I n. 175. t86.
I YI
Bosanquct . B. t 192
Burke, Edmund, 89-90. q4
Cabinet . 30, 90-1 . 93-.
Capacity. `LL Abi l i ty
Cause. 8-9. 1 85 . 196
Charismatic. 170-2. 180
ChMity. 48. 50. 1 1 3, 1 1 1 . 1.6. 1 41 .
146. 1 52. 203
Choice . 45-. 56-4. 71-80. 83.
89. 1 25-6. 129. 1 32-3. 149.
1 5 1 -2. 169, 1 71 -2 . 177. 1 81 ,
188
Church. )2-.1. 37, 40- 1 . -. 6. 5.
86. 97. 15&-7
Churchi l l . Si r Winston. '7
Cinderella. 1 38
Cilizenship. 42-, 88. 108-9, 146,
1 61 . 182-4. 186. 189-90
I

City-state, 4 1 , 46, 87, 96


Civ

iI service, 30, 51 , 92, 94-5,


126-7, 196
Claim, 92, 105-6, 1 15, 1 31 , 138-9,
141-, 156-8, 163-, 172,
176, 179
Clarifcation of concepts, S, 15-20,
22-3, 26-9, 20S
Class, 7, 13, 39-40, 1 17, 167
Clough, A. H. , 48
Coercive power, see Power
Command, 165. 167, 170-1, 17S
Common good. 3-, 3S, 40, 68-73,
76. 78-9, 81-2, 136-7, 164,
l S I , 194-7, 201-5, 208
Communism, 12-13, 1 5, 18-19,
37, 47-50, 68-9, 84, 86-7,
136-7
Community, 35-3, 45-7, 50, 72,
86, 95-{, 136, 156-7, 164,
186-7, 203-4
Competition, 69, 71 , 135-7
Compulsion, 44, 50, 55, 67, 72,
76-82, 161-3, 171 -2, 177,
181, 188, 192, 206
Comte, Auguste. 24-5
Concepts. 15-18, 22-3. 26
Confict. 33-4, 47. 60, 74, 77-8,
81, 1 15, 145. 172-4, 207
Conscience, 58, 60. 78. 89,
1 17-18. 144, 155-{. 207
Consent. 81. 83. 88. 100, 161, 164.
176. 180-1. 189-92, 198,
201-2, 204-8
Conservatism. 49, 69-70, 86-7.
1 13. 1 18-19
Conservative Party, 15, 70
Consistency, 9-15. 22-3. 26-8,
122-4, 149
Constitution, 38-40, 51 , 74-5, 88,
92, 95, 1 53, 1 79-80
Contract, 2-4. 7. l i S, 1 41, 146-9,
161-3, 182-92, 198, 201-6
Copernicusy Nicolaus, 9
Crime. H, 25, 65-{, 92. 1 1 4-16,
183, 199, 201
Criminal law, see Law
Critical evaluation, 8-15, 18-22,
25-9. 208
-
Darwin. Charles. 9
Defence, 41 . 47. 50
Defnition. 16. 2. 30. 33-5. 43.
55-9. 62-3, ll5. 1534. 157.
165
De lega te. 89
Democracy
as form of goverment or rule g
18-19. 37-40. 83-97, 10-3,
204-8
Athenian. 18. 87-8. 1 1 7
liberal. 1 5. 18. 48-9. 64-5, 67,
76. SI-2. 4. ll4
people's. 18-19. 84-5
principles of. 12-15. 83-7.
95-103, 108, 120. 1 31
Desert, see Merit
Desire, 59-62. 78-80. 138
Device, 91-2. 95. 188-91 . 203
Devlin, (Patrick) Lrd. 81
Dickens, Charles. 40
Discrimination, 1 16, 120-33,
139-0
Divine right. 180-1
Dominion, 160-3. 170. 1 78
Economics, 6, 24, 4, 42, 47,
67-71 , 82. 87. 1 10. 134,
138-9. 147-8, 196
Education. 6. 19, 32-3, 38. 40-1,
49-50. 65. 72-3, 84-, 103,
109-10. 1 12. 123-, 129, 131,
133-5, 137-8. 140. 142
Effective (authority or power),
76-7. 158. 160. 163-5, 171-.
205
Elections, see Voting
Electoral Coliege, S8-9
End, 59. 70-3, 76-, 81-2, 9S, 142,
145. 150-1. 180. 195-8. 201-8
Ends-in-themselves, 142
Engels, Friedrich. 13. 86
Entitlements. 150-2
Equality. 14-15. 19. 23-4. 70, 81,
83-7, 95-103, 1 1 7, 1 19-39.
145-51 , 160
before the law, 108, 120-2
of consideration, 132-3
of opportunity, 85, 132-5
of satisfaction of needs, 132,
135-9
Equity. see Fairness
European Community. 19, 53-4,
154
Executive. 301, 51, 82, 88-90,
92-5
Explanation, &-9, 13, 21 . 24,
185
Facility, 129-30, 138, 1 67-8
Fact. 12, 14. 22, 25, 28, 75. 96 .
101. 130-2, 139, 147, 169
Fairess, 49, 70. 73. 1 1 4-30. 135,
137-49. 151-2, 198, 202
Family, 6, 37-1, 45-{, 50, 65,
85-{, 95-{. 125-{, 142. 152,
164, 181, 186
Federation, 53, 96. 100, 129. 153
Fiction, 75, 98, 168-9. 172
Force, sec Power. coercive
Formal, 122-4, 139
Fraternity. 15, 86, 129
Free choice, 56, 60-1 , 76-80. 1 81 ,
188-9
Freedom. see Libert j
Function, 46-50, 55, 66. 72-6, 82.
92, 94, 1 1 8, 122. 149, 197-8.
701 'I
Gemeinschafr. 35-7
General interest, see Common
good; Interest
Generalization. 6-7
General wi l l. see Will
Geseilsch"!,, 35-7
God. 96, 16, 160-1 , 18t1
Good and evil, 10, 12, 4 1 . 48,
59-61 . 76-7, 92, 144, 195
Government. JIl-2, 83, 87-95,
187-9
Greece. ancient, 7, to. 18. 4 1 .
46-7. 87-8, 96, 1 1 6-17, 182-3
Green, T. H + . 63, 192
Guilt, 1 1 5- 16, 121-2, 125
Hamiel" 175 .. .-
Haringtan. Sir John, 162
I
f,r- , A . ;8-'-
Hayek, F. A + . 71
Hegel. G. W. F. , 192
Hereditary succession. 1 6\ , 164.
176. 179
Hobbes. Thomas, 77-8, 97, 1 60-3,
173. 178, 184-9, 191
Hohfeld. W. N . 105-, 167
Homer. 1 8. 63
Human ri ght>. see Righls.
common or human
Hume, David. 25, 163, 1 91
Hypothesis, &-8, 15, 21 . 25, 27,
147, 206
Ideal, 7, 62. 83-7, 90, 96, 136,
193-5
lde,liism, philosophic.11. 58..3.
78-9
Ideology. 7, 13. 21-3, 47
Impartiality, 100, 121 -33
Improvement of concepts. 16-18.
22-3. 28
Independence. 97-100
Indi vidual. 1 8. 48, 65-{, 68, 73,
77-8, 82. 98-9. 1 1 1 . 1 13-19,
142-5, 150, 195
I nnocenee. 1 1 5-16, 121 -2, 125
Interest. 3. 36, 39-41 , 59, 69,
78-9, 1.'0. 145, 1 91 , 195-7.
201 . 203. 207
general. 3-5, 69-73, 79, 87,
l I S-16, 130. 136, 140-5, 1 81 .
189, 1 94-7. 201-4
self-. 14, 4(l-1 , 71, 124, 145-9,
176-8. 184-7, 1 91 . 194-7. 203
i nl ernalional law, see Law
internationnl relations. 31 . 44, 47,
53-4. 95-103. 153-4. I 58-{iO,
174
Jesus of Nazareth. 180
21 4 Index
Judiciary. 51 . 92--. 1 18-19. 121-2.
1 25-7
Jurisdiction. 43-6. 52-5. 100. 163.
176. 1 8 1
Justice. 5. 12. 1 8. 23-5. 49-50. 64.
67-73. 76. 81-3. 85. 87. 99.
5. 1 81 . 184. 197-203. 205, 207
lustifcation, 8, 80, 130, 145,
185-6, 208
Kant, Immanuel. 60, 142
Kelsen. Hans, 5 1
Labour Party. 1 5, 70. 91
Language, 1 4. 24, 26, 75, 79. 96,
1 17. 165-72. 175-8, 1 91-2
Law
civil. 44, 47. 66-8. 82. 92. 1 1 5.
1 21
criminal. 44. 47. 65-6, 73. 81 -2.
92. 1 14-16. 1 21 . 143
explanatory. 6, 28. 1 47
international, 4, 53-4, 95-1 0,
174
nalura1. 96-7. 106-7
of mental development. 24
of oligarchy. 7
positive, 1-5. 53-5. 64-82. 85.
92-4. 97-10. 1 07-8. 1 I {22.
126-7. 130. 139. 146. 1 54-8.
163-. 168-9. 172-6. 1 79-80.
1 82-5. 190. 197-208
sociology of, 7
Legal !!erion, sec Fiction
Legislature. 30-1 . 5 1 . 75-6, gR-t4,
101 . 1 1 2. 1 53
Liberal democracy. see
Democracy
Liberalism. 84, 86. 135. 137
Liberty. 1 4-1 5. 1 8. 23-. 48. 3.
83-6. 92-3, 95. 97. 100,
!O3-9. 1 12, 1 14. 1 16-17. 1 1 9.
1 25. 1 27-8. 136-7. 147.
149-50. 1 5960. 1 67. 169.
1 72. ' 1 84. 193. 198-9
l .iccllcc. 5()-60. 9 ! , 1 60.-7
Lintoln. Abraham, 87
Locke, John, 77, 97, 107. 150, 190,
192, 1 97-9
Logic, 1 1 , 26-7, 79, ll5, 122-,
175, 185
Luther, Martin, 169
Maheu, R., 124
Maine, Sir Henry, 7
Majority, 58, 73, 87-91 , 97. 101-3,
145, 193-, 205-8
Marxism. 1 3, 40, 86-7, 164
Marx, Karl, 7, 1 3, 40. 137
Maximin. 148
Means, 59, 70-1 , 98, 138. 1 42.
197-8, 201 , 203, 208
Merit, 88, 1 15-16, 1 19-21 . 1 30,
136-7, 139-7, 150
Metaphysics, 24-5, 58, 109
Method, 27, 47, 501
Methodology, 23-9
Michels, R. , 7
Mill, 1 . S 65-6. 78, 81 , 84. 87,
173
Minimal State, 48-9, 74, 81 . 149
Minimum, basic, 49, 72. 137-9,
142, 148-9
Monarchy, 37-9, 85, 92-3
Montesquieu, (C. L. de Secondat)
Baron de, 93
Moral
conduct. 1 0. 4 1 , 59-61 , 65,
76-8. 81 , 1 13-14. 1 17. 123-4.
1 44. 194-5
ends. sec End
ju"ice, 49. 99. 1 13-1 4. 1 1 7-18.
1 29-30. 139. 200
obligation. see Obligation
philosophy. see Philosophy
point of view, 53, 1 1 4. 155-6.
1 76-7
principles. 10, 13, 86. lO6-7,
1 14, 122, 147, 200
rights, see Rights
Morgenthau. H. 1 , 1 59
Moses. 180
Names. 1 6
Nation. 37. 41 -3, 96. 98. 129
Nationalism, 42
Nationality. 42, IOR-9
Nation-State. 37. 4 1-3, 97. 174
Naturalization. 43, 1 82-. 189
Natural will, see Will
Nature, 56-7, 61-3. 75, 84, 97.
130, 133. 1 35. 138. 1 84-6. 190
Nazism, 13-1 4, 57. 104
Necessary condition. 59, 1 58. 1 71
Necessity, 27, 44. 56. 59-, 79.
1 69-72. 177. 203-
Need, 7 1-2. 1 19-2 1 . 127. 13{-2.
136--2. 1 45-8. 150
Negative, 48-50. 55, 57-8. 82. 1 3 1 .
197, 201-2
Neill. A. S., 38
Newton. Sir Isaac, 24-5
Norm, 7, 62. 1 19, 130
Norman, R. , 63-
Normative. 7, 2 1 -3. 25, 170
Nozick. R + 149-52
Obedience. 2-5. 44-5. 78. 146.
1 55-7. 161-3. 165, 1 67.
170-2, 1 75-8. 1 82. 184-8.
198. 201 , 204-8
Obligation
in relation 10 a right. 1 6, 43, 98.
105-6, 1 61 . 166-9. 172. 178,
1 82-3. 200. 203-4
legal. 98. 155-6. 160. 1 75-9.
186. 200
moral. 106, 1 55-7. 1 61-2. 169.
1 75 81 . 1 84-5. 1 96-208
of prmi."e. 1 62-.1, 17R. I H2-Q2
politicul. 2-5. D. 1 46. [ (1 1 -2. 7
prudential. 1 76-t). I 8-,. I RR.
1 9tJ. 203
Obliged. 1 71 . 1 76-8. 203
Oligarchy. 7. 37-40, 85, 88
Ombudsman, 95
Omnicompetence, 46-8. 74-81 .
207
Oppenheim, L. F. L > . 1 0
Order. 41 , 47-50. 55. 99. 1 1J-19.
145, 1 72. 201
Organic theory. 47. q8
Orwell. Georgc. 01 -2. 137
lrlex L I )
Paine. Thomas, 1 10
Parliament. 30, 75-6, 9{-5, 1 18.
153, 1 90
Parliamentarv Question, 94
Participation 95, 1 08-9
Penetocracy, 40
Perelman. Ch . . 122
Peters. R. S. , 1 31
Phi losophy
conservative, 8
moral. 10. 1 2, 24. 1 22. 176. 185
of knowledge, 9-12, 1 7. 2 1 -2.
24
of practice, 10-13. 17-1 8. 2 1
of science, 24-7
political. 1 . 32. 35. 74. 97. 146.
1 65, 193. 208
sceptical. 8, 1 0
social. 6-7, 1 0. 1 2, 1 7. 20. 23-.
28. 1 70
traditional. 7-l5, 18- 29
Plamenatz. J. P. , 193
Plato. 7. 46. 59. 78, 84-5. 1 17-18.
120. 135, 1 45. 163, 1 82-7. 190
Plutocracy. 40
Police. 5 1 . 57, 92, 126-7. 162
Polis. 4 1 . 46
Political
argument. 2
hehaviour, 30-2
contrasted with social. 6, 23-,
3{-5
institutions. 30-1 . 85, &7-95,
100-.. 204
panics. 7, I S . 3(}... 1 . 40. 4{. R2.
KK- 1 . 5. 1 01
philosophy. see Philosophy
"cience, 5-7. 20, 24, 153
sovereignty. see Sovereignty
theory. See Theory
Politics. 6. 30-5, 37-8. 47, 87.
153-. 1 57. 161 . 1 64. 194
Polit v. 39-0
Posi ti ve. 7, 2 1 . 23-5 . 28. 48-50.
55. SR. 1 2 1 . 139. 201-2
lliw. sce Lnw
Possihility. 74-6. 16R-q
210 Inde
Power
balance of, 159-W
coercive, 16, 32, 502, 55, 63,
78, S, 90, 92, 9, 101,
155-74, 178-9, 188, 192,
1 95-6, 199, 201, 203
different senses of, 33-4, 1 57,
165-8, 171
great, 99, 101, 159-0
in relation to authority, 75-6.
10, 167-72, 178-9, 192, 204
irresistible, 160-2
separation of. 51 . 92-4. 153
Presuppositions. 14-15. 27-8, 124.
1 31 . 1 38
Promise, 3. 146, 162-3, 178,
182-92, 205-6
Prudence, see interest, self;
Obligation, prudential
Psychology, 10, 75. 147, 149, IS6
Pufendorf, Samuel, 187
Punishment, 44-5. 5 1 . 66, 92. 108,
1 1 4-1 6, 140. 143-5, 1 55. 157,
183. 199, 202, 207
Purpose. 35-41 , 47. 50. 142. 1 91.
197-. 201
Race. 13-14, 76. 126-31
Rationality. 78. 122-4. 132. 1 45-9.
208
Rational will, see Will
Rawls. 1 + . 145-9
Reasons
for action. 77. 124. 126. 163-4.
176-81, 189-92. 196
for belief. 8-1 5. 21-2. 18S-
Reform. 49. 82. 1 1 3. 1 18-19. 135.
152
Regulation. 3 1-2. 37-41 . 47
Relcvance, 120-2, 125-. 1 31-3.
1 39
Religion, 6, 9, 37. 40-1, 45-7. 50,
57, 60-1. 65, 96-7. 1 1 7-18,
128-9. 142. 156, 164, 170. 180
Representative, 88-94, 108, 190
Responsibility , 27, 50. 62, 72. 86,
88. 120. 142-3. 145
Restraint. 56-64. SO
Reward, 134, 1367, 140, 144,
150, 202
Right and wrong, 10, 12, 21 , 57,
61 , 65-, 77-8, S, 1 13-14.
125, 135, 176
Rights
bill of, lOS, 1 10-11
civil and political, 108-9, 1 1 1-12
common or human, 4, 53-,
72, 103-12, 125, 127-8, 139,
198-200
economic, social, and cultural,
109-12
in relation to authority, 165-7,
170-1, 175, 178, 202-4
in relation to justice, 5, 49. 71 ,
73, 1 14-19, 127-8, 130-2,
145, 147, 150-2, 197-202
in relation to obligations. 16, 43,
98, 105-6, 114, 130, 139, 161 ,
166-7, 169-70, 172, 175, 17S,
197-20, 204
legal, 43-4, 48-9, 85, 98, !OS.
107, 1 14, 1 17, 155, 199-200
moral, 72, 106-7, 1 14, 1 17 . 130.
155, 197-20
natural, 104-8, 110, 1 17, 184.
190, 192, 197-200
of action, 105-6. 166-8, 175
of recipienee, 105-6. 139, 167,
172, 175, 179, 198
of the individual, S, 18, 68. 73,
82. 1 15-19, 145
or entitlements. 1 50-2
Robespierre. Maximilien. 1 10
Role, 126, 130. 132-3
Roosevelt, Eleanor, 104
Roosevelt , Franklin D. , 57
Rousseau. JeanJacques, 3, 78. 87,
192-4
Royalty, 39-40
Rules, 31 , 50-2, 83, 86, 101 . 1 54.
156, 164, 168-71 , 179-81 .
185, 198
Sabine, G. H. , 84
Sanctions. 47, 51 , 65, 68. 76. 174,
202
Science, 8-10, 12, 14-15. 17. 24-7.
87
Sciences
natural, 6, 9, 2 1 . 27-8
social, 5-7, 2 1 . 24-8, 147
Scientifc theory. see Theory
Security. 47-50. 55. 73. 77. 107-8.
172. 185, 201
Self-developmenl. 59. 133. 138.
143
Selfinterest, see Interes\
Self-realization. 58-63. 136, 143
Separation of powers. see Power
Slavery. 39, 60-3, 78-80. 88. 96.
108, 1 61
Smith, Adam; 71
Social
anthropology. 24
class. see Class
contract, see Contract
contrasted with political. 6,
23-4. 30
freedom, see Liberty
groups, 35-7. 40. 1 1 7-18.
1 27-30
ideals. see Ideals
justice, 49. 7 1-2. 87. 1 1 8-19.
135
morality, 1 1 3-14
philosophy, see Philosophy
purposes. 41
sciences. see Sciences
studies. 6, 28
Sociali<m. 69-71 , 86-7. 1 37
Society, 6-7. 1 0. 12. 17-18. 25.
31 -2. 35. 44. 64-5. 71 -3.
1 1 4-19. 128-9, 134. 138-5.
t47-9. 1 84-7
international. 95-103
tribal. 3 1 -2. 1 1 7. 180
Sociological theory. see Theory
Sociology. 5-7. 24, 35, S7. 1 69-70
Socrates. 1 6. 1 82-3. 190
Sophists. 1fI
SovereignlY, 16. 1 9. 23. 3 1 . 52-5.
97-1 00, 6. 175. 184-6
poli tical. contrasted with legal,
1 54-64
State. 7. 23, 2, 64-82, 85, 95-103.
107. 1 1 1 -1 2. 1 18, 129. 136.
139. 146, 149-51 , 1 53-64.
172-. 1 79-90, 193. t95-6,
208
Stephen. Sir James Fitzjamcs, 1 1 4
SlIbjecl. 93-4. 1 61-2, 179. 186
Sufficient condition, 158. 160
Superpower. 159-0
Supremacy. 52-5. 97, 99. 1 53-60,
165. 173-4
Surrender. 163. 188-9
Synthesis. 1 6-1 7. 22-3, 28
Talent . LL' Ability
Theology. 24-. 106-7. 1 6tH. 199
Theory
political. 5-7. 97-8
scientifc and philosophital . 5-9,
21-7. 1 85-6
sociological , 5-7, 35
Timocracy. 39
Tocqueville. Alexis de, 84. 87
Tonnies, F + . 35. 37, 186-7
Totalitarianism. 1 8. 41 , 47. 74, 76.
163
Trade lin ions. 46. 50-2, 68, 109.
1 81
Trlldition. 9-1 1 . 96-7. 170-1
Truth. 10. 12. 2 \ . 25. 27. \06-7
Turgot, A. R. - l. , 1 1 0
Tyranny. 39. 87, 163
UNESCO. 125
United Nations Organizati on. 97,
1 00--4 . 1 1 0-12
Universality. 43-5 . 8 1 . 83. !6,
\04-8. 1 30-2. 139. 1 St . 205.
208
Utilitarian. 4-5, 61, 1 40-5. 1!5.
197. 2(J2
( I l i litv. 7 1-2. l I5-16. 134. 137.
140-. 189. 197, 20n-2
Values. 12-1 5. 22, 28. 58-9. 63-4.
77. 80. 85. 1 17, 145. 149
Valle!. E. de, 97
Voluntary, 45. 54, 67, 83. 129,
Voluntary cont.
163. 171. 181-3. 188. 192.
197. 201-2. 206-7
Voting. 30, 43, 85-91 . 95. 100-3.
108-9, 1 12. 13l . 20&
Weber. Max, 169-70
Welfare or well-being, 48-50.
71-3. 82. 148-9, 201-2
Welfare State. 18. 49-50. 72.
136-7. 142
y
-
q
Will
free. CC Free choice
general, 3, 78, 87, 181, 192-7.
201-5
holy, 6
natural, 35, 37, 186
rational, 35, 37, 195
real, 192. 195-<
Wilson, Harold (Lord Wilson of
Rievaulx), 91
Worth, 120-2, 145
!
I
I
\
I
!
l

Potrebbero piacerti anche